You are on page 1of 3

The Joy ofAnalysis

LYNNE ROGERS

ICHARD TARUSKIN'S ESSAY "CATCHING UP WITH that of "technique of composition" and that of "form," what he
Rimsky-Korsakov" is an engaging and rhetorically heated sees as a discrepancy in the degree of development (i.e., inno-
narrative that describes, from a highly personal perspec- vation) between the melodic and rhythmic elements of Arnold
tive, a scholarly quest and related skirmish. In this story, the Schoenberg's serial music. 5 Taruskin's misreading of this sec-
author-protagonist attempts valiantly to redeem a musical hero tion of Analysis and Value Judgment may underline the inten-
misunderstood in the West. At the same time, he offers historical sity of his opinion; it also undermines Dahlhaus's implied
vindication for the work of two music theorists, who subse- authority in restricting the possible tasks of musical analysis
quently reject his interdisciplinary olive branch. The protago- to merely two. Even if Dahlhaus did offer this binary opposi-
nist nonetheless sees reasons to hope in the younger generations tion, surely the assertion that analysis is capable of only two

Downloaded from http://mts.oxfordjournals.org/ at :: on August 22, 2015


of theorists. goals is too limiting; this ubiquitous and valued—if sometimes
Much of the essay revolves around one of Taruskin's many controversial—activity assuredly claims a longer and more varied
important contributions to music history and theory: the un- catalog of aims.
earthing of a pedigree for Igor Stravinsky's octatonicism. In One such purpose, which has likely been experienced by al-
particular, this lineage convincingly links the composer's octa- most all—if not all—readers of this journal, is the scratching of
tonic practice to that of his teacher Nikolai Rimsky-Korsakov. the musical and intellectual itch, arising from the bite of curios-
Even for scholars who wish to address other aspects of ity, to explore that which moves, intrigues, or strikes us in a
Stravinsky's music, the weight of the evidence supporting the particular composition. (In the interest of full disclosure, I feel
connection to Rimsky-Korsakov demands cognizance of the compelled to add the related "because it's fun" and "because it's
relationship and its repercussions. Furthermore, by advocating enjoyable," which might better remain in the closet in the cur-
the reassessment of Rimsky-Korsakov in the West, Taruskin rent climate.) In this case, analysis may well be a private activity.
gives us the gift of another major musical repertory to listen to The findings of such a solitary pursuit, however, often make
and contemplate. their way eventually to more public forums, and thus feed aims
But Taruskin's larger aim in this essay goes beyond issues in that we might characterize as "going beyond" the study of an
the Stravinskian domain. The aforementioned narrative high- individual musical work. One such aim for analysis would in-
lights what he sees as failings of music theory in general and deed involve identifying compositional techniques as advocated
of analysis in particular: the neglect of historical evidence and by Taruskin. Such findings are of interest not only to historians
the willful ignorance of the constructive nature of analytical and theorists, but also to composers and improvisers, who might
findings. In response, Taruskin proposes at the close of his employ what they learn in their own works or performances. 6
essay "a theory of theory: that is, a criterion, or a set of criteria, Analysis is and could be employed, however, for other tasks as
for what makes music theory and its analytical toolkit cultur- well, including: to enhance pedagogy; to inform criticism; to
ally relevant and potentially illuminating." 1 He had earlier assist performance; to provide test cases or offer support for
characterized this "theory of theory" as "a definition of the music-historical or music-theoretical concepts; or to place
tasks of music analysis," which we might understand as its music more broadly in cultural, historical, or social contexts.
aims or purposes. 2 As a starting point for the discussion of Analysis can support any of these goals, but the relationship
these tasks, Taruskin paraphrases Carl Dahlhaus in Analysis is not unidirectional. The subjects of these tasks—composi-
and Value Judgment as distinguishing "between analysis that tional practice; pedagogy; performance; historical or theoretical
uncovers technique of composition and analysis that uncovers
form," and asserts his preference for the former. 3
5 Ibid. (52-53). Dahlhaus sees Schoenberg's melodies in this repertory as
It is ironic then that Dahlhaus does not actually address dodecaphonic and atonal, and his rhythms as rooted in tonal traditions. He
analysis as a topic either on the page of Analysis and Value proposes that the composer might have favored conventional rhythmic
Judgment that Taruskin cites, or within the section to which the constructs to make themes recognizable as such for the purpose of convey-
page belongs. 4 Rather, Dahlhaus ponders from two viewpoints, ing form, which he sees as a concern for Schoenberg. Thus, Dahlhaus asks
if what appears as a discrepancy between melody and rhythm from the
viewpoint of technique of composition could be understood as being necessary
I Taruskin (2011,181). from the viewpoint of form (italics mine).
z Ibid. (169). 6 Such use of analysis is typical, for example, for jazz musicians, who routinely
3 Ibid. (181). analyze other composers' and players' arrangements and improvisations both
4 Dahlhaus, "Analogy and compensation" ([1970] 1983, 50-53). to understand the traditions and to acquire devices for their own use.

208
THE JOY OF ANALYSIS 209

generalizations; extramusical context—could just as easily in- another memorable turn of phrase to his argument. 11
form analysis, and often do. Indeed, work in the above areas can Nonetheless, Taruskin's advocacy for the thoughtful consider-
contribute to analytical goals that throw the spotlight on the ation of both context and subjectivity is well taken and will
individual piece and a listener's or analyst's experience of it. benefit analysts investigating the structure and expressive
Analysis thus might be used to find more to hear in a musical power of individual works, as well as those seeking broader
work, thereby intensifying one's own relationship to and experi- views of repertories and evidence for compositional devices.
ence of it; to explain or account for one's hearing to others; to Indeed, some scholars have not only begun to acknowledge
inspire others to return to a work to contemplate it anew; or to the existence of subjectivity in the analytical process, but have
guide others who might wish to approximate the analyst's lis- celebrated it, developing new conceptions of the ways in which
tening experience.? we relate to musical works and the meaning of what we say
Like analytical goals that go beyond the piece, aims with this about them. 12 Furthermore, we might note that the practice of
narrower but perhaps deeper focus also warrant serious consid- analysis contains a significant subjective component whether
eration, and indeed serve for many of us as inspiration for schol- its goal is greater understanding of an individual work or its
arship. As Marion Guck notes, "presumably we all came to our aims go "beyond the piece." Despite this subjectivity, or per-
present positions through a strong attraction to music and to haps because it is so deeply informed by culture and training
specific pieces." 8 To be sure, many of us are passionate about that it often passes for objectivity, members of our musical and
building historical generalizations or uncovering compositional scholarly community can understand, and sometimes even
practices. Nonetheless, much as we may be moved to consider a

Downloaded from http://mts.oxfordjournals.org/ at :: on August 22, 2015


agree on, each other's analytical communications. 13 From this
composition as "a statistical sample from a musical population," shared context emerges the notion of musical judgment, a
it is the individual work that lies at the root of our most essen- sense, whether real or contrived, that we frequently employ.
tial relationship to music. 9 As elusive as the concept of musical judgment is, there ap-
If analysis for the purpose of understanding musical works pears to be ample evidence of its existence. With it, we make
and listeners' experiences of them is to be a valid aim within the decisions about pieces and evaluate the performances and anal-
contemporary scholarly community, however, and not restricted yses of others. That musical judgment can be applied effec-
to the privacy of an analyst's study, we must continue to address tively to create analyses that ring true for others is exemplified
certain criticisms leveled at analysis that seeks to discover—in by Arthur Berger's and Pieter van den Toorn's discoveries of
that proverbial phrase—"how it works." As noted earlier, two octatonic practices in Stravinsky's works. Their analytical paths
such criticisms, both wielded by Taruskin in his essay, fault led them to findings that only later received the benefit of his-
much musical analysis for ignoring historical context and disre- torical underpinnings. This suggests that analysis involving
garding the role of subjectivity. These concerns intersect in that what we might describe as good musical judgment can indeed
the context in which a piece was composed—cultural, historical, reveal musical "truths," including those that historians would
social—is most often distinct from the context in which it is happily endorse. I do not advocate that analysis indulge in the
contemplated by the analyst. An analyst's own context—created naiveté of ignoring the influences of either historical context or
through musical training, cultural environment, and other fac- subjectivity, but rather that musical judgment be recognized as
tors—may exert an influence even if, and perhaps more strongly a legitimate and probably inescapable component of musical
if, the analyst is unaware of that possibility. 10 scholarship.
These criticisms did not, of course, originate with Taruskin, I think of my own experiences when I was a Master's stu-
but his deservedly renowned skill as a prose stylist renders dent working on my thesis, likely similar to the experiences of
them particularly vivid, if sometimes overly polemical. For in- many reading this essay. Although a result of my work ful-
stance, his binary opposition of analysis used to achieve filled Taruskin's preferred role for analysis—the uncovering of
"merely a taxonomy of musical configurations" (what theorists a technique of composition—this was not even a suspicion
do) versus analysis used to achieve "insight into practice" when I began work by listening repeatedly to a much-loved
(what historians do), ignores much valuable work by both and increasingly scratchy LP recording of Stravinsky's
theorists and historians, although it does add excitement and
II Taruskin (2011, 180).
7 A number of authors voice or imply these aims. For examples of particu- 12 See, for instance, Dubiel (2011) and Guck (2006). Both authors view anal-
larly explicit statements see Agawu (2004, 270-73) and (2009, 12); Dubiel ysis as interpretation and the roles of subjectivity and musical experience as
(2011, 526, 528); and Guck (2006, 201, 207). unavoidable and crucial. See also Lochhead (2006), in which the author
8 Guck (1997, 345). discusses the necessity and validity of "experiential evidence" in her analysis
9 Babbitt (1987, 4). of a late-twentieth-century work for piano and tape, for which the score
10 Many authors discuss the problem of context in analysis, including Jim does not represent all of the musical sounds. The issues she raises, along
Samson ([1999] 2001, 44), who, even as he notes the value of analysis, with her thoughtful conclusions, could apply more generally to the role of
observes "the heavily mediated character of any analytical insight." Judy aural experience in analysis.
Lochhead (2006, 239-52) summarizes strategies with which scholars have 13 Scott Burnham (1997, 325) attributes this shared understanding at least
addressed the problem of context and applies a modified version of one in part to our "fundamental relation to the materiality of music" and our
such strategy in her own analysis. experiences as practicing musicians.
2I0 MUSIC THEORY SPECTRUM 33 (20II)

"Dumbarton Oaks" Concerto. I heard and sensed at several WORKS CITED


points particularly striking sounds that moved me, but puz-
zled me as well. No musical compositions or devices I had Agawu, Kofi. 2004. "How We Got Out of Analysis, and How
studied to that point prepared me to understand these sounds. to Get Back In Again." Music Analysis 23 (2-3): 267-86.
That these effects emerged from a neoclassical work hinting Agawu, V. Kofi. 2009. Music as Discourse: Semiotic Adventures in
at the familiarity of an older tradition without actually deliv- Romantic Music. Oxford Studies in Music Theory. Oxford:
ering on this promise only increased my desire to discover Oxford University Press.
how Stravinsky created them. With more hearings and later Babbitt, Milton. 1987. Words about Music: The Madison Lectures.
analysis of the score, I detected an interactive scheme among Ed. Stephen Dembski and Joseph N. Straus. Madison:
certain musical elements that seemed to be responsible for the University of Wisconsin Press.
features I found so notable and effective. I understand in ret- Burnham, Scott. 1997. "Theorists and 'The Music Itself.' " The
rospect that, as Samson puts it, "When we analyse . . . we Journal of Musicology 15 (3): 316 29. -

construct the object of our analysis according to certain pre- Dahlhaus, Carl. [1970] 1983. Analysis and Value Judgment
suppositions," and thus realize that I did not actually unearth (Analyse and Werturteil). Trans. Siegmund Levarie. New
an intact structural treasure merely from a thicket of notes. 14 York: Pendragon Press.
At the time, however, it felt as if I had, as if I had uncovered Dubiel, Joseph. 2011. "Analysis." In The Routledge Companion to
an important mechanism through which the striking passages Philosophy and Music. Ed. Theodore Gracyk and Andrew

Downloaded from http://mts.oxfordjournals.org/ at :: on August 22, 2015


and their constructions could make sense. Then, on a micro- Kania. 525-34. London: Routledge.
film of Stravinsky's handwritten musical sketches for the Guck, Marion. 1997. "Music Loving, Or the Relationship with
Concerto—my first foray into sketch study—I saw incorpo- the Piece." The Journal of Musicology 15 (3): 343-52.
rated in the composer's work on one of the passages the tech- ---. 2006. "Analysis as Interpretation: Interaction,
nique I had discerned through analysis, thus giving a type of Intentionality, Invention." Music Theory Spectrum 28 (2):
historical confirmation to my analytical findings. Although 191-209.
my more mature (or, at least, older) self is aware that interpre- Lochhead, Judy. 2006. "How Does It Work?": Challenges to
tation and subjectivity played a role in all three of the stages Analytic Explanation." Music Theory Spectrum 28 (2): 233-54.
just described—listening, analysis, and sketch study—I am Samson, Jim. [1999] 2001. "Analysis in Context." In Rethinking
nonetheless left with the strong feeling that there was a ker- Music. Ed. Nicholas Cook and Mark Everist. 35-54. Oxford:
nel of validity to the entire process, and that at least part of Oxford University Press.
this kernel lay in the piece itself. The dual threat of context Taruskin, Richard. 2011. "Catching Up with Rimsky-Korsakov."
and subjectivity could not completely obscure the individual- Music Theory Spectrum 33 (2): 169 85. -

ity of the musical work. As Samson notes, "Even reception


studies usually conclude that the work's identity is not infi-
nitely permeable . . . and that determinacy recedes only to
certain 'horizons.'" 15
In subsequent years, I have often repeated this process of
intensifying my listening experiences through analysis and
sketch study, the process itself gaining breadth and depth as it
is informed by primary sources, the work of other scholars—
both historians and theorists—and my own findings. The
greatest personal benefit of my research into Stravinsky's com-
positional techniques and historical context lies not in those
ends but rather in their roles in the illumination and reinter-
pretation of the elements that initially touched me within the
works themselves. For some analysts (myself included), the un-
dermining of the fiction of scholarly objectivity fails to invali-
date the analytical act, no matter what its aims. Rather, thanks
to those scholars—including Richard Taruskin—who lead the
way in challenging and redefining the aims and boundaries of
,

analysis, the identity of the work, and the nature of the ana-
lyst's relationship to music, we can anticipate the vigorous en-
richment of our field. Music Theory Spectrum, Vol. 33, Issue 2, pp. 208-210, ISSN 0195-6167,
electronic ISSN 1533-8339. © 2011 by The Society for Music Theory.
All rights reserved. Please direct all requests for permission to photocopy
or reproduce article content through the University of California Press's
14 Samson ([1999] 2001, 44). Rights and Permissions website, at http://www.ucpressjournals.com/
15 Ibid. reprintinfo.asp. DOI: 10.1525/mts.2011.33.2.208

You might also like