You are on page 1of 8

Addiction Research & Theory

ISSN: 1606-6359 (Print) 1476-7392 (Online) Journal homepage: https://www.tandfonline.com/loi/iart20

Challenging the brain disease model of addiction:


European launch of the addiction theory network

Nick Heather, David Best, Anna Kawalek, Matt Field, Marc Lewis, Frederick
Rotgers, Reinout W. Wiers & Derek Heim

To cite this article: Nick Heather, David Best, Anna Kawalek, Matt Field, Marc Lewis, Frederick
Rotgers, Reinout W. Wiers & Derek Heim (2018) Challenging the brain disease model of addiction:
European launch of the addiction theory network, Addiction Research & Theory, 26:4, 249-255,
DOI: 10.1080/16066359.2017.1399659

To link to this article: https://doi.org/10.1080/16066359.2017.1399659

Published online: 10 Nov 2017.

Submit your article to this journal

Article views: 39633

View related articles

View Crossmark data

Citing articles: 45 View citing articles

Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at


https://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=iart20
ADDICTION RESEARCH & THEORY
2018, VOL. 26, NO. 4, 249–255
https://doi.org/10.1080/16066359.2017.1399659

EDITORIAL

Challenging the brain disease model of addiction: European launch of the


addiction theory network

Introduction they were delivered at the conference, in the present


editorial.
In February 2014, the journal Nature published an editorial
concerned primarily with the attempt by animal rights acti-
vists to close down addiction research labs that experimented If obesity is also a brain disease, what are the
on animals (Animal Farm 2014). The editorial also stated implications for the brain disease model of
that drug addiction was ‘a chronic relapsing disease that addiction?
changes the structure and function of the brain’ and that
Matt Field
this was not ‘particularly controversial, at least among scien-
tists’ (p. 5). Derek Heim wrote a letter to the journal protest- Nora Volkow, one of the most high-profile proponents of
ing against these assertions and, with the assistance of Nick the BDMA (Volkow et al. 2016), has argued that obesity
Heather, succeeded in obtaining the signatures of 94 addic- should be considered a brain disease that shares many fea-
tion scholars and researchers from around the world. An tures with the addiction brain disease (Volkow et al. 2008,
abbreviated form of the letter was published in Nature 2013). The central tenets of the brain disease model of obes-
(Heim 2014). It disagreed with the one-dimensional por- ity are that, in vulnerable individuals, consumption of
trayal of addiction in the editorial and the claim that this energy-dense food results in powerful momentary increases
was uncontroversial among scientists, further arguing that in dopamine activity in the reward system. This eventually
‘substance abuse cannot be divorced from its social, psycho- overrides homeostatic control mechanisms that govern food
logical, cultural, political, legal and environmental contexts: intake and leads to a number of enduring changes in brain
it is not simply a consequence of brain malfunction’ (p. 40). structure and function, resulting in loss of control over food
Then, following a vigorous defence of the brain disease intake. The brain disease model of obesity is supported by
model of addiction (BDMA) by its most prominent support- observations that obesity is characterised by structural and
ers (Volkow and Koob 2015; Volkow et al. 2016) against functional changes in regions of the brain that underlie
criticisms by Hall and colleagues (Hall et al. 2014, 2015), reward sensitivity, incentive motivation, and self-control, and
Heim and Heather contacted the letter signatories to ask that these changes are largely indistinguishable from those
whether they would be interested in joining a group, to be seen in the ‘addicted brain’ (Volkow et al. 2008, 2013).
known as the Addiction Theory Network (ATN), with the This is an interesting development. The most influential
aims of opposing the dominant influence of the BDMA and neurobiological models of addiction (i.e., ‘brain disease’
collaborating to develop alternative ways of understanding models) emphasise that the functional or structural changes
and responding to addiction. A high proportion agreed and in the brain that underlie the transition from recreational
others have subsequently joined. At the time of writing (27 drug use to addiction occur after repeated consumption of
June 2017), membership stands at 91. The network addictive drugs (alcohol, nicotine, cocaine, opiates etc.), but
activity consists mainly of a google group https://groups.goo- are not an inevitable consequence of repeated consumption
gle.com/forum/#!forum/addictiontheorynetwork but there is of all rewards, including natural rewards such as food,
also a ResearchGate project https://www.researchgate.net/ warmth and sex (Robinson and Berridge 1993; Koob and Le
project/Addiction-Theory-Network and a Twitter account Moal 1997; Goldstein and Volkow 2002). Therefore, the sug-
(@AddictTheoryNet). gestion that similar brain changes may, in fact, also arise
The exact organisational form and structure the ATN will after repeated exposure to food represents a quiet abandon-
take and the range of activities it will engage in is still ment of those earlier claims that there is something special
developing and under discussion. However, occasional face- about addictive drugs that leads to brain disease if vulnerable
to-face meetings are considered essential. The first such people consume them in sufficient quantities.
meeting was the European launch of the network by means There have been challenges to the claim that obesity
of a symposium held at the Annual Conference of the New should be characterised as a brain disease, including observa-
Directions in the Study of Alcohol Group in Weston-super- tions that brain responses during anticipation and consump-
Mare, Somerset, UK on 12 May 2017. The symposium was tion of food, and differences in brain function between
chaired by Professor Betsy Thom of Middlesex University obese and normal weight individuals, are not consistent
and a panel discussion following the presentations was mod- across studies and do not offer strong support for claims
erated by Derek Heim. There were six presentations, each of that energy-dense food is ‘addictive’ or that obesity should
which is summarised by its author(s), in the order in which be characterised as a brain disease (Ziauddeen et al. 2012).
250 N. HEATHER ET AL.

However, I argue that these attempts to frame obesity as an wellbeing as an intrinsically social process that is embedded
addiction-like brain disease expose a more fundamental in local communities.
weakness in the BDMA. We could accept that both addiction It is not only the developmental pathway of recovery but
and obesity are characterised by changes in the structure and the mechanisms of change that challenge 'brain disease' as a
function of the brain, and that these changes reflect a conse- sufficient explanation for recovery (irrespective of the utility
quence of chronic exposure to rewarding, pleasurable stimuli of the BDMA in explaining onset). Kelly (2017) has argued
that in turn increase the motivation to consume those that, not only is Alcoholics Anonymous strongly associated
rewards whilst reducing the ability to control behaviour. But with positive recovery outcomes, but that this peer-delivered
if these brain changes are indeed an inevitable response to mutual aid approach works primarily through its impact on
the repetition of pleasurable acts (rather than something spe- social networks (for men) and changes in abstinence self-
cific to addictive drugs), then the more parsimonious explan- efficacy (for women). This is consistent with a social identity
ation is that they are a completely ‘normal’ and predictable approach showing that recovery initiation and maintenance
reorganisation of the structure of the brain and change in its are most strongly explained by the transition from using to
function, rather than hallmarks of a ‘disease’. This is the recovery groups. This is consistent with a re-analysis of
argument favoured by Marc Lewis which can account for the Project MATCH data (Longabaugh et al. 2010) and is predi-
brain changes that characterise addiction, overeating, and all cated on the transition in norms, values and beliefs associ-
manner of behavioural addictions such as problem gambling ated with switching from using to recovery-oriented social
(Lewis 2017). groups.
Not only does the success of mutual aid and peer-sup-
ported pathways challenge the idea of biological determinism
Challenging the brain disease model of addiction in addiction, it also challenges the implicitly moral argument
from a recovery perspective of partial determinism in which addicts are 'lesser' in their
David Best and Anna Kawalek choices resulting from the draining of will and volition that
addiction is perceived to cause. ‘Recovery’ also contributes to
The American National Institute on Drug Abuse (2008) the challenge to the BDMA in the sense that, as well as char-
states that addiction is a chronic, relapsing brain disease acterising a personal experience, it summarises a pre-figura-
characterised by compulsive drug seeking and use, despite tive political movement that resists medical labelling and the
harmful consequences. While this biology-based definition of power of pharmaco-solutions in a latter-day version of anti-
addiction aims to ‘alleviate the moral judgement, discrimin- psychiatry. Recovery is a contested concept but one that
ation and stigma associated with drug use’ (Seear 2017, shifts the timeline of addiction understanding, its locus and
p. 1), evidence suggests that the BDMA has only furthered its mechanisms and that promotes self-determination and
the stigma associated with addiction, leaving addicts increas- strength-based choices.
ingly vulnerable to exclusion and marginalisation (Heather
2017b).
The emergence of a recovery paradigm has challenged the Bioethical implications of the brain disease model
conceptualisation of addiction as a biologically-driven phe- of addiction
nomenon rooted in human pathology. Evidence indicates
that recovery is a social experience, occurring within social Frederick Rotgers
contexts which change recovery experiences at a subjective Modern bioethics rests upon four basic principles of practice:
level, with the emphasis on the social and on strengths. respect for autonomy, nonmaleficence, beneficence, and just-
There is a high prevalence of recovery; Sheedy and Whitter ice (Beauchamp and Childress 1989; Childress 1997). Of
(2009) showed that, on average, over half (58%) of alcohol these, respect for autonomy tends to trump the others when
or other drug addicts recover (with variability), whilst in a it comes to situations involving whether or not a person
recent survey of recovery in Canada 51% of participants should receive treatment for addiction, and whether or not
reported achieving stable recovery at their first attempt in addicts are competent to make decisions about various
spite of entrenched addiction, challenging both the chronic aspects of their lives. The principle of respect for autonomy
and the relapsing components of the model (McQuaid et al. states that in any decision-making on the part or on behalf
2017). of an individual, specifically in clinician-patient relationships,
There is also evidence that recovery is more than simply the clinician’s duty is to respect the autonomous choice of
the reversal of addiction. Hibbert and Best (2011) demon- the patient. Autonomous choice can be defined as ‘personal
strated that those in long-term recovery were ‘better than rule of the self by adequate understanding while remaining
well’ with higher life quality following recovery than ‘typical’ free from controlling interferences by others and from per-
non-addict populations, challenging the idea that recovery is sonal limitations that prevent choice’ (Faden and Beauchamp
a return to a homeostatic zero (Lewis 2017). Similarly, the 1986, p. 6, emphasis added). This definition implies that
Life in Recovery Survey showed that, of those in stable recov- clinicians should only withhold decisional power from indi-
ery, 79.4% are engaged in meaningful activities; this made viduals who suffer from either external control or personal
them twice as enmeshed within the wider community than limitations that prevent them from making adequate deci-
individuals not in recovery (Best et al. 2015). Recovery is sions that are consistent with personal values (Childress
ultimately not about reversal of pathology but the growth of 1997).
ADDICTION RESEARCH & THEORY 251

The BDMA as proposed by Leshner (1997) and Volkow by the dominant medical model of addiction, which tends to
and colleagues (Volkow et al. 2016) has the basic tenet that ignore the importance of personal empowerment for recov-
repeated substance use leads to brain changes that render ery. The help addicts need isn't medical; it's psychological.
the individual incapable of making certain types of decisions Certain cognitive, emotional and social skills are particularly
and choices effectively. In essence, the BDMA suggests that useful for voluntarily steering one's path out of addiction.
addiction prevents addicts from making a variety of decisions In this contribution I explore some of these skills through
about their lives, especially ones involving whether or not to the use of a metaphor. These skills are similar to those
use drugs at any given time. This view invites paternalism needed to steer a toboggan racing down a hill. What are the
by treatment providers and others who view the addict as parallels between steering one's drug use and one's toboggan
requiring treatment that he/she might not wish to undergo, run?
but as incapable of effectively deciding to accept a treatment
recommendation (Vandeveer 1986). This raises the question 1. There is a strong force pulling the path in the present
of the extent to which addicts are actually incapable of mak- direction. For tobogganing it's gravity – the slope of the
ing decisions about their lives, the extent to which addiction hill; for addiction it's habit strength – the recurrence of
actually prevents such decision-making, and how we are to the addictive urge. The force of gravity translates to
ascertain when and whether addiction had rendered the speed in tobogganing; the force of habit translates to
individual incompetent in this way. It is clear from widely intensity or duration in addiction. The better we under-
replicated research findings that most addicts clearly are not stand these forces, the more easily we can help those
incompetent in this way—that is, most ultimately make whose momentum is propelled by them.
effective decisions about their substance use in the context 2. Techniques for steering have remarkable similarities. On
of personal values that emerge at some point in time and a toboggan, you'd best use small, subtle movements, like
outweigh the value of drug-taking (see Heyman 2009). leaning in one direction or sticking your elbow in the
Heyman notes the experience of William Burroughs who, snow. If you try a sharp turn, say by leaning too force-
when his family declined to further support him financially, fully or thrusting your foot out, you will surely topple.
and unwilling to work at a traditional job, stopped taking In addiction, it is also useful to apply subtle cognitive
drugs (Heyman 2009). The BDMA also raises questions tricks, like choosing the street you take home from
about whether an addict has the capacity to effectively make
work to avoid the liquor store, or telling yourself you
decisions about other aspects of life that might intersect with
can get through a day at a time. Gentle self-directed
decisions about drug-taking, e.g. finances, entry into con-
nudges and self-talk work far better than ‘I must never
tracts, etc., further inviting a paternalism that risks becoming
do this again!’ (Snoek et al. 2016). For both tobogganing
coercive and disrespectful of individual autonomy.
and addiction, precision and timing are more important
Arguably, a fully-fledged acceptance of the BDMA could
result in increased violation of addicts’ civil and human than brute force.
rights in the name of beneficence. Additionally, so doing 3. For both tobogganing and addiction, the contribution of
may, given the toxicity of some treatments for some individ- other people – especially those at hand – is critical.
uals, result in harm to the addict by virtue of creating a Toboggans can be more easily steered when all three or
negative view of treatment that results in further reluctance four passengers lean in the same direction at the same
time (in sync). In addiction, interpersonal advice, emo-
to seek help for addiction. Such an outcome would clearly
tional availability, and support work best when they are
be in violation of the principle of nonmaleficence
in sync with the addict's own plans, intentions, and tim-
(Beauchamp and Childress 1989). Thus, in the author’s view,
ing. That's why we need to be ready to help when some-
the BDMA raises significant bioethical questions that need
one is ‘ready’ to quit.
to be addressed going forward.
4. Repetition is fundamental to tobogganing and recovery.
In tobogganing it's simple – the more runs you make,
Steering a path through addiction: lessons from the more skilled you become. But in addiction, repeated
tobogganing attempts are criticised, especially by those entrenched in
legalistic or moralistic positions. Addiction experts
Marc Lewis remind us that ‘Relapse is part of recovery’ (Witkiewitz
As a developmental psychologist, I tend to see mental health and Marlatt 2004). Each time you go through the pro-
issues and personality patterns as trajectories that continue cess of failing, or almost succeeding, you are more likely
to progress and modify their direction (as constrained by to try more skilfully next time. Few addicts quit without
their own histories) from within, over the lifespan. several tries.
Addiction can be viewed as a trajectory that emerges, 5. For both tobogganing and recovery, self-compassion,
becomes ingrained, and then in most cases evolves further self-confidence, and respect and admiration from others
(people quit or learn to control their use) over time (Lewis help the person keep trying until they get it right. If we
2017). were to scorn and denigrate those whose toboggan flips
Indeed, most people in addiction eventually quit, and a over, they'd be less likely to take another run. So let's
majority of those do so without treatment (Heyman and respect and encourage addicts who need a number of
Mims 2017). When treatment is pursued, it is compromised tries to finally quit.
252 N. HEATHER ET AL.

Risks of being misunderstood when one denies that illustrates how influential advocates of the BDMA have
addiction is best viewed as a brain disease been and that it has been unquestioningly accepted in
many quarters. But this is not a good reason for dis-
Nick Heather missing criticisms or alternative approaches. The pro-
Portrayals of addiction rejecting the premise that it is a nouncements of these august bodies are precisely the
chronic, relapsing brain disease – for example, that it is bet- views of addiction that should be challenged in the
ter seen as a disorder of choice (Heyman 2009; Heather and interests of a proper scientific understanding.
Segal 2017) - are frequently misunderstood or misrepre-
sented. Examples may be found in the comments of an It should go without saying that the debate about whether
anonymous reviewer of an article now published analysing or not addiction is best seen as a chronic, relapsing brain
the role of ‘compulsion’ in theories of addiction (Heather disease should eventually be decided, or at least strongly
2017a). Some of these misunderstandings and how they may influenced, by evidence and reasoned debate. Tactics used by
be countered might be paraphrased as follows: supporters of the BDMA are sometimes inimical to this
aspiration. It does no good to avoid proper scientific debate
I. The view that addiction is a disorder of choice trivialises by claiming that the issue has already been decided or by
a tragic condition and does a huge disservice to the field. implying that raising doubts about the validity of the BDMA
There are no logical grounds for concluding that seeing is always irresponsible and inevitably dangerous to the health
it as a disorder of choice trivialises addiction; no advo- and welfare of persons labelled as addicts.
cate of such a view is unaware of the tragic consequen-
ces of addiction.
Testing the brain disease model of addiction
II. Seeing addiction as a disorder of choice is dangerous
because it is close to the moral argument that we in the Reinout W. Wiers
addictions field have been trying to stamp out for 40
The BDMA has been proposed as a summary of the current
years - that individuals with addiction are bad people
scientific state of affairs (Leshner 1997; Koob and Volkow
who should be punished. Advocates of addiction as a
2010; Volkow et al. 2016). This has been disputed by others,
disorder of choice explicitly state that it is not a free
emphasising spontaneous recovery even after severe addic-
choice for which addicts should be blamed and specific- tion (e.g. Heyman 2009; Lewis 2015). I argue that the
ally reject the idea that it represents a moral failing BDMA is a testable hypothesis that remains to be
(e.g, Heather 2017b). It is conceded that a theory (dis)proved.
couched in terms of ‘weakness of will’ and self-control The BDMA states that addictive behaviours change the
may present special difficulties for communication with brain in various ways, which makes repeated relapse more
the general public. Misunderstandings would likely be likely, including changes in reward sensitivity (stronger
fuelled by oversimplified, distorted or sensationalist sensitivity to the rewarding effects of the addictive sub-
portrayals in the media, including those prompted or stance or behaviour, desensitisation of other rewards),
taken advantage of by scientists and clinicians with stress reactivity and negative affect, and reduced cognitive
vested interests in the BDMA. control and self-regulation. There is strong evidence back-
III. The argument that cravings are only sometimes powerful ing up these hypothesised changes, both from animal and
and generally not difficult to resist is blatantly false. human literatures (Koob and Volkow 2010); the question
Such an argument would be blatantly false if it had is whether this proves that addiction is a brain disease.
been made but those who reject the BDMA repeatedly Importantly, it has been claimed that addiction is not just
stress that addictive desires can be abnormally strong a passing disease like the flu, but a chronic disease like
and extremely difficult to resist (e.g. Heather 2017a). diabetes and chronic hypertension (Leshner 1997). Hence,
IV. The Heyman (2009) argument is that addiction self- the BDMA not only states that there are brain changes
cures and therefore is not compulsive-like. Yet it is also which occur as one gets addicted (true), but also that
argued that relapse can occur at any time. So how can these brain changes are chronic and cause relapse. In its
one ever be self-cured? The discrepancy between the strong form this statement is obviously untrue, as pointed
established fact of high rates of natural recovery from out both with epidemiological and historical data (Heyman
addiction in the general population and its characterisa- 2009) and with case-histories of severely addicted people
tion as a relapsing condition is more apparent than who successfully quit (Lewis 2015). However, this falsifies
real. Rates of natural recovery are high even though the strong BDMA (one black swan is enough to falsify
there is evidence that addicts may make many attempts the statement that all swans are white), but does not
to recover before they eventually succeed. mean a lighter form of the BDMA is not true: addiction
V. The National Institutes of Health, the American Society severity is a continuum and for severe cases the BDMA
of Addiction Medicine and a recent Surgeon General's may hold true (Berridge 2017; Fenton and Wiers 2017).
report make the identical case based on scientific evi- However, it would then have to be shown that:
dence of addiction as a brain disorder. Proponents of
the BDMA often defend the model by referring to 1. There are neural changes specifically related to severity
respected organisations that endorse it but this merely of addiction;
ADDICTION RESEARCH & THEORY 253

2. These changes do not reverse with prolonged as the dogma of the BDMA – the repeated, public pro-
abstinence; nouncements that science has already clearly established that
3. These changes increase the risk of relapse after a period addiction is a chronic, relapsing brain disease and that it is
of abstinence. surprising anyone should continue to doubt the truth of this
assertion (Volkow et al. 2016). At the same time, anyone
At present, none of these claims has been proven beyond who does voice such doubts is often castigated as reckless
dispute. First, many studies have compared brains of and irresponsible, ignorant of the realities of addiction and
addicted people with controls, but any difference could be a as potentially placing the lives of addicts at risk. In other cir-
risk-marker rather than a consequence; there are no con- cumstances such dogma might be harmless and could be jus-
vincing longitudinal studies yet available (Schulte et al. tifiably ignored but the problem is that it is a dogma that
2014), but this could change in the future with large pro- has come to dominate public discourse and national policy
spective neuroimaging studies on the way (Imagen, ABCD)1. on addiction, at least in the USA and increasingly, we fear,
The second claim also remains to be proven and, while there in other countries of the world. Research linked to the
are indications of lack of recovery in some functions, there BDMA has also come to swallow up almost all the funding
is evidence of recovery in others (Lewis 2017; Schulte et al. for research on addiction on the planet, resulting in a demise
2014). The third claim is likely to be true: a sensitised in funding for research on the prevention of addiction and
reward response, strong stress-reactivity, combined with lack approaches other than pharmacotherapy to its treatment.
of control are likely to contribute to relapse, as do other This self-perpetuating research agenda has also tended to
neurocognitive correlates of addiction such as lack of insight appropriate all available data on neurobiological change in
(Goldstein et al. 2009), and reduced ability of voluntary addiction, thus side-lining interpretations that stress neuro-
choice (Fenton and Wiers 2017; Wiers et al. 2016). In add- psychological development and neuroplasticity in contrast to
ition, there can be ‘collateral damage’ strongly related to the pathology (Lewis 2017). And the dominance of the BDMA
addiction (e.g. Korsakoff’s syndrome) which may contribute has limited the dissemination of approaches to addiction
to relapse (Fenton and Wiers 2016). However, the causal that are known to be cheap and effective in reducing harm
role of these changes with respect to relapse remains to be (Hall et al. 2014, 2015).
established beyond doubt. (There is some evidence for a pre- We therefore see the future tasks of the ATN as the clari-
dictive value of cue reactivity (Schacht et al. 2012), but cer- fication and articulation of the main grounds for criticising
tainly not strong enough at this moment to support BDMA the BDMA, and their dissemination both to the scientific
rather than alternative accounts.) In conclusion, the BDMA and addiction professional communities and to the general
consists of a number of hypotheses that could be tested for public and decision-makers. The network will hopefully pro-
different addictions. It appears premature at best to describe vide the opportunity for colleagues in different geographical
it as the current state of knowledge. areas and/or from different scientific disciplines to form col-
laborations to work towards these ends. While network
members may differ in their specific objections to the
Concluding remarks BDMA, there may also be disagreement on what models of
addiction should replace it. Nevertheless, the ATN will hope-
It is clear from the six summaries presented above that there fully foster collaborations on developing new ways of under-
are a range of views on what is wrong with the BDMA, both standing addiction and their consequences for the
from a strictly scientific perspective and from a consider- prevention and reduction of harm. Lastly, as a counterpoint
ation of its consequences for the avoidance and reduction of to the dogma of the BDMA, we will make strenuous efforts
harm due to addiction. Some find that some forms of what to avoid slipping into dogma ourselves. In disputes of this
is known as addiction are not usefully thought of as brain kind, involving fundamental assumptions about human
disease, some that addiction is not just brain disease in the nature and society, it is all too easy to descend into ideo-
absence of other kinds of determinant, and some that it is logical rancour. As scientists, we need to keep in mind
not best seen as brain disease of any kind or in any way. At
Popper’s (1992) admonitions concerning the need for falsifi-
the same time, criticisms come from various vantage points
ability in scientific propositions; we must always be willing
that may seem to have little in common with each other –
to say, as clearly as we can, what it would take to change
from philosophy, psychology and behavioural science, social
our minds and admit that addiction was, after all, best seen
science and even from neuroscience. This is not the place to
as a disease of the brain. We trust that advocates of the
attempt to identify all the objections to the BDMA that cur-
BDMA will do the same from their point of view.
rently exist or might conceivably exist, but the question can
be asked, in the midst of this diversity, what is the point of
forming a network dedicated to challenging the brain disease Acknowledgements
model.
Thanks are due to Anthony Moss for useful comments on parts of
Perhaps the best answer to this question is that all adher- a previous version of this editorial. We also thank Wulf
ents of the ATN share an objection to what they perceive Livingstone, Betsy Thom and all others who contributed to the suc-
cess of the symposium held at the NDSAG Annual Conference.
1
See the homepages of these two studies: https://imagen-europe.com/ & The symposium was supported by a Network Grant from Alcohol
https://abcdstudy.org/ Research UK.
254 N. HEATHER ET AL.

Disclosure statement National Institute on Drug Abuse. 2008. Drugs, brains, and behavior:
the science of addiction, revised ed. Washington (DC): National
The authors have no conflicts of interest to declare. Institute on Drug Abuse.
Popper K. 1992. The logic of scientific discovery. London (UK):
Routledge.
Robinson TE, Berridge KC. 1993. The neural basis of drug craving: an
References incentive-sensitization theory of addiction. Brain Res Brain Res Rev.
Animal Farm. 2014. Editorial. Nature. 506:5. 18:247–291.
Beauchamp TL, Childress JF. 1989. Principles of biomedical ethics. Schacht JP, Anton RF, Myrick H. 2012. Functional neuroimaging stud-
3rd ed. New York (NY): Oxford University Press. ies of alcohol cue reactivity: a quantitative meta-analysis and system-
Berridge KC. 2017. Is addiction a brain disease? Neuroethics. 10:29–33. atic review. Addict Biol. 18:121–133.
Best D, Albertson K, Irving J, Lightowlers C, Mama-Rudd A, Schulte MHJ, Cousijn J, den Uyl TE, Goudriaan AE, van den Brink W,
Chaggar A. 2015. UK life in recovery survey. Sheffield (UK): Veltman DJ, Schilt T, Wiers RW. 2014. Recovery of
Sheffield Hallam University. neurocognitive functions following sustained abstinence after sub-
Childress JF. 1997. Practical reasoning in bioethics. Bloomington (IN): stance dependence and implications for treatment. Clin Psychol Rev.
Indiana University Press. 34:531–550.
Faden RR, Beauchamp TL. 1986. A history and theory of informed con- Seear K. 2017. The emerging role of lawyers as addiction ‘quasi-
sent. New York (NY): Oxford University Press. experts’. Int J Drug Policy. 44:183–191.
Fenton T, Wiers RW. 2017. Free will, black swans and addiction. Sheedy CK, Whitter M. 2009. Guiding principles and elements of
Neuroethics. 10:157–165. recovery-oriented systems of care: what do we know from the
Goldstein RZ, Bechara A, Garavan H, Childress AR, Paulus MP, research? HHS Publication No. (SMA) 09–4439. Rockville MD:
Volkow ND. 2009. The neurocircuitry of impaired insight in drug Center for Substance Abuse Treatment, Substance Abuse and Mental
addiction. Trends Cogn Sci (Regul Ed) Sci. 13:372–380. Health Services Administration.
Goldstein RZ, Volkow ND. 2002. Drug addiction and its underlying Snoek A, Levy N, Kennett J. 2016. Strong-willed but not successful: the
neurobiological basis: neuroimaging evidence for the involvement of importance of strategies in recovery from addiction. Addict Behav
the frontal cortex. Am J Psychiatry. 159:1642–1652. Reports. 4:102–107.
Hall W, Carter A, Forlini C. 2014. The brain disease model of addic- Vandeveer D. 1986. Paternalistic intervention: the moral bounds on
tion: is it supported by the evidence and has it delivered on its beneficence. Princeton (NJ): Princeton University Press.
promises? Lancet Psychiatry. 2:105–110. Volkow N, Koob G. 2015. Brain disease model of addiction: why is it
Hall W, Carter A, Forlini C. 2015. Brain disease model of addiction: so controversial? Lancet Psychiatry. 2:677–679.
misplaced priorities? Lancet Psychiatry. 2:867. Volkow ND, Koob GF, McLellan AT. 2016. Neurobiologic advances
Heather N. 2017a. Is the concept of compulsion useful in the explan- from the brain disease model of addiction. N Engl J Med.
ation or description of addictive behaviour and experience? Addict 374:363–371.
Behav Reports. 6:15–38. Volkow ND, Wang GJ, Fowler JS, Telang F. 2008. Overlapping
Heather N. 2017b. Q: Is addiction a brain disease or a moral failing? A: neuronal circuits in addiction and obesity: Evidence of sys-
neither. Neuroethics. 10:115–124. tems pathology. Philos Trans R Soc B Biol Sci.
Heather N, Segal G. 2017. Addiction and choice: rethinking the rela- 363:3191–3200.
tionship. Oxford (UK): Oxford University Press. Volkow ND, Wang GJ, Tomasi D, Baler RD. 2013. Obesity and addic-
Heim D. 2014. Addiction: not just brain malfunction (Letter). Nature. tion: neurobiological overlaps. Obes Rev. 14:2–18.
507:40. Wiers RW, Field M, Stacy AW. 2016. Passion’s slave? Conscious
Heyman GM. 2009. Addiction: a disorder of choice. Cambridge (MS): and unconscious cognitive processes in alcohol and drug abuse. In:
Harvard University Press. Sher KJ, editor, The Oxford handbook of substance use and sub-
Heyman GM, Mims V. 2017. What addicts can teach us about addic- stance use disorders. vol 1. Oxford (UK): Oxford University Press;
tion: a natural history approach. In Heather N, Segal G, editors. p. 1–80.
Addiction and choice: rethinking the relationship. Oxford (UK): Witkiewitz K, Marlatt GA. 2004. Relapse prevention for alcohol
Oxford University Press; p. 385–408. and drug problems: that was zen, this is tao. Am Psychol.
Hibbert L, Best D. 2011. Assessing recovery and functioning in former 59:224–235.
problem drinkers at different stages of their recovery journey. Drug Ziauddeen H, Farooqi IS, Fletcher PC. 2012. Obesity and the brain:
Alcohol Rev. 30:12–20. how convincing is the addiction model? Nat Rev Neurosci.
Kelly K. 2017. Is Alcoholics Anonymous religious, spiritual, neither? 13:279–286.
Findings from 25 years of mechanisms of behaviour change research.
Addiction. 112:929–936.
Koob GF, Le Moal M. 1997. Drug abuse: hedonic homeostatic dysregu-
lation. Science. 278:52–58.
Nick Heather
Koob GF, Volkow ND. 2010. Neurocircuitry of addiction. Department of Psychology, Faculty of Health & Life Sciences,
Neuropsychopharmacology. 35:217–238. Northumbria University, Newcastle upon Tyne, UK
Leshner AI. 1997. Addiction is a brain disease, and it matters. Science. nick.heather@unn.ac.uk
278:45–47.
Lewis M. 2015. The biology of desire: why addiction is not a disease.
New York (NY): PublicAffairs. David Best and Anna Kawalek
Lewis M. 2017. Addiction and the brain: development, not disease. Department of Law & Criminology, Sheffield Hallam
Neuroethics. 10:7–18. University, Sheffield, UK
Longabaugh R, Wirtz PW, Zywiak WH, O'Malley SS. 2010. Network
support as a prognostic indicator of drinking outcomes: the
Matt Field
COMBINE study. J Stud Alcohol Drugs. 71:837–846.
McQuaid RJ, Malik A, Moussouni K, Baydack N, Stargardter M, Department of Psychological Sciences, University of Liverpool
Morrisey M. 2017. Life in recovery from addiction in Canada. Ottawa, and the UK Centre for Tobacco and Alcohol Studies,
Ontario Canadian Centre on Substance Use and Addiction. Liverpool, UK
ADDICTION RESEARCH & THEORY 255

Marc Lewis Derek Heim


Department of Social Development (Emeritus), Radboud Department of Psychology, Edgehill University,
University, Nijmegen The Netherlands Ormskirk, UK

Frederick Rotgers ß 2017 Informa UK Limited, trading as Taylor & Francis Group
John Jay College of Criminal Justice, New York, USA

Reinout W. Wiers
Addiction Development & Psychopathology (ADAPT)-Lab,
ABC & Yield Research Priority Areas, Department of
Psychology, University of Amsterdam, Amsterdam,
The Netherlands

You might also like