You are on page 1of 608

ebook

THE GUILFORD PRESS


ATLAS OF MORAL PSYCHOLOGY
Atlas
of Moral
Psychology

Edited by

Kurt Gray
Jesse Graham

THE GUILFORD PRESS


New York  London
Copyright © 2018 The Guilford Press
A Division of Guilford Publications, Inc.
370 Seventh Avenue, Suite 1200, New York, NY 10001
www.guilford.com

All rights reserved

No part of this book may be reproduced, translated, stored in a retrieval


system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical,
photocopying, microfilming, recording, or otherwise, without written permission
from the publisher.

Printed in the United States of America

This book is printed on acid-free paper.

Last digit is print number: 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1

Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data is available


from the publisher.

ISBN 978-1-4625-3256-8 (hardcover)


About the Editors

Kurt Gray, PhD, is Assistant Professor of Psychology and Neuroscience at the


University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill. He studies moral psychology,
mind perception, and agent-based modeling. Dr. Gray has been named a Ris-
ing Star by the Association for Psychological Science, which awarded him the
Janet Spence Award for Transformative Early Career Research. He has also
received the Sage Young Scholar Award, the Wegner Theoretical Innovation
Prize from the Society for Personality and Social Psychology, and the Early
Career Award and Best Social Cognition Paper Award from the International
Social Cognition Network, and is a Fellow of the Society of Experimental So-
cial Psychology. Widely cited in the media, Dr. Gray has spoken at two TED
events and is coauthor (with Daniel M. Wegner) of a book for general readers,
The Mind Club: Who Thinks, What Feels, and Why It Matters. His website is
www.mpmlab.org.

Jesse Graham, PhD, is Associate Professor of Management at the Eccles School


of Business, University of Utah. He studies people’s core moral, political, and
religious convictions. Dr. Graham is a Fellow of the Society of Experimental
Social Psychology and of the Moral Psychology Research Group. He has been
named a Rising Star by the Association for Psychological Science and also has
been honored with the Sage Young Scholar Award, the General Education
Teacher of the Year Award from University of Southern California, the Award
for Excellence in Scholarship in the Sciences from the University of Virginia,
and the Morton Deutsch Award for best paper published in Social Justice Re-
search. Dr. Graham is coeditor (with Piercarlo Valdesolo) of Social Psychology
of Political Polarization.

v
Contributors

Mark D. Alicke, PhD, Jason M. Cowell, PhD,


Department of Psychology, Ohio University, Department of Psychology,
Athens, Ohio The University of Chicago, Chicago, Illinois
Karl Aquino, PhD, Clayton R. Critcher, PhD,
UBC Sauder School of Business, Haas School of Business,
University of British Columbia, Vancouver, University of California, Berkeley,
British Columbia, Canada Berkeley, California
Brock Bastian, PhD, Fiery Cushman, PhD,
Melbourne School of Psychological Sciences, Department of Psychology, Harvard University,
University of Melbourne, Melbourne, Australia Cambridge, Massachusetts
Roy F. Baumeister, PhD, Audun Dahl, PhD, Department of Psychology,
Department of Psychology, University of California, Santa Cruz,
Florida State University, Tallahassee, Florida Santa Cruz, California
C. Daryl Cameron, PhD, Department of Jean Decety, PhD, Department of Psychology,
Psychology, The Pennsylvania State University, The University of Chicago, Chicago, Illinois
University Park, Pennsylvania
Morteza Dehghani, PhD,
Nate C. Carnes, PhD, Department of Department of Psychology,
Psychological and Brain Sciences, University of Southern California,
University of Massachusetts Amherst, Los Angeles, California
Amherst, Massachusetts
Peter DeScioli, PhD,
Hanah A. Chapman, PhD, Department of Political Science,
Department of Psychology, Brooklyn College, Stony Brook University, Stony Brook, New York
Brooklyn, New York
Anton J. M. Dijker, PhD,
Mina Cikara, PhD, Department of Psychology, Department of Health Promotion,
Harvard University, Cambridge, Massachusetts Maastricht University,
Maastricht, The Netherlands
Paul Conway, PhD, Department of Psychology,
Florida State University, Tallahassee, Florida

vii
viii Contributors

Peter H. Ditto, PhD, Department of Psychology Rumen Iliev, PhD, Ford School of Public Policy,


and Social Behavior, University of California, University of Michigan, Ann Arbor, Michigan
Irvine, Irvine, California
Yoel Inbar, PhD, Department of Psychology,
Susan T. Fiske, PhD, Department of Psychology, University of Toronto Scarborough,
Princeton University, Princeton, New Jersey Scarborough, Ontario, Canada
Jeremy A. Frimer, PhD, Department of Carol Iskiwitch, MA, Department of
Psychology, University of Winnipeg, Psychology, University of Southern California,
Winnipeg, Manitoba, Canada Los Angeles, California
Adam D. Galinsky, PhD, Columbia Business Ronnie Janoff‑Bulman, PhD, Department of
School, Columbia University, New York, Psychological and Brain Sciences, University
New York of Massachusetts Amherst,
Amherst, Massachusetts
Roger Giner‑Sorolla, PhD,
School of Psychology, Keynes College, Kate Johnson, MA, Department of Psychology,
University of Kent, Canterbury, United Kingdom University of Southern California, Los Angeles,
California
Francesca Gino, PhD, Harvard Business School,
Harvard University, Cambridge, Massachusetts Adam Kay, PhD, Sauder School of Business,
University of British Columbia, Vancouver,
Geoffrey P. Goodwin, PhD, Department
British Columbia, Canada
of Psychology, University of Pennsylvania,
Philadelphia, Pennsylvania Justin J. Kelly, BSc, Melbourne School
of Psychological Sciences, University of
Sara Gottlieb, PhD, Department of Psychology,
Melbourne, Parkville, Victoria, Australia
University of California, Berkeley,
Berkeley, California Melanie Killen, PhD, Department of Human
Development and Quantitative Methodology,
Aner Govrin, PhD, Department of Psychology,
University of Maryland, College Park,
Bar Ilan University, Tel Aviv, Israel
College Park, Maryland
Jesse Graham, PhD, Eccles School of Business,
Joshua Knobe, PhD, Departments of Philosophy,
University of Utah, Salt Lake City, Utah
Psychology, and Linguistics, Yale University,
Kurt Gray, PhD, Department of Psychology and New Haven, Connecticut
Neuroscience, University of North Carolina
Robert Kurzban, PhD, Department of
at Chapel Hill, Chapel Hill, North Carolina
Psychology, University of Pennsylvania,
Jeff Greenberg, PhD, Department of Psychology, Philadelphia, Pennsylvania
The University of Arizona, Tucson, Arizona
Simon M. Laham, PhD, Melbourne School
Joshua D. Greene, PhD, of Psychological Sciences, University of
Department of Psychology, Harvard University, Melbourne, Parkville, Victoria, Australia
Cambridge, Massachusetts
Justin F. Landy, PhD, The University of Chicago
Jonathan Haidt, PhD, New York University Booth School of Business, The University
Stern School of Business, New York University, of Chicago, Chicago, Illinois
New York, New York
Julia J. Lee, PhD, Stephen M. Ross School of
J. Kiley Hamlin, PhD, Department of Business, University of Michigan, Ann Arbor,
Psychology, University of British Columbia, Michigan
Vancouver, British Columbia, Canada
Brittany S. Liu, PhD, Department of Psychology,
Eric G. Helzer, PhD, Johns Hopkins Carey Kalamazoo College, Kalamazoo, Michigan
Business School, Johns Hopkins University,
Tania Lombrozo, PhD, Department of
Baltimore, Maryland
Psychology, University of California, Berkeley,
Joseph Hoover, MS, Department of Psychology, Berkeley, California
University of Southern California,
Los Angeles, California
 Contributors ix

Stephen Loughnan, PhD, Department of Jesse J. Prinz, PhD, Department of Philosophy,


Psychology, The University of Edinburgh, City University of New York Graduate Center,
Edinburgh, United Kingdom New York, New York
Jackson G. Lu, MPhil, Columbia Business Tom Pyszczynski, PhD, Department of
School, Columbia University, New York, New Psychology, University of Colorado
York Colorado Springs, Colorado Springs, Colorado
Edouard Machery, PhD, Department of History Tage S. Rai, PhD, MIT Sloan School of
and Philosophy of Science, University of Management, Massachusetts Institute of
Pittsburgh, Pittsburgh, Pennsylvania Technology, Cambridge, Massachusetts
Bertram F. Malle, PhD, Department of Ross Rogers, MS, Department of Psychology,
Cognitive, Linguistic and Psychological Ohio University, Athens, Ohio
Sciences, Brown University, Providence,
Derek D. Rucker, PhD, Kellogg School of
Rhode Island
Management, Northwestern University,
Katherine McAuliffe, PhD, Evanston, Illinois
Department of Psychology, Boston College,
Laurie R. Santos, PhD, Department of
Chestnut Hill, Massachusetts
Psychology, Yale University, New Haven,
Peter Meindl, PhD, Department of Psychology, Connecticut
University of Pennsylvania,
Julian A. Scheffer, BSc, Department of
Philadelphia, Pennsylvania
Psychological and Brain Sciences,
Brett Mercier, MS, Department of Psychology University of Iowa, Iowa City, Iowa
and Social Behavior, University of California,
Chelsea Schein, BA, Department of Psychology
Irvine, Irvine, California
and Neuroscience, University of North Carolina
Ryan Miller, BA, Department of Psychology, at Chapel Hill, Chapel Hill, North Carolina
Harvard University, Cambridge, Massachusetts
Kate C. S. Schmidt, MA, Department of
Marlon Mooijman, PhD, Kellogg School Philosophy, Washington University in St. Louis,
of Management, Northwestern University, St. Louis, Missouri
Evanston, Illinois
Simone Schnall, PhD, Department of
Matt Motyl, PhD, Department of Psychology, Psychology, University of Cambridge,
University of Illinois at Chicago, Cambridge, United Kingdom
Chicago, Illinois
Azim Shariff, PhD, Department of Psychology,
Darcia Narvaez, PhD, University of Oregon, Eugene, Oregon
Department of Psychology,
Walter Sinnott‑Armstrong, PhD,
University of Notre Dame, Notre Dame, Indiana
Department of Philosophy, Duke University,
David T. Newman, JD, USC Marshall School of Durham, North Carolina
Business, University of Southern California, Los
Jessica A. Sommerville, PhD, Department of
Angeles, California
Psychology, University of Washington, Seattle,
Shaun Nichols, PhD, Department of Philosophy, Washington
The University of Arizona, Tucson, Arizona
Victoria L. Spring, BA, Department of
Gabriela Pavarini, PhD, Department of Psychological and Brain Sciences,
Psychology, University of Cambridge, University of Iowa, Iowa City, Iowa
Cambridge, United Kingdom
Stephen Stich, PhD, Department of Philosophy
Jared Piazza, PhD, Department of Psychology, and the Center for Cognitive Science,
Lancaster University, Lancaster, Rutgers, The State University of New Jersey,
United Kingdom New Brunswick, New Jersey
Jesse L. Preston, PhD, Department of Nina Strohminger, PhD, The Wharton School,
Psychology, University of Warwick, Coventry, University of Pennsylvania,
United Kingdom Philadelphia, Pennsylvania
x Contributors

Sarah Taylor, MA, Department of Psychology, Adam Waytz, PhD, Kellogg School of


Ohio University, Athens, Ohio Management, Northwestern University,
Evanston, Illinois
Elliot Turiel, PhD, Graduate School of
Education, University of California, Berkeley, Scott S. Wiltermuth, PhD,
Berkeley, California USC Marshall School of Business,
University of Southern California,
Eric Luis Uhlmann, PhD, INSEAD, Singapore
Los Angeles, California
Piercarlo Valdesolo, PhD, Department of
Sean P. Wojcik, PhD, Data and Analytics,
Psychology, Claremont McKenna College,
Upworthy, New York, New York
Claremont, California
Andrea M. Yetzer, MA, Department of
Julia W. Van de Vondervoort, MA,
Psychology, Northwestern University, Evanston,
Department of Psychology,
Illinois
University of British Columbia, Vancouver,
British Columbia, Canada Liane Young, PhD, Department of Psychology,
Boston College, Chestnut Hill, Massachusetts
Kees van den Bos, MA, Department of Social
and Organizational Psychology, Jamil Zaki, PhD, Department of Psychology,
Utrecht University, Utrecht, The Netherlands Stanford University, Stanford, California
John Voiklis, PhD, Department of Cognitive, Ting Zhang, PhD, Columbia Business School,
Linguistic and Psychological Sciences, Columbia University, New York, New York
Brown University, Providence, Rhode Island
Talee Ziv, PhD, Department of Psychology,
Felix Warneken, PhD, Department of University of Washington, Seattle, Washington
Psychology, University of Michigan, Ann Arbor,
Michigan
Preface

Cartography used to be tricky business. In mapping out the oceans and land­
masses of the world, mapmakers had to endure attacks from animals, attacks
from other people, starvation, hypothermia, and even worse. Mapping out the
moral domain is no less challenging: The researchers who have written chap­
ters in this volume have had to endure uncertainty and scientific challenges
on the path to reviewing truths in moral psychology. In this volume, we pre­
sent 57 chapters from the freshest minds in moral psychology. These chapters
provide an overview of the strikingly large terrain of the field. Welcome to the
Atlas of Moral Psychology.
When we conceived of the idea of the atlas, we asked contributors to take
a stand on a number of questions that we had developed, including whether
morality was intuitive or deliberative; whether morality involved one, two, or
many processes; whether morality was domain general or domain specific; and
whether morality was the same across cultures. These questions reflected our
own theoretical leanings, and it quickly became clear that moral psychology
had more—and bigger—questions than we had ever imagined.
This volume is so exciting because you can see just how big morality is
and how many other fields it intersects with. Moral psychology started as a
small offshoot of philosophy many years ago, but now it is a microcosm of the
entire field of psychology, with debates about thinking and reasoning, new
understandings of social cognition and the self, questions about animals and
God, and even critical introspection.
This book is structured into 12 sections, each of which explores a conti­
nent of moral psychology: morality and thinking, morality and feeling, moral­
ity and social cognition, morality and intergroup conflict, morality and cul­
ture, morality and the body, morality and beliefs, dynamic moral judgment,
developmental and evolutionary roots of morality, moral behavior, studying

xi
xii Preface

moral judgment, and clarifying morality. Each chapter can be thought of as a


different country, with its own unique perspective on the world. Some chapters
are very close to one another in content, whereas others are quite far apart.
Like real countries, some chapters are very consonant with one another, while
others have clear disagreements.
Despite the diversity of chapters, they are united by a common desire:
to understand the answer to an important question. We have structured the
opening of each chapter to be two simple sentences. The first sentence is the
question we seek to answer, and the second sentence is the answer provided by
the authors. In this way, readers can tailor their reading to whatever questions
they seek to be answered. The questions are listed on the part-opening pages.
Contents

PART I.  Morality and Thinking

 1. Can We Understand Moral Thinking without Understanding Thinking? 3


Joshua D. Greene

 2. Reasoning at the Root of Morality 9


Elliot Turiel

 3. Moral Judgment: Reflective, Interactive, Spontaneous, Challenging,  20


and Always Evolving
Melanie Killen and Audun Dahl

 4. On the Possibility of Intuitive and Deliberative Processes Working 31


in Parallel in Moral Judgment
Kees van den Bos

 5. The Wrong and the Bad 40


Shaun Nichols

PART II.  Morality and Feeling

 6. Empathy Is a Moral Force 49


Jamil Zaki

xiii
xiv Contents

 7. Moral Values and Motivations: How Special Are They? 59


Ryan Miller and Fiery Cushman

 8. A Component Process Model of Disgust, Anger, and Moral Judgment 70


Hanah A. Chapman

 9. A Functional Conflict Theory of Moral Emotions 81


Roger Giner‑Sorolla

10. Getting Emotions Right in Moral Psychology 88


Piercarlo Valdesolo

PART III.  Morality, Social Cognition, and Identity

11. What Do We Evaluate When We Evaluate Moral Character? 99


Erik G. Helzer and Clayton R. Critcher

12. Moral Cognition and Its Basis in Social Cognition and Social Regulation 108
John Voiklis and Bertram F. Malle

13. Morality Is Personal 121


Justin F. Landy and Eric Luis Uhlmann

14. A Social Cognitive Model of Moral Identity 133


Karl Aquino and Adam Kay

15. Identity Is Essentially Moral 141


Nina Strohminger

16. The Core of Morality Is the Moral Self 149


Paul Conway

17. Thinking Morally about Animals 165


Steve Loughnan and Jared Piazza

PART IV.  Morality and Intergroup Conflict

18. Morality Is for Choosing Sides 177


Peter DeScioli and Robert Kurzban

19. Morality for Us versus Them 186


Adam Waytz and Liane Young

20. Pleasure in Response to Outgroup Pain as a Motivator 193


of Intergroup Aggression
Mina Cikara
 Contents xv

21. How Can Universal Stereotypes Be Immoral? 201


Susan T. Fiske

PART V.  Morality and Culture

22. Moral Foundations Theory: On the Advantages of Moral Pluralism 211


over Moral Monism
Jesse Graham, Jonathan Haidt, Matt Motyl, Peter Meindl, Carol Iskiwitch,
and Marlon Mooijman

23. The Model of Moral Motives: A Map of the Moral Domain 223


Ronnie Janoff‑Bulman and Nate C. Carnes

24. Relationship Regulation Theory 231


Tage S. Rai

25. A Stairway to Heaven: A Terror Management Theory Perspective 241


on Morality
Andrea M. Yetzer, Tom Pyszczynski, and Jeff Greenberg

26. Moral Heroes Are Puppets 252


Jeremy A. Frimer

27. Morality: A Historical Invention 259


Edouard Machery

28. The History of Moral Norms 266


Jesse J. Prinz

PART VI.  Morality and the Body

29. The Moralization of the Body: Protecting and Expanding 279


the Boundaries of the Self
Gabriela Pavarini and Simone Schnall

30. Grounded Morality 292


Simon M. Laham and Justin J. Kelly

PART VII.  Morality and Beliefs

31. Moral Vitalism 303


Brock Bastian

32. The Objectivity of Moral Beliefs 310


Geoffrey P. Goodwin
xvi Contents

33. Folk Theories in the Moral Domain 320


Sara Gottlieb and Tania Lombrozo

34. Free Will and Moral Psychology 332


Roy F. Baumeister

35. The Geographies of Religious and Nonreligious Morality 338


Brett Mercier and Azim Shariff

36. The Egocentric Teleological Bias: How Self‑Serving Morality 352


Shapes Perceptions of Intelligent Design
Jesse L. Preston

PART VIII. Dynamic Moral Judgment

37. Moralization: How Acts Become Wrong 363


Chelsea Schein and Kurt Gray

38. Moral Coherence Processes and Denial of Moral Complexity 371


Brittany S. Liu, Sean P. Wojcik, and Peter H. Ditto

39. What Is Blame and Why Do We Love It? 382


Mark D. Alicke, Ross Rogers, and Sarah Taylor

PART IX. Developmental and Evolutionary Roots of Morality

40. Do Animals Have a Sense of Fairness? 393


Katherine McAuliffe and Laurie R. Santos

41. The Infantile Roots of Sociomoral Evaluations 402


Julia W. Van de Vondervoort and J. Kiley Hamlin

42. Atlas Hugged: The Foundations of Human Altruism 413


Felix Warneken

43. The Developmental Origins of Infants’ Distributive Fairness Concerns 420


Jessica A. Sommerville and Talee Ziv

44. Vulnerability‑Based Morality 430


Anton J. M. Dijker

45. The Attachment Approach to Moral Judgment 440


Aner Govrin

46. Ethogenesis: Evolution, Early Experience, and Moral Becoming 451


Darcia Narvaez
 Contents xvii

PART X.  Moral Behavior

47. On the Distinction between Unethical and Selfish Behavior 465


Jackson G. Lu, Ting Zhang, Derek D. Rucker, and Adam D. Galinsky

48. In Search of Moral Equilibrium: Person, Situation, 475


and Their Interplay in Behavioral Ethics
Julia J. Lee and Francesca Gino

49. Unconflicted Virtue 485


Kate C. S. Schmidt

50. Moral Clarity 493


Scott S. Wiltermuth and David T. Newman

PART XI.  Studying Morality

51. Why Developmental Neuroscience Is Critical 505


for the Study of Morality
Jean Decety and Jason M. Cowell

52. Implicit Moral Cognition 516


C. Daryl Cameron, Julian A. Scheffer, and Victoria L. Spring

53. Into the Wild: Big Data Analytics in Moral Psychology 525
Joseph Hoover, Morteza Dehghani, Kate Johnson, Rumen Iliev,
and Jesse Graham

54. Applied Moral Psychology 537


Yoel Inbar

PART XII. Clarifying Morality

55. The Moral Domain 547


Stephen Stich

56. There Is No Important Distinction between Moral 556


and Nonmoral Cognition
Joshua Knobe

57. Asking the Right Questions in Moral Psychology 565


Walter Sinnott‑Armstrong

Index 573
ATLAS OF MORAL PSYCHOLOGY
PART I
MORALITY AND THINKING

Q U E S T I O N S A N S W E R E D I N PA R T I

CHAPTER 1  Can we understand moral thinking without


understanding thinking?

CHAPTER 2  What is the role of reasoning in morality?

CHAPTER 3  Why is moral reasoning fundamental to an explanation


of the development of morality?

CHAPTER 4  Is moral judgment intuitive or deliberative?

CHAPTER 5  How can a theory of moral judgment explain why people think
certain actions are wrong, not simply bad?
CHAPTER 1

Can We Understand Moral Thinking


without Understanding Thinking?

Joshua D. Greene

Can we understand moral thinking without understanding


thinking?

Only up to a point; to understand morality well enough to put it into


a flexibly behaving machine, we must first learn more about how our
brains compose and manipulate structured thoughts.

Nerds of a certain age will recall Command- Paxton, 2009), structured behavioral events
er Data from Star Trek: The Next Genera- (Frankland & Greene, 2015), and people’s
tion, the humanoid android on a personal intentions (Young, Cushman, Hauser, &
quest to become more human. Data’s posi- Saxe, 2007; Young, Camprodon, Hauser,
tronic brain features an “ethical subrou- Pascual-Leone, & Saxe, 2010). Critically,
tine,” a computational add-on designed to these neural pathways, when engaged in
enhance his capacity for moral judgment. moral cognition, appear to be doing the
The field of moral cognition has bad news same things they do in other contexts that
for Commander Data. His ethical subrou- have nothing in particular to do with moral-
tine may be wonderful, but it’s not making ity, such as making trade-offs between risk
him more human. and reward (Knutson, Taylor, Kaufman,
As far as we can tell, there is nothing in Peterson, & Glover, 2005), overriding au-
our brains specifically dedicated to moral tomatic responses based on explicit task
thinking (Greene, 2014; Parkinson et al., demands (Miller & Cohen, 2001), imagin-
2011; Ruff & Fehr, 2014; Young & Dungan, ing distal events (Buckner, Andrews-Hanna,
2012). (But see Hauser, 2006, and Mikhail, & Schacter, 2008; De Brigard, Addis, Ford,
2011, for a dissenting view). Observe human Schacter, & Giovanello, 2013), understand-
brains engaged in moral judgment and you’ll ing who did what to whom (Wu, Waller, &
see neural activity representing the values of Chatterjee, 2007), and keeping track of who
available alternatives (Blair, 2007; Hutcher- believes what (Mitchell, 2009; Saxe, Carey,
son et al., 2015; Moll et al., 2006; Shenhav & Kanwisher, 2004). It’s not just that neu-
& Greene, 2010, 2014; Zaki & Mitchell, roscientific data are too coarse-grained to
2011; Hutcherson et al., 2015), explicit de- distinguish the distinctively moral patterns
cision rules (Greene et al., 2004; Greene & of thinking from the rest. Behavioral stud-

3
4 M O R A L I T Y A N D T H I N K I N G

ies indicate that moral and nonmoral think- Haidt, 2001, 2012; Kohlberg, 1969; Turiel,
ing follow similar patterns and make use 2006). This debate has featured evidence
of shared computational resources when implicating brain regions associated pri-
we evaluate options (Crockett, 2013, 2016; marily with emotion (Ciaramelli, Muccioli,
Cushman, 2013; Krajbich, Hare, Bartling, Ladàvas, & di Pellegrino, 2007; Koenigs et
Morishima, & Fehr, 2015), reason (Paxton, al., 2007; Shenhav & Greene, 2014), along
Ungar, & Greene, 2012), imagine (Amit & with other brain regions associated pri-
Greene, 2012), and understand the minds marily with cognitive control (Cushman,
of others (Moran et al., 2011). Cognitively Murray, Gordon-McKeon, Wharton, &
speaking, morality does not appear to be Greene, 2012; Greene et al., 2004; Paxton
special. & Greene, 2009; Shenhav & Greene, 2014).
If morality isn’t “a thing” in the brain, More recently, this contrast has been recast
then what exactly are researchers who spe- in terms of more basic computational prin-
cialize in moral psychology trying to under- ciples (Crockett, 2013; Cushman, 2013), a
stand? I believe that morality can be a mean- welcome development. But in nearly all of
ingful scientific topic even if moral cognition our attempts to explain moral judgment and
has no distinctive cognitive mechanisms behavior in terms of neural mechanisms, the
of its own. An analogy: Motorcycles and explanations have featured very general pro-
sailboats have very little in common at the cesses, not detailed content. For example, we
mechanistic level, respectively resembling may explain people’s responses to the clas-
nonvehicles such as lawn mowers and kites sic footbridge dilemma (Thomson, 1985) in
more than they resemble each other. Never- terms of affective responses enabled by the
theless, they are both vehicles in good stand- amygdala and the ventromedial prefrontal
ing. They rightly belong to the same catego- cortex (vmPFC), along with a competing
ry because of what they do, not how they cost–benefit decision rule supported by the
do it. In the same way, the various kinds of dorsolateral prefrontal cortex (DLPFC), but
thinking we call moral may be bound to- nowhere in the neural data is there anything
gether, not by their engagement of distinc- specifically related to a trolley, train tracks,
tive cognitive mechanisms but by the com- a footbridge, pushing one person, or saving
mon function they serve: enabling otherwise the lives of five. We know this information
selfish individuals to reap the benefits of is in there, but we’ve only the most coarse-
social existence (Frank, 1988; Gintis, 2005; grained theories about how these details are
Greene, 2013; Haidt, 2012). If this func- represented and transformed in the process
tional account of morality is correct, then of moral judgment.
moral cognition, as a field or subfield, is In behavioral research, detailed content
best understood as a bridge. It’s an attempt plays a more prominent role. We distinguish
to connect the concepts of everyday moral between different ways of causing harm
life—right and wrong, good and bad, virtue (Cushman, Young, & Hauser, 2006; Greene
and vice—to the subpersonal mechanisms of et al., 2009; Spranca, Minsk, & Baron,
the mind and brain. Bridges are exciting to 1991), different kinds of moral violations
build and useful once completed, but they and norms (Graham et al., 2011; Janoff-
are rarely destinations of their own. What Bulman, Sheikh, & Hepp, 2009; Young &
happens after the bridge opens? Where does Saxe, 2011), different moral roles (Gray &
the traffic go? Wegner, 2009), and much more besides. But
On the neuroscientific side, the field of these content-based distinctions and effects,
moral cognition has focused on implicating however interesting and useful they may be,
rather general cognitive functions and cor- seem more like hints—intriguing products of
responding neural regions and networks. the underlying cognitive mechanisms, rather
For example, there has been some debate than descriptions of those mechanisms. If
concerning the relative roles of intuitive Commander Data ever learns to think about
and affective processes on the one hand moral questions like a human, he’ll be sen-
and more controlled, rule-based reasoning sitive to the act/omission distinction, care
on the other (Greene, 2013; Greene, Som- less about people’s intentions when they do
merville, Nystrom, Darley, & Cohen, 2001; things that are disgusting, and so on. But we
 Can We Understand Moral Thinking? 5

currently have no idea how we would actu- ductionism. If “really” understanding moral
ally program or train in these features. thinking requires deciphering the language
The problem, I believe, is that we’re try- of thought, why stop there? To “really” un-
ing to understand moral thinking in the derstand the language of thought, don’t we
absence of a more general understanding of need to understand how populations of neu-
thinking. When you hear about a moral di- rons represent things more generally? And
lemma, involving, say, a trolley headed for to “really” understand that, don’t we need a
five unsuspecting people and a footbridge, better of understanding of neurophysiology?
your brain responds to this string of words And beneath that, must we not understand
by activating a set of conceptual represen- organic chemistry, chemical physics, and so
tations (trolley, footbridge , five , man, on? Does this not lead to the absurd conclu-
etc.). These representations are not merely sion that the only “real” understanding of
activated to form a semantic stew of trolley- anything comes from particle physics?
ness, footbridgeness, and so forth. Rather, I sympathize with this objection, but I
they are combined in a precise way to yield think it goes too far. How far down the re-
a highly specific structured representation ductionist hierarchy we must go depends on
of the situation in question, such that it’s what we’re trying to do and what we get for
the five on the tracks, the man on the foot- our deeper digging. If you’re a sailor, you
bridge, the trolley headed toward the five, need to understand the weather, but under-
and you with the option to push the man in standing the physics and chemistry of the at-
the name of the greater good. What’s more, mosphere probably won’t do you much addi-
our brains naturally construct a representa- tional good. By contrast, if you’re developing
tion of the situation so as to fill in count- models of weather and climate, pushing the
less unstated facts, such as the fact that the bounds of long-range prediction, a detailed
man, if pushed, will fall quickly through the knowledge of the underlying mechanics is
air rather than gently floating to the ground surely essential. Today, much of psychology,
like a feather. Our understanding of how including moral psychology, looks more like
all of this cognitive infrastructure works is sailing than cutting-edge atmospheric mod-
rather limited. In saying this, I do not mean eling. We isolate a specific variable in a spe-
to discount the great strides made by phi- cific and somewhat artificial context, and,
losophers (e.g., Fodor, 1975; Frege, 1976), if all goes well, we can say something about
linguists (e.g., Fillmore, 1982; Talmy, 2000), the general direction and size of the effect of
psychologists (e.g., Johnson-Laird, 1983; manipulating that variable in that context.
Johnson-Laird, Khemlani, & Goodwin, But if our long-term goal is to understand
2015; Kriete, Noelle, Cohen, & O’Reilly, and predict real human behavior in complex
2013; Marcus, 2001; Pinker, 1994, 2007), circumstances, with many behaviorally sig-
and neuroscientists (e.g., Fedorenko, Behr, nificant variables operating simultaneously,
& Kanwisher, 2011; Friederici et al., 2003; we’ll probably have to understand the think-
Hagoort, Hald, Bastiaansen, & Petersson, ing behind that behavior in a more encom-
2004; Huth, de Heer, Griffiths, Theunis- passing way, not just in terms of “effects” but
sen, & Gallant, 2016; Pallier, Devauchell, in terms of the underlying cognitive causes
& Dehaene, 2011) in addressing this large of those effects. I doubt that we’ll need to
problem. What I mean is that we still lack descend into particle physics, but I suspect
a systematic understanding of what David that we’ll have to go significantly deeper
Hume (1739/1978) and other Enlightenment than we currently do. In the best case, we’ll
philosophers called “the Understanding” understand the infrastructure of high-level
and what Fodor (1975) called the “language cognition in sufficient detail that we could
of thought.” program or train Commander Data to think
How well can we understand moral as we do—morally and otherwise.
thinking—or any other kind of high-level Following this hunch, I and my collabora-
thinking—without understanding the un- tors have begun to pursue more basic ques-
derlying mechanics of thought? Pretty well, tions about the nature of high-level cogni-
some might say. This worry about underly- tion and its neural basis: How does the brain
ing mechanisms could just be fetishistic re- combine concepts to form thoughts (Frank-
6 M O R A L I T Y A N D T H I N K I N G

land & Greene, 2015)? How are thoughts correlates of episodic counterfactual thinking.
manipulated in the process of reasoning? Neuropsychologia, 51(12), 2401–2414.
How do thoughts presented in words get Fedorenko, E., Behr, M. K., & Kanwisher, N.
translated into mental images? And how do (2011). Functional specificity for high-level
linguistic processing in the human brain. Pro-
our brains distinguish the things we believe ceedings of the National Academy of Sciences
from the things we desire or merely think of the USA, 108(39), 16428–16433.
about? I don’t know whether these investi- Fillmore, C. (1982). Frame semantics. In The
gations will bear fruit for moral psychology, Linguistic Society of Korea (Ed.), Linguistics
sometime soon or ever. But this kind of re- in the morning calm (pp. 111–137). Seoul:
search seems to me worth pursuing for its Hanshin.
own sake, and there’s a chance that it will Fodor, J. A. (1975). The language of thought
teach us things about morality that we can’t (Vol. 5). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
learn any other way. Press.
Frank, R. H. (1988). Passions within reason:
The strategic role of the emotions. New York:
Norton.
REFERENCES
Frankland, S. M., & Greene, J. D. (2015). An
architecture for encoding sentence meaning
Amit, E., & Greene, J. D. (2012). You see, the
in left mid-superior temporal cortex. Proceed-
ends don’t justify the means: Visual imagery
ings of the National Academy of Sciences of
and moral judgment. Psychological Science,
the USA, 112(37), 11732–11737.
23(8), 861–868.
Frege, G. (1976). Logische untersuchungen (2nd
Blair, R. J. (2007). The amygdala and ventro-
suppl. ed.). Göttingen, Germany: Vanden-
medial prefrontal cortex in morality and psy-
hoeck und Ruprecht.
chopathy. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 11,
Friederici, A. D., Rueschemeyer, S. A., Hahne,
387–392. A., & Fiebach, C. J. (2003). The role of left
Buckner, R. L., Andrews-Hanna, J. R., & Schact- inferior frontal and superior temporal cortex
er, D. L. (2008). The brain’s default network. in sentence comprehension: Localizing syntac-
Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, tic and semantic processes. Cerebral Cortex,
1124(1), 1–38. 13(2), 170–177.
Ciaramelli, E., Muccioli, M., Ladàvas, E., & di Gintis, H. (Ed.). (2005). Moral sentiments and
Pellegrino, G. (2007). Selective deficit in per- material interests: The foundations of cooper-
sonal moral judgment following damage to ation in economic life. Cambridge, MA: MIT
ventromedial prefrontal cortex. Social Cogni- Press.
tive and Affective Neuroscience, 2, 84–92. Graham, J., Nosek, B. A., Haidt, J., Iyer, R., Kol-
Crockett, M. J. (2013). Models of morality. eva, S., & Ditto, P. H. (2011). Mapping the
Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 17(8), 363–366. moral domain. Journal of Personality and So-
Crockett, M. J. (2016). How formal models can cial Psychology, 101(2), 366–385.
illuminate mechanisms of moral judgment and Gray, K., & Wegner, D. M. (2009). Moral type-
decision making. Current Directions in Psy- casting: Divergent perceptions of moral agents
chological Science, 25(2), 85–90. and moral patients. Journal of Personality and
Cushman, F. (2013). Action, outcome, and value Social Psychology, 96(3), 505.
a dual-system framework for morality. Per- Greene, J. (2013). Moral tribes: Emotion, rea-
sonality and Social Psychology Review, 17(3), son, and the gap between us and them. New
273–292. York: Penguin.
Cushman, F., Murray, D., Gordon-McKeon, S., Greene, J. D. (2014). The cognitive neuroscience
Wharton, S., & Greene, J. D. (2012). Judg- of moral judgment and decision-making. In
ment before principle: Engagement of the M. S. Gazzaniga (Ed.), The cognitive neuro-
frontoparietal control network in condemning sciences V (pp. 1013–1023). Cambridge, MA:
harms of omission. Social Cognitive and Af- MIT Press.
fective Neuroscience, 7(8), 888–895. Greene, J. D., Cushman, F. A., Stewart, L. E.,
Cushman, F., Young, L., & Hauser, M. (2006). Lowenberg, K., Nystrom, L. E., & Cohen, J.
The role of conscious reasoning and intuition D. (2009). Pushing moral buttons: The inter-
in moral judgment: Testing three principles of action between personal force and intention in
harm. Psychological Science, 17(12), 1082– moral judgment. Cognition, 111(3), 364–371.
1089. Greene, J. D., Nystrom, L. E., Engell, A. D., Dar-
De Brigard, F., Addis, D. R., Ford, J. H., Schact- ley, J. M., & Cohen, J. D. (2004). The neu-
er, D. L., & Giovanello, K. S. (2013). Remem- ral bases of cognitive conflict and control in
bering what could have happened: Neural moral judgment. Neuron, 44, 389–400.
 Can We Understand Moral Thinking? 7

Greene, J. D., & Paxton, J. M. (2009). Patterns Kohlberg, L. (1969). Stage and sequence: The
of neural activity associated with honest and cognitive-developmental approach to social-
dishonest moral decisions. Proceedings of the ization. In D. A. Goslin (Ed.), Handbook of
National Academy of Sciences of the USA, socialization theory and research (pp. 347–
106(30), 12506–12511. 480). Chicago: Rand McNally.
Greene, J. D., Sommerville, R. B., Nystrom, L. Krajbich, I., Hare, T., Bartling, B., Morishima,
E., Darley, J. M., & Cohen, J. D. (2001). An Y., & Fehr, E. (2015). A common mecha-
fMRI investigation of emotional engagement nism underlying food choice and social deci-
in moral judgment. Science, 293, 2105–2108. sions. PLOS Computational Biology, 11(10),
Hagoort. P., Hald, L., Bastiaansen, M., & Pe- e1004371.
tersson, K. M. (2004). Integration of word Kriete, T., Noelle, D. C., Cohen, J. D., &
meaning and world knowledge in language O’Reilly, R. C. (2013) Indirection and sym-
comprehension. Science, 304(5669), 438–441. bol-like processing in the prefrontal cortex
Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional dog and its ra- and basal ganglia. Proceedings of the Nation-
tional tail: A social intuitionist approach al Academy of Sciences of the USA, 110(41),
to moral judgment. Psychological Review, 16390–16395.
108(4), 814–834. Marcus, G. F. (2001). The algebraic mind: Inte-
Haidt, J. (2012). The righteous mind: Why good grating connectionism and cognitive science.
people are divided by religion and politics. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
New York: Pantheon. Mikhail, J. (2011). Elements of moral cognition:
Hauser, M. D. (2006). The liver and the moral Rawls’ linguistic analogy and the cognitive
organ. Social Cognitive and Affective Neuro- science of moral and legal judgment. New
science, 1(3), 214–220. York: Cambridge University Press.
Hume, D. (1978). A treatise of human nature (L. Miller, E. K., & Cohen, J. D. (2001). An integra-
A. Selby-Bigge & P. H. Nidditch, Eds.). Ox- tive theory of prefrontal cortex function. An-
ford, UK: Oxford University Press. (Original nual Review of Neuroscience, 24, 167–202.
work published 1739) Mitchell, J. P. (2009). Inferences about men-
Hutcherson, C. A., Montaser-Kouhsari, L., tal states. Philosophical Transactions of the
Woodward, J., & Rangel, A. (2015). Emotion- Royal Society of London Series B: Biological
al and utilitarian appraisals of moral dilemmas Sciences, 364(1521), 1309–1316.
are encoded in separate areas and integrated Moll, J., Krueger, F., Zahn, R., Pardini, M., de
in ventromedial prefrontal cortex. Journal of Oliveira-Souza, R., & Grafman, J. (2006).
Neuroscience, 35(36), 12593–12605. Human fronto-mesolimbic networks guide de-
Huth, A. G., de Heer, W. A., Griffiths, T. L., cisions about charitable donation. Proceedings
Theunissen, F. E., & Gallant, J. L. (2016). of the National Academy of Sciences of the
Natural speech reveals the semantic maps that USA, 103, 15623–15628.
tile human cerebral cortex. Nature, 532(7600), Moran, J. M., Young, L. L., Saxe, R., Lee, S. M.,
453–458. O’Young, D., Mavros, P. L., & Gabrieli, J.
Janoff-Bulman, R., Sheikh, S., & Hepp, S. D. (2011). Impaired theory of mind for moral
(2009). Proscriptive versus prescriptive mo- judgment in high-functioning autism. Pro-
rality: Two faces of moral regulation. Journal ceedings of the National Academy of Sciences
of Personality and Social Psychology, 96(3), of the USA, 108(7), 2688–2692.
521–537. Pallier, C., Devauchelle, A. D., & Dehaene, S.
Johnson-Laird, P. N. (1983). Mental models: To- (2011). Cortical representation of the constitu-
wards a cognitive science of language, infer- ent structure of sentences. Proceedings of the
ence, and consciousness (No. 6). Cambridge, National Academy of Sciences of the USA,
MA: Harvard University Press. 108(6), 2522–2527.
Johnson-Laird, P. N., Khemlani, S. S., & Good- Parkinson, C., Sinnott-Armstrong, W., Koralus,
win, G. P. (2015). Logic, probability, and P. E., Mendelovici, A., McGeer, V., & Wheat-
human reasoning. Trends in Cognitive Sci- ley, T. (2011). Is morality unified?: Evidence
ences, 19(4), 201–214. that distinct neural systems underlie moral
Knutson, B., Taylor, J., Kaufman, M., Peterson, judgments of harm, dishonesty, and disgust.
R., & Glover, G. (2005). Distributed neural Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 23(10),
representation of expected value. Journal of 3162–3180.
Neuroscience, 25(19), 4806–4812. Paxton, J. M., Ungar, L., & Greene, J. D. (2012).
Koenigs, M., Young, L., Adolphs, R., Tranel, Reflection and reasoning in moral judgment.
D., Cushman, F., Hauser, M., & Damasio, A. Cognitive Science, 36(1), 163–177.
(2007). Damage to the prefrontal cortex in- Pinker, S. (1994). The language instinct. New
creases utilitarian moral judgments. Nature, York: Harper Perennial Modern Classics.
446, 908–911. Pinker, S. (2007). The stuff of thought: Lan-
8 M O R A L I T Y A N D T H I N K I N G

guage as a window into human nature. New In M. Killen & J. Smetana (Eds.), Handbook
York: Viking. of moral development (pp. 1–30). Mahwah,
Ruff, C. C., & Fehr, E. (2014). The neurobiol- NJ: Erlbaum,
ogy of rewards and values in social decision Wu, D. H., Waller, S., & Chatterjee, A. (2007).
making. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 15(8), The functional neuroanatomy of thematic role
549–562. and locative relational knowledge. Journal of
Saxe, R., Carey, S., & Kanwisher, N. (2004). Cognitive Neuroscience, 19(9), 1542–1555.
Understanding other minds: Linking devel- Young, L., Camprodon, J. A., Hauser, M., Pas-
opmental psychology and functional neuro- cual-Leone, A., & Saxe, R. (2010). Disruption
imaging. Annual Review of Psychology, 55, of the right temporoparietal junction with
87–124. transcranial magnetic stimulation reduces the
Shenhav, A., & Greene, J. D. (2010). Moral judg- role of beliefs in moral judgments. Proceedings
ments recruit domain-general valuation mecha- of the National Academy of Sciences of the
nisms to integrate representations of probability USA, 107(15), 6753–6758.
and magnitude. Neuron, 67(4), 667–677. Young, L., Cushman, F., Hauser, M., & Saxe,
Shenhav, A., & Greene, J. D. (2014). Integrative R. (2007). The neural basis of the interaction
moral judgment: Dissociating the roles of the between theory of mind and moral judgment.
amygdala and ventromedial prefrontal cortex. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sci-
Journal of Neuroscience, 34(13), 4741–4749. ences of the USA, 104(20), 8235–8240.
Spranca, M., Minsk, E., & Baron, J. (1991). Young, L., & Dungan, J. (2012). Where in the
Omission and commission in judgment and brain is morality?: Everywhere and maybe no-
choice. Journal of Experimental Social Psy- where. Social Neuroscience, 7(1), 1–10.
chology, 27(1), 76–105. Young, L., & Saxe, R. (2011). When ignorance
Talmy, L. (2000). Toward a cognitive seman- is no excuse: Different roles for intent across
tics: Concept structuring systems (Vols. 1–2). moral domains. Cognition, 120(2), 202–214.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Zaki, J., & Mitchell, J. P. (2011). Equitable deci-
Thomson, J. (1985). The trolley problem. Yale sion making is associated with neural markers
Law Journal, 94, 1395–1415. of intrinsic value. Proceedings of the National
Turiel, E. (2006). Thought, emotions and social Academy of Sciences of the USA, 108(49),
interactional processes in moral development. 19761–19766.
CHAPTER 2

Reasoning at the Root of Morality

Elliot Turiel

What is the role of reasoning in morality?

Moral decisions involve reasoning about different considerations


and goals, including moral goals of welfare, justice, and rights, and
nonmoral goals, including social coordination.

In psychological writings on the topic of by Nussbaum (1999, p. 71): “human beings


morality, there is sometimes, though not are above all reasoning beings, and . . . the
often enough, an effort to link research and dignity of reason is the primary source of
theory to philosophical approaches. In my human equality.” Promoting the same per-
view, such linkages are positive, because it is spective, Sen (1999, p. 272) maintained that
important for research to be guided by sub- “it is the power of reason that allows us to
stantive definitions of the domain of study. consider our obligations and ideals as well
Given the contested positions often seen in as our interests and advantages. To deny this
the field of psychology, it is not surprising freedom of thought would amount to a se-
that consensus does not exist as to which vere constraint on the reach of our rational-
philosophical–epistemological positions are ity.” Part of human reasoning is choice and
supported by evidence from psychological reflection upon social conditions: “Central
research nor as to which philosophical tra- to leading a human life . . . are the responsi-
ditions to utilize. bilities of choice and reasoning” (Sen, 2006,
My approach is associated, in a gen- p. xiii).
eral way, with philosophical conceptions However, an emphasis on reasoning
of morality centrally involving judgment should not be taken to mean, as sometimes is
or reasoning (e.g., Dworkin, 1977, 1993; mistakenly done, that emotions are regarded
Gewirth, 1978, 1982; Habermas, 1993; as unimportant. Emotions are important in
Nussbaum, 1999, 2000; Okin, 1989; Rawls, the context of reasoning, but they need to
1971, 1993; Sen, 1999, 2006, 2009). The be seen not as forces driving judgments or
substantive aspects of morality formulated decisions, nor as independent of thought:
in these philosophical traditions include “Emotions are not just the fuel that powers
welfare of persons, justice, rights, civil lib- the psychological mechanisms of a reason-
erties, and equalities—as connected with ing creature, they are parts, highly complex
judgment, thought, and reflection. As put and messy parts, of this creature’s reasoning

9
10 M O R A L I T Y A N D T H I N K I N G

itself” (Nussbaum, 2001, p. 3). The inter- developed increased concerns with justice
connections referred to by Nussbaum take and rights (for reviews, see Smetana, 2006,
the form of evaluative appraisals: “I shall and Turiel, 1983, 2002, 2015). The con-
argue that emotions always involve thought figuration of moral judgments differs from
of an object combined with thought of the the configuration of judgments about social
object’s salience or importance; in that sense organizations, with their systems of norms
they always involve appraisal or evaluation” and conventions, as well as from judgments
(Nussbaum, 2001, p. 23). The proposition about the domain of personal jurisdiction.
that emotions entail evaluative appraisals is To state it briefly, judgments in the moral
also present in psychological theory and re- domain are not contingent on rules, author-
search (Frijda, 1986; Lazarus; 1991; Moors ity dictates, or existing practices. By con-
& Scherer, 2013; see also Turiel & Dahl, in trast, conventional norms are judged to be
press). dependent on existing rules, the dictate of
There are several broad questions that those in authority, and common practices in
need to be addressed in psychological per- a social system. The personal domain per-
spectives associated with the philosophical tains to concepts regarding areas of freedom
perspectives on judgment, reasoning, and of choice and autonomy. (These rather brief
reflection. As already noted, one question characterizations derive from much more
bears on the nature of morality, that is, extensive and detailed discussions and re-
how to define the moral domain. A ques- search documentation.)
tion related to such definitions is whether As it has been proposed and found that
morality is a category substantively differ- these domains of social judgment are formed
ent from other categories of judgment about by children in many cultures, the question
social relationships. In turn, questions arise arises as to how it can be that children grow-
regarding how morality develops in onto- ing up with different cultural practices form
genesis, how to explain processes of moral similar judgments. The answer to this ques-
decision making, which in turn are associ- tion is twofold. One part has to do with the
ated with the place of cultural practices in theoretical proposition that children con-
moral development and decision making. struct thinking through their interactions
In this chapter, I briefly outline a position with the world (Kohlberg, 1969, 1971; Piag-
on a definition of morality and its distinc- et, 1932, 1970; Turiel, 1983, 2002; Werner,
tion from other social domains, as well as 1957). In this perspective, development is
on processes of development. In the main, neither genetically nor environmentally de-
I consider explanations of decision making termined but involves constructions in ef-
and their connection with cultural practices. forts to make sense of experiences, social
rules, roles of authorities, social institutions,
and cultural practices.
The Development of Morality and Other The second part of the answer to the ques-
Social Domains tion is that, with regard to morality, a major
source of development is children’s everyday
There are, indeed, correspondences between experiences with others of the same ages
philosophical conceptions of the realm of and of different ages (younger and older
morality and the psychology of morality as children, adults) having to do with harm,
documented by a large number of studies benefits, fairness, equality, and adjudication
conducted over many years in many cultural of disagreements and conflicts. Concrete-
settings. The research has shown that, by ly, these types of experiences include, as a
fairly early ages (4–6 years), children form few examples, children hurting each other
complex configurations of judgments about (physically and emotionally), helping and
welfare, justice, and rights that differ from failing to help, sharing and failing to share,
their judgments about other aspects of social including and excluding others, cooperating
interactions. Young children’s moral think- and failing to cooperate, and treating people
ing is mainly focused on issues of welfare, equally and unequally. Moreover, children
whereas older children’s judgments, while are not solely recipients of “moral” messages
including concerns with welfare, also have from adults. They interact with adults over
 Reasoning at the Root of Morality 11

many of the same issues and observe adults mands of authority to inflict pain and harm
interacting with each other harmoniously on others.
and with conflicts—and sometimes around In actuality, the findings are not as
matters of harm, helping, sharing, cooperat- straightforward as often portrayed. An im-
ing, and equality. portant set of findings, often overlooked, in
These types of experiences, social interac- each of the studies is that variations were
tions, and observations might be connected found in behaviors by experimental condi-
with the formation of judgments about per- tions. For instance, it was found that par-
sons, but they are also centrally involved in ticipants went along with the groups (con-
the formation of moral judgments. A num- federates of the researchers) in erroneously
ber of observational studies with preschool- judging the length of lines in some condi-
ers (Nucci & Turiel, 1978; Nucci, Turiel, tions and not others (e.g., depending on the
& Encarnacion-Gawrych, 1983; Nucci & number of others giving correct and incor-
Weber, 1995) and older children (Nucci & rect responses; see also Ross, Bierbrauer, &
Nucci, 1982a, 1982b; Turiel, 2008) have Hoffman, 1976). These experiments did not
documented that children’s social interac- clearly involve moral issues, but they most
tions around events classified as moral differ likely involved judgments and reflection on
from social interactions around events in the the part of most participants and not simple
conventional and personal domains. Interac- conformity. Asch’s (1952) own interpretation
tions around moral transgressions typically of the finding in the condition in which most
do not involve commands or communica- went along with the group was that partici-
tions about rules and expectations of adults. pants were attempting to understand what
Interactions around moral transgressions appeared to them as a perplexing social situ-
are about the effects of actions on people, ation that involved a conflict between their
the perspectives of others, the need to avoid own perceptions and those of the rest in the
harm, and the pain experienced, as well as group. They were, therefore, led to question
communications about welfare and fairness. their own perceptions and give credibility
By contrast, interactions around convention- to the judgments of the others. The studies
al events revolve around adherence to rules, on bystander intervention, which involved
commands from those in authority, and an moral issues pertaining to helping others in
emphasis on social order. distress (Latané & Darley, 1968), also ob-
tained variations by social contexts. It was
found that participants were more likely to
Processes of Social and Moral intervene and help another when alone than
Decision Making when others were present.
The contextual variations evident in the
It might appear that the findings that the body of research from the social psychologi-
moral judgments of children and adults are cal studies do not simply reflect that indi-
not contingent on adherence to rules nor viduals are pushed and pulled by situational
based on authority dictates and common factors. Rather, they strongly suggest that
practices are inconsistent with a set of still individuals do reason about social situations
well-known findings from classic social in ways that lead them to perceive the vary-
psychological experiments of about 40–60 ing facets of the social situations and that,
years ago. I am referring to experiments on in the process, they apply and attempt to
so-called conformity (Asch, 1952, 1956), coordinate or weigh and balance different
bystander intervention (Latané & Darley, considerations in the decision-making pro-
1968, 1970), and obedience to authority cess. Such different considerations can in-
(Milgram, 1963, 1974). In common portray- clude conflicting moral goals or conflicting
als (e.g., textbooks, essays, and the media), moral and nonmoral goals. The Milgram
the experiments are said to show that indi- experiments provide us with an illustrative
viduals (adults) conform to the group even in example of how behavioral choices can in-
solutions of simple tasks (comparing lengths volve processes of coordination. To review
of lines), fail to intervene to help another in briefly, the central components of the ex-
distress in group settings, and obey the com- periments are that participants were placed
12 M O R A L I T Y A N D T H I N K I N G

in situations in which they were instructed went on that such analyses would have re-
by an experimenter (usually wearing a white vealed that participants were attending both
lab coat) to administer increasing levels of to the harm experienced by the other while
electric shocks (which were not real) to an- wishing to prevent it and to the goals of the
other person (who was an accomplice of scientific enterprise, which they wished to
the researcher) in the guise of the learning maintain. These two goals were in conflict,
of word associations. Participants were told and participants were most likely trying to
that it was a study of the effects of punish- coordinate the two.
ment on learning and memory. In one ex- The findings of different experimental
perimental condition, the experimenter gave conditions in the research (Milgram, 1974)
instructions directly to the participant, who are congruent with the idea that participants
was in the same room, while the so-called were coordinating different considerations
learner, who had been strapped to the elec- and goals. In contrast with the finding in
tric shock apparatus, was not visible but one experimental condition that the major-
within hearing range in an adjacent room. It ity of participants continued administering
is in that condition that approximately 65% electric shocks to another person, in several
of participants continued administering the other conditions most defied the instruc-
shocks to the end of the scale in spite of loud tions of the “authority” and refused to con-
protest from the victim (learner). tinue administering the shocks (Milgram,
The common interpretation that large 1974). In some experimental conditions,
numbers of people obey authority even when the location and proximity of the person re-
commanded to inflict severe pain on another ceiving the shocks were varied in ways that
fails to consider that the experimental situ- increased the salience of the harm (e.g., the
ations included multiple components that learner was in the same room; the partici-
participants attempted to take into account. pant was told to place the learner’s hand on
The most obvious are considerations of the a shock plate). In other conditions, the place
conflict between inflicting physical pain on and role of the experimenter was varied in
another and adhering to the instructions es- ways that decreased the significance of the
tablished by the goals of the experimenter as scientific enterprise and the role of the ex-
conveyed to participants, coupled with the perimenter (e.g., instructions given by tele-
exhortations to continue the experiment be- phone; authority delegated to someone who
cause that is what is required (Turiel, 2002; was not part of the team of researchers). In
Turiel & Smetana, 1984). Milgram’s (1974) most of these other conditions, the large ma-
descriptions of the details of what occurred jority of participants decided to stop shock-
in the experiment indicate that most par- ing the learner and thus defied the experi-
ticipants, regardless of their ultimate deci- menter’s instructions (for more details, see
sion, were experiencing conflict about the Turiel, 2002, and Turiel & Smetana, 1984).
two considerations (e.g., even when con- If we also put into the mix—as explained
tinuing to administer the shocks, partici- by Baumrind (1964, 2013)—the decisions
pants displayed a good deal of anxiety and of the researcher (i.e., Milgram) and those
would stop to tell the experimenter that the who assisted him in carrying out the stud-
“learner” was in pain and danger, that the ies, the coordination becomes further mul-
experimenter should look to see if he was tilayered. Milgram engaged in deception by
all right, that they did not want to harm placing newspaper advertisements to recruit
the learner). Unfortunately, the reactions of participants that stated the study was on
participants were not systematically ana- memory and learning. Those who chose to
lyzed. Such analyses should have examined participate were deceived again by Milgram
the emotional reactions of the participants, and his associates (i.e., the persons in the
the verbal interactions of participants with roles of experimenter and learner) when they
the experimenter, and comments from par- were told face-to-face that the study was on
ticipants to the person (supposedly) receiv- learning and memory, that the person given
ing the electric shocks. It seems likely from the role of learner was another participant
the way Milgram (1974) described what who had chosen to be in the study, and that
 Reasoning at the Root of Morality 13

they would be administering electric shocks A contrasting proposition is that decision


(all falsehoods). At least in the case of the making involves processes of coordination
researcher himself, the acts of deception of different types of substantive judgments.
were based on the decision that deceiving The evidence for this proposition is not lim-
others should be given less priority than the ited to the social psychological studies I have
goals of a scientific enterprise on what they mentioned. Research directly examining
regarded as important questions of whether judgments in the moral domain bearing on
people obey authority in carrying out acts rights, social inclusion and exclusion, and
that inflict physical pain on others1. honesty, trust, and deception shows that
Consequently, the actions of both the re- coordination between different social goals
searchers and the study participants involve is central in decision making. For example,
coordination of moral goals (preventing it has been found in several cultures that
harm), honesty, and the role of authority or children, adolescents, and adults endorse
experts in achieving scientific goals. This in- freedoms of speech, religion, and literacy
terpretation is connected with the findings as rights in response to general questions
of distinct domains of thinking, including and in some situations. However, in some
morality, social conventions, and personal situations they also give lesser priority to
jurisdiction. Processes of coordination are the expression of these rights when they are
often involved in social and moral decisions, in conflict with other moral considerations,
as individuals form different types of judg- such as physical harm (Day, 2014; Helwig,
ments, which they can apply in reflective 1995, 1997; Helwig, Ruck, & Peterson-­
and flexible ways, and because many social Badila, 2014; Helwig & Turiel, 2017; Ruck,
situations are multifaceted in that they in- Abramovitch, & Keating, 1998; Turiel &
clude more than one component. Moreover, Wainryb, 1998). A similar pattern of find-
the different components in social situations ings was obtained in research on concepts of
can be in conflict with each other. Conflicts the fairness of social inclusion (Horn, 2003;
are sometimes between moral and nonmoral Killen, Lee-Kim, McGlothlin, & ­ Stagnor,
considerations and sometimes between dif- 2002; Killen, Pisacane, Lee-Kim, & Ardila-
ferent moral considerations. When making Rey, 2001). Children and adolescents judged
decisions, individuals perceive multiple com- exclusion based on race or gender as wrong,
ponents and often have to give priority to but they also judged exclusion to be accept-
one over another—not always to the moral able when in conflict with other consider-
considerations and goals (as was the case for ations, such as the legitimacy of achieving
some in the Milgram experiments). group goals (e.g., in sport or academic com-
From the perspective of the development petitions).
of distinct developmental pathways within Research on honesty or trust with chil-
domains and processes of coordination in dren and adolescents has yielded compa-
decision making, it is not necessarily the rable results. Honesty is particularly inter-
case that morality is given priority over esting with regard to coordination because
other substantive considerations. It is some- it is often assumed that it is an obviously
times assumed that individuals will give pri- moral good that ought to be unwaveringly
ority to morality and that, insofar as they maintained. As illustrated in philosophical
do not, it is because psychological factors discussions, however, honesty is not always
other than judgment or reasoning take hold. straightforward and does not necessarily
Those assumptions include (1) that one has dictate the moral course of action. Some
insufficient self-control to live up to one’s philosophical discussions have centered on
ideals (Mischel & Mischel, 1976); (2) that Kant’s contention that it is always wrong to
disengagement with morality has occurred lie (Bok, 1978/1999), posing the example of
(Bandura, 2002); (3) that a sufficient moral someone passing a bystander who is soon
identity has not been formed (Blasi, 1984); thereafter asked by a murderer where his in-
or (4) that the development of moral judg- tended victim has gone. It has been argued
ments has not progressed to a sufficiently that in such a situation the moral prescrip-
advanced stage (Kohlberg, 1971). tion to save a life should take precedence
14 M O R A L I T Y A N D T H I N K I N G

over the moral prescription to tell the truth Research also shows that physicians accept
and that there is even a moral obligation for the legitimacy of deception as a means of
the bystander to engage in deception. preventing physical harm to patients (Free-
Research on honesty and deception with man, Rathore, Weinfurt, Schulman, & Sul-
adolescents and adults clearly shows that masy, 1999).
individuals attempt to coordinate differ-
ent moral goals, as well as moral and non-
moral goals. In one study (Perkins & Turiel, Decision Making
2007), groups of 12- to 13-year-olds and and Cultural Practices
16- to 17-year-olds made judgments about
hypothetical situations in which parents A significant component in processes of de-
and peers give directives to an adolescent re- cision making regarding social situations is
garding moral (directives to hit another or disparities in power and control—which was
to engage in racial discrimination), personal seen in the study with the adolescents (Per-
(which club to join, whom to date), and pru- kins & Turiel, 2007). The relevant finding is
dential (homework, riding a motorcycle) ac- that fewer of the adolescents judged decep-
tivities. The actor in the situation does not tion of peers acceptable than deception of
comply with the directive and lies about it. parents for the morally relevant and person-
It was found that the large majority of the al issues. Although the adolescents thought
adolescents in both age groups judged it ac- that the restrictions directed by peers were
ceptable to deceive parents about demands not legitimate, they were less likely to accept
considered morally wrong on the grounds deception of peers than of parents. The dif-
of preventing injustice or harm. The major- ference between how adolescents perceived
ity of adolescents also judged that deception the acceptability of deception of parents
was justified when parents directed personal and friends points to another element of the
choices, although the older adolescents were coordination of different considerations in
more likely to judge deception of parents re- moral and social decision making. The rea-
garding personal choices as acceptable than son that deception of friends is considered
the younger ones (92 vs. 62%). However, less acceptable is that such relationships are
adolescents do not simply regard deception seen as based on equality and mutuality,
as acceptable, because they gave priority to whereas relationships with parents involve
honesty regarding the prudential acts, with greater inequality in power.
the large majority judging that it is not right Although there are differences in power
to deceive parents in those situations (such and status between parents and adolescents,
directives were seen as within parents’ legiti- adolescents did not always accept parental
mate authority to place restrictions bearing directives. They distinguished between ac-
on the potential harm to their children). tivities that they saw as within legitimate
Adolescents, therefore, coordinate judg- parental authority and those they regarded
ments about the value of honesty or trust as not within legitimate parental authority.
with moral, personal, and prudential consid- Those judgments, along with the judgments
erations in different ways. By the age of 12 about deception of parents, reflect both ac-
or 13 years, they make decisions upholding ceptance of and opposition to authority (see
moral judgments about harm and fairness also research on adolescents’ disclosure and
over honesty in some situations. Similarly, nondisclosure with parents; e.g., Finkenau-
judgments about the importance of main- er, Engels, & Meeus, 2002; Kerr & Stat-
taining certain personal choices are bal- tin, 2000; Smetana, Metzger, Gettman, &
anced against the value of honesty—though Campione-Barr, 2006; Smetana, Villalobos,
more uniformly in late than early adoles- Tasopoulos-Chan, Gettman, & Campione-
cence. Similar findings have been obtained Barr, 2009).
in research with adults on their judgments Social opposition and moral resistance are
about deception when aimed at promoting not restricted to adolescents or adults living
well-being and preventing harm in the con- in Western cultures. A number of psycholog-
text of marital relationship with power dif- ical and anthropological studies have shown
ferences (Turiel, Perkins, & Mensing, 2009). that opposition and resistance stem from
 Reasoning at the Root of Morality 15

reasoning and reflection about fairness, • Females act to assert freedoms and avoid
personal choices, social organization, and undue control.
cultural practices. The psychological studies
were conducted in patriarchal cultures with Both Abu-Lughod and Wikan have docu-
social inequalities between males and fe- mented that females, in their everyday lives,
males as part of the social organization and engage in overt and covert actions (includ-
cultural practices. The studies, conducted in ing the use of deception) designed to combat
the Middle East (Guvenc, 2011; Wainryb & restrictions placed on them and thereby sub-
Turiel, 1994), India (Neff, 2001), Colombia vert cultural practices of gender inequality
(Mensing, 2002), and Benin (Conry-­Murray, (see Turiel, 2015, for more extensive discus-
2009), assessed the judgments of adolescent sion).
and adult males and females regarding prac-
tices of inequality in matters pertaining to
education, work, recreational activities, and Some Conclusions about Moral Thought
decision making in the family. For the pres- and Cultures
ent purposes, I highlight several features of
the findings. As already noted, orientations to social re-
lationships and persons are heterogeneous
• Males and females are cognizant of the within individuals and within cultures.
inequalities. Males assert their indepen- Moral judgments about welfare, justice, and
dence and freedom of choice and their rights and about independence are not spe-
right to exert control over females (in cific to cultures or to regions, such as West-
keeping with cultural practices). ern and non-Western parts of the world (e.g.,
• Females are aware of cultural practices Oyserman, Coon, & Kemmelmeier, 2002;
granting independence and control to Raeff, 2006; Spiro, 1993; Turiel, 2002;
males, in some respects accepting social Turiel & Wainryb, 1994, 2000). However,
roles (often due to fear of consequences of moral judgments are not applied in abso-
defiance). lutistic ways, as individuals do attempt to
• Females strive for freedoms and equal- coordinate their moral judgments with so-
ity, evaluating many cultural practices cial, personal, and pragmatic judgments in
involving inequalities between males and social situations with multiple components.
females as unfair. We can consider moral and social judgments
in the patriarchal cultures studied. Whereas
The findings of those studies indicate females are critical of the fairness of cultural
that moral and social judgments within practices of inequality, males are more likely
cultures are heterogeneous in that there are to accept a hierarchical system that places
orientations to personal entitlements and males in dominant positions and females in
independence, as well as morality and in- subordinate positions. This does not mean
terdependence. Moreover, people reflect on that males do not hold concepts of fair-
cultural practices and are able to take criti- ness and equality, as they would apply such
cal perspectives on social organization and moral concepts to many relationships with
coordinate commitments to cultural norms other males and in some instances to females
with moral judgments of unfairness. Hence, (Sen, 1997).
there can be relationships of both harmony Cultures also undergo transformations
and conflict within cultures. These orienta- over time. Such transformations may be a
tions are not limited to people’s judgments. consequence of the types of tensions and
Fieldwork by anthropologists, such as Abu- conflicts over inequalities, rights, and domi-
Lughod’s (1993) work among Bedouins in nation of one group over another evident
rural areas of Egypt and Wikan’s (1996) in the psychological and anthropological
with people living in conditions of poverty studies in the patriarchal cultures. Con-
in Cairo, documents that females in patri- flicts, inequalities, and domination are not
archal cultures act on their judgments. An- restricted to gender and do include differ-
other feature of the research findings is, ences between racial, ethnic, and social class
therefore, that: groups. The philosopher Gregory Vlastos
16 M O R A L I T Y A N D T H I N K I N G

articulated the possible sources of cultural within cultures. In some respects—not all by
and societal changes as follows: “The great any means—there are more commonalities
historical struggles for social justice have in perspectives of those in similar positions
centered about some demand for equal in different cultures than between those in
rights: the struggle against slavery, political different positions in the same culture.
absolutism, economic exploitation, the dis-
franchisement of women, colonialism, racial
oppression” (1962, p. 31). NOTE
The conclusions drawn by Vlastos are
1. In an interesting twist, Baumrind (2013) ex-
consistent with findings that indicate that plained how the actions of the associates
there are “collective practices” that are at could be construed as “obedience to author-
the same time contested practices. This ity” by their adherence to the instructions of
seeming contradiction occurs because prac- the person in a position of authority who re-
tices can appear to be collective in that they cruited them to play roles entailing deception
are part of public pronouncements and/or in the research they carried out. They went
public documents and endorsed by those in along with the “legitimate authority” who in-
positions of power and authority. Yet those structed them to engage in acts that resulted
in lower positions in the social hierarchy in emotional distress to the participants, and
who regard them as unfair contest those thereby gave priority to the perceived worthy
scientific goals over preventing harm.
practices.
The findings of differences in perspec-
tives of different groups (e.g., females and REFERENCES
males) in social hierarchies have implica-
tions for how to characterize differences and Abu-Lughod, L. (1993). Writing women’s
similarities among cultures. In addition to worlds: Bedouin stories. Berkeley: University
commonalities between cultures (such as in of California Press.
moral judgments) and differences between Asch, S. E. (1952). Social psychology. Engle-
cultures (such as in ways moral judgments wood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
are applied), there can be some commonali- Asch, S. E. (1956). Studies of independence and
conformity: A minority of one against a unan-
ties in social perspectives between those in imous majority. Psychological Monographs,
different cultures who occupy similar posi- 70(9).
tions in their respective social hierarchies Bandura, A. (2002). Selective moral disengage-
and which, in turn, make for differences in ment in the exercise of moral agency. Journal
perspectives of those of different positions of Moral Education, 31, 101–119.
within their own culture. Figure 2.1 outlines Baumrind, D. (1964). Some thoughts on the eth-
such relations of perspectives. The general ics of research: After reading Milgram’s “Be-
proposition is that there are multiple layers havioral Study of Obedience.” American Psy-
of similarities and differences between and chologist, 19, 421–423.

Culture A Culture B

Higher in the hierarchy Similar Higher in the hierarchy


(wealthier, male, greater power (wealthier, male, greater power
and control) and control)

similar and similar and


different different
Lower in the hierarchy (poorer, Similar Lower in the hierarchy (poorer,
female, lesser power and female, lesser power and
control) control)

FIGURE 2.1.  A schematic view of cultural comparisons.


 Reasoning at the Root of Morality 17

Baumrind, D. (2013). Is Milgram’s deceptive re- Helwig, C. C., & Turiel, E. (2017). The psy-
search ethically acceptable? Theoretical and chology of children’s rights. In M. Ruck, M.
Applied Ethics, 2, 1–18. Peterson-Badali, & M. Freeman (Eds.), Hand-
Blasi, A. (1984). Moral identity: Its role in moral book of children’s rights: Global and multi-
functioning. In J. L. Gewirtz & W. M. Kur- disciplinary perspectives (pp. 132–148). New
tines (Eds.), Morality, moral behavior, and York: Routledge.
moral development (pp. 128–139). New York: Horn, S. S. (2003). Adolescents reasoning about
Wiley. exclusion from social groups. Developmental
Bok, S. (1999). Lying: Moral choice in public and Psychology, 39, 71–84.
private life. New York: Vintage Books. (Origi- Kerr, M., & Stattin, H. (2000). What parents
nal work published 1979) know, how they know it, and several forms of
Conry-Murray, C. (2009). Adolescent and adult adolescent adjustment: Further support for a
reasoning about gender roles and fairness in reinterpretation of monitoring. Developmen-
Benin, West Africa. Cognitive Development, tal Psychology, 36, 366–380.
24, 207–219. Killen, M., Lee-Kim, J., McGlothlin, H., & Stag-
Day, K. (2014). The right to literacy and cultural nor, C. (2002). How children and adolescents
change: Zulu adolescents in post-apartheid value gender and racial exclusion. Monographs
rural South Africa. Cognitive Development, of the Society for Research in Child Develop-
29, 81–94. ment, 67(4, Serial No. 271).
Dworkin, R. (1977). Taking rights seriously. Killen, M., Pisacane, K., Lee-Kim, J., & Ardi-
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. la-Rey, A. (2001). Fairness or stereotypes?:
Dworkin, R. (1993). Life’s dominion: An argu- Young children’s priorities when evaluating
ment about abortion, euthanasia, and indi- group exclusion and inclusion. Developmental
vidual freedom. New York: Knopf. Psychology, 37, 587–596.
Finkenauer, C., Engels, R. C. M. E., & Meeus, Kohlberg, L. (1969). Stage and sequence: The
W. (2002). Keeping secrets from parents: Ad- cognitive-developmental approach to social-
vantages and disadvantages of secrecy in ado- ization. In D. Goslin (Ed.), Handbook of so-
lescence. Journal of Youth and Adolescence, cialization theory and research (pp. 347–480).
2, 123–136. Chicago: Rand McNally.
Freeman, V. G., Rathore, S. S., Weinfurt, K. P., Kohlberg, L. (1971). From is to ought: How to
Schulman, K. A., & Sulmasy, D. P. (1999). commit the naturalistic fallacy and get away
Lying for patients: Physician deception of with it in the study of moral development. In
third-party payers. Archives of Internal Medi- T. Mischel (Ed.), Psychology and genetic epis-
cine, 159, 2263–2270. temology (pp. 151–235). New York: Academic
Frijda, N. (1986). The emotions. New York: Press.
Cambridge University Press. Latané, B., & Darley, J. M. (1968). Group inhibi-
Gewirth, A. (1978). Reason and morality. Chi- tion of bystander intervention in emergencies.
cago: University of Chicago Press. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
Gewirth, A. (1982). Human rights: Essays on 10, 215–221.
justification and applications. Chicago: Uni- Latané, B., & Darley, J. M. (1970). The unre-
versity of Chicago Press. sponsive bystander: Why doesn’t he help?
Guvenc, G. (2011). Women’s construction of New York: Appleton-Crofts.
familial-gender identities and embodied sub- Lazarus, N. (1991). Emotion and adaptation.
jectivities in Saraycik, Turkey. Unpublished New York: Oxford University Press.
manuscript, Isik University, Istanbul, Turkey. Mensing, J. F. (2002). Collectivism, individu-
Habermas, J. (1993). Justification and applica- alism, and interpersonal responsibilities in
tion. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. families: Differences and similarities in social
Helwig, C. C. (1995). Adolescents’ and young reasoning between individuals in poor, urban
adults’ conceptions of civil liberties: Freedom families in Colombia and the United States.
of speech and religion. Child Development, Unpublished doctoral dissertation, University
66, 152–166. of California, Berkeley, CA.
Helwig, C. C. (1997). The role of agent and social Milgram, S. (1963). Behavioral study of obedi-
context in judgments of freedom of speech and ence. Journal of Abnormal and Social Psy-
religion. Child Development, 68, 484–495. chology, 67, 371–378.
Helwig, C. C., Ruck, M., & Peterson-Badali, M. Milgram, S. (1974). Obedience to authority.
(2014). Rights, civil liberties, and democracy. New York: Harper & Row.
In M. Killen & J. G. Smetana (Eds.), Hand- Mischel, W., & Mischel, H. (1976). A cognitive
book of moral development (2nd ed., pp. 46– social-learning approach to morality and self-
69). Mahwah, NJ: Taylor & Francis. regulation. In T. Lickona (Ed.), Moral devel-
18 M O R A L I T Y A N D T H I N K I N G

opment and behavior: Theory, research, and and interdependence. Human Development,
social issues (pp. 84–107). New York: Holt, 49, 96–121.
Rinehart & Winston. Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of justice. Cambridge,
Moors, A., & Scherer, K. R. (2013). The role of MA: Harvard University Press.
appraisal in emotion. In M. D. Robinson, E. R. Rawls, J. (1993). Political liberalism. New York:
Watkins, & E. Harmon-Jones (Eds.), Hand- Columbia University Press.
book of cognition and emotion (pp. 131–155). Ross, L., Bierbrauer, G., & Hoffman, S. (1976).
New York: Guilford Press. The role of attributional processes in confor-
Neff, K. D. (2001). Judgments of personal au- mity and dissent: Revisiting the Asch situa-
tonomy and interpersonal responsibility in the tion. American Psychologist, 31, 148–157.
context of Indian spousal relationships: An ex- Ruck, M. D., Abramovitch, R., & Keating, D.
amination of young people’s reasoning in My- P. (1998). Children’s and adolescents’ under-
sore, India. British Journal of Developmental standings of rights: Balancing nurturance and
Psychology, 19, 233–257. self-determination. Child Development, 69,
Nucci, L. P., & Nucci, M. S. (1982a). Children’s 404–417.
responses to moral and social conventional Sen, A. (1997, July 14, 21). Human rights and
transgressions in free-play settings. Child De- Asian values. The New Republic, pp. 33–39.
velopment, 53, 1337–1342. Sen, A. (1999). Development as freedom. New
Nucci, L. P., & Nucci, M. S. (1982b). Children’s York: Knopf.
social interactions in the context of moral and Sen, A. (2006). Identity and violence: The illu-
conventional transgressions. Child Develop- sion of destiny. New York: Norton.
ment, 53, 403–412. Sen, A. (2009). The idea of justice. Cambridge,
Nucci, L. P., & Turiel, E. (1978). Social interac- MA: Harvard University Press.
tions and the development of social concepts Smetana, J. G. (2006). Social domain theory:
in preschool children. Child Development, 49, Consistencies and variations in children’s
400–407. moral and social judgments. In M. Killen &
Nucci, L. P., Turiel, E., & Encarnacion-Gaw- J. G. Smetana (Eds.), Handbook of moral de-
rych, G. (1983). Children’s social interactions velopment (pp. 119–153). Mahwah, NJ: Erl-
and social concepts: Analyses of morality and baum.
convention in the Virgin Islands. Journal of Smetana, J. G., Metzger, A., Gettman, D. C., &
Cross-Cultural Psychology, 14, 469–487. Campione-Barr, N. (2006). Disclosure and
Nucci, L. P., & Weber, E. (1995). Social inter- secrecy in adolescent–parent relationships.
actions in the home and the development of Child Development, 77, 201–217.
young children’s conceptions of the personal. Smetana, J. G., Villalobos, M., Tasopoulos-
Child Development, 66, 1438–1452. Chan, M., Gettman, D. C., & Campione-
Nussbaum, M. C. (1999). Sex and social justice. Barr, N. (2009). Early and middle adolescents’
New York: Oxford University Press. disclosure to parents about activities in dif-
Nussbaum, M. C. (2000). Women and human ferent domains. Journal of Adolescence, 32,
development: The capabilities approach. 693–713.
Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Spiro, M. (1993). Is the Western conception of
Nussbaum, M. C. (2001). Upheavals of thought: the self “peculiar” within the context of the
The intelligence of emotions. Cambridge, UK: world cultures? Ethos, 21, 107–153.
Cambridge University Press. Turiel, E. (1983). The development of social
Okin, S. M. (1989). Justice, gender, and the fam- knowledge: Morality and convention. Cam-
ily. New York: Basic Books. bridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Oyserman, D., Coon, H. M., & Kemmelmeier, Turiel, E. (2002). The culture of morality: Social
M. (2002). Rethinking individualism and col- development, context, and conflict. Cam-
lectivism: Evaluation of theoretical assump- bridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
tions and meta-analyses. Psychological Bul- Turiel, E. (2008). Thought about actions in so-
letin, 128, 3–72. cial domains: Morality, social conventions,
Perkins, S. A., & Turiel, E. (2007). To lie or not and social interactions. Cognitive Develop-
to lie: To whom and under what circumstanc- ment, 23, 126–154.
es. Child Development, 78, 609–621. Turiel, E. (2015). Moral development. In W. F.
Piaget, J. (1932). The moral judgment of the Overton & P. C. Molenaar (Eds.), Handbook
child. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. of child psychology: Vol. 1. Theory and method
Piaget, J. (1970). Psychology and epistemology. (7th ed., pp. 484–522). Hoboken, NJ: Wiley.
New York: Viking Press. Turiel, E., & Dahl, A. (in press). The develop-
Raeff, C. (2006). Multiple and inseparable: Con- ment of domains of moral and conventional
ceptualizing the development of independence norms, coordination in decision-making, and
 Reasoning at the Root of Morality 19

the implications of social opposition. In K. Turiel, E., & Wainryb, C. (1998). Concepts of
Bayertz & N. Roughley (Eds.), The normative freedoms and rights in a traditional hierarchi-
animal: On the anthropological significance cally organized society. British Journal of De-
of social, moral, and linguistic norms. Ox- velopmental Psychology, 16, 375–395.
ford, UK: Oxford University Press. Turiel, E., & Wainryb, C. (2000) Social life in
Turiel, E., Perkins, S. A., & Mensing, J. F. (2009). cultures: Judgments, conflicts, and subversion.
Judgments about deception in marital rela- Child Development, 71, 250–256.
tionships. Unpublished manuscript, University Vlastos, G. (1962). Justice and equality. In R. B.
of California, Berkeley, CA. Brandt (Ed.), Social justice (pp. 31–72). Engle-
Turiel, E., & Smetana, J. G. (1984). Social wood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
knowledge and social action: The coordina- Wainryb, C., & Turiel, E. (1994). Dominance,
tion of domains. In W. M. Kurtines & J. L. subordination, and concepts of personal enti-
Gewirtz (Eds.), Morality, moral behavior, and tlements in cultural contexts. Child Develop-
moral development: Basic issues in theory and ment, 65, 1701–1722.
research (pp. 261–282). New York: Wiley. Werner, H. (1957). Comparative psychology of
Turiel, E., & Wainryb, C. (1994). Social reason- mental development. New York: International
ing and the varieties of social experience in cul- Universities Press.
tural contexts. In H. W. Reese (Ed.), Advances Wikan, U. (1996). Tomorrow, God willing: Self-
in child development and behavior (Vol. 25, made destinies in Cairo. Chicago: University
pp. 289–326). New York: Academic Press. of Chicago Press.
CHAPTER 3

Moral Judgment
Reflective, Interactive, Spontaneous,
Challenging, and Always Evolving

Melanie Killen
Audun Dahl

Why is moral reasoning fundamental to an explanation of


the development of morality?

Reasoning is the process by which humans create and apply prin‑


ciples for how individuals ought to treat one another; it is neither
innate nor inculcated, but constructed through everyday interactions
over the course of development.

A Conceptualization of Morality In fact, most people in all communities are


concerned with the moral issues of others’
The psychological study of morality inves- welfare, rights, and fairness (Appiah, 2005;
tigates how people relate to moral issues by Gewirth, 1978; Nussbaum, 1999; Sen,
applying, endorsing, enforcing, defending, 2009; Turiel, 2006). Moreover, the denial of
coordinating, and giving priority to moral just and fair treatment of others prevents the
principles. By moral principles, we mean full capacities of human cooperation, cog-
principles protecting others’ welfare, rights, nition, and culture to flourish. As has been
fairness, and justice. This definition of mo- proposed and well documented, the decline
rality implies that moral considerations af- of violence among humankind over the past
fect people’s lives in numerous ways: People several millennia can be attributed to chang-
condemn violence, are outraged by injustice, es in societal organizations that have pro-
applaud selflessness, are torn by dilemmas, moted increases in moral reasoning (Pinker,
and often seek to promote the well-being 2011). Without a doubt, morality is a core
of others. Across these diverse situations, feature of humanity.
people retain their moral concerns even How moral principles arise, where they
though the elicited thoughts, emotions, and come from, the biological correlates and
behaviors that accompany such moral con- moral orientations of the construction of such
cerns often vary with the changing morally principles is at the center of current moral
relevant circumstances (Nussbaum, 2013). psychological inquiry (Schein & Gray, 2017;

20
 Moral Judgment 21

Turiel, 2014). In this chapter, we discuss the and (2) affiliations with groups and the de-
developmental origins of morality, drawing velopment of group identity are important
on theories and empirical research in devel- for the development of the individual and
opmental science. Understanding the origins for becoming part of a community but also
and developmental changes of any phenom- contribute to challenges to morality with
enon provides insights into sources of in- the emergence of prejudicial (unfair) judg-
fluence, change, and evolution throughout ments, discriminatory behavior, and social
the life course. Although morality was once inequalities.
thought to be the province of adulthood (chil- With these points in mind, we aim to ex-
dren were viewed as selfish, antagonistic, or plain why individuals both uphold deeply
as a blank slate), a large body of research has felt moral principles yet, at the same time,
demonstrated that children are social beings, give priority to nonmoral concerns in cer-
oriented toward others, motivated to help tain contexts. Developmental research pro-
others and to cooperate, and, beginning in vides the basis for identifying the complex-
early childhood, capable of drawing categori- ity of morality throughout the lifespan, how
cal distinctions between moral considerations morality can be fostered or hindered, and
and other social organizational norms (Kil- the role of social cognition and group affili-
len & Smetana, 2015). Moreover, starting ation as part of the acquisition and develop-
at preschool age, children justify moral judg- ment of morality.
ments by reference to fairness, rights, or oth-
ers’ welfare, whereas they justify conventional
judgments by reference to rules, authority, Defining Morality
and social traditions. Over several decades,
empirical evidence has demonstrated that the We begin with our definition of morality,
developmental emergence of morality stems the criteria that have been generated and
out of social interactions, both with peers and empirically validated, and how morality is
through adult–child exchanges, and changes a central part of psychological function-
slowly over the life course (Killen & Smetana, ing and development. To define morality
2015). Morality is constructed through social for psychological science means situating it
interactions and observations of events in the within the broader realm of social consid-
world, involving evaluation, reflection, and erations that are brought to bear on deci-
judgments about the fair treatment of others sion making, which includes societal con-
(Dahl & Killen, 2017; Piaget, 1932; Turiel, cerns about group functioning, traditions,
2006). and conventions, as well as psychological
The application of moral judgments to concerns about autonomy, personal choice,
social life is not always easy, however, and and individual prerogatives. Our model is a
many different theories have been proposed social science one, drawing on philosophi-
about what makes it difficult, why apparent cal categories to define morality as prescrip-
discrepancies between judgments and action tive norms about how others ought to treat
exist, and why atrocities are committed. one another with respect to justice, fairness,
The question of why humans do not always others’ welfare, equality, and rights (see
uphold moral codes is a very complex issue Gewirth, 1978; Scheffler, 2015; Sen, 2009).
and necessitates providing a clear defini- These norms, though, are not coded in the
tion of morality and its relation to thought, DNA, nor solely transmitted by adults, nor
emotion, and behavior. In this short chapter learned exclusively through explicit teach-
we address these issues through our discus- ing. Instead, a large body of developmental
sion of two substantial points about moral- science research has documented how evalu-
ity, based on developmental science theory ations of moral transgressions (violations of
and data. These points are: (1) children’s fair and equal treatment of others) evolve
first moral concerns and understandings are throughout childhood as children become
constructed from early social orientations more capable of making inferences about
through everyday interactions established their own and others’ social experiences,
in infancy, through observations of help- reading emotional cues of others, and deter-
ing and responding to the distress of others; mining what makes an act wrong.
22 M O R A L I T Y A N D T H I N K I N G

In general, the findings have revealed that ance with unfair authority practices. Gen-
children, beginning around 3–4 years of age eralizability enables morality to be those
and becoming more systematic over the next sets of norms and expectations that apply to
7–8 years, use criteria such as impartiality, individuals and groups from different com-
generalizability, and autonomy from author- munities, cultures, and nationalities, as has
ity when evaluating decisions about fairness, been shown with expectations regarding the
equality, and rights and refer to an alterna- wrongfulness of child abuse, for example.
tive set of criteria, such as rule contingency, Thus the criteria that individuals use indi-
alterability, and group norms, when evalu- cate that morality is more than an arbitrary
ating decisions involving cultural traditions, set of rules agreed upon by individuals in a
practices, and conventions (Killen & Smeta- culture, even though this might be what some
na, 2015; Malti & Ongley, 2014; Nucci, individuals articulate when asked “What
2001; Smetana, Jambon, & Ball, 2014; Turi- is morality?” Conventions that structure
el, 2006). As one brief example, when asked groups and make groups work well do not
about the rule “Do not hit others,” children necessarily provide the foundation necessary
view unprovoked hitting as wrong even when for fair and just treatment of others. Many
told that a teacher said it was all right (“It’s examples of cultural norms that perpetuate
still wrong because it would be mean, and harassment, victimization, and the unfair
you could get a bruise which would hurt”), and unjust treatment of its members exist
conveying their understanding that the act is throughout history and continue to be per-
not contingent on authority mandates (e.g., vasive in current societies around the world.
autonomy from authority). These data indi- To effect change and improve the quality of
cate that assessing children’s moral evalua- life for individuals across the globe, conflicts
tions by coding whether they state that an between cultural conventions and moral
act is “good” or “bad” does little to convey principles are debated, evaluated and recti-
the depth of their moral knowledge; nor does fied. Extensive developmental data reveal
it provide critical and unique evidence for that children and adolescents, just as adults
moral judgments in childhood, given that do, spend much of their social life debating,
many acts that are “good” or “bad” have evaluating, reflecting, and determining how
little to do with morality. best to resolve conflicts that entail concerns
Moreover, around the globe, children of unfairness and unequal treatment of oth-
and adolescents formulate obligatory ex- ers.
pectations that apply across individuals
and groups, such as those pertaining to the
right to be treated with fairness, protection Why Do Otherwise Rational
of welfare, and equality (Helwig, Ruck, & Individuals Give Priority
Peterson-Badali, 2014; Wainryb, Shaw, & to Nonmoral Considerations?
Maianu, 1998). Acts of unprovoked harm,
the denial of resources, property destruc- From infancy to adulthood, moral knowl-
tion, and lack of free speech are viewed as edge emerges and becomes complex, reflect-
violations of moral principles about fair- ing underlying criteria that reveal a system-
ness and protection of others’ welfare that atic capacity for reasoning about morality.
require an impartial perspective, indepen- At the same time, children’s awareness and
dence from authority jurisdiction, and an knowledge about other aspects of social
application across contexts. life—such as self-identity, group identity, so-
Autonomous decision making is a neces- cial institutions, social group goals, personal
sary aspect of morality because authority projects and ambitions, others’ intentions,
expectations are not always consistent with and the facts of the world—become more
principles of morality. Providing autono- enriched, providing a greater level of connec-
mous evaluations of authority mandates tions to others in social life (Killen, Mulvey,
with respect to fairness and equality be- & Hitti, 2013). This increased awareness and
comes a way of determining whether cul- knowledge of social complexity, however,
tural norms, laws, and customs are unfair, also generates norms, values, and judgments
creating the context for victimization and that potentially challenge an emerging under-
harassment that could result from compli- standing and valuing of moral principles.
 Moral Judgment 23

Aspects of human psychological function- decision making, whether and how exter-
ing that reflect moral issues are sometimes nal sources of influence change the course
coordinated and coherent and, at other of moral development, and how conceptions
times, contradictory and antagonistic. Im- of morality change as human cognitive and
portantly, disagreement does not undermine social capacities develop concurrently. What
morality but often helps individuals to under- do we know about how morality emerges?
stand just what makes an act right or wrong
and to determine what aspects of the con-
text need to be considered to make a moral The Constructive Origins of Morality:
judgment. This is true not only in adult life It’s Neither Innate nor Learned
but during childhood as well, during which
peer-focused discussions serve a particularly The origin of morality is a fundamental
powerful role for the facilitation and acquisi- issue with implications for psychological
tion of moral concepts. Discussion, debate, accounts of morality. An abundance of evi-
and engagement enable individuals to un- dence indicates that morality is neither in-
derstand different perspectives of a complex nate nor learned, nor is it “both”; morality is
system embodied by moral principles. An constructed through social interactions and
adequate explanation of how people grapple cognitive reflection (see Dahl, 2014; Spen-
with such dilemmas, sometimes giving prior- cer et al., 2009). In abandoning the innate–
ity to nonmoral considerations, requires an learned dichotomy, we adopt a fundamen-
adequate account of the moral concerns and tally different—constructivist—framework
understandings that individuals bring into for understanding how moral capabilities
such situations pertaining to others’ welfare, emerge. Our proposition is that the first
rights, equality, and fairness. moral concerns and understandings are con-
structed from earlier, nonmoral capabilities
through social interactions. During the first
Social Cognitive Development: 2 years, infants observe and engage in mor-
A Developmental Science Approach ally relevant behaviors, such as helping and
to Morality harming others, without yet viewing such
actions as morally right or wrong. However,
Thus a general tenet of a social cognitive de- through repeated experiences in such inter-
velopmental approach is that children, ado- actions, children eventually form explicit
lescents, and adults are thinking, reasoning judgments reflecting moral evaluations, usu-
beings who reflect on social experiences and ally around the 2nd birthday and into the
social events in everyday life. Social cogni- 3rd year (Dahl, 2014).
tive developmental research, with specific Infants demonstrate social orientations
variants of this approach that have been soon after birth (Trevarthen, 1979). The
formulated within this broad perspective, reciprocal nature of their interactions with
such as social domain theory (Dahl, 2014; caregivers become particularly pronounced
Smetana et al., 2014; Turiel, 2006) and the with the onset of the social smile, around
social reasoning developmental model (Kil- 4–6 weeks after birth (Lavelli & Fogel,
len & Rutland, 2011; Rutland & Killen, 2002). Through their observations of and
2017), has reflected a broad research pro- interactions with others, they gradually
gram designed to analyze the origins, acqui- acquire an understanding of others and a
sition, and developmental trajectory of mo- sensitivity to the emotional signals of oth-
rality from infancy to adulthood. To do this, ers (Barrett & Campos, 1987; Dunn, 1988;
morality has to be measured using a wide Hoffman, 2000).
range of assessments, documenting individ- From a constructivist point of view, these
uals’ behavior, emotion attributions, judg- early orientations, understandings, and sen-
ments, and reasoning in multiple contexts sitivities form the foundations for subse-
(Malti, Gasser, & Buchmann, 2009; Malti quent moral acquisitions. They guide chil-
& Ongley, 2014; Rizzo & Killen, 2016). A dren’s interactions with others and how they
developmental science approach addresses make sense of others’ signals and actions.
fundamental questions about how early in Gradually, children go from simply being
development humans are capable of moral curious or distressed when others are dis-
24 M O R A L I T Y A N D T H I N K I N G

tressed to comforting others; they become for one over the other), not categorical judg-
increasingly competent helpers; they become ments (e.g. “this puppet is bad and should not
aware of others’ expectations of them; and hit the other puppet”), and to apply such pref-
their use of physical aggression declines erences to puppets, not to themselves or other
from late infancy to school age (Dunn, 2014; people (Dahl, Schuck, & Campos, 2013;
Hastings, Zahn-Waxler, & McShane, 2006; Dahl, 2014). Infants’ puppet preferences
Schmidt & Sommerville, 2011). However, it are, by most definitions, precursors to moral
is not until around the 3rd year of life that judgments. This is because these responses do
children’s social and cognitive experiences not reflect an obligation to act in a prescrip-
and abilities enable them to express and jus- tive manner toward others.
tify moral judgments, protest against moral Contemporary nativist theo.ries propose
violations, distribute resources with con- that infants’ experiences are insufficient to
cerns for equality and fairness, and show explain these social preferences. However,
clear signs of guilt or shame (Smetana et al., there is no research on whether the emer-
2012; Vaish, Missana, & Tomasello, 2011). gence of looking and reaching preferences is
tied to specific social experiences. What we
do know is that most infants are involved
Why Is Morality Not Innate?
in reciprocal social interactions with their
The constructivist approach, which argues caregivers from the earliest periods of life
that there are qualitative changes in chil- (Trevarthen, 1979; Tronick, 1989). There is
dren’s orientations toward others’ welfare, currently no evidence to suggest that infants
differs from nativist theories, which argue would develop the documented social pref-
that at least some components of morality erences without engaging in and observing
are innate. Importantly, nativists are not social interactions in everyday life over the
denying that infants lack certain moral ca- course of several months. More generally,
pabilities. For instance, infants do things given the constant interplay of environments,
that—in older children—would be consid- organisms, and genes at all stages of devel-
ered distinctly immoral. In one study, over opment (prenatal, perinatal, and postnatal),
80% of 1-year-olds used force against an- some researchers have questioned whether
other person, by hitting, biting, or kicking, we can meaningfully distinguish between
without any provocation or sign of frustra- “innate” and “non-innate” psychological
tion (Dahl, 2015). And although infants characteristics (e.g. Spencer et al., 2009).
show some responsiveness to signals of dis- In sum, infants from a very early age show
tress in others, only a minority of such sig- complex sensitivities to social interactions,
nals elicit concerned or comforting behavior some of which are reflected in their prefer-
until well into the 2nd year (Hay, Nash, & ential looking and reaching toward helpful
Pedersen, 1981; Roth-Hanania, Davidov, & puppets. Yet we do not think these sensitivi-
Zahn-Waxler, 2011; Zahn-Waxler, Radke- ties are properly characterized as innate (as
Yarrow, Wagner, & Chapman, 1992). For they are observed after months of social in-
these and other reasons, most researchers teractions), nor do we consider these sensitiv-
appear to agree that morality as a whole is ities to reflect fully formed moral judgments.
not innate (Hamlin, 2015).
A controversial question is whether in-
Why Are We Also Saying That Morality Is
fants at least have innate moral concepts or
Not Learned?
innate capabilities of forming moral evalua-
tions (Bloom, 2013; Hamlin, 2015). The de- Learning theory has a long history in re-
bate has focused on a series of experiments search on moral and social development
in which 3- to 5-month-old infants show (Aronfreed, 1968; Bandura & Walters,
looking and reaching preferences for puppets 1963). Its basic tenet, reflected in contempo-
that help, rather than hinder, the goal acquisi- rary characterizations of non-nativist posi-
tion of another puppet (Hamlin, 2015). Im- tions, as well as in statements of socializa-
portantly, infants’ responses in these studies tion theories, is that children acquire moral
differ from moral capabilities in older chil- concerns and understandings because adults
dren. So far, research has only found infants teach the children to be moral. Children are
to have relative preferences (i.e. preference thought to adopt parental teachings through
 Moral Judgment 25

acceptance of explicit instruction, punish- Moral Judgments: Application of Moral


ments, rewards, or imitation. Concepts to Social Life
Within most learning-based approaches to
morality, there is little distinction between Much effort has recently been invested in
compliance and morality. As long as children determining whether moral evaluations are
follow the commands of their parents in the best described as the result of unconscious,
absence of supervision, they are taken to be automatic intuitions, deliberative reasoning
showing adaptive moral development (Ko- from explicit principles, or some combina-
chanska & Aksan, 2006). The conflation of tion of these (see Dahl & Killen, in press). In
compliance and morality is problematic for, order to adequately answer this debate, how-
at least, two reasons. First, most children do ever, it would be necessary to have some way
not uncritically accept parental commands. of deciding with some certainty whether a
Infants and toddlers show high rates of non- given moral judgment is intuitive, deliberate,
compliance (Kuczynski, Kochanska, Radke- or both. Unfortunately, operationalization of
Yarrow, & Girnius-Brown, 1987), while these three terms has proven extremely dif-
older children challenge parental authority ficult. For instance, although intuitive judg-
on issues they consider to be under personal ments are sometimes defined as judgments
jurisdiction. Moreover, children do not give made without awareness of going through
parents or teachers the authority to alter steps of reasoning, researchers who claim
basic moral prohibitions against hitting or to study intuitive judgments typically do not
stealing (Killen & Smetana, 2015; Smetana assess whether people have such awareness.
& Braeges, 1990). Thus children do not seem From our viewpoint, a more fruitful research
to acquire moral judgments solely through agenda focuses on the concepts involved in
compliance with adult mandates. Rather, the generation of moral and other social
children evaluate caregiver messages within judgments, revealed by patterns of reason-
the context of their own moral and nonmor- ing, emotion attributions, and justifications
al concerns and understandings (Grusec & that guide individuals’ decision making and
Goodnow, 1994). Second, compliance can behavior in morally relevant situations.
lead to distinctly immoral actions, whereas By the 3rd year of life children consistent-
resistance to immoral commands is, in some ly and inconsistently apply their emerging
cases, the morally better course of action moral judgments to their everyday interac-
(Turiel, 2002). tions with others, as well as those witnessed
Thus our constructivist view of the emer- and unwitnessed (events described to chil-
gence of morality differs from both the na- dren by others). An important part of the
tivist and the learning perspectives. Moral research program is to determine what
considerations do not emerge independently factors contribute to inconsistent applica-
of social experiences, nor are they acquired tion of moral judgments and how morality
by simply accepting messages received from is applied (or not applied) in social interac-
parents. We argue that genuine moral con- tions. Research has determined that children
cerns and understandings are constructed weigh multiple considerations, which does
over the course of the first years of life not mean that children are not moral but,
through reciprocal interactions taking place rather, that humans have competing con-
in the everyday lives of children. In the 2 cerns; morality does not always “win out.”
first years, children display many skills that Thus an interesting question is to determine
lay the foundations for morality, such as the circumstances under which children give
helping, empathy, and emotion understand- priority to fairness and what adults can do
ing. Still, children at this age do not dem- to enable them to become capable of and
onstrate the categorical evaluations based aware of the necessity of moral priority.
on concerns of others’ welfare, rights, and
fairness we consider to be necessary compo-
nents of morality. We now turn to research Constructing Morality in the Context
on how these moral considerations, once of Intergroup Relationships
acquired, operate in the increasingly multi-
faceted social worlds in which children find A challenging context for the application
themselves. of morality is one that arises as groups be-
26 M O R A L I T Y A N D T H I N K I N G

come increasingly salient to identity during to reject gender-stereotypical bases for ex-
childhood and throughout adolescence and clusion (Horn & Sinno, 2014)
adulthood (Nesdale et al., 2010). Accord- As illustrated with data regarding moral-
ing to social identity development theories, ity and intergroup contexts, children often
group identity generates ingroup preferences fluctuate, sometimes giving priority to ste-
that have the potential to lead to outgroup reotypical norms associated with group
dislike in order to enhance the ingroup af- identity, and other times recognizing that
filiation. Ingroup bias, as well as outgroup the fair decision overrides other concerns.
dislike, often (but not necessarily) lead to This portrayal of moral reasoning does not
unfair and unequal treatment of others. Re- fit the definition of automatic, uncontrolled
search findings reveal that group affiliation intuitions or conscious deliberations (when
both facilitates moral concerns for others defined as some sort of logical deductive pro-
due to an attachment to one’s ingroup and cess). These judgments are not uncontrolled
the need to belong and increases ingroup in the sense that children are consciously ex-
bias and a heightened concern for effective pressing their desires to be fair to others or
group functioning (Olson, Dweck, Spelke, to adhere to group norms. At the same time,
& Banaji, 2011; Rutland, Killen, & Abrams, the conceptual systems implicated in this
2010; Weller & Lagattuta, 2014). process are not logically or hierarchically
As with moral judgments, prejudice in the ordered but, instead, reflect qualitatively dif-
form of intergroup bias in childhood does not ferent domains of reasoning, moral, societal,
begin as an automatic, uncontrolled, intui- and psychological (Turiel, 2014).
tive process, despite extensive research with One way to investigate how individuals
adults conducted to show it being an automat- weigh different considerations is to assess
ic process. Instead, prejudicial attitudes in the judgments about a complex issue that re-
form of outgroup dislike emerge slowly over flects moral as well as nonmoral decisions.
childhood as children’s experiences either en- Social exclusion based on group member-
courage or hinder negative attitudes about the ship (such as gender, race, nationality, and
outgroup (Baron, 2015; Nesdale et al., 2010; ethnicity) has been the focus of a number of
Rutland & Killen, 2015). How groups are de- studies because of its multifaceted dimen-
fined, how ingroup bias and outgroup threat sions. Individuals often view it as unfair to
emerge, and when children view it as unfair to exclude someone from a group activity sole-
act in a prejudicial manner toward others are ly because of their gender, race, or ethnicity
evolving, developmental processes, with both (such as excluding black women from living
coordinated and uncoordinated deliberations in an all-white sorority house at a univer-
about what constitutes as fair and equal treat- sity). However, individuals often view it as
ment of others in the context of group dynam- legitimate to exclude someone from a group
ics. Further, social experiences and contact when inclusion would be viewed as having a
with members of outgroups plays a significant negative impact on the effective functioning
role in decreasing negative attitudes about of the group (such as excluding men from
others based on group membership. living in an all-female sorority house at a
What we know is that young children university). In a series of studies with chil-
inconsistently reveal an ingroup bias, and dren about intergroup social exclusion, the
which group is defined as the ingroup is also findings have indicated that children con-
highly variable, depending in large part on sistently give priority to morality (and fair-
the messages about group membership re- ness) in straightforward exclusion contexts
ceived from adults, peers, and other sources but often rely on stereotypical expectations
(such as the media) in society (Hitti & Kil- in complex or ambiguous contexts (Killen,
len, 2015). For example, schools in which Pisacane, Lee-Kim, & Ardila-Rey, 2001).
gender is made extremely salient, with gen-
der-specific toys and activities (often done
stereotypically), children group themselves Morality Requires Weighing
by gender and often use stereotypic informa- Multiple Considerations
tion to exclude others (Bigler & Liben, 2007;
Brown, Bigler, & Chu, 2010). Yet, even in It is not the case that everyone uses moral
such contexts, young children are also likely reasons to reject intergroup exclusion, for
 Moral Judgment 27

example, even when asked about it explic- loyalty, has the potential to fly in the face of
itly. Some individuals condone racial exclu- deeply held moral principles.
sion, for example, based on a perception of
peer discomfort and parental disapproval
(“Your friends might not be comfortable Rectifying Social Inequalities:
sitting next to someone who is a differ- Cognitive Complexity and Effort
ent race, and you don’t want to upset your
friends”; “Your parents might not want you Fortunately, with age, children begin to
to invite someone to your house who is a take disadvantaged status and inequalities
different race because they think that they into account when making decisions about
do not have any manners”) (Killen, 2007; the allocation of resources, a central moral
Killen, Henning, Kelly, Crystal, & Ruck, decision throughout social life. Rectifying
2007). preexisting inequalities, however, requires
In contrast, other individuals reject in- unequal allocation of resources to balance
tergroup exclusion using reasons based on out existing inequities; children are capa-
challenging exclusionary group norms (“Of ble of doing this spontaneously as early as
course you should let them sit next to you. 8–10 years of age (Elenbaas & Killen, 2016;
How will you find out what you have in Olson et al., 2011).
common? Your friends need to learn not to In a study by Elenbaas and Killen (2016),
be like that.”) and fairness (“If you aren’t increasing awareness of overarching econom-
friends with them just because of their skin ic inequalities combined with increasingly
color, then how will we learn to get along? negative moral judgments of the resource
You know it’s kind of like not fair to be like disparity led children, with age, to endorse
that.”; “Sometimes you have to teach your actions taken to attenuate the inequality by
parents not to be racist”). The factors that giving more to an institution serving African
determine which types of reasons and ex- Americans that had received less in the past.
planations children use to reject intergroup These judgments reveal the effort that chil-
exclusion appear to be social relational dren go through to preserve fair treatment of
(cross-group friendships), messages from au- others, taking into account social inequali-
thority (adult use of markers to reduce group ties, and disadvantaged status.
differences and to encourage peer integra- Across a number of studies, children use
tion), and the power of group norms (when reasons to identify who owns what for en-
groups have norms of inclusion rather than suring fair allocation of resources, to assert
exclusion). The evidence does not support the necessity of individual rights, and to
an intuitive, automatic process but a social avoid harm to others in contexts of compet-
constructivist trajectory that includes inter- ing considerations (Blake, Ganea, & Harris,
action, discussion, affiliations, and reason- 2012; Helwig, 1998; Jambon & Smetana,
ing. 2014). These judgments require effort, reflec-
Studies in which decisions about fairness tion, and evaluation. As children get older
have to be made in the context of group dy- and move into adolescence, the construction
namics reveal the increasing coordination, of moral judgments is evident in their navi-
with age, of intergroup attitudes and moral gation of social networks, cliques, and peer
judgments. To some extent, it appears that groups. Adolescents reject parental expecta-
young children are more “moral” than older tions to refrain from cross-group friendships
children because they often apply moral but recognize that their peers may provide
principles of equality without consideration pressure to conform to ingroup norms, view-
for group dynamics or group identity con- ing deviations as a form of group disloyalty.
cerns. Young children will challenge group These conflicts provide lifelong challenges
norms, often at the expense of a benefit to morality. But the fact that children are
to their own group, to ensure equal treat- grappling with it and making efforts to rec-
ment of others. With age, children develop tify inequalities is important (and encourag-
strong affiliations with groups and under- ing). These examples provide evidence for
stand group dynamics, which is essential as the assertion that the application of morality
a member of any community. However, this to complex social contexts reflects a devel-
affiliation, when turned into unquestioning opmental and constructive process.
28 M O R A L I T Y A N D T H I N K I N G

Conclusions: Morality Is Developing codes, creating debate but often resulting in


across the Lifespan acts of extreme aggression. Humans sponta-
neously construct moral codes in early devel-
Morality is constructed through social inter- opment, and, with age, they coordinate such
actions and involves reflection, evaluation, considerations with other issues to rectify
and abstraction about social events in the social inequalities and distribute resources
world. By early childhood, children formu- fairly, taking multiple factors into account.
late prescriptive norms about how individu- The fact that young children make moral
als ought to treat one another. Morality is judgments provides an important window of
neither innate nor learned; nor an intuitive opportunity for the facilitation of morality
judgment; nor a form of conscious delibera- to create a more just world.
tion independent of social experience. Chil-
dren, adolescents, and adults make meaning-
ful decisions about how to treat others fairly ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
and justly. This process is not easy, however,
and moral development through the lifespan We are grateful for our discussions, debates, and
reflects debate, dialogue, discussion, and reflections about morality with our colleagues
argument. Without prescriptive norms of and graduate students. We thank Laura Elenbaas
how individuals ought to treat one another, and Michael Rizzo for very helpful feedback on
the manuscript. We extend our appreciation to
humans would not have codes to live by or
the editors for their inclusion of diverse perspec-
develop obligatory ways of interacting with tives in a moral atlas.
one another that reflect fairness, kindness,
and justice.
Throughout history, humankind has com- REFERENCES
mitted horrific atrocities and has also gen-
erated codes of conduct to live by, and to Appiah, K. A. (2005). The ethics of identity.
prevent, rectify, and address social inequali- Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
ties and maltreatment, including the Magna Aronfreed, J. (1968). Conduct and conscience:
Carta, the U.N. Declaration of Human The socialization of internalized control over
Rights, the U.S. Bill of Rights, and the Bill behavior. Oxford, UK: Academic Press.
of Rights for a New South Africa, to name Bandura, A., & Walters, R. H. (1963). Social
learning and personality development. New
a few. In fact, many countries in the world
York: Holt, Rinehart & Winston.
have constitutions that include a bill of Baron, A. S. (2015). Constraints on the develop-
rights. These codified moral laws were cre- ment of implicit intergroup attitudes. Child
ated, constructed, and formulated by indi- Development Perspectives, 9, 50–54.
viduals to prevent the reoccurrence of prior Barrett, K. C., & Campos, J. J. (1987). Perspec-
violations of rights, as well as previous au- tives on emotional development: II. A func-
thoritarian practices that contributed to past tionalist approach to emotions. In J. D. Osof-
atrocities. Morality exists despite these laws, sky (Ed.), Handbook of infant development
and oftentimes laws reflect unfair practices, (2nd ed., pp. 555–578). Oxford, UK: Wiley.
which leads morality to necessarily be inde- Bigler, R. S., & Liben, L. S. (2007). Developmen-
pendent of laws themselves. Codifying moral tal intergroup theory: Explaining and reducing
norms is not reifying them but providing a children’s social stereotyping and prejudice.
basis by which to remind individuals of the Current Directions in Psychological Science,
necessity of giving priority to principles of 16, 162–166.
Blake, P. R., Ganea, P. A., & Harris, P. L. (2012).
fairness, justice, others’ welfare, and rights,
Possession is not always the law: With age, pre-
even in the context of salient and deeply held schoolers increasingly use verbal information
conflicting beliefs and social norms. to identify who owns what. Journal of Experi-
The fact that violations of such rights mental Child Psychology, 113, 259–272.
are pervasive throughout the world is not Bloom, P. (2013). Just babies: The origins of
to deny that these constitutional rights are good and evil. New York: Crown.
deeply held. As we have discussed in our de- Brown, C. S., Bigler, R. S., & Chu, H. (2010). An
velopmental analysis, other factors in social experimental study of the correlates and con-
life become salient, and conflict with moral sequences of perceiving oneself to be the target
 Moral Judgment 29

of gender discrimination. Journal of Experi- Hitti, A., & Killen, M. (2015). Expectations
mental Child Psychology, 107, 100–117. about ethnic peer group inclusivity: The role
Dahl, A. (2014). Definitions and developmen- of shared interests, group norms, and stereo-
tal processes in research on infant morality. types. Child Development, 86, 1522–1537.
Human Development, 57, 241–249. Hoffman, M. L. (2000). Empathy and moral
Dahl, A. (2015). Infants’ unprovoked acts of development: Implications for caring and jus-
force toward others. Developmental Science, tice. New York: Cambridge University Press.
19, 1049–1057. Horn, S. S., & Sinno, S. (2014). Gender, sexual
Dahl, A., & Killen, M. (in press). The devel- orientation, and discrimination based on gen-
opment of moral reasoning from infancy to der and sexual orientation. In M. Killen & J.
adulthood. In J. Wixted (Ed.), The Stevens’ S. Smetana (Eds.), Handbook of moral devel-
handbook of experimental psychology and opment (2nd ed., pp. 317–339). New York:
cognitive neuroscience, volume 3: Develop- Psychology Press.
mental and social psychology. New York: Jambon, M., & Smetana, J. G. (2014). Moral
Wiley. complexity in middle childhood: Children’s
Dahl, A., Schuck, R. K., & Campos, J. J. (2013). evaluations of necessary harm. Developmen-
Do young toddlers act on their social prefer- tal Psychology, 50, 22–33.
ences? Developmental Psychology, 49, 1964– Killen, M. (2007). Children’s social and moral
1970. reasoning about exclusion. Current Directions
Dunn, J. (1988). The beginnings of social under- in Psychological Science, 16, 32–36.
standing. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Univer- Killen, M., Henning, A., Kelly, M. C., Crystal,
sity Press. D., & Ruck, M. (2007). Evaluations of interra-
Dunn, J. (2014). Moral development in early cial peer encounters by majority and minority
childhood and social interaction in the family. U.S. children and adolescents. International
In M. Killen & J. G. Smetana (Eds.), Hand- Journal of Behavioral Development, 31, 491–
book of moral development (2nd ed., pp. 135– 500.
159). New York: Psychology Press. Killen, M., Mulvey, K. L., & Hitti, A. (2013). So-
Elenbaas, L., & Killen, M. (2016). Children rec- cial exclusion in childhood: A developmental
tify inequalities for disadvantaged groups. De- intergroup perspective. Child Development,
velopmental Psychology, 52, 1318–1329. 84, 772–790.
Gewirth, A. (1978). Reason and morality. Chi- Killen, M., Pisacane, K., Lee-Kim, J., & Ardi-
cago: University of Chicago Press. la-Rey, A. (2001). Fairness or stereotypes?:
Grusec, J. E., & Goodnow, J. J. (1994). Impact Young children’s priorities when evaluating
of parental discipline methods on the child’s group exclusion and inclusion. Developmental
internalization of values: A reconceptualiza- Psychology, 37, 587–596.
tion of current points of view. Developmental Killen, M., & Rutland, A. (2011). Children and
Psychology, 30, 4–19. social exclusion: Morality, prejudice, and
Hamlin, J. K. (2015). Does the infant possess a group identity. New York: Wiley-Blackwell.
moral concept? In E. Margolis & S. Laurence Killen, M., & Smetana, J. G. (2015). Origins and
(Eds.), The conceptual mind: New directions development of morality. In M. Lamb (Ed.),
in the study of concepts (pp. 477–518). Cam- Handbook of child psychology (7th ed., Vol.
bridge, MA: MIT Press. 3, pp. 701–749). New York: Wiley-Blackwell.
Hastings, P. D., Zahn-Waxler, C., & McShane, Kochanska, G., & Aksan, N. (2006). Children’s
K. (2006). We are, by nature, moral creatures: conscience and self-regulation. Journal of Per-
Biological bases of concern for others. In M. sonality, 74, 1587–1617.
Killen & J. G. Smetana (Eds.), Handbook of Kuczynski, L., Kochanska, G., Radke-Yarrow,
moral development (pp. 411–434). Mahwah, M., & Girnius-Brown, O. (1987). A develop-
NJ: Erlbaum. mental interpretation of young children’s non-
Hay, D. F., Nash, A., & Pedersen, J. (1981). Re- compliance. Developmental Psychology, 23,
sponses of six-month-olds to the distress of 799–806.
their peers. Child Development, 52, 1071– Lavelli, M., & Fogel, A. (2002). Developmental
1075. changes in mother–infant face-to-face com-
Helwig, C. C. (1998). Children’s conceptions of munication: Birth to 3 months. Developmen-
fair government and freedom of speech. Child tal Psychology, 38, 288–305.
Development, 69, 518–531. Malti, T., Gasser, L., & Buchmann, M. (2009).
Helwig, C. C., Ruck, M. D., & Peterson-Badali, Aggressive and prosocial children’s emotion
M. (2014). Rights, civil liberties, and democ- attributions and moral reasoning. Aggressive
racy. In M. Killen & J. G. Smetana (Eds.), Behavior, 35, 90–102.
Handbook of moral development (2nd ed., Malti, T., & Ongley, S. F. (2014). The develop-
pp. 46–69). New York: Psychology Press. ment of moral emotions and moral reasoning.
30 M O R A L I T Y A N D T H I N K I N G

In M. Killen & J. G. Smetana (Eds.), Hand- Smetana, J. G., & Braeges, J. L. (1990). The de-
book of moral development (2nd ed., pp. 163– velopment of toddlers’ moral and convention-
183). New York: Psychology Press. al judgments. Merrill–Palmer Quarterly, 36,
Nesdale, D., Durkin, K., Maass, A., Kiesner, J., 329–346.
Griffiths, J., Daly, J., & McKenzie, D. (2010). Smetana, J. G., Jambon, M., & Ball, C. (2014).
Peer group rejection and children’s outgroup The social domain approach to children’s
prejudice. Journal of Applied Developmental moral and social judgments. In M. Killen &
Psychology, 31, 134–144. J. G. Smetana (Eds.), Handbook of moral de-
Nucci, L. P. (2001). Education in the moral do- velopment (2nd ed., pp. 23–45). New York:
main. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Taylor & Francis.
Press. Smetana, J. G., Rote, W. M., Jambon, M., Taso-
Nussbaum, M. C. (1999). Sex and social justice. poulos-Chan, M., Villalobos, M., & Comer, J.
Oxford, UK: University of Oxford Press. (2012). Developmental changes and individual
Nussbaum, M. C. (2013). Political emotions: differences in young children’s moral judg-
Why love matters for justice. Cambridge, ments. Child Development, 83, 683–696.
MA: Harvard University Press. Spencer, J. P., Blumberg, M. S., McMurray, B.,
Olson, K. R., Dweck, C. S., Spelke, E. S., & Robinson, S. R., Samuelson, L. K., & Tomb-
Banaji, M. R. (2011). Children’s responses to lin, J. B. (2009). Short arms and talking eggs:
group-based inequalities: Perpetuation and Why we should no longer abide the nativist–
rectification. Social Cognition, 29, 270–287. empiricist debate. Child Development Per-
Piaget, J. (1932). The moral judgment of the spectives, 3, 79–87.
child. New York: Free Press. Trevarthen, C. (1979). Communication and co-
Pinker, S. (2011). The better angels of our na- operation in early infancy: A description of
ture: Why violence has declined. New York: primary intersubjectivity. In M. Bullowa (Ed.),
Viking. Before speech: The beginning of human com-
Rizzo, M. T., & Killen, M. (2016). Children’s munication (pp. 321–348). Cambridge, UK:
understanding of equity in the context of in- Cambridge University Press.
equality. British Journal of Developmental Tronick, E. Z. (1989). Emotions and emotional
Psychology, 34, 569–581. communication in infants. American Psychol-
Roth-Hanania, R., Davidov, M., & Zahn- ogist, 44, 112–119.
Waxler, C. (2011). Empathy development Turiel, E. (2002). The culture of morality: Social
from 8 to 16 months: Early signs of concern development, context, and conflict. Cam-
for others. Infant Behavior and Development, bridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
34, 447–458. Turiel, E. (2006). The development of morality.
Rutland, A., & Killen, M. (2015). A developmen- In W. Damon (Ed.), Handbook of child psy-
tal science approach to reducing prejudice and chology (6th ed., Vol. 3, pp. 789–857). Hobo-
social exclusion: Intergroup processes, social- ken, NJ: Wiley.
cognitive development, and moral reasoning. Turiel, E. (2014). Morality: Epistemology, devel-
Social Issues and Policy Review, 9, 121–154. opment, and social opposition. In M. Killen
Rutland, A., & Killen, M. (2017). Fair resource & J. G. Smetana (Eds.), Handbook of moral
allocation among children and adolescents: development (2nd ed., pp. 3–22). New York:
The role of group and developmental pro- Psychology Press.
cesses. Child Development Perspectives, 11, Vaish, A., Missana, M., & Tomasello, M. (2011).
56–62. Three-year-old children intervene in third-
Rutland, A., Killen, M., & Abrams, D. (2010). party moral transgressions. British Journal of
A new social-cognitive developmental per- Developmental Psychology, 29, 124–130.
spective on prejudice: The interplay between Wainryb, C., Shaw, L. A., & Maianu, C. (1998).
morality and group identity. Perspectives on Tolerance and intolerance: Children’s and
Psychological Science, 5, 279–291. adolescents’ judgments of dissenting beliefs,
Schein, C., & Gray, K. (in press). The theory of speech, persons, and conduct. Child Develop-
dyadic morality: Reinventing moral judgment ment, 69, 1541–1555.
by redefining harm. Personality and Social Weller, D., & Lagattuta, K. H. (2014). Children’s
Psychology Review. judgments about prosocial decisions and emo-
Schmidt, M. F. H., & Sommerville, J. A. (2011). tions: Gender of the helper and recipient mat-
Fairness expectations and altruistic sharing in ters. Child Development, 85, 2011–2028.
15-month-old human infants. PLOS ONE, Zahn-Waxler, C., Radke-Yarrow, M., Wagner,
6(10), e23223. E., & Chapman, M. (1992). Development of
Sen, A. K. (2009). The idea of justice. Cam- concern for others. Developmental Psychol-
bridge, MA: Harvard University Press. ogy, 28, 126–136.
CHAPTER 4

On the Possibility of Intuitive
and Deliberative Processes Working
in Parallel in Moral Judgment

Kees van den Bos

Is moral judgment intuitive or deliberative?

The parallel morality hypothesis suggests that the answer is both,


such that intuitive and deliberative processes operate in parallel to
drive moral judgment, and there is an asymmetry such that delibera‑
tive processes are more easily impaired than intuitive processes (the
former needing more cognitive resources and motivated correction
than the latter).

In this chapter, I focus on the issue of how sibility that intuitive and deliberative pro-
people form judgments of morality and so- cesses tend to operate in parallel. That is,
cial justice. That is, how do people come to the parallel morality hypothesis that I put
ascertain that something is right or wrong? forward here suggests that intuitive and
An important issue pertaining to this ques- deliberative processes simultaneously influ-
tion is the debate about whether people ence the construction of moral judgments.
primarily rely on their gut feelings, auto- However, there is an asymmetry such that
matic affective reactions, and other intuitive it may be more likely that deliberative pro-
processes to assess what they think is right cesses are impaired to some extent than
and wrong or whether morality and justice intuitive processes are. This asymmetry is
judgments are derived by careful conscious proposed because it can be assumed that
reasoning, rationalistic thought, and other intuitive processes are more automatic and
deliberative processes (see, e.g., Beauchamp, need fewer cognitive resources and are less
2001). A main aim of the current chapter is affected by motivation to correct for self-
to argue that both intuitive and deliberative interested impulses than deliberative pro-
processes are important in understanding cesses do. This suggests that people’s capa-
the psychology of moral judgment. bility and motivation to reason should have
More precisely, I argue that, when people strong effects on the exact moral judgments
form moral judgments, there is a good pos- that people construct.

31
32 M O R A L I T Y A N D T H I N K I N G

One way to test the parallel morality hy- Wilke, 1997). Thus both (self-oriented) pref-
pothesis is to examine people’s reactions in erences and (other-oriented) fairness con-
situations in which they are suddenly better siderations are influencing satisfaction with
off than comparable other persons. For ex- advantageous inequity (Van den Bos, Wilke,
ample, imagine that you are a student who Lind, & Vermunt, 1998).
had a job last summer, together with a fellow People usually will know whether their
student. The two of you worked together in outcome gives them pleasure before they
a pair. You and your fellow student have have insight into the fairness aspects of the
worked equally hard and performed equally outcome distribution (e.g., Epley & Ca-
well. On the last day of summer, you receive ruso, 2004; Epley, Morewedge, & Keysar,
a bonus of $500 U.S. Your fellow student 2004; Messick & Sentis, 1979, 1983; Moore
receives a bonus of $250 U.S. How satisfied & Loewenstein, 2004; Van den Bos et al.,
are you with the bonus you received? 2006). For example, Messick and Sentis
Or imagine that you are going to live in a (1979, 1983), state that people generally
new rented house. The rent of this house has have more immediate access to or knowledge
yet to be determined. To decide on the rent, of their preferences than of what is fair, and
each individual tenant has to appear before they usually know their preferences before
a rent tribunal. The rent tribunal will decide they know what is fair. In other words, pref-
on the monthly rent that you will have to erence is primary (Zajonc, 1980) and people
pay. To determine this rent, your neighbor, assess whether and how fairness is relevant
who will rent a comparable house, also has in a later phase (possibly almost immediate-
to appear before the rent tribunal. A week ly). Related to this, Moore and Loewenstein
after you and your neighbor have been at the (2004) argue that self-interest is automatic,
tribunal, you are informed that the rent that viscerally compelling, and typically uncon-
you will have to pay is $750. Your neighbor scious, whereas paying attention to fairness
will have to pay $1,000. How satisfied are concerns is usually a more thoughtful pro-
you with the rent that you will have to pay? cess. Similarly, Epley and Caruso (2004)
Last example: Consider yourself partici- propose that people automatically interpret
pating in a study on how people perform objects and events egocentrically and only
tasks. In the experiment, you work on cer- subsequently correct or adjust that interpre-
tain tasks for 10 minutes. You participate in tation when necessary. The automatic de-
the experiment with another person, who fault occurs rapidly, but correction requires
completes a similar amount of tasks within time and attentional resources (Epley et al.,
the 10 minutes. At the end of the study the 2004).
experimenter gives you three lottery tickets Extending this line of reasoning one step
with which you can win $200. The other further, what I am proposing here is that self-
participant receives only one lottery ticket. oriented preferences tend to influence peo-
How satisfied are you with your lottery tick- ple’s reactions spontaneously and constant-
ets? ly, whereas other-oriented fairness concerns
These examples represent cases in which demand (at least somewhat) more delibera-
people react to situations in which they are tion and hence more cognitive resources and
overpaid, as their outcomes are better than more motivation to correct for self-oriented
the outcomes of comparable other persons intuitions than preferences do. Thus I am
(Adams, 1965; Austin, McGinn, & Sus- suggesting that self-oriented preferences and
milch, 1980; Buunk & Van Yperen, 1989). other-oriented fairness concerns may work
People’s levels of satisfaction with these ar- in parallel, with the former being more auto-
rangements of advantageous inequity rep- matic and more continuously influencing of
resent a combination of conflicting social people’s reactions than the latter.
motives (Van den Bos, Peters, Bobocel, &
Ybema, 2006). A positive source of affect
is derived from the egoism-based pleasure Historical Context
of receiving a relatively good outcome. A
source of negative affect is provided by the The parallel morality hypothesis reflects
fairness-based feeling of being unfairly ad- the broad debate between intuition and
vantaged (Van den Bos, Lind, Vermunt, & deliberation in morality and justice. Ever
 Intuitive and Deliberative Processes in Parallel 33

since the days of Aristotle, Aristippus, and ful conscious reasoning, the view I propose
Plato, there have been arguments in moral adopts an integrative approach focusing on
philosophy and philosophical ethics that ei- the simultaneous operation of both intuitive
ther intuitionist or rationalist conceptions and deliberative processes in the formation
of justice are true (for an overview, see, e.g., of moral judgment and justice and fairness
Beauchamp, 2001). For example, on the one concerns. Examining the possibility that in-
hand, there are theorists who argue that mo- tuitive and deliberative processes may work
rality and justice judgments are derived from in parallel may help to overcome, solve, or
feelings, not from reasoning (e.g., Hume, perhaps sidestep important aspects of the
1739/1951). On the other hand, there are ancient and ongoing impasse of believing in
ethicists who conceive of morality and jus- either intuitionist or rationalist conceptions
tice as predominantly principles that can be (see, e.g., Haidt, 2003, vs. Pizarro & Bloom,
defined by reference to objective standards 2003).
of right and wrong (e.g., Hare, 1981; Rawls, The hypothesis that I put forward here
1971/1992) and who develop rationalistic argues that it makes more sense and that
ethical theories that attempt to deduce a it is scientifically more exciting to adopt
foundation for ethics from the meaning of an integrative approach, in which social
rationality itself (e.g., Kant, 1785/1959). conditions are studied that affect the rela-
Similarly, in the literature on moral psy- tive importance of intuitive and deliberative
chology, there are debates between intu- conceptions. Viewed in this way, the parallel
itionists, who argue that people’s intuitive morality hypothesis constitutes a modern,
feelings about what is right or wrong cause process-oriented approach to the interplay of
moral judgments and that moral reasoning social psychological factors that, combined,
is usually a post hoc construction generated are likely to have an impact on the forma-
after moral judgments have been reached tion of moral and justice judgments and ex-
(e.g., Haidt, 2001; Kagan, 1984; Wilson, amines how these concerns affect people’s
1993), and rationalists, who state that moral reactions and how individuals interact with
judgments are caused primarily by processes other people and how they behave in society.
of cognitive reasoning (e.g., Kohlberg, 1969;
Piaget, 1932/1975; Turiel, 1983).
In short, in the history of morality and so- Theoretical Stance
cial justice, there tend to be two broad ways
of thinking about morality and the justice The parallel morality hypothesis is related to
concept that encompass many elements of approaches that focus on initial self-centered
the essence of moral judgment and social gut reactions to unfair situations followed
justice: Intuitionist notions suggest that by controlled attempts to correct these first
morality and justice concerns are mainly reactions. In this respect, the hypothesis is
the result of spontaneous or even automatic similar to earlier work on people’s responses
evaluations and are strongly influenced by to various outcome distributions (see, e.g.,
subjective and affective factors, whereas ra- Epley & Caruso, 2004; Epley et al., 2004;
tionalist theories emphasize that reasoning Knoch, Pascual-Leone, Meyer, Treyer, &
causes morality and justice judgments to be Fehr, 2006; Messick & Sentis, 1979, 1983;
constructed primarily in a deliberate, objec- Moore & Loewenstein, 2004). The hy-
tive, and cognitive way (for an overview, see pothesis is differentiated from these earlier
Beauchamp, 2001). dual-process studies by its emphasis on the
The parallel morality hypothesis is impor- possibility that intuitive and deliberative
tant, I argue, because it reflects a more mod- processes may work in parallel.
ern approach to how people form judgments The parallel quality of intuitive and de-
of morality and justice (Strack & Deutsch, liberative processes is also present in more
2003). That is, rather than continuing the general models on how people process in-
age-old and ongoing controversy between formation that have noted that intuitive and
intuitive and deliberative models of moral- deliberative processes operate in parallel as
ity and justice, focusing on whether morality two independent systems that can be concur-
and justice are best characterized by either rently active and compete for dominance in
spontaneous affective reactions or care- overt responses (see, e.g., Strack & Deutsch,
34 M O R A L I T Y A N D T H I N K I N G

2004; see also Gilovich & Griffin, 2002; other persons. Building on classical and
Kahneman & Frederick, 2002). The parallel modern social psychological theories, we ar-
morality hypothesis differs somewhat from gued that when individuals are reacting to
these other two-systems models in its propo- these arrangements of advantageous inequi-
sition that intuitive and deliberative process- ty, judging the advantage is quick and easy,
es tend to be consequently invoked such that as self-interested preferences are primary
intuitive processes in general are more spon- (Messick & Sentis, 1983; see also Zajonc,
taneously invoked than deliberative process- 1980). We further proposed that adjusting
es are. The parallel morality hypothesis is this appraisal requires cognitive resources,
also differentiated from these more general as it entails integrating fairness concerns
psychological models by its focus on moral- with the initial preference appraisal. We
ity and justice concerns. investigated this hypothesis in a number of
The hypothesis that I put forward is dif- different experiments using different para-
ferent from notions that suggest that proso- digms and different manipulations. Com-
cial reactions are spontaneous and intuitive mon elements in our experiments were that
(e.g., Rand, Greene, & Nowak, 2012). The we varied whether participants’ cognitive
hypothesis also differs from ideas ventilated processing was either strongly or weakly
in the literature that justice concerns are limited while responding to the stimulus ma-
genuine and have nothing to do with or out- terials (see, e.g., Gilbert, Pelham, & Krull,
weigh egocentric responses (see, e.g., Lerner, 1988; Gilbert & Osborne, 1989; see also
2003; Lerner & Goldberg, 1999). The hy- Wegner & Erber, 1992). Furthermore, in all
pothesis is also different from theories that experiments, advantageous inequity condi-
adopt either an intuitionist (see, e.g., Haidt, tions were included in which participants
2001) or a rationalistic (Kant, 1785/1959) received an outcome that was better than
approach to the study of morality and social the outcome of a comparable other person,
justice. and the main dependent variable was par-
ticipants’ outcome satisfaction evaluations.
Findings thus obtained indeed showed that
Evidence participants are more satisfied with advanta-
geous inequity when they are under high (as
There are important research findings that opposed to low) cognitive load.
support important components of the hy- Knoch et al. (2006) examined whether
pothesis put forward here. Some compo- people accept or reject unfair offers made
nents of the hypothesis are yet to be tested to them by other participants in ultimatum
thoroughly (which is the primary reason that games. The authors argued that people’s first
I put forward the parallel morality hypoth- reactions to the unfair offers are such that
esis as a “hypothesis,” not as a “model” and they are inclined to satisfy their self-interest-
certainly not as a “theory”). And some evi- ed needs, and controlling this self-interested
dence reported in the literature seems to be impulse overrides this primary impulse. The
inconsistent with the hypothesis. This sec- dorsolateral prefrontal cortex (DLPFC) is in-
tion reviews very briefly some evidence for volved in the control of impulsive reactions.
the hypothesis and also indicates evidence Thus impairing the DLPFC by low-frequen-
that is as yet missing, as well as suggestions cy repetitive transcranial magnetic stimula-
that contradict my line of reasoning. tion (rTMS) will inhibit the control function
Data that support important components of the DLPFC and thus strengthen the self-
of the hypothesis put forward here come interest motive. Knoch et al. (2006) indeed
from various sources. Here, I focus on reac- showed that inhibiting the right DLPFC
tions to advantageous inequity, acceptance substantially reduced people’s willingness to
or rejection of unfair offers in ultimatum reject their partners’ intentionally unfair of-
games, and what information children and fers in ultimatum bargaining games. These
adults look at during a perspective-taking findings suggest that control is needed to
task. fight or resist unfairness.
Van den Bos et al. (2006) examined how Epley et al. (2004) tested a related line of
satisfied people are with outcomes that are reasoning by tracking children’s and adults’
better than the outcomes of comparable eye movements as they completed a perspec-
 Intuitive and Deliberative Processes in Parallel 35

tive-taking task. Results obtained from an eration is central to human social behavior
experiment conducted in the Children’s Mu- and that cooperation is intuitive because
seum of Boston suggested that both children cooperative heuristics are developed in daily
and adults automatically interpret objects life, in which cooperation is typically advan-
and events egocentrically and only subse- tageous. Findings obtained from different
quently correct or adjust that interpretation economic games suggest that forcing partici-
when necessary. These findings indicate that pants to decide quickly increases cooperative
the automatic default occurs rapidly but that behavior, whereas instructing them to reflect
correction requires time and attentional re- and forcing them to decide slowly decreases
sources. Furthermore, children generally be- cooperation. Furthermore, priming partici-
have more egocentrically than adults when pants to trust their intuitions increases co-
assessing another’s perspective. This differ- operation with primes that induce delibera-
ence does not, however, indicate that adults tive reflection. According to the authors of
process information less egocentrically than this intriguing paper, these results suggest
children, but rather that adults are better that intuition supports cooperation in social
able to subsequently correct an initial ego- dilemmas and that reflection can undermine
centric interpretation. these cooperative impulses. These findings
A line of reasoning that ostensibly contra- are, indeed, very interesting. However, the
dicts what I am proposing here comes from notion that reflection can undermine coop-
some aspects of Lerner’s just-world theory erative impulses can be explained by Miller’s
that suggest that genuine justice concerns (1999) notion that, upon reflection, people
outweigh more egocentric responses (e.g., tend to adhere to a norm of self-interest be-
Lerner, 2003; Lerner & Goldberg, 1999). I cause they think their culture (and perhaps
think that this, indeed, may be the case in especially a North American culture; see,
some circumstances—for example, when e.g., Henrich, Heine, & Norenzayan, 2010a,
someone sacrifices his or her own life to safe 2010b) tends to value self-interest over fair-
the life of another person who is completely ness and morality concerns.
unrelated to him or her, in an act of true al- Moreover, data that well could falsify an
truism (see also Batson, 1991, 1998). How- important component of the parallel moral-
ever, please note that although the findings ity hypothesis include findings from recent
briefly reviewed here suggest that people’s studies that suggest that people can engage
primitive core may sometimes (e.g., when in successful response inhibition of hedo-
their cognitive capacities have been severely nistic impulses. For example, Veling, Aarts,
limited) push them in an egocentric direc- and Papies (2011) show that stop signals can
tion, it may well be the case that frequently inhibit chronic dieters’ responses toward
people try to free cognitive resources to do palatable foods. Furthermore, Veling and
the right thing. Thus morality, fairness, and Van Knippenberg (2006) note that forming
justice concerns are frequently a very real intentions can inhibit responses to distract-
concern to people (Van den Bos et al., 2006; ing stimuli, and recent evidence suggests that
see also Staub, 1989, 2011). Furthermore, it arousal can modulate response inhibition
may well be that for the majority of people, (Weinbach, Kalanthroff, Avnit, & Henik,
the genuine self seems to be a prosocial self 2015) and that medial prefrontal cortical
(Van den Bos, Van Lange, et al., 2011). Thus regions contribute in important ways to con-
my hypothesis is that genuine concerns for ditioned inhibition (Meyer & Bucci, 2014).
fairness tend to correct self-interested im- Importantly, when people are able to inhibit
pulses most of the time (but not always) spontaneous egocentric responses to such
among most (but not all) individuals (Van an extent that these responses are not really
den Bos, 2015; see also Miller, 1999). there anymore for a long time, this would
Data that could truly falsify the line of falsify the claim of my hypothesis that both
reasoning put forward here would need to self-centered and fairness/morality concerns
indicate that fairness and morality concerns tend to operate in parallel. Indeed, success-
are more primary than egocentric tenden- ful response inhibition of self-centered intu-
cies are. Rand et al. (2012) presented some itions in the morality and justice domains
findings that exactly tested this alternative would suggest that a dual-process account
prediction. These authors argued that coop- of intuitive and deliberative concerns is more
36 M O R A L I T Y A N D T H I N K I N G

appropriate than a framework that suggests ogy and law. For example, intuition and de-
that these concerns work in parallel. In fact, liberation may simultaneously influence the
I ground important components of my line decisions of judges. Research could try to
of reasoning on earlier studies that explicitly test the possible parallel operation of emo-
can be viewed as instances of a dual-­process tion-driven impulses to what is described
approach to self-centered and deliberate in legal files and rationalistic, deliberative
correction processes (see, e.g., Epley et al., thoughts about how laws and legal rules
2004). Furthermore, precisely because con- apply precisely to what happened in the legal
clusive evidence for the “parallel” compo- issues at hand.
nent of the parallel morality hypothesis is In the last two decades or so, psychology
missing, I explicitly put forward the predic- has moved away from rationalistic and de-
tion as it is, a hypothesis. Clearly, tight data liberative thinking and paid much attention
need to be collected to show or falsify the to intuitive and fast decision making. This
parallel component of the hypothesis. has yielded great developments in the field of
Personally, I think that full and constant psychological science. However, now is the
inhibition such that self-centered preferenc- time, I argue, to start paying more attention
es are not active anymore for a long time is to the unique reasoning capabilities that hu-
rather unlikely. That is, I think that self-cen- mans have. Coupled with the ideals of the
tered reactions can be inhibited, but to me Enlightenment (and associated prescriptive
it seems likely that these reactions will also assumptions present in Kantian philosophy),
kick back and start affecting people’s reac- this could reveal the positive aspects of care-
tions once more. For example, we can inhibit ful and deliberative thought about right and
hedonistic responses to palatable food (Vel- wrong and the important role that conscious
ing et al., 2011), but dieters will also tell that processes play in this (see also Baumeister &
it is hard to constantly inhibit the responses Masicampo, 2010), quite possibly in addi-
to eat all those many things that we like tion or parallel to more intuitive and affect-
but that are bad for us and our diet. Thus, I driven processes (such as initial egocentric
note that definitely more research is needed responses to advantageous injustice).
to sort out the strength and long-term ef- Studying these issues could perhaps also
fects of response inhibition of self-centered reveal that moral judgments derived by de-
impulses, including egocentric intuitions in liberate reasoning are qualitatively different
the morality and justice domains. This as- from impressions of what is right or wrong
pect and other aspects of the hypothesis put derived from relying on gut feelings. Inter-
forward here can now be tested in detail in estingly, work in other domains seems to
future research. be related to this issue, such as research on
more automatic and more controlled compo-
nents of stereotypes and prejudice (see, e.g.,
Extension and Expansion Devine, 1989; see also Gilbert et al., 1988;
Kawakami, Dovidio, Moll, Hermsen, &
The real-world implications of the parallel Russin, 2000). The domain of psychology
morality hypothesis are such that people’s and law could yield good testing ground to
responses and behaviors may indeed often examine the interplay between intuitive and
reflect both intuitive and deliberative pro- deliberative, as well as spontaneous and con-
cesses. These processes may or may not be trolled, processes in detail.
related to self-centered and other-oriented Another domain that may or may not be
reactions, respectively. Thus, intuitive pro- related to intuitive and deliberative paral-
cesses may not always reflect self-interested lel processes as discussed here is the area
responses, and deliberative processes may of behavioral activation and inhibition sys-
not necessarily reflect other-oriented con- tems. Many psychologists had good reasons
cerns. Future research can and should test to consider behavioral activation and inhi-
the various components of the parallel mo- bition as constituting independent systems
rality hypothesis in detail. (e.g., Carver & White, 1994; Gable, Reis, &
One area to which this line of reasoning Elliot, 2000; Gray & McNaughton, 2000),
could be extended is the domain of psychol- but current cognitive psychologists also tend
 Intuitive and Deliberative Processes in Parallel 37

to focus on the interaction between activat- Austin, W., McGinn, N. C., & Susmilch, C.
ing and inhibitory processes (e.g., Knyazev, (1980). Internal standards revisited: Effects
Schutter, & Van Honk, 2006). Related to of social comparisons and expectancies on
this is work on moral disengagement that judgments of fairness and satisfaction. Jour-
nal of Experimental Social Psychology, 16,
examines the deactivation of self-regulatory
426–441.
processes that can inhibit unethical behav- Bal, M., & Van den Bos, K. (2012). Blaming for
ior (e.g., Bandura, 1990, 1996). Processes a better future: Future orientation and associ-
of moral disengagement can lead people ated intolerance of personal uncertainty lead
to convince themselves that certain ethical to harsher reactions toward innocent victims.
standards do not apply to themselves in par- Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin,
ticular situations, for instance, by disabling 38, 835–844.
cognitive mechanisms of self-condemnation Bandura, A. (1990). Selective activation and dis-
(but see Reynolds, Dang, Yam, & Leavitt, engagement of moral control. Journal of So-
2014). Whether behavioral activation and cial Issues, 46, 27–46.
inhibition can operate in parallel ways when Bandura, A. (1996). Mechanisms of moral dis-
engagement in the exercise of moral agency.
responding to issues of morality and social
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
justice is a topic that needs further concep- 71, 364–374.
tual exploration and empirical examination Batson, C. D. (1991). The altruism question: To-
(Van den Bos & Lind, 2013). ward a social psychological answer. Hillsdale,
Importantly, other issues of right and NJ: Erlbaum.
wrong besides the topics briefly reviewed Batson, C. D. (1998). Altruism and prosocial
here need to be examined in detail. These is- behavior. In D. T. Gilbert, S. T. Fiske, & G.
sues include, but are not limited to, research Lindzey (Eds.), The handbook of social psy-
on moral dilemmas (e.g., Van den Bos, Mül- chology (4th ed., Vol. 2, pp. 282–316). Bos-
ler, & Damen, 2011) and the belief in a ton: McGraw-Hill.
just world (e.g., Bal & Van den Bos, 2012; Baumeister, R. F., & Masicampo, E. J. (2010).
Conscious thought is for facilitating social and
Van den Bos & Maas, 2009). The moderat-
cultural interactions: How mental simulations
ing effects of culture (e.g., Van den Bos et serve the animal–culture interface. Psycholog-
al., 2010; Van den Bos, Brockner, Van den ical Review, 117, 945–971.
Oudenalder, Kamble, & Nasabi, 2013; Van Beauchamp, T. L. (2001). Philosophical ethics:
den Bos, Van Veldhuizen, & Au, 2015), so- An introduction to moral philosophy (3rd ed.).
cial value orientations (e.g., Van den Bos, Boston: McGraw-Hill.
Van Lange, et al., 2011), and social psycho- Buunk, B. P., & Van Yperen, N. W. (1989). Social
logical concepts such as ego depletion (Lose- comparison, equality, and relationship satis-
man & Van den Bos, 2012) need to be taken faction: Gender differences over a ten-year pe-
into consideration as well. riod. Social Justice Research, 3, 157–180.
In conclusion, the current chapter argues Carver, C. S., & White, T. L. (1994). Behavioral
inhibition, behavioral activation, and affective
that moral judgment may be an intuitive and responses to impending reward and punish-
a deliberative phenomenon, best character- ment: The BIS/BAS scales. Journal of Person-
ized by two processes working in parallel. ality and Social Psychology, 67, 319–333.
In delineating some thoughts about these is- Devine, P. G. (1989). Stereotypes and prejudice:
sues, I hope to have conveyed that it may be Their automatic and controlled components.
conducive to the fields of morality and social Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
justice (broadly defined) to start examining 56, 5–18.
the intriguing possibility that intuitive and Epley, N., & Caruso, E. M. (2004). Egocentric
deliberative processes work in parallel in ethics. Social Justice Research, 17, 171–188.
moral judgment. Epley, N., Morewedge, C. K., & Keysar, B.
(2004). Perspective taking in children and
adults: Equivalent egocentrism but differential
REFERENCES correction. Journal of Experimental Social
Psychology, 40, 760–768.
Adams, J. S. (1965). Inequity in social exchange. Gable, S. L., Reis, H. T., & Elliot, A. J. (2000).
In L. Berkowitz (Ed.), Advances in experimen- Behavioral activation and inhibition in every-
tal social psychology (Vol. 2, pp. 267–299). day life. Journal of Personality and Social Psy-
New York: Academic Press. chology, 78, 1135–1149.
38 M O R A L I T Y A N D T H I N K I N G

Gilbert, D. T., & Osborne, R. E. (1989). Think- fairness by disrupting the right prefrontal cor-
ing backward: Some curable and incurable tex. Science, 314, 829–832.
consequences of cognitive busyness. Journal Knyazev, G. G., Schutter, D. J. L. G., & Van
of Personality and Social Psychology, 57, Honk, J. (2006). Anxious apprehension in-
940–949. creases coupling of delta and beta oscillations.
Gilbert, D. T., Pelham, B. W., & Krull, D. S. International Journal of Psychophysiology,
(1988). On cognitive busyness: When person 61, 283–287.
perceivers meet persons perceived. Journal of Kohlberg, L. (1969). Stage and sequence: The
Personality and Social Psychology, 54, 733– cognitive-developmental approach to social-
740. ization. In D. A. Goslin (Ed.), Handbook of
Gilovich, T., & Griffin, D. (2002). Introduc- socialization theory and research (pp. 347–
tion—Heuristics and biases: Then and now. 480). Chicago: Rand McNally.
In T. Gilovich, D. Griffin, & D. Kahneman Lerner, M. J. (2003). The justice motive: Where
(Eds.), Heuristics and biases: The psychology social psychologists found it, how they lost it,
of intuitive judgment (pp. 1–18). New York: and why they may not find it again. Personali-
Cambridge University Press. ty and Social Psychology Review, 7, 388–399.
Gray, J. A., & McNaughton, N. (2000). The neu- Lerner, M. J., & Goldberg, J. H. (1999). When
ropsychology of anxiety: An enquiry into the do decent people blame victims?: The differ-
functions of the septo-hippocampal system. ing effects of the explicit/rational and implicit/
Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. experiential cognitive systems. In S. Chaiken
Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional dog and its ra- & Y. Trope (Eds.), Dual-process theories in
tional tail: A social intuitionist approach to social psychology (pp. 627–640). New York:
moral judgment. Psychological Review, 108, Guilford Press.
814–834. Loseman, A., & Van den Bos, K. (2012). A self-
Haidt, J. (2003). The emotional dog does learn regulation hypothesis of coping with an unjust
new tricks: A reply to Pizarro and Bloom world: Ego-depletion and self-affirmation as
(2003). Psychological Review, 110, 197–198. underlying aspects of blaming of innocent vic-
Hare, R. M. (1981). Moral thinking: Its levels, tims. Social Justice Research, 25, 1–13.
method, and point. Oxford, UK: Clarendon Messick, D. M., & Sentis, K. (1979). Fairness
Press. and preference. Journal of Experimental So-
Henrich, J., Heine, S. J., & Norenzayan, A. cial Psychology, 15, 418–434.
(2010a). Most people are not WEIRD. Nature, Messick, D. M., & Sentis, K. (1983). Fairness,
466, 29. preference, and fairness biases. In D. M. Mes-
Henrich, J., Heine, S. J., & Norenzayan, A. sick & K. S. Cook (Eds.), Equity theory:
(2010b). The weirdest people in the world? Be- Psychological and sociological perspectives
havioral and Brain Sciences, 33, 61–83. (pp. 61–94). New York: Praeger.
Hume, D. (1951). A treatise of human nature. Meyer, H. C., & Bucci, D. J. (2014). The contri-
Oxford, UK: Clarendon. (Original work pub- bution of medial prefrontal cortical regions to
lished 1739) conditioned inhibition. Behavioral Neurosci-
Kagan, J. (1984). The nature of the child. New ence, 128, 644–653.
York: Basic Books. Miller, D. T. (1999). The norm of self-interest.
Kahneman, D., & Frederick, S. (2002). Repre- American Psychologist, 54, 1053–1060.
sentativeness revisited: Attribute substitution Moore, D. A., & Loewenstein, G. (2004). Self-
in intuitive judgment. In T. Gilovich, D. Grif- interest, automaticity, and the psychology of
fin, & D. Kahneman (Eds.), Heuristics and conflict of interest. Social Justice Research, 17,
biases: The psychology of intuitive judgment 189–202.
(pp. 49–81). New York: Cambridge University Piaget, J. (1975). The moral judgment of the
Press. child. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Kant, I. (1959). Foundation of the metaphysics (Original work published 1932)
of morals. Indianapolis, IN: Bobbs-Merrill. Pizarro, D. A., & Bloom, P. (2003). The intel-
(Original work published 1785) ligence of the moral intuitions: Comment on
Kawakami, K., Dovidio, J. F., Moll, J., Hermsen, Haidt (2001). Psychological Review, 110,
S., & Russin, A. (2000). Just say no (to stereo- 193–196.
typing): Effects of training in negation of ste- Rand, D. G., Greene, J. D., & Nowak, M. A.
reotypic associations on stereotype activation. (2012). Spontaneous giving and calculated
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, greed. Nature, 489, 427–430.
78, 871–888. Rawls, J. (1992). A theory of justice. Oxford,
Knoch, D., Pascual-Leone, A., Meyer, K., Treyer, UK: Oxford University Press. (Original work
V., & Fehr, E. (2006). Diminishing reciprocal published 1971)
 Intuitive and Deliberative Processes in Parallel 39

Reynolds, S. J., Dang, C. T., Yam, K. C., & psychology of the belief in a just world: Ex-
Leavitt, K. (2014). The role of moral knowl- ploring experiential and rationalistic paths to
edge in everyday immorality: What does it victim blaming. Personality and Social Psy-
matter if I know what is right? Organizational chology Bulletin, 35, 1567–1578.
Behavior and Human Decision Processes, Van den Bos, K., Müller, P. A., & Damen, T.
123, 124–137. (2011). A behavioral disinhibition hypothesis
Staub, E. (1989). The roots of evil: The origins of interventions in moral dilemmas. Emotion
of genocide and other group violence. New Review, 3, 281–283.
York: Cambridge University Press. Van den Bos, K., Peters, S. L., Bobocel, D. R., &
Staub, E. (2011). Uncertainty, and the roots and Ybema, J. F. (2006). On preferences and doing
prevention of genocide and terrorism. In M. A. the right thing: Satisfaction with advantageous
Hogg & D. L. Blaylock (Eds.), Extremism and inequity when cognitive processing is limited.
the psychology of uncertainty (pp. 263–280). Journal of Experimental Social Psychology,
Oxford, UK: Wiley-Blackwell. 42, 273–289.
Strack, F., & Deutsch, R. (2003). The two sides Van den Bos, K., Van Lange, P. A. M., Lind, E.
of social behavior: Modern classics and over- A., Venhoeven, L. A., Beudeker, D. A., Cram-
looked gems on the interplay between auto- winckel, F. M., . . . Van der Laan, J. (2011).
matic and controlled processes. Psychological On the benign qualities of behavioral disin-
Inquiry, 14, 209–215. hibition: Because of the prosocial nature of
Strack, F., & Deutsch, R. (2004). Reflective and people, behavioral disinhibition can weaken
impulsive determinants of social behavior. pleasure with getting more than you deserve.
Personality and Social Psychology Review, 8, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
220–247. 101, 791–811.
Turiel, E. (1983). The development of social Van den Bos, K., Van Veldhuizen, T. S., & Au, A.
knowledge: Morality and convention. Cam- K. C. (2015). Counter cross-cultural priming
bridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. and relative deprivation: The role of individu-
Van den Bos, K. (2015). Genuine concerns for alism–collectivism. Social Justice Research,
fairness tend to correct self-interested impuls- 28, 52–75.
es. Social Justice Research, 28, 230–232. Van den Bos, K., Wilke, H. A. M., Lind, E. A., &
Van den Bos, K., Brockner, J., Stein, J. H., Stein- Vermunt, R. (1998). Evaluating outcomes by
er, D. D., Van Yperen, N. W., & Dekker, D. M. means of the fair process effect: Evidence for
(2010). The psychology of voice and perfor- different processes in fairness and satisfaction
mance capabilities in masculine and feminine judgments. Journal of Personality and Social
cultures and contexts. Journal of Personality Psychology, 74, 1493–1503.
and Social Psychology, 99, 638–648. Veling, H., Aarts, H., & Papies, E. K. (2011).
Van den Bos, K., Brockner, J., Van den Oude- Using stop signals to inhibit chronic dieters’
nalder, M., Kamble, S. V., & Nasabi, A. responses toward palatable foods. Behaviour
(2013). Delineating a method to study cross- Research and Therapy, 11, 771–780.
cultural differences with experimental control: Veling, H., & Van Knippenberg, A. (2006).
The voice effect and countercultural contexts Shielding intentions from distraction: Forming
regarding power distance. Journal of Experi- an intention induces inhibition of distracting
mental Social Psychology, 49, 624–634. stimuli. Social Cognition, 24, 409–425.
Van den Bos, K., & Lind, E. A. (2013). On Wegner, D. M., & Erber, R. (1992). The hyper-
sense-making reactions and public inhibition accessibility of suppressed thoughts. Journal
of benign social motives: An appraisal model of Personality and Social Psychology, 63,
of prosocial behavior. In J. M. Olson & M. 903–912.
P. Zanna (Eds.), Advances in experimental so- Weinbach, N., Kalanthroff, E., Avnit, A., &
cial psychology (Vol. 48, pp. 1–58). San Diego, Henik, A. (2015). Can arousal modulate re-
CA: Academic Press. sponse inhibition? Journal of Experimental
Van den Bos, K., Lind, E. A., Vermunt, R., & Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cogni-
Wilke, H. A. M. (1997). How do I judge my tion, 41, 1873–1877.
outcome when I do not know the outcome of Wilson, J. Q. (1993). The moral sense. New
others?: The psychology of the fair process York: Free Press.
effect. Journal of Personality and Social Psy- Zajonc, R. B. (1980). Feeling and thinking: Pref-
chology, 72, 1034–1046. erences need no inferences. American Psychol-
Van den Bos, K., & Maas, M. (2009). On the ogist, 35, 151–175.
CHAPTER 5

The Wrong and the Bad

Shaun Nichols

How can a theory of moral judgment explain why people think


certain actions are wrong, not simply bad?

By incorporating rules.

It is bad when a puppy falls off a cliff. It is question whether babies judge that it was
wrong when a person throws a puppy off a wrong for the agent to hinder, and Hamlin
cliff. Both of these events are morally unfor- does not argue for that richer interpretation
tunate. But many moral systems maintain of the data. By contrast, much moral psy-
that there is a critical distinction between chology on children and adults has focused
bad and wrong events (see, e.g., Aquinas, explicitly on judgments of wrongness (Blair,
Kant, Ross). Accidents and natural disas- 1995; Cushman, Young, & Hauser, 2006;
ters can have morally bad consequences, but Greene & Sinnott-Armstrong, 2008; T ­ uriel,
only actions can be wrong. This distinction 1983). Research on the moral–convention-
isn’t merely the province of philosophy. Or- al distinction explores how children and
dinary people frequently condemn actions as adults distinguish between different kinds
wrong, not merely bad. An adequate theory of wrongness (Turiel, 1983). Children judge
of human morality must explain these kinds that it is wrong—impermissible—to stand
of judgments. up during story time. They also judge that
The moral reactions of infants (see, e.g., it is wrong to pull hair. The former kind of
Hamlin, Wynn, & Bloom, 2007) and non- case is taken to be a conventional violation;
human animals (see, e.g., de Waal, Leim­ the latter a moral violation. And these differ-
gruber, & Greenberg, 2008) are naturally ent kinds of violations exhibit systematically
interpreted in terms of moral badness (or different patterns of responses in children
goodness). Kiley Hamlin and colleagues and adults. Importantly, though, all of these
showed babies events in which one agent involve judgments of wrongness. Similarly,
either helps or hinders another agent. They in the moral dilemma tradition, partici-
found that babies preferred helpers to hin- pants are presented with scenarios—such as
derers. A plausible explanation of the phe- throwing a person in front of a train—and
nomenon is that the babies assign a nega- asked about the permissibility of such an ac-
tive valence to hinderers. But it is a further tion (Cushman et al., 2006; Mikhail, 2011).

40
 The Wrong and the Bad 41

Our account of wrongness judgments is find it aversive to witness suffering; simi-


traditional: These judgments involve struc- larly, it’s widely acknowledged that humans
tured representations of rules that invoke learn to find certain kinds of actions aversive
abstract notions such as harm, knowledge, through habit learning. Thus, if we can ex-
and innocence to proscribe certain actions plain moral judgment in terms of some such
(e.g., Mallon & Nichols, 2010; Nichols, widely accepted low-level processes, then
2004; Nichols & Mallon, 2006; Nichols, we have no need to appeal to such cognitive
Kumar, Lopez, Ayars, & Chan, 2016; see extravagances as richly structured rules de-
also Mikhail, 2011). People judge that it is fined over abstract categories.
wrong to throw a puppy off of a cliff because
they have a rule that proscribes intentionally
causing harm to an innocent creature, and Arguments
they recognize that the event counts as a vio-
lation of that rule since a puppy is an inno- Despite its tough-minded appeal, the race to
cent creature and bouncing down a moun- lower levels can neglect the very phenomena
tain is a harm. we want to understand. Trying to explain
human cognition without adverting to sym-
bolic processing makes it difficult to capture
Theoretical Context core phenomena such as the systematicity
and inferential potential of thought (Fodor
We favor an account of moral judgment that & Pylyshyn, 1988). Similarly, it is difficult
depends on structured rules defined over ab- to capture the distinctive nature and speci-
stract concepts (Nichols & Mallon, 2006; ficity of wrongness judgments without ad-
Nichols et al., 2016). But many theories of verting to structured rules.
moral judgment try to make do with a much Humans naturally find certain things
more austere set of resources. It is a familiar aversive, including such varied phenomena
pattern in cognitive science to seek low-level as electric shock and suffering in others (see,
explanations for apparently high-level cogni- e.g., Blair, 1999). Furthermore, like other
tive phenomena. This is perhaps most appar- animals, we can acquire aversions through
ent in disputes about symbolic processing. habit learning (Crockett, 2013; Cushman,
Some influential connectionist approaches 2013). If grasping a green apple frequently
attempt to explain cognition with no re- leads to being shocked, then I will develop an
course to symbols (McClelland, Rumelhart, aversion to grasping green apples. These are
& Hinton, 1986). There is a related trend uncontroversial components of the human
in accounts of moral judgment that eschew mind. But finding something aversive is not
rules in favor of lower level factors. the same as judging it wrong. I find clean-
In low-level accounts of moral judgment, ing the litter box extremely aversive. But I
the primitive ingredient is typically some kind do not judge it to be wrong to clean the litter
of aversion. Blair’s account of the moral–con- box. By contrast, I judge that it is wrong to
ventional distinction is based on the distress eat beef (for various reasons), but I find eat-
associated with seeing others in distress (Blair, ing beef very appealing. My behavior often
1995). Greene’s account of nonutilitarian re- conforms to my aversions and attractions—I
sponses to dilemma cases is based on alarm- often avoid cleaning the litter box, and I fre-
like reactions of ancient emotions systems quently eat beef. But insofar as we are trying
(Greene, Sommerville, Nystrom, Darley, & to understand our judgments of wrongness,
Cohen, 2008). Cushman (2013) and Crock- we need to capture the fact that the litter
ett (2013) explain key aspects of nonutilitar- box aversion does not involve a judgment of
ian judgment by adverting to reinforcement wrongness. We need something more than
learning, especially habit learning. aversion to explain the wrongness judgment.
Low-level accounts are often attractive Aversion alone does not discriminate be-
because they build on processes that are un- tween the wrong and the bad. Furthermore,
controversially present in the organism. In simple aversions seem not to have the req-
the present case, few dispute that humans uisite level of precision to capture moral
42 M O R A L I T Y A N D T H I N K I N G

judgment. Natural aversions tend to be trig- cousin. If people systematically judge that
gered by concrete cues—we find a crying it is wrong to slaughter cattle, then this is
face aversive, but not a simple statement that because they encode a rule defined over the
someone, somewhere, is crying. Normative concept cattle . If people systematically
judgments, however, often involve not con- judge that it is wrong to spank your child
crete cues but abstract categories such as except for punishment, then this is because
harm. Often our feelings of aversion track they encode a rule defined over the concept
specific cues, whereas our moral judgments punishment. A system built on natural
track the abstract category. Consider the fa- aversion or habit learning that does not ex-
mous line attributed to Stalin, that a single ploit such concepts as parallel cousin and
death is a tragedy, but a million deaths is a cattle will be poorly equipped to explain
statistic. We might well find it more aversive how it is that people seem to know and abide
to imagine a single person being murdered by these norm systems so effectively.
than to acknowledge the murders of a mil- Accounts of moral judgment based solely
lion. But we would certainly not make the on aversion thus have difficulties with both
moral judgment that the murder of one is the specificity of moral judgments and the
more wrong or worse than the murder of a fact that the judgments are of impermissibil-
million. Our judgments about the wrong- ity. By contrast, a rule-based system easily
ness of the action are defined over the ab- accommodates both of these core phenom-
stract category murder, not the aversion. ena of moral judgment. At a minimum, it is
Indeed, in many cases, the relevant cate- hard to see how anything but a rule-based
gories are clearly not perceptually available. system can accommodate cases such as the
Consider, for instance, moral judgments norm systems surrounding cousin marriage.
surrounding cousin marriage. In some cul- And a rule-based system can easily extend
tures (parts of Korea and India), it is abso- to such cases as prohibitions on murder,
lutely forbidden to marry one’s first cousin; theft, and so forth. That is, once we grant
in other cultures (e.g., in Saudi Arabia), it that judgments about wrongful marriage
is permitted; in other cultures, it is forbid- are guided by rules defined over abstract
den to marry one’s parallel cousin (i.e., the categories such as parallel cousin, it is natu-
child of a parent’s same-sex sibling), but not ral to grant that judgments about wrongful
a cross-cousin (i.e., the child of a parent’s harm are guided by rules defined over such
opposite-sex sibling). This is just one kind of abstract categories as harm, knowledge, and
norm, but norm systems in general have de- intention.
terminative proscriptions surrounding mar- From this perspective, it seems unparsi-
riage, sex, and insults. This also holds for monious to hold that wrongness judgments
harm-based norm systems. Norm systems in the harm domain count as a special is-
determine what can be harmed (e.g., cattle, land of wrongness judgments that does not
outsiders, children), how they can be harmed involve rules.
(e.g., slaughtering, swindling, spanking), None of this is to deny that natural aver-
and when they can be harmed (e.g., for food, sions and habit learning play an important
for advantage, for punishment). role in moral judgments of wrongness.
It is very important for members of each Moral judgments that involve actions that
community to learn the local system. To get produce intrinsically aversive outcomes
it wrong can mean punishment, ostracism, (such as cues of suffering) might well be
even death. And people do generally get treated as distinctively wrong because of the
these things right. A rule-based account is aversion (Nichols, 2004). The rule in this
obviously well suited to explain why people case might take on special salience because
can get it right, because such an account of its close ties to aversive outcomes. In addi-
draws on concepts that offer the greatest tion, even if we allow that rules play a role in
precision available. If people systematical- moral judgment, it’s a further question how
ly judge that it is wrong to marry parallel the rules become internalized. Some kind
cousins, then this is because they encode of reinforcement learning might well be key
a rule defined over the concept parallel here. That is, reinforcement learning might
 The Wrong and the Bad 43

explain why we attach value to certain rules. tinctions. The idea is that the evidence the
In these ways, the low-level accounts might child receives is too impoverished to explain
be used to supplement rule-based accounts the complex set of moral distinctions that
rather than displace them. she acquires. A key part of the problem is
the lack of negative evidence in the moral
domain (Dwyer et al., 2010, p. 492). Chil-
Extension and Expansion dren are generally not told what actions are
not impermissible, as reflected by the fact
The foregoing provides reason to believe noted above that children are not told that it
that structured rules play an essential role is sometimes okay to produce an unintended
in moral judgment. However, a major limi- but foreseen harm. The poverty of the stim-
tation of rule-based theories is that it has ulus argument here is supposed to parallel
been unclear how the rules are acquired. Chomsky’s argument for an innate language
This problem is especially salient given the acquisition device: Just as the child ends up
apparent complexity of the rules revealed in with complex syntactic rules that outstrip
studies on moral dilemmas. In the standard the available evidence, so too the child ends
“footbridge” dilemma, participants are up with moral rules that outstrip the avail-
presented with an agent who intentionally able evidence.
kills an innocent person for a greater good; The moral grammar hypothesis provides
participants regard this action as wrong. one explanation for how complex rules
In the standard “switch” dilemma, partici- might be acquired. We have been pursuing
pants are presented with an agent whose an alternative, learning-theoretic approach
action produces, as a side effect, the death to these issues. Recent work in Bayesian
of an innocent person for a greater good; learning provides a novel account of how
participants regard this action as permissi- people learn from negative evidence (Xu &
ble (Cushman et al., 2006; Mikhail, 2011). Tenenbaum, 2007). To see the idea, con-
Even children reveal this kind of pattern sider trying to determine whether a deck of
in reasoning about dilemmas (reported in cards is a pinochle deck (which has no cards
Mikhail, 2011). On a rule-based explana- numbered under 9) or a regular deck. You
tion of this pattern of responses, the rule observe a sequence of random draws from
against killing forbids intentionally killing the deck. The draws unfold as follows: Jack,
but not knowingly killing in the service of a King, 10, Ace, Queen, Jack, 10, 10, Ace.
greater good (Mikhail, 2011). That is a sub- With each of these successive draws, you
tle distinction to acquire, and children are should start becoming more confident that
presumably never given any explicit instruc- it is a pinochle deck. Why? Because if it were
tion on the matter. Few parents tell children a regular deck, it would be a suspicious co-
“It is wrong to intend to hurt someone but incidence that none of the cards is under
sometimes okay to hurt someone as a side 9. That provides evidence that there are no
effect, depending on the value of the in- cards under 9 in the deck.
tended effect.” So if we are to explain chil- Now consider the fact that many moral
dren’s facility at moral distinctions in terms rules apply to what an agent intentionally
of structured rules, we need some explana- does, but not to what an agent allows to hap-
tion for how children arrive at such complex pen. Again, parents don’t give children ex-
rules despite scant instruction. plicit instructions on the matter. They don’t
One way to explain the acquisition of say such things as “it’s wrong to produce
such rules is to posit innate biases. A num- this outcome, but it’s not wrong to allow the
ber of theorists have accordingly suggested outcome to persist.” But it’s possible that the
that there is an innate moral grammar that children can infer this based on the kinds
guides the acquisition of these complex rules of examples of violations they receive. If all
(e.g., Dwyer, Huebner, & Hauser, 2010: of the observed examples of violations are
Mikhail, 2007). In particular, theorists have examples in which the agent intentionally
suggested that a poverty of the stimulus ar- produced the outcome, this might count as
gument applies for learning these moral dis- evidence that the operative rule does not say
44 M O R A L I T Y A N D T H I N K I N G

that it is impermissible to allow the outcomes ACKNOWLEDGMENTS


to persist. Imagine getting the following ran-
dom sample of violations of a school rule: I’d like to thank Alisabeth Ayars for comments
John violated the rule by putting a truck on on an earlier draft of this chapter. Research for
this chapter was supported by Office of Naval
the shelf, Jill violated the same rule by put-
Research Grant No. 11492159.
ting a ball on the shelf, and Mike violated
the rule by putting a doll on the shelf. Now,
is Mary violating the rule when she sees a REFERENCES
puzzle on the shelf and doesn’t remove it?
The sample violations were all examples of a Blair, R. J. R. (1995). A cognitive developmental
person intentionally producing the outcome. approach to morality: Investigating the psy-
If these samples are representative, then this chopath. Cognition, 57(1), 1–29.
suggests that the rule applies to what a per- Blair, R. J. R. (1999). Psychophysiological re-
son does and not to what a person allows to sponsiveness to the distress of others in chil-
happen (or persist). Otherwise it would be dren with autism. Personality and Individual
Differences, 26(3), 477–485.
surprising that none of the sample violations Crockett, M. J. (2013). Models of morality.
included a person allowing the outcome to Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 17(8), 363–366.
happen or persist. In recent experiments, we Cushman, F. (2013). Action, outcome, and value:
find that when given only intended-outcome A dual-system framework for morality. Per-
examples such as those above, adult par- sonality and Social Psychology Review, 17(3),
ticipants do not generalize to say that the 273–292.
person who allowed the outcome to persist Cushman, F., Young, L., & Hauser, M. (2006).
violated the rule (Nichols et al., 2016). By The role of conscious reasoning and intuition
contrast, when given two examples in which in moral judgment: Testing three principles of
a person allows the outcome to persist (e.g., harm. Psychological Science, 17(12), 1082–
1089.
leaving the puzzle on the shelf), participants
de Waal, F. B., Leimgruber, K., & Greenberg,
immediately generalize to other such cases. A. R. (2008). Giving is self-rewarding for
This suggests that people are sensitive to evi- ­monkeys. Proceedings of the National Acad-
dence that bears on whether the rule applies emy of Sciences of the USA, 105(36), 13685–
only to what an agent does, or also to what 13689.
an agent allows. Dwyer, S., Huebner, B., & Hauser, M. D. (2010).
These early results suggest new direc- The linguistic analogy: Motivations, results,
tions for rule-based theorists to investigate. and speculations. Topics in Cognitive Science,
But the results are preliminary, and most of 2(3), 486–510.
the important questions remain completely Fodor, J. A., & Pylyshyn, Z. W. (1988). Connec-
open. For instance, in the learning studies, tionism and cognitive architecture: A critical
analysis. Cognition, 28(1), 3–71.
participants show a strong bias in favor of Greene, J. D., & Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2008).
intention-based rules, even when they have The secret joke of Kant’s soul. In W. Sinnott-
only one example to learn from (Nichols et Armstrong (Ed.), Moral psychology: Vol.
al., 2016). Why do people have such a strong 3. The neuroscience of morality: Emotion,
bias in favor of intention-based rules? Does disease, and development (pp. 35–79). Cam-
that require a nativist account? Further- bridge, MA: MIT Press.
more, all of this work on novel rule learning Greene, J. D., Sommerville, R. B., Nystrom, L.
has been done on adults, and we don’t know E., Darley, J. M., & Cohen, J. D. (2008). An
whether children, too, will make these kinds fMRI investigation of emotional engagement
of inferences. It is also unclear how the child in moral judgment. Science, 293(5537), 2105–
2108.
thinks about the hypothesis space. Do chil-
Hamlin, J. K., Wynn, K., & Bloom, P. (2007).
dren naturally think in terms of intention- Social evaluation by preverbal infants. Nature,
based versus outcome-based rules? If so, 450(7169), 557–559.
why do they settle on this particular hypoth- Mallon, R., & Nichols, S. (2010). Rules. In J.
esis space? Advocates of rule-based theories Doris (Ed.), The moral psychology handbook
of moral judgment have a lot of territory to (pp. 297–320). Oxford, UK: Oxford Univer-
explore. sity Press.
 The Wrong and the Bad 45

McClelland, J. L., Rumelhart, D. E., & Hinton, natural foundations of moral judgment. New
G. E. (1986). The appeal of parallel distributed York: Oxford University Press.
processing. In D. E. Rumelhart, J. L. McClel- Nichols, S., Kumar, S., Lopez, T., Ayars, A., &
land, & the PDP Research Group (Eds.), Par- Chan, H. (2016). Rational learners and moral
allel distributed processing (Vol. 1, pp. 3–44). rules. Mind and Language, 31(5), 530–554.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press/Bradford Books. Nichols, S., & Mallon, R. (2006). Moral di-
Mikhail, J. (2007). Universal moral grammar: lemmas and moral rules. Cognition, 100(3),
Theory, evidence and the future. Trends in 530–542.
Cognitive Sciences, 11(4), 143–152. Turiel, E. (1983). The development of social
Mikhail, J. (2011). Elements of moral cognition: knowledge: Morality and convention. Cam-
Rawls’ linguistic analogy and the cognitive bridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
science of moral and legal judgment. Cam- Xu, F., & Tenenbaum, J. B. (2007). Word learn-
bridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. ing as Bayesian inference. Psychological Re-
Nichols, S. (2004). Sentimental rules: On the view, 114(2), 245.
PART II
MORALITY AND FEELING

Q U E S T I O N S A N S W E R E D I N PA R T I I

CHAPTER 6  What is empathy’s role in driving moral behavior?

CHAPTER 7  Does morality have specialized cognitive and neural processes?

CHAPTER 8  What is the role of disgust in morality?

CHAPTER 9  What makes some emotions moral emotions?

CHAPTER 10  How can moral psychology use more nuanced and developed
theories of emotion to inform its process models?
CHAPTER 6

Empathy Is a Moral Force

Jamil Zaki

What is empathy’s role in driving moral behavior?

Here I argue that empathy is a noisy but useful moral compass and,
in particular, that (1) empathy’s limits in guiding morality often reflect
an empathizer’s motives, not his or her capacities; (2) motivating
people to empathize can overcome these limits; and (3) empathy
lends affective “force” to morality, such that empathy-based moral
behavior produces benefits that other forms of moral action do not.

People share each other’s emotional lives. 2014), which in turn provide an intuitive
We react not only to events that befall us, “compass” that guides moral action. Indi-
but also to the experiences of those around viduals with psychopathy, who often lack
us. The tendency to share, understand, and empathy, provide a striking example of how
care about others’ inner lives constitutes important this compass is (Blair, 2005).
empathy (Davis, 1994; Decety & Jackson, Does empathy’s compass always guide
2004; Zaki & Ochsner, 2016). people toward ideal moral behavior? Prob-
Psychologists and neuroscientists have ably not. Like other affective responses in-
produced a deluge of research on empathy volved in moral decision making (Haidt,
in recent decades. This trend reflects inter- 2001), empathy is noisy and biased. It can
est not only in empathy’s characteristics but spur concern for the well-being of some
also in its power to encourage prosocial and people but not others, for instance, skew-
moral action. Individuals help the targets ing prosocial behavior unfairly toward in-
of their empathy (Batson, 1991, 2011) and group members. Empathy can even generate
“humanize” those targets, for instance by clearly immoral choices—for instance, when
resisting stereotypes about them or treating empathy for one’s own community encour-
them fairly (Galinsky & Moskowitz, 2000). ages aggression toward other groups (Lickel,
These behaviors likely reflect empathy’s ef- Miller, Stenstrom, Denson, & Schmader,
fects in prompting aversion to others’ pain 2006).
and pleasure in others’ success (Lamm, De- These biases and constraints have led the-
cety, & Singer, 2011; Morelli, Lieberman, orists to propose that empathy constitutes a
& Zaki, 2015; Morelli, Sacchet, & Zaki, suboptimal, and even dangerous, source of

49
50 M O R A L I T Y A N D F E E L I N G

moral behavior (Bloom, 2013; Prinz, 2011a). low a shift in popular empathy. For instance,
For instance, Bloom (2013) highlights the Harriet Beecher Stowe’s novel Uncle Tom’s
case of “Baby Jessica,” who became trapped Cabin, which prompted widespread empa-
in a well. Her case was captured on televi- thy for the struggles of slaves, also intensi-
sion and subsequently produced a worldwide fied support for the abolitionist movement
outpouring of empathy. Donors provided of the 19th century (Appiah, 2010).
hundreds of thousands of dollars to support This and other work has inspired scien-
Baby Jessica, while ignoring the simultane- tific accounts under which empathy provides
ous suffering of countless others. a vital, evolutionarily old emotional founda-
How could an emotional state that pro- tion for moral action (De Waal, 2010) and
duces such misguided moral behavior ever the expansion of moral values (Pinker, 2011).
be trusted? Critics of empathy suggest that On such accounts, social turmoil, such as
morality can better serve the greater good political polarization, reflects people’s fail-
if it is guided by utilitarian principles (i.e., ure to empathize with members of other
doing the most good for the most people), as groups (Trout, 2009), and remedying such
opposed to emotion. This viewpoint is im- problems requires either reinstating lost em-
portant and clearly right in many cases. It pathy or building empathic concern for ever
is also incomplete and risks discarding the wider swaths of the population (Krznaric,
baby with the proverbial well water. 2014; Rifkin, 2009; Singer, 2011).
Here I offer a counterpoint to recent criti- More recently, however, a growing coun-
cisms of empathy, in two parts. First, I sug- tercurrent has questioned the utility of empa-
gest that the limits of empathy are not stable thy in driving moral action. This argument
and instead reflect individuals’ motivation builds on the broader idea that emotions
to connect with or avoid others’ experiences. provide powerful but noisy inputs to people’s
These motives shift dynamically across situ- moral calculus (Haidt, 2001). Affective reac-
ations, and strategies that increase empathic tions often tempt people to make judgments
motivation can also reduce biases associated that are logically and morally indefensible.
with empathy. Second, although utilitarian Such emotional static famously includes
principles best guide the behavior of large moral dumbfounding, under which people’s
groups, individuals who act morally “with experience of disgust causes them to judge
feeling” are likely to be more committed to others’ actions as wrong when they have no
and fulfilled by their behaviors. Thus, to the rational basis for doing so (Cushman, Young,
extent that people can align their principles & Hauser, 2006). Emotion drives other irra-
and affect, empathy can lend emotional tional moral judgments, such as people’s ten-
meaning to moral actions. dency to privilege physical force (a “hot” fac-
tor) over more important dimensions, such
as harm, when judging the moral status of an
Historical Context action (Greene, 2014; Greene et al., 2009).
Even incidental, morally irrelevant feelings
The modern concept of empathy is tied alter moral judgment, further damaging the
at the roots to moral philosophy. Adam credibility of emotion in guiding a sense of
Smith, in The Theory of Moral Sentiments right and wrong (Wheatley & Haidt, 2005).
(1790/2002), famously described the “fel- In sum, although emotions play a power-
low feeling”—vicarious experience of oth- ful role in moral judgment, they need not
ers’ emotions—as a source of civilizing and play a useful role. Instead, capricious emo-
moral action. In the intervening centuries, tion-driven intuitions often attract people
empirical data have borne out Smith’s in- toward internally inconsistent and wrong-
sight. In particular, Batson systematically headed judgments. From a utilitarian per-
demonstrated that empathy encourages spective aimed at maximizing well-being,
moral actions, including the maintenance of these biases render emotion a fundamentally
equity and kindness to people in need (e.g., mistaken moral engine (cf. Greene, 2014).
Batson, 2011; Batson et al., 2003; Batson & Does this criticism apply to empathy? In
Shaw, 1991). At a macro level, key moments many ways, it does. Like other affective
in a culture’s moral development often fol- states, empathy arises in response to evoca-
 Empathy Is a Moral Force 51

tive experiences, often in noisy ways that missed it too readily. I believe this for two
hamper objectivity. For instance, people ex- reasons.
perience more empathy, and thus the moral
obligation to help, in response to the visible
Empathy Is Motivated, and Limits on Empathy
suffering of others, as in the case of Baby
Are Not Stable
Jessica described above. This empathy leads
people to donate huge sums of money to help Critics of empathy characterize it as biased:
individuals whose stories they read about or responding to morally irrelevant content
see on television, while ignoring widespread (e.g., visibility) while missing morally rel-
misery that they could more efficaciously re- evant content (e.g., total suffering). Must
lieve (Genevsky, Västfjäll, Slovic, & Knut- moral “mistakes” like these always char-
son, 2013; Slovic, 2007; Small & Loewen- acterize empathy? In order to answer this
stein, 2003). Empathy also collapses reliably question, we must first ask another: To what
when sufferers and would-be empathizers extent can people control their experience of
differ along dimensions of race, politics, empathy? Psychological theory and lay intu-
age, or even meaningless de novo group as- ition converge to suggest that empathy tends
signments (Cikara, Bruneau, & Saxe, 2011; to fall out of our control. Imagine, for in-
Zaki & Cikara, 2015). stance, witnessing someone suffer a horrific
Even when people experience empathy, the industrial accident. In cases such as this, it
causal link between affect and moral action doesn’t seem as though observers select their
can be circuitous and noisy. At an interindi- level of empathy; vicarious distress simply
vidual level, empathy fails to predict sensitiv- happens to them. The assertion that empa-
ity to just versus unjust outcomes (Decety & thy is automatic runs through the philoso-
Yoder, 2015). Worse, in some cases empathy phy (Goldman, 2006), psychology (Hatfield,
inspires expressly unjust behavior. For in- Forbes, & Rapson, 2013), and neuroscience
stance, close connection with ingroup mem- (Gallese, 2007) of empathy (for a compre-
bers can prompt aggression toward outgroup hensive review of this account, see Zaki,
members (Gilead & Liberman, 2014; Waytz 2014).
& Epley, 2012). Even when empathy gener- If empathy is automatic, then people can
ates rapport across group boundaries, it can control neither when they feel empathy
do so at the cost of justice. Low-status group nor when they do not. Under such a state
members who empathize with higher status of affairs, the biases that characterize em-
individuals grow reticent to criticize unfair pathy—such as ingroup favoritism—are as
structural norms, such as unequal access uncontrollable as the experience of empathy
to education and resources (Dixon, Tropp, itself. This assumption underlies arguments
Durrheim, & Tredoux, 2010; Saguy, Tausch, for minimizing the role of empathy in moral
Dovidio, & Pratto, 2009). In these cases, decision making. For instance, Greene
empathy improves surface-level relations be- (2014) suggests that “automatic empathy
tween groups at the cost of more meaningful programs” lead people toward poor moral
social change (Zaki & Cikara, 2015). choices and that “it would be foolish to let
Empathy thus falls prey to the same limi- the inflexible operating characteristics of
tations as other emotions in driving moral our empathy gizmos serve as foundational
behavior: It is hot-headed, short-sighted, moral principles” (p. 264).
and parochial. We would begrudge these This take on empathy reflects a broader
qualities in policy makers trying to render view of emotions as fundamentally distinct
the most good for the largest number of from and inaccessible to cognition. This
people. So why should people ever rely on model is at least as old as Plato’s account of
empathy when making moral judgments? reason and passion. It is also incorrect. De-
cades of data from affective science demon-
strate that logic and emotion interact perva-
Theoretical Stance sively. Moral theorists focus largely on one
side of this interaction: ways that emotions
Empathy is not a perfect source of moral inadvertently color thinking, producing ir-
choice, but I think its recent critics have dis- rational but strongly held judgments. The
52 M O R A L I T Y A N D F E E L I N G

opposite causal direction—from thinking further in the later section on extension and
to affect—matters just as much. Cognition expansion).
takes part in “constructing” the emotions
that people feel (Barrett, 2013; Schachter &
Empathy‑Based Action Confers
Singer, 1962) and judge others to feel (Ong,
Unique Benefits
Zaki, & Goodman, 2015). Cognition–­affect
interactions also characterize emotion regu­ If empathy is motivated, people should be
lation, through which people alter their feel­ capable of empathizing in “smarter” ways
ings in response to their goals (Gross, 2015; that supersede group boundaries and other
Inzlicht, Bartholow, & Hirsh, 2015; Ochs­ morally irrelevant factors. Still, empathy
ner, Silvers, & Buhle, 2012). will always be subject to some noise and can­
Emotion regulation often comprises not match the optimal moral principles that
people’s attempts to feel better by reduc­ emerge from a utilitarian approach (Singer,
ing negative affect or maximizing positive 2015). Empathy will never provide anyone
affect, but people sometimes want to feel with a perfect moral compass. As such, even
bad. For instance, prior to conflicts, people if empathic limits can be overcome, why
up-regulate their experience of anger, and, bother?
prior to making a request for support, they One important reason is that prosocial
up-regulate sadness (Tamir, 2009). In these and moral action driven by empathy might
contexts, negative emotions help people ac­ differ from action based solely on principle.
complish their goals and thus become the These differences confer at least some ad­
target of regulation strategies. “Social” emo­ vantages to empathy-based action, many of
tions such as gratitude, righteous anger, and which reflect the added force emotions lend
guilt are particularly useful in driving inter­ to action.
personal outcomes such as cooperation (De­ First, emotional goals often take prec­
Steno, 2015; Trivers, 1971). As such, people edent over nonemotional goals, and people
regulate their experience of these states in pursue such goals with urgency and imme­
response to social goals. diacy. Principles are difficult to abide on an
I propose that empathy follows suit. In­ empty stomach or under other states that tax
stead of succumbing to their experience (or people’s psychological energy. For instance,
nonexperience) of empathy, people often cognitive load interferes with utilitarian
choose to engage with or avoid others’ emo­ moral judgments (Greene, Morelli, Lowen­
tions. This choice can be conscious or not, berg, Nystrom, & Cohen, 2008). Emotions,
and—like other forms of emotion regula­ by contrast, guide behavior efficiently and
tion—it (1) reflects people’s goals in a given in ways that are robust to limits on people’s
context and (2) can be carried out through cognitive bandwith. As such, to the extent
multiple strategies (for a thorough review of that people can tune empathy to match their
this model, see Zaki, 2014). principles, they gain access to a “hot,” emo­
A motivated account recasts the “empath­ tional engine for powering prosocial behav­
ic failures” described earlier. When people ior (DeSteno, 2009).
exhibit blunted empathy to strangers or Second, emotion-based moral behavior
outgroup members, this does not mean that might confer benefits that other moral be­
they are incapable of empathizing; instead haviors do not. Prosocial actions “help the
they might be unmotivated to do so (Key­ helper,” such that acting kindly renders peo­
sers & Gazzola, 2014). This is important ple healthier and longer-lived (Dunn, Aknin,
because it suggests that limits of empathy & Norton, 2014; Thoits & Hewitt, 2001).
are not “baked in” to the nature of empa­ These benefits likely reflect boosts in sub­
thy itself. Instead, they signal local features jective well being—such as increased happi­
of a situation that reduce people’s propen­ ness and decreased stress—that prosociality
sity to empathize. To the extent that this is provides (Dunn, Aknin, & Norton, 2008;
the case, empathic limits can be overcome Zaki & Mitchell, 2013). I propose that these
by increasing motivation to empathy, and boosts most often follow prosocial acts driv­
empathy can be harnessed to build moral en by passion, not principle. The benefits
concern on a broad scale (this is discussed of emotion-driven moral action likely tran­
 Empathy Is a Moral Force 53

scend single individuals. Recipients of oth- Dweck (2006; Dweck & Leggett, 1988) has
ers’ support, for instance, benefit most from demonstrated that people vary in their be-
emotion-driven help, and emotion strength- liefs about whether characteristics such as
ens the reputational and relational benefits intelligence, prejudice, and personality are
associated with helping others. “fixed” and out of their control or “mal-
In sum, emotions in general—and empa- leable” and within their control. People who
thy in particular—add weight both to the hold malleable, as compared with fixed, the-
efficiency of prosocial actions and to their ories embrace challenges and difficulties as
benefits. If this is the case, then cultivating opportunities to grow valued psychological
empathy-based morality stands as a worth- skills (Blackwell, Trzesniewski, & Dweck,
while goal. 2007; Dweck, Chiu, & Hong, 1995; Rattan
& Dweck, 2010; Yeager, Trzesniewski, &
Dweck, 2012).
Evidence Recently, we found that lay theories con-
cerning empathy likewise affect empathic
Decades of research support a motivated motivation (Schumann, Zaki, & Dweck,
model of empathy (see Zaki, 2014, for re- 2014). People who held a malleable empath-
view). In particular, it is clear that situation- ic theory—or in whom we induced such a
al factors reliably increase and decrease peo- theory—exhibited more willingness to em-
ple’s desire to empathize. This is reflected pathize than people holding a fixed lay the-
across self-reports, behavior, and brain ac- ory. This difference was especially stark in
tivity (Cameron & Payne, 2011; Keysers & cases in which people might not otherwise
Gazzola, 2014; Tamir, 2013). When empa- feel motivated to empathize, such as inter-
thy is goal-inconsistent—for instance, when group settings or when empathy promises to
it carries heavy financial or emotional costs be painful.
or interferes with people’s ability to compete These data dovetail to support the idea
with others—people avoid empathy-provok- that empathy is far from automatic and
ing situations and cues (Davis et al., 1999; often reflects people’s motives to connect
Pancer, McMullen, Kabatoff, Johnson, & with or avoid others’ emotions. This further
Pond, 1979; Shaw, Batson, & Todd, 1994). suggests, crucially, that features of empathy
By contrast, manipulations that render that often render it a poor moral compass
empathy more goal-relevant cause people to can be reversed. Increasing empathic mo-
expand their empathic experience. People tives can also expand the scope of empathy,
who are lonely or desire social connection, even to cases in which it typically fails.
as compared with people who are more so- Evidence also supports the contention
cially “sated,” play closer attention to oth- that empathy lends weight to moral actions
ers’ internal states (Gump & Kulik, 1997; and the benefits they confer. Consider the
Pickett, Gardner, & Knowles, 2004). Like- effect of prosociality on well-being (Dunn
wise, people who believe that empathy is et al., 2014; Thoits et al., 2001). Kindness
socially desirable or common among their pays dividends to those who engage in it, but
peers also act empathically themselves, more recent work suggests that such benefits
even toward outgroup members (Nook, are strongest for individuals who are affec-
Ong, Morelli, Mitchell, & Zaki, 2017; Tar- tively engaged in their prosocial acts. For
rant, Dazeley, & Cottom, 2009; Thomas & instance, volunteering decreases mortality
Maio, 2008). In these cases, goal relevance risks in older adults, but only if their ser-
increases empathic effort, or the extent to vice is driven by “other-oriented” motives,
which people pursue empathy. Empathy and such as empathic concern for people in need
its consequences—including prosocial and (Konrath, Fuhrel-Forbis, Lou, & Brown,
kind action—follow suit. 2012). Likewise, college students experience
Interestingly, the very notion that em- increased happiness and reduced stress after
pathy is out of people’s control might hin- providing practical help to others, but these
der empathic effort. This follows from the effects are strongest in people who empathi-
broader idea of “lay theories,” or beliefs cally engage with the targets of their help
people hold about psychological constructs. (Morelli, Lee, Arnn, & Zaki, 2015).
54 M O R A L I T Y A N D F E E L I N G

Empathy-based prosociality maximally address the empathy deficit (cf. Zaki & Ci-
benefits not only helpers but also the re- kara, 2015). A small but growing number
cipients of their help. When people turn to of interventions focus on building empathy
each other under both difficult and happy across settings including medical training
circumstances, they seek out not only con- (Riess, Kelley, Bailey, Dunn, & Phillips,
crete help but also emotional connection 2012), education (ahin, 2012), conflict
(Rimé, 2007; Zaki & Williams, 2013). As resolution (Todd & Galinsky, 2014), and the
such, people feel closer to support provid- treatment of clinical populations in which
ers who experience and exhibit empathy, as empathy is impaired, such as in autism spec-
opposed to those who provide less emotion- trum disorders (Golan & Baron-Cohen,
ally responsive support (Gable, Gonzaga, & 2006; Hadwin, Baron-Cohen, Howlin, &
Strachman, 2006; Gable & Reis, 2010). Hill, 1996). The majority of these interven-
Finally, emotion serves as a broader so- tions focus on two strategies: building em-
cial signal about the meaning of prosocial pathic skills, such as emotion recognition,
actions. Groups elevate the moral status of and inducing people to think more about
people who act prosocially (Hardy & Van social targets. This strategy is effective over-
Vugt, 2006). Here, too, emotion matters. In- all (van Berkhout & Malouff, 2016), but a
dividuals who express emotion when acting motivated model of empathy suggests that
prosocially are perceived by others as more it is also incomplete. In many cases, people
genuinely motivated to help others, further fail to empathize not because they are inca-
building the social capital kindness provides pable of doing so but because they are un-
(Barasch, Levine, Berman, & Small, 2014). motivated to share, understand, or generate
Broadly, this work demonstrates that peo- concern for others’ internal lives. As such,
ple benefit most not from moral acts alone, interventions should complement training in
but rather from those that are imbued with empathic skills with “psychological levers”
affective force. Empathy is a messy source (Miller & Prentice, 2010) that can build peo-
of prosociality, and at a broad policy level ple’s desire to empathize in the first place.
utilitarian principles provide a clearer moral Second, the work covered here offers evi-
compass than affect. But at an individual dence about why we should care about em-
level, not only can people flexibly align em- pathic deficits. On some accounts, a lack of
pathy with their principles, but doing so also empathy—although alarming—might be in-
renders their subsequent moral action more consequential. This conclusion is predicated
powerful. on the idea that empathy is at best a dubious
source of moral behavior and at worst a bar-
rier to broad moral progress (Bloom, 2014;
Extension and Expansion Greene, 2014; Prinz, 2011b). Here I propose
that this perspective obscures both people’s
Former President Obama routinely refers to flexibility to grow their empathy beyond its
an “empathy deficit” that threatens the co- typical limits and also the unique power of
hesion of our social fabric (Obama, 2006). empathy in rendering moral acts more ben-
Consistent with his view, college students’ eficial.
self-reported empathy has dwindled over Empathy is noisy, but scientists should not
the last 30 years (Konrath, O’Brien, & be so quick to dismiss it as a moral force.
Hsing, 2011). Empathy deficits pervade cru- Although unstable when compared with
cial social problems, such as the increasing principles, emotion can lend those principles
polarization that characterizes our politi- deeper psychological meaning.
cal system (Prior, 2013), the rise of bully-
ing among adolescents (Wang, Iannotti, &
REFERENCES
Nansel, 2009), and medical professionals’
lack of connection to their patients (Haque Appiah, A. (2010). The honor code: How moral
& Waytz, 2012). revolutions happen. New York: Norton.
The ideas laid out above offer two broad Barasch, A., Levine, E. E., Berman, J. Z., &
points about this state of affairs. First, they Small, D. A. (2014). Selfish or selfless?: On the
make novel suggestions about how we can signal value of emotion in altruistic behavior.
 Empathy Is a Moral Force 55

Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, tional architecture of human empathy. Behav-
107(3), 393. ioral and Cognitive Neuroscience Reviews,
Barrett, L. F. (2013). Psychological construc- 3(2), 71–100.
tion: The Darwinian approach to the science Decety, J., & Yoder, K. J. (2015). Empathy and
of emotion. Emotion Review, 5(4), 379–389. motivation for justice: Cognitive empathy and
Batson, C. D. (1991). The altruism question: To- concern, but not emotional empathy, predict
ward a social-psychological answer Hillsdale, sensitivity to injustice for others. Social Neu-
NJ: Erlbaum. roscience, 11(1), 1–14.
Batson, C. D. (2011). Altruism in humans. Ox- DeSteno, D. (2009). Social emotions and in-
ford, UK: Oxford University Press. tertemporal choice, “hot” mechanisms for
Batson, C. D., Lishner, D. A., Carpenter, A., building social and economic capital. Current
Dulin, L., Harjusola-Webb, S., Stocks, E. L., Directions in Psychological Science, 18(5),
. . . Sampat, B. (2003). “ . . . As you would 280–284.
have them do unto you”: Does imagining DeSteno, D. (2015). Compassion and altruism:
yourself in the other’s place stimulate moral How our minds determine who is worthy of
action? Personality and Social Psychology help. Current Opinion in Behavioral Sciences,
Bulletin, 29(9), 1190–1201. 3, 80–83.
Batson, C. D., & Shaw, L. (1991). Evidence for Dixon, J., Tropp, L. R., Durrheim, K., &
altruism: Toward a pluralism of prosocial mo- Tredoux, C. (2010). “Let them eat harmony”:
tives. Psychological Inquiry, 2(2), 107–122. Prejudice-reduction strategies and attitudes
Blackwell, L. S., Trzesniewski, K. H., & Dweck, of historically disadvantaged groups. Current
C. S. (2007). Implicit theories of intelligence Directions in Psychological Science, 19(2),
predict achievement across an adolescent tran- 76–80.
sition: A longitudinal study and an interven- Dunn, E., Aknin, L. B., & Norton, M. I. (2008).
tion. Child Development, 78(1), 246–263. Spending money on others promotes happi-
Blair, R. J. (2005). Responding to the emotions ness. Science, 319(5870), 1687–1688.
of others: Dissociating forms of empathy Dunn, E., Aknin, L., & Norton, M. (2014). Pro-
through the study of typical and psychiatric social spending and happiness: Using money
populations. Consciousness and Cognition, to benefit others pays off. Current Directions
14(4), 698–718. in Psychological Science, 23(2), 41–47.
Bloom, P. (2013, May 20). The baby in the well: Dweck, C. S. (2006). Mindset: The new psychol-
The case against empathy. The New Yorker, ogy of success. New York: Random House.
p. 20. Dweck, C. S., Chiu, C. Y., & Hong, Y. (1995).
Bloom, P. (2014, September 10). Against empa- Implicit theories and their role in judgments
thy. Boston Review. and reactions: A word from two perspectives.
Cameron, C. D., & Payne, B. K. (2011). Escaping Psychological Inquiry, 6(4), 267–285.
affect: How motivated emotion regulation cre- Dweck, C. S., & Leggett, E. L. (1988). A social-
ates insensitivity to mass suffering. Journal of cognitive approach to motivation and person-
Personality and Social Psychology, 100(1), 1. ality. Psychological Review, 95(2), 256–273.
Cikara, M., Bruneau, E., & Saxe, R. (2011). Gable, S. L., Gonzaga, G. C., & Strachman, A.
Us and them: Intergroup failures in empathy. (2006). Will you be there for me when things
Current Directions in Psychological Science, go right?: Supportive responses to positive
20, 149–153. event disclosures. Journal of Personality and
Cushman, F., Young, L., & Hauser, M. (2006). Social Psychology, 91(5), 904.
The role of conscious reasoning and intuition Gable, S. L., & Reis, H. T. (2010). Good news!:
in moral judgment: Testing three principles of Capitalizing on positive events in an interper-
harm. Psychological Science, 17(12), 1082– sonal context. Advances in Experimental So-
1089. cial Psychology, 42, 195–257.
Davis, M. (1994). Empathy: A social psychologi- Galinsky, A. D., & Moskowitz, G. B. (2000).
cal approach. New York: Westview Press. Perspective-taking: Decreasing stereotype ex-
Davis, M., Mitchell, K. V., Hall, J. A., Lothert, pression, stereotype accessibility, and in-group
J., Snapp, T., & Meyer, M. (1999). Empathy, favoritism. Journal of Personality and Social
expectations, and situational preferences: Per- Psychology, 78(4), 708.
sonality influences on the decision to partici- Gallese, V. (2007). Before and below “theory of
pate in volunteer helping behaviors. Journal of mind”: Embodied simulation and the neural
Personality, 67(3), 469–503. correlates of social cognition. Philosophical
De Waal, F. (2010). The age of empathy: Na- Transactions of the Royal Society of London
ture’s lessons for a kinder society. New York: B: Biological Sciences, 362(1480), 659–669.
Random House. Genevsky, A., Västfjäll, D., Slovic, P., & Knut-
Decety, J., & Jackson, P. L. (2004). The func- son, B. (2013). Neural underpinnings of the
56 M O R A L I T Y A N D F E E L I N G

identifiable victim effect: Affect shifts pref- (2015). Emotional foundations of cognitive
erences for giving. Journal of Neuroscience, control. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 19(3),
33(43), 17188–17196. 126–132.
Gilead, M., & Liberman, N. (2014). We take care Keysers, C., & Gazzola, V. (2014). Dissociating
of our own: Caregiving salience increases out- the ability and propensity for empathy. Trends
group bias in response to out-group threat. in Cognitive Sciences, 18(4), 163–166.
Psychological Science, 25(7), 1380–1387. Konrath, S., Fuhrel-Forbis, A., Lou, A., &
Golan, O., & Baron-Cohen, S. (2006). System- Brown, S. (2012). Motives for volunteering are
izing empathy: Teaching adults with Asperger associated with mortality risk in older adults.
syndrome or high-functioning autism to rec- Health Psychology, 31(1), 87.
ognize complex emotions using interactive Konrath, S., O’Brien, E., & Hsing, C. (2011).
multimedia. Development and Psychopathol- Changes in dispositional empathy in American
ogy, 18(2), 591–617. college students over time: A meta-analysis.
Goldman, A. I. (2006). Simulating minds: The Personality and Social Psychology Review,
philosophy, psychology, and neuroscience of 15(2), 180–198.
mindreading. New York: Oxford University Krznaric, R. (2014). Empathy: A handbook for
Press. revolution. New York: Random House.
Greene, J. (2014). Moral tribes: Emotion, reason Lamm, C., Decety, J., & Singer, T. (2011). Me-
and the gap between us and them. New York: ta-analytic evidence for common and distinct
Penguin Press. neural networks associated with directly expe-
Greene, J., Cushman, F. A., Stewart, L. E., rienced pain and empathy for pain. NeuroIm-
Lowenberg, K., Nystrom, L. E., & Cohen, J. age, 54(3), 2492–2502.
D. (2009). Pushing moral buttons: The inter- Lickel, B., Miller, N., Stenstrom, D. M., Den-
action between personal force and intention in son, T. F., & Schmader, T. (2006). Vicarious
moral judgment. Cognition, 111(3), 364–371. retribution: The role of collective blame in
Greene, J., Morelli, S. A., Lowenberg, K., Nys- intergroup aggression. Personality and Social
trom, L. E., & Cohen, J. D. (2008). Cogni- Psychology Review, 10(4), 372–390.
tive load selectively interferes with utilitarian Miller, D., & Prentice, D. (2010). Psychological
moral judgment. Cognition, 107(3), 1144– levers of behavior change. In E. Shafir (Ed.),
1154. Behavioral foundations of policy. New York:
Gross, J. J. (2015). Emotion regulation: Current Russell Sage Foundation.
status and future prospects. Psychological In- Morelli, S., Lee, I., Arnn, M., & Zaki, J. 2015).
quiry, 26(1), 1–26. Emotional and instrumental support provision
Gump, B. B., & Kulik, J. A. (1997). Stress, af- interact to predict well-being. Emotion, 15(4),
filiation, and emotional contagion. Journal of 484–493.
Personality and Social Psychology, 72(2), 305. Morelli, S., Lieberman, M., & Zaki, J. (2015).
Hadwin, J., Baron-Cohen, S., Howlin, P., & The emerging study of positive empathy. So-
Hill, K. (1996). Can we teach children with cial and Personality Psychology Compass,
autism to understand emotion, belief, or pre- 9(2), 57–68.
tense? Development and Psychopathology, 8, Morelli, S., Sacchet, M. D., & Zaki, J. (2014).
345–365. Common and distinct neural correlates of
Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional dog and its ra- personal and vicarious reward: A quantitative
tional tail: A social intuitionist approach meta-analysis. NeuroImage, 112, 244–253.
to moral judgment. Psychological Review, Nook, E., Ong, D., Morelli, S., Mitchell, J., &
108(4), 814–834. Zaki, J. (2017). Prosocial conformity: Social
Haque, O. S., & Waytz, A. (2012). Dehumaniza- norms motivate broad generosity and empa-
tion in medicine: Causes, solutions, and func- thy. Manuscript submitted for publication.
tions. Perspectives on Psychological Science, Obama, B. (2006). Commencement address.
7(2), 176–186. Northwestern University, Evanston, IL.
Hardy, C. L., & Van Vugt, M. (2006). Nice guys Ochsner, K., Silvers, J., & Buhle, J. (2012). Func-
finish first: The competitive altruism hypoth- tional imaging studies of emotion regulation:
esis. Personality and Social Psychology Bulle- A synthetic review and evolving model of the
tin, 32(10), 1402–1413. cognitive control of emotion. Annals of the
Hatfield, E., Forbes, M., & Rapson, R. (2013). New York Academy of Sciences, 1251, E1–
Emotional contagion as a precursor to collec- E24.
tive emotions. In C. von Scheve & M. Salmela Ong, D., Zaki, J., & Goodman, N. (2015). Af-
(Eds.), Collective emotions. Oxford, UK: Ox- fective cognition: Exploring lay theories of
ford University Press. emotion. Cognition, 143, 141–162.
Inzlicht, M., Bartholow, B. D., & Hirsh, J. B. Pancer, S. M., McMullen, L. M., Kabatoff, R.
 Empathy Is a Moral Force 57

A., Johnson, K. G., & Pond, C. A. (1979). consequences. Journal of Personality and So-
Conflict and avoidance in the helping situa- cial Psychology, 67(5), 879–887.
tion. Journal of Personality and Social Psy- Singer, P. (2011). The expanding circle: Ethics,
chology, 37(8), 1406–1411. evolution, and moral progress. Princeton, NJ:
Pickett, C. L., Gardner, W. L., & Knowles, M. Princeton University Press.
(2004). Getting a cue: The need to belong and Singer, P. (2015). The most good you can do:
enhanced sensitivity to social cues. Person- How effective altruism is changing ideas
ality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 30(9), about living ethically. New Haven, CT: Yale
1095–1107. University Press.
Pinker, S. (2011). The better angels of our na- Slovic, P. (2007). If I look at the mass I will never
ture: Why violence has declined. New York: act: Psychic numbing and genocide. Judgment
Viking. and Decision Making, 2(2), 79–95.
Prinz, J. (2011a). Against empathy. Southern Small, D. A., & Loewenstein, G. (2003). Helping
Journal of Philosophy, 49(1), 214–233. a victim or helping the victim: Altruism and
Prinz, J. (2011b). Is empathy necessary for mo- identifiability. Journal of Risk and Uncertain-
rality? In A. Coplan & P. Goldie (Eds.), Em- ty, 26(1), 5–16.
pathy: Philosophical and psychological per- Smith, A. (2002). The theory of moral senti-
spectives (pp. 211–229). New York: Oxford ments. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University
University Press. Press. (Original work published 1790)
Prior, M. (2013). Media and political polariza- Tamir, M. (2009). What do people want to feel
tion. Annual Review of Political Science, 16, and why?: Pleasure and utility in emotion reg-
101–127. ulation. Current Directions in Psychological
Rattan, A., & Dweck, C. S. (2010). Who con- Science, 18(2), 101–105.
fronts prejudice?: The role of implicit theories Tamir, M. (2013). What do people want to feel
in the motivation to confront prejudice. Psy- in intractable conflicts? Paper presented at the
chological Science, 21(7), 952–959. meeting of the Society for Experimental Social
Riess, H., Kelley, J. M., Bailey, R. W., Dunn, E. Psychology, Berkeley, CA.
J., & Phillips, M. (2012). Empathy training for Tarrant, M., Dazeley, S., & Cottom, T. (2009).
resident physicians: A randomized controlled Social categorization and empathy for out-
trial of a neuroscience-informed curriculum. group members. British Journal of Social Psy-
Journal of General Internal Medicine, 27(10), chology, 48(3), 427–446.
1280–1286. Thoits, P. A., & Hewitt, L. N. (2001). Volunteer
Rifkin, J. (2009). The empathic civilization: The work and well-being. Journal of Health and
race to global consciousness in a world in cri- Social Behavior, 42(2), 115–131.
sis. New York: Penguin Press. Thomas, G., & Maio, G. R. (2008). Man, I feel
Rimé, B. (2007). Interpersonal emotion regula- like a woman: When and how gender-role mo-
tion. In J. Gross (Ed.), Handbook of emotion tivation helps mind-reading. Journal of Per-
regulation (pp. 466–485). New York: Guil- sonality and Social Psychology, 95(5), 1165.
ford Press. Todd, A. R., & Galinsky, A. D. (2014). Perspec-
Saguy, T., Tausch, N., Dovidio, J. F., & Pratto, F. tive-taking as a strategy for improving inter-
(2009). The irony of harmony: Intergroup con- group relations: Evidence, mechanisms, and
tact can produce false expectations for equal- qualifications. Social and Personality Psychol-
ity. Psychological Science, 20(1), 114–121. ogy Compass, 8(7), 374–387.
ahin, M. (2012). An investigation into the ef- Trivers, R. (1971). The evolution of reciprocal
ficiency of empathy training program on pre- altruism. Quarterly Review of Biology, 46,
venting bullying in primary schools. Children 35–57.
and Youth Services Review, 34(7), 1325–1330. Trout, J. (2009). The empathy gap: Building
Schachter, S., & Singer, J. E. (1962). Cognitive, bridges to the good life and the good society.
social, and physiological determinants of emo- New York: Penguin Press.
tion state. Psychological Review, 69, 379–399. van Berkhout, E., & Malouff, J. (2016). The ef-
Schumann, K., Zaki, J., & Dweck, C. S. (2014). ficacy of empathy training: A meta-analysis
Addressing the empathy deficit: Beliefs about of randomized controlled trials. Journal of
the malleability of empathy predict effort- Counseling Psychology, 63(1), 32–41.
ful responses when empathy is challenging. Wang, J., Iannotti, R. J., & Nansel, T. R. (2009).
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, School bullying among adolescents in the
107(3), 475–493. United States: Physical, verbal, relational, and
Shaw, L., Batson, C. D., & Todd, R. M. (1994). cyber. Journal of Adolescent Health, 45(4),
Empathy avoidance: Forestalling feeling for 368–375.
another in order to escape the motivational Waytz, A., & Epley, N. (2012). Social connection
58 M O R A L I T Y A N D F E E L I N G

enables dehumanization. Journal of Experi- Zaki, J., & Cikara, M. (2015). Addressing em-
mental Social Psychology, 48(1), 70–76. pathic failures. Current Directions in Psycho-
Wheatley, T., & Haidt, J. (2005). Hypnotic dis- logical Science, 24(6), 471–476.
gust makes moral judgments more severe. Psy- Zaki, J., & Mitchell, J. P. (2013). Intuitive pro-
chological Science, 16(10), 780–784. sociality. Current Directions in Psychological
Yeager, D. S., Trzesniewski, K. H., & Dweck, C. Science, 22(6), 466–470.
S. (2012). An implicit theories of personality Zaki, J., & Ochsner, K. (2016). Empathy. In L. F.
intervention reduces adolescent aggression in Barrett, M. Lewis, & J. Haviland-Jones (Eds.),
response to victimization and exclusion. Child Handbook of emotions (4th ed., pp. 871–
Development, 84(3), 970–988. 884). New York: Guilford Press.
Zaki, J. (2014). Empathy: A motivated account. Zaki, J., & Williams, W. C. (2013). Interpersonal
Psychological Bulletin, 140(6), 1608–1647. emotion regulation. Emotion, 13(5), 803–810.
CHAPTER 7

Moral Values and Motivations


How Special Are They?

Ryan Miller
Fiery Cushman

Does morality have specialized cognitive and neural processes?

Moral cognition—including the value of moral actions, outcomes,


and their integration—is supported by domain-general cognitive and
neural architecture tied to reward processing and economic decision
making.

Moral values are central to human identity. moral values—and punish them when they
Charles Darwin considered the human moral don’t. In contrast, we don’t punish them for
sense, or “conscience,” to be the single most hating Mozart (at least not often). Similarly,
important attribute distinguishing us from we feel guilt or shame when our own actions
other animals (1872), and recent research are inconsistent with our moral values, but
suggests that the particular constellation of we don’t usually feel guilt or shame when
moral traits you possess is a big part of what we violate our food preferences and try a
makes you “you” (Strohminger & Nichols, new dish. Moral values also tend to be sa-
2014). Given this privileged status, we ask a cred, meaning people are unwilling to place
simple question: Is there something special a material price tag on them or openly trade
that makes moral value different from other them against secular goods (Tetlock, Kristel,
kinds of values that humans hold? Is the way Beth, Green, & Lerner, 2000).
it is acquired, stored, or implemented in the A closer look, however, reveals broad sim-
brain fundamentally special? Or might the ilarities between moral and nonmoral value.
difference be less sharp, with a common sys- Both motivate us to obtain certain goals or
tem (or systems) handling value of all kinds? desirable outcomes—such as the welfare
In many ways, the moral value we attach of sick children or the newest technologi-
to particular behaviors or social outcomes, cal gadget—and we experience pleasure in
such as generosity, honesty, or fairness, can both cases when we succeed. Both types of
be contrasted with other types of values, value are also heavily influenced by the spe-
such as a love of money, chocolate cake, or cific culture in which we live; just as local
Mozart. We expect others to have particular customs shape our tastes in music, food, or

59
60 M O R A L I T Y A N D F E E L I N G

beauty, they also shape how we view harm, learning moral norms (such as average group
fairness, and charitable obligations (Hen- behavior or expressions of approval and dis-
rich et al., 2001; Lamba & Mace, 2013). gust) appear to update value representations
Our valuation of morally laden acts, such in the brain via the same processes as non-
as sacrificing one individual to save others, social rewards and punishments. Fourth, we
also appears to be susceptible to many of consider how these values influence moral
the same biases that plague the valuation of judgment, including research that they are
monetary goods during economic decision traded against each other in a way that re-
making (Rai & Holyoak, 2010). And, as sembles economic decision making. In the
it happens, moral values can be traded off final section of the chapter, we highlight
against each other and, with the right rhe- several important questions that should be
torical gloss, even against material interests addressed by future research.
(Tetlock, 2003). Many individuals are also
perfectly willing to bargain sacred values for
monetary gain in practice (especially when Moral Value and Nonmoral Machinery
they think no one is watching), as scandal-
Outcome Value
prone politicians often remind us.
Drawing on evidence from cognitive neu- The subjective values of a wide variety of
roscience, neuroeconomics, and social psy- pleasurable and aversive outcomes appear to
chology, we argue that these similarities are be encoded in a common network of neu-
more than superficial coincidences. Rather, ral structures. The receipt of positive stim-
they reflect a shared cognitive and neural uli, such as food, sex, and money, is most
architecture underlying moral and nonmor- prominently associated with activity in the
al value. This is not to say, of course, that ventral striatum (VS) and the medial orbito-
there is nothing special about moral values. frontal cortex (mOFC; Bartra, McGuire, &
The basic claim is that the motivational, and Kable, 2013; Kable & Glimcher, 2007; Liu,
perhaps affective, aspects of moral value— Hairston, Schrier, & Fan, 2011). Activity
those intrinsic feelings that make you want in the VS has been found to correlate with
to help a charity and feel pleasure when self-reported ratings of pleasure (Salimpoor,
you do or to avoid harming someone and Benovoy, Larcher, Dagher, & Zatorre, 2011;
feel bad when you don’t—are encoded by a Sescousse, Li, & Dreher, 2015), and activity
domain-general system that also represents in both the VS and mOFC during the pas-
and processes a host of nonmoral rewards sive viewing of items predicts subsequent
and punishments. Furthermore, the process choice of those same items (Levy, Lazzaro,
of moral learning, whereby we update the Rutledge, & Glimcher, 2011). Aversive out-
moral value that we assign to particular ac- comes, on the other hand, are more often as-
tions or behaviors, is likely to be supported sociated with activity in the anterior insula
by domain-general learning processes that (AI) and anterior cingulate cortex (ACC). A
have been consistently identified as impor- large meta-analysis of reward-related studies
tant in learning the value of nonmoral goods found that the value of “negative rewards”
and actions. (i.e., punishments) is preferentially encoded
In the first part of this chapter, we look at in the AI and ACC (Bartra et al., 2013), and
four basic lines of research supporting this activation in the AI correlates with the self-
claim. First, we examine evidence that the reported intensity of affective states (Zaki,
subjective value (and disvalue) of morally rel- Davis, & Ochsner, 2012). Both these regions
evant, prosocial (and antisocial) outcomes is are also central components of what has
encoded in the same brain regions as non- been dubbed the “pain matrix,” a network
moral rewards and punishments. We then of regions consistently involved in the sub-
consider how moral action values—such as jective experience of pain (Davis, 2000).
those placed on generosity or nonviolence— Notably, a variety of social concerns
might rely on the same cognitive and neu- (often referred to as “social preferences”;
ral processes that support action valuation Fehr & Fischbacher, 2002) are also encod-
in nonmoral domains. Third, we look at ed in these very same regions (see Ruff &
how social reinforcers that are important to Fehr, 2014, for a review). For instance, the
 Moral Values and Motivations 61

way that we value others’ well-being looks When making unilateral decisions about
very similar to the way we value our own. how to distribute money among themselves
When good things happen to others—espe- and others, participants show increased
cially if we like them, or if they’re similar mOFC activity for equitable distributions
to us—we show increased activity in over- and increased AI activation when making
lapping regions of the VS (Mobbs et al., inequitable distributions (Zaki & Mitchell,
2009). Watching others in pain, on the other 2011). Furthermore, the AI response during
hand, is associated with activity in the AI these trials predicts overall unwillingness
and ACC (Jackson, Brunet, Meltzoff, & to make inequitable decisions. Finally, and
Decety, 2006; Lamm, Nusbaum, Meltzoff, perhaps most pertinent to a discussion on
& Decety, 2007; Singer et al., 2004), and morality, disinterested third parties mak-
the magnitude of AI response predicts the ing decisions about how to distribute money
willingness to reduce an ingroup member’s among other individuals also show insula
pain by enduring pain oneself (Hein, Silani, activity when the proposed distribution is
Preuschoff, Batson, & Singer, 2010). Inter- unfair, and this is related to both its rejec-
estingly, and perhaps troublingly, the deci- tion rate (Civai, Crescentini, Rustichini, &
sion not to help an outgroup member is best Rumiati, 2012; Corradi-Dell’Acqua, Civai,
predicted by VS activity, suggesting that tak- Rumiati, & Fink, 2013) and a willingness
ing pleasure in others’ pain may be an im- to pay money to create equality among the
portant inhibitor of prosocial action. group (Dawes et al., 2012).
The moral value of fairness is associated Researchers have also studied how the
with similar neural signatures. One of the subjective value of mutual cooperation
tools most commonly used to study fair- might be encoded in the brain. The standard
ness preferences in the lab is the Ultimatum method used in this literature is the Prison-
Game. In this game, one player, the Decider, er’s Dilemma game, in which two partners
is endowed with an initial sum of money, are each privately faced with the decision
and she has to decide how much of it to to either “cooperate” or “defect.” Coopera-
share with a second player, the Responder. If tion, which involves giving up a little so that
the Responder doesn’t like the offer, he can your partner gains a lot, is obviously costly
reject it, and neither player gets anything. for the cooperator, but it leads to the great-
Responders who are offered a fair share are est group benefit if both partners do it. On
more likely to accept the offer, feel happi- any given trial, however, an individual can
er about it, and show increased activity in do even better for herself if she defects (i.e.
both mOFC and VS (Tabibnia, Satpute, & contributes nothing) while her partner co-
Lieberman, 2008). Unfair offers lead to in- operates. Out of the four possible combina-
creased AI activation, and the magnitude of tions of cooperation and defection, mutual
this neural response predicts rejection of the cooperation leads to the highest activity in
offer (Sanfey, Rilling, Aronson, Nystrom, & reward-related regions (including the VS and
Cohen, 2003). Of course, a fair offer is bet- mOFC; Rilling et al., 2002). Interestingly,
ter than a low offer for the Responder, so finding out that the other person cooperated
preferences for fairness are necessarily con- when you defected is associated with the
founded with self-interest in the Ultimatum lowest activity in these regions, despite the
Game. fact that it provides the highest monetary
A variety of other tasks provide even payout, underscoring the power of social
stronger evidence for the involvement of consequences to modulate neural represen-
domain-general valuation mechanisms in tations of reward.
the pure fairness motive. Individuals who
passively view a series of variable monetary
Action Value
allocations to themselves and another study
participant show increased reward-related In the previous section, we covered several
activity in mOFC and VS when the two to- instances in which the subjective value of
tals are brought closer together, regardless morally relevant outcomes appears to be
of who is getting the money that turn (Trico- represented in domain-general regions that
mi, Rangel, Camerer, & O’Doherty, 2010). also process nonmoral rewards. Many times
62 M O R A L I T Y A N D F E E L I N G

when we talk about moral values, however, continue to influence behavior even when
we do not simply mean the value that we the associated outcome is no longer valu-
place on states of affairs out in the world, able. For instance, rats who learn to press
such as whether two people have an equal a lever for food will continue to press the
amount of money or whether a friend is ex- lever even after they are full, provided train-
periencing pleasure or pain. Rather, we refer ing has been extensive enough (Dickinson,
to the value (or disvalue) we place on partic- 1985). Though this insensitivity to devalu-
ular actions with social consequences, such ation is typically discussed in the context of
as charitable giving or not harming others. drug addiction and compulsive behaviors
Is there reason to believe that these moral in humans (Gillan et al., 2014; Schwabe,
“action values” might also supported by a Dickinson, & Wolf, 2011), it has also been
more domain-general cognitive and neural demonstrated in healthy adults using a task
architecture? analogous to rat devaluation paradigms
To answer this question, we should first (­Tricomi, Balleine, & O’Doherty, 2009).
clarify what nonmoral action values are and Intriguingly, we also see instances of a
how they might be derived by learning pro- similar phenomenon in the domain of mo-
cesses in a normal environment of rewards rality. Consider the act of charitable giv-
and punishments. An action value is a moti- ing, which has been found to be driven by
vational construct that represents the expect- a mix of two motives (Andreoni, 1990). On
ed future reward conditioned upon choosing the one hand, you may give money because
an action, and it is often based on the re- you value the welfare of the charity, often
ward history of prior choices in relevantly referred to as altruistic giving. On the other
similar circumstances. For instance, if a rat hand, you may give money because you value
receives cheese every time it presses a lever, (or derive utility from) the act of giving itself.
it will come to assign a high action value to This motive has been termed “warm glow”
lever-pressing, and it will be more likely to because of the positive feelings it engenders
press the lever in the future. (The magnitude in the giver. How do we know warm glow
of this value will, of course, depend on just exists? Individuals feel better when they are
how much the rat likes the cheese.) actively giving the money themselves rather
In environments in which action—out- than passively transferring it (Harbaugh,
come contingencies are relatively stable, Mayr, & Burghart, 2007), personal giving
this type of learning is very useful and can is not crowded out by external sources of
lead to benefits in computational efficiency aid (Eckel, Grossman, & Johnston, 2005),
and speed during future decision making. and individuals continue to give even when
By storing values directly on actions, the they know their donation is completely inef-
actor doesn’t need to reference an internal fectual (Crumpler & Grossman, 2008). This
model of the relationships between actions insensitivity to changes in the utility of the
and the particular outcomes they lead to. donation mirrors what we see in devalua-
Instead, it simply performs the action with tion paradigms and hints at the influence of
the highest value. For this reason, learning a positive “action value” attached to chari-
and decision-making programs that rely on table giving.
cached action values are often referred to as Where might this action value come from?
“model free,” whereas those that choose ac- One possibility is that being embedded in a
tions by searching over an internal model of generally cooperative society teaches us that
the world are referred to as “model-based” prosocial, cooperative behavior is actually in
(Dayan & Niv, 2008). There is good evi- our long-term best interest (Peysakhovich &
dence that humans naturally employ both Rand, 2015; Rand et al., 2014). By continu-
of types of decision making (Daw, Gersh- ally having our cooperative acts positively
man, Seymour, Dayan, & Dolan, 2011), and reinforced, we come to place a high value on
they seem to be supported at least in part by prosocial action, just like the cheese-loving
dissociable neural systems (Gläscher, Daw, rat places a high value on lever pressing. In
Dayan, & O’Doherty, 2010). a study testing this idea, participants who
One interesting feature of action values is were first assigned to a cooperative envi-
that, under the right circumstances, they can ronment in which it paid to be nice were
 Moral Values and Motivations 63

subsequently more likely to donate money tached to antisocial actions are represented
to an anonymous individual (with no pos- in many of the same reward-related brain re-
sibility of reciprocation) than participants gions that we have previously discussed. The
who were first assigned to a more competi- warm glow associated with the prosocial act
tive environment in which few people coop- of giving to a charity, for instance, appears
erated (Peysakhovich & Rand, 2015). This to be localized to the VS (Harbaugh et al.,
suggests that the high value these coopera- 2007). Studies on violent behaviors are a bit
tive individuals learned to place on prosocial more difficult to interpret, in part because
action in the first phase “spilled over” into they have not isolated the violent act from its
the second phase, even though there was no harmful outcomes. Nevertheless, one study
longer any rational self-benefit. found that the aversiveness of imagined
We also find evidence of the same disso- harmful actions, such as forcibly removing
ciation between action and outcome values organs from a young child, was encoded in
in cases of aversion to antisocial action. (mid-)insula and the ACC, and functional
Cushman, Gray, Gaffey, and Mendes (2012) connectivity analyses suggest that the in-
brought participants into the lab and asked formation in the ACC was passed to the
them to perform several pseudo-violent ac- mOFC during moral judgment (Hutcherson,
tions, such as slamming the head of a lifelike Montaser-Kouhsari, Woodward, & Ran-
baby doll against a table or hitting a realistic- gel, 2015). In another study, the aversive-
looking artificial leg with a hammer. Despite ness of up-close-and-personal harmful ac-
knowledge that these actions could cause tions tracked activity in the amygdala, and
no harm, participants showed significant this appraisal was integrated into an overall
signs of physiological aversion (measured moral value representation in the mOFC
by peripheral vasoconstriction) when simply (Shenhav & Greene, 2014). The amygdala
thinking about performing these actions. is important in learning to avoid negative
Furthermore, these physiological changes outcomes (Delgado, Jou, LeDoux, & Phelps,
were greater than in either a control group 2009) and could here represent the learned
that performed metabolically matched ac- association between violent actions and the
tions or a witness group that watched some- harm that they typically cause (Blair, 2007).
one else perform the same actions. People Future studies will be necessary to obtain a
also report that they would feel uncomfort- more fine-grained picture of how action and
able performing pseudo-violent actions in outcome values are independently represent-
more natural contexts, such as stabbing a fel- ed in these regions.
low actor in the neck with a retractable stage
knife as part of a play (Miller, Hannikainen,
Feedback and Learning
& Cushman, 2014). These data suggest that
the motoric properties of canonically violent So far, we have discussed the various cogni-
actions (such as hitting, stabbing, and shoot- tive and neural substrates of moral value, but
ing), which usually cause substantial harm, we have not said much about the reinforcers
can acquire a negative value that is sufficient that create or modify these values. Given the
to trigger an aversive response even after the consistency of moral norms within cultures
harmful outcome has been removed. and variability of moral norms between cul-
Although multiple theoretical accounts tures (Henrich et al., 2001; Lamba & Mace,
have emerged in recent years detailing how 2013), one of the primary ways to learn the
model-free learning algorithms might shape specific values of your culture is via social
both prosocial (Gsiarz & Crockett, 2015) feedback. This is likely to come in one of
and antisocial (Crockett, 2013; Cushman, two forms: prescriptive (involving direct sig-
2013) behavior and moral judgment, few, if nals of approval and disapproval) or descrip-
any, studies have attempted to directly com- tive (involving information about others’
pare the neural circuits involved in the mod- behavior). If moral values are encoded in do-
el-free learning of both moral and nonmoral main-general regions, we might expect the
action values. Several studies do, however, feedback that comes from these two sources
suggest that the positive values attached to to operate over the same domain-general cir-
prosocial actions and the negative values at- cuitry as nonmoral feedback.
64 M O R A L I T Y A N D F E E L I N G

Consistent with this hypothesis, the sight an aversion to harm influence your judg-
of faces signaling disapproval elicits activ- ment that it is morally prohibited?
ity in the ACC (Burklund, Eisenberger, & To address this question, Shenhav and
Lieberman, 2007), and this same region,
­ Greene (2010) asked participants to judge
along with the AI, is activated in individuals the moral acceptability of killing one indi-
who are subject to social exclusion (Eisen- vidual in order to save others, varying both
berger, Lieberman, & Williams, 2003). Fa- the number of people saved and the prob-
cial expressions of disgust (another potential ability that they would die if nothing was
form of disapproval) also appear to amplify done. Not only was the expected value of
error processing in the ACC (Boksem, Ruys, action (number saved × probability) encoded
& Aarts, 2011). Indicators of social approv- in the VS, but sensitivities to this value in
al, on the other hand, are associated with the brain showed up as sensitivities in moral
increased activity in more reward-related re- judgment. In other words, the more this
gions, including the VS and mOFC (Jones et reward-related region tracked the value of
al., 2011). lives saved when reading scenarios, the more
Descriptive norms also have a powerful ef- the participant incorporated the value into
fect on behavior—thanks to the human de- his or her ratings of acceptability, suggesting
sire to conform—and this influence can be that reward was indeed modulating percep-
seen playing out in the same brain regions. tions of wrongness. There is also evidence
When one finds out his or her behavior or for action values (as opposed to outcome
preferences match the group norm, it elicits values) influencing moral judgment. In a
activity in the VS; when they deviate from previously mentioned study, Cushman and
the norm, it leads to increased activity in colleagues (2012) found that performing
the AI and ACC (Wu, Luo, & Feng, 2016). pseudo-violent (harmless) actions generated
Furthermore, the magnitude of response in signs of aversive arousal. The magnitude of
these latter regions predicts the likelihood this physiological aversion also predicted
that the individual will change his or her be- how wrong participants thought it would be
haviors or preferences to match those of the to kill one individual to save many others.
group (e.g., Klucharev, Hytönen, Rijpkema, Similarly, how uncomfortable you think it
Smidts, & Fernández, 2009; Zaki, Schirm- would make you to perform pseudo-­violent
er, & Mitchell, 2011). Interestingly, this actions predicts your condemnation of
change in preference is often accompanied harmful actions, even when controlling for
by a commensurate change in reward-relat- such things as empathy and emotional reac-
ed striatal activity, suggesting conformity tivity (Miller et al., 2014).
involves an updating of intrinsic preferences, Two recent neuroimaging studies have
rather than a superficial acquiescence to so- provided a window into how exactly these
cial pressures (Wu et al., 2016). action and outcome values might be influ-
encing moral judgment. In economic de-
cision making, the values of two or more
From Value to Judgment
goods have to be compared with each other
We have discussed several ways in which the in order to make a choice, but often their
hedonic and motivational properties of mor- values are not on the same scale (e.g., choos-
ally relevant outcomes and actions mirror ing a cake now or your health in 20 years).
those of their nonmoral cousins, both cog- To perform this feat, the brain transforms
nitively and neurally. And it is easy to see these values into a “common currency” that
how these properties might promote moral appears to be encoded in mOFC (Chib, Ran-
behavior. Just as we are more likely to order gel, Shimojo, & O’Doherty, 2009; Kable
an entrée that our brain finds pleasing, we & Glimcher, 2007; Plassmann, O’Doherty,
are more likely to donate money to a char- & Rangel, 2007). Interestingly, this same
ity if we find it intrinsically rewarding. But process seems to be occurring during moral
what about the relation of these prosocial judgment. Using tasks that pit an aversive
values to moral judgment? Does a desire to action (such as killing) against a utilitarian
act charitably toward others influence your justification (such as saving lives), Shenhav
judgment that it is morally required? Does and Greene (2014) and Hutcherson and col-
 Moral Values and Motivations 65

leagues (2015) have found evidence that the placing intrinsic value on prosocial actions
appraisal values of each individual option, may facilitate their success. Indeed, humans
as well as the integrative moral judgment, are extremely sensitive to whether their part-
are represented in mOFC in the moments ners want to cooperate for its own sake or
before a judgment is made. whether they only do so after calculating the
A common thread running through these costs (Hoffman, Yoeli, & Nowak, 2015).
studies is that they involve conflict, or com- Several important questions remain, how-
peting moral concerns. We believe that this ever, concerning the nature of these value
may tell us something about the circum- representations. First, it is currently unclear
stances in which value (as a potentially af- to what extent we can truly interpret ac-
fect-laden, motivational construct) is most tivity in reward-related regions such as the
likely to influence judgment. Many moral VS as “intrinsic” valuation (or “private ac-
propositions, such as “Murder is wrong,” ceptance”), divorced from social expecta-
are likely to be stored in semantic memory tions and pressures. Some studies looking
and easily referenced. This is presumably the at conformity-induced changes in these re-
reason that psychopaths are able to recog- gions have favored this view (Berns, Capra,
nize simple moral violations, despite having Moore, & Noussair, 2010; Klucharev et al.,
reduced motivation to comply with them 2009; Zaki et al., 2011), but the evidence
(Aharoni, Sinnott-Armstrong, & Kiehl, is mixed. Brain regions involved in theory
2012; Blair, 1995). However, we may lack of mind, for instance, can modulate value
clear propositional knowledge concerning representations in the mOFC (Hare, Cam-
which moral rules are more important than erer, Knoepfle, O’Doherty, & Rangel, 2010;
others. In a situation in which two moral Strombach et al., 2015), and knowledge of
norms—for example, do not kill versus others’ presence can amplify activity in the
save the most lives—are in competition, it VS during charitable donations (Izuma,
might be necessary to reference the affective Saito, & Sadato, 2008). These studies high-
or motivational associations you have with light the context-dependent nature of value
each norm in order to render a judgment. It construction and demonstrate that anticipat-
is precisely these circumstances in which the ed social rewards (such as reputation) might
judgments of psychopaths appear to diverge simultaneously contribute to reward-related
most from those of healthy adults (Koenigs, activity in these regions. Future neuroimag-
Kruepke, Zeier, & Newman, 2012). ing studies might consider using alternative
techniques such as multivoxel pattern analy-
sis (MVPA) to dissociate multiple sources of
Conclusion and Future Directions reward.
We also lack clear evidence on the degree
The fingerprint of domain-general reward of specialization for moral stimuli within
and valuation processes can be seen in sever- the reward system. Though the bulk of re-
al key components of moral cognition. The search comparing social and nonsocial re-
hedonic and motivational value attached to wards have found extensive overlap, a grow-
prosocial and antisocial outcomes, the ac- ing number of studies hint at some degree
tions that lead to them, and the social feed- of regional specificity (Ruff & Fehr, 2014).
back that shapes them all seem to be reflect- For instance, the values of money (nonso-
ed in regions that have been implicated in cial) and erotic (social) stimuli are encoded
generic reward-learning tasks. Furthermore, in distinct regions of the mOFC (Sescousse,
the values of competing moral concerns ap- Redouté, & Dreher, 2010), and learning
pear to be translated into a “common cur- about the reliability of nonsocial cues versus
rency” in the mOFC during moral judgment, human advisors in predicting reward seems
just as we see in economic decision making. to rely on computationally similar yet neu-
This shared neural architecture may reflect rally adjacent processing streams (Behrens,
the outsized role social cooperation plays Hunt, Woolrich, & Rushworth, 2008). Few,
in human fitness and survival. Cooperative if any, studies, however, have directly com-
ventures can lead to great personal benefits pared moral learning with nonsocial reward
in both the short term and long term, and learning, and even fewer have compared
66 M O R A L I T Y A N D F E E L I N G

moral learning with nonmoral social learn- ventional distinction. Journal of Abnormal
ing. These are two areas that are ripe for in- Psychology, 121, 484–497.
vestigation. Andreoni, J. (1990). Impure altruism and dona-
Finally, further research is needed to un- tions to public goods: A theory of warm-glow
giving. Economic Journal, 100, 464–477.
derstand how exactly moral action values Ayars, A. (2016). Can model-free reinforcement
are learned. Some scholars have rightly learning explain deontological moral judg-
questioned whether we have the requisite ments? Cognition, 150, 232–242.
reinforcement history to form robust action Bartra, O., McGuire, J. T., & Kable, J. W. (2013).
values by personal experiential learning, The valuation system: A coordinate-based
particularly when it comes to relatively rare meta-analysis of BOLD fMRI experiments ex-
antisocial actions such as hitting, stabbing, amining neural correlates of subjective value.
or shooting (Ayars, 2016; also similar to NeuroImage, 76, 412–427.
the “poverty of the stimulus” argument, see Behrens, T. E. J., Hunt, L. T., Woolrich, M. W.,
& Rushworth, M. F. S. (2008). Associative
Mikhail, 2007).
learning of social value. Nature, 456, 245–
There are several potential solutions to 249.
this problem. First, we can dynamically ad- Behrens, T. E. J., Woolrich, M. W., Walton, M.
just learning rates, or how fast action val- E., & Rushworth, M. F. S. (2007). Learn-
ues are updated, depending on perceived ing the value of information in an uncertain
certainty of the outcome (Behrens, Wool- world. Nature Neuroscience, 10, 1214–1221.
rich, Walton, & Rushworth, 2007). In other Berns, G. S., Capra, C. M., Moore, S., & Nous-
words, actions that are known to reliably sair, C. (2010). Neural mechanisms of the in-
cause harm may acquire strong negative fluence of popularity on adolescent ratings of
values after very little experience. Second, music. NeuroImage, 49, 2687–2696.
Blair, R. J. R. (1995). A cognitive developmental
watching others, also known as observa-
approach to morality: Investigating the psy-
tional or vicarious learning, activates the chopath. Cognition, 57, 1–29.
same neural pathways as firsthand experi- Blair, R. J. R. (2007). The amygdala and ventro-
ence and can be an efficient way of learn- medial prefrontal cortex in morality and psy-
ing actions that one is unlikely to perform chopathy. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 11,
oneself (Burke, Tobler, Baddeley, & Schultz, 387–392.
2010; Olsson, Nearing, & Phelps, 2007). Boksem, M. A. S., Ruys, K. I., & Aarts, H.
Third, instructional learning can lead to top- (2011). Facing disapproval: Performance mon-
down modulation of reinforcement learning itoring in a social context. Social Neurosci-
pathways (Doll, Jacobs, Sanfey, & Frank, ence, 6, 360–368.
Burke, C. J., Tobler, P. N., Baddeley, M., &
2009; Li, Delgado, & Phelps, 2011), result- Schultz, W. (2010). Neural mechanisms of ob-
ing in neural responses that mirror firsthand servational learning. Proceedings of the Na-
learning. Lastly, mental simulation can play tional Academy of Sciences of the USA, 107,
an important role in shaping action values 14431–14436.
(Gershman, Markman, & Ross, 2014); by Burklund, L. J., Eisenberger, N. I., & Lieberman,
using our model-based system to simulate M. D. (2007). The face of rejection: Rejection
various actions and their likely rewards and sensitivity moderates dorsal anterior cingulate
punishments, we can “train up” the cached activity to disapproving facial expressions. So-
action values in our model-free system so cial Neuroscience, 2, 238–253.
Chib, V. S., Rangel, A., Shimojo, S., & O’Doherty,
that learning occurs much more quickly and
J. P. (2009). Evidence for a common represen-
efficiently. Which of these explanations best tation of decision values for dissimilar goods
describes how moral action values form is in human ventromedial prefrontal cortex.
an open question, but we hope this chapter Journal of Neuroscience, 29, 12315–12320.
provides several fruitful avenues for future Civai, C., Crescentini, C., Rustichini, A., & Ru-
research. miati, R. I. (2012). Equality versus self-interest
in the brain: Differential roles of anterior in-
sula and medial prefrontal cortex. NeuroIm-
REFERENCES age, 62, 102–112.
Corradi-Dell’Acqua, C., Civai, C., Rumiati, R. I.,
Aharoni, E., Sinnott-Armstrong, W., & Kiehl, K. & Fink, G. R. (2013). Disentangling self- and
A. (2012). Can psychopathic offenders discern fairness-related neural mechanisms involved
moral wrongs?: A new look at the moral/con- in the ultimatum game: An fMRI study. So-
 Moral Values and Motivations 67

cial Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience, 8, decision making: A tale of two systems. Jour-
424–431. nal of Experimental Psychology: General,
Crockett, M. J. (2013). Models of morality. 143, 182–194.
Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 17, 363–366. Gsiarz, F., & Crockett, M. J. (2015). Goal-di-
Crumpler, H., & Grossman, P. J. (2008). An ex- rected, habitual and Pavlovian prosocial be-
perimental test of warm glow giving. Journal havior. Frontiers in Behavioral Neuroscience,
of Public Economics, 92, 1011–1021. 9, 1–18.
Cushman, F. (2013). Action, outcome, and value: Gillan, C. M., Morein-Zamir, S., Urcelay, G.
A dual-system framework for morality. Per- P., Sule, A., Voon, V., Apergis-Schoute, A.
sonality and Social Psychology Review, 17, M., . . . Robbins, T. W. (2014). Enhanced
273–292. avoidance habits in obsessive–compulsive dis-
Cushman, F., Gray, K., Gaffey, A., & Mendes, order. Biological Psychiatry, 75, 631–638.
W. B. (2012). Simulating murder: The aversion Gläscher, J., Daw, N., Dayan, P., & O’Doherty,
to harmful action. Emotion, 12, 2–7. J. P. (2010). States versus rewards: Dissocia-
Darwin, C. (1872). The descent of man, and se- ble neural prediction error signals underlying
lection in relation to sex. London: Murray. model-based and model-free reinforcement
Davis, K. D. (2000). The neural circuitry of pain learning. Neuron, 66, 585–595.
as explored with functional MRI. Neurologi- Harbaugh, W. T., Mayr, U., & Burghart, D. R.
cal Research, 22, 313–317. (2007). Neural responses to taxation and vol-
Daw, N. D., Gershman, S. J., Seymour, B., untary giving reveal motives for charitable do-
Dayan, P., & Dolan, R. J. (2011). Model-based nations. Science, 316, 1622–1625.
influences on humans’ choices and striatal Hare, T. A., Camerer, C. F., Knoepfle, D. T.,
prediction errors. Neuron, 69, 1204–1215. O’Doherty, J. P., & Rangel, A. (2010). Value
Dawes, C. T., Loewen, P. J., Schreiber, D., Sim- computations in ventral medial prefrontal
mons, A. N., Flagan, T., McElreath, R., . . . cortex during charitable decision making in-
Paulus, M. P. (2012). Neural basis of egali- corporate input from regions involved in so-
tarian behavior. Proceedings of the National cial cognition. Journal of Neuroscience, 30,
Academy of Sciences of the USA, 109, 6479– 583–590.
6483. Hein, G., Silani, G., Preuschoff, K., Batson, C.
Dayan, P., & Niv, Y. (2008). Reinforcement D., & Singer, T. (2010). Neural responses to
learning: The good, the bad and the ugly. Cur- ingroup and outgroup members’ suffering pre-
rent Opinion in Neurobiology, 18, 185–196. dict individual differences in costly helping.
Delgado, M. R., Jou, R. L., LeDoux, J., & Phelps, Neuron, 68, 149–160.
L. (2009). Avoiding negative outcomes: Track- Henrich, J., Boyd, R., Bowles, S., Camerer, C.,
ing the mechanisms of avoidance learning in Fehr, E., Gintis, H., & McElreath, R. (2001).
humans during fear conditioning. Frontiers in In search of Homo economicus: Behavioral
Behavioral Neuroscience, 3, 1–9. experiments in 15 small-scale societies. Amer-
Dickinson, A. (1985). Actions and habits: The ican Economic Review, 91, 73–78.
development of behavioural autonomy. Philo- Hoffman, M., Yoeli, E., & Nowak, M. A.
sophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: (2015). Cooperate without looking: Why we
Biological Sciences, 308, 67–78. care what people think and not just what they
Doll, B. B., Jacobs, W. J., Sanfey, A. G., & Frank, do. Proceedings of the National Academy of
M. J. (2009). Instructional control of rein- Sciences of the USA, 112, 1727–1732.
forcement learning: A behavioral and neuro- Hutcherson, C. A., Montaser-Kouhsari, L.,
computational investigation. Brain Research, Woodward, J., & Rangel, A. (2015). Emo-
1299, 74–94. tional and utilitarian appraisals of moral
Eckel, C. C., Grossman, P. J., & Johnston, R. M. dilemmas are encoded in separate areas and
(2005). An experimental test of the crowding integrated in ventromedial prefrontal cortex.
out hypothesis. Journal of Public Economics, Journal of Neuroscience, 35, 12593–12605.
89, 1543–1560. Izuma, K., Saito, D. N., & Sadato, N. (2008).
Eisenberger, N. I., Lieberman, M. D., & Wil- Processing of social and monetary rewards in
liams, K. D. (2003). Does rejection hurt?: An the human striatum. Neuron, 58, 284–294.
fMRI study of social exclusion. Science, 302, Jackson, P. L., Brunet, E., Meltzoff, A. N., &
290–292. Decety, J. (2006). Empathy examined through
Fehr, E., & Fischbacher, U. (2002). Why social the neural mechanisms involved in imagining
preferences matter: The impact of non-selfish how I feel versus how you feel pain. Neuropsy-
motives on competition, cooperation and in- chologia, 44, 752–761.
centives. Economic Journal, 112, C1–C33. Jones, R. M., Somerville, L. H., Li, J., Ruberry,
Gershman, S. J., Markman, A. B., & Ross, A. E. J., Libby, V., Glover, G., . . . Casey, B. J.
(2014). Retrospective revaluation in sequential (2011). Behavioral and neural properties of so-
68 M O R A L I T Y A N D F E E L I N G

cial reinforcement learning. Journal of Neuro- of virtue: Creating norms of cooperation and
science, 31, 13039–13045. defection in the laboratory. Management Sci-
Kable, J. W., & Glimcher, P. W. (2007). The ence, 62, 631–647.
neural correlates of subjective value during in- Plassmann, H., O’Doherty, J., & Rangel, A.
tertemporal choice. Nature Neuroscience, 10, (2007). Orbitofrontal cortex encodes willing-
1625–1633. ness to pay in everyday economic transactions.
Klucharev, V., Hytönen, K., Rijpkema, M., Journal of Neuroscience, 27, 9984–9988.
Smidts, A., & Fernández, G. (2009). Rein- Rai, T. S., & Holyoak, K. J. (2010). Moral prin-
forcement learning signal predicts social con- ciples or consumer preferences?: Alternative
formity. Neuron, 61, 140–151. framings of the trolley problem. Cognitive Sci-
Koenigs, M., Kruepke, M., Zeier, J., & New- ence, 34, 311–321.
man, J. P. (2012). Utilitarian moral judgment Rand, D. G., Peysakhovich, A., Kraft-Todd, G.
in psychopathy. Social Cognitive and Affective T., Newman, G. E., Wurzbacher, O., Nowak,
Neuroscience, 7, 708–714. M. A., & Greene, J. D. (2014). Social heuris-
Lamba, S., & Mace, R. (2013). The evolution tics shape intuitive cooperation. Nature Com-
of fairness: Explaining variation in bargain- munications, 5, 3677.
ing behaviour. Proceedings of the Royal So- Rilling, J. K., Gutman, D. A., Zeh, T. R., Pa-
ciety of London B: Biological Sciences, 280, gnoni, G., Berns, G. S., & Kilts, C. D. (2002).
2012–2028. A neural basis for social cooperation. Neuron,
Lamm, C., Nusbaum, H. C., Meltzoff, A. N., 35, 395–405.
& Decety, J. (2007). What are you feeling?: Ruff, C. C., & Fehr, E. (2014). The neurobiol-
Using functional magnetic resonance imaging ogy of rewards and values in social decision
to assess the modulation of sensory and affec- making. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 15,
tive responses during empathy for pain. PLOS 549–562.
ONE, 2, e1292. Salimpoor, V. N., Benovoy, M., Larcher, K., Da-
Levy, I., Lazzaro, S. C., Rutledge, R. B., & Glim- gher, A., & Zatorre, R. J. (2011). Anatomical-
cher, P. W. (2011). Choice from non-choice: ly distinct dopamine release during anticipa-
Predicting consumer preferences from blood tion and experience of peak emotion to music.
oxygenation level-dependent signals obtained Nature Neuroscience, 14, 257–262.
during passive viewing. Journal of Neurosci- Sanfey, A. G., Rilling, J. K., Aronson, J. A., Nys-
ence, 31, 118–125. trom, L. E., & Cohen, J. D. (2003). The neural
Li, J., Delgado, M. R., & Phelps, E. A. (2011). basis of economic decision-making in the ulti-
How instructed knowledge modulates the matum game. Science, 300, 1755–1758.
neural systems of reward learning. Proceed- Schwabe, L., Dickinson, A., & Wolf, O. T.
ings of the National Academy of Sciences of (2011). Stress, habits, and drug addiction: A
the USA, 108, 55–60. psychoneuroendocrinological perspective.
Liu, X., Hairston, J., Schrier, M., & Fan, J. Experimental and Clinical Psychopharmacol-
(2011). Common and distinct networks un- ogy, 19, 53–63.
derlying reward valence and processing stages: Sescousse, G., Li, Y., & Dreher, J.-C. (2015).
A meta-analysis of functional neuroimaging A common currency for the computation of
studies. Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Re- motivational values in the human striatum.
views, 35, 1219–1236. Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience,
Mikhail, J. (2007). Universal moral grammar: 10, 467–473.
Theory, evidence and the future. Trends in Sescousse, G., Redouté, J., & Dreher, J.-C.
Cognitive Sciences, 11, 143–152. (2010). The architecture of reward value cod-
Miller, R., Hannikainen, I., & Cushman, F. ing in the human orbitofrontal cortex. Journal
(2014). Bad actions or bad outcomes?: Differ- of Neuroscience, 30, 13095–13104.
entiating affective contributions to the moral Shenhav, A., & Greene, J. D. (2010). Moral judg-
condemnation of harm. Emotion, 14(3), 573– ments recruit domain-general valuation mech-
587. anisms to integrate representations of prob-
Mobbs, D., Yu, R., Meyer, M., Passamonti, L., ability and magnitude. Neuron, 67, 667–677.
Seymour, B., Calder, A. J., . . . Dalgleish, T. Shenhav, A., & Greene, J. D. (2014). Integrative
(2009). A key role for similarity in vicarious moral judgment: Dissociating the roles of the
reward. Science, 324, 900. amygdala and ventromedial prefrontal cortex.
Olsson, A., Nearing, K. I., & Phelps, E. A. Journal of Neuroscience, 34, 4741–4749.
(2007). Learning fears by observing others: Singer, T., Seymour, B., O’Doherty, J., Kaube,
The neural systems of social fear transmission. H., Dolan, R. J., & Frith, C. D. (2004). Em-
Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience, pathy for pain involves the affective but not
2, 3–11. sensory components of pain. Science, 303,
Peysakhovich, A., & Rand, D. G. (2015). Habits 1157–1162.
 Moral Values and Motivations 69

Strohminger, N., & Nichols, S. (2014). The es- al striatum in human habit learning. Europe-
sential moral self. Cognition, 131, 159–171. an Journal of Neuroscience, 29, 2225–2232.
Strombach, T., Weber, B., Hangebrauk, Z., Tricomi, E., Rangel, A., Camerer, C. F., &
Kenning, P., Karipidis, I. I., Tobler, P. N., & O’Doherty, J. P. (2010). Neural evidence for
Kalenscher, T. (2015). Social discounting in- inequality-averse social preferences. Nature,
volves modulation of neural value signals by 463, 1089–1091.
temporoparietal junction. Proceedings of the Wu, H., Luo, Y., & Feng, C. (2016). Neural sig-
National Academy of Sciences of the USA, natures of social conformity: A coordinate-
112, 1619–1624. based activation likelihood estimation meta-
Tabibnia, G., Satpute, A. B., & Lieberman, M. D. analysis of functional brain imaging studies.
(2008). The sunny side of fairness: Preference Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews, 71,
for fairness activates reward circuitry (and 101–111.
disregarding unfairness activates self-control Zaki, J., Davis, J. I., & Ochsner, K. N. (2012).
circuitry). Psychological Science, 19, 339–347. Overlapping activity in anterior insula during
Tetlock, P. E. (2003). Thinking the unthinkable: interoception and emotional experience. Neu-
Sacred values and taboo cognitions. Trends in roImage, 62, 493–499.
Cognitive Sciences, 7, 320–324. Zaki, J., & Mitchell, J. P. (2011). Equitable deci-
Tetlock, P. E., Kristel, O. V., Beth, S., Green, M. sion making is associated with neural markers
C., & Lerner, J. S. (2000). The psychology of of intrinsic value. Proceedings of the National
the unthinkable: Taboo trade-offs, forbidden Academy of Sciences of the USA, 108, 19761–
base rates, and heretical counterfactuals. Jour- 19766.
nal of Personality and Social Psychology, 78, Zaki, J., Schirmer, J., & Mitchell, J. P. (2011).
853–870. Social influence modulates the neural com-
Tricomi, E., Balleine, B. W., & O’Doherty, J. P. putation of value. Psychological Science, 22,
(2009). A specific role for posterior dorsolater- 894–900.
CHAPTER 8

A Component Process Model


of Disgust, Anger, and Moral Judgment

Hanah A. Chapman

What is the role of disgust in morality?

The component process model of morality proposed in this chapter


suggests that moral disgust is driven primarily by negative character
evaluations, explaining why both purity and nonpurity transgres‑
sions trigger disgust and why purity transgressions are morally
condemned.

The emotion of disgust has played an out- “purity” or “divinity” transgressions, mean-
sized role in moral psychology over the past ing acts that violate sexual or bodily norms
15 years. As described below, research on (Graham, Haidt, & Nosek, 2009; Rozin et
moral disgust has informed such key debates al., 1999). Purity transgressions raise a num-
as whether moral judgment is rational or ber of important questions, which I return
intuitive; whether morality consists of one to shortly. However, for the current ques-
process or many; and whether morality is tion—what kinds of immoral things are dis-
culturally uniform or variable. What, then, gusting—they are not very interesting: It is
is the role of disgust in morality? As noted hardly surprising that purity transgressions
by Tybur and colleagues (Tybur, Lieberman, evoke disgust, given that they involve proto-
Kurzban, & DeScioli, 2012), it is critical to typical disgust elicitors such as body prod-
break this question into smaller pieces to ucts and biologically disadvantageous sex.
avoid confusion. More interesting, and more controversial,
is the question of whether immoral things
1.  What kinds of immoral things are dis- that are not intrinsically disgusting, such
gusting? One perspective is that only dis- as harm, unfairness, and disloyalty, can
gusting immoral things can evoke disgust evoke disgust. People certainly report dis-
(Horberg, Oveis, Keltner, & Cohen, 2009; gust toward nonpurity transgressions, but
Rozin, Lowery, Imada, & Haidt, 1999; there has been debate about whether this
Russell & Giner-Sorolla, 2013). “Disgust- disgust is synonymous with anger (Cam-
ing immoral things” are often referred to as eron, Lindquist, & Gray, 2015; Chapman

70
 Disgust, Anger, and Moral Judgment 71

& Anderson, 2013; Royzman, Atanasov, suggests that incidental disgust has at best
Landy, Parks, & Gepty, 2014; Rozin, Haidt, a weak effect on moral judgments (Landy &
& Fincher, 2009; Russell & Giner-Sorolla, Goodwin, 2015). Thus it is unlikely that the
2013). This issue is fraught with method- disgust associated with purity transgressions
ological pitfalls, and the evidence is evolving is sufficient to cause moral condemnation.
very rapidly, but at present there is reason Another explanation is that purity con-
to think that nonpurity transgressions can cerns may constitute a distinct moral mod-
indeed evoke disgust that is meaningfully ule: that is, for some people, it may be intrin-
distinct from anger (see the discussion of ev- sically wrong to do something disgusting,
idence later in the chapter). Thus, to answer perhaps because doing so contaminates the
the first question, both purity and nonpu- purity or sanctity of the soul (Graham et al.,
rity transgressions can be disgusting. 2009; Rozin, Lowery, et al., 1999). This may
explain wrongness judgments for some pu-
2.  Why are nonpurity transgressions dis- rity transgressions. However, the vignettes
gusting? Contemporary theories of disgust used as stimuli in moral judgment studies
propose that disgust’s original function was are heterogeneous and psychologically com-
to facilitate disease avoidance (Oaten, Ste- plex, which admits the possibility of alterna-
venson, & Case, 2009; Tybur et al., 2012). tive explanations. For example, people may
It is therefore not clear why nonpurity trans- perceive that some purity transgressions
gressions, which do not involve disease vec- have harmful consequences even when the
tors, can evoke disgust. The explanation may scenarios are constructed so as to be free
lie in the opposing behavioral tendencies from explicit harm (Gray, Schein, & Ward,
associated with disgust and anger. In par- 2014; Royzman, Leeman, & Baron, 2009).
ticular, whereas anger is linked to approach Perhaps more importantly, doing something
motivation and may be aimed at chang- disgusting (i.e. committing a purity trans-
ing the target’s future behavior (Carver & gression) may be an especially strong sig-
Harmon-Jones, 2009; Fischer & Roseman, nal that the transgressor has bad character
2007), disgust is associated with withdrawal (Uhlmann & Zhu, 2013; Uhlmann, Pizarro,
and avoidance (Rozin, Haidt, & McCau- & Diermeier, 2015). Here, moral judgments
ley, 1999). Therefore, disgust in response may reflect condemnation of the transgres-
to nonpurity transgressions may subserve sor as a person as much as condemnation of
withdrawal motivation in the moral domain the person’s acts.
(Chapman & Anderson, 2013; Hutcherson
& Gross, 2011). Withdrawal/avoidance 4.  Are there other differences between
might be useful under a number of differ- purity and nonpurity transgressions? Re-
ent circumstances. Most prominently, it may searchers have suggested that moral judg-
be futile to try to influence a transgressor’s ments about purity and nonpurity trans-
future behavior when his or her actions gressions may rely on different cognitive
stem from bad character (Fischer & Rose- processes. For example, two studies have
man, 2007). Thus nonpurity transgressions found that the transgressor’s malignant ver-
that stem from or signal bad character may sus innocent intent matters less for condem-
be especially likely to elicit disgust (Giner- nation of purity transgressions compared
Sorolla & Chapman, 2017; Hutcherson & with nonpurity transgressions (Chakroff,
Gross, 2011). Dungan, & Young, 2013; Young & Saxe,
2011). Such findings have been taken as evi-
3.  Why are purity transgressions im- dence for distinct moral modules for purity
moral? In other words, why is it wrong to and nonpurity transgressions (Chakroff &
do something disgusting, if doing so does Young, 2015). However, close examination
not violate any other moral rules? One ex- of the data reveals that evidence is actually
planation, derived from the social intuition- mixed (see the later section on evidence).
ist model (Haidt, 2001), is that the strong Moreover, the complexity and heteroge-
feelings of disgust evoked by purity trans- neity of moral transgression stimuli once
gression directly cause negative moral judg- again opens up the possibility of alternative
ments. However, a recent meta-analysis explanations. Many differences could arise
72 M O R A L I T Y A N D F E E L I N G

because purity transgressions may primar- explains why harmless purity transgressions
ily activate—and could even derive their are condemned. For nonpurity transgres-
wrongness from—character judgments sions, perception of negative consequences
rather than consequence judgments (Uhl- triggers moral condemnation and anger in
mann et al., 2015; Uhlmann & Zhu, 2013). parallel; anger then motivates approach-­
That said, this idea cannot account for all related responses. Not shown in Figure 8.1
of the reported differences between purity is the idea that purity transgressions that are
and nonpurity transgressions, suggesting perceived to have negative consequences will
that purity-related moral cognition may be also trigger anger and approach-related be-
at least partially distinct from non-purity- haviors. Many cognitive differences between
related moral cognition. purity and nonpurity transgressions could
Figure 8.1 summarizes this perspective on arise because harmless purity transgressions
moral judgment and emotion, which I call activate character judgments to a greater ex-
the component process model (CPM).1 Ac- tent than consequence judgments, whereas
cording to the CPM, a number of component harmful nonpurity transgressions typically
cognitive processes contribute to disgust, activate both consequence judgments and
anger, and moral judgments. For harmless character judgments. Some differences can-
purity transgressions (e.g. consensual incest), not be easily accounted for in this way, how-
disgust can stem from core disgust evalua- ever; thus the CPM allows for purity-specific
tions triggered by stimuli such as biologi- and non-purity-specific moral evaluations to
cally disadvantageous sex or contact with influence judgments.
contaminants. Purity transgressions also
trigger disgust by activating negative char-
acter evaluations (“only a messed-up person Historical Context
would do something like that”). Nonpurity
transgressions (e.g., unprovoked violence) Research on disgust has informed a number
can trigger negative character judgments of the broader debates in moral psychology.
as well, which similarly lead to disgust. In These include whether there are one or two
turn, disgust motivates avoidance-related re- or many moral processes; whether morality
sponses. Negative character judgments also is primarily intuitive or rational; and wheth-
contribute to moral condemnation, which er morality is culturally uniform or varied.

Harmless purity transgression Nonpurity transgression


(e.g., consensual incest) (e.g., unprovoked violence)

Character Character Consequence


evaluation evaluation evaluation
Purity-specific Nonpurity-
Core disgust
moral evaluations specific moral
evaluation
evaluations

Negative consequence
Negative character judgment
judgment

Moral judgment
Disgust Anger
(condemnation)

Avoidance-related, low-risk Approach-related, high-risk


responses responses
(e.g., shunning, gossip) (e.g., punishment)

FIGURE 8.1.  The component process model (CPM) of moral judgment and emotion.
 Disgust, Anger, and Moral Judgment 73

•• “One or two or many processes?,” in- types of transgressions. Thus the CPM is a
formed by “What kinds of immoral things multiprocess model. According to the CPM,
are disgusting?”; “Why are disgusting things both character evaluations and consequence
immoral?”; and “Are there other differences evaluations contribute to moral judgment;
between purity and nonpurity transgres- other processes may also contribute, but they
sions?” One of the earliest multiprocess are not considered here. Both purity and non-
models of moral judgment in the field of purity transgressions can trigger character
psychology is the CAD triad hypothesis evaluations, which explains why both types
(Rozin, Lowery, et al., 1999). The CAD hy- of transgressions can evoke disgust. Purity
pothesis takes as its starting point the three transgressions may often activate character
moral processes described by anthropolo- judgments to a greater extent than conse-
gist Richard Shweder, namely, community, quence judgments, perhaps because most
autonomy, and divinity (Shweder, Much, purity transgressions do not have obvious
Mahaprata, & Park, 1997). According to negative consequences (Uhlmann & Zhu,
the CAD hypothesis, these codes are linked 2013). In a strong version of the CPM, there
to the emotions of contempt, anger, and dis- are no qualitative differences in the process-
gust, respectively. The CAD hypothesis was es that contribute to judgments about purity
a precursor to moral foundations theory, and nonpurity transgressions; all of the ap-
which reduces the emphasis on distinct emo- parent cognitive differences between these
tions but retains the idea that divinity (a.k.a. transgression types can be accounted for
purity) is a distinct moral process (Graham by quantitative differences in the degree to
et al., 2009). Other work has also developed which character and consequence judgments
the idea that purity violations, and the dis- are activated. However, a weaker version
gust associated with them, represent a dis- of the theory (shown in Figure 8.1) allows
tinct moral process (Chakroff & Young, cognitive processes that are unique to purity
2015; Russell & Giner-Sorolla, 2013). In and nonpurity transgressions. Note that the
sum, one historical trend has been to take weaker version of the CPM still maintains
evidence for a selective relationship between that both types of transgressions can acti-
particular emotions (especially disgust) and vate character and consequence judgments.
particular types of transgressions (especially
purity) as evidence for multiple moral pro- •• “Intuitive versus deliberative,” in-
cesses. formed by “Why are disgusting things im-
Recently, the opposite approach has moral?” The original description of the so-
emerged: If purity transgressions and non- cial intuitionist model (SIM; Haidt, 2001)
purity transgressions evoke similar emo- opens with a vignette that depicts consen-
tions (e.g., if both can evoke disgust), then sual incest. Consensual incest is often mor-
this may provide evidence against the idea ally condemned, even though there appears
of multiple moral processes and in favor of to be no harm. If there is no harm, then
single-process models such as the dyadic where does the wrongness judgment come
model (Cameron et al., 2015; Gray, Waytz, from? The answer, according to the SIM, is
& Young, 2012). According to the dyadic the powerful feelings of disgust evoked by
model, moral judgment depends primarily incest. Thus the fact that disgusting things
on the evaluation of negative consequences, are sometimes immoral has been taken as
which leads to an undifferentiated negative evidence that emotion is what causes moral
emotional response. The dyadic model thus judgment. Experimental work showing that
explains the wrongness of seemingly harm- incidental disgust can increase condemna-
less purity transgressions by suggesting that tion of moral transgressions has also been
they are implicitly perceived as having nega- taken as support for the idea that emotion
tive consequences, that is, as being harmful causes moral judgment (Eskine, Kacinik, &
(Gray et al., 2014). Prinz, 2011; Schnall, Haidt, Clore, & Jor-
The alternative suggested by the CPM is dan, 2008; Wheatley & Haidt, 2005). How-
that moral judgment relies on a number of ever, a recent meta-analysis of disgust induc-
component cognitive processes that may be tion studies suggests that incidental disgust
activated to different degrees by different has at best a small effect on moral judgment
74 M O R A L I T Y A N D F E E L I N G

(Landy & Goodwin, 2015). In contrast to transgressions can evoke disgust. Thus the
the SIM, the CPM puts character evaluation CPM differs from theories in which disgust
upstream of disgust. Such evaluations could is linked uniquely to purity transgressions,
be either implicit or explicit; thus the CPM is such as the CAD triad hypothesis (Rozin,
ambivalent as to the intuitive-versus-deliber- Lowery, et al., 1999), work by Young and
ative nature of morality. colleagues (Chakroff & Young, 2015; Young
& Saxe, 2011), and older work by Giner-­
•• “Culturally uniform or variable?,” in- Sorolla, Russell, and their colleagues (Rus-
formed by “Why are disgusting things im- sell & Giner-Sorolla, 2013). The strong ver-
moral?” Some cultures judge that purity sion of the CPM also diverges from modular
transgressions are immoral, whereas others theories such as moral foundations theory
do not. For example, American conserva- (Graham et al., 2009) insofar as it denies
tives condemn purity transgressions much that the cognitive processes associated with
more than American liberals (Graham et al., purity transgressions are fully distinct from
2009). According to moral foundations the- those underlying nonpurity transgressions.
ory, disgusting things are immoral to such (The weak version of the CPM does allow
people because these individuals have a dis- for distinct, in addition to common, pro-
tinct moral process for purity; this process is cesses). Finally, the CPM differs from SIM
absent in individuals who do not condemn (Haidt, 2001) in that it places evaluations
disgusting things (Graham et al., 2009; Gra- of character and consequences upstream of
ham et al., 2011). In other words, differences moral judgment and emotion.
of opinion about purity transgressions pro- By contrast, the CPM is very much al-
vide evidence that morality is culturally vari- lied with and indebted to a number of other
able. By contrast, the CPM draws on social theories. Specifically, the CPM attempts to
domain theory (Turiel, Killen, & Helwig, combine elements of several existing theo-
1987) to suggest an alternative explanation ries in a novel way so as to produce a unified
for cultural variability in condemnation of account of the moral judgments and emo-
purity transgressions. Specifically, different tions elicited by purity and nonpurity trans-
cultures may make different informational gressions. The CPM borrows from person-
assumptions about purity transgressions centric models of morality (Uhlmann et al.,
(Turiel, Hildebrandt, Wainryb, & Saltz­ 2015) the idea that character evaluations are
stein, 1991). For example, to the extent that critical to moral judgment, and that they can
a particular culture assumes that a disgust- at least partly explain why harmless purity
ing act is harmful (to the self, others, the transgressions are judged as wrong. The per-
community, or the natural order), it will be son-centric model does not specifically ad-
moralized by that culture. Similarly, to the dress emotions, however, whereas the CPM
extent that a particular culture assumes that does. The idea that moral disgust might be
a disgusting act indicates bad character, it related to character judgments has its origins
will be moralized. American liberals, for ex- in the work of Giner-Sorolla and colleagues
ample, believe that homosexual sex is nei- (Giner-Sorolla & Chapman, 2017), and in
ther harmful nor indicative of bad character; Hutcherson and colleagues’ social–function-
therefore, American liberals do not moralize alist model (Hutcherson & Gross, 2011).
homosexuality. The CPM thus accounts for Hutcherson and colleagues were also among
cultural variability in moralization of purity the first to suggest that moral disgust might
transgressions by pointing to variability in be associated with withdrawal motivation.
the component processes of character and However, Hutcherson and colleagues were
consequence evaluation. primarily interested in disgust evoked by
nonpurity transgressions and did not ad-
dress the link between purity transgressions
Theoretical Stance and character evaluations that the CPM in-
cludes.
The CPM differs substantially from some Finally, the CPM has a mixed relation-
major theories of morality. First, accord- ship with some other theories. The CPM
ing to the CPM, both purity and nonpurity agrees with the dyadic model of morality
 Disgust, Anger, and Moral Judgment 75

(Gray et al., 2012) as to the importance of As well, nonpurity transgressions trigger


consequence (a.k.a. harm) judgments for facial movements associated with disgust,
moral condemnation. However, the CPM namely, activity of the levator labii muscle,
also emphasizes the role of character and which wrinkles the nose and/or raises the
suggests that character judgment as well as upper lip (Cannon, Schnall, & White, 2011;
harm judgments may contribute to condem- Chapman, Kim, Susskind, & Anderson,
nation of purity transgressions. The dyadic 2009). Finally, trait disgust predicts con-
model is, more broadly, an example of a demnation of nonpurity transgressions even
constructivist model of morality (Cameron when controlling for trait anger (Chapman
et al., 2015), with which the CPM shares the & Anderson, 2014; Jones & Fitness, 2008).
general idea that moral cognition consists of The CPM’s second claim is that disgust
several different cognitive processes that can evoked by nonpurity transgressions sub-
be combined in different ways. However, serves withdrawal/avoidance motivation in
constructivist models tend to favor an undif- the moral domain. The logic here is that
ferentiated negative emotional response to active, approach-related behaviors are not
transgressions, whereas the CPM proposes always the best way to deal with a transgres-
that different component cognitive processes sion. Indeed, game-theoretic modeling shows
trigger different emotions. Finally, construc- that active punishment (which may entail a
tivist models typically favor cultural–cogni- cost to the punisher) is almost always a less
tive explanations for emotion differentiation, efficient strategy than rejection or avoidance
in which distinct emotions such as anger (Ohtsuki, Iwasa, & Nowak, 2009). There
and fear arise from an individual’s culturally is, however, only indirect support for the
driven conceptualization of what is funda- idea that withdrawal in the moral domain
mentally an undifferentiated affective expe- is tied to disgust. Nonmoral disgust in gen-
rience (Barrett, 2006). By contrast, the CPM eral is associated with withdrawal motiva-
is more inspired by biological–­evolutionary tion (Rozin, Haidt, & McCauley, 2000), in
reasoning, in which distinct emotions repre- contrast to the approach motivation linked
sent unique adaptations to particular kinds to anger (Carver & Harmon-Jones, 2009).
of opportunities and threats in the ancestral However, only one study has directly tested
environment (Cosmides & Tooby, 2000; the potential link between moral disgust
Ekman, 1992; Frijda, 1987). and withdrawal motivation, by asking par-
ticipants whether they would be “willing to
go to some effort” to avoid a transgressor
Evidence (Hutcherson & Gross, 2011). This research
actually found that anger, but not disgust,
The CPM’s first claim is that both purity predicted avoidance, although the question
and nonpurity transgressions can evoke wording may have suggested an active re-
disgust that is distinct from anger. This is a sponse more closely allied with anger than
methodologically treacherous area, because disgust. Thus more research is needed to test
disgust and anger evoked by moral trans- the claim that moral disgust is associated
gressions share considerable variance (Chap- with withdrawal motivation. Such work
man & Anderson, 2013; Russell & Giner- should be careful to give participants an op-
Sorolla, 2013). However, a small body of portunity to actually express their behavior-
evidence does support the idea that moral al tendencies, as perceived ability to attain a
disgust evoked by nonpurity transgressions behavioral goal influences motivational in-
is distinct from anger. First, endorsement of tensity (Brehm & Self, 1989; Harmon-Jones,
disgust words (e.g., repulsed, sickened) in Sigelman, Bohlig, & Harmon-Jones, 2003).
response to nonpurity transgressions is pre- A challenge for work seeking to link moral
dicted by endorsement of facial expressions disgust to withdrawal is that most transgres-
of disgust but not facial expressions of anger sions probably evoke both anger and disgust
(Gutierrez, Giner-Sorolla, & Vasiljevic, and hence will probably activate both ap-
2011). In other words, describing nonpurity proach and withdrawal tendencies. Here,
transgressions as “disgusting” is not fully the solution may be to use transgression
the same as describing them as “angering.” stimuli that isolate the cognitive processes
76 M O R A L I T Y A N D F E E L I N G

hypothesized to lead to disgust and anger. tribute to circumstances. Indeed, individuals


This leads to the CPM’s third claim: Disgust who commit purity transgressions (e.g., hav-
is linked to character judgments, whereas ing sex with a dead chicken) are judged to
anger is linked to consequence judgments. In have worse character than those who com-
principle, it should be possible to dissociate mit nonpurity transgressions (e.g., stealing a
the action tendencies associated with moral dead chicken), even though nonpurity trans-
disgust and anger by using stimuli that pri- gressions are judged to be more immoral
marily activate character or consequence (Uhlmann & Zhu, 2013). Thus there is good
judgments, respectively. This is also tricky, evidence that purity transgressions signal
however, because it is easy to confound bad bad character. Still missing, however, is evi-
character and negative consequences. For dence that purity transgressions are judged
example, given a stripped-down scenario to be immoral because of the character judg-
such as hitting someone’s finger with a ham- ments that they engender, as hypothesized
mer (Chakroff & Young, 2015) or slapping by the CPM.
someone in the face (Chapman & Ander- Finally, the CPM claims that at least
son, 2014), participants may default to the some of the apparent cognitive differences
assumption that the negative consequences between purity and nonpurity transgres-
occurred because the transgressor is a bad sions are due to differential activation of the
person (Giner-Sorolla & Chapman, 2017). same underlying cognitive processes, namely
One way to disentangle character and character and consequence judgments. This
consequence judgments is to cross the pres- stands in contrast to the claim that qualita-
ence or absence of the desire to cause harm, tively different cognitive processes under-
which indicates bad character, with the pres- lie judgments about purity and nonpurity
ence or absence of negative consequences transgressions (Chakroff & Young, 2015;
(Giner-Sorolla & Chapman, 2017). For ex- Graham et al., 2009).
ample, an individual might desire to cause Here it is critical to distinguish between
harm but never act on it, or an individual the cognitive processes that influence moral
may not desire harm but something bad judgments and the cognitive processes that
happens anyway. Research in this vein has influence feelings of disgust. According to
found that desire to commit harm predicts the CPM, disgust evoked by purity trans-
disgust and that this effect is mediated by gressions has two sources: a core disgust
the perception of bad character. By contrast, evaluation (triggered by the presence of
negative consequences predict anger but not pathogens, biologically disadvantageous
disgust. These findings are consistent with sex, etc.) and a character evaluation. The
the CPM’s claim that moral disgust is driven core disgust evaluation likely dominates the
by negative character evaluations, whereas disgust response to most purity transgres-
moral anger is driven by negative conse- sions and is probably insensitive to the fac-
quence evaluations. tors that influence wrongness judgments.
The CPM’s third claim is that purity For example, previous work has shown that
transgressions are judged to be immoral at disgust in response to purity transgressions
least in part because they signal bad char- is unaffected by whether or not the victim
acter. At present, there is only partial evi- consented to the transgression (Russell &
dence for this claim. In general, behaviors Piazza, 2014). This makes sense: Core dis-
that are statistically rare (Ditto & Jemmott, gust evaluations will be triggered whether or
1989; Fiske, 1980; McKenzie & Mikkelsen, not the victim consented, because either way
2007; Snyder, Kleck, Strenta, & Mentzer, a core disgust stimulus was present. By con-
1979) and low in attributional ambiguity trast, wrongness judgments are attenuated
(Snyder et al., 1979) are perceived as highly when the victim consents to a purity trans-
informative about character traits. Purity gression (Russell & Piazza, 2014). Thus the
transgressions, such as drinking urine or en- cognitive processes that influence disgust
gaging in consensual incest, certainly satisfy are not necessarily the same as those that
these conditions (Uhlmann et al., 2015). By influence moral judgments. In what follows,
contrast, nonpurity transgressions such as my focus is on the cognitive processes that
theft may be more common and easier to at- influence moral judgments and whether they
 Disgust, Anger, and Moral Judgment 77

might differ between purity and nonpurity evidence for a difference in the role of in-
transgressions. tent across purity and nonpurity domains
First, some differences between purity is actually somewhat mixed. For example,
and nonpurity transgressions can be easily one study found no interaction between
explained by the idea that purity transgres- transgression type and intent for wrong-
sions tend to activate character judgments to ness judgments (Russell & Giner-Sorolla,
a greater extent than nonpurity transgres- 2011b). Critics have also argued that the pu-
sions. For example, people are more likely rity transgressions used in many studies are
to make person-based attributions for purity novel and bizarre (Gray & Keeney, 2015),
transgressions than for nonpurity transgres- to which I would add psychologically com-
sions (Chakroff & Young, 2015). This fits plex and potentially rife with confounds.
nicely with the idea that purity transgres- Indeed, unintentional disgusting behaviors
sions may be an especially strong signal of that are more everyday and innocuous (e.g.,
bad character because of their statistical in- getting dog feces on one’s hands when try-
frequency and low attributional ambiguity ing to clean it off one’s shoes) are not judged
(Uhlmann et al., 2015). Note that nonpurity as morally wrong at all (Chapman, 2017).
transgressions also trigger person-based at- In sum, it is currently not clear whether the
tributions, albeit to a lesser extent, consis- role of intent really differs between purity
tent with the idea that both transgression and nonpurity transgressions.
types can involve character judgments. One final difference between purity and
A related finding is that self-directed nonpurity transgressions is also challenging
transgressions evoke more disgust (con- for a strong version of the CPM. Specifically,
trolling for anger) than do other-directed generating reasons why someone might jus-
transgressions (Chakroff et al., 2013). Self- tifiably commit a purity transgression re-
directed transgressions were also associated duces wrongness ratings to a lesser extent
with more negative character judgments than generating reasons why someone might
than other-directed transgressions, con- commit a nonpurity transgression (Russell
sistent with the idea that disgust is related & Giner-Sorolla, 2011a). On the one hand,
to character judgments. This suggests that this could be because it is difficult to come
what a person does to him- or herself may up with good reasons for committing a pu-
reveal character more than what he or she rity transgression. Consistent with this idea,
does to others. Indeed, whereas there could participants produce less elaborated justifi-
be situational reasons for doing something cations for their feelings of disgust compared
to someone else, we usually only do things with anger (Russell & Giner-Sorolla, 2011c).
to ourselves when we want to, and desires On the other hand, even when the scenario
speak strongly to character. explicitly provides external reasons for com-
Some differences between purity and non- mitting the transgression, people judge that
purity transgressions are difficult to explain purity transgressions are more voluntary
using character and consequence judgments, than nonpurity transgressions (Chakroff &
and thus they could present a challenge to Young, 2015). For example, a person who
a strong version of the CPM in which char- hits his sister in a game of truth or dare is
acter and consequence judgments are the judged to have acted more freely than a per-
only cognitive processes that contribute to son who kisses his sister. This could suggest
differences between transgression types. For a genuine difference in the cognitive pro-
example, two studies have reported that the cesses that underlie moral judgments about
transgressor’s intent matters less for moral purity and nonpurity transgressions, which
judgments about purity transgressions than would be compatible with the weaker ver-
for judgments about nonpurity transgres- sion of the CPM.
sions (Chakroff et al., 2013; Young & Saxe,
2011). It is difficult to see how this differ-
ence could be accounted for by the idea that Extension and Expansion
purity transgressions tend to activate char-
acter judgments to a greater extent than The CPM is part of a new wave of research
do nonpurity transgressions. That said, the that emphasizes that character and conse-
78 M O R A L I T Y A N D F E E L I N G

quence judgments are distinct aspects of rity transgressions are morally condemned;
moral cognition (Uhlmann et al., 2015). An it can also account for at least some of the
important future direction for this line of cognitive differences between purity and
work will be to determine whether charac- nonpurity transgressions. More evidence
ter and consequence judgments might be as- is certainly needed to shore up the CPM’s
sociated with different behavioral responses claims, and the model must ultimately be
to moral transgressions. Most research on expanded to include other important moral
how people respond to transgressions has cognitive processes such as judgments of in-
focused on punishment, especially pun- tent. Nonetheless, the CPM holds the prom-
ishment that entails a cost to the punisher ise of making sense of two decades’ worth
(Carlsmith, Darley, & Robinson, 2002; of work on moral disgust and of informing
Henrich et al., 2006). Costly punishment is the fundamental debates about morality that
just that, however: costly at worst, risky at this volume seeks to address.
best. In the grand scheme, therefore, punish-
ment may be less important than rejection
and avoidance, which fall under the umbrel- NOTE
la of “partner choice” (Bull & Rice, 1991;
1. The CPM as depicted in Figure 8.1 focuses on
Kuhlmeier, Dunfield, & O’Neill, 2014).
the causes of moral disgust and anger rather
In spite of its potential importance, part- than trying to provide a complete model of
ner choice remains extremely understudied. moral judgment. Thus, for simplicity, the
For example, we do not know when people model omits other critical moral cognitive
might opt for partner choice over punish- processes, such as the role of intent judg-
ment or what the motivational underpin- ments.
nings of partner choice might be. The CPM
points at potential answers to such ques-
tions. First, negative character evaluations REFERENCES
may be a major reason for selecting partner
Barrett, L. F. (2006). Solving the emotion para-
choice over punishment. If a person trans-
dox: Categorization and the experience of
gresses because he or she has a fundamen- emotion. Personality and Social Psychology
tally bad character, then he or she is likely Review, 10(1), 20–46.
to transgress again in the future, and ef- Brehm, J. W., & Self, E. A. (1989). The intensity
forts to deter such behavior (e.g., through of motivation. Annual Review of Psychology,
punishment) are likely to be ineffective 40, 109–131.
(Fischer & Roseman, 2007; Hutcherson & Bull, J. J., & Rice, W. R. (1991). Distinguishing
Gross, 2011). Second, given that disgust is mechanisms for the evolution of co-operation.
hypothesized to subserve withdrawal and Journal of Theoretical Biology, 149(1), 63–74.
avoidance in the moral domain (Chapman Cameron, C. D., Lindquist, K. A., & Gray, K.
& Anderson, 2013; Hutcherson & Gross, (2015). A constructionist review of morality
and emotions: No evidence for specific links
2011), disgust may provide the motivation between moral content and discrete emotions.
for partner choice. In sum, the CPM predicts Personality and Social Psychology Review,
that character evaluations should be a major 19(4), 371–394.
predictor of partner choice and that disgust Cannon, P. R., Schnall, S., & White, M. (2011).
provides the motivation to reject and avoid Transgressions and expressions: Affective fa-
transgressors. cial muscle activity predicts moral judgments.
To summarize, the CPM proposes that Social Psychological and Personality Science,
character and consequence evaluations 2(3), 325–331.
both contribute to moral judgments and Carlsmith, K. M., Darley, J. M., & Robinson,
that these moral cognitive processes trigger P. H. (2002). Why do we punish?: Deterrence
and just deserts as motives for punishment.
the emotions of disgust and anger, respec- Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
tively. In turn, disgust and anger motivate 83(2), 284.
avoidance- and approach-related behav- Carver, C. S., & Harmon-Jones, E. (2009). Anger
ioral responses. This model parsimoniously is an approach-related affect: Evidence and
explains why both purity and nonpurity implications. Psychological Bulletin, 135(2),
transgressions trigger disgust and why pu- 183–204.
 Disgust, Anger, and Moral Judgment 79

Chakroff, A., Dungan, J., & Young, L. (2013). sets of moral foundations. Journal of Personal-
Harming ourselves and defiling others: What ity and Social Psychology, 96(5), 1029–1046.
determines a moral domain? PLOS ONE, Graham, J., Nosek, B. A., Haidt, J., Iyer, R., Kol-
8(9). Available at www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/ eva, S., & Ditto, P. H. (2011). Mapping the
pmc/articles/PMC3770666. moral domain. Journal of Personality and So-
Chakroff, A., & Young, L. (2015). Harmful situ- cial Psychology, 101(2), 366.
ations, impure people: An attribution asym- Gray, K., & Keeney, J. E. (2015). Impure, or just
metry across moral domains. Cognition, 136, weird?: Scenario sampling bias raises ques-
30–37. tions about the foundation of morality. Social
Chapman, H. (2017). The moral psychology of Psychological and Personality Science, 6(8),
ordinary purity transgressions. Manuscript in 859–868.
preparation. Gray, K., Schein, C., & Ward, A. (2014). The
Chapman, H., & Anderson, A. K. (2013). Things myth of harmless wrongs in moral cognition:
rank and gross in nature: A review and synthe- Automatic dyadic completion from sin to suf-
sis of moral disgust. Psychological Bulletin, fering. Journal of Experimental Psychology:
139(2), 300–327. General, 143, 1600–1615.
Chapman, H., & Anderson, A. K. (2014). Trait Gray, K., Waytz, A., & Young, L. (2012). The
physical disgust is related to moral judgments moral dyad: A fundamental template unifying
outside of the purity domain. Emotion, 14(2), moral judgment. Psychological Inquiry, 23(2),
341–348. 206–215.
Chapman, H., Kim, D. A., Susskind, J. M., & Gutierrez, R., Giner-Sorolla, R. S., & Vasiljevic,
Anderson, A. K. (2009). In bad taste: Evidence M. (2011). Just an anger synonym?: Moral
for the oral origins of moral disgust. Science, context influences predictors of disgust word
323(5918), 1222–1226. use. Cognition and Emotion, 26(1), 53–64.
Cosmides, L., & Tooby, J. (2000). Evolutionary Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional dog and its ra-
psychology and the emotions. In M. Lewis & tional tail: A social intuitionist approach
J. Haviland-Jones (Eds.), Handbook of emo-
to moral judgment. Psychological Review,
tions (2nd ed., pp. 91–115). New York: Guil-
108(4), 814–834.
ford Press.
Harmon-Jones, E., Sigelman, J., Bohlig, A., &
Ditto, P. H., & Jemmott, J. B. (1989). From rarity
Harmon-Jones, C. (2003). Anger, coping, and
to evaluative extremity: Effects of prevalence
frontal cortical activity: The effect of coping
information on evaluations of positive and
potential on anger-induced left frontal activ-
negative characteristics. Journal of Personal-
ity and Social Psychology, 57(1), 16–26. ity. Cognition and Emotion, 17(1), 1–24.
Ekman, P. (1992). An argument for basic emo- Henrich, J., McElreath, R., Barr, A., Ensminger,
tions. Cognition and Emotion, 6(3/4), 169– J., Barrett, C., Bolyanatz, A., . . . Ziker, J.
200. (2006). Costly punishment across human soci-
Eskine, K. J., Kacinik, N. A., & Prinz, J. J. eties. Science, 312(5781), 1767–1770.
(2011). A bad taste in the mouth: Gustatory Horberg, E. J., Oveis, C., Keltner, D., & Cohen,
disgust influences moral judgment. Psycho- A. B. (2009). Disgust and the moralization of
logical Science, 22(3), 295–299. purity. Journal of Personality and Social Psy-
Fischer, A. H., & Roseman, I. J. (2007). Beat chology, 97(6), 963–976.
them or ban them: The characteristics and so- Hutcherson, C. A., & Gross, J. J. (2011). The
cial functions of anger and contempt. Journal moral emotions: A social-functionalist ac-
of Personality and Social Psychology, 93(1), count of anger, disgust, and contempt. Journal
103–115. of Personality and Social Psychology, 100(4),
Fiske, S. T. (1980). Attention and weight in per- 719–737.
son perception: The impact of negative and Jones, A., & Fitness, J. (2008). Moral hypervigi-
extreme behavior. Journal of Personality and lance: The influence of disgust sensitivity in
Social Psychology, 38(6), 889–906. the moral domain. Emotion, 8(5), 613–627.
Frijda, N. (1987). Emotion, cognitive structure, Kuhlmeier, V. A., Dunfield, K. A., & O’Neill, A.
and action tendency. Cognition and Emotion, C. (2014). Selectivity in early prosocial behav-
1(1), 15–143. ior. Frontiers in Psychology, 5, 836.
Giner-Sorolla, R. S., & Chapman, H. A. (2017). Landy, J. F., & Goodwin, G. P. (2015). Does
Beyond purity: Moral disgust toward bad incidental disgust amplify moral judgment?:
character. Psychological Science, 28(1), 80– A meta-analytic review of experimental evi-
91. dence. Perspectives on Psychological Science,
Graham, J., Haidt, J., & Nosek, B. A. (2009). 10(4), 518–536.
Liberals and conservatives rely on different McKenzie, C. R., & Mikkelsen, L. A. (2007). A
80 M O R A L I T Y A N D F E E L I N G

Bayesian view of covariation assessment. Cog- Russell, P. S., & Piazza, J. (2014). Consenting
nitive Psychology, 54(1), 33–61. to counter-normative sexual acts: Differential
Oaten, M., Stevenson, R., & Case, T. (2009). effects of consent on anger and disgust as a
Disgust as a disease-avoidance mechanism. function of transgressor or consenter. Cogni-
Psychological Bulletin, 135(2), 303. tion and Emotion, 29(4), 634–653.
Ohtsuki, H., Iwasa, Y., & Nowak, M. A. (2009). Schnall, S., Haidt, J., Clore, G. L., & Jordan, A.
Indirect reciprocity provides only a narrow H. (2008). Disgust as embodied moral judg-
margin of efficiency for costly punishment. ment. Personality and Social Psychology Bul-
Nature, 457(7225), 79–82. letin, 34(8), 1096–1109.
Royzman, E., Atanasov, P., Landy, J. F., Parks, Shweder, R. A., Much, N., Mahaprata, M., &
A., & Gepty, A. (2014). CAD or MAD?: Anger Park, L. (1997). The “big three” of moral-
(not disgust) as the predominant response to ity (autonomy, community, divinity) and
pathogen-free violations of the divinity code. the “big three” explanations of suffering. In
Emotion, 14, 892–907. A. Brandt & P. Rozin (Eds.), Morality and
Royzman, E., Leeman, R., & Baron, J. (2009). health (pp. 119–169). New York: Psychology
Unsentimental ethics: Towards a content-spe- Press.
cific account of the moral–conventional dis- Snyder, M. L., Kleck, R. E., Strenta, A., & Men-
tinction. Cognition, 112(1), 159–174. tzer, S. J. (1979). Avoidance of the handi-
Rozin, P., Haidt, J., & Fincher, K. (2009). From capped: An attributional ambiguity analysis.
oral to moral. Science, 323(5918), 1179. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
Rozin, P., Haidt, J., & McCauley, C. (1999). 37(12), 2297–2306.
Disgust: The body and soul emotion. In T. Turiel, E., Hildebrandt, C., Wainryb, C., &
Dalgleish & M. J. Power (Eds.), Handbook of Saltzstein, H. (1991). Judging social issues:
cognition and emotion (pp. 429–445). New Difficulties, inconsistencies, and consistencies.
York: Wiley. Monographs of the Society for Research in
Rozin, P., Haidt, J., & McCauley, C. (2000). Dis- Child Development, 56, 35–116.
gust. In M. Lewis & J. Haviland-Jones (Eds.), Turiel, E., Killen, M., & Helwig, C. (1987). Mo-
Handbook of emotions (2nd ed., pp. 637– rality: Its structure, functions, and vagaries. In
653). New York: Guilford Press. J. Kagan (Ed.), The emergence of morality in
Rozin, P., Lowery, L., Imada, S., & Haidt, J. young children (pp. 155–243). Chicago: Uni-
(1999). The CAD triad hypothesis: A map- versity of Chicago Press.
ping between three moral emotions (contempt, Tybur, J. M., Lieberman, D., Kurzban, R., &
anger, disgust) and three moral codes (commu- DeScioli, P. (2012). Disgust: Evolved function
nity, autonomy, divinity). Journal of Personal- and structure. Psychological Review, 120(1),
ity and Social Psychology, 76(4), 574–586. 65–84.
Russell, P. S., & Giner-Sorolla, R. S. (2011a). Uhlmann, E. L., Pizarro, D. A., & Diermeier, D.
Moral anger is more flexible than moral dis- (2015). A person-centered approach to moral
gust. Social Psychological and Personality Sci- judgment. Perspectives on Psychological Sci-
ence, 2(4), 360–364. ence, 10(1), 72–81.
Russell, P. S., & Giner-Sorolla, R. S. (2011b). Uhlmann, E. L., & Zhu, L. (2013). Acts, per-
Moral anger, but not moral disgust, responds sons, and intuitions: Person-centered cues and
to intentionality. Emotion, 11(1), 233–240. gut reactions to harmless transgressions. So-
Russell, P. S., & Giner-Sorolla, R. S. (2011c). So- cial Psychological and Personality Science, 5,
cial justifications for moral emotions: When 279–285.
reasons for disgust are less elaborated than for Wheatley, T., & Haidt, J. (2005). Hypnotic dis-
anger. Emotion, 11(3), 637. gust makes moral judgments more severe. Psy-
Russell, P. S., & Giner-Sorolla, R. S. (2013). chological Science, 16(10), 780–784.
Bodily moral disgust: What it is, how it is dif- Young, L., & Saxe, R. (2011). When ignorance
ferent from anger, and why it is an unreasoned is no excuse: Different roles for intent across
emotion. Psychological Bulletin, 139(2), 328. moral domains. Cognition, 120, 202–214.
CHAPTER 9

A Functional Conflict Theory


of Moral Emotions

Roger Giner‑Sorolla

What makes some emotions moral emotions?

Emotions are moral in nature when they regulate the interests of a


higher level of social organization than the currently focal one by
means of four functions that sometimes dysfunctionally conflict:
appraisal, association, self-regulation, and communication.

My theory tries to explain why people have another), and possibly gratitude. Shame,
emotional reactions to moral situations. It is anger, pride, disgust: All of these are moral
thus a theory of moral emotions. However, emotions, but they serve other functions as
it is important to keep in mind the some- well. It is that ambiguity that makes them so
times-noted distinction between a criminal interesting.
lawyer (one who deals in criminal cases) and The key constructs here are emotions:
a criminal lawyer (one who is a criminal mental and sometimes physiological phe-
him- or herself; Gilligan et al., 2010). Like- nomena consisting of eliciting perceptions,
wise, an emotion that deals with moral situ- subjective feelings, and expressions through
ations is not necessarily one that possesses several channels, action motivations, and
the essence of moral virtue. In fact, there are verbal labels to refer to the whole thing: not
very few emotions that are elicited only by perfectly, but functionally. Emotions are dis-
moral situations—by “moral” here, I mean tinguished from other states and from each
concerns that respond to the interest of an- other in several ways. They are activated by
other over and above one’s own. Among concerns about oneself or about values and
the negative emotions, only guilt seems to people close to oneself (unlike perception,
be “moral” in this sense; even shame some- reasoning, curiosity, etc.). They are hard to
times works selfishly to protect one’s own control upon activation, so that they serve as
reputation. Among the positive emotions, an authentic signal of motivations for one-
we can count sympathy, the rather rarefied self and others (unlike language, decisions,
construct of elevation (which by definition etc.). And distinct emotions are culturally
responds to an example of moral virtue in constructed from underlying biological ele-

81
82 M O R A L I T Y A N D F E E L I N G

ments to communicate and motivate indi- Particularly interesting phenomena arise


vidually and socially adaptive behavior. The when these functions conflict with each
more socially adaptive the function of an other. Unlike appraisal theories (e.g., Laza-
emotion, the more we can say it is moral. rus, 1991), which attribute dysfunctional
I see four specific overlapping functions of side effects of emotion to inaccurate input
emotions as bearing potential relevance to into an otherwise working system, my func-
morality (Giner-Sorolla, 2012). tional conflict theory proposes that dys-
function arises when an emotion activated
1. In the appraisal function, people as- to serve one function falls foul of another.
sess stimuli in relation to goals (here, moral For example, expressing moral anger may be
ones); the outcome of this assessment pro- a way to communicate one’s moral charac-
motes an emotional response, which pre- ter or to regulate and externalize one’s own
pares and motivates an adaptive behavior. insecurities, without necessarily correspond-
For example, you see a baby crying, you feel ing to the actual situation in a way that
bad for it (sympathy, or empathy) and run would accurately serve appraisal’s function.
over to help; if nobody had done that for us
when we were little, none of us would be
here. Historical Context

2.  Associative learning is often seen as ir- This is an integrative theory that calls up
rational, but I see it as functional, too, and four strands of functional theorizing about
perhaps even morally functional. For exam- emotions in general and moral emotions
ple, children often learn to associate a na- in particular. The theory invites them all
tional song and symbols with pride. Unlike to a party hosted by the underlying adap-
appraisal, this connection between an arbi- tive principle of exaptation, in which a sin-
trary signifier and a signified emotion arises gle structure can serve multiple functions
without purpose or goal, but its easy and (Gould, 2010). Let’s stroll around the party
unquestioning availability later in life can and ask the four functions about their his-
coordinate large groups of people to action. torical roots.
In some ways, what we consider core moral Some theories, in the tradition of David
values depend on unreasoned, basic affective Hume and Jonathan Haidt, expect emotions
associations (Maio & Olson, 1998). to be functional guides to moral behavior,
and these historical perspectives find kin-
3.  Emotions also have a regulatory role to ship in today’s appraisal theory. This has
play, some more than others; for example, taken on many forms since it was prefig-
shame, pride, and guilt seem to be partially ured by the work of Magda Arnold (1960),
internalized anticipations of our reactions developed by Lazarus and Folkman (1984)
to the social effect of our own actions. An- in the context of coping, and further split
ticipating emotional appraisals and associa- into many different schemes over the two
tions helps us behave accordingly, without decades hence (e.g., Lazarus, 1991; Ortony,
needing to feel or express the full weight of Clore, & Collins, 1990; Roseman, 1984;
the emotion. There are also motivations and Smith & Ellsworth, 1985; Weiner, 1985).
concerns that regulate emotions, undercut- Moral appraisals are fundamentally social,
ting the full weight of guilt and shame in even if internalized in the self, and motivate
particular by deploying excuses and ratio- such behaviors as punishment of wrongdo-
nalizations. ers (anger), ostracism and avoidance (disgust
and contempt), and praise and support of
4. Finally, emotions communicate these virtuous persons (elevation).
states to others in a more trustworthy way But not all appraisals are sensitive to con-
than language, or other representations, text, and soon enough the associative func-
can. Facial expressions, vocal timbre, and tion appears to state its case. Regardless of
positions and attitudes of the body do this whether or not these context-insensitive,
work. stimulus-triggered emotional associations
 A Functional Conflict Theory of Moral Emotions 83

are classified as a special kind of appraisal Certainly, in survivor guilt, the reaction to
(as Moors, Ellsworth, Scherer, & Frijda having kept one’s life while someone else has
[2013] do), it is undeniable that they form lost it for no good reason shows that guilt has
a large part of the case for morally relevant left its original function of resource distribu-
emotions being irrational, unhelpful, and tion far behind and reacts to inequality even
even in some cases immoral. The underly- when there is no hope of restoring it. Thus the
ing template for the irrationality of emotions regulatory function bridges the apparent gap
comes from Freud and other psychodynamic between associative and appraisal modes by
theorists, who see affective associations as showing how a relatively more internalized,
partaking of primary-process wish fulfill- automatized, and mysterious moral feeling is
ment, more to do with people’s past internal just a rational social appraisal that has taken
drama than their present external situation on a life of its own.
(e.g. Freud, 1900/2008). In moral psychol- Likewise, the communication function
ogy, Nussbaum (2004) has argued that dis- steps in from the other side and reminds
gust, in particular, as an associative emotion the associative and appraisal functions of
is more supportive of irrational prejudice how it, too, draws on both of them. Com-
than of wise and fair moral judgment. How- municating emotions regulates the social
ever, one can see many examples of other environment, just as feeling them regulates
emotions, such as anger, also being activated action. This notion, too, is relatively recent
out of proportion to the situation based on in psychological theory but by now well sup-
simmering provocations in the recent or dis- ported (Parkinson, Fischer & Manstead,
tant past. Even emotions such as sympathy 2004; Parkinson & Manstead, 2015; van
can backfire, as when news footage of un- Kleef, 2009). Social regulation of emotions,
clothed children in faraway parts prompts too, is a very recently devised and studied
donations of used clothing that, en masse, topic (Totterdell, Hershcovis, Niven, Reich,
undercut local producers and further impov- & Stride, 2012). The full complexity of how
erish the economy (cf. Bloom, 2016). a network of people show their emotions to
As the shoving match between association others, how these emotions as well as ac-
and appraisal gets more heated, self-regula- tions and utterances seek to influence the
tion and communication step in and try to feelings of others, and how these changes
mediate. The self-regulation function in my reflect back on us—all of this is perhaps a
theory draws on fairly recent ideas about the topic for a more complex and computation-
use of emotions as checks or feedbacks to be- al model than the simple lab experiment in
havior, rather than as motivators of it (e.g., psychology can reveal.
Carver, Lawrence, & Scheier, 1996; Higgins, It may seem that this is a disjunctive the-
1987; Baumeister, Vohs, DeWall, & Zhang, ory, but in fact I tie these four functions to-
2007). In some sense, appraisal and self- gether in the construct of the emotion and
regulation belong to the same family when declare that the promise and problem of
it comes to moral emotions. Because moral human emotions comes from the fact that
concerns are ultimately social, each self-reg- the four functions are jammed together in
ulatory emotion can be seen as the internal- this party, whose metaphorical usefulness is
ization of an appraisal that would be ratio- rapidly outstaying its welcome. What would
nal in a directly social context. For example, happen if we could be completely rational
when we accidentally harm someone we care and exert executive control over the input
about, we feel both empathic distress at their to our appraisals, and so turn off our emo-
overt expression of pain and anxiety at their tions at will? Then our representations of
overt disapproval. Guilt and shame preempt emotions would be worthless as a signal of
this direct perception and invite us to become true intentions, just as they would be worth-
distressed at our own bad behavior. Thus, less as commitments to our own longer term
when guilt, shame, and other emotions act causes. It is in fact this insight of the econo-
preemptively on the self, they lose their char- mist Robert Frank (1988) that underscores
acter of appraisal and become regulatory. how the conflict between reason and un-
In this way, they may even seem irrational. reason has a meaning, and unreason is not
84 M O R A L I T Y A N D F E E L I N G

to be dismissed lightly. This, ultimately, is one characteristic of many of the most in-
my view of morality. Moral feelings are the teresting moral emotions is that they can
currency tying us to other individuals, to be activated in response to a number of dif-
our groups and our culture, without really ferent conceptual inputs and carry through
giving us the option of leaving them—or, from one context to another. Only some
at least, ensuring that leaving them will be of these may be morally relevant. For ex-
done with pain and dislocation. ample, pride can result from viewing one’s
Another aspect of history that I wish to own highly competent technical accom-
address is the long debate about whether plishments or from a basic, unconditional
emotions are necessary for moral judgment acceptance of oneself; anger can result from
and action. Made famous by the contrast of personally relevant goal blockage, a threat
the philosophers Hume and Kant (Nichols, to one’s person or group, or the violation of
2004), the debate has been resurrected in re- a moral principle (cf. Kuppens, Mechelen,
cent times by social emotionalist theory (e.g., Smits, & Boeck, 2003). From this point of
Greene & Haidt, 2002) and some of its crit- view, moral emotions per se might be said to
ics (e.g., Huebner, Dwyer, & Hauser, 2009; be outright dangerous to valid moral deci-
Monin, Pizarro, & Beer, 2007). Much of this sion making because they accept prejudicial,
debate is still being worked out empirically, incidental influence from unrelated factors.
but it is clear to me that the vagueness of the Although nonemotional judgments are also
terms emotion, affect, and passion needs to subject to carryover effects from context, a
be sharpened if we are to continue it produc- particular feature of emotions is that they
tively (Giner-Sorolla, 1999). Clearly, there create their own motivation and reality. In
can be no moral considerations without a both self-deception and self-presentation,
basic sense of value, of good or bad, a simple moral reasons for having an emotion are
level of evaluation sometimes labeled as af- the most acceptable, morality being the pre-
fect. However, most uses of this term imply dominant attribute when judging persons,
something deeper, a subjective sense of mo- oneself, and groups (Ellemers & van den
tivation and importance that is not necessar- Bos, 2012; Wojciszke, 2005). The danger in
ily arousal, for both the lethargy of sadness moral emotions, then, is not that they exist,
and the excitation of anger can compel us. but that emotions activated by selfish con-
In previous writing (Giner-Sorolla, 2012), cerns can be given a veneer of moral reasons.
I have waved away the question of whether The honesty of emotion, backed by its un-
any given state is an emotion by advocating controllability, does not, however, extend to
the term emotional to apply to this combina- a guarantee of its truly moral nature.
tion of valence and importance. I am not so
sure about this usage now, because it seems
an emotion is also more than a motivation. Theoretical Stance
Emotions, or components of them, have the
tendency to linger on and affect subsequent Theories of moral emotions per se are actu-
states. They have expressive elements, too. ally few in social psychology, although there
From this point of view, moral judgment have been schemes distinguishing pairs or
needs only the simple valence judgment, as triads of moral emotions internally, such as
when one judges a hypothetical act as right the ideas of Tangney (Tangney & Dearing,
or wrong. Moral action that is persistent 2002) and many others on the difference
and motivated to overcome self-interests between guilt and shame, and various ideas
and other obstacles, however, I would think about what distinguishes anger from disgust
needs to be facilitated by feeling a sense and (sometimes) from the Contempt/Anger/
of relevance. And beyond mere motiva- Disgust (CAD) triad (Russell & Giner-­
tion, moral emotions contribute the ability Sorolla, 2013). I believe that the theory I
to communicate this sincere motivation to offer in Giner-Sorolla (2012) is the only spe-
other people, and to facilitate. cific general theory of the morally relevant
Finally, although it may not stand up as nature of emotions, although there have
part of the formal definition of an emotion, been taxonomies of moral emotions (Haidt,
 A Functional Conflict Theory of Moral Emotions 85

2003) and general statements of emotional- Evidence


ism (Haidt, 2001).
One idea that has been very influential Mainly, the evidence supporting my theory
on my theory is the social–functional emo- has been collected as support for the four in-
tions theory of Keltner and Haidt (1999). dividual perspectives that it integrates, and
This opened my eyes to the possibility that, an account of the state of these literatures as
unlike the usual claims of “one appraisal = of a few years ago can be found in Chapter 2
one emotion” prevalent at the time, categori- of Giner-Sorolla (2012). But more than stat-
cal emotions can arise from more than one ing that these functions coexist and promot-
input and serve more than one function. A ing a distal just-so explanation to integrate
main difference is that Keltner and Haidt them, this theory does present a number of
base their differing functions on analyses of falsifiable statements that can in principle be
different levels of social organization, from tested.
individual to cultural; they do not integrate Perhaps the most testable claim I propose
multiple emotion theories as I do. This is ac- is that the same construct of emotion serves
tually a complementary perspective that, if all four functions. One could easily conceive
included, would lead to a truly complicated of a rival argument that the four functions
two-dimensional categorization in which are served by modular, independent psy-
individuals consider the four functions on chological and physiological structures. To
four different levels of social organization— give just one example of an adversarial test
so that people can appraise national as well of these ideas, my theory would state that
as individual concerns, for example, or com- communicative aspects of emotions are acti-
municate emotions about family concerns to vated by the other functions, such that facial
a family. expressions and other expressive elements
Other than that, my functional theory is occur even when a person does not think he
fairly independent of other controversies in or she is being observed. This would be falsi-
moral psychology, such as how many indi- fied strongly by evidence that there is no fa-
vidual principles govern moral judgment cial communication in nonsocial situations
(Cameron, Lindquist, & Gray, 2015; Gra- (or that the facial grimaces produced in such
ham, Haidt, & Nosek, 2009; Kugler, Jost, & situations have some other purpose, such as
Noorbaloochi, 2014). Even if it could be con- embodying feedback or regulating air flow,
clusively shown that there is only one basis e.g., facial feedback hypotheses; McIntosh,
of moral judgment, the different emotion 1996); and challenged more weakly by evi-
experiences could underpin different ways dence that expressive elements of emotion
of perceiving and communicating this moral come forth much more strongly in social
material. For example, shame could repre- than nonsocial situations. Likewise, the
sent a way of dealing with one’s own moral theory would be falsified to some degree by
failures that is character-focused, while guilt evidence that associative activation of a par-
is more situation-focused (e.g. Tracy & Rob- ticular emotion from memory differs in its
ins, 2006). The attempt to map specific emo- effects and output from creation of “fresh”
tions onto specific moral or immoral acts, emotions through new appraisal of experi-
although it has some support, is not the only ence.
factor feeding into the experience of feelings
in morally relevant situations. The relevance
of acts to appraising moral character (Giner- Extension and Expansion
Sorolla & Chapman, 2016) and the utility
of emotion expressions according to differ- The theory generates a number of implica-
ent social goals (Kupfer & Giner-Sorolla, tions, the most important of which being
2016), for example, bear on which of two that emotions are neither to be celebrated
linked emotions (anger vs. disgust) predomi- nor despised as inputs to moral decision
nates, even when the acts in question violate making. With this comes the suggestion that
the same underlying principle of moral judg- we can gain understanding of emotions by
ment, that is, direct harm to others. carefully considering in what way they are
86 M O R A L I T Y A N D F E E L I N G

functioning in the current moral situations. The complete second season [Television se-
For example, is your disgust at a criminal ries]. Culver City, CA: Sony Pictures Home
defendant really due to moral disapproval Entertainment.
or to his or her physical unattractiveness? Giner-Sorolla, R. (1999). Affect in attitude: Im-
mediate and deliberative perspectives. In S.
These functional considerations tie into Chaiken & Y. Trope (Eds.), Dual process the-
legal concepts of admissible and inadmis- ories in social psychology (pp. 441–461). New
sible evidence, into clinical considerations of York: Guilford Press.
self-deceptive and accurate knowledge, and Giner-Sorolla, R. (2012). Judging passions:
into the tug-of-war between certainty and Moral emotions in persons and groups. Hove,
open-mindedness that characterizes most UK: Psychology Press.
processes of persuasion. Giner-Sorolla, R., & Chapman, H. A. (2016). Be-
As for expanding the theory: Is this not yond purity: Moral disgust toward bad char-
complicated enough? In all seriousness, I acter. Psychological Science, 28(1), 80–91.
Gould, S. J. (2010). The panda’s thumb: More
have tried to provide a comprehensive the-
reflections in natural history. New York: Nor-
ory of moral emotions, and I think the next ton.
step is not to further accessorize it but to get Graham, J., Haidt, J., & Nosek, B. A. (2009).
more solid evidence for some of the large- Liberals and conservatives rely on different
scale implications, as outlined herein. sets of moral foundations. Journal of Person-
ality and Social Psychology, 96(5), 1029.
Greene, J., & Haidt, J. (2002). How (and where)
REFERENCES does moral judgment work? Trends in Cogni-
tive Sciences, 6(12), 517–523.
Arnold, M. B. (1960). Emotion and personality. Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional dog and its ra-
New York: Columbia University Press. tional tail: A social intuitionist approach
Baumeister, R. F., Vohs, K. D., DeWall, C. N., to moral judgment. Psychological Review,
& Zhang, L. (2007). How emotion shapes be- 108(4), 814–834.
havior: Feedback, anticipation, and reflection, Haidt, J. (2003). The moral emotions. In R.
rather than direct causation. Personality and J. Davidson, K. R. Sherer, & H. H. Gold-
Social Psychology Review, 11(2), 167–203. smith (Eds.), Handbook of affective sciences
Bloom, P. (2016). Against empathy: The case for (pp. 852–870). New York: Oxford University
rational compassion. New York: Ecco. Press.
Cameron, C. D., Lindquist, K. A., & Gray, K. Higgins, E. T. (1987). Self-discrepancy: A theory
(2015). A constructionist review of morality relating self and affect. Psychological Review,
and emotions: No evidence for specific links 94(3), 319–340.
between moral content and discrete emotions. Huebner, B., Dwyer, S., & Hauser, M. (2009).
Personality and Social Psychology Review, The role of emotion in moral psychology.
19(4), 371–394. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 13(1), 1–6.
Carver, C. S., Lawrence, J. W., & Scheier, M. Keltner, D., & Haidt, J. (1999). Social functions
F. (1996). A control-process perspective on of emotions at four levels of analysis. Cogni-
the origins of affect. In L. L. Martin & A. tion and Emotion, 13(5), 505–521.
Tesser (Eds.), Striving and feeling: Interac- Kugler, M., Jost, J. T., & Noorbaloochi, S.
tions among goals, affect, and self-regulation (2014). Another look at moral foundations
(pp. 11–52). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. theory: Do authoritarianism and social domi-
Ellemers, N., & van den Bos, K. (2012). Morality nance orientation explain liberal–conservative
in groups: On the social-regulatory functions differences in “moral” intuitions? Social Jus-
of right and wrong. Social and Personality tice Research, 27(4), 413–431.
Psychology Compass, 6(12), 878–889. Kupfer, T. R., & Giner-Sorolla, R. (2016). Com-
Frank, R. H. (1988). Passions within reason: The municating moral motives: The social signal-
strategic role of the emotions. New York: Nor- ing function of disgust. Social Psychological
ton. and Personality Science. [Epub ahead of print]
Freud, S. (2008). The interpretation of dreams Kuppens, P., Mechelen, I. V., Smits, D. J. M.,
(R. Robertson, Ed.; J. Crick, Trans.). Oxford, & Boeck, P. D. (2003). The appraisal basis of
UK: Oxford University Press. (Original work anger: Specificity, necessity and sufficiency of
published 1900) components. Emotion, 3(3), 254–269.
Gilligan, V., Moore, K., Porter, D., Cranston, Lazarus, R. S. (1991). Progress on a cognitive–
B., Gunn, A., Mitte, R. J., . . . Sony Pictures motivational–relational theory of emotion.
Home Entertainment. (2010). Breaking bad: American Psychologist, 46(8), 819–834.
 A Functional Conflict Theory of Moral Emotions 87

Lazarus, R. S., & Folkman, S. (1984). Stress, ap- of emotion: A structural theory. In P. Shaver
praisal, and coping. New York: Springer. (Ed.), Review of personality and social psy-
Maio, G. R., & Olson, J. M. (1998). Values as chology (Vol. 5, pp. 11–36). Beverly Hills, CA:
truisms: Evidence and implications. Journal of SAGE.
Personality and Social Psychology, 74(2), 294. Russell, P. S., & Giner-Sorolla, R. (2013). Bodily
McIntosh, D. N. (1996). Facial feedback hypoth- moral disgust: What it is, how it is different
eses: Evidence, implications, and directions. from anger, and why it is an unreasoned emo-
Motivation and Emotion, 20(2), 121–147. tion. Psychological Bulletin, 139(2), 328.
Monin, B., Pizarro, D. A., & Beer, J. S. (2007). Smith, C. A., & Ellsworth, P. C. (1985). Patterns
Deciding versus reacting: Conceptions of of cognitive appraisal in emotion. Journal
moral judgment and the reason–affect debate. of Personality and Social Psychology, 48(4),
Review of General Psychology, 11(2), 99–111. 813–838.
Moors, A., Ellsworth, P. C., Scherer, K. R., & Tangney, J. P., & Dearing, R. L. (2002). Shame
Frijda, N. H. (2013). Appraisal theories of and guilt. New York: Guilford Press.
emotion: State of the art and future develop- Totterdell, P., Hershcovis, M. S., Niven, K.,
ment. Emotion Review, 5(2), 119–124. Reich, T. C., & Stride, C. (2012). Can em-
Nichols, S. (2004). Sentimental rules: On the ployees be emotionally drained by witnessing
natural foundations of moral judgment. Ox- unpleasant interactions between coworkers?:
ford, UK: Oxford University Press. A diary study of induced emotion regulation.
Nussbaum, M. C. (2004). Hiding from human- Work and Stress, 26(2), 112–129.
ity: Disgust, shame, and the law. Princeton, Tracy, J. L., & Robins, R. W. (2006). Appraisal
NJ: Princeton University Press. antecedents of shame and guilt: Support for a
Ortony, A., Clore, G. L., & Collins, A. (1990). theoretical model. Personality and Social Psy-
The cognitive structure of emotions. Cam- chology Bulletin, 32(10), 1339–1351.
bridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Van Kleef, G. A. (2009). How emotions regulate
Parkinson, B., Fischer, A. H., & Manstead, A. social life: The emotions as social information
S. R. (2004). Emotions in social life: Cultur- (EASI) model. Current Directions in Psycho-
al, group and interpersonal processes. New logical Science, 18(3), 184–188.
York: Taylor & Francis. Weiner, B. (1985). An attributional theory of
Parkinson, B., & Manstead, A. S. R. (2015). achievement motivation and emotion. Psycho-
Current emotion research in social psychol- logical Review, 92(4), 548–573.
ogy: Thinking about emotions and other peo- Wojciszke, B. (2005). Morality and competence
ple. Emotion Review, 7(4), 371–380. in person- and self-perception. European Re-
Roseman, I. J. (1984). Cognitive determinants view of Social Psychology, 16, 155–188.
C H A P T E R 10

Getting Emotions Right


in Moral Psychology

Piercarlo Valdesolo

How can moral psychology use more nuanced and developed


theories of emotion to inform its process models?

Close attention to how modern affective science has divided the


landscape of emotions can not only help more accurately map the
moral domain, but also help solve current theoretical debates.

Over the past two decades, theorists have ist” (Barrett, 2006; Clore & Ortony, 2013;
begun to emphasize the importance of emo- Cunningham, Dunfield, & Stillman, 2013;
tion to moral judgment. But moral psychol- Lindquist, 2013; Russell, 2003) and “basic”
ogy continues to be in need of more nuanced (Ekman & Cordaro, 2011; Izard, 2011;
and developed theories of emotion to inform Keltner, Haidt, & Shiota, 2006; Leven-
its process models. This chapter argues that son, 2011; Panksepp & Watt, 2011) theo-
(1) as models of moral judgment afford in- ries of emotion has crept into debates over
creasingly prominent roles to emotion, any taxonomies of moral concerns (Cameron,
attempt at mapping the moral domain re- Lindquist, & Gray, 2015; Graham et al.,
quires closer attention to the state of cut- 2013; Gray, Young, & Waytz, 2012). Argu-
ting-edge affective science and (2) in doing ments as to whether emotions are best de-
so, theorists will be able to learn from some scribed as distinct causal mechanisms that
of the problems associated with dominant demonstrate consistent and specific relation-
competing theories of emotion and avoid ships with outputs (e.g., innate and universal
co-opting them into competing theories of affect programs for disgust, anger, fear) or
what best defines morality. I highlight one as arising from more general combinatorial
way in which this may be happening in cur- processes (e.g., core affect and conceptual
rent popular theories of morality and adopt knowledge) have been adapted to argue for
a particular critique from affective science mapping morality as either specific cor-
to offer a potential theoretical resolution. respondences between moral content and
Specifically, this chapter focuses on how psychological experiences (e.g., innate and
the modern debate between “construction- universal responses to violations of purity

88
 Getting Emotions Right 89

or loyalty) or as involving a combination of role of affect. In the social intuitionist model


more elemental affective responses and con- (SIM), Haidt (2001) offered the following
ceptual knowledge relevant to moral con- account of a moral intuition:
cerns (e.g., core affect and knowledge about
dyadic harm). . . . can be defined as the sudden appearance in
In doing so, however, important linger- consciousness of a moral judgment, including
ing questions associated with these theories an affective valence (good–bad, like–dislike),
of emotion have also been borrowed. Most without any conscious awareness of having
gone through steps of searching, weighing evi-
crucially for this debate in moral psychology dence, or inferring a conclusion. . . . One sees
is the question of what version of basic emo- or hears about a social event and one instantly
tion theory (BET) moral psychologists are feels approval or disapproval. (p. 818)
adopting. Recent constructionist critiques
pose fatal problems for some versions of BET Similarly, the affective route in Greene’s
(Lindquist, Wager, Kober, Bliss-Moreau, & dual-process model is defined by an intui-
Barrett, 2012) but are only questionably rel- tive good–bad or like–dislike feeling state.
evant to others (cf. Scarantino & Griffiths, Throughout much of the research that built
2011; Scarantino, 2012a, 2012b). Therefore, upon these theories, it remained unclear
the viability of categorical approaches to how emotional states beyond mere valence
mapping the moral domain rests at least in might influence moral judgments and what
part on where their allegiances lie in affec- theories of emotion the researchers might be
tive science. adopting.
This chapter argues for more specific- Other models of morality have posited
ity on the part of moral psychologists on more specific relationships between the
both sides of this debate. Those adopting kinds of eliciting situations people encoun-
the theoretical approach of basic emotion ter, the discrete emotions they experience,
theory to argue for pluralist models ought and the moral judgments they subsequently
to be clearer on the version of BET to which make (Graham et al., 2013; Horberg, Oveis,
they subscribe, and those adopting a con-
Keltner, & Cohen, 2009; Russell & Giner-
structionist approach to argue for primitiv-
Sorolla, 2013; Rozin, Lowery, Imada, &
ist models ought to acknowledge the current
Haidt, 1999). These theories argue that
limitations of their critique to only certain
discrete emotional states are preferentially
versions of moral pluralism.
linked with specific categories of moral con-
cerns (e.g., anger with harm, disgust with
purity) and emphasize the specificity and
The Role of Emotions in Modern
consistency of this link.
Moral Psychology
These kinds of categorical approaches to
Although few theorists now cling to mod- linking moral concerns with emotional re-
els of morality that do not posit important sponses have been labeled whole-number
causal roles for emotions, the complexity accounts of morality (Cameron, Payne, &
with which these models define the relation- Doris, 2013), the most well known of which
ship between emotions and morality varies is moral foundations theory (MFT; Haidt &
substantially. Early theories were mostly Joseph, 2004; Graham, Haidt, & Nosek,
concerned with demonstrating simply that 2009; Graham et al., 2011; Graham et al.,
emotional processes are causally related to 2013). MFT was specifically developed as
moral judgments, and so were understand- an elaboration on the SIM. Graham et al.
ably vague as to precisely how this relation- (2013) offer the following explanation:
ship unfolded and as to the particular defini-
There is not just one moral intuition—a general
tion of emotion they adopted. For example, flash of “wrongness”—just as there is not one
the two articles largely credited for ushering taste receptor on the tongue whose output tells
in a surge of interest in the role of emotions us “delicious!” Rather, we posit that there are
in moral decision making (Greene, Som- a variety of rapid, automatic reactions to pat-
merville, Nystrom, Darley, & Cohen, 2001; terns in the social world. When we detect such
Haidt, 2001) seemed to focus solely on the patterns, moral modules fire, and a fully en-
90 M O R A L I T Y A N D F E E L I N G

culturated person has an affectively-­valenced dinated psychological responses to discrete


experience. Not just a feeling of ‘good!’ or moral concerns.
‘bad!’, but an experience with a more specific
‘flavor’ to it, such as ‘cruel!’, ‘unfair!’, ‘betray-
al!’, ‘subversive!’, or ‘sick!’ (pp. 109–110).
What Defines a Whole‑Number Approach?
But what theory of emotion takes you Cameron, Lindquist, and Gray (2015) de-
from the SIM, identifying the role of mere scribe whole-number accounts as positing
pleasure or displeasure at an eliciting situ- “a core number of evolved and encapsu-
ation, to MFT, in which the more specific lated mental mechanisms corresponding to
affective flavors such as compassion, anger, ‘foundational’ moral content . . . and ‘basic’
or disgust are linked to specific concerns emotions” (p. 372). This views MFT as pre-
such as harm and purity? Either implicitly or dicting an exclusive and local relationship
explicitly, these whole-number approaches between moral content and discrete emo-
ground their view of emotion in some ver- tions. Discrete emotions should be consis-
sion of BET. tently and specifically evoked by distinct
moral domains. For example, disgust should
be evoked for every instance of a purity vio-
Basic Emotions and Moral Foundations lation, and disgust should be evoked only for
instances of purity violations. This is what
MFT argues for the existence of moral foun- is meant by a one-to-one mapping between
dations composed of innate cognitive mech- psychological responses and moral founda-
anisms that are responsive to a set of par- tions. Importantly, this characterization
ticular adaptive concerns relevant to social implies that even if specific emotions are
living (e.g., protecting children, forming co- preferentially linked with moral foundations
alitions). These mechanisms are triggered by (e.g., purity corresponds with disgust more
particular social cues (e.g., distress, cheat- than with anger, and harm corresponds with
ing, uncleanliness), and in turn they trigger anger more than with disgust), this would
psychological responses, including char- still “contradict the fundamental assump-
acteristic emotional states, geared toward tions underlying whole number accounts”
motivating adaptive behavioral responses. (Cameron et al., p. 8). Such “softer” theories
In keeping with BET, these characteristic are dismissed as predicting an exclusivity
emotions represent distinct biological mech- that is “far from the exclusivity posited by
anisms thought to “prompt us in a direc- whole-number accounts” (p. 9).
tion that, in the course of our evolution, has In short, constructionists argue that
done better than other solutions in recurring whole-number frameworks by definition
circumstances” (Ekman & Cordaro, 2011, cannot explain any meaningful overlap
p. 364). between moral content and emotional re-
Critics of whole-number approaches to sponding. If harm and purity violations are
morality, however, have argued that it is pre- found to trigger both anger and disgust,
cisely this conceptual reliance on BET that even if there may be meaningful differences
is problematic (Cameron et al., 2013; Schein in effect sizes in the direction predicted by
& Gray, 2015; Gray & Keeney 2015a; Gray, whole-number theories, then such variabil-
Young, & Waytz, 2012; Cheng, Ottati, & ity must be treated as error and cannot be
Price, 2013). These researchers argue that in accommodated by the theory. Put simply,
adopting this theory of emotions, any theory “moral infractions are thought to activate
of distinct moral domains rests on an em- one moral concern and not others” (Schein
pirically untenable basis. Specifically, given & Gray, 2015, p. 1151).
that there is no good evidence showing that
discrete emotions reflect “affect programs”
or any other kind of consistent and coordi- Constructionism Defeats This
nated affective response specific to particu- Whole‑Number Approach
lar kinds of adaptive challenges, then there
will likely be no solid empirical basis for ac- On this characterization of MFT, construc-
cepting the existence of consistent and coor- tionists only need to demonstrate that some
 Getting Emotions Right 91

meaningful amount of within-domain vari- predominantly influences moral judgments


ability in emotional responding exists; that, about issues that express the associated con-
for example, “harm and purity . . . involve cern” (p. 239; emphasis added). Graham
substantial internal variability and large et al. (2013) describe moral foundations as
overlap with other kinds of moral content” adaptive modules but resist saying that this
(Cameron et al., 2015, p. 7). This has been entails a view of “fully encapsulated entities
the approach of the constructionist critique with fixed neural localizations” (p. 62). And
in emotion research, and it has largely been most recently, Graham (2015) acknowledges
successful in accumulating relevant evidence that “evidence for cognitive differences does
(Barrett, 2006; Barrett, Mesquita, Och- not preclude there also being similarities,
sner, & Gross, 2007; Kassam, Markey, and evidence for cognitive similarities does
Cherkassky, Loewenstein, & Just, 2013; not preclude there also being differences”
Lindquist, 2013; Lindquist et al., 2012). (p. 872).
Constructionist models, at their core, are These statements suggest that the theory
“inspired by the observation of variability allows for overlap in emotional responding
in emotional responding and the failure of to moral concerns and that it might not be
basic emotion approaches to account for this committed to the kind of one-to-one map-
variability” (Barrett, 2009, p. 1290). Simi- ping of traditional BET. But if this is the case,
larly, moral constructionists successfully would it indeed contradict the fundamental
adopt this rhetorical and empirical strategy assumptions involved in whole-number ac-
by amassing a substantial body of research counts? Constructionists certainly think so:
arguing against one-to-one mapping of “Cognitive modules are by definition op-
moral content and emotional responding posed to domain general processes that cut
(cf. Cameron et al., 2013; Cheng, Ottati, & across content” (Gray & Keeney, 2015b,
Price, 2013; Gray & Keeney, 2015a; Schein p. 875), and any whole-number account that
& Gray, 2015). Indeed, if whole-number ap- acknowledges meaningful variability must
proaches to morality are committed to theo- be “internally inconsistent” (2015b, p. 876).
retical assumptions predicting one-to-one On this account, the only theoretical
mapping, then their empirical prognosis is framework that can accommodate variabil-
grim, and they likely need revision. ity between moral content and emotional
responding is constructionism. But what are
the fundamental assumptions construction-
But Is This the Whole Number Approach ists take whole-number accounts to be mak-
Adopted by MFT? ing? And might constructionist critiques be
hasty in concluding that all whole-number
But of central importance to applying this accounts are bound by them?
critique to theories such as MFT is whether If so, there may be versions of whole-
whole-number models of morality are indeed number theories that can retain the central
of the sort that constructionists describe. theoretical commitments of a basic emo-
Whole-number approaches have not been tions approach, defined by an emphasis on
particularly clear on the extent to which the specific correspondences between moral
they adopt traditional BET as a theoretical content and emotional responding, even in
framework. At times, moral modules are the face of evidence of within-domain vari-
conceived of in similar ways to traditional ability. Such an approach to mapping the
BET—that is, as “little switches in the brains moral landscape would both acknowledge
of all animals,” triggered by specific moral the modern constructionist critique and still
inputs (Haidt, 2012, p. 123). But there is at predict meaningfully specific, consistent,
least some indication that the theory might and ontologically distinct cognitive mecha-
not entail the strong view constructionists nisms underlying moral domains and dis-
ascribe to it. Writing about the link between crete emotional responses.
the content of particular sociomoral con- A consideration of how modern affective
cerns and subsequent emotional responses, scientists have been attempting to reconcile
Horberg, Oveis, and Keltner (2011) write: constructionist and basic theories of emo-
“We therefore expect to observe domain tion can highlight a more productive path
specificity effects, wherein a distinct emotion forward for moral psychologists. I highlight
92 M O R A L I T Y A N D F E E L I N G

one such way in the remainder of this chap- sponses to characterize each kind of emotion,
ter. but they also assume that these responses are
caused by distinct emotion mechanisms. The
causal mechanism for anger is presumed re-
sponsible for the coordinated package or cor-
A Revised BET as a Foundation for MFT related set of features that constitute an anger
response. (Barrett, 2006, p. 31)
Constructionist critiques assume commit-
ment to what Scarantino has termed radical This same resistance drives construction-
locationism (2012c). Specifically, that is that ist critiques of morality: “harm and purity
“discrete emotions consistently and specifi- are not unique moral mechanisms” (Cam-
cally correspond to distinct brain regions. eron et al., 2015, p. 377). And a lack of
A brain region corresponds to an emotion evidence for these kinds of distinct causal
consistently just in case it shows increased mechanisms for emotions and moral do-
activation for every instance of that emo-
mains prompts constructionists toward the
tion, and specifically just in case it shows
primitivist conclusion: “that there are no
increased activation only for instances of
natural kinds of emotion/anger/fear/etc.,”
that emotion” (2012c, p. 161). And for
and, therefore, researchers should “search
good reason. These are precisely the kinds
for natural kinds at the level of primitive
of claims traditional basic emotion theo-
components of discrete emotions” (Scaran-
rists have made. Ekman and Cordero (2011)
tino, 2012a, p. 364). Constructionists see
argue that basic emotions are evolutionarily
whole-number categories as merely descrip-
shaped, biologically prewired, and psycho-
tively different but nonetheless unified by an
logically primitive responses that are elicited
underlying psychological mechanism (e.g.,
by automatic appraisals and generate auto-
concerns about harm) and warn against
matic and mandatory response patterns in
confusing “practically useful categories with
the brain.
ontologically distinct cognitive processes”
But the viability of a theory of basic emo-
tions, and therefore any theory of morality (Cameron et al., 2015, p. 377). For exam-
rooted in BET, need not be yoked to only this ple, just as ice and steam are descriptively
particular version of BET. Basic emotion ap- distinct but nonetheless unified by the same
proaches can come in different flavors, some underlying essence (water), distinctions be-
more vulnerable to constructionist critiques tween discrete emotions and moral domains
than others. And a revised BET, not com- may be practically useful, but they do not
mitted to radical locationism, might well reflect ontologically distinct processes and
provide a strong empirical basis for theories therefore do not qualify as natural kinds (cf.
positing ontologically distinct content–emo- Gray, Young, & Waytz, 2012, p. 102.).
tion links in moral psychology. Therefore, But this is an essentialist view of what
the viability of categorical approaches to constitutes a natural kind, and, at least ac-
morality rests at least in part on where their cording to some theorists, it may be well
allegiances lie in affective science. What suited for the chemical and physical sciences
might such a revised BET look like? And do but not necessarily the biological and so-
whole-number approaches in morality seem cial sciences (Boyd, 1999; Machery, 2005;
amenable to adopting such a revision? Samuels, 2009; Wilson, Barker, & Brigandt,
2007). The latter are best described by an
antiessentialist approach in which “variabil-
Essentialist versus Anti‑Essentialist ity among kind members is the norm, bor-
Assumptions in Whole‑Number Theories derline cases often emerge, and generaliza-
tions tend to be exception-ridden and only
When constructionists argue against radical locally valid” (Scarantino, 2012a, p. 365).
locationism, they are resisting the modeling Adopting an antiessentialist definition of
of discrete emotions as natural kinds: natural kinds renders the lack of evidence
for one-to-one mapping of emotions to un-
Natural kind models of emotion not only derlying mechanism, and moral content to
assume that there are distinct profiles of re- emotion, irrelevant to the question of the
 Getting Emotions Right 93

viability of all whole-number approaches Conclusion


to emotions or morality. On this approach,
there is no good reason for predicting exclu- As theories of moral psychology afford
sive and local causal mechanisms, either for greater causal roles to emotions, the need
discrete emotions or for moral domains. The to specify a theoretical framework for emo-
only criteria that need be demonstrated in tions has increased. This is particularly true
order to qualify as a natural kind are that for researchers interested in the question of
the categories in question have “demon- how to best scientifically define and search
strable explanatory and predictive value in for evidence of whole-number models of
their respective domains” (Scarantino & morality. The debate in modern affective
Griffiths, 2011, p. 451). This view allows science between constructionist and BET
whole-number theories to account for with- models can guide such a pursuit, not only by
in-category variability while still predicting providing insight into that state of empiri-
the existence of natural kinds that reflect cal support for such kinds of whole-number
domain-specific, as opposed to domain-gen- theories but also by recommending a way
eral, mechanisms. forward that avoids some of the conceptual
This reconceptualization also allows for ambiguities associated with advocating for
the existence of natural kinds at multiple one view or another.
levels of analysis. The essentialist commit- Whole-number advocates ought to be
ment of constructionists compels them to clearer on their fundamental assumptions
search for natural kinds solely at the level of and situate their theory with respect to cur-
“the most basic psychological descriptions rent models of emotion. If it is committed to
that cannot be further reduced to anything traditional BET and an essentialist view of
else mental” (Lindquist et al., 2012, p. 124). natural kinds, then the constructionist cri-
But antiessentialism allows for the existence tique applies, and MFT needs to be revised
of natural kinds at any level of analysis so in light of the compelling evidence from
long as they satisfy the criterion of predic- both affective science and moral psychol-
tive power. ogy against the kind of radical locationism
So important questions for moral psy- it would predict. However, if whole-number
chologists assessing the viability of whole- theories adopt a revised version of BET built
number theories become not whether moral on antiessentialist assumptions, then they
domains consistently and specifically ac- can predict a level of functional specializa-
tivate unique psychological responses; nor tion for domain-specific mechanisms that
whether perceptions of a more general con- does not involve radical locationism and al-
cern, such as harm (Gray, Schein & Ward, lows meaningful variability. On this account,
2014; Schein & Gray, 2015), superordinate finding significant overlap between different
all judgments of moral wrongness; nor what moral content and discrete emotions would
kind of process constitutes the true “es- not contradict the fundamental assumptions
sence” of morality (Gray, Young, & Waytz, underlying whole-number accounts. Indeed,
2012; Graham & Iyer, 2012). Rather, the it would be precisely the level of exclusivity
focus becomes solely whether categories of such accounts would expect. Most impor-
moral concerns can provide explanatory tant, clarifying this theoretical issue could
value above and beyond domain-general shift the focus of empirical research entirely
processes. Such categories can, in theory, toward testing this revised view of func-
be both practically useful and ontologically tional specialization, as opposed to arguing
distinct. Domains such as harm and purity against a framework that moral psycholo-
can both reflect unique moral mechanisms gists may not be adopting.
and demonstrate meaningful overlap with
other kinds of moral content. If this is the REFERENCES
kind of framework within which modern
whole-number theorists in morality operate, Barrett, L. (2006). Are emotions natural kinds?
then the constructionist critique can be ac- Perspectives on Psychological Science, 1(1),
commodated. 28–58.
94 M O R A L I T Y A N D F E E L I N G

Barrett, L. F. (2009). Variety is the spice of life: weird?: Scenario sampling bias raises ques-
A psychological construction approach to un- tions about the foundation of morality. Social
derstanding variability in emotion. Cognition Psychological and Personality Science, 6(8),
and Emotion, 23(7), 1284–1306. 859–868.
Barrett, L. F., Mesquita, B., Ochsner, K. N., & Gray, K., & Keeney, J. E. (2015b). Disconfirming
Gross, J. J. (2007). The experience of emotion. moral foundations theory on its own terms:
Annual Review of Psychology, 58, 373–403. Reply to Graham (2015). Social Psychological
Boyd, R. (1999). Homeostasis, species, and high- and Personality Science, 6(8), 874–877.
er taxa. In R. A. Wilson (Ed.), Species: New Gray, K., Schein, C., & Ward, A. F. (2014). The
interdisciplinary essays (pp. 141–185). Cam- myth of harmless wrongs in moral cognition:
bridge, MA: MIT Press. Automatic dyadic completion from sin to suf-
Cameron, C. D., Lindquist, K. A., & Gray, K. fering. Journal of Experimental Psychology:
(2015). A constructionist review of morality General, 143, 1600–1615.
and emotions: No evidence for specific links Gray, K., Young, L., & Waytz, A. (2012). Mind
between moral content and discrete emotions. perception is the essence of morality. Psycho-
Personality and Social Psychology Review, logical Inquiry, 23(2), 101–124.
19(4), 371–394. Greene, J. D., Sommerville, R. B., Nystrom, L.
Cameron, C. D., Payne, B. K., & Doris, J. M. E., Darley, J. M., & Cohen, J. D. (2001). An
(2013). Morality in high definition: Emotion fMRI investigation of emotional engagement
differentiation calibrates the influence of in- in moral judgment. Science, 293(5537), 2105–
cidental disgust on moral judgments. Journal 2108.
of Experimental Social Psychology, 49(4), Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional dog and its ra-
719–725. tional tail: A social intuitionist approach
Cheng, J. S., Ottati, V. C., & Price, E. D. (2013). to moral judgment. Psychological Review,
The arousal model of moral condemnation. 108(4), 814–834.
Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, Haidt, J. (2012). The righteous mind: Why good
49(6), 1012–1018. people are divided by politics and religion.
Clore, G. L., & Ortony, A. (2013). Psychological New York: Vintage.
construction in the OCC model of emotion. Haidt, J., & Joseph, C. (2004). Intuitive ethics:
Emotion Review, 5(4), 335–343. How innately prepared intuitions generate
Cunningham, W. A., Dunfield, K. A., & Still- culturally variable virtues. Daedalus, 133(4),
man, P. E. (2013). Emotional states from af- 55–66.
fective dynamics. Emotion Review, 5(4), Horberg, E. J., Oveis, C., & Keltner, D. (2011).
344–355. Emotions as moral amplifiers: An appraisal
Ekman, P., & Cordaro, D. (2011). What is meant tendency approach to the influences of distinct
by calling emotions basic. Emotion Review, emotions upon moral judgment. Emotion Re-
3(4), 364–370. view, 3(3), 237–244.
Graham, J. (2015). Explaining away differences Horberg, E. J., Oveis, C., Keltner, D., & Cohen,
in moral judgment: Comment on Gray & Kee- A. B. (2009). Disgust and the moralization of
ney (2015). Social Psychological and Person- purity. Journal of Personality and Social Psy-
ality Science, 6(8), 869–873. chology, 97(6), 963.
Graham, J., Haidt, J., Koleva, S., Motyl, M., Iyer, Izard, C. E. (2011). Forms and functions of emo-
R., Wojcik, S. P., & Ditto, P. H. (2013). Moral tions: Matters of emotion–cognition interac-
foundations theory: The pragmatic validity of tions. Emotion Review, 3(4), 371–378.
moral pluralism. Advances in Experimental Kassam, K. S., Markey, A. R., Cherkassky, V. L.,
Social Psychology, 47, 55–130. Loewenstein, G., & Just, M. A. (2013). Iden-
Graham, J., Haidt, J., & Nosek, B. A. (2009). tifying emotions on the basis of neural activa-
Liberals and conservatives rely on different tion. PLOS ONE, 8, 1–12.
sets of moral foundations. Journal of Person- Keltner, D., Haidt, J., & Shiota, L. (2006). So-
ality and Social Psychology, 96(5), 1029. cial functionalism and the evolution of emo-
Graham, J., & Iyer, R. (2012). The unbearable tions. In M. Schaller, D. Kenrick, & J. Simp-
vagueness of “essence”: Forty-four clarifica- son (Eds.), Evolution and social psychology
tion questions for Gray, Young, and Waytz. (pp. 115–142). New York: Psychology Press.
Psychological Inquiry, 23(2), 162–165. Levenson, R. W. (2011). Basic emotion questions.
Graham, J., Nosek, B. A., Haidt, J., Iyer, R., Kol- Emotion Review, 3(4), 379–386.
eva, S., & Ditto, P. H. (2011). Mapping the Lindquist, K. A. (2013). Emotions emerge from
moral domain. Journal of Personality and So- more basic psychological ingredients: A mod-
cial Psychology, 101(2), 366. ern psychological constructionist model. Emo-
Gray, K., & Keeney, J. (2015a). Impure, or just tion Review, 5(4), 356–368.
 Getting Emotions Right 95

Lindquist, K. A., Wager, T. D., Kober, H., Bliss- In M. Broome & L. Bortolotti (Eds.), Psychia-
Moreau, E., & Barrett, L. F. (2012). The brain try as cognitive neuroscience: Philosophical
basis of emotion: A meta-analytic review. Be- perspectives (pp. 49–82). Oxford, UK: Oxford
havioral and Brain Sciences, 35(3), 121–143. University Press.
Machery, E. (2005). Concepts are not a natural Scarantino, A. (2012a). How to define emotions
kind. Philosophy of Science, 72(3), 444–467. scientifically. Emotion Review, 4(4), 358–368.
Panksepp, J., & Watt, D. (2011). What is basic Scarantino, A. (2012b). Some further thoughts
about basic emotions?: Lasting lessons from on emotions and natural kinds. Emotion Re-
affective neuroscience. Emotion Review, 3(4), view, 4(4), 391–393.
387–396. Scarantino, A. (2012c). Functional specialization
Rozin, P., Lowery, L., Imada, S., & Haidt, J. does not require one-to-one mapping between
(1999). The CAD triad hypothesis: A map- brain regions and emotions. Behavioral and
ping between three moral emotions (contempt, Brain Sciences, 35(3), 161–162.
anger, disgust) and three moral codes (commu- Scarantino, A., & Griffiths, P. (2011). Don’t give
nity, autonomy, divinity). Journal of Personal- up on basic emotions. Emotion Review, 3(4),
ity and Social Psychology, 76(4), 574–586. 444–454.
Russell, J. A. (2003). Core affect and the psycho- Schein, C., & Gray, K. (2015). The unifying
logical construction of emotion. Psychological moral dyad: Liberals and conservatives share
Review, 110(1), 145–172. the same harm-based moral template. Person-
Russell, P. S., & Giner-Sorolla, R. (2013). Bodi- ality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 41(8),
ly moral disgust: What it is, how it is differ- 1147–1163.
ent from anger, and why it is an unreasoned Wilson, R. A., Barker, M. J., & Brigandt, I.
emotion. Psychological Bulletin, 139(2), 328– (2007). When traditional essentialism fails:
351. Biological natural kinds. Philosophical Top-
Samuels, R. (2009). Delusion as a natural kind. ics, 35, 189–215.
PART III
MORALITY, SOCIAL COGNITION,
AND IDENTITY

Q U E S T I O N S A N S W E R E D I N PA R T I I I

CHAPTER 11  What do people evaluate when they assess


another person’s moral character?

CHAPTER 12  What is the basis of moral cognition?

CHAPTER 13  What is the purpose of moral judgment?

CHAPTER 14  Is moral behavior the product of intuitive psychological


processes that can show both flexibility and cross-situational stability?

CHAPTER 15  What explains the deep connection between morality


and the folk concept of personal identity?

CHAPTER 16  What is the best way to characterize morality?

CHAPTER 17  Why are we comfortable with eating animals,


but uncomfortable with hurting them?
C H A P T E R 11

What Do We Evaluate
When We Evaluate Moral Character?

Erik G. Helzer
Clayton R. Critcher

What do people evaluate when they assess another person’s moral


character?

In this chapter, we define moral character in novel social cognitive


terms and offer empirical support for the idea that the central quali‑
ties of moral character are those deemed essential for social relation‑
ships.

The notion of moral character is central to acter evaluation is due to its function in so-
the way that people think about and evalu- cial life. Evaluation of character is, we think,
ate one another (Landy & Uhlmann, Chap- inherently a judgment about a person’s qual-
ter 13, this volume; Pizarro & Tannenbaum, ifications for being a solid long-term social
2011). People prioritize moral character investment. That is, people attempt to suss
traits when judging the overall favorability out moral character because they want to
of a person (Goodwin, Piazza, & Rozin, know whether a particular agent is the type
2014) and define personal identity largely in of person who likely possesses the necessary
terms of moral characteristics (Strohminger (even if not sufficient) qualities they expect
& Nichols, 2014). Moreover, assessments of in a social relationship. In developing these
moral character seem to be rooted in a shared ideas theoretically and empirically, we con-
social reality: People’s self-rated standing on sider what form moral character takes, dis-
a variety of moral character traits tends to cuss what this proposal suggests about how
be associated with the way that others view people may and do assess others’ moral char-
them (Cohen, Panter, Turan, Morse, & Kim, acter, and identify an assortment of qualities
2013), and different observers tend to agree that our perspective predicts will be central
with one another about a target’s character to moral character evaluation.
(Helzer et al., 2014). We begin by putting forward a new idea
We approach this chapter from the theo- of what we think moral character means,
retical standpoint that the centrality of char- rooted in a social-cognitive view of the per-

99
100 M O R A L I T Y, S O C I A L C O G N I T I O N , A N D I D E N T I T Y

son as a moral being. We introduce the idea John a bad guy if he does not tell the truth
that a person’s moral character takes the to his boss? Possibly, but to know for sure,
form of moral cognitive machinery—essen- most perceivers would want to know why
tially a processor that accepts inputs that, John lied. Even kicking a puppy or donat-
if the processor functions well, should out- ing an organ may be, with reflection, more
put morally relevant judgments and behav- properly characterized as saving a life or
ior. Because our perspective suggests that abusing a loved one, respectively, when one
moral judgment is ultimately an exercise in learns that the dog was being moved out of
evaluating character, we argue that many oncoming traffic or that the donor refused to
inputs that are assumed to change people’s honor the wishes of a suffering, terminally
moral thinking—even inputs that are not ill family member. Stated differently, if one
themselves moral in nature—should change does not know why others behaved as they
how people are judged for what morally rel- did, then in most circumstances one cannot
evant actions they take. We illustrate these properly characterize their actions. Indeed,
implications by drawing on our own recent a plethora of research on the use of inten-
empirical work that has investigated how tions, motives, desires, metadesires, beliefs,
people engage in moral character evalua- and other mental states in moral evaluation
tion—what we see as an exercise in identify- (Critcher, Inbar, & Pizarro, 2013; Fedotova,
ing whether a person possesses the “right” Fincher, Goodwin, & Rozin, 2011; Gray,
kind of moral-­cognitive machinery to pro- Young, & Waytz, 2012; Monroe & Reeder,
duce sound moral decisions. 2011; Pizarro, Uhlmann, & Salovey, 2003;
We next take on the question of content: Reeder, 2009) collectively highlights the idea
What are the more specific characteristics of that others’ inferred or stated mental con-
a person with good moral character? That tents provide the proper context in which to
is, instead of considering the abstract form evaluate the deeper meaning, and thus moral
that moral character may take, we ask what significance, of their actions.
qualities define moral character. In this sec- If outwardly observed behavior alone is
tion, we present several forms of preliminary insufficient for classifying most moral be-
evidence suggesting that moral qualities are haviors, it is all the more insufficient for
those that describe necessary conditions of evaluating character. Moral character re-
social investment. In so doing, we engage sides not in behaviors themselves, but in the
with two questions. First, we consider how person and his or her cross-temporal, cross-
our perspective is compatible with both situational proclivity to make morally rel-
moral pluralism and moral universalism— evant decisions in either upstanding or dis-
how moral codes may show variety and con- reputable ways. We propose that good moral
sistency across cultural contexts. Second, character can be thought of as a well-func-
we consider in what circumstances people tioning moral-cognitive processor, one that
should be more or less likely to assume that translates relevant inputs (e.g., situational
others’ character is more or less upstanding. cues, emotional impulses) into morally ap-
propriate outputs (judgment and behavior).
And by relevant, we do not mean cues that
A Social Cognition Conception normatively should influence one’s judgment
of Moral Character and behavior. Instead, we identify cues as
relevant if they are seen as likely to influence
In determining whether someone has good one’s moral thinking and thus provide infor-
moral character, the most intuitive place to mation about the soundness of the agent’s
start might be with outward behavior. Cer- processor. For example, if a woman donates
tain actions (e.g., kicking puppies, donat- to a cleft lip charity after seeing emotionally
ing an organ), in and of themselves, would evocative pictures of those with this birth
seem to offer a diagnostic view of the agent’s defect, we gain reassuring information that
character. However, in most cases, outward she responds in such uncomfortable situa-
behavior alone is insufficient for character tions with empathy and compassion instead
evaluation because such information fails to of by putting on her blinders, and this tells
fully characterize what an actor has done. Is us something favorable about her character.
 Moral Character 101

That said, the worthiness of donating to the commander must decide whether to order
charity certainly does not depend on wheth- an air strike against an al-Qaeda terrorist
er a donor has seen such pictures. cell, which would kill several top al-Qaeda
By analogy, consider what it means for a leaders and thwart an imminent 9/11-style
car to function properly. On the one hand, attack, but would also sacrifice one innocent
one could merely assess its “behavior”: Does person. In recent research, we (Critcher, Hel-
the car do the things that a “good” car does, zer, Tannenbaum, & Pizarro, 2017) asked
namely, travel from its origin to its intended people to assess the moral character of a
destination? But note that even a broken- commander who orders this strike or choos-
down jalopy may pass this test. The driver es not to under one of two conditions. In one
might want to get the car from the top of condition, the commander can see a terrorist
a mountain to a valley below. If this were leader through the window of the building
accomplished only by pushing the car over as he decides whether to strike. In the other
a ledge, we would hardly say this car was in condition, the commander can see the inno-
good working order (and most likely would cent person. On a strict act-based account
not be anytime soon). If the car’s outward of moral judgment, and according to several
“behavior” is insufficient, what might we normative ethical theories (including both
use to determine whether the car is a good, deontology and utilitarianism), the com-
safe investment? We know a car functions mander’s vantage point should be irrelevant
well when it responds appropriately to input to the evaluation of the commander’s actions
from the driver: a turn of the key, of the or character. That is, his vantage point does
wheel, or of the radio volume knob should not change his actions’ consonance with
have predictable consequences for the en- these ethical theories’ prescriptions. How-
gine, the car’s trajectory, and the stereo. If ever, we found that the commander’s point
those inputs do not prompt the relevant out- of view did matter: On average, people saw
puts, we say the car is broken. We would be him as having less praiseworthy character if
reluctant to ride in such a car, let alone pur- he ordered the strike with the innocent per-
chase it, and we would likely keep our loved son, rather than the terrorist, in view.
ones away, as well. The reason this seemingly irrelevant vari-
We argue that assessments of moral ation in context mattered to people’s judg-
character—the moral-cognitive machin- ments is that it revealed something about
ery inside a person that responds to influ- the goodness of the agent’s moral-cognitive
encing inputs with potentially appropriate machinery, its response to triggering inputs
outputs—operate similarly. Thus, in judg- with appropriate (or inappropriate) outputs.
ing others’ character, people want to know When the terrorist was in view, participants
whether agents attend to relevant cues, pro- assumed that utilitarian concerns about pre-
cess those cues appropriately, and arrive at venting future large-scale destruction would
their moral decisions in light of those cues in loom large in the commander’s mind. But
the way that a good moral decision maker— when the innocent translator loomed large
that is, one who has good moral-cognitive in the commander’s visual field, it was as-
machinery—would do. If moral judgment sumed that deontological prohibitions
is indeed in the service of determining who against taking life would weigh heavily on
is a good candidate for social investment, it his conscience. The commander was seen
makes sense that perceivers are concerned as possessing more praiseworthy character
not merely with an agent’s specific actions if he then acted on the thoughts that were
or motives, but with whether the agent can believed to be prompted by his context. The
be trusted to make sound moral decisions in contextual dependency we observed in this
light of the many inputs and contexts that he and other studies suggests that people were
or she may face. looking for evidence of a well-functioning
It follows, then, that moral judgments moral-cognitive machinery—one that re-
(serving as a read-off of perceived moral sponds to environmental inputs that are as-
character) should be sensitive to the dem- sumed to inspire morally relevant cognitions
onstrated link between inputs and outputs. with the matching behavioral outputs. In so
Consider the following scenario: A military doing, perceivers are observing moral char-
102 M O R A L I T Y, S O C I A L C O G N I T I O N , A N D I D E N T I T Y

acter that accelerates when the pedal is de- tion about what constitutes morality. That
pressed and that stops short when the brake is, to understand what traits define those
is slammed. with good and bad character, one must
stipulate the boundaries of morality. On the
one hand, some have balked at the notion
From General to Specific: What Defines that morality is a unified construct (Sinnott-
Moral Character? Armstrong & Wheatley, 2012; Stich, Chap-
ter 55, this volume). And, as such, it might
To say that agents have good moral charac- seem intractable to clearly delineate what
ter is to say their moral-cognitive machinery behavioral domains are or are not relevant
works soundly; it predictably translates in- to morality. On the other hand, if one takes
puts into morally appropriate outputs. But a functionalist approach to defining mo-
what qualities are people looking for when rality by answering what morality (and, in
they are assessing another’s moral charac- turn, moral character judgment) is for, the
ter? In moral psychologists’ quest to under- boundaries of what is and is not relevant to
stand what differentiates actions that people morality may come into sharper focus. Tak-
deem morally acceptable versus those con- ing such a functionalist approach, Haidt
sidered unacceptable, they have spent most and Kesebir (2010) argue that moral systems
of their efforts examining people’s reactions have the ultimate goal of keeping individu-
to moral dilemmas. Such dilemmas afford als’ immoral impulses in check so as to make
the opportunity to isolate various features of social systems function. But even those who
actions and examine their effects on result- have taken more of a micro approach on
ing moral judgments, providing a crisp pic- morality by considering what characterizes
ture of the features of action to which moral morally relevant behaviors have also con-
judgments are responsive. cluded that morality resides in one person’s
In this effort to locate the fine line be- relationship to another (see Rai, Chapter 24,
tween right and wrong, however, moral psy- this volume). For example, Gray et al. (2012)
chologists have not paid as much attention argue that moral infractions are understood
to more prototypical, everyday examples through a common schema, a dyadic tem-
of morality and immorality (cf. Hofmann, plate that involves an agentic wrongdoer
Wisneski, Brandt, & Skitka, 2014). This and a passive victim. Combining both per-
neglect poses a problem for applying our spectives, one understands morality as an
character-based perspective. Without more inherently social concern that offers norma-
clearly understanding the domains that are tive prescriptions for how people should and
more or less typical of lay conceptions of should not relate to one another.
morality, we do not know precisely what it is But even if morality’s broader purpose is
that people are trying to assess or comment social, many have been quick to note that not
on when they consider others’ moral charac- all (im)moral actions exist in social contexts
ter. To return to the car example, one might (e.g., Alicke, 2012). If so, it may call into
be comfortable investing long term in a car, question the degree to which moral charac-
even if it needs a new sound system, because ter is understood through a social lens. For
sound systems are inessential features (for example, urinating on a holy book, mastur-
most of us) and are thus only somewhat rel- bating with an American flag, or sprinkling
evant to the car’s overall value. Most would a former pet’s ashes over one’s meal are all
say a car still works even when the radio’s actions that strike many as immoral, even if
volume knob does not. However, the same the social victims are difficult to identify in
person would be reluctant to invest in a car such solitary activities. Although observing
with an engine that does not always start. In such victimless wrongs may still entail an
the same way, although a variety of qualities automatic identification of a victim (Gray,
or domains could be argued to be moral in Schein, & Ward, 2014), our character-based
nature, we consider which qualities are more perspective on morality suggests that the
or less essential to the definition. social victims need not be found directly in
The question of what qualities define the consequences of the actions. That is, we
good moral character is ultimately a ques- stress that moral evaluation is not merely in
 Moral Character 103

the service of prescribing and proscribing related to moral character and whether what
specific actions. Instead, it is a concern with differentiates such qualities is the degree to
identifying morally trustworthy and un- which they are socially essential in nature.
trustworthy people. As such, some actions In one study, we exposed 186 undergradu-
may be labeled as immoral not because they ates at the University of California, Berkeley,
directly victimize someone but because they to 40 positive personality traits. Participants
reflect a flawed moral-cognitive machinery rated all traits on several dimensions, two of
that is likely to bring harm to others in the which are relevant to our current interests.
future. In other words, we suspect that even They indicated to what extent each trait was
those who override the initial impulse to see morally relevant and how essential each trait
harm in victimless wrongs may be reluctant was by indicating their willingness to pursue
to place social trust in the perpetrators. Few a relationship with a person, even if he or
would see “Bible-urinater” as evaluatively she was not characterized by the trait. As ex-
neutral when it comes to selecting a babysit- pected, the two dimensions were extremely
ter (cf., Doris, 2002). It is for a similar rea- tightly correlated, r(38) = .87. A trait’s moral
son that attempted (but unrealized) harms connotation and social essentialism were
are morally vilified. A terrorist whose plot nearly one and the same.
was foiled may have caused no one any In another study, we experimentally ma-
harm, but the probability of his doing so in nipulated the perceived morality of traits.
the future is likely perceived to be relatively We identified 13 traits that were relatively
high. ambiguous in their moral connotation. For
Combining these character-focused and example, people differ in whether they think
social perspectives on morality, we argue reasonable is or is not indicative of some-
that what differentiates moral dimensions one’s moral character. We first presented
from other dimensions of personality—and people with 13 traits that were clearly moral
thus what people focus on in their assess- (e.g., honorable) or clearly nonmoral (e.g.,
ments of moral character—are those char- imaginative) and explicitly labeled the traits
acteristics deemed to be socially essential. as such. Participants then saw the 13 ambig-
Positive personality characteristics can uous traits, to which we gave the contrasting
range from those that are essential and non- label—moral for those who had first viewed
negotiable for long-term social investment the nonmoral traits and nonmoral for those
to those that are merely preferable or op- who had first viewed the moral traits. Fram-
tional. Although many of us would gravitate ing the same trait as moral prompted people
toward potential friends who are attractive, to see it as more socially essential than when
talented, or funny, we are willing to form it was framed as nonmoral.
close friendships even with those who do not In a third investigation, community par-
meet one or all of these criteria. These are ticipants were given 60 traits and asked to
pluses, but not musts. In contrast, most of rate how characteristic each was of someone
us would not be willing to invest in people they liked—that is, someone in whom they
who are callous, insulting, or conniving. would invest time and interpersonal resourc-
This is because people likely have thresh- es (Hartley et al., 2017). What was first nota-
olds for others’ compassion, empathy, and ble was that moral traits and corresponding
trustworthiness, below which they would immoral traits clustered at the top and bot-
rather abandon such relationships instead of tom of the list, respectively; traits that were
investing in them further. instead related to competence and affability
If it is the case that assessments of moral filled in the middle ranks. Looking more
character are determinations of whether a carefully at which moral traits tended to be
person is worthy of long-term social invest- at the top or bottom of the list, we gain a
ment, then our perspective suggests that clearer picture of what moral dimensions are
there should be a strong overlap between indeed most socially essential. Traits related
what traits are most moral and what traits to interpersonal trust (honesty, fairness,
are most socially essential. We describe three trusting) and interpersonal distrust (unfaith-
preliminary efforts to examine empirically ful, cruel) were at the top and bottom of the
what qualities are central, peripheral, or un- rankings, respectively. Other moral traits
104 M O R A L I T Y, S O C I A L C O G N I T I O N , A N D I D E N T I T Y

that did not relate to how people treat oth- which to consider a number of questions
ers but instead people’s more general disposi- in more detail. We discuss four here. First,
tions (e.g., grateful, wholesome) were more the socially essential account accommo-
middling in their perceived necessity. dates both universalism and pluralism in
This suggests that moral traits related to people’s moral codes. Although there is a
trustworthiness—a quality of those who core set of qualities that describe those who
can be counted on to behave in fair and make dependable social relationship part-
predictable ways—may be the most socially ners (e.g., trustworthiness, fairness), social
essential and, as such, most core to concep- groups may vary in how such qualities are
tions of moral character. If so, we might properly enacted. For example, although
expect to see evidence that people are par- most people will agree that fairness is a core
ticularly attuned to the trustworthiness of value to promote within societies, people
others. We see three distinct lines of work as may vary in whether they believe a respect
promoting this conclusion. First, trustwor- for authority or ability is the fair way to
thiness is a core component of one of two define social hierarchy. Of course, there is
primary dimensions underlying social cogni- also likely to be some variability in different
tion and person perception broadly (Fiske, cultures’ conceptions of what qualities are
Cuddy, & Glick, 2007). Second, people au- socially essential. One question for future
tomatically assess others’ trustworthiness research is whether there exists a relation-
from brief exposure to targets’ faces (Engell, ship—either positive or negative—between
Haxby, & Todorov, 2007), an efficiency the degree of cross-cultural variability in
that highlights the importance of such as- the perceived essentialness of a trait and the
sessments to social relations. Third, people likelihood that the trait is seen as essential in
reason quite efficiently when others fail to any given culture. For example, those from
display untrustworthy behavior—overcom- interdependent cultures may be more likely
ing the fundamental attribution error (Fein, to see pridefulness as socially dangerous and
1996) and the confirmation bias (Brown guilt-proneness as an encourager of social
& Moore, 2000)—leading some to posit harmony than are those from independent
an evolved cheater detection system (Cos- cultures (Mesquita, De Leersnyder, & Al-
mides & Tooby, 1992). In other words, ef- bert, 2014). Does the cultural variability
fectively identifying who is versus who is surrounding these prescriptions suggest that
not trustworthy may be sufficiently impor- prescriptive norms encouraging or discour-
tant to have been selected for evolutionarily. aging such traits are likely to be less strong
Of course, what form such trustworthiness than those governing moral universals? Or,
takes, whether its concrete instantiation is instead, in light of such cultural variability,
universal or culturally variable, and what are such qualities moralized more because
characterizes the circumstances in which they are diagnostic of one’s commitment to
breaking trust is acceptable (or even morally one’s ingroup and its norms?
advisable) is not answered by this perspec- Second, if the task of moral judgment is to
tive. But by understanding that trust is seen deduce whether a person has socially essen-
as a core feature of worthwhile social tar- tial traits, then qualities that are not them-
gets, it suggests that understanding the de- selves socially essential—but that signal the
tails of how we determine others’ trustwor- presence or absence of such essential prop-
thiness (as opposed to, say, their gratitude) erties—may become moralized as well. For
will give us a clearer picture of what contrib- example, although hedonism need not inter-
utes to assessments of moral character. fere with the quality of social relationships
(Schwartz, 2006) some people—­ especially
conservatives (Iyer, Koleva, Graham, Ditto,
Implications of and Questions Raised & Haidt, 2012)—pass moral judgment on
by the Present Account those who prioritize the pursuit of pleasure.
At first blush, this appears to be at odds with
Viewing moral judgment as an exercise in our account. But once one considers that
determining whether others have socially es- many hedonists actually are socially dis-
sential character traits offers a lens through agreeable—those identified by Ksendzova,
 Moral Character 105

Iyer, Hill, Wojcik, and Howell (2015) as Fourth, if people are interested in invest-
maladaptive hedonists—and that even those ing only in individuals who have sufficient-
hedonists who are not disagreeable tend to ly solid moral character, just how strong a
reject conservative, group-binding moral moral character is it necessary for them to
­ideals such as respect for authority and in- have? Note that one’s social interactions do
group loyalty, it becomes apparent that he- not merely involve other people; they also
donists are likely to lack a number of these involve oneself. Furthermore, the self pro-
qualities that many find socially essential. By vides a useful and omnipresent comparison
accepting that acts are judged on the basis of standard by which we make sense of oth-
what they imply about moral character, not ers (Dunning & Cohen, 1992; Dunning &
necessarily on the moral consequences that Hayes, 1996). People who do not donate to
they directly cause, it is easier to understand charity are likely to find a $150 check to the
why acts that merely signal the potential ab- American Cancer Society to be generous,
sence of socially essential personality charac- whereas those who give away 20% of their
teristics will themselves become moralized. income may be less impressed. Given that
Third, if good moral character is deemed self-views offer a natural context by which
essential for pursuing a relationship with to evaluate others, it is likely that judgments
someone but one does not know another’s of others’ social investment value will be de-
moral character before interacting with him termined by how their credentials compare
or her, then this would seem to offer up a to one’s own.
conundrum. Wouldn’t people be constantly The trick is that people often possess in-
discouraged from expanding their social flated, rather than accurate, perceptions of
networks if candidates for such expansion their own strengths and weaknesses (Critch-
are of unknown moral character? Of course, er, Helzer, & Dunning, 2010; Dunning,
there are steps that people can take to reduce 2005). Given that others are unlikely to stack
the risk inherent in wading into novel social up well against this aggrandized standard,
territory. People can find out others’ opin- the same psychological tactics that make
ions of a potential social investment or test people feel worthy in their own eyes may di-
them in smaller ways. But people must be minish their perceptions of others’ worthi-
motivated to explore new opportunities and ness. These self-enhancing views, writ large,
seek out this potentially reassuring informa- might lead people to unnecessarily dismiss
tion to begin with or decide whether to give others as having insufficient moral charac-
someone a chance when trusted social net- ter. But research suggests a moderator of self-
works cannot provide this information. enhancement that may alleviate such a ten-
One way out of this conundrum is to ap- dency. Alicke, Klotz, Breitenbecher, Yurak,
proach new individuals with an optimistic and Vredenburg (1995) first documented
outlook on their moral character (Critcher & that people compare themselves more hum-
Dunning, 2014). In recent work, people say bly against a specific individual (e.g., an un-
that they “assume the best” about certain known student seated nearby) than against
positive traits in others until such high hopes a population of others from which that indi-
are proven wrong. More important, people vidual was drawn (e.g., all students). So, al-
tend to endorse this strategy more for moral though the typical college student is likely to
traits than for nonmoral ones (Critcher & see herself as more studious than her peers,
Dunning, 2015). But when it comes to actu- she will not necessarily see herself as more
ally giving others the benefit of the doubt, it studious than any particular peer against
seems that people apply such hopeful expec- whom she compares herself. Furthermore,
tations when considering specific individuals people rate themselves more humbly when
but not when pondering humanity in gen- offering ratings of themselves and another
eral. This bias may be functional: Given that individual at the same time compared to
social relationships are pursued with individ- making those self and social judgments at
uals (instead of all of humanity), optimism different points in time (Critcher & Dun-
about their moral character may be a helpful ning, 2015). Highlighting how such humility
nudge in pushing one to at least preliminarily is functional in light of the socially essential
test out the goodness of a prospective friend. account, both tendencies were stronger for
106 M O R A L I T Y, S O C I A L C O G N I T I O N , A N D I D E N T I T Y

moral traits (Critcher & Dunning, 2014, Cosmides, L., & Tooby, J. (1992). Cognitive ad-
2015). In other words, people temper their aptations for social exchange. In J. H. Barkow,
own moral self-views so as to avoid preemp- L. Cosmides, & J. Tooby (Eds.), The adapted
tively dismissing specific individuals as un- mind: Evolutionary psychology and the gen-
eration of culture (pp. 163–228). Oxford, UK:
worthy of social investment. Oxford University Press.
Critcher, C. R., & Dunning, D. (2014). Thinking
about others vs. another: Three reasons judg-
Conclusions ments about collectives and individuals differ.
Social and Personality Psychology Compass,
Judgments of moral character provide rich 8, 687–698.
information about others’ likely reactions Critcher, C. R., & Dunning, D. (2015). When
and behaviors across a range of situations, and why I think I’m better than them, but not
ultimately informing decisions about wheth- him. Unpublished manuscript.
Critcher, C. R., Helzer, E. G., & Dunning, D.
er to invest in social relationships with them. (2010). Self-enhancement via redefinition: De-
In this chapter, we have brought forth empir- fining social concepts to ensure positive views
ical evidence in support of this functionalist of the self. In M. Alicke & C. Sedikides (Ed.),
view of moral evaluation and have reviewed Handbook of self-enhancement and self-pro-
recent research illuminating the process and tection (pp. 69–91). New York: Guilford Press.
focus of that search. We argue that moral Critcher, C. R., Helzer, E. G., Tannenbaum, D.,
character evaluation involves both a general & Pizarro, D. A. (2017). Moral evaluations
assessment of the soundness of a person’s depend upon mindreading moral occurrent
beliefs. Unpublished manuscript.
moral-cognitive machinery and a more spe-
Critcher, C. R., Inbar, Y., & Pizarro, D. A.
cific assessment of the appropriateness of (2013). How quick decisions illuminate moral
the outputs of that machinery. By appreciat- character. Social Psychological and Personal-
ing that the study of moral evaluation must ity Science, 4, 308–315.
move beyond the question of “What makes Doris, J. M. (2002). Lack of character: Personal-
acts moral or immoral?” to “What charac- ity and moral behavior. New York: Cambridge
terizes those of high or low moral charac- University Press.
ter?”, we expect that future research will be Dunning, D. (2005). Self-insight: Roadblocks
able to uncover additional strategies that so- and detours on the path to knowing thyself.
New York: Psychology Press.
cial perceivers use to determine whether oth-
Dunning, D., & Cohen, G. L. (1992). Egocentric
ers are morally good people and thus worthy definitions of traits and abilities in social judg-
of social investment. ment. Journal of Personality and Social Psy-
chology, 63, 341–355.
Dunning, D., & Hayes, A. F. (1996). Evidence
REFERENCES for egocentric comparison in social judgment.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
Alicke, M. D. (2012). Self-injuries, harmless 71, 213–229.
wrongdoing, and morality. Psychological In- Engell, A. E., Haxby, J. V., & Todorov, A. (2007).
quiry, 23, 125–128. Implicit trustworthiness decisions: Automatic
Alicke, M. D., Klotz, M. L., Breitenbecher, D. coding of face properties in the human amyg-
L., Yurak, T. J., & Vredenburg, D. S. (1995). dala. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 19,
Personal contact, individuation, and the bet- 1508–1519.
ter-than-average effect. Journal of Personality Fedotova, N. O., Fincher, K. M., Goodwin, G.
and Social Psychology, 68, 804–825. P., & Rozin, P. (2011). How much do thoughts
Brown, W. M., & Moore, C. (2000). Is prospec- count?: Preference for emotion versus principle
tive altruist-detection an evolved solution to in judgments of antisocial and prosocial be-
the adaptive problem of subtle cheating in havior. Emotion Review, 3, 316–317.
cooperative ventures?: Supportive evidence Fein, S. (1996). Effects of suspicion on attribu-
using the Wason selection task. Evolution and tional thinking and the correspondence bias.
Human Behavior, 21, 25–37. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
Cohen, T. R., Panter, A. T., Turan, N., Morse, 70, 1164–1184.
L., & Kim, Y. (2013). Agreement and similar- Fiske, S. T., Cuddy, A. J. C., & Glick, P. (2007).
ity in self–other perceptions of moral charac- Universal dimensions of social cognition:
ter. Journal of Research in Personality, 47, Warmth and competence. Trends in Cognitive
816–830. Science, 11, 77–83.
 Moral Character 107

Goodwin, G. P., Piazza, J., & Rozin, P. (2014). donist: The personality and ethics behind the
Moral character predominates in person per- value and maladaptive pursuit of pleasure.
ception and evaluation. Journal of Personality Personality and Individual Differences, 79,
and Social Psychology, 106, 148–168. 68–74.
Gray, K., Schein, C., & Ward, A. F. (2014). The Mesquita, B., Deleersnyder, J., & Albert, D.
myth of harmless wrongs in moral cognition: (2014). The cultural regulation of emotions.
Automatic dyadic completion from sin to suf- In J. J. Gross (Ed.), The handbook of emotion
fering. Journal of Experimental Psychology: regulation (2nd ed., pp. 284–301). New York:
General, 143, 1600–1615. Guilford Press.
Gray, K., Young, L., & Waytz, A. (2012). Mind Monroe, A. E., & Reeder, G. D. (2011). Motive-
perception is the essence of morality. Psycho- matching: Perceptions of intentionality for co-
logical Inquiry, 23, 101–124. erced action. Journal of Experimental Social
Haidt, J., & Kesebir, S. (2010). Morality. In S. Psychology, 47, 1255–1261.
Fiske, D. Gilbert, & G. Lindzey (Eds.), Hand- Pizarro, D. A., & Tannenbaum, D. (2011). Bring-
book of social psychology (5th ed., pp. 797– ing character back: How the motivation to
832). Hoboken, NJ: Wiley. evaluate character influences judgments of
Hartley, A. G., Furr, R. M., Helzer, E. G., Jaya- moral blame. In P. Shaver & M. Mikulincer
wickreme, E., Velasquez, K. R., & Fleeson, (Eds.), The social psychology of morality: Ex-
W. (2016). Morality’s centrality to liking, re- ploring the causes of good and evil (pp. 91–
specting, and understanding others. Social 108). Washington, DC: American Psychologi-
Psychological and Personality Science, 7(7), cal Association.
648–657. Pizarro, D. A., Uhlmann, E., & Salovey, P.
Helzer, E. G., Furr, R. M., Hawkins, A., Bar- (2003). Asymmetries in judgments of moral
ranti, M., Blackie, L. E. R., & Fleeson, W. blame and praise: The role of perceived meta-
(2014). Agreement on the perception of moral desires. Psychological Science, 14, 267–272.
character. Personality and Social Psychology Reeder, G. D. (2009). Mindreading and disposi-
Bulletin, 40, 1698–1710. tional inference: MIM revised and extended.
Hofmann, W., Wisneski, D. C., Brandt, M. J., & Psychological Inquiry, 20, 73–83.
Skitka, L. J. (2014). Morality in everyday life. Schwartz, S. H. (2006). Basic human values:
Science, 345, 1340–1343. Theory, measurement, and applications.
Iyer, R., Koleva, S., Graham, J., Ditto, P., & Haidt, French Review of Sociology, 47, 929–968.
J. (2012). Understanding libertarian morality: Sinnott-Armstrong, W., & Wheatley, T. (2012).
The psychological dispositions of self-identi- The disunity of morality and why it matters to
fied libertarians. PLOS ONE, 7, e42366. philosophy. The Monist, 95, 355–377.
Ksendzova, M., Iyer, R., Hill, G., Wojcik, S. P., Strohminger, N., & Nichols, S. (2014). The es-
& Howell, R. T. (2015). The portrait of a he- sential moral self. Cognition, 131, 159–171.
C H A P T E R 12

Moral Cognition and Its Basis


in Social Cognition and Social Regulation

John Voiklis
Bertram F. Malle

What is the basis of moral cognition?

Moral judgments are grounded in a number of cognitive and social


cognitive processes, which guide the social regulation of behav‑
ior and are, in turn, constrained by such regulation to be fair and
evidence-based.

Human beings live complex social lives, cial agents over antisocial agents (Hamlin,
composed of various types of relationships 2014), but socially mature moral capacities
across nested social hierarchies, all struc- rely heavily on nonmoral capacities: those
tured by rights, rules, and obligations. of social cognition (Guglielmo, Monroe, &
However, selfish goals persist, and keeping Malle, 2009).
individuals’ goals in line with community Social cognition encompasses a hierar-
interests has become the primary challenge chy of interdependent concepts, processes,
of modern morality. To meet this challenge, and skills that allow individuals to perceive,
human societies have developed two major understand, and—most important for the
social-cultural tools: a vast network of rules, present topic—evaluate one another. For
norms, and values (Sripada & Stich, 2006; example, norm enforcers infer the mental
Ullmann-Margalit, 1977) and complex so- processes that generated a transgressive
cial practices of norm enforcement, such as behavior (e.g., motive, belief, intention) be-
blame, praise, apology, and reconciliation fore blaming the transgressor (Malle, Gug-
(Semin & Manstead, 1983). lielmo, & Monroe, 2014). The transgressor
This kind of social-cultural morality must likewise infer the mental processes that
has to be taught, learned, and enforced by generated the social act of blaming (e.g.,
community members, even by the youngest the norm enforcer’s goals, knowledge, and
among them (Göckeritz, Schmidt, & Toma- power of enforcing sanctions) when decid-
sello, 2014). Acquiring norms likely benefits ing to deny or admit, maintain or correct the
from early-appearing preferences for proso- norm-violating behavior.

108
 Moral Cognition and Its Basis 109

These, then, are the phenomena this chap- Dichotomies often suffer from exaggera-
ter aims to illuminate. We show how the el- tions and simplifications. We hope to present
ements of social cognition ground people’s a framework that goes beyond extreme posi-
moral cognition and how social and moral tions and relies instead on theoretical analy-
cognition together guide the social regula- sis, existing empirical evidence, and predic-
tion of behavior by moral norms. We aim tions about new phenomena. We believe that
to identify the concepts, mechanisms, and drawing a line and designating two opposing
practices that go into making various kinds sides—reason versus passion, cognition ver-
of moral judgments and the forms and func- sus emotion, deliberation versus intuition—
tions of socially expressing those judgments. is an unproductive way to tackle a multifac-
eted phenomenon. We should, rather, survey
the landscape and acknowledge the complex
Historical Context terrain of social life so as to discover the dif-
ferent psychological adaptations and social
The most prominent debates in moral phi- practices that have allowed people to navi-
losophy grapple with dichotomies. Per- gate the terrain—imperfectly, but not in as
haps the oldest of these concerns the rela- bumbling and blundering a way as is some-
tive influences of reason and passion on times portrayed. What enables such adaptive
human behavior (Hume, 1751/1998; Kant, navigation, we try to show, is the interactive
1785/2012). Moral psychology, too, has system of moral cognition, social cognition,
been heavily influenced by this dichotomy. and social regulation.
During an early phase, scholars expressed This system is schematically illustrated in
great confidence in the human capacity to Figure 12.1, in which the parts both inform
reason about moral matters—albeit a ca- one another (e.g., mental state inferences
pacity that needs time to develop (Piaget, informing a blame judgment) and also jus-
1932; Kohlberg, 1981). During a later phase, tify one another (e.g., a wrongness judgment
scholars expressed sometimes fierce skepti- providing justification for an act of social
cism toward such reasoning capacities and regulation).
offered emphatic claims about the primacy Two aspects of this schematic deserve
of affect in moral judgment (Alicke, 2000; comment. First, when we use the term so-
Greene, 2008), about people’s inability to cial cognition, we are not pitching our tent
access the cognitive basis of their judgments on the “reason” side of a dichotomy but
(Nisbett & Wilson, 1977; Haidt, 2001), and rather conceiving of social cognition as a
about the many biases from which these large toolbox that contains both fast and
judgments suffer (Ditto, Pizarro, & Tannen- automatic mechanisms as well as slow and
baum, 2009). controlled mechanisms, both automatic and

FIGURE 12.1.  Schematic relationship between social cognition, moral cognition, and social regulation.
110 M O R A L I T Y, S O C I A L C O G N I T I O N , A N D I D E N T I T Y

both intuition and deliberation, both affect other to follow the instruction and may be
and thought. Second, whereas the relation- willing to enforce it through sanctions (Bic-
ship between social cognition and moral chieri, 2006; Brennan et al., 2013).
cognition has been discussed before (e.g., We can now conceptualize moral cogni-
Shaver, 1985; Weiner, 1995), the appeal to tion as the set of capacities that allow people
social regulatory mechanisms of morality to properly engage with social and moral
goes beyond the parameters of existing de- norms. People have to (1) learn, store, acti-
bates. Highlighting the social function of vate, and deploy norms; (2) make judgments
moral cognition can reveal much about how (e.g., of permissibility, wrongness, blame)
that process operates. We discuss both of about these norms; (3) make decisions in
these issues shortly. light of these norms; and (4) communicate
about the norms and their violations (e.g.,
prescribe, justify, apologize).1
Theoretical Framework
How Is Social Cognition Involved
To achieve the promised survey of the moral
in Moral Cognition?
landscape and to elucidate how moral cogni-
tion, social cognition, and social regulation What is social cognition? We endorse an in-
are related, we address three questions: (1) clusive definition that subsumes under the
What makes moral cognition moral?; (2) term all conceptual and cognitive tools that
What social cognitive processes are involved serve the overarching goal of making sense
in it?; and (3) How does moral cognition in- of other human agents. Figure 12.2 displays
teract with social regulation? many of these tools arranged in tree-like hi-
erarchy (for a glossary and detailed discus-
sion, see Malle, 2008, 2015). On the bot-
What Makes Moral Cognition Moral?
tom are those that have evolved earlier in
The moral domain is that of regulating indi- phylogeny, develop earlier in ontogeny, and
vidual behavior in the context of community are generally simpler and faster processes;
interests. Rules, norms, and values set the on the top are those that have evolved more
standards that, if fulfilled, serve community recently, develop later in childhood, and are
goals and allow the community and its in- generally more complex and slower pro-
dividuals to succeed. The broader literature cesses. The tools often rely on the output of
sometimes distinguishes moral from con- tools below them, and in concert these tools
ventional rules or moral from social norms perform important tasks in social life, such
(Brennan, Eriksson, Goodin, & Southwood, as explanation, prediction, and moral judg-
2013; Kohlberg, 1981). But for many pur- ment (depicted outside the tree itself). More-
poses, it is best to assume a continuum of over, several of the processes at once presup-
norms—defined as standards and instruc- pose and shape fundamental concepts, such
tions that guide people in what they should as intentionality, belief, desire, and emotion
do. We can then identify prototypes at each categories.
end. Moral norms, on one end, are part of Against this background it is now easy to
a hierarchy in which moral “principles” and illustrate how social cognition supports and
“values” are the most abstract instructions; interacts with the four capacities of moral
social-­conventional norms, at the other end, cognition.
can often stand alone in regulating just one In norm learning, social cognition con-
particular behavior or in solving a coordina- tributes some of the learning mechanisms:
tion problem. What the elements of this con- Mimicry and imitation provide powerful
tinuum have in common is that, in represent- tools of adopting norms through action,
ing an instruction as a norm (as opposed to a and face processing and goal identification
goal or habit), people keenly take into account allow people to read others’ evaluations of a
that (1) a sufficient number of individuals in given behavior and thereby infer the norms
the community in fact follow the instruction, that the behavior conformed to or violated.
and (2) a sufficient number of individuals in For example, a scowl toward somebody who
the community expect and demand of each asks a new acquaintance too many private
 Moral Cognition and Its Basis 111

FIGURE 12.2.  Broad conceptualization of social cognition as a tree-like, hierarchical collection of cog-
nitive tools.

questions can teach and enforce norms of Moral communication, finally, includes
privacy and autonomy. such phenomena as expressing moral judg-
Moral judgment would be impossible ments either to the alleged violator or to
without the basic tools of recognizing another community member (Dersley &
agents, parsing the behavior stream to iden- Wootton, 2000; Traverso, 2009); negotiat-
tify (un)intentional norm violations, as well ing blame through justification and excuses
as empathy (often with the victim), simula- (Antaki, 1994); and apology, compensation,
tion, and mental state inference to gauge the or forgiveness to repair social estrangement
agent’s specific reasons for committing the after a norm violation (McKenna, 2012;
violation. Moreover, social categorization Walker, 2006). People rely on mental state
can influence judgments through prejudice inferences during communicative interac-
(Eberhardt, Davies, Purdie-Vaughns, & tions, and especially during social–moral
Johnson, 2006) and also help assign specific interactions, to accurately assess the other’s
norms to people in particular roles, groups, goals and knowledge, because the stakes
and positions. Often overlooked is the fact of maintaining relationships are high and
that different moral judgments require dif- under the threat of sanctions. Trait infer-
ferent levels of social-cognitive involvement: ences may be formed through observation
Gauging the permissibility of an action is or gossip, especially when norm violators
largely a matter of analyzing an action cat- do not respond to social regulation attempts
egory relative to a norm system; the agent’s by their community. Also, low-level tools of
specific mental states are less important. gaze and face processing, empathy, and goal
Wrongness appears to be judged more on the inference are needed to gauge the honesty
basis of the agent’s mental state (Cushman, of justifications, the genuineness of apolo-
2008), whereas blame incorporates all these gies, and the seriousness of threatened sanc-
information inputs (Malle et al., 2014). tions.
Moral decisions and actions rely in part
on the tools of self-awareness, simulation
How Does Social Regulation Interact
of one’s own future guilt, empathy with po-
with Moral Cognition?
tential victims, and others’ moral sanctions.
Such decisions and actions also involve so- We claimed earlier that heeding the social
cial categorization of one’s roles and obli- regulatory function of moral cognition can
gations and accumulated trait inferences of benefit our understanding of how moral
one’s virtues (or lack thereof). cognition itself operates. We now illustrate
112 M O R A L I T Y, S O C I A L C O G N I T I O N , A N D I D E N T I T Y

one such benefit by reconsidering the debate fied, or preventable (Alicke, 2000; Knobe,
over how accurate or biased people are in 2010). Nevertheless, community members
forming moral judgments (Alicke, 2000; help correct these expressions of premature,
Ditto, 2009; Malle et al., 2014; Nadler & biased, or inaccurate moral judgments by
McDonnell, 2011). challenging those who blurt out allegations
The accuracy or bias of a given moral and by demanding warrant from those who
judgment is difficult to measure, because overblame, thereby calming and slowing the
the laboratory rarely offers an objective cri- processes of accusation and punishment. 2
terion for the correct judgment. Typically, Communities could not survive if their
researchers offer information to participants members blamed and punished one another
that they “should not” take into account, without evidence or without differentiating
and when some of them do, a “bias” is diag- between, say, mild and severe, intentional
nosed. For example, many researchers have and unintentional violations. The regula-
argued that outcome severity, the motives tory functions of moral judgment, and the
and character of the norm violator, or the required warrant for such judgments, there-
likeability of the victim must not be part of fore push those judgments to be more rea-
an unbiased moral judgment. But it is un- sonable, accurate, and fair, by the standards
clear who gets to decide, and on what basis, of the community in which they occur.3
what people should or should not take into
account (Malle et al., 2014; Nadler, 2012).
Relating Social Cognition, Moral Cognition,
Moreover, the potential arbiters, “philoso-
and Social Regulation
phers, legal theorists and psychologists”
(Alicke, 2008, p. 179), often do not agree We can now offer a more detailed schematic
with one another. of the relationships between social cogni-
In the absence of objective criteria, an ap- tion, moral cognition, and social regula-
pealing alternative is to consider a moral tion. In choosing the pictorial language of
judgment’s function of regulating social be- a flow diagram (Figure 12.3), we naturally
havior as a suitable standard—the socially leave out some complexity, but it forces us
shared criteria that people use to accept, to make explicit certain theoretical commit-
question, criticize, or reject moral judg- ments, which can be tested experimentally.
ments. For example, what do people accept The flow of processes begins with a nega-
as the grounds of intense blame? They con- tive event, which prompts the perceiver to
sider that the behavior violated an important assess whether the event was caused by an
norm, that the violation was intentional, agent who violated norms. If “yes,” social
that the agent had no justifying reasons to cognitive processes analyze the violator’s
perform the behavior, and so forth (Malle et mental states (including intentions and
al., 2014). When would people reject intense goals). This information feeds into moral
blame? They do so when the behavior vio- cognition, which generates judgments about
lated a merely insignificant norm, when the wrongness or blame. The outputs of moral
violation was unintentional and unavoidable and social cognition, along with preceding
but the norm enforcer treated it as if it were information about the event and the norms
intentional, and so forth. Bias is then diag- that were violated, feed into a decision about
nosed when norm enforcers overblame or whether public moral criticism is warranted.
underblame relative to what is acceptable in If warrant exceeds threshold, the perceiver
the community (Kim, Voiklis, Cusimano, & is likely to deliver public moral criticism
Malle, 2015). (though many other considerations may in-
These standards of blame put pressure on hibit criticism, such as role constraints, fear
people to keep their biases in check. Severe of retaliation, etc.). This moral criticism may
violations sometimes elicit powerful emo- prompt a timely change in the violator’s be-
tional responses that can lead to premature havior or, if not, the perceiver may consider
accusations or unfair punishment; further, renewed criticism or alternative responses,
an observer’s quick moral evaluation some- including gossip or retreat.
times taints subsequent inferences about The full stop with which we break off
whether the violation was intentional, justi- the flow diagram conceals a more complex,
 Moral Cognition and Its Basis 113

FIGURE 12.3.  Flow diagram of processes of social and moral cognition in the context of social regula-
tion of norm violations.

finely tuned social dynamic between norm goal-directed harm as less permissible and
enforcers and norm violators: They negoti- more often as wrong than they judge harm
ate levels of blame, meet accusation with as a side effect (Cushman & Young, 2011).
justification, criticism with remorse, re- Thus moral and legal distinctions overlap
morse with forgiveness, all in the service of with (and perhaps derive from) more general
rebuilding and maintaining social relation- purpose social cognitive judgments. This
ships (Walker, 2006). derivative relationship is corroborated by
results from functional magnetic resonance
imaging and lesion studies showing that the
Evidence processing involved in either social or moral
judgment activate many of the same regions
Empirical evidence for the social cognitive in the prefrontal cortex (Forbes & Grafman,
basis of moral judgment has been accumulat- 2010).
ing over the past several years. In many stud- People’s cognitive system also makes dis-
ies, lay people clearly rely on social cognitive tinctions between types of moral judgments
inferences of intentionality when judging ev- that vary by the objects they judge: Badness
eryday moral actions (Lagnado & Channon, judges mere events, wrongness judges inten-
2008) and when mastering fine distinctions tional actions, and blame judges an agent’s
between willingly, knowingly, intentionally, specific relationship to a norm violation,
and purposefully violating a norm (Gugliel- whether intentional or unintentional (Malle
mo & Malle, 2010)—distinctions that also et al., 2014; Monin, Pizarro, & Beer, 2007;
inform legal classifications of negligence Sher, 2006). These judgments also differ in
and recklessness. Likewise, lay people judge their sensitivity to causal and mental state in-
114 M O R A L I T Y, S O C I A L C O G N I T I O N , A N D I D E N T I T Y

formation (Cushman, 2008; Malle, Scheutz, rant. In a subsequent series of studies, we


Arnold, Voiklis, & Cusimano, 2015), but tested the hypothesis that people likely fol-
experiments on the detailed causal processes low “norms of blaming” when scaling the
that flow between social cognition and these intensity of moral criticism to the severity
differing judgments remain lacking. of transgressions (Kim et al., 2015). Indeed,
Experiments on social expressions of when judging the appropriateness of vari-
blame are also scarce. Nevertheless, initial ous levels of moral criticism in response to
work in our lab has demonstrated that, as a range of mild to severe transgressions,
with private judgments, people have a finely participants displayed a norm against “over-
tuned map of public acts of moral criticism blaming” (i.e., overly intense criticism for
(Voiklis, Cusimano, & Malle, 2014). For mild violations) but were more tolerant of
example, the rich vocabulary used by Eng- “underblaming.”
lish speakers to describe such acts—rang-
ing from chiding violators to lashing out at
Individual and Situational Variability in Social
them—do not merely represent linguistic
and Moral Cognition
variations but pick out systematic features
of the underlying moral judgment and of So far, we have addressed social and moral
the social context. When participants as- cognition at the level of cognitive system
sessed 28 acts (described by the most com- components that exist in all neurotypical
mon verbs of moral criticism) on numerous adults. Nevertheless, social cognitive per-
properties of judgment and context, the first formance can vary as a function of matu-
two dimensions of a principal components ration, neurological damage, and psycho-
analysis were intensity of expression and di- pathology (Frith & Frith, 2003) and can
rection of expression (toward the offender also be due to motivation (Klein & Hodges,
or toward others). Figure 12.4 depicts the 2001) and task difficulty (Birch & Bloom,
quadrants of this space and four verbs that 2007). Often these deficits are presented as
mark the prototypical acts in each quad- evidence that people are reflexively egocen-

FIGURE 12.4.  Four prototypes of public acts of moral criticism amidst variation of intensity of expres-
sion and direction of expression.
 Moral Cognition and Its Basis 115

tric in their perception of other minds (Lin, work, is in good part the result of gradual
Keysar, & Epley, 2010). An alternative inter- differentiation in social cognition (Baird &
pretation is that people are dispositionally Astington, 2004). For example, norm learn-
or situationally unprepared for attending to ing becomes more sophisticated as mental
the full range of social information. In fact, state inferences improve, and blame judg-
preliminary evidence suggests that “warm- ments become more sophisticated as the
ing up” social cognition with a practice task conceptual framework of mind grows. Spe-
facilitates spontaneously unbiased predic- cifically, as mental state concepts of belief
tions (in a mixed-motive game) and sponta- and desire mature by ages 4–5 (Wellman,
neously subtle assessments of intentions and 1990), outcome considerations in blame
intentionality (Knobe, 2003), especially for are balanced by mental state considerations
those scoring on the lower end of a social (Nelson-Le Gall, 1985). And as further dif-
cognitive performance measure (Voiklis, in ferentiations of the intentionality concept
preparation). So even though shallow pro- emerge (Baird & Moses, 2001), the distinc-
cessing and bias may predominate in states tion between justified and unjustified viola-
of disengagement, the correct situational tions and between preventable and unpre-
cues can bring most individuals to their full ventable outcomes emerge as well (Fincham,
social cognitive potential. Among these situ- 1982; Shaw & Sulzer, 1964).
ational cues, the community’s demand for
warrant in moral criticism (especially blame)
What Data Would Falsify Our Proposal?
must rank very high, but direct tests of this
hypothesis remain lacking. The strongest evidence against our proposal
There is, however, evidence for the mallea- would show that early moral evaluations
bility and the social shaping of moral reason- or emotions in response to norm violations
ing more generally. As with other forms of precede and swamp subsequent social cogni-
(public) reasoning (Crowell & Kuhn, 2012; tive processing (Alicke, 2000; Knobe, 2010),
Kuhn, Zillmer, Crowell, & Zavala, 2013), a reversal of what our framework suggests.
moral judgment can improve with practice Confirmation of this claim requires methods
and feedback. Much as habitual reliance on for assessing temporal and causal relations
heuristics (e.g., confirmation seeking) can between processes (millisecond by millisec-
be overcome with deliberate practice (Kuhn, ond), but such methods have yet to be intro-
2011), people might likewise overcome any duced into moral psychology. Furthermore,
habitual neglect of social cognitive informa- confirmation of this claim requires measur-
tion. Howe (1991), for example, showed in ing a perceiver’s affective responses after the
an experimental context that circuit judges perceiver recognizes an event as norm violat-
adjusted their blame judgments to mitigat- ing but before the perceiver determines the
ing information twice as strongly as students agent’s causal involvement, intentionality,
did. Applying one’s social cognitive abilities mental states, and so forth. Given the evi-
might also be a matter of mindset. When in- dence for very early and automatic process-
duced to believe in the malleability, as op- ing of agency and intentionality (Barrett,
posed to the fixedness, of empathy, people Todd, Miller, & Blythe, 2005; Decety, Mi-
appear more willing to expend empathic ef- chalska, & Kinzler, 2012), it would be diffi-
fort toward challenging targets (Schumann, cult, both theoretically and experimentally,
Zaki, & Dweck, 2014). Moreover, people to fit any kind of graded affect into this tight
with a malleable mindset appear to seek out early time window. Nevertheless, people are
these challenges in order to improve their likely to perceive some kind of preconceptu-
empathy; the challenge provides the learn- al badness before they process all the details
ing opportunity, and the motivation to learn of a norm-violating event. Arguably, such an
helps them meet that challenge. undifferentiated sense of badness does not
Beyond skill learning, the vast develop- represent a moral judgment (e.g., of blame),
mental literature on changes in moral judg- so arriving at such a judgment would require
ment and decision making support the claim additional social cognitive processing. If this
of malleability. Gradual differentiation in processing were systematically biased in
moral cognition, according to our frame- favor of confirming the initial negative as-
116 M O R A L I T Y, S O C I A L C O G N I T I O N , A N D I D E N T I T Y

sessment (Alicke, 2000), moral judgments the appropriate level of punishment). The
would still be fundamentally reliant on so- fine balance between these different forces
cial cognition—but on less accurate social may be examined with agent-based model-
cognition. ing methods (Elsenbroich & Gilbert, 2014).
A second major challenge to our proposal “Societies” that balance socially demanded
would be that social regulation of norm en- accuracy against socially demanded una-
forcement does not, as we propose, push so- nimity should be most successful because
cial (and moral) cognition toward systematic they keep the costs of false accusations and
information processing and accuracy. Evi- exaggerated punishment in check. However,
dence would have to show that the demand stratified societies in which some subgroups
for warrant of moral judgments can be easily have more power may shift these costs to the
satisfied by biased and inaccurate social cog- less powerful groups. The current incarcera-
nitive information. It would not be enough tion rates of minorities in the United States
to show that under some circumstances de- is an example of such a dynamic. As a coun-
mand for warrant is ineffective but, rather, terforce, however, recently increasing public
that widespread demand for warrant either scrutiny of aggressive policing of minorities
does not exist or, even if it exists as a social signals a renewed demand for warrant for
practice, does not predict quality of social social–moral blame and punishment.
and moral processing. Institutional mechanisms of regulation,
such as the state and the law, were long be-
lieved to be the dominant forms of regula-
Extension and Expansion tion. But evidence from the fields of anthro-
pology, psychology, sociology, and legal
Social Regulation of Moral Judgments
studies suggests that informal, interpersonal
Our hypothesis that social regulation is not moral regulation is evolutionarily and cul-
only the expression of moral judgment but turally old, arises developmentally early,
a mechanism that keeps moral judgments and is the predominant way, even today, of
honest has yet to be tested. A first require- keeping individual community members in
ment of testing it will be to design suitable line with collective interests. Referring back
experimental manipulations of community to our flow diagram (Figure 12.3), ordinary
members putting demands for warrant on social regulation sometimes fails; an entic-
a perceiver who is expressing a moral judg- ing research direction might be to examine
ment. A second requirement will be to devise when institutional mechanisms take over so-
reliable measures of accuracy in moral judg- cial regulation and when these mechanisms
ments and the perceiver’s systematic respon- are more effective than interpersonal ones.
siveness to evidence.
Our theoretical model predicts that the
Affect and Emotion as Social–Moral Signals
impact of demands for warrant varies by
moral judgment type. Permissibility judg- Although the exact causal roles of affect
ments are primarily reflections of shared and emotion in the information-processing
norms, so the presence of a community phase of moral cognition are still under de-
member should simply increase reliabil- bate, their involvement in public expressions
ity and collective agreement in these kinds of moral criticism may be more readily ap-
of judgments, whereas the more complex parent (Wolf, 2011). Affect intensity—in
blame judgments should become more de- words, face, and posture—scales such ex-
liberate and evidence-based (taking into ac- pressions (Voiklis et al., 2014) so that others
count intentionality, mental states, etc.) in recognize one’s degree of outrage (McGeer,
the presence of a community representative. 2012; de Melo, Carnevale, Read, & Gratch,
There is also a reverse prediction—that an 2014). These expressions signal how impor-
overwhelming need to be accepted by one’s tant the violated norm is to the blamer, teach
community can lead to more biased infor- young community members about such im-
mation processing if the community has portance rankings, and also communicate
strong expectations (e.g., about the guilt to norm violators what possible other sanc-
or innocence of a norm violator or about tions might follow if they show no insight or
 Moral Cognition and Its Basis 117

atonement. Evidence for this social function tentionality inferences in live interactions)
of moral emotions might come from physi- and moral capacities (e.g., recognizing norm
ological studies that show a ramping up of violations and forming evidence-based judg-
negative arousal from early violation detec- ments). In addition, research will need to
tion to late public expression. That is, the identify the conditions under which humans
very opportunity to express one’s judgment ascribe features such as intentionality, free
publicly may increase the involvement of af- will, or blame to artificial agents (Malle et
fect that was previously, during mere “in the al., 2015; Meltzoff, Brooks, Shon, & Rao,
head” judgments, quite modest. Additional 2010; Monroe, Dillon, & Malle, 2014), be-
support might come from evidence that cause such ascriptions fundamentally alter
perceivers have less differentiated emotions human–­ machine interactions. Integrating
when they cognitively form their moral judg- robots into research will enable a better un-
ments than when they publicly express them, derstanding of social and moral cognition,
because anticipating public scrutiny leads to and integrating robots into society will re-
more attentive information appraisals. Here, quire such understanding to achieve benefi-
too, perceivers’ perception of a community’s cial human–robot coexistence.
strong expectations may sometimes unduly
modulate their public judgments, such as of-
fering exaggerated expressions of outrage; Summary
this, in turn, can fuel even stronger expres-
sions by other community members and Returning from social cognitive science fic-
escalate collective moral condemnation be- tion, we close by recapping our theoretical
yond what perceivers felt in private. framework for understanding the processes
of moral cognition. We argue that a hierar-
Artificial Morality chy of social cognitive tools ground moral
cognition and that social and moral cogni-
Work on moral psychology has recently ex- tion together guide the social regulation of
panded into artificial morality—the study behavior. The practice of social–moral reg-
and design of computational models of ulation, in turn, puts pressure on commu-
moral competence (Mao & Gratch, 2012; nity members to engage in reasonably fair
Tomai & Forbus, 2008) and implementa- and evidence-based moral criticism. With
tion in social robots (Wallach & Allen, the help of these cognitive adaptations and
2008; Malle & Scheutz, 2014). Social ro- social practices, people are able to navigate
bots—embodied machines that are able to the terrain of morality, accruing bumps and
interact with humans—play an increasing bruises along the way but surviving as the
role in contemporary society. Around a
most sophisticated social creature currently
decade ago there were no robots in private
roaming the earth.
homes, whereas in 2014, 4.7 million service
robots for personal and domestic use were
sold worldwide (International Federation of ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
Robotics, 2015). These robots rarely pos-
ses extensive social cognitive capacities but We are grateful for the collective work and
are improving rapidly (Nourbakhsh, 2013), insights by all members of our lab (http://re-
and robots may soon function as social com- search.clps.brown.edu/SocCogSci/Personnel/
panions or assistants in health care, educa- personnel.html). This project was supported by
tion, security, and emergency response. In grants from the Office of Naval Research (Nos.
such applications, however, robots will need N00014-14-1-0144 and N00014-13-1-0269).
to have basic moral competence to ensure
physically and psychologically safe interac- NOTES
tions with humans (Malle & Scheutz, 2014).
Designing such robots offers appealing 1. Perhaps a helpful term for this set of capacities
new avenues for research, by testing more would be moral competence (Malle, 2016;
precise, formally specified models of both Malle & Scheutz, 2014). A complete render-
social cognitive capacities (e.g., making in- ing of this competence would include both
118 M O R A L I T Y, S O C I A L C O G N I T I O N , A N D I D E N T I T Y

positive and negative behaviors, but here we moral judgment derive from nonmoral psy-
focus, in keeping with the literature, on nega- chological representations. Cognitive Science,
tive behaviors. 35, 1052–1075.
2. These socially corrective strategies are not in- de Melo, C. M., Carnevale, P. J., Read, S. J.,
ventions of modern legal institutions; rather, & Gratch, J. (2014). Reading people’s minds
they are successful informal practices that from emotion expressions in interdependent
have persisted throughout history (Boehm, decision making. Journal of Personality and
1999; Pospisil, 1971). Social Psychology, 106, 73–88.
3. There are well-known limits to this shaping Decety, J., Michalska, K. J., & Kinzler, K. D.
process: For example, members of a given (2012). The contribution of emotion and cog-
group may demand fair and accurate norm nition to moral sensitivity: A neurodevelop-
enforcement for one another but not for mem- mental study. Cerebral Cortex, 22, 209–220.
bers of disliked or lower status outgroups. Dersley, I., & Wootton, A. (2000). Complaint
sequences within antagonistic argument. Re-
search on Language and Social Interaction,
REFERENCES 33, 375–406.
Ditto, P. H. (2009). Passion, reason, and necessi-
Alicke, M. D. (2000). Culpable control and the ty: A quantity-of-processing view of motivated
psychology of blame. Psychological Bulletin, reasoning. In T. Bayne & J. Fernández (Eds.),
126, 556–574. Delusion and self-deception: Affective and
Alicke, M. D. (2008). Blaming badly. Journal of motivational influences on belief formation.
Cognition and Culture, 8, 179–186. (pp. 23–53). New York: Psychology Press.
Antaki, C. (1994). Explaining and arguing: The Ditto, P. H., Pizarro, D. A., & Tannenbaum, D.
social organization of accounts. London: (2009). Motivated moral reasoning. In D. M.
SAGE. Bartels, C. W. Bauman, L. J. Skitka, & D. L.
Baird, J. A., & Astington, J. W. (2004). The role Medin (Eds.), Moral judgment and decision
of mental state understanding in the develop- making (pp. 307–338). San Diego, CA: Else-
ment of moral cognition and moral action. vier Academic Press.
New Directions for Child and Adolescent De- Eberhardt, J. L., Davies, P. G., Purdie-Vaughns,
velopment, 2004, 37–49. V. J., & Johnson, S. L. (2006). Looking death-
Baird, J. A., & Moses, L. J. (2001). Do pre- worthy: Perceived stereotypicality of black de-
schoolers appreciate that identical actions may fendants predicts capital-sentencing outcomes.
be motivated by different intentions? Journal Psychological Science, 17, 383–386.
of Cognition and Development, 2, 413–448. Elsenbroich, C., & Gilbert, G. N. (2014). Mod-
Barrett, H. C., Todd, P. M., Miller, G. F., & elling norms. Dordrecht, The Netherlands:
Blythe, P. W. (2005). Accurate judgments of Springer.
intention from motion cues alone: A cross-cul- Fincham, F. D. (1982). Moral judgment and the
tural study. Evolution and Human Behavior, development of causal schemes. European
26, 313–331. Journal of Social Psychology, 12, 47–61.
Bicchieri, C. (2006). The grammar of society: Forbes, C. E., & Grafman, J. (2010). The role of
The nature and dynamics of social norms. the human prefrontal cortex in social cogni-
New York: Cambridge University Press. tion and moral judgment. Annual Review of
Birch, S. A. J., & Bloom, P. (2007). The curse Neuroscience, 33, 299–324.
of knowledge in reasoning about false beliefs. Frith, U., & Frith, C. D. (2003). Development
Psychological Science, 18, 382–386. and neurophysiology of mentalizing. Philo-
Boehm, C. (1999). Hierarchy in the forest: The sophical Transactions of the Royal Society of
evolution of egalitarian behavior. Cambridge, London, Series B: Biological Sciences, 358,
MA: Harvard University Press. 459–473.
Brennan, G., Eriksson, L., Goodin, R. E., & Göckeritz, S., Schmidt, M. F. H., & Tomasello,
Southwood, N. (2013). Explaining norms. M. (2014). Young children’s creation and
New York: Oxford University Press. transmission of social norms. Cognitive De-
Crowell, A., & Kuhn, D. (2012). Developing dia- velopment, 30, 81–95.
logic argumentation skills: A 3-year interven- Greene, J. D. (2008). The secret joke of Kant’s
tion study. Journal of Cognition and Develop- soul. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral
ment, 15, 363–381. psychology: Vol. 3. The neuroscience of mo-
Cushman, F. (2008). Crime and punishment: rality: Emotion, brain disorders, and develop-
Distinguishing the roles of causal and inten- ment (pp. 35–80). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
tional analyses in moral judgment. Cognition, Guglielmo, S., & Malle, B. F. (2010). Can unin-
108, 353–380. tended side effects be intentional?: Resolving a
Cushman, F., & Young, L. (2011). Patterns of controversy over intentionality and morality.
 Moral Cognition and Its Basis 119

Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, Lagnado, D. A., & Channon, S. (2008). Judg-
36, 1635 –1647. ments of cause and blame: The effects of in-
Guglielmo, S., Monroe, A. E., & Malle, B. F. tentionality and foreseeability. Cognition,
(2009). At the heart of morality lies folk psy- 108, 754–770.
chology. Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal Lin, S., Keysar, B., & Epley, N. (2010). Reflex-
of Philosophy, 52, 449–466. ively mindblind: Using theory of mind to in-
Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional dog and its ra- terpret behavior requires effortful attention.
tional tail: A social intuitionist approach to Journal of Experimental Social Psychology,
moral judgment. Psychological Review, 108, 46, 551–556.
814–834. Malle, B. F. (2008). The fundamental tools, and
Hamlin, J. K. (2014). The origins of human mo- possibly universals, of social cognition. In R.
rality: Complex socio-moral evaluations by M. Sorrentino & S. Yamaguchi (Eds.), Hand-
preverbal infants. In J. Decety & Y. Christen book of motivation and cognition across cul-
(Eds.), New frontiers in social neuroscience tures (pp. 267–296). New York: Elsevier/Aca-
(Vol. 21, pp. 165–188). New York: Springer demic Press.
International. Malle, B. F. (2015). Social robots and the tree
Howe, E. S. (1991). Integration of mitigation, in- of social cognition. In Y. Nagai & S. Lohan
tention, and outcome damage information, by (Eds.), Proceedings of the Workshop “Cog-
students and circuit court judges. Journal of nition: A bridge between robotics and in-
Applied Social Psychology, 21, 875–895. teraction” at HRI’15, Portland, Oregon
Hume, D. (1998). An enquiry concerning the (pp. 13–14). Available at www.macs.hw.ac.
principles of morals (T. L. Beauchamp, Ed.). uk/~kl360/HRI2015W/proceedings.html.
Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. (Origi- Malle, B. F. (2016). Integrating robot ethics and
nal work published 1751) machine morality: The study and design of
International Federation of Robotics. (2015). moral competence in robots. Ethics and Infor-
World robotics: Service robots 2015. Frank- mation Technology, 18(4), 243–256.
furt, Germany: Author. Available at www.ifr. Malle, B. F., Guglielmo, S., & Monroe, A. E.
org/worldrobotics. (2014). A theory of blame. Psychological In-
Kant, I. (2012). Groundwork of the metaphys- quiry, 25, 147–186.
ics of morals (M. Gregor & J. Timmermann, Malle, B. F., & Scheutz, M. (2014). Moral
Trans.; rev. ed.). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge competence in social robots. Proceedings of
University Press. (Original work published the IEEE International Symposium on Eth-
1785) ics in Engineering, Science, and Technology
Kim, B., Voiklis, J., Cusimano, C., & Malle, B. (pp. 30–35). Chicago: Institute of Electrical
F. (2015, February). Norms of moral criticism: and Electronics Engineers.
Do people prohibit underblaming and over- Malle, B. F., Scheutz, M., Arnold, T., Voiklis, J.,
blaming? Poster presented at the annual meet- & Cusimano, C. (2015). Sacrifice one for the
ing of the Society of Personality and Social good of many?: People apply different moral
Psychology, Long Beach, CA. norms to human and robot agents. Proceed-
Klein, K. J. K., & Hodges, S. D. (2001). Gender ings of the Tenth Annual ACM/IEEE Inter-
differences, motivation, and empathic accu- national Conference on Human-Robot Inter-
racy: When it pays to understand. Personality action, HRI ‘15 (pp. 117–124). New York,:
and Social Psychology Bulletin, 27, 720–730. Association for Computing Machinery.
Knobe, J. (2003). Intentional action and side Mao, W., & Gratch, J. (2012). Modeling social
effects in ordinary language. Analysis, 63, causality and responsibility judgment in multi-
190–194. agent interactions. Journal of Artificial Intel-
Knobe, J. (2010). Person as scientist, person as ligence Research, 44, 223–273.
moralist. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 33, McGeer, V. (2012). Civilizing blame. In D. J.
315–329. Coates & N. A. Tognazzini (Eds.), Blame: Its
Kohlberg, L. (1981). The philosophy of moral de- nature and norms (pp. 162–188). New York:
velopment: Moral stages and the idea of jus- Oxford University Press.
tice. San Francisco: Harper & Row. McKenna, M. (2012). Directed blame and con-
Kuhn, D. (2011). What people may do versus can versation. In D. J. Coates & N. A. Tognazzini
do. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 34, 83. (Eds.), Blame: Its nature and norms (pp. 119–
Kuhn, D., Zillmer, N., Crowell, A., & Zavala, 140). New York: Oxford University Press.
J. (2013). Developing norms of argumenta- Meltzoff, A. N., Brooks, R., Shon, A. P., & Rao,
tion: Metacognitive, epistemological, and R. P. N. (2010). “Social” robots are psycholog-
social dimensions of developing argumentive ical agents for infants: A test of gaze following.
competence. Cognition and Instruction, 31, Neural Networks, 23, 966–972.
456–496. Monin, B., Pizarro, D. A., & Beer, J. S. (2007).
120 M O R A L I T Y, S O C I A L C O G N I T I O N , A N D I D E N T I T Y

Deciding versus reacting: Conceptions of Sher, G. (2006). In praise of blame. New York:
moral judgment and the reason–affect debate. Oxford University Press.
Review of General Psychology, 11, 99–111. Sripada, C. S., & Stich, S. (2006). A framework
Monroe, A. E., Dillon, K. D., & Malle, B. F. for the psychology of norms. In P. Carruthers,
(2014). Bringing free will down to Earth: Peo- S. Laurence, & S. Stich (Eds.), The innate
ple’s psychological concept of free will and its mind: Vol. 2. Culture and cognition (pp. 280–
role in moral judgment. Consciousness and 301). New York: Oxford University Press.
Cognition, 27, 100–108. Tomai, E., & Forbus, K. (2008). Using qualita-
Nadler, J. (2012). Blaming as a social process: tive reasoning for the attribution of moral re-
The influence of character and moral emotion sponsibility. In B. C. Love, K. McRae, & V. M.
on blame. Law and Contemporary Problems, Sloutsky (Eds.), Proceedings of the Thirtieth
75, 1–31. Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science
Nadler, J., & McDonnell, M.-H. (2011). Moral Society (pp.149–154). Austin, TX: Cognitive
character, motive, and the psychology of Science Society.
blame. Cornell Law Review, 97, 255–304. Traverso, V. (2009). The dilemmas of third-party
Nelson-Le Gall, S. A. (1985). Motive–outcome complaints in conversation between friends.
matching and outcome foreseeability: Effects Journal of Pragmatics, 41, 2385–2399.
on attribution of intentionality and moral Ullmann-Margalit, E. (1977). The emergence of
judgments. Developmental Psychology, 21, norms. Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press.
323–337. Voiklis, J. (in preparation). A little “mindread-
Nisbett, R. E., & Wilson, T. D. (1977). Telling more ing” practice facilitates later social-cognitive
than we can know: Verbal reports on mental pro- inferences. Manuscript in preparation.
cesses. Psychological Review, 84, 231–259. Voiklis, J., Cusimano, C., & Malle, B. F. (2014).
Nourbakhsh, I. R. (2013). Robot futures. Cam- A social-conceptual map of moral criticism.
bridge, MA: MIT Press. In P. Bello, M. Guarini, M. McShane, & B.
Piaget, J. (1932). The moral judgment of the Scassellati (Eds.), Proceedings of the 36th an-
child. London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner. nual meeting of the Cognitive Science Society
Pospisil, L. (1971). Anthropology of law: A com- (pp. 1700–1705). Austin, TX: Cognitive Sci-
parative theory. New York: Harper & Row. ence Society.
Schumann, K., Zaki, J., & Dweck, C. S. (2014). Walker, M. U. (2006). Moral repair: Recon-
Addressing the empathy deficit: Beliefs about structing moral relations after wrongdoing.
the malleability of empathy predict effortful New York: Cambridge University Press.
responses when empathy is challenging. Jour- Wallach, W., & Allen, C. (2008). Moral ma-
nal of Personality and Social Psychology, 107, chines: Teaching robots right from wrong.
475–493. New York: Oxford University Press.
Semin, G. R., & Manstead, A. S. R. (1983). The Weiner, B. (1995). Judgments of responsibility:
accountability of conduct: A social psycho- A foundation for a theory of social conduct.
logical analysis. London: Academic Press. New York: Guilford Press.
Shaver, K. G. (1985). The attribution of blame: Wellman, H. M. (1990). The child’s theory of
Causality, responsibility, and blameworthi- mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
ness. New York: Springer Verlag. Wolf, S. (2011). Blame, Italian style. In R. J. Wal-
Shaw, M. E., & Sulzer, J. L. (1964). An empiri- lace, R. Kumar, & S. Freeman (Eds.), Reason
cal test of Heider’s levels in attribution of re- and recognition: Essays on the philosophy of
sponsibility. Journal of Abnormal and Social T. M. Scanlon (pp. 332–347). New York: Ox-
Psychology, 69, 39–46. ford University Press.
C H A P T E R 13

Morality Is Personal

Justin F. Landy
Eric Luis Uhlmann

What is the purpose of moral judgment?

We argue that the basic goal of moral cognition is often not to praise
or condemn specific actions but, rather, to try to understand other
people’s dispositional moral character via their actions, and that
incorporating lay virtue ethics into psychological theory helps to
paint a more complete picture of people’s moral psychology.

In 2007, the Atlanta Falcons’ star quarter- even premeditated murder might not. While
back Michael Vick was exposed for bank- gratuitous animal cruelty may not rise to the
rolling a dog-fighting ring. Details about the level of murder in American jurisprudence,
fights were grim; dogs that proved insuf- in everyday moral psychology it points to
ficiently violent in test fights, for example, severe deficits in empathy and moral char-
were brutally hanged or drowned. Vick was acter.
criminally prosecuted and sentenced to 23 In the present chapter, we argue that the
months in prison, even though prosecutors goal of moral cognition is often not to praise
had recommended a maximum sentence of or condemn specific actions but, rather,
only 18 months (McCann, 2007). He also to try to understand other people’s moral
lost his $130 million contract with the Fal- character via their actions (Pizarro & Tan-
cons, who ruled out his ever returning to the nenbaum, 2011; Uhlmann, Pizarro, & Di-
team, and team owner Arthur Blank told ermeier, 2015). Human beings often act as
reporters he felt personally betrayed (King, intuitive virtue ethicists who view behaviors
2007). as signals of underlying moral traits such as
What underlies the public outrage over trustworthiness and compassion. In mak-
Vick’s actions, and the Falcons’ finality in ing this argument, we first briefly review
cutting their ties to him? Although few ob- historical approaches to the philosophy
servers would argue that killing a pit bull and psychology of ethics before introducing
is more morally blameworthy than killing our theoretical perspective, which we term
a human being, Vick’s behavior suggests a person-centered morality. We then explore
callous and sadistic personal character that two lines of empirical evidence supporting

121
122 M O R A L I T Y, S O C I A L C O G N I T I O N , A N D I D E N T I T Y

our argument that moral judgment is often 2008; Sunstein, 2005). Similarly, Greene
about evaluating people, not acts: first, and colleagues (Greene, Morelli, Lowen-
character assessments are automatic, yet nu- berg, Nystrom, & Cohen, 2008; Greene,
anced, and serve an important functional Sommerville, Nystrom, Darley, & Cohen,
purpose. Second, character information 2001) have advanced a dual-process model
can outweigh information about objective of moral judgment, in which automatic, Sys-
harm, and judgments of character can often tem 1 processes are said to produce deon-
diverge from evaluations of acts. Next, we tological moral judgments, and deliberative,
present evidence that results supporting the System 2 processes can sometimes override
person-centered view of morality are highly these System 1 processes and produce utili-
replicable. To close, we argue that recogniz- tarian judgments. In response to this line of
ing that human beings have a preoccupation work, some researchers have argued that
with moral virtues leads to the insight that deliberate reasoning is associated with nei-
our moral judgments can be both rational ther deontological nor utilitarian judgment
and intuitive, in meaningful senses. (Royzman, Landy, & Leeman, 2015), and
others have suggested that, rather than re-
sulting from System 2 overruling System 1,
Historical Perspectives on Morality utilitarian judgments are a product of dispo-
sitional thinking styles (Baron, Scott, Finch-
Since the Enlightenment, moral philosophy er, & Metz, 2015). Still others have empiri-
has been dominated by two opposing per- cally disputed the presumed optimality of
spectives on ethics. On one side stand con- utilitarian judgments (Bartels & Pizarro,
sequentialist philosophers, who view the 2011).
outcomes resulting from an action as the Despite the myriad theoretical and em-
only meaningful criterion for evaluating its pirical disputes, scholarship on deontology
morality or immorality. The most prominent and consequentialism is united by one com-
consequentialist theory is utilitarianism, monality: It takes discrete actions to be of
which judges as morally right the action that primary concern in moral judgment. That is,
maximizes good outcomes across all mor- both deontological and consequentialist eth-
ally relevant beings (Bentham, 1823/1970; ical theories are focused on what makes par-
Mill, 1861/1998; Smart & Williams, 1973). ticular actions right or wrong, and empirical
Standing in opposition to consequentialist studies of deontological and utilitarian judg-
theories of ethics are deontological theories, ment are focused on when and why people
which evaluate the rightness or wrongness judge particular actions to be permissible or
of an action according to whether it adheres impermissible. There is, however, a “third
to a moral rule or duty (Kant, 1785). There voice” in ethical philosophy that takes a
are several forms of deontology, some of different approach: Virtue ethics places the
which view the consequences of an act as focus on the character of moral actors. In
one morally important feature among many, other words, the driving question in virtue
and some of which emphasize strict adher- ethics is not “What is the right thing to do?”
ence to moral rules, regardless of the con- but rather “How can I be a good person?”
sequences (see Bartels, 2008; Kagan, 1998), Virtue ethics may actually be the oldest
but all of which deny that maximizing good philosophical approach to normative ethics
outcomes, by any means necessary, is the (Aristotle, trans. 1998), though it has only
only meaningful ethical principle. reemerged as a prominent alternative to de-
Moral psychologists have inherited this ontology and utilitarianism comparatively
preoccupation with deontological and utili- recently (Anscombe, 1958).
tarian approaches to ethics from their philo-
sophically minded counterparts. Decision
researchers have commonly treated utilitar- Person‑Centered Morality
ian theory as normatively correct and pro-
ceeded to document systematic departures Just as normative theories of virtue ethics
from this ethical standard (Baron, 1994, contend that people’s chief moral concern
 Morality Is Personal 123

ought to be with cultivating moral virtues, targets are best predicted by their moral-
we argue that, descriptively, moral cogni- ity across a wide range of contexts. Perhaps
tion is often more concerned with evaluat- their most striking result is that impressions
ing others’ character than the rightness or of real individuals, based on their obituaries,
wrongness of their actions, a view that we were best predicted by the morality informa-
call person-centered morality (PCM; Pizar- tion the obituaries conveyed, even though
ro & Tannenbaum, 2011; Uhlmann et al., they contained more information about
2015). Rather than a stand-alone model in their achievements and ability, overall. Par-
its own right, PCM is more of a needed cor- ticipants learned more about the competence
rective to descriptive theories that have fo- and ability of the deceased individuals, but
cused on judgments of acts. We believe that primarily attended to their morality when
a complete theory of moral cognition can- forming opinions of them.
not neglect characterological evaluations of In fact, moral character is so fundamen-
people. tally important in social evaluation that
Why would moral judgment be oriented good character may be among the only un-
toward character assessments, rather than ambiguously positive attributes that a per-
praise and condemnation for particular ac- son can possess. This point is illustrated by
tions? We see a functionalist reason why a study in which participants expressed pref-
moral judgment so often focuses on the per- erences for the presence or absence of trait
son. Many researchers have argued that it is characteristics in others. When they consid-
vitally important to be able to predict other ered an acquaintance who had a reputation
people’s likely intentions toward us—will for being competent, sociable, incompetent,
this person be benevolent or malevolent, or unsociable, they always preferred this
trustworthy or treacherous (e.g., Abele & person to be moral, rather than immoral,
Wojciszke, 2007; Cottrell, Neuberg, & Li, and they preferred moral acquaintances to
2007; Cuddy, Fiske, & Glick, 2008; Fiske, be sociable and competent. However, they
Cuddy, & Glick, 2007; Pizarro & Tan- preferred immoral acquaintances to be un-
nenbaum, 2011; Wojciszke, Bazinska, & sociable and incompetent (Landy et al.,
Jaworski, 1998; Wojciszke, Dowhyluk, & 2016; see also Peeters, 1992; Wojciszke, Ba-
Jaworski, 1998)? We agree; indeed, this zinska, & Jaworski, 1998). We argue that
seems to us to be the most important piece positive attributes such as intelligence and
of information we can know about another friendliness are considered negative and un-
person with whom we may interact (Good- desirable in the wicked, because they make
win, 2015; Goodwin, Piazza, & Rozin, it more likely that such people can success-
2014), and it is a person’s moral character fully carry out their ill intentions toward us.
that should be informative about their good People even seem to consider understanding
or bad intentions (Landy, Piazza, & Good- the “intentions” of nonhuman animals to be
win, 2016). Consistent with this perspec- of great importance. Although it seems un-
tive, judgments of character are largely de- likely that we make full-blown judgments of
termined by information about a person’s moral character for animals, people readily
intentions, rather than other considerations, make attributions about an animal’s disposi-
such as the outcomes they have caused (Mar- tional harmfulness, which contribute to be-
tin & Cushman, 2015, 2016). Judgments of liefs about whether the animal is worthy of
character are even influenced by inferences moral protection (Piazza, Landy, & Good-
about the sorts of intentions a person would win, 2014).
have, under other circumstances (Landy, From this functionalist perspective, dis-
Linder, & Caruso, 2017). Furthermore, in- crete moral and immoral acts are informa-
formation about a person’s moral character tive of another’s likely future intentions
has been found to dominate in impression insofar as they provide information about
formation—Goodwin et al. (2014), using that person’s underlying character. Or, as
correlational, experimental, and archival Helzer and Critcher (Chapter 11, this vol-
research designs, demonstrated that overall ume) phrase it, discrete acts are “outputs”
impressions of both real and hypothetical that respond to situational “inputs” and
124 M O R A L I T Y, S O C I A L C O G N I T I O N , A N D I D E N T I T Y

provide information about the “moral cog- character, depending on how it is per-
nitive machinery” a person possesses. To formed. For instance, when faced with an
possess sound moral cognitive machinery is opportunity to do something clearly im-
precisely to possess good moral character, moral, an actor who immediately gives
which they define as those personality traits in to temptation is seen as having worse
most necessary for cooperative social rela- character than an actor who does so only
tionships, particularly traits relating to how after deliberation. Conversely, an actor who
one treats other people. immediately decides to do the right thing
Given their functional importance, we is seen as having better character than an
would expect assessments of character to actor who deliberates first. Faster decisions
come naturally to people. Indeed, this is indicate less internal conflict about what to
the case. Incredibly, infants as young as 6 do, and therefore more extreme (good or
months old show a preference for a “help- bad) character (Critcher, Inbar, & Pizarro,
er” character who aided another character 2013). Yet, in more complex situations with
in reaching a goal over a “hinderer” char- multiple, competing moral concerns, delib-
acter, who prevented them from reaching eration and careful reflection are seen as
the goal (Hamlin, Wynn, & Bloom, 2007). indicative of good moral character (Landy,
Moreover, judgments of trustworthiness Herzog, & Bartels, 2017). This illustrates
and aggression can be made by adults after how judgments of character can respond to
as little as 100 milliseconds of exposure to a quite subtle aspects of behaviors.
human face, and these judgments are highly It should be obvious by now that infer-
correlated with analogous judgments made ences about character are a frequent part of
with no time constraints (Willis & Todor- social and moral cognition. But what exactly
ov, 2006). This result is also supported by do these inferences consist of? That is, what
neurological evidence: Amygdala activation trait attributes do people see as relevant to
in response to faces correlates with the pres- assessments of character, or, phrased differ-
ence of features that are thought to indicate ently, what are the constituent elements of
dishonesty, even when the task at hand does the lay concept of “good character”? Sev-
not require one to assess the target’s charac- eral attempts have been made to answer this
ter (Engell, Haxby, & Todorov, 2007). This question, with somewhat disparate results,
suggests that we automatically assess trust- but aggregating across them, trustworthi-
worthiness in others, even with only mini- ness and compassion seem to be viable can-
mal information, and even when we are not didates for “core” elements of moral char-
consciously motivated to do so. acter.1 Walker and Hennig (2004) identified
Of course, we do not evaluate a person’s three types of moral exemplar—just, caring,
character solely on the basis of his or her and brave—and found that traits ascribed
facial features; we typically rely on behav- to each varied considerably. However, those
ior to inform our judgments, and, in such traits ascribed to all three were largely re-
cases, assessments of character can be quite lated to honesty and integrity (e.g., truthful,
nuanced, responding to a variety of behav- honest) and to compassion toward others
ioral features. One widely studied feature (e.g., helpful, empathic). Similarly, Walker
has been called diagnosticity (Skowronski & and Pitts (1998) used hierarchical clus-
Carlston, 1989). Immoral behaviors are seen ter analysis to organize traits ascribed to a
as more diagnostic of character than moral moral person. They found that traits related
behaviors, because, by definition, moral to being caring and honest clustered together
people rarely engage in immoral behaviors, and that other elements of trustworthiness
but immoral people sometimes strategically (integrity, dependability) formed their own
engage in moral behaviors. Thus moral be- clusters. Other clusters related to being prin-
haviors are often not particularly informa- cipled, loyal, fair, and confident. Lapsley and
tive as to underlying character, whereas im- Lasky (2001) elicited traits that participants
moral behaviors are highly diagnostic (see thought were aspects of “good character,”
also Reeder & Brewer, 1979). then had a separate sample rate how charac-
Further, even the same action can seem teristic each trait was of a person with good
like a better or a worse indicator of moral character. The majority of the traits rated as
 Morality Is Personal 125

most characteristic related to trustworthi- Some Anecdotes and Some Evidence


ness (e.g., sincere, honest) or compassion
(e.g., understanding, kind), though some A perfect example of person-centered moral
were not closely related to these virtues (e.g., judgment is public outrage over frivolous
loyal, fair). Using a similar procedure, Aqui- executive perks. Why do such perks elicit
no and Reed (2002) had participants gener- widespread condemnation, notwithstand-
ate traits that are characteristic of a moral ing the fact that they may waste relatively
person. Most of the traits produced related few organizational resources and do little
to trustworthiness or compassion. Lastly, concrete harm? Merrill Lynch Chief Execu-
Piazza, Goodwin, Rozin, and Royzman tive Officer John Thain, for instance, pro-
(2014) introduced a conceptual distinction voked outrage when—in the midst of lay-
between “core goodness traits” that should ing off thousands of employees—he spent
be desirable in anyone and “value commit- lavishly redecorating his personal office.
ment traits” (e.g., committed, hardworking) Extravagances included $28,000 curtains, a
that contribute to good character in good or $1,400 garbage can, and an $87,000 area
neutral people but make the character of bad rug. After the spending was reported in the
people (e.g., a “dedicated Nazi”) even worse. media, Thain promptly lost his position as
Half of the core goodness traits related to CEO. Interestingly, Thain’s compensation
trustworthiness (e.g., honest, trustwor- of more than $80 million a year elicited no
thy) or compassion (e.g., kind, charitable), such vitriol (Gasparino, 2009). In cases such
though others did not (e.g., just, humble). 2 as this, the issue seems not to be the objec-
Across all of these studies, trustworthiness tive degree of waste but, rather, what these
and compassion emerge as central elements frivolous expenses say about the executives
of good character. Other traits appear as as people.
well, but none so often and so consistently. Empirical support for this idea comes
We take this as evidence that people think from Tannenbaum, Uhlmann, and Diermei-
of the “good person” as someone who can er (2011, Study 2), who asked their partici-
be trusted and who will treat others kindly. pants which of two candidates they would
Evaluations of character are a fundamen- hire as CEO of a manufacturing company.
tal part of social cognition. They are func- The candidates were comparable in their
tionally important and automatic, though qualifications and differed only in their
they can also respond to subtle aspects of be- requested compensation. One candidate
haviors in quite nuanced ways. The person- requested a salary of $2 million, whereas
centered approach to moral judgment also the other requested a salary of $1 million
contributes unique and testable predictions plus an additional benefit that would cost
(Pizarro & Tannenbaum, 2011; Uhlmann $40,000. In one condition, this benefit was
et al., 2015). For instance, acts that provide a cash signing bonus, and participants quite
clear signals of poor moral character elicit reasonably preferred the low-salary candi-
moral condemnation completely out of pro- date. However, in another condition, the
portion to the objective harm that they cause requested benefit was a marble table for the
(Pizarro, Tannenbaum, & Uhlmann, 2012). CEO’s office, and in yet another, it was a
Furthermore, striking dissociations can marble table with the candidate’s portrait
emerge between moral evaluations of an act carved into it. In both of these conditions,
and the person who performs the act. Such participants preferred to hire the candidate
act–person dissociations suggest that nei- who requested $2 million in salary over the
ther type of judgment can be subsumed into candidate who requested $1 million and the
the other. That is, judgments of character perk. Participants indicated that the request
cannot merely be aggregations of act judg- for the table indicated poor character (spe-
ments, and judgments of acts cannot merely cifically, low integrity), and that the can-
be inputs into character judgments. These didate who requested it would make less
findings provide some of the strongest avail- sound business decisions than the candidate
able evidence that moral virtues are neces- who requested the higher salary. Thus, when
sary to account for the full scope of human a job candidate requested a frivolous, self-
moral cognition. indulgent perk, participants inferred poor
126 M O R A L I T Y, S O C I A L C O G N I T I O N , A N D I D E N T I T Y

moral character, and this inference led to an-beating counterpart. This is an example
their rejecting the candidate, paralleling the of an act–person dissociation.
public outrage directed at John Thain and A similar study compared judgments of
his $87,000 area rug. another pair of unlikable managers. The
Interestingly, this result seems to stem “violent” manager expressed his displea-
from the perceived informational value of the sure at a coworker by punching him in the
requested perk. Participants did not just see face, whereas the “racist” manager did so by
the table requester as having worse character muttering a racial slur about the coworker
than the high-salary requester; they felt that to himself (Uhlmann, Zhu, & Diermeier,
they knew more about his underlying moral 2014). The violent manager’s action was
character. A more direct demonstration that seen as more immoral, probably due to the
objectively less harmful acts can be seen as obvious physical harm that it caused. Yet
more informative of poor character comes the racist manager was seen as having worse
from a study about two unfriendly manag- moral character, again showing a dissocia-
ers, a “misanthropic” manager who was tion between judgments of the immorality of
rude to all of his employees and a “bigoted” acts and the character of actors.
manager who was rude only to his black Both of these studies concerned inferences
employees (Uhlmann, Tannenbaum, Zhu, of character from actions that, though less
& Diermeier, 2009). Though the bigoted immoral than focal comparisons, are still
manager harmed fewer people, participants clearly morally negative (i.e., animal cruelty
strongly preferred the misanthropic manag- and racial epithets). However, there may be
er to the bigoted manager and saw the big- some circumstances in which even a mor-
ot’s behavior as more informative about his ally praiseworthy act can be indicative of
character than the misanthrope’s. Another bad moral character. In an initial test of
study on this topic examined the informa- this idea, participants read about two target
tional value regarding character provided by persons: a medical research assistant whose
tipping behavior (Uhlmann, Tannenbaum, duties involved inducing tumors in mice and
& Diermeier, 2010). Participants considered then administering painful injections of ex-
a restaurant patron who tipped $15 in pen- perimental cancer drugs and a pet store as-
nies to be a worse person than a patron who sistant whose job involved giving gerbils a
tipped $14 in bills, despite being materially grooming shampoo and then tying bows on
more generous, and this effect was mediated them. Even though the medical research as-
by the perceived informational value of his sistant’s acts were seen as more praisewor-
act rather than the immorality of the act thy than those of the pet store assistant, she
itself. All of this research converges on the was simultaneously perceived as more cold-
conclusion that an act that does objectively hearted and aggressive (Uhlmann, Tannen-
less harm (or more good) can nonetheless baum, & Diermeier, 2009). Strikingly, these
signal worse moral character. results were found even among participants
Let us now return to the sordid tale of Mi- who strongly supported animal testing.
chael Vick recounted earlier. We argued that This demonstrates a pattern of dissociation
the cruelty he enacted upon animals led to complementary to that of the cat-beater and
inferences of severe character deficits, more racial-slur studies: An act can be objectively
so than some harmful actions directed at hu- praiseworthy, yet still signal poor character.
mans may have. Evidence for this assertion This finding has since been replicated in
comes from studies involving two jilted lov- the context of utilitarian dilemmas. In one
ers (Tannenbaum et al., 2011, Studies 1a and study, participants read about a group of
1b). Participants read about two men who people who were stranded on a sinking life
learned that their girlfriends were cheating raft but could throw one injured passenger
on them. Both men flew into a rage; one beat overboard to save everyone else (Uhlmann,
up his unfaithful girlfriend, the other beat Zhu, & Tannenbaum, 2013). When they
up her cat. Participants judged the former elected to do this, their action was rated as
action to be more immoral but judged the more morally right than when they elected
cat beater as having worse character (specifi- not to. Yet the passengers who sacrificed
cally, as having less empathy) than his wom- one life to save many were seen as having
 Morality Is Personal 127

worse moral character than the passengers fects, originally found by Uhlmann and his
who did not. In two follow-up studies, par- colleagues, at 25 partner universities. The 10
ticipants read about a hospital administrator effects included 6 that explicitly tested pre-
who had to choose between funding an ex- dictions derived from PCM, many of which
pensive surgical procedure to save one sick we have discussed in the present chapter.
boy or purchasing a new piece of hospital The replication effect sizes for these six ef-
equipment that would save 500 lives in the fects were all statistically significant in the
future. As in the “life raft” study, the ad- expected direction, although the bad-tipper
ministrator who chose to save more people effect described earlier replicated only for
by sacrificing one was seen as having done samples in the United States. Perhaps the
the morally right thing but as having worse most theoretically crucial effect was the
moral character. Also, as in the “frivolous act–person dissociation such that carrying
perk” study discussed above, these results out medical tests on animals was seen as a
were attributable to the informational value praiseworthy act, but also led to negative
ascribed to the person’s action. The utilitar- character inferences. Across numerous rep-
ian administrator’s choice to buy the new lication sites, standardized mean difference
equipment was seen as diagnostic of a lack (d) associated with this finding was over 2,
of empathy, which mediated the effect of his indicating an extremely large and robust ef-
decision on overall assessments of his char- fect. In contrast, two out of four original
acter. Interestingly, though, he was also seen effects that involved topics other than per-
as a better leader for having made the more son-centered moral judgments entirely failed
pragmatic choice. In some cases, it seems, to replicate. The overall results of the PPIR
doing the right thing requires a bad person. suggest that PCM is reliable and replicable.
We have reviewed evidence supporting Given this, we now consider how the psy-
two novel hypotheses derived from PCM. chological importance of moral virtues can
First, information about an actor’s charac- best be integrated into prevailing models of
ter can outweigh information about objec- moral judgment.
tive harm in social judgments. Furthermore,
judgments of the morality of acts can di-
verge from judgments of an actor’s charac- Moral Judgment Can Be Both Intuitive
ter, suggesting that neither type of judgment and Rational
can fully explain the other and that both are
important aspects of moral cognition. Char- Modern moral psychology is divided over
acter matters. the root of moral judgments. Some research-
ers (Landy & Royzman, in press; Royzman,
Landy, & Goodwin, 2014) support variants
Person‑Centered Morality Is Robust of traditional rationalist models (e.g., Turiel,
and Replicable 1983) that emphasize the role of reason-
ing and cognitive deliberation in produc-
The field of psychology (and science more ing moral judgments. Many others claim
broadly) currently finds itself in the midst instead that moral judgments are the result
of a crisis of confidence in the replicability of rapid, automatic evaluations, often called
of our findings (Pashler & Wagenmakers, intuitions (Haidt, 2001, 2007). We argue
2012; Nosek, Spies, & Motyl, 2012), with that moral judgment can be both rational
many high-profile failures of replication and intuitive3 in important senses and that
emerging recently (e.g., Klein et al., 2014; PCM can provide the bridge to unite these
Open Science Collaboration, 2015). One approaches.
approach to addressing this concern is to As we argued above, character judgments
replicate research findings in independent serve an important functional purpose. We
laboratories before, rather than after, they think that this makes them, in an important
are published. In a large-scale prepublica- sense, rational, in that they meet the funda-
tion independent replication (PPIR) project, mental need to understand others’ likely in-
­Schweinsberg et al. (2016) attempted to rep- tentions toward us. Importantly, participants
licate 10 unpublished moral judgment ef- themselves do not appear to view person-
128 M O R A L I T Y, S O C I A L C O G N I T I O N , A N D I D E N T I T Y

centered judgments as irrational. Research 2010) because they are exceptionally statis-
shows that when targets are judged simulta- tically rare (Ditto & Jemmott, 1989; Fiske,
neously (joint evaluation), participants think 1980), because they represent extreme devia-
more carefully and are less likely to make tions from normative behavior (Chakroff &
judgments that they themselves consider un- Young, 2015), and because there is almost
justified (Gaertner & Dovidio, 1986; Hsee, no conceivable reason to commit them that
Loewenstein, Blount, & Bazerman, 1999; is external to the person, making them low
Pizarro & Uhlmann, 2005). In our empiri- in attributional ambiguity (Snyder, Kleck,
cal investigations, perceived informational Strenta, & Mentzer, 1979; see also Gray
value regarding character can outweigh ob- & Keeney, 2015). Therefore, it is quite rea-
jective harm in eliciting condemnation in sonable to draw strong character inferences
both joint and separate evaluation (Tannen- from them. Indeed, when participants made
baum et al., 2011; Uhlmann, Tannenbaum, character judgments, they were less morally
Zhu, & Diermeier, 2009; Zhu, Uhlmann, dumbfounded when they were asked about
& Diermeier, 2014), and act–person dis- offenses that are rare, deviant, and unam-
sociations readily emerge under conditions biguous, yet harmless, than when they were
of either joint or separate evaluation (e.g., asked about prototypically harmful offenses
Tannenbaum et al., 2011; Uhlmann & Zhu, (Uhlmann & Zhu, 2014, Study 3). Haidt
2014; Uhlmann, Tannenbaum, & Diermei- and colleagues’ participants were not able
er, 2009; Uhlmann et al., 2013). Thus PCM to articulate why a harmless act is wrong,
appears compatible with a subjective sense but they probably could have roughly articu-
of making rational judgments. lated why it indicates bad character.
We noted earlier that, in addition to being Integrating these theoretical perspectives
functional, character judgments are often and relevant bodies of empirical evidence,
automatic—that is, they are intuitive. Haidt we propose that the person-centered nature
and colleagues have demonstrated the role of moral cognition can unite rationalist and
of automatic intuitions in moral judgment in intuitionist perspectives on human moral-
their widely cited studies of “moral dumb- ity. Moral judgment is rational and adaptive
founding.” They show that people condemn because social perceivers effectively exploit
harmless transgressions such as eating a the informational value of social behaviors
dead dog or fornicating with a chicken car- to draw reasonable inferences about the un-
cass but cannot provide explanations for derlying vices and virtues of other agents.
their condemnation (Haidt, Bjorklund, & Moral judgment is intuitive because infer-
Murphy, 2011; Haidt, 2001; Haidt, Koller, ences about other people often must be made
& Dias, 1993; though see Royzman, Kim, quickly and efficiently for reasons of basic
& Leeman, 2015). These studies all exam- survival. The ancient notion that moral-
ined evaluations of acts, however. ity is fundamentally concerned with human
Applying the PCM perspective to the virtues is supported by a growing body of
moral dumbfounding paradigm demon- empirical evidence and has much to add to
strates our point that moral judgment can contemporary models of moral judgment.
be both rational and intuitive. In another ex-
ample of an act–person dissociation, partici-
pants rated harmless but offensive actions— NOTES
copulating with a dead chicken and eating a
dead dog—as less morally wrong than theft, 1. Insofar as trustworthiness can be seen as the
which directly causes harm. However, the likelihood that one will keep one’s promises
chicken-lover and the dog-eater were seen and will not cheat others, these two core ele-
ments of character bear resemblances to Kohl-
as having worse moral character than the
berg’s (1969) ethics of justice and Gilligan’s
thief (Uhlmann & Zhu, 2014). Important- (1982) ethics of care, as well as Turiel’s (1983)
ly, this characterological assessment seems definition of the moral domain, which, he ar-
rationally defensible—such acts as mastur- gues, involves “justice, rights, and welfare”
bating into poultry have high informational (p. 3). All of these theories of morality are
value for judging character (Nelson, 2005; fundamentally act-centered, but their conver-
Nelson, McKenzie, Cottrell, & Sejnowski, gence with the study of character speaks to
 Morality Is Personal 129

our point that PCM must be a part of any in- Test (sometimes) predict utilitarian moral
tegrated theory of moral cognition. Haidt and judgment (and other things)? Journal of Ap-
Graham (2007; Graham, Haidt, & Nosek, plied Research in Memory and Cognition, 4,
2009) argue for additional, widely important 265–284.
virtues or “moral foundations,” including re- Bartels, D. (2008). Principled moral sentiment
spect for and obedience to authority, loyalty and the flexibility of moral judgment and deci-
to one’s ingroup, and bodily and sexual puri- sion making. Cognition, 108, 381–417.
ty. However, across cultures and subcultures, Bartels, D. M., & Pizarro, D. A. (2011). The
only virtues relating to fairness (which include mismeasure of morals: Antisocial personality
honesty and integrity) and caring for others traits predict utilitarian responses to moral di-
are endorsed universally. Therefore, we see lemmas. Cognition, 121, 154–161.
our assertion that trustworthiness and com- Bentham, J. (1970). An introduction to the prin-
passion are core elements of moral character ciples of morals and legislation. London:
as largely consistent with their work. Althone Press. (Original work published 1823)
2. It is worth noting that the purpose of this Chakroff, A., & Young, L. (2015). Harmful situ-
study was to illustrate the distinction between ations, impure people: An attribution asym-
core goodness and value commitment traits metry across moral domains. Cognition, 136,
and to explore the importance of this distinc- 30–37.
tion in impression formation, not to produce a Cottrell, C. A., Neuberg, S. L., & Li, N. P.
complete catalog of all traits of each type. We (2007). What do people desire in others?: A
suspect that a complete list of core goodness sociofunctional perspective on the importance
virtues would be dominated by trustworthi- of different valued characteristics. Journal of
ness and compassion traits. Personality and Social Psychology, 92, 208–
3. The precise nature of these automatic in- 231.
tuitions is not relevant here, and PCM does Critcher, C. R., Inbar, Y., & Pizarro, D. A.
not speak to this issue. They could be affec- (2013). How quick decisions illuminate moral
tive evaluations (Haidt, 2001; Haidt & Jo- character. Social Psychological and Personal-
seph, 2004), cognitive computations that have ity Science, 4, 308–315.
been automatized and can be run without Cuddy, A. J. C., Fiske, S. T., & Glick, P. (2008).
conscious involvement under normal circum- Warmth and competence as universal dimen-
stances (Aarts & Custers, 2009; Kahneman sions of social perception: The stereotype con-
& Klein, 2009; Stanovich, West, & Toplak, tent model and the BIAS map. Advances in
2011), or some combination of both. Experimental Social Psychology, 40, 61–149.
Ditto, P. H., & Jemmott, J. B., III. (1989). From
rarity to evaluative extremity: Effects of prev-
REFERENCES alence information on evaluations of positive
and negative characteristics. Journal of Per-
Aarts, H., & Custers, R. (2009), Habit, action, sonality and Social Psychology, 57, 16–26.
and consciousness. In W. P. Banks, (Ed.), En- Engell, A. E., Haxby, J. V., & Todorov, A. (2007).
cyclopedia of consciousness (Vol. 1, pp. 315– Implicit trustworthiness decisions: Automatic
328). Oxford, UK: Elsevier. coding of face properties in the human amyg-
Abele, A. E., & Wojciszke, B. (2007). Agency dala. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 19,
and communion from the perspective of self 1508–1519.
versus others. Journal of Personality and So- Fiske, S. T. (1980). Attention and weight in per-
cial Psychology, 93, 751–763. son perception: The impact of negative and
Anscombe, G. E. M. (1958). Modern moral phi- extreme behavior. Journal of Personality and
losophy. Philosophy, 33, 1–19. Social Psychology, 38, 889–906.
Aquino, K., & Reed, A., II. (2002). The self-im- Fiske, S. T., Cuddy, A. J. C., & Glick, P. (2007).
portance of moral identity. Journal of Person- Universal dimensions of social cognition:
ality and Social Psychology, 83, 1423–1440. Warmth and competence. Trends in Cognitive
Aristotle. (1998). The Nicomachean ethics (W. Sciences, 11, 77–83.
D. Ross, trans.). Oxford, UK: Oxford Univer- Gaertner, S. L., & Dovidio, J. F. (1986). The
sity Press. aversive form of racism. In J. F. Dovidio & S.
Baron, J. (1994). Nonconsequentialist decisions. L. Gaertner (Eds.), Prejudice, discrimination,
Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 17, 1–10 and racism (pp. 61–89). Orlando, FL: Aca-
Baron, J. (2008). Thinking and deciding. New demic Press.
York: Cambridge University Press. Gasparino, C. (2009, January 22). John Thain’s
Baron, J., Scott, S., Fincher, K., & Metz, S. E. $87,000 rug. The Daily Beast. Retrieved from
(2015). Why does the Cognitive Reflection www.thedailybeast.com.
130 M O R A L I T Y, S O C I A L C O G N I T I O N , A N D I D E N T I T Y

Gilligan, C. (1982). In a different voice. Cam- for intuitive expertise: A failure to disagree.
bridge, MA: Harvard University Press. American Psychologist, 64, 515–526.
Goodwin, G. P. (2015). Moral character in per- Kant, I. (2002). Groundwork for the metaphys-
son perception. Current Directions in Psycho- ics of morals (A. Zweig, Trans.). New York:
logical Science, 24, 38–44. Oxford University Press. (Original work pub-
Goodwin, G. P., Piazza, J., & Rozin, P. (2014). lished 1785)
Moral character predominates in person per- King, P. (2007, August 20). A boss betrayed:
ception and evaluation. Journal of Personality Falcons’ Blank deeply saddened by Vick’s de-
and Social Psychology, 106, 148–168. mise. Sports Illustrated. Retrieved from http://
Graham, J., Haidt, J., & Nosek, B. A. (2009). sportsillustrated.cnn.com.
Liberals and conservatives rely on different Klein, R. A., Ratliff, K. A., Vianello, M., Adams,
sets of moral foundations. Journal of Person- R. B., Jr., Bahník, Š., Bernstein, M. J., . . ., &
ality and Social Psychology, 96, 1029–1046. Nosek, B. A. (2014). Investigating variation in
Gray, K., & Keeney, J. E. (2015). Impure or just replicability: A “many labs” replication proj-
weird?: Scenario sampling bias raises ques- ect. Social Psychology, 45, 142–152.
tions about the foundations of morality. So- Kohlberg, L. (1969). Stage and sequence: The
cial Psychological and Personality Science, 6, cognitive-developmental approach to social-
859–868. ization. In D. A. Goslin (Ed.), Handbook of
Greene, J. D., Morelli, S. A., Lowenberg, K., socialization theory and research (pp. 347–
Nystrom, L. E., & Cohen, J. D. (2008). Cog­ 480). Chicago: Rand McNally.
nitive load selectively interferes with utilitar- Landy, J. F., Herzog, N. R., & Bartels, D. M.
ian moral judgment. Cognition, 107, 1144– (2017). Moral thoughtfulness: Thinking care-
1154. fully about complex moral problems is a vir-
Greene, J. D., Sommerville, R. B., Nystrom, tue. Manuscript in preparation.
L. E., Darley, J. M., & Cohen, J. D. (2001). An Landy, J. F., Linder, J. N., & Caruso, E. M.
fMRI investigation of emotional engagement (2017). Latent intentions: Why over-justify-
in moral judgment. Science, 293, 2105–2108. ing innocence makes you seem like a worse
Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional dog and its ra- person. Manuscript in preparation.
tional tail: A social intuitionist approach to Landy, J. F., Piazza, J., & Goodwin, G. P. (2016).
moral judgment. Psychological Review, 108, When it’s bad to be friendly and smart: The
814–834. desirability of sociability and competence de-
Haidt, J. (2007). The new synthesis in moral psy- pends on morality. Personality and Social Psy-
chology. Science, 316, 998–1002. chology Bulletin, 42, 1272–1290.
Haidt, J., Bjorklund, F., & Murphy, S. (2011). Landy, J. F., & Royzman, E. B. (in press). Moral
Moral dumbfounding: When intuition finds reasoning. In G. Pennycook (Ed.), The new
no reason. Unpublished manuscript. reflectionism in cognitive psychology: Why
Haidt, J., & Graham, J. (2007). When morality reason matters. East Sussex, UK: Psychology
opposes justice: Conservatives have moral in- Press.
tuitions that liberals may not recognize. Social Lapsley, D. K., & Lasky, B. (2001). Prototypic
Justice Research, 20, 98–116. moral character. Identity, 1, 345–363.
Haidt, J., & Joseph, C. (2004). Intuitive ethics: Martin, J. W., & Cushman, F. (2015). To punish
How innately prepared intuitions generate or to leave: Distinct cognitive processes under-
culturally variable virtues. Daedalus, 133, lie partner control and partner choice behav-
55–66. iors. PLOS ONE, 10(4), e0125193.
Haidt, J., Koller, S., & Dias, M. (1993). Affect, Martin, J. W., & Cushman, F. (2016). Why we
culture, and morality, or is it wrong to eat forgive what can’t be controlled. Cognition,
your dog? Journal of Personality and Social 147, 133–143.
Psychology, 65, 613–628. McCann, M. (2007, December 10). Analyzing
Hamlin, J., Wynn, K., & Bloom, P. (2007). So- the Vick sentence: The reason behind ruling,
cial evaluation by preverbal infants. Nature, how long he’ll serve, more. Sports Illustrated.
450, 557–559. Retrieved from http://sportsillustrated.cnn.
Hsee, C. K., Loewenstein, G. F., Blount, S., & com.
Bazerman, M. H. (1999). Preference reversals Mill, J. S. (1998). Utilitarianism. New York:
between joint and separate evaluation of op- Oxford University Press. (Original work pub-
tions: A review and theoretical analysis. Psy- lished 1861)
chological Bulletin, 125, 576–590. Nelson, J. D. (2005). Finding useful questions:
Kagan, S. (1998). Normative ethics. Boulder, On Bayesian diagnosticity, probability, im-
CO: Westview Press. pact, and information gain. Psychological Re-
Kahneman, D., & Klein, G. (2009). Conditions view, 112, 979–999.
 Morality Is Personal 131

Nelson, J. D., McKenzie, C. R. M., Cottrell, Royzman, E. B., Landy, J. F., & Leeman, R. F.
G. W., & Sejnowski, T. J. (2010). Experience (2015). Are thoughtful people more utilitari-
matters: Information acquisition optimizes an?: CRT as a unique predictor of moral mini-
probability gain. Psychological Science, 21(7), malism in the dilemmatic context. Cognitive
960–969. Science, 39, 325–352.
Nosek, B. A., Spies, J. R., & Motyl, M. (2012). Schweinsberg, M., Madan, N., Vianello, M.,
Scientific utopia: II. Restructuring incentives Sommer, A., Jordan, J., Zhu, L., . . . Uhlmann,
and practices to promote truth over publish- E. L. (2016). The pipeline project: Pre-publica-
ability. Perspectives on Psychological Science, tion independent replications of a single labo-
7, 615–631. ratory’s research pipeline. Journal of Experi-
Open Science Collaboration. (2015). Estimating mental Social Psychology, 66, 55–67.
the reproducibility of psychological science. Skowronski, J. J., & Carlston, D. E. (1989).
Science, 349, 6251. Negativity and extremity biases in impression
Pashler, H., & Wagenmakers, E.-J. (2012). Edi- formation: A review of explanations. Psycho-
tors’ introduction to the special section on logical Bulletin, 105, 131–142.
replicability in psychological science: A crisis Smart, J. J. C., & Williams, B. (1973). Utili-
of confidence? Perspectives on Psychological tarianism: For and against. Cambridge, UK:
Science, 7, 528–530. Cambridge University Press.
Peeters, G. (1992). Evaluative meanings of adjec- Snyder, M. L., Kleck, R. E., Strenta, A., & Men-
tives in vitro and in context: Some theoreti- tzer, S. J. (1979). Avoidance of the handi-
cal implications and practical consequences of capped: An attributional ambiguity analysis.
positive negative asymmetry and behavioural- Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
adaptive concepts of evaluation. Psychologia 37, 2297–2306.
Belgica, 32, 211–231. Stanovich, K. E., West, R. F., & Toplak, M. E.
Piazza, J., Goodwin, G., Rozin, P., & Royzman, (2011). The complexity of developmental pre-
E. (2014). When a virtue is not a virtue: Con- dictions from dual process models. Develop-
ditional virtues in moral evaluation. Social mental Review, 31, 103–118.
Cognition, 32, 528–558. Sunstein, C. R. (2005). Moral heuristics. Behav-
Piazza, J., Landy, J. F., & Goodwin, G. P. (2014). ioral and Brain Sciences, 28, 531–541.
Cruel nature: Harmfulness as an important, Tannenbaum, D., Uhlmann, E. L., & Diermeier,
overlooked dimension in judgments of moral D. (2011). Moral signals, public outrage, and
standing. Cognition, 131, 108–124. immaterial harms. Journal of Experimental
Pizarro, D. A., & Tannenbaum, D. (2011). Bring- Social Psychology, 47, 1249–1254.
ing character back: How the motivation to Turiel, E. (1983). The development of social
evaluate character influences judgments of knowledge: Morality and convention. Cam-
moral blame. In P. Shaver & M. Mikulincer bridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
(Eds.), The social psychology of morality: Ex- Uhlmann, E. L., Pizarro, D., & Diermeier, D.
ploring the causes of good and evil (pp. 91– (2015). A person-centered approach to moral
108). New York: APA Books. judgment. Perspectives on Psychological Sci-
Pizarro, D. A., Tannenbaum, D., & Uhlmann, E. ence, 10, 72–81.
L. (2012). Mindless, harmless, and blamewor- Uhlmann, E. L., Tannenbaum, D., & Diermeier,
thy. Psychological Inquiry, 23, 185–188. D. (2009). The cold-hearted prosociality effect.
Pizarro, D. A., & Uhlmann, E. L. (2005). Do Unpublished finding selected for replication in
normative standards advance our understand- the Pipeline Project (Schweinsberg et al., in
ing of moral judgment? Behavioral and Brain press). Full study report available in the online
Sciences, 28, 558–559. supplement for Schweinsberg et al. (in press).
Reeder, G. D., & Brewer, M. B. (1979). A sche- Uhlmann, E. L., Tannenbaum, D., & Diermeier,
matic model of dispositional attribution in in- D. (2010). The bad tipper effect. Unpublished
terpersonal perception. Psychological Review, finding selected for replication in the Pipeline
86, 61–79. Project (Schweinsberg et al., in press). Full
Royzman, E. B., Kim, K., & Leeman, R. F. study report available in the online supplement
(2015). The curious tale of Julie and Mark: for Schweinsberg et al. (in press).
Unraveling the moral dumbfounding effect. Uhlmann, E. L., Tannenbaum, D., Zhu, L., &
Judgment and Decision Making, 10, 296–313. Diermeier, D. (2009). The bigot–misanthrope
Royzman, E. B., Landy, J. F., & Goodwin, G. P. effect. Unpublished finding selected for repli-
(2014). Are good reasoners more incest-friend- cation in the Pipeline Project (Schweinsberg et
ly?: Trait cognitive reflection predicts selective al., in press). Full study report available in the
moralization in a sample of American adults. online supplement of Schweinsberg et al. (in
Judgment and Decision Making, 9, 175–190. press).
132 M O R A L I T Y, S O C I A L C O G N I T I O N , A N D I D E N T I T Y

Uhlmann, E. L., & Zhu, L. (2014). Acts, persons, conceptions of moral maturity. Developmen-
and intuitions: Person-centered cues and gut re- tal Psychology, 34, 403–419.
actions to harmless transgressions. Social Psy- Willis, J., & Todorov, A. (2006). First impres-
chological and Personality Science, 5, 279–285. sions: Making up your mind after a 100-ms
Uhlmann, E. L., Zhu, L., & Diermeier, D. exposure to a face. Psychological Science, 17,
(2014). When actions speak volumes: The role 592–598.
of inferences about moral character in outrage Wojciszke, B., Bazinska, R., & Jaworski, M.
over racial bigotry. European Journal of So- (1998). On the dominance of moral categories
cial Psychology, 44, 23–29. in impression formation. Personality and So-
Uhlmann, E. L., Zhu, L., & Tannenbaum, D. cial Psychology Bulletin, 24, 1251–1263.
(2013). When it takes a bad person to do the Wojciszke, B., Dowhyluk, M., & Jaworski, M.
right thing. Cognition, 126, 326–334. (1998). Moral and competence-related traits:
Walker, L. J., & Hennig, K. H. (2004). Differing How do they differ? Polish Psychological Bul-
conceptions of moral exemplarity: Just, brave, letin, 29, 283–294.
and caring. Journal of Personality and Social Zhu, L., Uhlmann, E. L., & Diermeier, D. (2014).
Psychology, 86, 629–647. Moral evaluations of bigots and misanthropes.
Walker, L. J., & Pitts, R. C. (1998). Naturalistic Available at https://osf.io/a4uxn.
C H A P T E R 14

A Social Cognitive Model of Moral Identity

Karl Aquino
Adam Kay

Is moral behavior the product of intuitive psychological processes


that can show both flexibility and cross-situational stability?

Yes, if we conceptualize moral identity as a highly accessible mental


representation that mediates between people’s internal states, situ‑
ational cues and contingencies, and subsequent behavior.

In this chapter we explain how Aquino consistency. A number of scholars followed


and Reed’s (2002) social cognitive model suit by proffering similar definitions that
of moral identity contributes to our under- equated having a moral identity with a sus-
standing of moral behavior. We present their tained commitment to moral action in line
definition of moral identity, the assumptions with a person’s moral beliefs or values (e.g.,
of their model, and the underlying prin- Bergman, 2004; Colby & Damon, 1992;
ciples that link moral identity as they con- Damon, 1984). More recently, Blasi (2005)
ceptualize it to moral functioning. But first, proposed a three-component model that lays
we present a brief historical review of how out the theoretical requirements for having
other scholars have defined moral identity a moral identity: (1) willpower, (2) integrity,
so we can situate Aquino and Reed’s (2002) and (3) moral desire—which he described
model within the broader family of related thus: “willpower is necessary to deal with
concepts and theories that have been widely internal and external obstacles in pursuing
discussed in the literature. one’s long-term objectives; integrity relates
The concept of moral identity first cap- to one’s commitments to the sense of self;
tured the interest of moral psychologists moral desires guide willpower and integ-
after Blasi (1983) introduced the term in his rity and provide them with their moral sig-
self model of moral functioning. Accord- nificance” (Blasi, 2005, p. 72). Blasi (2005)
ing to Blasi, moral identity is an individual argued that these three virtues possess a
difference reflecting the degree to which trait-like stability and are cultivated through
commitment to moral goals and ideals is conscious effort.
characteristic of a person’s sense of self. Although sound theoretical arguments
Blasi suggested that what connects moral exist for treating moral identity as a combi-
identity to behavior is the desire for self- nation of trait-like properties and conscious

133
134 M O R A L I T Y, S O C I A L C O G N I T I O N , A N D I D E N T I T Y

deliberation, there are also limitations to moral identity and behavior are built into
applying this perspective broadly to explain the architecture of all functioning human
moral behavior. There is little doubt that brains. They are part of an interrelated
moral behavior is at least partly regulated set of processes that constitute what dual-­
by conscious effort, but numerous theorists process models of human cognition refer to
have argued that this fails to fully account as System 1 (e.g., Haidt & Bjorklund, 2007;
for the fact that much, perhaps even most, Stanovich & West, 2000). System 1 consists
of what constitutes “everyday morality” is of functions in the brain from which emo-
the result of automatic, intuitive, or habitual tions and quick, automatic, valenced judg-
processes outside of conscious awareness ments arise. It is distinguished and dissoci-
(Haidt, 2001; Lapsley & Narvaez, 2004). ated from System 2, which consists of the
A second limitation of treating moral iden- “higher executive functions” of the brain,
tity as having durable, trait-like properties such as those involved in planning, reason-
is that it fails to account for the multifac- ing, and regulating impulses (for reviews of
eted and protean nature of identity (Aquino, dual-processing theory, see Evans, 2008;
Freeman, Reed, Lim, & Felps, 2009). A so- Kahneman, 2011).
cial cognitive framework of moral identity In addition to being associated with Sys-
can address these limitations and is the basis tem 1 processing, Aquino and Reed’s (2002)
for Aquino and Reed’s (2002) model. conception of moral identity is distinguished
Social cognitive theory (SCT) is a gen- by a number of features that are in accord
eral framework that takes into account the with social cognitive principles. First, the
joint and reciprocal influence of disposi- schema of traits that constitutes a person’s
tional variables and environmental factors moral identity is presumed to vary in its ac-
on behavior (e.g., Bandura, 2001; Cervone cessibility in long-term memory. When this
& Shoda, 1999; Mischel & Mischel, 1976). schema is chronically accessible, it is read-
SCT draws from principles of social cogni- ily and easily made available for processing
tion to capture the stability and accessibility social information and is therefore experi-
of knowledge structures such as identity, as enced as being a more essential aspect of a
well as their dependence on situational in- person’s sense of self. The chronic accessibil-
fluences. Drawing from SCT, Aquino and ity of moral identity can also be referred to
Reed (2002) proposed a conceptualization as its “strength” or “centrality” (Aquino et
of moral identity as a mental representation al., 2009). In SCT, knowledge accessibility
organized around a set of moral trait associ- is a general principle of cognitive function-
ations. Their definition rests on the assump- ing, and it is assumed that more readily ac-
tion that some knowledge structures, such cessible mental constructs have a stronger
as the traits people ascribe to themselves, influence on behavior than less accessible
are more closely connected to one another ones (Higgins, 1996). Because the accessi-
within the associative network of concepts bility of knowledge structures varies across
in long- and short-term memory than others. individuals (Higgins, 1996; Higgins, King,
In their model, the traits that constitute the & Mavin, 1982), a social cognitive model of
mental representation of a person’s moral moral identity allows us to treat it as having
identity are those that correspond to lay con- disposition-like properties (Higgins, 1996).
struals of what it means to be a moral per- A second defining characteristic of Aquino
son (e.g., honesty, kindness, compassion). and Reed’s (2002) model is that regardless
Aquino and Reed’s (2002) model accepts of its level of chronic accessibility, a moral
the notion that moral identity can motivate identity can also be activated (or deactivat-
behavior through the desire to maintain self- ed) by situational cues. A social cognitive
consistency (Mulder & Aquino, 2013). But it model treats moral identity as a construct
also allows for the possibility of other, more that can be made more or less salient at any
generic processes that are not connected to given time. Accordingly, a person whose
moral functioning, do not require conscious moral identity is not chronically accessible
deliberation, and are not driven by a con- can still be prompted by situational cues
sistency motive to explain moral behavior. to temporarily experience a strong moral
These processes are generic insofar as the identity. This, in turn, can motivate the per-
cognitive operations that mediate between son to behave more morally (Bargh, Bond,
 A Social Cognitive Model of Moral Identity 135

Lombardi, & Tota, 1986). Conversely, a identity symbolization can sometimes be


person whose moral identity is chronically driven by impression management or instru-
accessible may be influenced by situational mental motives (Winterich, Aquino, Mittal,
factors to momentarily lose sense of this & Schwartz, 2013), and therefore may not
identity, which diminishes its motivational validly represent a person’s phenomenologi-
power (Stryker, 1980). Because people must cal experience of “having” a moral identity.
balance multiple and sometimes competing The distinction between moral identity in-
identities, of which only a subset known as ternalization and symbolization is consistent
the “working self-concept” is activated at with the view that people are simultaneously
any given time (Markus & Kunda, 1986), both agents and actors (Frimer, Schaefer, &
the influence of any one of these identities Oakes, 2014). Whereas the agentic self is
on behavior is strongest when that particu- private and therefore more prone to being
lar identity is relatively more salient (Carver driven by selfish motives that increase a per-
& Scheier, 1998; Skitka, 2003). Together, son’s chances for survival, the self as actor
the accessibility of moral identity and its re- recognizes that survival is also facilitated by
sponsiveness to situational cues allows this being accepted into social groups and gain-
social cognitive conception to account for ing the benefits of mutually beneficial ex-
both the intraindividual stability and coher- change (Frimer et al., 2014). Thus the self as
ence of a moral character and the variability actor is motivated to behave prosocially and
of moral behavior across situations (Aquino to support goals to enhance social attrac-
et al., 2009; Lapsley & Narvaez, 2004). It tiveness, even if the self as agent might want
also allows for the possibility of conceptual- to do otherwise. We can incorporate Aquino
izing moral identity as a state that exhibits and Reed’s (2002) two-dimensional model
within-person variation, which is consistent of moral identity into this dualistic descrip-
with how some scholars have described per- tion to suggest that, although the agentic self
sonality (Fleeson, 2004). may indeed be primarily egoistic, a highly
A final defining feature of Aquino and accessible mental representation of a private
Reed’s (2002) social cognitive model is that moral self in working memory (e.g., being
it conforms to notions of the self proposed high in moral identity internalization) can
by other identity theorists, who suggest that moderate this tendency for selfishness (Win-
it has both a private and a public aspect (e.g., terich, Mittal, & Aquino, 2014). Similarly,
Fenigstein, Scheier, & Buss, 1975; James, the motivation to engage in moral identity
1890/1950; Schlenker, 1980). Aquino and symbolization can lead to prosocial behav-
Reed (2002) refer to these dimensions of iors (Winterich et al., 2014), although in this
moral identity as internalization and sym- case the underlying goal of increasing one’s
bolization, respectively. Internalization is chances of being accepted into and gaining
closest to what Blasi and like-minded theo- status within groups may be more egoistic.
rists mean by moral identity because it re- Thus, moral identity symbolization and the
flects people’s subjective experience that it self as actor may be seen as conceptually co-
is central to their overall self-concept. It is terminous.
this relatively enduring association between Aquino and Reed’s (2002) social cognitive
people’s sense of self and the mental repre- model is situated within a broader literature
sentation of their moral character that links that can be divided into three general cat-
the internalized aspect of moral identity to egories. These categories range from “flex-
moral action. The symbolization dimension ible” to “firm” to “strong” views of what
reflects people’s tendency to express their moral identity is and how it influences moral
moral identity through outward actions in behavior. A flexible view recognizes the role
the world. Although such expressions have of individual differences, yet places signifi-
been considered an indicator of having a cant emphasis on the effect of situational
particular identity (e.g., Erikson, 1964) or a factors on the processes that motivate moral
means of self-verifying an identity (Swann, behavior. A firm view gives relatively less at-
1983), Aquino and Reed (2002) are agnostic tention to situational cues, placing primary
about whether symbolization reveals any- emphasis on individual differences in moral
thing about the “authenticity” of moral iden- identity to explain moral behavior. Never-
tity. Indeed, it has been suggested that moral theless, it leaves open the possibility that
136 M O R A L I T Y, S O C I A L C O G N I T I O N , A N D I D E N T I T Y

situational factors can sometimes lead peo- Firm views of moral identity place prima-
ple to exhibit behavior that is the product of ry emphasis on individual differences and
nondeliberative, unconscious processes that less on the conscious, deliberative processes
are partly driven by moral identity. Finally, that lead to its emergence. Most representa-
a strong view also places primary emphasis tive of this perspective is the work of Walker
on individual differences, yet unlike the firm and Frimer (2007), who contend that moral
view it places considerably more importance judgment is necessary but ultimately inad-
on the conscious, deliberative processes that equate in accounting for moral behavior. In-
lead people to have a moral identity in the stead, they argue that individual-difference
first place. variables have considerably more explana-
Since Aquino and Reed’s (2002) social tory power. Their view is firm insofar as
cognitive model assumes that behavior is the personality traits upon which they place
the product of an interplay between dispo- such heavy reliance are relatively fixed and
sitional traits and situational cues, resulting stable; however, it falls short of being strong
in different behaviors in different contexts, to the extent that it does not emphasize how
it fits into the flexible category. Another moral identity becomes incorporated into
model that falls into this category is Laps- personality.
ley and Narvaez’s (2004) model of “moral Strong conceptions of moral identity pro-
personality,” which is substantially similar vide this explanation. Strong views also
to Aquino and Reed’s (2002), although it place great emphasis on the role of reflec-
does not explicitly recognize the internaliza- tion, reasoning about morality, and the con-
tion and symbolization dimensions of moral struction of narratives that give meaning and
identity. Both models draw from the notion coherence to people’s behavior over time.
that people hold prototypes (Walker & Pitts, For example, Blasi (2005)—whose work we
1998) of the moral character. consider emblematic of the strong view—
From a social cognitive perspective, these contends that moral action is a function of
prototypes help people evaluate new stimuli the extent to which morality is important to
(Kahneman & Frederick, 2005) and make the self-concept, which, in turn, he saw as
sense of their moral landscape. Aquino and an individual difference with trait-like prop-
Reed (2002) suggest that when a distinct erties. Similarly, Colby and Damon (1992)
image of a moral prototype is brought to recognize four developmental processes
mind, it can lead people to act as this proto- that combine personality traits and a strong
type would in the same situation (Kihlstrom “commitment” to moral advancement: (1) a
& Klein, 1994). This idea raises the possibil- continuing capacity for change; (2) certainty
ity that moral identity may function as a heu- about moral values and principles, balanced
ristic (O’Reilly, Aquino, & Skarlicki, 2016). by open-mindedness and truth seeking; (3)
Heuristics are cognitive shortcuts that facili- positivity, humility, love, and faith; and (4)
tate “fast and frugal” ways of thinking, and an identity that fuses the personal with the
it has been suggested that they can elicit in- moral and emphasizes the importance of
tuitive judgments about moral “wrongness” integrity. Finally, McAdams (2008) unites
(Gigerenzer, 2010; Sinnott-Armstrong, dispositional traits, characteristic adapta-
Young, & Cushman, 2010; Sunstein, 2005). tions (e.g., motivational, developmental, and
If moral identity is indeed a form of moral strategic aspects of personality evidenced in
prototype (Walker & Pitts, 1998), then, like particular situations), and life narratives to
other prototypes, it can influence how people explain moral behavior. Life narratives are
behave at the neurochemical level (Reynolds, seen as psychosocial constructions of per-
2006). Reynolds (2006) proposed that pro- sonal identity over which people have a sub-
totypes are not mere metaphors but, rather, stantial amount of conscious dominion.
actual neurochemical imprints used to form Rather than seeing the firm and strong
quick, intuitive judgments. Yet, however views as competing or incompatible with
prototypes are conceived, what binds flex- Aquino and Reed’s (2002) more flexible
ible theories of moral identity is a recogni- model, we suggest that they can be recon-
tion that moral behavior is often the result of ciled by recognizing the role and explana-
automatic, intuitive processes that lie outside tory value of each. A flexible view captures
of conscious awareness. moral identity’s fluidity, malleability, and
 A Social Cognitive Model of Moral Identity 137

computational efficiency. We maintain that of doing so increase (Reed, Kay, Finnel,


this is the default operative mechanism for Aquino, & Levy, 2016).
how moral identity influences behavior for Similar effects have also been found when
the typical person in most situations. A moral identity is made temporarily salient
firm view, by contrast, may be appropriate by situational cues. For example, activating
in considering the morally gifted, who are moral identity leads people to be more will-
dispositionally wired by a combination of ing to sacrifice their own financial interests
natural endowments, life experiences, and for the benefit of others (Aquino et al., 2009)
intentional practice to be more concerned and be less aversive to donating time over
about morality. These people may take their money to prosocial causes, even when doing
predisposition toward moral behavior for so is subjectively unpleasant (Reed et al.,
granted and therefore act morally in most 2016). Conversely, it has been shown that
situations without necessarily working con- making moral identity less salient increases
sciously to enhance their moral orientation the likelihood of self-interested behavior.
toward the world. Finally, we maintain that For example, in one study, financial perfor-
strong views of moral identity may be more mance incentives reduced moral identity sa-
efficacious for explaining the behavior of lience and led people to be more deceitful in
true moral exemplars whose commitment business negotiations (Aquino et al., 2009).
to moral goals and projects is enduring and Finally, moral identity has also been
consistent. These people have a natural shown to influence moral and immoral be-
predisposition to act morally, but they also havior by amplifying or dampening the ef-
place a considerable amount of value and ef- fects of other motivators. For example, peo-
fort on developing their moral selves. ple whose moral identity is either chronically
Although we see each of these conceptions accessible or temporarily activated are more
as having its own place, it must be recog- likely to act prosocially after experiencing a
nized that a significant body of empirical state of moral elevation (Aquino, McFerran,
evidence is growing to support the flexible & Laven, 2011). Moral identity centrality
social cognitive model put forth by Aquino has also been shown to motivate potential
and Reed (2002). Since they proposed their donors to give more money to charities when
model of moral identity over a decade ago, they are perceived to be in alignment with
numerous studies have been conducted that the donors’ political identity (Winterich,
show relationships between the chronic ac- Zhang, & Mittal, 2012). Conversely, it has
cessibility of moral identity, its temporary been found that moral identity salience de-
activation, and a host of morally relevant creases the tendency of strong adherents
outcomes. Extensive reviews have been con- to binding ingroup values (e.g., obedience,
ducted on this body of research elsewhere loyalty, and purity) to reduce their support
(e.g., Boegershausen, Aquino, & Reed, for the torture of outgroup members (Smith,
2015; Shao, Aquino, & Freeman, 2008), so Aquino, Koleva, & Graham, 2014).
we shall canvass only a select sample of the Although there is significant empirical
empirical evidence that supports their view. support for Aquino and Reed’s (2002) social
Studies show that the chronic accessibil- cognitive model of moral identity, a few in-
ity of moral identity, as measured by Aquino consistent findings in the literature cast doubt
and Reed’s (2002) scale, is positively related on the universality of some of its underly-
to a host of prosocial behaviors. For ex- ing premises. For example, activating moral
ample, it has been linked to higher levels of identity has been shown to both increase
volunteerism (Aquino & Reed, 2002; Wint- and decrease moral behavior. Although the
erich et al., 2013), charitable giving (Reed, preponderance of the evidence suggests that
Aquino, & Levy, 2007), and organizational priming moral identity increases prosocial
citizenship behavior (McFerran, Aquino, behavior (Aquino et al., 2009; Reed et al.,
& Duffy, 2010). It has also been associated 2007), at least one study has found that it
with higher levels of honesty in economic generates a moral licensing effect that leads
games (Mulder & Aquino, 2013). Most re- to a decrease in prosocial behavior (Sachde-
cently, it has been shown to reduce people’s va, Iliev, & Medin, 2009). One recent study
aversion to giving time over money to proso- further showed an inconsistency in moral
cial causes, even as the psychological costs priming, with a heightened salience of moral
138 M O R A L I T Y, S O C I A L C O G N I T I O N , A N D I D E N T I T Y

identity leading to higher intentions to do- as well as in their external words and public
nate time over money to charitable causes, behaviors. Such individuals may be thought
yet no significant difference when it comes of as having “congruent” moral identities.
to donation behavior (Reed et al., 2016). Ac- By contrast, those who are high (low) in in-
cordingly, it is still unclear when and under ternalization and low (high) in symboliza-
what circumstances activating moral iden- tion may be concerned (indifferent) about
tity in the working self-concept increases or morality in their internal thoughts and
decreases prosocial behavior, or when it has private actions yet indifferent (concerned)
any effect at all. Future research is required about it in their external words and public
to explain these inconsistencies and clarify behaviors. Such individuals may be thought
the conditions under which moral priming is of as having “incongruent” moral identities.
and is not effective. Researchers in this field are starting to rec-
Further questions have been raised with ognize the important difference these moral
respect to the association of moral identity identity profiles can make. For example,
centrality and behaviors following deceit. Rupp, Shao, Thornton, and Skarlicki (2013)
For example, one study showed that high theorized that morally imbued actions such
moral identifiers prefer to compensate for as corporate social responsibility may have
lying with subsequent truth telling, as op- a more profound influence on people higher
posed to behaving consistently with their in internalization than symbolization. In
prior deceit (Mulder & Aquino, 2013). addition, Winterich and colleagues (2013)
However, this was shown to be the case only showed that a promise of public recognition
with subsequent behaviors that are qualita- can serve to motivate people high in sym-
tively different from past behaviors, and only bolization to volunteer their time, but only
when it involved actively lying as opposed when internalization is low.
to concealing a truth. Moreover, such com- In the future, researchers should continue
pensatory behavior was demonstrated only to explore what different combinations of
with respect to lying and failed to replicate moral identity internalization and symbol-
in the case of cheating (Mulder & Aquino, ization reveal about underlying goals and
2013). A host of questions therefore remain motivations, as well as the behaviors that
about the effects of prior immoral behavior flow from them. Indeed, this more nuanced
on subsequent moral behavior when moral approach may help shed light on some of
identity has high centrality. Further research the inconsistencies in the literature. For ex-
is required to answer these questions and ample, whether priming moral identity in-
clarify the impact of moral identity central- creases or decreases prosocial behavior may
ity on different types of moral behavior. depend not only on the nature of the moral
We contend that Aquino and Reed’s identity profile being primed but also on the
(2002) model is well suited for investigat- behavior in question (e.g., whether or not it
ing such questions, as it allows researchers yields public recognition).
to work with moral identities not only of To summarize, with a framework that rec-
different degrees but also of different types. ognizes moral cognition and behavior to be
For example, bifurcating each dimension of the product of the intuitive, generic psycho-
moral identity suggests a four-part typology logical processes described in this chapter,
of moral identity profiles: (1) low internaliza- Aquino and Reed’s (2002) social cognitive
tion and low symbolization; (2) low internal- model of moral identity is uniquely suited to
ization and high symbolization; (3) high in- explain how moral behavior is characterized
ternalization and low symbolization; and (4) both by cross-situational stability and coher-
high internalization and high symbolization. ence and by dynamic flexibility. It is unique
Each profile represents a different arrange- insofar as it recognizes that moral behavior
ment of goals and motivations, and therefore is the result of a complex interplay of indi-
suggests a different orientation toward act- vidual differences, situational contingencies,
ing morally. For example, individuals who and prior behavior. This flexible model of
are high (low) in both moral identity inter- moral cognition and behavior is likely to
nalization and symbolization may be consis- prove helpful in resolving some of the linger-
tently more (less) concerned with morality in ing issues in the still-nascent moral identity
their internal thoughts and private actions, literature. At the same time, as researchers
 A Social Cognitive Model of Moral Identity 139

continue to work with the model, they are In D. Cervone & Y. Shoda (Eds.), The coher-
sure to reveal further inconsistencies and ence of personality: Social-cognitive bases
raise more questions. These would be posi- of consistency, variability, and organization
tive developments for the scientific study of (pp. 3–33). New York: Guilford Press.
Colby, A., & Damon, W. (1992). Some do care:
morality, for if the foundational assump-
Contemporary lives of moral commitment.
tions of Aquino and Reed’s (2002) model are New York: Free Press.
falsified or otherwise brought into question, Damon, W. (1984). Self-understanding and
then refinements can be made to enhance its moral development from childhood to ado-
explanatory power. Until then, the data thus lescence. In W. M. Kurtines & J. L. Gewirtz
far suggest that it continues to be a valuable (Eds.), Morality, moral behavior, and moral
model for exploring how human beings nav- development (pp. 109–127). New York: Wiley.
igate the fuzzy moral terrain of everyday life. Erikson, E. H. (1964). Insight and responsibility.
New York: Norton.
Evans, J. B. T. (2008). Dual-processing accounts
REFERENCES of reasoning, judgment, and social cognition.
Annual Review of Psychology, 59, 255–278.
Aquino, K., Freeman, D., Reed, A., II, Lim, V. K. Fenigstein, A., Scheier, M. F., & Buss, A. H.
G., & Felps, W. (2009). Testing a social-cog- (1975). Public and private self-consciousness:
nitive model of moral behavior: The interac- Assessment and theory. Journal of Consulting
tive influence of situations and moral identity and Clinical Psychology, 43, 522–527.
centrality. Journal of Personality and Social Fleeson, W. (2004). Moving personality beyond
Psychology, 97(1), 123–141. the person–situation debate: The challenge
Aquino, K., McFerran, B., & Laven, M. (2011). and opportunity of within-person variability.
Moral identity and the experience of moral Current Directions in Psychological Science,
elevation in response to acts of uncommon 13(2), 83–87.
goodness. Journal of Personality and Social Frimer, J. A., Schaefer, N. K., & Oakes, H.
Psychology, 100, 703–718. (2014). Moral actor, selfish agent. Journal of
Aquino, K., & Reed, A., II. (2002). The self-im- Personality and Social Psychology, 106(5),
portance of moral identity. Journal of Person- 790–802.
ality and Social Psychology, 83, 1423–1440. Gigerenzer, G. (2010). Moral satisficing: Re-
Bandura, A. (2001). Social cognitive theory: An thinking moral behavior as bounded rational-
agentic perspective. Annual Review of Psy- ity. Topics in Cognitive Science, 2, 528–554.
chology, 52, 1–26. Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional dog and its ra-
Bargh, J. A., Bond, R. N., Lombardi, W. J., & tional tail: A social intuitionist approach
Tota, M. E. (1986). The additive nature of to moral judgment. Psychological Review,
chronic and temporary sources of construct 108(4), 814–834.
accessibility. Journal of Personality and Social Haidt, J., & Bjorklund, F. (2007). Social intu-
Psychology, 50(5), 869–878. itionists answer six questions about morality.
Bergman, R. (2004). Identity as motivation: To- In W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral psychol-
ward a theory of the moral self. In D. K. Laps- ogy: Vol. 2. The cognitive science of morality
ley & D. Narvaez (Eds.), Moral development, (pp. 181–217). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
self, and identity (pp. 21–46). Mahwah, NJ: Higgins, E. T. (1996). The “self-digest”: Self-
Erlbaum. knowledge serving self-regulatory functions.
Blasi, A. (1983). Moral cognition and moral ac- Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
tion: A theoretical perspective. Developmen- 71(6), 1062–1083.
tal Review, 3, 178–210. Higgins, E. T., King, G. A., & Mavin, G. H.
Blasi, A. (2005). Moral character: A psychologi- (1982). Individual construct accessibility and
cal approach. In D. K. Lapsley & F. C. Power subjective impressions and recall. Journal of
(Eds.), Character psychology and character Personality and Social Psychology, 43, 35–47.
education (pp. 67–100). Notre Dame, IN: Uni- James, W. (1950). The principles of psychology.
versity of Notre Dame Press. New York: Dover. (Original work published
Boegershausen, J., Aquino, K., Reed, A., II. 1890)
(2015). Moral identity. Current Opinion in Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking fast and slow.
Psychology, 6, 162–166. Toronto, Ontario: Random House Canada.
Carver, C. S., & Scheier, M. F. (1998). On the Kahneman, D., & Frederick, S. (2005). A model
self-regulation of behavior. New York: Cam- of heuristic judgment. In K. J. Holyoak & R.
bridge University Press. G. Morrison (Eds.), The Cambridge handbook
Cervone, D., & Shoda, Y. (1999). Social-cogni- of thinking and reasoning (pp. 109–127).
tive theories and the coherence of personality. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
140 M O R A L I T Y, S O C I A L C O G N I T I O N , A N D I D E N T I T Y

Kihlstrom, J. F., & Klein, S. B. (1994). The self Schlenker, B. R. (1980). Impression manage-
as a knowledge structure. In R. S. Wyer, Jr. & ment: The self-concept, social identity and in-
K. Thomas (Eds.), Handbook of socialization terpersonal relations. Monterey, CA: Brooks/
theory and research (pp. 347–480). Chicago: Cole.
Rand McNally. Shao, R., Aquino, K., & Freeman, D. (2008). Be-
Lapsley, D. K., & Narvaez, D. (2004). A social- yond moral reasoning: A review of moral identi-
cognitive approach to the moral personality. ty research and its implications for business eth-
In D. K. Lapsley & D. Narvaez (Eds.), Moral ics. Business Ethics Quarterly, 18(4), 513–540.
development, self, and identity (pp. 189–212). Sinnott-Armstrong, W., Young, L., & Cushman,
Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. F. (2010). Moral intuitions. In J. M. Doris &
Markus, H., & Kunda, Z. (1986). Stability and the Moral Psychology Research Group (Eds.),
malleability of the self-concept. Journal of Per- The moral psychology handbook (pp. 246–
sonality and Social Psychology, 51, 858–866. 272). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
McAdams, D. P. (2008). Personal narratives and Skitka, L. J. (2003). Of different minds: An ac-
the life story. In O. P. John, R. W. Robins, & cessible identity model of justice reasoning.
L. A. Pervin (Eds.), Handbook of personality: Personality and Social Psychology Review, 7,
Theory and research (3rd ed., pp. 242–262). 286–297.
New York: Guilford Press. Smith, I. H., Aquino, K., Koleva, S., & Graham,
McFerran, B., Aquino, K., & Duffy, M. (2010). J. (2014). The moral ties that bind . . . Even
How personality and moral identity relate to to out-groups: The interactive effect of moral
individuals’ ethical ideology. Business Ethics identity and the binding moral foundations.
Quarterly, 20(1), 35–56. Psychological Science, 25(8), 1554–1562.
Mischel, W., & Mischel, H. N. (1976). A cogni- Stanovich, K. E., & West, R. F. (2000). Individ-
tive social-learning approach to morality and ual differences in reasoning: Implications for
self-regulation. In T. Lickona (Ed.), Moral de- the rationality debate. Behavioral and Brain
velopment and behavior (pp. 84–107). New Sciences, 23, 645–665.
York: Holt, Rinehart & Winston. Stryker, S. (1980). Symbolic interactionism: A
Mulder, L. B., & Aquino, K. A. (2013). The role social structural version. Menlo Park, CA:
of moral identity in the aftermath of dishon- Benjamin/Cummings.
esty. Organizational Behavior and Human Sunstein, C. R. (2005). Moral heuristics. Behav-
Decision Processes, 121, 219–230. ioral and Brain Sciences, 28(4), 531–573.
O’Reilly, J., Aquino, K., & Skarlicki, D. P. Swann, W. B., Jr. (1983). Self-verification: Bring-
(2016). The lives of others: Third parties’ re- ing social reality into harmony with the self.
sponses to others’ injustice. Journal of Applied In J. Suls & A. G. Greenwald (Eds.), Social
Psychology, 101(2), 171–189. psychological perspectives on the self (Vol. 2,
Reed, A., II, Aquino, K., & Levy, E. (2007). pp. 33–66). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Moral identity and judgments of charitable be- Walker, L. J., & Frimer, J. A. (2007). Moral
haviors. Journal of Marketing, 71, 178–193. personality of brave and caring exemplars.
Reed, A., II, Kay, A., Finnel, S., Aquino, K., & Personality Processes and Individual Differ-
Levy, E. (2016). I don’t want the money, I just ences, 93(5), 845–860.
want your time: How moral identity over- Walker, L. J., & Pitts, R. C. (1998). Naturalistic
comes the aversion to giving time to pro-social conceptions of moral maturity. Developmen-
causes. Journal of Personality and Social Psy- tal Psychology, 34, 403–419.
chology, 110(3), 435–457. Winterich, K. P., Aquino, K., Mittal, V., &
Reynolds, S. J. (2006). A neurocognitive model Schwartz, R. (2013). When moral identity
of the ethical decision-making process: Impli- symbolization motivates prosocial behavior:
cations for study and practice. Journal of Ap- The role of recognition and moral identity in-
plied Psychology, 91(4), 737–748. ternalization. Journal of Applied Psychology,
Rupp, D. H., Shao, R., Thornton, M. A., & 98(5), 759–770.
Skarlicki, D. P. (2013). Applicants’ and em- Winterich, K. P., Mittal, V., & Aquino, K. (2013).
ployees’ reactions to corporate social respon- When does recognition increase charitable be-
sibility: The moderating effects of first-party havior?: Toward a moral identity-based model.
justice perceptions and moral identity. Person- Journal of Marketing, 77(3), 121–134.
nel Psychology, 66, 895–933. Winterich, K. P., Zhang, Y., & Mittal, V. (2012).
Sachdeva, S., Iliev, R., & Medin, D. L. (2009). How political identity and charity position-
Sinning saints and saintly sinners: The para- ing increase donations: Insights from moral
dox of moral self-regulation. Psychological foundations theory. International Journal of
Science, 20(4), 523–528. Research in Marketing, 29, 346–354.
C H A P T E R 15

Identity Is Essentially Moral

Nina Strohminger

What explains the deep connection between morality and the folk
concept of personal identity?

This relationship may seem mysterious, until we recognize that iden‑


tity perception is primarily a process for tracking moral agents, rather
than differentiating individuals.

Identity takes up a vast amount of real estate that break it—are crucial for understanding
in the field of psychology. Broadly speak- how people think about personal identity.
ing, identity is how you think of yourself The puzzle of diachronic identity is well
and other people. It concerns what features illustrated by conflicting accounts of what
go into, collectively, making someone who happens to identity in the wake of brain
they are. The term identity often evokes cat- damage. Consider the infamous case of
egories of social membership: gender, race, Phineas Gage, who survived a freak accident
class, sexual orientation, and so on. But it’s that saw a metal rod the size of a javelin
a big space; a lot goes into our identities. perforate his skull. Though his intellectual
There is also, for instance, our bodies and abilities remained intact, Gage became so
life histories and intellect and character. intemperate and volatile that his friends said
The focus of this chapter is one aspect of “Gage was no longer Gage” (Macmillan,
identity in particular: the puzzle of diachron- 2000). Contrast this with the actor Gene
ic identity. Something maintains diachronic Wilder, who passed away of Alzheimer’s
identity if it continues to be the same with disease in 2016. His nephew insisted that
itself over time. The puzzle is this: How is it the illness “never stole his ability to rec-
that a person can change radically over time, ognize those that were closest to him, nor
yet seem to be the same person as before? took command of his central-gentle-life af-
And how is it that relatively minor tweaks firming core personality. It took enough, but
can lead a person to seem fundamentally al- not that” (Miller, 2016). Wilder, even at his
tered, even unrecognizable? most incapacitated, remained Wilder until
By some lights, this is a philosophical his dying day.
question, but it is also a psychological one. There is no reason to be coy about our
The factors that give rise to the sense of iden- punchline, particularly as it is embedded in
tity continuity over time—and the factors the title and preamble of this chapter. Emerg-

141
142 M O R A L I T Y, S O C I A L C O G N I T I O N , A N D I D E N T I T Y

ing research suggests that the greatest factor grandiose versions of this idea show up in
in establishing diachronic personal identity modern psychology, in the form of theories
is the continuity of moral capacities. In this that identity emerges from a complex inter-
chapter, I go over the evidence for this claim play between narrative structure and dispo-
and suggest a possible explanation. sition (McAdams & Manczak, 2015).
Meanwhile, the past century of social psy-
chology has been grappling with a very dif-
Some History ferent notion of personal identity, one that
understands it in contrast with the group
For the past few hundred years, most discus- (Festinger, 1954; Erikson, 1959; Diener,
sions of diachronic personal identity have 1979; Brewer, 1991). Whereas group iden-
revolved around the putative importance of tity consists of the properties that bind us
memory. Under this view, identity unwinds to others, individual identity is what sets
from the spool of continuous experience, us apart: our unique set of hobbies, pref-
with autobiographical memory as its most erences, quirks, and dispositions. What
obvious manifestation. makes you you is what allows you to be
John Locke (1690/2009), generally con- picked out of the crowd (Nelson & Miller,
sidered the progenitor of this view, provides 1995; ­ Vignoles, Chryssochoou, & Break-
the following thought experiment: “Should well, 2000; Blanton & Christie, 2003). This
the soul of a prince, carrying with it the con- view is nicely captured by the old Far Side
sciousness of the prince’s past life, enter and cartoon where a penguin stands in a sea of
inform the body of a cobbler everyone sees indistinguishable penguins, belting out “I
he [the cobbler] would be the same person just gotta be me-ee-eee!” For humans, to be
with the prince, accountable only for the robbed of individuating characteristics is to
prince’s actions” (Book II, Ch. 27, Sec. 15). be thrown into an unmitigated identity di-
Everyone sees this, he says: It is not only saster (Erikson, 1959).
self-evident, but a view widely shared. This The idea that morality might be at the
is a common rhetorical device in philosophy. heart of personal identity is both new and
The problem is, when phrased this way—as profoundly ancient. Hints of it permeate ev-
a matter of universally held human intu- eryday thinking under a variety of guises.
ition—the claim ceases being only a meta- Perhaps the most compelling of these is how
physical one and becomes a scientific one various religious traditions characterize the
as well. Is this really how the typical person self. In Abrahamic religions, the pith of the
understands identity? self is commonly known as the soul. The
Not one to sit out on the important de- soul is the immaterial, eternal essence of a
bates, William James (1891) arrived at a person that survives the body after death
similar conclusion: “If a man wakes up one and lends each person their unique identity.
fine day unable to recall any of his past ex- It also happens to be the seat of the moral
periences, so that he has to learn his biog- conscience. (In an old episode of The Simp-
raphy afresh he feels, and he says, that he sons, Bart sells his soul for $5. He soon dis-
is a changed person” (p. 336). A century covers that automatic doors fail to open for
later, the neurologist Oliver Sacks (1985) him, jokes no longer elicit mirth, and pets
ponders this question when documenting recoil at his touch, as if he were a monster.)
a patient with Korsakov’s syndrome. The Certain Eastern religions (such as Hindu-
man’s amnesia was so severe that he had lost ism and Jainism) have a similar concept, the
not only his entire past life but also his abil- atman. The atman represents the true self of
ity to add new memories. He was bereft of a person, in spiritual form. It is not just any
any narrative structure to hold the arc of his part of a person’s essence, but their moral
existence together. “One tended to speak of center especially. The atman is the part of
him, instinctively, as a spiritual casualty—a the self that gets reincarnated from one life
‘lost soul’: was it possible that he had been to the next. Personal enlightenment deter-
‘de-souled’ by a disease?” (p. 37).1 To rob mines whether the atman will be reincarnat-
someone of his memories is to snuff out his ed into something great, like a goddess, or
personhood, indeed his very existence. Less something punitive, like a slug. The atman
 Identity Is Essentially Moral 143

is thus strongly associated with moral and as adult Nina Strohminger, even though she
spiritual wisdom. looks quite different and is not even made of
When social psychologists first began the same cellular matter (Buchholz, Druid,
looking at person perception several de- & Frisén, 2005). And while the bloated Elvis
cades ago, they noticed a curious pattern. of the 1970s bore little resemblance to the
The most salient properties of a person—the dreamboat Elvis of 20 years prior, we per-
ones that leave the strongest impression on ceive them to be the same person, in a way
observers—are those that relate to interper- that even the most uncanny Elvis imperson-
sonal warmth (Anderson, 1968; Wojciszke, ator can’t match (Sternberg, Chawarski, &
Bazinska, & Jaworski, 1998). More detailed Allbritton, 1998). The persisting essence of
analyses reveal that, within the wide um- persons underlies the superstition that the
brella of warmth traits (a category that in- psychological traits of organ donors can
cludes sense of humor and extroversion), it manifest in transplant recipients (Sylvia &
is moral traits, like honesty and compassion, Novak, 1997; Inspector, Kutz, & David,
that are pulling most of that weight (Bram- 2004; Meyer, Leslie, Gelman, & Stilwell,
billa, Rusconi, Sacchi, & Cherubini, 2011; 2013) and seeps into beliefs about how souls
Goodwin, Piazza, & Rozin, 2014). are reincarnated into new bodies (Bloom &
Of course, what makes us like someone Gelman, 2008).
is not interchangeable with diachronic iden- The principle of psychological essential-
tity and need not draw on the same set of ism, therefore, yields two important points.
personal features. Likewise, cross-cultural It shows that we can perceive underlying
religious texts offer only the broadest in- constancy in spite of apparent change, and
sinuations about folk intuitions of identity. it suggests a mechanism for doing so (i.e., by
Ultimately, we must turn to direct empirical positing an underlying essence). Further, if
evidence. psychological essentialism is applied to indi-
vidual persons, this suggests that some per-
sonal traits will be treated as identity confer-
A Brief Detour: Essentialism ring, whereas others will be more ancillary.

Before continuing, it is worth taking a mo-


ment to consider the cognitive mechanism Some Empirical Evidence
that allows us to make sense of identity
transformations in the first place: essential- One way of getting at folk conceptions of
ism. identity is to plumb folk intuitions about the
Psychological essentialism refers to the soul. As noted above, the Western notion of
tendency to infer underlying, often hidden, the soul represents a kind of placeholder for
properties in an object that explain its be- the concept of the self. When asked about
havior and confer its underlying nature or which traits would transfer when a soul
“essence” (Medin & Ortony, 1989; Gelman, switches bodies, participants rank moral
2003). Although essentialism was originally traits as more likely to survive the transition
used to explain how people reason about than memories or individuating preferences
natural kinds (Keil, 1989; Gelman & Well- like musical taste and career ambitions, as
man, 1991), it permeates reasoning about well as other mental and physical features
social categories (Taylor, 1996; Hirschfeld, (Strohminger & Nichols, 2014). Similarly,
1995), artifacts (Newman, Diesendruck, when asked about which traits would be
& Bloom, 2011), and personality (Haslam, reincarnated into the next life, participants
Bastian, & Bissett, 2004). Essentialism is select moral traits (like honesty, trustwor-
what explains our ability to see that an ugly thiness, and generosity) more often than
duckling and the swan it turns into are the personality traits (like intelligence, sense
same individual. of humor, and creativity; Strohminger &
As it is with cygnets, so it is with humans. Nichols, 2014). This effect holds cross-
Persons seem to have an essence that endures culturally. When Hindu Indians are asked
across time and physical changes. We con- which traits would transfer with the soul,
sider baby Nina Strohminger to be the same they consistently rate moral traits more like-
144 M O R A L I T Y, S O C I A L C O G N I T I O N , A N D I D E N T I T Y

ly than other mental traits (Garfield, Nich- than those with Alzheimer’s, whose impair-
ols, Rai, & Strohminger, 2015; Nichols, ments are primarily memory-based; both re-
Strohminger, Rai, & Garfield, 2016). Even sult in more perceived identity change than
Buddhist Tibetans, who expressly deny the amyotrophic lateral sclerosis (ALS), a neu-
existence of the self or atman, believe that rodegenerative disease whose symptoms are
moral traits are most likely to survive a soul primarily motor and noncognitive. Not only
switch. And while there are some systematic that, but deterioration of the moral faculty
cross-­cultural differences in characterizing across all three of these diseases was nearly
the underlying self, the belief that it is fun- the only impairment that altered perceived
damentally moral appears to be cross-cul- identity. Even in real cases of psychological
turally robust (Kung, Eibach, & Grossman, change, morality has a singular impact on
2016; De Freitas et al., in press). perceived identity continuity.
Nor is this intuition limited to religious be- There is a twist here. Diachronic identity
liefs about the nature of the soul. When asked is not simply moral, but appears to be espe-
how different someone would be if they took cially biased toward the morally good (New-
a pill that altered one of a variety of mental man, Knobe, & Bloom, 2014; Strohminger,
traits—memories, personality, preferences, Newman, & Knobe, in press). For example,
perceptual abilities, and so on—participants Tobia (2016) finds that a Phineas Gage-type
responded that a person would be the most person is seen as more radically transformed
fundamentally changed if he or she took a when an accident robs him of a moral com-
drug that altered moral traits or behaviors, pass than when it bequeaths him with one.
such as a pill that cured psychopathy or People seem to incorporate this into their
made someone into a thief (Strohminger & naive beliefs about how personal growth
Nichols, 2014). This judgment is just as true happens over the lifespan. Whereas nega-
for assessments of one’s own identity as it is tive moral changes give rise to a dramatic
for that of others (Heiphetz, Strohminger, & identity rupture, positive changes are seen
Young, 2017). The privileging of moral traits as merely revealing an underlying capacity
emerges in childhood. Eight- to 10-year-olds that was there all along (Molouki & Bartels,
report that a person would be most radically 2017). Perhaps this is why improvements to
changed if they took a pill that altered uni- the self are so often seen as “discoveries”
versally held moral beliefs than other sorts (Schlegel, Vess, & Arndt, 2012).
of beliefs or preferences (Heiphetz, Strohm-
inger, Young, & Gelman, 2016). Morality is
not only central to identity; it is also seen as Some Certain Uncertainties
the most causally central feature of the mind
(Chen, Urminsky, & Bartels, 2016). This is Earlier, we stated that essentialism is what
consistent with the more general rule that allows us to perceive stasis in the face of
the essential properties of a concept tend to change. But when the sense of diachronic
be causally central (Sloman, Love, & Ahn, identity breaks—most often, and most eas-
1998). ily, when moral features change—very little
Nowhere is the evidence for the moral is known about this mechanism. One pos-
self more unequivocal than in actual cases sibility is that, in determining what matters
of psychological change. Strohminger and for the identity of others, people draw on
Nichols (2015) surveyed family members what they personally value most. This ac-
of people with different forms of neurode- count would be consistent with the more
generative disease, asking them questions general tendency to project internal knowl-
about identity change across the disease edge onto external targets, such as the
progression—for instance, whether the pa- false consensus effect (Krueger & Clement,
tient ever seems like a stranger to them, or 1994). A projective account is supported by
whether the patient seems like a fundamen- the finding that individuals scoring high in
tally changed person. They found that pa- psychopathy weight morality less heavily
tients whose principal symptoms are moral when judging identity in others. (I will note
impairment (from frontotemporal dementia) that, as the author of many of the studies
are seen as having a more altered identity cited in this chapter, this is the only time I
 Identity Is Essentially Moral 145

have ever failed to find the moral self effect; deep down, this could be a valuable tool in
Strohminger & Nichols, 2016.) mitigating intergroup conflict (De Freitas &
The astute reader will rightly observe that Cikara, 2016). Identity change in dementia
there is a difference between how a person patients—largely brought on by moral de-
experiences their own sense of identity and generation—predicts relationship deteriora-
how they perceive the identity of others. And tion between caregiver and patient (Strohm-
while studies find that people report that inger & Nichols, 2015). Unfortunately, the
moral changes would affect their own iden- flip side of this is that people also report an
tity more than other types of mental change unwillingness to take psychopharmaceuti-
(Heiphetz et al., in press), one could fur- cals to cure moral deficits because of a reluc-
ther level the charge that what one predicts tance to interfere with the innermost parts
would happen need not reflect what one of the self (Riis, Simmons, & Goodwin,
would actually experience. 2 This poses both 2008). Finally, in an odd phenomenon that
a practical and a logical challenge for the seems to reflect the tendency of humans to
experimentalist. It may well be the case that anthropomorphize with reckless abandon,
a sudden, complete loss of autobiographical even corporate identity appears to be essen-
memories would lead a person to feel so un- tially moral, with corporate integrity edging
moored they would report being completely out other factors such as product quality
different from their previous self, as Wil- and profits (Strohminger, Pizarro, & Ariely,
liam James (1891) surmised. But this may be 2017). Such findings may ultimately bear on
difficult to measure, given that a judgment legal issues relating to corporate personhood
of whether one has changed must inevita- and corporate social responsibility.
bly be based on the memory of what has There is, however, a deeper intellectual
been lost. It doesn’t help that anosognosia puzzle here. We have shown that moral-
(a lack of awareness of one’s illness) is co- ity plays the most powerful role in shaping
morbid with many brain diseases (Prigatano judgments of diachronic identity. The evi-
& Schacter, 1991). Another factor may be dence for this conclusion is overwhelming,
the severity of the deficit—perhaps a mild and the effect is remarkably robust across
or moderate memory lapse does not change contexts and testing procedures. The cen-
experienced identity continuity, but a total trality of morality even shades into other,
disappearance does (Eustache et al., 2013). related concepts, like impression formation
This would explain the inconsistency of the and personhood. A natural question to ask
studies that have attempted to answer this at this juncture is, Why? Why does moral-
question (Klein, Cosmides, & Costabile, ity appear at this nexus, again and again, no
2003; Rose Addis & Tippett, 2004; Duval matter how we slice it?
et al., 2012; Levitin, 2012). More work will To answer this question, it may be helpful
be required to disentangle these possibili- to step back and consider the reason people
ties. keep track of persons in the first place. Few
animals, it turns out, have individual rec-
ognition for conspecifics in the way that
Some Expansions humans do. Those that do all have some-
thing in common: They are social (Tibbetts
The basic finding that diachronic identity & Dale, 2007; Sheehan & Tibbetts, 2011).
is essentially moral has several broader im- They rely on one another to survive.
plications. It has long been recognized that Evolutionary biologists have pointed out
the more central morality is to one’s sense that, in order for the building blocks of
of identity, the more morally one behaves morality to emerge, animals must be able
(Blasi, 1983; Aquino & Reed, 2002; Hardy to keep track of individuals in the environ-
& Carlo, 2005; Aquino, Freeman, Reed, ment (Nowak, 2006). Reciprocal altruism
Lim, & Felps, 2009; Monin & Jordan, requires that agents keep tabs on who has
2009). This suggests that self-identity is a helped in the past, in order to know whom
driving force in regulating moral behavior, to help in the future (Trivers, 1971). Like-
along with moral reasoning and emotions. wise, the most effective cooperation strategy
Given that we think of other selves as good requires that one keep track of offenders in
146 M O R A L I T Y, S O C I A L C O G N I T I O N , A N D I D E N T I T Y

order to punish them in future interactions 2. Prevailing evidence suggests that future and
(Axelrod, 1980). past selves are treated as friendly strangers,
Indeed, the whole reason that Locke and rather than as numerically identical with the
other enlightenment philosophers were present self (Bartels & Rips, 2010). Perhaps
the hypothetical self works the same way.
so concerned with personal identity in the
first place was that they recognized it to
be a forensic concept, foundational to any REFERENCES
coherent theory of personal responsibil-
ity (Locke, 1690/2009; Hume, 1739/2003; Anderson, N. H. (1968). Likableness ratings of
Reid, 1785/1850). If a person’s identity is 555 personality-trait words. Journal of Per-
ever-changing, how can we hold them ac- sonality and Social Psychology, 9(3), 272–279.
countable for the deeds of their past self? Aquino, K., Freeman, D., Reed, A., II, Lim, V.
K., & Felps, W. (2009). Testing a social-cog-
So perhaps this puzzle has been arranged nitive model of moral behavior: The interac-
backward. It is not that morality is central to tive influence of situations and moral identity
diachronic identity. Rather, it’s that identity centrality. Journal of Personality and Social
is a cog within the larger machinery of the Psychology, 97(1), 123–141.
moral cognitive system. What we ‘re doing Aquino, K., & Reed, A., II. (2002). The self-
when we’re trying to figure out who some- importance of moral identity. Journal of Per-
one is “deep down,” or when we’re trying to sonality and Social Psychology, 83(6), 1423–
pin down their essence, is to determine what 1440.
they’ll be like as a social partner—whether Axelrod, R. (1980). Effective choice in the pris-
they’ll cheat or be nice, help us or hurt us. oner’s dilemma. Journal of Conflict Resolu-
tion, 24(1), 3–25.
We really want to know what kind of moral Bartels, D. M., & Rips, L. J. (2010). Psychologi-
being they are. And maybe this is what per- cal connectedness and intertemporal choice.
sonal identity is all about. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Gen-
eral, 139(1), 49–69.
Blanton, H., & Christie, C. (2003). Deviance
A Certain Irony regulation: A theory of action and identity.
Review of General Psychology, 7(2), 115–149.
Embedded within this conclusion is a cer- Blasi, A. (1983). Moral cognition and moral ac-
tain understated irony. Diachronic identity tion: A theoretical perspective. Developmen-
is not chiefly about identification. It is not tal Review, 3(2), 178–210.
Bloom, P., & Gelman, S. (2008). Psychological
even about differentiation. Nearly everyone essentialism in selecting the 14th Dalai Lama.
has empathy, yet this is more important to Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 12(7), 243–243.
identity than distinctive traits like one’s ap- Brambilla, M., Rusconi, P., Sacchi, S., & Cheru-
pearance or talents or musical preferences. bini, P. (2011). Looking for honesty: The pri-
Our understanding of a person’s identity mary role of morality (vs. sociability and com-
has much more to do with how this indi- petence) in information gathering. European
vidual will operate within the larger group. Journal of Social Psychology, 41(2), 135–143.
What they’ll be like to cooperate with. What Brewer, M. B. (1991). The social self: On being
they’ll be like as romantic partners. As busi- the same and different at the same time. Per-
ness partners. Identity is about fitting in, not sonality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 17(5),
475–482.
standing out. Buchholz, B., Druid, H., & Frisén, J. (2005).
We are such social creatures that even that Retrospective birth dating of cells in humans.
most autonomous concept—the individual Cell, 122, 133–143.
person—still ultimately reflects our depen- Chen, S. Y., Urminsky, O., & Bartels, D. M.
dence on others. (2016). Beliefs about the causal structure of
the self-concept determine which changes dis-
rupt personal identity. Psychological Science,
NOTES 27(10), 1398–1406.
De Freitas, J., & Cikara, M. (2016). Deep down
1. Sacks’s case study has a twist ending, one my enemy is good: Thinking about the true
that is consistent with the thesis of the present self reduces intergroup bias. Unpublished
chapter. The curious reader is encouraged to manuscript.
read his essay in full. De Freitas, J., Sarkissian, H., Grossman, I., De
 Identity Is Essentially Moral 147

Brigard, F., Luco, A., Newman, G., & Knobe, Inspector, Y., Kutz, I., & David, D. (2004). An-
J. (in press). Consistent belief in a good true other person’s heart: Magical and rational
self in misanthropes and three interdependent thinking in the psychological adaptation to
cultures. Cognitive Science. heart transplantation. Israel Journal of Psy-
Diener, E. (1979). Deindividuation, self-aware- chiatry and Related Sciences, 41(3), 161–173.
ness, and disinhibition. Journal of Personality James, W. (1891). The principles of psychology
and Social Psychology, 37(7), 1160–1171. (Vol. 1). London: Macmillan.
Duval, C., Desgranges, B., de La Sayette, V., Bel- Keil, F. (1989). Concepts, kinds, and cognitive
liard, S., Eustache, F., & Piolino, P. (2012). development. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
What happens to personal identity when se- Klein, S. B., Cosmides, L., & Costabile, K. A.
mantic knowledge degrades?: A study of the (2003). Preserved knowledge of self in a case
self and autobiographical memory in semantic of Alzheimer’s dementia. Social Cognition,
dementia. Neuropsychologia, 50(2), 254–265. 21(2), 157–165.
Erikson, E. H. (1959). Identity and the life cycle. Krueger, J., & Clement, R. W. (1994). The truly
New York: Norton. false consensus effect: An ineradicable and
Eustache, M.-L., Laisney, M., Juskenaite, A., egocentric bias in social perception. Journal
Letortu, O., Platel, H., Eustache, F., & Des- of Personality and Social Psychology, 67(4),
granges, B. (2013). Sense of identity in advanced 596–610.
Alzheimer’s dementia: A cognitive dissociation Kung, F. Y. H., Eibach, R., & Grossman, I.
between sameness and selfhood? Conscious- (2016). Culture, fixed-world beliefs, relation-
ness and Cognition, 22(4), 1456–1467. ships and perception of identity change. Social
Festinger, L. (1954). A theory of social com- Psychological and Personality Science, 7(7),
parison processes. Human Relations, 7(2), 631–639.
117–140. LaCour, M. J., & Green, D. P. (2014). When con-
Garfield, J. L., Nichols, S., Rai, A. K., & Strohm- tact changes minds: An experiment on trans-
inger, N. (2015). Ego, egoism and the impact mission of support for gay equality. Science,
of religion on ethical experience: What a para- 346(6215), 1366–1369.
doxical consequence of Buddhist culture tells Levitin, D. (2012, December). Amnesia and the
us about moral psychology. Journal of Ethics, self that remains when memory is lost. Atlan-
19(3–4), 293–304. tic Monthly.
Gelman, S. (2003). The essential child: Origins Locke, J. (2009). An essay concerning human
of essentialism in everyday thought. New understanding. New York: WLC Books.
York: Oxford University Press. (Original work published 1690)
Gelman, S., & Wellman, H. (1991). Insides and Macmillan, M. (2000). Restoring Phineas Gage:
essences: Early understandings of the non-ob- A 150th retrospective. Journal of the History
vious. Cognition, 38(3), 213–244. of the Neurosciences, 9(1), 46–66.
Goodwin, G. P., Piazza, J., & Rozin, P. (2014). McAdams, D. P., & Manczak, E. (2015). Person-
Moral character predominates in person per- ality and the life story. In M. Mikulincer, P. R.
ception and evaluation. Journal of Personality Shaver, M. L. Cooper, & R. J. Larsen (Eds.),
and Social Psychology, 106(1), 148–168. APA handbook of personality and social psy-
Hardy, S. A., & Carlo, G. (2005). Identity as a chology: Vol. 4. Personality processes and in-
source of moral motivation. Human Develop- dividual differences (pp. 425–446). Washing-
ment, 48(4), 232–256. ton, DC: American Psychological Association.
Haslam, N., Bastian, B., & Bissett, M. (2004). Medin, D., & Ortony, A. (1989). Psychological
Essentialist beliefs about personality and their essentialism. In S. Vosniadou & A. Ortony
implications. Personality and Social Psychol- (Eds.), Similarity and analogical reasoning
ogy Bulletin, 30(12), 1661–1673. (pp. 179–195). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge
Heiphetz, L., Strohminger, N., & Young, L. University Press.
(2017). The role of moral beliefs, memories, Meyer, M., Leslie, S.-J., Gelman, S. A., & Stil-
and preferences in representations of identity. well, S. M. (2013). Essentialist beliefs about
Cognitive Science, 41(3),744–767. bodily transplants in the United States and
Heiphetz, L., Strohminger, N., Young, L., & India. Cognitive Science, 37(4), 668–710.
Gelman, S. A. (2016). Who am I?: The role of Miller, J. (2016, August 29). Gene Wilder, comic
moral beliefs in children’s and adults’ under- actor and Willy Wonka star, is dead at 83.
standing of identity. Unpublished manuscript. Vanity Fair.
Hirschfeld, L. (1995). Do children have a theory Molouki, S., & Bartels, D. M. (2017). Personal
of race? Cognition, 54(2), 209–252. change and the continuity of identity. Cogni-
Hume, D. (2003). A treatise of human nature. tive Psychology.
New York: Courier. (Original work published Monin, B., & Jordan, A. H. (2009). The dynamic
1739) moral self: A social psychological perspective.
148 M O R A L I T Y, S O C I A L C O G N I T I O N , A N D I D E N T I T Y

In D. Narvaez & D. K. Lapsley (Eds.), Person- Sloman, S. A., Love, B. C., & Ahn, W.-K. (1998).
ality, identity, and character: Explorations in Feature centrality and conceptual coherence.
moral psychology (pp. 341–354). New York: Cognitive Science, 22(2), 189–228.
Cambridge University Press. Sternberg, R., Chawarski, M., & Allbritton, D.
Nelson, L. J., & Miller, D. T. (1995). The distinc- (1998). If you changed your name and ap-
tiveness effect in social categorization: You are pearance to those of Elvis Presley, who would
what makes you unusual. Psychological Sci- you be?: Historical features in categorization.
ence, 6(4), 246–249. American Journal of Psychology, 111(3), 327–
Newman, G., Diesendruck, G., & Bloom, P. 351.
(2011). Celebrity contagion and the value of Strohminger, N., Newman, G., & Knobe, J. (in
objects. Journal of Consumer Research, 38(2), press). The true self: A psychological concept
215–228. distinct from the self. Perspectives on Psycho-
Newman, G., Knobe, J., & Bloom, P. (2014). logical Science.
Value judgments and the true self. Personal- Strohminger, N., & Nichols, S. (2014). The es-
ity and Social Psychology Bulletin, 40(2), sential moral self. Cognition, 131(1), 159–171.
203–216. Strohminger, N., & Nichols, S. (2015). Neuro-
Nichols, S., Strohminger, N., Rai, A. K., & Gar- degeneration and identity. Psychological Sci-
field, J. L. (2016). Death and the self. Unpub- ence, 26(9), 1468–1479.
lished manuscript. Strohminger, N., & Nichols, S. (2016). Psychop-
Nowak, M. (2006). Five rules for the evolution of athy and the moral self. Unpublished manu-
cooperation. Science, 314(5805), 1560–1563. script.
Prigatano, G. P., & Schacter, D. L. (1991). Strohminger, N., Pizarro, D., & Ariely, D.
Awareness of deficit after brain injury: Clini- (2017). Are corporations people?: The case of
cal and theoretical issues. Oxford, UK: Ox- corporate identity. Unpublished manuscript.
ford University Press. Sylvia, C., & Novak, W. (1997). A change of
Reid, T. (1850). Essays on the intellectual powers heart. Boston, MA: Little, Brown.
of man (Abridged ed.; J. Walker, Ed.). Cam- Taylor, M. (1996). The development of children’s
bridge, MA: John Bartlett. (Original work beliefs about social and biological aspects of
published 1785) gender differences. Child Development, 67(4),
Riis, J., Simmons, J. P., & Goodwin, G. P. 1555–1571.
(2008). Preferences for enhancement pharma- Tibbetts, E. A., & Dale, J. (2007). Individual rec-
ceuticals: The reluctance to enhance funda- ognition: It is good to be different. Trends in
mental traits. Journal of Consumer Research, Ecology and Evolution, 22(10), 529–537.
35(3), 495–508. Tobia, K. P. (2016). Personal identity, direction
Rose Addis, D., & Tippett, L. (2004). Memory of change, and neuroethics. Neuroethics, 9(1),
of myself: Autobiographical memory and iden- 37–43.
tity in Alzheimer’s disease. Memory, 12(1), Trivers, R. L. (1971). The evolution of reciprocal
56–74. altruism. Quarterly Review of Biology, 46(1),
Sacks, O. (1985). The lost mariner. In The man 35–57.
who mistook his wife for a hat (pp. 23–42). Vignoles, V. L., Chryssochoou, X., & Breakwell,
New York: Touchstone. G. M. (2000). The distinctiveness principle:
Schlegel, R. J., Vess, M., & Arndt, J. (2012). To Identity, meaning, and the bounds of cultural
discover or to create: Metaphors and the true relativity. Personality and Social Psychology
self. Journal of Personality, 80(4), 969–993. Review, 4(4), 337–354.
Sheehan, M. J., & Tibbetts, E. A. (2011). Spe- Wojciszke, B., Bazinska, R., & Jaworski, M.
cialized face learning is associated with indi- (1998). On the dominance of moral categories
vidual recognition in paper wasps. Science, in impression formation. Personality and So-
334(6060), 1272–1275. cial Psychology Bulletin, 24(12), 1251–1263.
C H A P T E R 16

The Core of Morality Is the Moral Self

Paul Conway

What is the best way to characterize morality?

Morality entails integrating emotions and cognition through the


universal evolved mechanisms of self and social perceptions, embed‑
ded within various cultural contexts, that functionally motivate and
regulate behavior to balance self-interest against group needs and
maintain successful societies.

Theories of moral psychology should be ca- ing in successful battle the next day (Hast-
pable of explaining moral behavior across ings, 1985, p. 26).
the world and throughout history. For exam- Moral psychology provides many lenses
ple, how can moral psychology explain the through which to view Manlius’s brutal ac-
behavior of Consul Manlius, leader of the tion, from cognitive-developmentalism (Kohl-
Roman army in 340 B.C.E.? Manlius insisted berg, 1969) to moral intuitionism (Haidt,
that no one engage the enemy without his 2001) to moral convictions (Skitka, Bauman,
orders, but before battle, an enemy mocked & Mullen, 2008) to cognitive templates of
and challenged Manlius’s son, Titus. Titus harm (Gray, Young, & Waytz, 2012) to dual-
fought the enemy and won. When Titus process models (Greene, Sommerville, Nys-
brought the enemy’s sword to honor his fa- trom, Darley, & Cohen, 2001). Although
ther, Manlius said, “I am moved, not only each of these perspectives highlights a differ-
by a man’s instinctive love for his children, ent facet of human morality, each struggles
but by this instance you have given of your to integrate the wide array of moral psychol-
bravery, perverted though it was by an idle ogy findings, because they tend to focus on
show of honor. But since the authority of the specific social cognitive processes, such as
consuls must either be established by your intuitions, reasoning, or mind perception.
death, or by your impunity be forever ab- Undoubtedly such processes play important
rogated . . . go and bind him to the stake.” roles in moral psychology—but the best way
Manlius then ordered his son executed. Ac- to integrate them is through the lens of the
cording to the historian Livy, the “orders of moral self. That is, moral self-perceptions and
Manlius” horrified the other soldiers but social perceptions are the key to motivating
also tightened discipline, making them more and regulating moral behavior and the key to
obedient and careful in their duties, result- moral judgments and decision making.

149
150 M O R A L I T Y, S O C I A L C O G N I T I O N , A N D I D E N T I T Y

Moral self-perceptions subsume and investment or else abandon moral striving


transcend the constructs of moral iden- altogether and thus relinquish claims to
tity—individual differences in the central- group resources.
ity of morality to the self-concept (Aquino One wrinkle to moral self-perception
& Reed, 2002; Blasi, 1984)—and moral theory is that perceivers may disagree—so
self-regard—contextual fluctuations in people must consider both public and pri-
moral self-perceptions based on recent be- vate and moral self-perceptions. Imagine
havior (Monin & Jordan, 2009). Moral someone stole money that you raised for
self-­perceptions also entail a meta-cognitive charity. You may feel higher moral standing
component: considering others’ perceptions than the selfish thief—but the charity direc-
of one’s moral standing in light of percep- tor who accuses you of taking the money
tions of those same others’ own moral degrades your public moral status. Nonethe-
standing. Hence moral self-perceptions are less, you may personally retain high private
inherently comparative: People think not moral standing (righteous innocence). Upon
only How moral am I? but How moral do encountering another member of the charity
my colleagues/family/neighbors think I am? board, your socially optimal behavior (con-
and How moral are my colleagues/family/ trition vs. defiance) may depend on that per-
neighbors? Thus the real question of moral son’s perception of your guilt or innocence.
self perceptions is How moral am I com- If the person assumes you are guilty, he or
pared to (specific) other people? Answering she may expect contrition. Conversely, if the
these questions entails considering evidence person believes your innocence, he or she
regarding one another’s character, so one’s may expect defiance. Conflict can emerge
perceived moral standing exists in relation from differing perceptions of moral status
to others’ perceived moral standing. among different parties.
Moral self-perceptions are inherently rela- The self model of morality is both func-
tive because morally superior people may tionalist and integrative: The moral self in-
pronounce moral judgment over morally in- tegrates other psychological processes into
ferior people, but not vice versa. Imagine a a holistic judgment of moral selfhood that
courtroom in which the defendant accuses serves to functionally regulate behavior. If
the judge of crimes and is taken seriously! this theory is correct, morality should form
Not only does accusing someone of a moral the core of self-perceptions and social per-
violation degrade the person’s moral stand- ceptions, and moral judgments should track
ing, but expressing the right to judge oth- perceptions of character and drive behav-
ers also demonstrates the judges’ own high ior. Moral self-perceptions should motivate
perceived standing. Hence, moral judgments and regulate the “give” and “take” of so-
amount to a power play: They imply that cial relations, and threatening or affirming
one holds moral superiority over those one the moral self should affect judgments and
is judging. behavior. Finally, moral self-perceptions
Moral self-perceptions serve to function- should reflect and regulate relations with
ally regulate behavior in order to balance others, such as rights and duties. Yet the
personal interests against the needs of one’s content of moral self-perceptions may vary
social group. Increasing moral self-percep- across history and culture, depending on the
tions requires investing in activities that contextually normative relation between self
benefit others, such as prosocial behavior and group—the moral duties of an ancient
or altruistic punishment. People who have soldier are different from those of a modern
earned high standing may either invest in nurse. Considering these points may help
further prosociality or “cash in” by relax- elucidate Manlius’s thinking.
ing moral strivings to reap the selfish ben-
efits (e.g., avoiding prosocial behavior, nep-
otism). Hence, moral self-perceptions can Historical Context
paradoxically sometimes increase and other
times reduce prosociality (Mullen & Monin, Moral self-theory emerges out of the cogni-
2016). People with lower moral standing tive-developmental literature. Building on
must attempt moral repair via further group Piaget (1965), Kohlberg (e.g., 1969) argued
 The Core of Morality Is the Moral Self 151

for a stage model of moral reasoning that central aspects of the self remain chroni-
culminates in Platonic rationalism (Plato, cally accessible, but context can influence
trans. 1949). However, the link between which other self-attributes people consider
moral reasoning and moral behavior is weak (e.g., Forehand, Deshpandé, & Reed, 2002).
at best (Blasi, 1980), leading theorists to Aquino and Reed (2002) applied these in-
propose a series of models (e.g., Rest, 1984; sights to Blasi’s (1995) view of the moral self
Damon, 1984; Colby & Damon, 1992) (see also Lapsley & Narvaez, 2004) to argue
that increasingly focused on the moral self that the moral self operates as but one as-
(see Bergman, 2002), culminating in Bla- pect of the overall self. For some people, it is
si’s (1995) argument that moral judgments more chronically active than for others, and
carry motivational weight due to a desire for context may either activate or suppress it—
self-consistency: When people apply moral for example, reminders of one’s good deeds
reasoning to themselves, failure to act mor- may inflate moral self-perceptions, whereas
ally betrays oneself. Such inconsistency is reminders of misdeeds may deflate them.
aversive (Bem, 1972; Festinger, 1957) and Likewise, as selves are inherently social
existentially threatening (Schlegel, Hicks, (Tajfel & Turner, 1985), group memberships
Arndt, & King, 2009). Hence identity as a may reflect on individual morality (Ellemers,
moral person powerfully motivates moral Pagliaro, Barreto, & Leach, 2008). Finally,
behavior (Hardy & Carlo, 2005). recent advances in person perception outline
Concurrently, developments in evolution- the powerful and previously underappreci-
ary theory increasingly suggested that mo- ated role of morality in forming perceptions
rality evolved to regulate social relations of others (e.g., Goodwin, Piazza, & Rozin,
(Alexander, 1987). Although some scholars 2014). The moral self-perspective incorpo-
scoffed at this idea (Dawkins, 1989), it trac- rates insights from all of these literatures.
es all the way back to Darwin (1874/1998).
The evolutionary pathway toward genuine
morality begins with caring for kin (Ham- Theoretical Stance
ilton, 1964) and reciprocal exchange with
non-kin (Trivers, 1971), moving toward The moral self model is functionalist and
broader indirect reciprocity in which group integrative: It draws on evolutionary theory
members help one another, keeping track of to posit the function of morality, to propose
group investment via image scoring (Nowak a parsimonious account, and to consiliently
& Sigmund, 1998) and gossip (Feinberg, explain a disparate set of findings.
Willer, Stellar, & Keltner, 2012). Addition-
ally, sexual selection (Hardy & Van Vugt,
Functionalist
2006; Miller, 2007) and group-level selec-
tion (Sober & Wilson, 1998) would have ac- The moral self integrates moral emotions
celerated moral behavior under conditions with reasoning to motivate situationally
consistent with early human lifestyles (Lee appropriate behavior. Keltner and Haidt
& DeVore, 1968). Such processes are impos- (1999) argued that moral emotions (e.g.,
sible without tracking each party’s sociality moral disgust) exapted (developed out of)
and selfishness: the moral selves of oneself from evolutionarily prior processes (e.g.,
and one’s compatriots. Hence, psychological physical disgust) and are shaped by culture
mechanisms motivating morality—moral and development to solve particular adap-
self and social perceptions—derived from tive problems (e.g., appraisals of rule vio-
evolutionary pressure (Gintis, Bowles, Boyd, lations; Nichols & Mallon, 2006; Wondra
& Fehr, 2003; DeScioli & Kurzban, 2013; & Ellsworth, 2015). Moral emotions serve
Haidt, 2001; Wright, 1994). multiple functions, including associative
Meanwhile, social cognitive research learning and communication, but most im-
clarified the psychology of self- and person portantly self- and social regulation (Giner-
perception. The self is rich and complex, and Sorolla, 2012). For example, gratitude mo-
people balance many, sometimes competing, tivates repaying social debts (McCullough,
identities, with only a subset active at any Kilpatrick, Emmons, & Larson, 2001), guilt
one time (Markus & Kunda, 1986). Thus motivates repairing damaged relationships
152 M O R A L I T Y, S O C I A L C O G N I T I O N , A N D I D E N T I T Y

(Baumeister, Stillwell, & Heatherton, 1994), ferent moral values because different social
anger motivates aggression toward moral strategies were historically most successful
violators (Skitka, Bauman, & Sargis, 2005), in those environments (Gangestad, Hasel-
and distress motivates avoiding harm (Cush- ton, & Buss, 2006)—for example, harsh
man, Gray, Gaffey, & Mendes, 2012)— environments particularly favor strong
but for an alternative view, see Cameron, cooperation (Smaldino, Schank, & McEl-
Lindquist, and Gray (2015). Moral emotions reath, 2013). Political differences in moral-
may have deep evolutionary roots (de Waal, ity (Haidt & Graham, 2007) may likewise
1996), but moral reasoning serves to for- stem from differences in successful strat-
malize morality into principles (Rest, 1984). egies: Conservative morality emphasizes
The moral self unites moral emotions with group regulation of individuals, which may
reasoning through development (Frimer & be optimal in traditional tight-knit commu-
Walker, 2009). nities, whereas liberal morality emphasizes
Although people perceive objectivity as a freeing individuals to pursue enlightened
core feature of moral judgments (Skitka et self-interest, which may be optimal in large,
al., 2008), there is pressure for both accu- globalized societies (Lakoff, 2010). Similar-
racy and self-enhancement (Krebs, 2008). ly, group characteristics such as power dis-
Accuracy is important for calibrating meta- tance, inequality, centralization, threat, and
perceptions of one’s moral character in order entitativity may all influence moral norms.
to maintain effective cooperation (Boyd &
Richerson, 2005), protecting low-power
Integrative
from high-power individuals (Boehm, 1999)
and preventing conflict escalation along kin The self perspective seeks to integrate rather
lines (DeScioli & Kurzban, 2013). People than overturn other theories of morality.
must demonstrate morality through costly Morality has many facets—for example,
signaling, such as donating to charity—­ emotions, behaviors, judgments, domains—
especially when monitored by the ingroup differentially emphasized by each theory.
(van Nunspeet, Gray, Gaffey, & Mendes, For example, regarding Manlius’s decision,
2015). Yet people use a variety of strategies one might postulate that he engaged in weak
to feel sufficiently moral, whether earned or moral reasoning (Kohlberg, 1969), lacked
not (Effron, 2014). People apply different empathy (Hoffman, 2000), or aimed to up-
moral standards to themselves than to others hold group cooperation (Fehr & Gächter,
(Lammers, 2012), pick moral standards that 2002). It appears he felt morally convicted
favor ingroups (Brandt, 2013; Skitka & Tet- about his decision—that it was objectively
lock, 1992), apply different standards when true, universal, obligatory, autonomous,
they benefit than when they suffer (Bocian & motivational, and affective and (most im-
Wojciszka, 2014), and strategically “forget” portant) that it reflected his core moral val-
moral rules (Shu, Gino, & Bazerman, 2010). ues and beliefs (Skitka et al., 2008). Perhaps
Accordingly, many conceptualizations of the a moral intuition—“the sudden appearance
moral self contrast a shallow, image-focused in consciousness of a moral judgment . . .
moral self with a deeper, purer, inner moral without any conscious awareness of having
self, or “true self” (Aquino & Reed, 2002; gone through steps of searching, weighing
Frimer, Schaefer, & Oakes, 2014; Newman, evidence, or inferring a conclusion”—drove
De Freitas, & Knobe, 2014). Manlius’s decision, which he buttressed via
Although aspects of morality are cultural- post hoc reasoning to persuade others to
ly universal (Fessler, 1999; Midgley, 1991), share this intuition (Haidt, 2001, p. 817).
there is also room for cultural variability Manlius’s intuitions appear to favor the
(Haidt & Joseph, 2004; Shweder, Much, & conservative moral domains of loyalty, pu-
Park, 1997). To the degree that social groups rity, and respect for authority more than the
face similar problems, moral judgments are liberal domains of harm and fairness, as he
universal. For example, intentionally hurt- prioritized obedience, group objectives, and
ing innocents is universally abhorred (Sousa, an unblemished reputation over aversion to
Holbrook, & Piazza, 2009; Turiel, 1983). killing his son or matching punishment with
Yet different environments may “evoke” dif- the crime (Graham, Haidt, & Nosek, 2009).
 The Core of Morality Is the Moral Self 153

Regardless, participants and observers likely from moral goals (Sutton, Smith, & Swet-
filtered this event through a dyadic cogni- tenham, 1999), and “altruistic” punishment
tive template of moral transgressions (Gray, seems partially motivated by demonstrat-
Young, & Waytz, 2012), assigning roles of ing one’s moral status (Kurzban, DeScioli,
victim and perpetrator, and ascribing more & O’Brien, 2007). Moral convictions serve
agency (capacity for action) to the former to uphold the moral self: Expressing moral
and experience (capacity for perception) to convictions demonstrates that one has “an
the latter (Gray, Gray, & Wegner, 2007). authentic moral point of view” (Skitka,
Accordingly, observers should have been 2002, p. 594). Likewise, moral intuitions
particularly sensitive to Titus’s pain and uphold the moral self: Although such intu-
viewed Manlius as particularly capable of itions drive condemnation of harmless ta-
action (Gray & Wegner, 2009)—although boos (e.g., Haidt, Koller, & Dais, 1993), val-
Manlius may have perceived himself as vic- idating the self reduces such condemnation
timized by his son’s rash action. Victims and (Mooijman & van Dijk, 2014). Similarly, the
perpetrators often view transgressions dif- moral cognitive template is fundamentally
ferently (Baumeister, Stillwell, & Wotman, tied to the self. Was Manlius the perpetra-
1994). tor or the victim? The answer depends on
Moreover, Manlius’s situation is similar his relation to oneself. Finally, even moral
to moral dilemmas in which causing harm dilemma judgments reflect the moral self:
maximizes outcomes (Foot, 1967). Livy ar- Conway and Gawronski (2013) found that
gues that Manlius’s action increased battle people with stronger moral identities expe-
success, hence making the world better rience stronger inclinations to both avoid
(through Roman eyes). Therefore, Manlius’s causing harm and maximize outcomes. Yet
action was moral according to utilitarian different dilemma answers have different
philosophical positions, in which moral- social costs (Lucas & Galinsky, 2015). Ac-
ity entails maximizing outcomes (e.g., Mill, cordingly, people’s answers are sensitive to
1861/1998). Conversely, Manlius’s action social circumstances (Kundu & Cummins,
was immoral according to deontological 2012; Lucas & Livingstone, 2014), and peo-
philosophical positions, in which morality ple justify their answers by integrating these
entails adhering to universal moral rules perspectives (Liu & Ditto, 2012).
(Kant, 1785/1959)—assuming the rule in
question is do no harm.1 Greene and col-
leagues’ (2001) dual-process model of moral Evidence
judgment suggests that deontological deci-
Morality Is Central to Self‑
sions (to avoid harm) are driven by affective
and Person Perception
reactions to harm, whereas utilitarian deci-
sions (to maximize outcomes) are driven by Lay people perceive morality as the essence
cognitive evaluations of outcomes. Accord- of the self (Strohminger & Nichols, 2014;
ing to this model, Manlius’s decision may Newman et al., 2014). Morality is iden-
have been driven by a deficit of affect, as in tify defining: Adhering to moral standards
psychopathy (e.g., Bartels & Pizarro, 2011), shared with group members signals group
and/or a surfeit of cognitive processing (e.g., membership (Ellemers & van den Bos, 2012).
Moore, Clarke, & Kane, 2008), each of People prefer to join (Leach, Ellemers, &
which might facilitate carrying out a brutal Barreto, 2007), and remain in (Boezeman &
action that improves outcomes. Ellemers, 2014) moral groups. Suppressing
Each of these perspectives highlights a self-interest to uphold group norms is key
different facet of the inordinate complexity for maintaining a self-image as a good group
of human morality. Yet, merely touring dif- member (Leach, Biliali, & Pagliaro, 2013)
ferent explanations is unsatisfying. Is moral who deserves respect (Pagliaro, Ellemers, &
psychology doomed to theory proliferation? Barreto, 2011). Accordingly, moral values
The self model integrates these perspectives. are central to identity (Rokeach, 1973), and
Moral reasoning fails to motivate behavior people are motivated to uphold these values
unless applied to the self (Blasi, 1995), em- in order to maintain their sense of identity
pathy may be destructive when decoupled (Hardy, 2006). Making moral decisions ac-
154 M O R A L I T Y, S O C I A L C O G N I T I O N , A N D I D E N T I T Y

tivates the self-concept (Christy & Schlegel, perceptions of the target’s past controllable
2015), and the brain regions involved in behavior (Shaver, 1985; Weiner, 1993), so
moral processing overlap with regions that socially useful targets deserve better treat-
process the self (Moll et al., 2007). Engaging ment (Olson, Cheung, Conway, Hutchison,
in either immoral or inauthentic behavior— & Hafer, 2011). Accordingly, people often
both of which violate the self—makes people engage in costly signaling (e.g., prosocial
feel impure and immoral (Gino, Kouchaki, behavior) to demonstrate usefulness (e.g.,
& Galinsky, 2015). Krebs, 2008). Together, these findings sug-
Moreover, judgments of morality are par- gest that people aim to determine others’
amount for assessing the character of indi- “true selves”—whether their core motiva-
viduals (Goodwin et al., 2014) and groups tions are selfish or laudable—and treat them
(Ellemers et al., 2008). Perceivers care more accordingly.
about targets’ morality than about their so-
ciability or competence (Brambilla, Rusconi,
Moral Self‑Perceptions Motivate and Regulate
Sacchi, & Cherubini, 2011). When evaluat-
Prosocial Behavior
ing others, people track more than mere out-
comes (Cushman, 2008)—outcomes offer In addition to defining the core of self- and
a window into intentions (Pizarro & Tan- social perception, the moral self regulates
nenbaum, 2011). Indeed, people infer nefari- behavior. Moral exemplars treat moral and
ous intentions upon encountering a moral personal goals as interchangeable (Colby &
violation and vice versa (Gray, Waytz, & Damon, 1992), and moral identity predicts
Young, 2012), and moral evaluations reflect prosocial behaviors (e.g., Aquino, Freeman,
perceived intentions (Guglielmo, Monroe, Reed, Felps, & Lim, 2009; Reed & Aqui-
& Malle, 2009), even among young children no, 2003) in everyday contexts (Hofmann,
(Hamlin, 2013). Immoral behaviors are Wisneski, Brandt, & Skitka, 2014). Invok-
more diagnostic of personality than moral ing the moral self can increase these effects
behaviors (Skowronski & Carlston, 1987), (Jennings, Mitchell, & Hannah, 2014):
because people view refraining from evil as Priming moral identity increases generos-
more obligatory than engaging in prosocial- ity (Reed, Aquino, & Levy, 2007), invoking
ity (Janoff-Bulman, Sheikh, & Hepp, 2009). the self (“don’t be a cheater”) reduces cheat-
Hence, immoral behavior clearly indicates ing (Bryan, Adams, & Monin, 2013), and
bad character. signing documents reduces dishonesty (Shu,
Perceived moral character, in turn, drives Mazar, Gino, Ariely, & Bazerman, 2012).
important social decisions, from judgments Recalling childhood activates the true self
of legal responsibility (Darley, 2009; Feath- (Baldwin, Biernat, & Landau, 2015), in-
er & Atchison, 1998; Skitka & Housten, creasing prosociality (Gino & Desai, 2012).
2001), to desired social distance (Skitka Labeling donors as charitable people increas-
et al., 2005) to trust (Delgado, Frank, & es subsequent donations, whereas labeling
Phelps, 2005; Simpson, Harrel, & Willer, nondonors uncharitable reduces donations
2013). People prefer leaders who embody (Kraut, 1973); likewise with the label caring
moral values (Haslam, Reicher, & Platow, (Burger & Caldwell, 2003). Conversely, pro-
2010) and policies buttressed by moral jus- viding extrinsic incentives for prosociality
tifications—unless such policies appear in- backfires by undermining the motivation to
sincere (Van Zant & Moore, 2015). People demonstrate one’s morality (Ariely, Bracha,
treat others in line with perceived deserv- & Meier, 2009).
ingness: a “state of compatibility in valence In addition to whether the moral self is ac-
between a target’s actions or traits and his tive, the way one conceptualizes the moral
or her outcomes” (Olson, Hafer, Cheung, self matters. People are typically moral satis-
& Conway, 2009, p. 127). People are highly ficers—they require only sufficient evidence
motivated to uphold deservingness (Lerner, of their morality (Skitka, 2002) to feel per-
1980) and react to violations both emotion- mitted to relax moral strivings (Miller &
ally (Feather & Sherman, 2002) and behav- Effron, 2010). Hence demonstrating egali-
iorally (Callan, Shead, & Olson, 2011). De- tarianism licenses discrimination (e.g., Ef-
servingness judgments stem primarily from fron, Cameron, & Monin, 2009), and re-
 The Core of Morality Is the Moral Self 155

calling prosociality reduces donations (for good reason not to. People engage in a va-
reviews, see Miller & Effron, 2010; Zhong, riety of justifications for unethical behavior
Liljenquist, & Cain, 2009; Effron & Con- (Shalvi, Gino, Barkan, & Ayal, 2015), such
way, 2015). Conversely, feeling insufficient- as minimizing moral failings through denial
ly moral motivates increased prosociality and motivated forgetting (Shu et al., 2010),
to restore moral self-perceptions (Jordan, distancing the self from moral failing (Ban-
Mullen, & Murnighan, 2011). Thus moral dura, 1990), and perceiving moral rules as
standing signals when one’s investment lev- flexible (lest they take a hit to the moral self;
els are sufficient that one may indulge in Cameron & Payne, 2012). People tend to
selfishness. Selfishness may also arise from avoid both tiny and large lies—the former
perceived victimization, to restore balance because they are not worth the cost of lying,
between deprived personal interest and and the latter because they threaten moral
group outcomes (Zitek, Jordan, Monin, & integrity (Mazar, Amir, & Ariely, 2008).
Leach, 2010). Unethical behavior increases when the role
Recently, researchers have begun to dis- of the self is diminished because justifica-
entangle the complex issue of when moral tions are more available (Shalvi, Handgraaf,
self-perceptions motivate versus relax moral & De Dreu, 2011) and when people feel
strivings (Blanken, van de Ven, & Zeelen- anonymous (Zhong, Bohns, & Gino, 2010),
berg, 2014; Mullen & Monin, 2016). Moral lack free will (Vohs & Schooler, 2007), or
consistency—acting moral when feeling do not need others (Gino & Pierce, 2009).
moral—appears most likely when people People also tend to avoid contemplating
abstractly consider the implications of past (even sensible) trade-offs that sacrifice moral
good deeds for their current identity rather values (Tetlock, Kristel, Elson, Green, &
than temptations (Conway & Peetz, 2012), Lerner, 2000), and, when they are exposed
view past moral behavior as reflecting com- to intense suffering, people strategically
mitment to (rather than progress toward) suppress their emotions to protect the self
moral goals (Susewind & Hoelzl, 2014), and (Cameron & Payne, 2011), which is tax-
recall costly (vs. costless) prosocial behavior, ing and may increase burnout (Omdahl &
which implies greater commitment to moral O’Donnell, 1999).
action (Gneezy, Imas, Brown, Nelson, & Threatening and affirming the moral self
Norton, 2012). Effron and Conway (2015) influences moral judgments and behavior.
suggested that consistency may result from People tend to intermix physical and psy-
affirming the moral self, whereas relaxed chological elements of morality, likely due to
strivings may result from disconfirming the evolutionary origins of moral emotions
an immoral self (e.g., disconfirming a rac- (Rozin, Haidt, & Fincher, 2009). Hence,
ist identity). This possibility meshes with recalling immoral behavior or exposure to
multiple-layer models of the moral self (e.g., other’s immorality induces a sense of con-
Frimer et al., 2014). Yet more work remains tamination (Eskine, Kacinik, & Webster,
to be done to unravel the paradox of when 2012), which motivates a desire to punish
moral self-perceptions increase versus re- (Inbar, Pizarro, & Bloom, 2012; Schnall,
duce moral strivings. Haidt, Clore, & Jordan, 2008)—which
in turn restores the moral self (Kurzban et
al., 2007). Conversely, feeling clean reduc-
Threatening and Affirming the Moral Self
es the perceived severity of transgressions
Affects Judgments and Behavior
and hence reduces guilt (Zhong & Liljen-
Unsurprisingly, people are highly motivated quist, 2006) and general judgment harsh-
to perceive themselves as moral (Eply & ness (Schnall, Benton, & Harvey, 2008),
Dunning, 2001; Monin & Jordan, 2009). but also elevates one’s moral status relative
Discrepancies between current self-percep- to the transgressor, allowing harsher judg-
tions and one’s moral obligations are psy- ments of them specifically (Zhong, Strejcek,
chologically uncomfortable (Higgins, 1987). & Sivanathan, 2010). Additionally, feeling
Accordingly, people are motivated to bolster immoral motivates the desire to physically
and protect moral self-perceptions (Effron, cleanse oneself (Zhong & Liljenquist, 2006),
Miller, & Monin, 2012)—unless there is a which is modality specific (Lee & Schwarz,
156 M O R A L I T Y, S O C I A L C O G N I T I O N , A N D I D E N T I T Y

2010), and motivates reconnection to high- mitting one to judge morally inferior others.
density social networks (Lee, Im, Parmar, & When one lacks moral standing, attempting
Gino, 2015)—unless one has experienced to regulate others may come across as hypo-
self-­
affirmation (Steele, 1988). Moreover, critical—the pot calling the kettle black—so
affirming the true self allows for shame-free those who wish to judge others must first
guilt in response to minor infractions (Vess, establish moral selfhood (Effron & Monin,
Schlegel, Hicks, & Arndt, 2013) and allows 2010).
people to admit past immorality, thereby An important implication of this view is
increasing reparations (Ĉehaji-Clancy, Ef- that moral judgments are inherently social
fron, Halperin, Liberman, & Ross, 2011; and relative: They are made by a moral self,
Schumann, 2014). Finally, exposure to regarding another moral self, both of whom
moral exemplars increases prosocial behav- are members of reference groups populated
ior (Schnall, Roper, & Fessler, 2010) when by yet more moral selves. Making moral
people identify with them (Nelson & Nor- judgments invokes power over the target by
ton, 2005)—but people resent moral exem- increasing relative moral distance: Those
plars when a direct comparison of behavior who judge must be more moral than those
reveals their moral inferiority (Cramwinck- they judge. Accordingly, people view judg-
el, Van Dijk, Scheepers, & Van den Bos, es as moral exemplars (Walker & Hennig,
2013; Monin, Sawyer, & Marquez, 2008). 2004) and view people who make moral
Although past immoral behavior often judgments as trustworthy (Simpson et al.,
motivates people to restore their threatened 2013). Conversely, people often view tar-
moral self through prosociality (Carlsmith gets of harm as deserving negative treatment
& Gross, 1969; Conway & Peetz, 2012), due to their poor moral character (Olson et
sometimes people incorporate moral failings al., 2009), rather than somehow outside the
into the self-concept: moral injury, which is “scope of justice” (Opotow, 1993; Olson
a serious problem for veterans and distinct et al., 2009). Hence, harm is morally justi-
from PTSD (Maguen & Litz, 2012). Moral- fiable if the target has violated important
ity and self-control are related (Baumeister standards (Tangney, Stuewig, & Mashek,
& Exline, 1999), and when people interpret 2007). In such cases, morality motivates
self-control failure as a global self-deficit, harm: moralistic aggression, in which ag-
they often give up self-regulating, inviting gressors exert physical superiority over the
further failure (Baumeister & Heatherton, morally inferior victim (Rai & Fiske, 2011).
1996). Similarly, people who incorporate Note that such aggression may appear im-
immorality into the self-concept may give moral from the victim’s but not the perpetra-
up on morality: Recalling immoral behavior tor’s perspective (Giner-Sorolla, 2012).
can reduce prosociality (Conway & Peetz,
2012); perceiving oneself as unethical in-
creases unethical behavior (Gino, Norton, Extension and Expansion
& Ariely, 2010); and perceiving global moral
defects increases defensiveness, not improve- There are several important implications of
ment (Gausel & Leach, 2011). the moral self view. First, moral judgments
(e.g., dilemma decisions, blame judgments)
are based not only on basic psychological
Moral Self‑Perceptions Allow Judging Others
processes (e.g., affect) but also on metaper-
Normally, people refrain from sharing their ceptions regarding what these judgments
inner thoughts regarding issues that do not suggest about one’s character. Engaging in
affect them (Ratner & Miller, 2001), but morally relevant behavior affects not only
moralizing an issue—by construing it as a one’s moral self-perceptions but also one’s
reflection of one’s core values and beliefs moral standing in relation to others—one
(Skitka, 2002)—frees people to express is always gaining or losing the moral high
their thoughts regardless of personal stake ground. Few theorists have fully appreciated
(Effron & Miller, 2012). In turn, express- how making moral judgments amounts to
ing one’s moral values in this way validates exerting power. More empirical work should
the moral self (Skitka, 2003), thereby per- clarify these ramifications.
 The Core of Morality Is the Moral Self 157

Second, a better understanding of the moral self and social perceptions in the con-
moral self is crucial for improving society. text of an ancient military order.
As moral self-perceptions can both increase
and relax moral strivings, researchers need
to clarify moderators—when does feeling NOTE
moral actually make one a better person?
1. Unless the deontological rule is obey thy fa-
Resolving this paradox may suggest simple ther and commander, in which case rules
behavioral “nudges” to increase prosociali- would entail harm. The dual-process model
ty. For example, considering how past moral fails to specify which moral rules are para-
deeds reflect one’s identity may motivate mount (Mikhail, 2007).
prosociality. Likewise, it is paramount to
better understand negative moral self-per-
ceptions. Considering immorality part of REFERENCES
one’s self-concept may lead to moral injury
(Maguen & Litz, 2012), reducing subsequent Alexander, R. D. (1987). The biology of moral
prosociality (Conway & Peetz, 2012), there- systems. New York: Aldine de Gruyter.
Aquino, K., Freeman, D., Reed, A., II, Felps, W.,
by creating a downward spiral (Baumeister & Lim, V. (2009). Testing a social-cognitive
& Heatherton, 1996). On the other hand, model of moral behavior: The interactive in-
a redemptive narrative is possible if people fluence of situations and moral identity cen-
share their stories of immoral behavior to trality. Journal of Personality and Social Psy-
help others (McAdams, 1993) or aim to re- chology, 97, 123–141.
store standing via prosocial acts (Baumeis- Aquino, K., & Reed, A., II. (2002). The self-im-
ter, Stillwell, & Heatherton, 1994). Perhaps portance of moral identity. Journal of Person-
increasing perceptions of self-malleability ality and Social Psychology, 83, 1423–1440.
(Schumann & Dweck, 2014) may influence Ariely, D., Bracha, A., & Meier, S. (2009). Doing
whether people accept or reject an immoral good or doing well?: Image motivation and
monetary incentives in behaving prosocially.
self. Researchers should clarify how and American Economic Review, 99, 544–555.
when negative moral self-perceptions are Baldwin, M. W., Biernat, M., & Landau, M. J.
useful versus destructive. (2015). Remembering the real me: Nostalgia
Finally, returning to our original ques- offers a window to the intrinsic self. Journal
tion: From the moral self perspective, Man- of Personality and Social Psychology, 108,
lius’s decision makes (brutal) sense. Simply 128–147.
put, Titus’s “idle show of honor” priori- Bartels, D. M., & Pizarro, D. A. (2011). The
tized personal honor over group interests mismeasure of morals: Antisocial personality
when group cohesion was paramount. Had traits predict utilitarian responses to moral di-
Manlius compounded Titus’s selfishness by lemmas. Cognition, 121, 154–161.
Baumeister, R. F., & Exline, J. J. (1999). Virtue,
engaging in blatant nepotism (i.e., punish- personality and social relations: Self-control
ing Titus less than others), this hypocrisy as the moral muscle. Journal of Personality,
would have compromised Manlius’s moral 67, 1165–1194.
self. Army leadership would have appeared Baumeister, R. F., & Heatherton, T. F. (1996).
corrupt, motivating others to shift priority Self-regulation failure: An overview. Psycho-
away from group goals to self-interest, di- logical Inquiry, 7, 1–15.
minishing group cohesion and thereby in- Baumeister, R. F., Stillwell, A. M., & Heather-
creasing the chance of disastrous defeat. In- ton, T. F. (1994). Guilt: An interpersonal ap-
stead, by sacrificing his son, Manlius clearly proach. Psychological Bulletin, 115, 243–267.
demonstrated his priority of group over self- Baumeister, R. F., Stillwell, A. M., & Wotman,
S. R. (1994). Victim and perpetrator accounts
ish interests, inspiring others to do the same. of interpersonal conflict: Autobiographical
Manlius also demonstrated the moral clar- narratives about anger. Journal of Personality
ity of a dispassionate judge, suggesting he and Social Psychology, 59, 994–1005.
would use his position of moral superiority Bem, D. J. (1972). Self-perception theory. In L.
to punish anyone who violated their duty. In Berkowitz (Ed.), Advances in experimental so-
doing so, Manlius enhanced group cohesion, cial psychology (Vol. 6, pp. 1–62). New York:
resulting in success over rivals. Manlius’s de- Academic Press.
cision was driven by a need to uphold his Bergman, R. (2002). Why be moral?: A concep-
158 M O R A L I T Y, S O C I A L C O G N I T I O N , A N D I D E N T I T Y

tual model from developmental psychology. and emotions: No evidence for specific rela-
Human Development, 45, 104–124. tionships between moral content and discrete
Blanken, I., van de Ven, N., & Zeelenberg, M. emotions. Personality and Social Psychology
(2014). A meta-analytic review of moral li- Review, 19, 1–24.
censing. Personality and Social Psychology Cameron, C. D., & Payne, D. K. (2011). Escaping
Bulletin, 41, 540–558. affect: How motivated emotion regulation cre-
Blasi, A. (1980). Bridging moral cognition and ates insensitivity to mass suffering. Journal of
moral action: A critical review of the litera- Personality and Social Psychology, 100, 1–15.
ture. Psychological Bulletin, 88, 1–45. Cameron, C. D., & Payne, B. K. (2012). The cost
Blasi, A. (1984). Moral identity: Its role in of callousness: Regulating compassion influ-
moral functioning. In W. M. Kurtines & J. L. ences the moral self-concept. Psychological
Gewirtz (Eds.), Morality, moral behavior, and Science, 23, 225–229.
moral development (pp. 128–139). New York: Ĉehaji-Clancy, S., Effron, D., Halperin, E.,
Wiley. Liberman, V., & Ross, L. D. (2011). Affirma-
Blasi, A. (1995). Moral understanding and the tion, acknowledgement of in-group responsi-
moral personality: The process of moral inte- bility, group-based guilt, and support for re-
gration. In W. M. Kurtines & J. L. Gewirtz parative measures. Journal of Personality and
(Eds.), Moral development: An introduction Social Psychology, 101(2), 256–270.
(p. 78). Boston: Allyn & Bacon. Christy, A. G., & Schlegel, R. J. (2015, Febru-
Bocian, K., & Wojciszka, B. (2014). Self-interest ary). Moral decisions and the true-self con-
bias in moral judgments of others’ actions. cept. Poster presented at the annual meeting of
Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, the Society for Personality and Social Psychol-
40, 898–909. ogy, Long Beach, CA.
Boehm, C. H. (1999). Hierarchy in the forest: Colby, A., & Damon, W. (1992). Some do care:
The evolution of egalitarian behavior. Cam- Contemporary lives of moral commitment.
bridge, MA: Harvard University Press. New York: Free Press.
Boezeman, E. J., & Ellemers, N. (2014). Volun- Conway, P., & Gawronski, B. (2013). Deontolog-
teer leadership: The role of pride and respect ical and utilitarian inclinations in moral deci-
in organizational identification and leadership sion-making: A process dissociation approach.
satisfaction. Leadership, 10, 160–173. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
Boyd, R., & Richerson, P. J. (2005). Solving the 104, 216–235.
puzzle of human cooperation. In S. C. Levin- Conway, P., & Peetz, J. (2012). When does feel-
son & P. Jaisson (Eds.), Evolution and culture: ing moral actually make you a better person?:
A Fyssen Foundation Symposium (pp. 105– Conceptual abstraction moderates whether
132). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. past moral deeds motivate consistency or com-
Brambilla, M., Rusconi, P. P., Sacchi, S., & pensatory behavior. Personality and Social
Cherubini, P. (2011). Looking for honesty: Psychology Bulletin, 38, 907–919.
The primary role of morality (vs. sociability Cramwinckel, F. M., Van Dijk, E., Scheepers,
and competence) in information gathering. D. T., & Van den Bos, K. (2013). The threat
European Journal of Social Psychology, 41, of moral refusers for one’s self-concept and
135–143. the protective function of physical cleansing.
Brandt, M. J. (2013). Onset and offset deserving- Journal of Experimental Social Psychology,
ness: The case of home foreclosures. Political 49, 1049–1058.
Psychology, 34, 221–238. Cushman, F. (2008). Crime and punishment:
Bryan, C. J., Adams, G. S., & Monin, B. (2013). Distinguishing the roles of causal and inten-
When cheating would make you a cheater: Im- tional analyses in moral judgment. Cognition,
plicating the self prevents unethical behavior. 108, 353–380.
Journal of Experimental Psychology: Gener- Cushman, F., Gray, K., Gaffey, A., & Mendes,
al, 142, 1001–1005. W. B. (2012). Simulating murder: The aversion
Burger, J. M., & Caldwell, D. F. (2003). The ef- to harmful actions. Emotion, 12, 2–7.
fects of monetary incentives and labeling on Damon, W. (1984). Self-understanding and
the foot-in-the-door effect: Evidence for a self- moral development from childhood to ado-
perception process. Basic and Applied Social lescence. In W. M. Kurtines & J. L. Gewirtz
Psychology, 25, 235–241. (Eds.), Morality, moral behavior, and moral
Callan, M. J., Shead, N. W., & Olson, J. M. development (pp. 109–127). New York: Wiley.
(2011). Personal relative deprivation, delay Darley, J. M. (2009). Morality in the law: The
discounting, and gambling. Journal of Person- psychological foundations of citizens’ desires
ality and Social Psychology, 101, 955. to punish transgressions. Annual Review of
Cameron, C. D., Lindquist, K. A., & Gray, K. Law and Social Science, 5, 1–23.
(2015). A constructionist review of morality Darwin, C. (1998). The descent of man. Am-
 The Core of Morality Is the Moral Self 159

herst, NY: Prometheus Books. (Original work Feather, N. T., & Atchison, L. (1998). Reactions
published 1874) to an offence in relation to the status and per-
Dawkins, R. (1989). The selfish gene. Oxford, ceived moral character of the offender. Austra-
UK: Oxford University Press. lian Journal of Psychology, 50, 119–127.
de Waal, F. (1996). Good natured: The origins of Feather, N. T., & Sherman, R. (2002). Envy, re-
right and wrong in humans and other animals. sentment, schadenfreude, and sympathy: Re-
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. actions to deserved and undeserved achieve-
Delgado, M. R., Frank, R. H., & Phelps, E. A. ment and subsequent failure. Personality and
(2005). Perceptions of moral character modu- Social Psychology Bulletin, 28, 953–961.
late the neural systems of reward during the Fehr, E., & Gächter, S. (2002). Altruistic punish-
trust game. Nature Neuroscience, 8, 1611– ment in humans. Nature, 415, 137–140.
1618. Feinberg, M., Willer, R., & Schultz, M. (2014).
DeScioli, P., & Kurzban, R. (2013). A solution to Gossip and ostracism promote cooperation in
the mysteries of morality. Psychological Bul- groups. Psychological Science, 25, 656–664.
letin, 139, 477–496. Fessler, D. (1999). Toward an understanding
Effron, D. A. (2014). Making mountains of mo- of the universality of second order emotions.
rality from molehills of virtue: Threat causes In A. Hinton (Ed.), Beyond nature or nur-
people to overestimate their moral credentials. ture: Biocultural approaches to the emotions
Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, (pp. 75–116). New York: Cambridge Univer-
40, 972–985. sity Press.
Effron, D. A., Cameron, J. S., & Monin, B. Festinger, L. (1957). A theory of cognitive dis-
(2009). Endorsing Obama licenses favoring sonance. Stanford, CA: Stanford University
whites. Journal of Experimental Psychology, Press.
45, 590–593. Foot, P. (1967). The problem of abortion and the
Effron, D. A., & Conway, P. (2015). When vir- doctrine of double effect. Oxford Review, 5,
tue leads to villainy: Advances in research on 5–15.
moral self-licensing. Current Opinion in Psy- Forehand, M. R., Deshpandé, R., & Reed, A., II.
chology, 6, 32–35. (2002). Identity salience and the influence of
Effron, D. A., & Miller, D. T. (2012). How the differential activation of the social self-schema
moralization of issues grants social legitimacy on advertising response. Journal of Applied
to act on one’s attitudes. Personality and So- Psychology, 87, 1086–1099.
cial Psychology Bulletin, 38, 690–701. Frimer, J. A., Schaefer, N. K., & Oakes, H.
Effron, D. A., Miller, D. T., & Monin, B. (2012). (2014). Moral actor, selfish agent. Journal of
Inventing racist roads not taken: The licensing Personality and Social Psychology, 106, 790–
effect of immoral counterfactual behaviors. 802.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, Frimer, J. A., & Walker, L. J. (2009). Reconciling
103, 916–932. the self and morality: An empirical model of
Effron, D. A., & Monin, B. (2010). Letting peo- moral centrality development. Developmental
ple off the hook: When do good deeds excuse Psychology, 45, 1669–1681.
transgressions? Personality and Social Psy- Gangestad, S. W., Haselton, M. G., & Buss, D.
chology Bulletin, 36, 1618–1634. M. (2006). Evolutionary foundations of cul-
Ellemers, N., Pagliaro, S., Barreto, M., & Leach, tural variation: Evoked culture and mate pref-
C. W. (2008). Is it better to be moral than erences. Psychological Inquiry, 17, 75–95.
smart?: The effects of morality and compe- Gausel, N., & Leach, C. W. (2011). Concern
tence norms on the decision to work at group for self-image and social-image in the man-
status improvement. Journal of Personality agement of moral failure: Rethinking shame.
and Social Psychology, 95, 1397–1410. European Journal of Social Psychology, 41,
Ellemers, N., & Van den Bos, K. (2012). Moral- 468–478.
ity in groups: On the social-regulatory func- Giner-Sorolla, R. (2012). Judging passions:
tions of right and wrong. Social and Personal- Moral emotions in persons and groups. New
ity Psychology Compass, 6, 878–889. York: Psychology Press.
Epley, N., & Dunning, D. (2000). Feeling “holier Gino, F., & Desai, S. (2012). Memory lane and
than thou”: Are self-serving assessments pro- morality: How childhood memories promote
duced by errors in self-or social prediction? prosocial behavior. Journal of Personality and
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, Social Psychology, 102, 743–758.
79, 861. Gino, F., Kouchaki, M., & Galinsky, A. D.
Eskine, K. J., Kacinik, N. A., & Webster, G. D. (2015). The moral virtue of authenticity: How
(2012). The bitter truth about morality: Vir- inauthenticity produces feelings of immoral-
tue, not vice, makes a bland beverage taste ity and impurity. Psychological Science, 26,
nice. PLOS ONE 7, e41159. 983–996.
160 M O R A L I T Y, S O C I A L C O G N I T I O N , A N D I D E N T I T Y

Gino, F., Norton, M., & Ariely, D. (2010). The Hamilton, W. D. (1964). The evolution of social
counterfeit self: The deceptive costs of faking behavior. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 7,
it. Psychological Science, 21, 712–720. 1–52.
Gino, F., & Pierce, L. (2009) The abundance Hamlin, J. K. (2013). Moral judgment and action
effect: Unethical behavior in the presence of in preverbal infants and toddlers: Evidence for
wealth. Organizational Behavior and Human an innate moral core. Current Directions in
Decision Processes, 109, 142–155. Psychological Science, 22, 186–193.
Gintis, H., Bowles, S., Boyd, R., & Fehr, E. Hardy, C. L., & Van Vugt, M. (2006). Nice guys
(2003). Explaining altruistic behavior in hu- finish first: The competitive altruism hypoth-
mans. Evolution and Human Behavior, 24, esis. Personality and Social Psychology Bulle-
153–172. tin, 32, 1402–1413.
Gneezy, A., Imas, A., Brown, A., Nelson, L. D., Hardy, S. A. (2006). Identity, reasoning, and
& Norton, M. I. (2012). Paying to be nice: emotion: An empirical comparison of three
Consistency and costly prosocial behavior. sources of moral motivation. Motivation and
Management Science, 58, 179–187. Emotion, 30, 207–215.
Goodwin, G. P., Piazza, J., & Rozin, P. (2014). Hardy, S. A., & Carlo, G. (2005). Identity as a
Moral character predominates in person per- source of moral motivation. Human Develop-
ception and evaluation. Journal of Personality ment, 48, 232–256.
and Social Psychology, 106, 148–168. Haslam, S. A., Reicher, S. D., & Platow, M. J.
Graham, J., Haidt, J., & Nosek, B. A. (2009). (2010). The new psychology of leadership:
Liberals and conservatives rely on different Identity, influence and power. London: Psy-
sets of moral foundations. Journal of Person- chology Press.
ality and Social Psychology, 96, 1029–1046. Hastings, M. (1985). The Oxford book of mili-
Gray, H. M., Gray, K., & Wegner, D. M. (2007). tary anecdotes. Oxford, UK: Oxford Univer-
Dimensions of mind perception. Science, 315, sity Press.
619. Higgins, T. (1987). Self-discrepancy: A theory
Gray, K., Waytz, A., & Young, L. (2012). The relating self and affect. Psychological Review,
moral dyad: A fundamental template unifying 94, 319–340.
moral judgment. Psychological Inquiry, 23, Hoffman, M. L. (2000). Empathy and moral
206–215. development: Implications for caring and jus-
Gray, K., & Wegner, D. M. (2009). Moral type- tice. New York: Cambridge University Press
casting: Divergent perceptions of moral agents Hofmann, W., Wisneski, D. C., Brandt, M. J., &
and moral patients. Journal of Personality and Skitka, L. J. (2014). Morality in everyday life.
Social Psychology, 96, 505–520. Science, 345, 1340–1343.
Gray, K., Young, L., & Waytz, A. (2012). Mind Inbar, Y., Pizarro, D. A., & Bloom, P. (2012).
perception is the essence of morality. Psycho- Disgusting smells cause decreased liking of
logical Inquiry, 23, 101–124. gay men. Emotion, 12, 23–27.
Greene, J. D., Sommerville, R. B., Nystrom, L. Janoff-Bulman, R., Sheikh, S., & Hepp, S. (2009).
E., Darley, J. M., & Cohen, J. D. (2001). An Proscriptive versus prescriptive morality: Two
fMRI investigation of emotional engagement faces of moral regulation. Journal of Personal-
in moral judgment. Science, 293, 2105–2108. ity and Social Psychology, 96, 521–537.
Guglielmo, S., Monroe, A. E., & Malle, B. F. Jennings, P. L., Mitchell, M. S., & Hannah, S.
(2009). At the heart of morality lies folk psy- T. (2014). The moral self: A review and inte-
chology. Inquiry, 5, 449–466. gration of the literature. Journal of Organiza-
Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional dog and its ra- tional Behavior, 36, S104–S168.
tional tail: A social intuitionist approach to Jordan, J., Mullen, E., & Murnighan, J. K.
moral judgment. Psychological Review, 108, (2011). Striving for the moral self: The effects
814–834. of recalling past moral actions on future moral
Haidt, J., & Graham, J. (2007). When morality behavior. Personality and Social Psychology
opposes justice: Conservatives have moral in- Bulletin, 37, 701–713.
tuitions that liberals may not recognize. Social Kant, I. (1959). Foundation of the metaphysics
Justice Research, 20, 98–116. of morals (L. W. Beck, Trans.). Indianapolis,
Haidt, J., & Joseph, C. (2004). Intuitive ethics: IN: Bobbs-Merrill. (Original work published
How innately prepared intuitions generate 1785)
culturally variable virtues. Daedalus, 133, Keltner, D., & Haidt, J. (1999). Social functions
55–66. of emotions at four levels of analysis. Cogni-
Haidt, J., Koller, S., & Dias, M. (1993). Affect, tion and Emotion, 13, 505–522.
culture, and morality, or is it wrong to eat Kohlberg, L. (1969). Stage and sequence: The
your dog? Journal of Personality and Social cognitive-developmental approach to social-
Psychology, 65, 613–628. ization. In D. A. Goslin (Ed.), Handbook of
 The Core of Morality Is the Moral Self 161

socialization theory and research (pp. 347– and mechanism produce both utilitarian and
480). Chicago: Rand McNally. risky choices. Perspectives on Psychological
Kraut, R. E. (1973). Effects of social labeling on Science, 10(4), 541–548.
giving to charity. Journal of Experimental So- Lucas, B. L., & Livingstone, R. W. (2014). Feel-
cial Psychology, 9, 551–562. ing socially connected increases utilitarian
Krebs, D. (2008). Morality: An evolutionary ac- choices in moral dilemmas. Journal of Experi-
count. Perspectives on Psychological Science, mental Social Psychology, 53, 1–4.
3, 149–172. Maguen, S., & Litz, B. (2012). Moral injury in
Kundu, P., & Cummins, D. D. (2012). Morality veterans of war. PTSD Research Quarterly,
and conformity: The Asch paradigm applied to 23, 1–3.
moral decisions. Social Influence, 8, 268–279. Markus, H., & Kunda, Z. (1986). Stability and
Kurzban, R., DeScioli, P., & O’Brien, E. (2007). malleability of the self-concept. Journal of Per-
Audience effects on moralistic punishment. sonality and Social Psychology, 51, 858–866.
Evolution and Human Behavior, 28, 75–84. Mazar, N., Amir, O., & Ariely, D. (2008). The
Lakoff, G. (2010). How liberals and conserva- dishonesty of honest people: A theory of self-
tives think. Chicago: University of Chicago concept maintenance. Journal of Marketing
Press. Research, 45, 633–644.
Lammers, J. (2012). Abstraction increases hy- McAdams, D. P. (1993). The stories we live by:
pocrisy. Journal of Experimental Social Psy- Personal myths and the making of the self.
chology, 48, 475–480. New York: Guilford Press.
Lapsley, D. K., & Narvaez, D. (2004). A social- McCullough, M. E., Kilpatrick, S. D., Emmons,
cognitive approach to the moral personality. R. A., & Larson, D. B. (2001). Is gratitude
In D. K. Lapsley & D. Narvaez (Eds.), Moral a moral affect? Psychological Bulletin, 127,
development, self, and identity (pp. 189–212). 249–266.
Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. Midgley, M. (1991). The origin of ethics. In P.
Leach, C. W., Bilali, R., & Pagliaro, S. (2013). Singer (Ed.), A companion guide to ethics
Groups and morality. In J. Simpson & J. F. (pp. 1–13). Oxford, UK: Blackwell Reference.
Dovidio (Eds.), APA handbook of personality Mikhail, J. (2007). Universal moral grammar:
and social psychology: Vol. 2. Interpersonal Theory, evidence and the future. Trends in
relationships and group processes (pp. 2–61). Cognitive Sciences, 11, 143–152.
Washington, DC: American Psychological As- Mill, J. S. (1998). Utilitarianism. New York:
sociation. Oxford University Press. (Original work pub-
Leach, C. W., Ellemers, N., & Barreto, M. lished 1861)
(2007). Group virtue: The importance of mo- Miller, D. T., & Effron, D. A. (2010). Psychologi-
rality (vs. competence and sociability) in the cal license: When it is needed and how it func-
positive evaluation of in-groups. Journal of tions. In M. P. Zanna & J. M. Olson (Eds.),
Personality and Social Psychology, 93, 234– Advances in experimental social psychology
249. (Vol. 43, pp. 117–158). San Diego, CA: Aca-
Lee, J. J., Im, D. K., Parmar, B. L., & Gino, F. demic Press/Elsevier.
(2015). Thick as thieves?: Dishonest behavior Miller, G. F. (2007). The sexual selection of
and egocentric social networks. Harvard Busi- moral virtues. Quarterly Review of Biology,
ness School Working Paper No. 15-064. Avail- 82, 97–125.
able at http://ssrn.com/abstract=2563196 Moll, J., de Oliveira-Souza, R., Garrido, G. J.,
orhttp://dx.doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.2563196 Bramanti, I. E., Caparelli, E. M., Pavia, M.
Lee, R. B., & DeVore, I. (Eds.). (1968). Man the L., . . ., & Grafman, J., (2007). The self as
hunter. Oxford, UK: Aldine. moral agent: Linking the neural bases of social
Lee, S. W. S., & Schwarz, N. (2010). Dirty hands agency and moral sensitivity. Social Neurosci-
and dirty mouths: Embodiment of the moral- ence, 2, 336–352.
purity metaphor is specific to the motor mo- Monin, B., & Jordan, A. H. (2009). The dynamic
dality involved in moral transgression. Psy- moral self: A social psychological perspective.
chological Science, 21, 1423–1425. In D. Narvaez & D. Lapsley (Eds.), Personal-
Lerner, M. J. (1980). The belief in a just world: ity, identity, and character: Explorations in
A fundamental delusion. New York: Plenum moral psychology (pp. 341–354). New York:
Press. Cambridge University Press.
Liu, B. S., & Ditto, P. H. (2012). What dilem- Monin, B., Sawyer, P. J., & Marquez, M. J.
ma?: Moral evaluation shapes factual belief. (2008). The rejection of moral rebels: Resent-
Social Psychological and Personality Science, ing those who do the right thing. Journal of
4, 316–323. Personality and Social Psychology, 95, 76–93.
Lucas, B. J., & Galinsky, A. D. (2015). Is utili- Mooijman, M., & van Dijk, W. W. (2014). The
tarianism risky?: How the same antecedents self in moral judgment: How self-affirmation
162 M O R A L I T Y, S O C I A L C O G N I T I O N , A N D I D E N T I T Y

affects the moral condemnation of harmless ploring the causes of good and evil (pp. 91–
sexual taboos. Cognition and Emotion, 29, 108). Washington, DC: American Psychologi-
1326–1334. cal Association.
Moore, A. B., Clark, B. A., & Kane, M. J. (2008). Plato. (1949). Timaeus (B. Jowett, Trans.). India-
Who shalt not kill?: Individual differences in napolis, IN: Bobbs-Merrill.
working memory capacity, executive control, Rai, T. S., & Fiske, A. P. (2011). Moral psychol-
and moral judgment. Psychological Science, ogy is relationship regulation: Moral motives
19, 549–557. for unity, hierarchy, equality, and proportion-
Mullen, E., & Monin, B. (2016). Consistency ality. Psychological Review, 118, 57–75.
versus licensing effects of past moral behavior. Ratner, R. K., & Miller, D. T. (2001). The norm
Annual Review of Psychology, 67, 363–385. of self-interest and its effects on social action.
Nelson, L. D., & Norton, M. I. (2005). From stu- Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
dent to superhero: Situational primes shape fu- 81, 5–16.
ture helping. Journal of Experimental Social Reed, A., II, & Aquino, K. F. (2003). Moral iden-
Psychology, 41, 423–430. tity and the expanding circle of moral regard
Newman, G. E., De Freitas, J., & Knobe, J. toward out-groups. Journal of Personality and
(2014). Beliefs about the true self explain Social Psychology, 84, 1270–1286.
asymmetries based on moral judgment. Cog- Reed, A., II, Aquino, K., & Levy, E. (2007).
nitive Science, 39, 96–125. Moral identity and judgments of charitable
Nichols, S., & Mallon, R. (2006). Moral dilem- behaviors. Journal of Marketing, 71(1), 178–
mas and moral rules. Cognition, 100, 530– 193.
542. Rest, J. R. (1984). The major components of
Nowak, M. A., & Sigmund, K. (1998). Evolution morality. In W. M. Kurtines & J. L. Gewirtz
of indirect reciprocity by image scoring. Na- (Eds.), Morality, moral behavior, and moral
ture, 393, 573–577. development (pp. 24–38) New York: Wiley.
Olson, J. M., Cheung, I., Conway, P., Hutchison, Rokeach, M. (1973). The nature of human val-
J., & Hafer, C. L. (2011). Distinguishing two ues. New York: Free Press.
meanings of moral exclusion: Irrelevance of Rozin, P., Haidt, J., & Fincher, K. (2009). From
fairness vs. rationalized harm-doing. Social oral to moral. Science, 323, 1179–1180.
Justice Research, 24, 1–26. Schlegel, R. J., Hicks, J. A., Arndt, J., & King, L.
Olson, J. M., Hafer, C. L., Cheung, I., & Con- A. (2009). Thine own self: True self-concept
way, P. (2009). Deservingness, the scope of accessibility and meaning in life. Journal of
justice, and actions toward others. In A. C. Personality and Social Psychology, 96, 473–
Kay, D. R. Bobocel, M. P. Zanna, & J. M. 490.
Olson (Eds.), The psychology of justice and Schnall, S., Benton, J., & Harvey, S. (2008).
legitimacy: The Ontario symposium (Vol. 11, With a clean conscience: Cleanliness reduces
pp. 125–149). New York: Psychology Press. the severity of moral judgments. Psychological
Omdahl, B. L., & O’Donnell, C. (1999). Emo- Science, 19, 1219–1222.
tional contagion, empathic concern and Schnall, S., Haidt, J., Clore, G. L., & Jordan, A.
communicative responsiveness as variables H. (2008). Disgust as embodied moral judg-
affecting nurses’ stress and occupational com- ment. Personality and Social Psychology Bul-
mitment. Journal of Advanced Nursing, 29, letin, 34, 1096–1109.
1351–1359. Schnall, S., Roper, J., & Fessler, D. M. T. (2010).
Opotow, S. (1993). Animals and the scope of jus- Elevation leads to altruism, above and beyond
tice. Journal of Social Issues, 49, 71–85. general positive affect. Psychological Science,
Pagliaro, S., Ellemers, N., & Barreto, M. (2011). 21, 315–320.
Sharing moral values: Anticipated ingroup Schumann, K. (2014). An affirmed self and a
respect as a determinant of adherence to mo- ­better apology: The effect of self-affirmation
rality-based (but not competence-based) group on transgressors’ responses to victims. Jour-
norms. Personality and Social Psychology nal of Experimental Social Psychology, 54,
Bulletin, 37, 1117–1129. 89–96.
Piaget, J. (1965). The moral judgment of the Schumann, K., & Dweck, C. S. (2014). Who ac-
child (M. Gabain, Trans.). New York: Free cepts responsibility for their transgressions?
Press. (Original work published 1932). Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin,
Pizarro, D. A., & Tannenbaum, D. (2011). Bring- 60, 1598–1610.
ing character back: How the motivation to Shalvi, S., Gino, F., Barkan, R., & Ayal, S. (2015).
evaluate character influences judgments of Self-serving justifications: Doing wrong and
moral blame. In M. Mikulincer & P. R. Shaver feeling moral. Current Directions in Psycho-
(Eds.), The social psychology of morality: Ex- logical Science, 24, 125–130.
 The Core of Morality Is the Moral Self 163

Shalvi, S., Handgraaf, M. J. J., & De Dreu, C. K. extremity biases. Journal of Personality and
W. (2011). Ethical manoeuvring: Why people Social Psychology, 52(4), 689.
avoid both major and minor lies. British Jour- Smaldino, P. E., Schank, J. C., & McElreath, R.
nal of Management, 22, S16–S27. (2013). Increased costs of cooperation help co-
Shaver, K. G. (1985). The attribution of blame: operators in the long run. American Natural-
Causality, responsibility, and blameworthi- ist, 181, 451–463.
ness. New York: Springer-Verlag. Sober, E., & Wilson, D. S. (1998). Unto others:
Shu, L. L., Gino, F., & Bazerman, M. (2010). The evolution and psychology of unselfish be-
Dishonest deed, clear conscience: When cheat- havior. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
ing leads to moral disengagement and motivat- Press.
ed forgetting. Personality and Social Psychol- Sousa, P., Holbrook, C., & Piazza, J. (2009). The
ogy Bulletin, 37, 330–349. morality of harm. Cognition, 113, 80–92.
Shu, L. L., Mazar, N., Gino, F., Ariely, D., & Ba- Steele, C. M. (1988). The psychology of self-af-
zerman, M. (2012). Signing at the beginning firmation: Sustaining the integrity of the self.
makes ethics salient and decreases dishonest Advances in Experimental Social Psychology,
self-reports in comparison to signing at the 21, 261–302
end. Proceedings of the National Academy of Strohminger, N., & Nichols, S. (2014). The es-
Sciences of the USA, 109, 15197–15200. sential moral self. Cognition, 131, 159–171.
Shweder, R. A., Much, N. C., Mahapatra, M., Susewind, M., & Hoelzl, E. (2014). A matter
& Park, L. (1997). The “big three” of moral- of perspective: Why past moral behavior can
ity (autonomy, community, and divinity), and sometimes encourage and other times discour-
the “big three” explanations of suffering. In A. age future moral striving. Journal of Applied
Brandt & P. Rozin (Eds.), Morality and health Social Psychology, 44, 201–209.
(pp. 119–169). New York: Routledge. Sutton, J., Smith, P. K., & Swettenham, J. (1999).
Simpson, B., Harrell, A., & Willer, R. (2013). Bullying and “theory of mind”: A critique of
Hidden paths from morality to cooperation: the “social skills deficit” view of antisocial be-
Moral judgments promote trust and trustwor- haviour. Social Development, 8, 117–127.
thiness. Social Forces, 91, 1529–1548. Tajfel, H., & Turner, J. C. (1985). The social
Skitka, L. J. (2002). Do the means always justify identity theory of intergroup behavior. In S.
the ends, or do the ends sometimes justify the Worschel & W. G. Austin (Eds.), Psychology
means?: A value protection model of justice of intergroup relations (pp. 7–24). Chicago:
reasoning. Personality and Social Psychology Nelson-Hall.
Bulletin, 28, 588–597. Tangney, J. P., Stuewig, J., & Mashek, D. J.
Skitka, L. J. (2003). Of different minds: An ac- (2007). Moral emotions and moral behavior.
cessibility identity model of justice reasoning. Annual Review of Psychology, 58, 345–372.
Personality and Social Psychology Review, 7, Tetlock, P. E., Kristel, O. V., Elson, S., Green,
286–297. M. C., & Lerner, J. S. (2000). The psychology
Skitka, L. J., Bauman, C. W., & Mullen, E. of the unthinkable: Taboo trade-offs, forbid-
(2008). Morality and justice: An expanded den base rates, and heretical counterfactuals.
theoretical perspective and review. In K. A. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
Hedgvedt & J. Clay-Warner (Eds.), Advances 78, 853–870.
in group processes: Vol. 25. Justice (pp. 1–27). Trivers, R. (1971). The evolution of reciprocal al-
Bingley, UK: Emerald Group. truism. Review of Biology, 46, 35–57.
Skitka, L. J., Bauman, C. W., & Sargis, E. G. Turiel, E. (1983). The development of social
(2005). Moral conviction: Another contribu- knowledge: Morality and convention. Cam-
tor to attitude strength or something more? bridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, van Nunspeet, F., Derks, B., Ellemers, N., &
88, 895–917. Nieuwenhuis, S. (2015). Moral impression
Skitka, L. J., & Houston, D. A. (2001). When management: Evaluation by an in-group mem-
due process is of no consequence: Moral man- ber during a moral IAT affects perceptual at-
dates and presumed defendant guilt or inno- tention and conflict and response monitoring.
cence. Social Justice Research, 14, 305–326. Social Psychological and Personality Science,
Skitka, L. J., & Tetlock, P. E. (1992). Allocat- 6, 183–192.
ing scarce resources: A contingency model of Van Zant, A. B., & Moore, D. A. (2015). Lead-
distributive justice. Journal of Experimental ers’ use of moral justifications increases pol-
Social Psychology, 28, 491–522. icy support. Psychological Science, 26, 934–
Skowronski, J. J., & Carlston, D. E. (1987). So- 943.
cial judgment and social memory: The role of Vess, M., Schlegel, R. J., Hicks, J. A., & Arndt, J.
cue diagnosticity in negativity, positivity, and (2013). Guilty, but not ashamed: “True” self-
164 M O R A L I T Y, S O C I A L C O G N I T I O N , A N D I D E N T I T Y

conceptions influence affective responses to Zhong, C.-B., Bohns, V. K., & Gino, F. (2010). A
personal shortcomings. Journal of Personal- good lamp is the best police: Darkness increas-
ity, 83, 213–224. es self-interested behavior and dishonesty. Psy-
Vohs, K. D., & Schooler, J. (2008). The value of chological Science, 21, 311–314.
believing in free will: Encouraging a belief in Zhong, C.-B., & Liljenquist, K. A. (2006). Wash-
determinism increases cheating. Psychological ing away your sins: Threatened morality and
Science, 19, 49–54. physical cleansing. Science, 313, 1451–1452.
Walker, L. J., & Hennig, K. H. (2004). Differing Zhong, C.-B., Liljenquist, K., & Cain, D. M.
conceptions of moral exemplarity: Just, brave, (2009). Moral self-regulation: Licensing and
and caring. Journal of Personality and Social compensation. In D. De Cremer (Ed.), Psycho-
Psychology, 86, 629–647. logical perspectives on ethical behavior and
Weiner, B. (1993). On sin versus sickness: A decision making (pp. 75–89). Charlotte, NC:
theory of perceived responsibility and social Information Age.
motivation. American Psychologist, 48, 957. Zhong, C.-B., Strejcek, K., & Sivanathan, N.
Wondra, J. D., & Ellsworth, P. C. (2015). An ap- (2010). A clean self can render harsh moral
praisal theory of empathy and other vicarious judgment. Journal of Experimental Social
emotional experiences. Psychological Review, Psychology, 46, 859–862.
122, 411–428. Zitek, E. M., Jordan, A. H., Monin, B., & Leach,
Wright, R. (1994). The moral animal: The new F. R. (2010). Victim entitlement to behave self-
science of evolutionary psychology. New ishly. Journal of Personality and Social Psy-
York: Pantheon Books. chology, 98, 245–255.
C H A P T E R 17

Thinking Morally about Animals

Steve Loughnan
Jared Piazza

Why are we comfortable with eating animals, but uncomfortable


with hurting them?

A blend of attributions, emotions, and identity processes combine to


help us evade this moral dilemma.

It is difficult to think morally about animals. Suitner, 2008). Among these unusual cases,
The category animal itself is sufficiently we would suggest that animals are the most
vast and variable as to be almost psycho- long-standing. Whether as predator, prey,
logically meaningless, stretching from the pest, or pet, both ancestral and modern hu-
near-human capacities of great apes to the mans spend their days surrounded by ani-
alien simplicity of microscopic organisms. mals and animal products. Unlike the tools
This objective variability is compounded and artifacts that also surround us, our
by a subjective variability; different people, treatment of animals has a decidedly moral
in different places, at different times, think flavor. Yet the extent of our moral respon-
about the same animals differently (Amiot sibilities toward animals has been and will
& Bastian, 2015). Crossing this biological continue to be a matter of dispute.
diversity among the animal kingdom with In this chapter, we attempt to map how
the psychological diversity among people re- people think morally about animals, par-
sults in an explosion of complexity. ticularly when thinking about the suffering
The great anthropologist Claude Levi- of animals. The main way in which people
Strauss recognized this when he wrote that harm animals is by eating them (in terms of
animals are both “good to eat” and “good the scale of suffering); however, our work is
to think” (Levi-Strauss, 1962). Although not limited to the psychology of meat. We
the authors of this chapter are divided on argue that three main psychological pro-
whether animals are good to eat, we agree cesses are at work when people are thinking
that they are good to think with, especially morally about animals: attribution, emotion,
where morality is concerned. Animals reside and identity (see Figure 17.1). At the cognitive
in a moral gray area between artifacts and level, we focus on attributions of intelligence,
humans, shared with spirits, gods, and ro- experience, harmfulness, and categorization.
bots (Haslam, Kashima, Loughnan, Shi, & At the level of emotions, we examine both

165
166 M O R A L I T Y, S O C I A L C O G N I T I O N , A N D I D E N T I T Y

• Intelligent? Can suffer?


Attribution/ Cute? [+]
categorization • Dangerous? [–]
• Animal used as food? [–]

• Elicit disgust or fear? [–]


Emotion • Elicit sympathy or
tenderness? [+]

• Negative implications
for self or group morality?
[–]
Identity
• Positive implications
for self or group morality?
[+]

FIGURE 17.1.  Factors shown to enhance [+] or reduce [–] the perceived moral standing of animals.

the emotions that animals elicit and the emo- ing specific domains. In this chapter, we
tions we feel about our treatment of animals. focus on such a domain.
Finally, for identity, we examine how our Within the domain of animals and moral-
treatment of animals, or prevailing attitudes ity, we see several important psychological
about the treatment of animals, can challenge theories of morality at work. In this chapter,
our moral identities, resulting in a number of we employ to a greater or lesser extent per-
downstream consequences. We then use this spectives on mind perception (Waytz, Gray,
model of thinking morally about animals to Epley, & Wegner, 2010) and the social intu-
point to empirical shortcomings and future itionist model (Haidt, 2001). We also draw
directions for this field. on a range of established moral psychologi-
cal phenomena and effects, including mo-
tivated cognition (Dunning, 1999; Kunda,
Historical Context 1990), moral identity processes (Minson &
Monin, 2012), moral emotions (especially
Unlike many of the contributions to this disgust, guilt, and tenderness), and rational-
volume, our approach to thinking morally izations (Mercier, 2011; Piazza et al., 2015),
about animals is not steeped in a particu- and make the distinction between judgment
lar theoretical tradition. Rather, we adopt and decision making. Finally, we cast an
a domain-based approach to the study of even broader net to draw on social psycho-
morality and animals. By this we mean that logical classics such as cognitive dissonance
the study of animals is an important domain theory (Festinger, 1957), the stereotype
in its own right, and one in which we can content model (Fiske, Cuddy, Glick, & Xu,
see multiple theories of human psychology 2002), and the study of prejudice.
more generally at work. The notion that we
should focus on domains in addition to psy-
chological processes was outlined by Paul Theoretical Stance
Rozin (2006). Rozin argues that psychology
has been focused primarily on uncovering Our moral judgment and behavior toward
domain-general processes and that this has animals draw on three bases: cognition,
resulted in a relative neglect of understand- emotion, and identity. Below we outline how
 Thinking Morally about Animals 167

all three can change the way we engage mor- Mind attribution to animals is not the
ally with animals. only attributional factor influencing judg-
ments of animal moral standing. Recently,
Piazza et al. (2014) found that, as with hu-
Cognition
mans, the character of the animal also mat-
Cognitive processes capture how we think ters. Animals that are seen as dangerous
about animals. We focus on how animals and harmful, particularly to human beings
are perceived, specifically the types of minds (e.g., snakes, sharks), suffer declinations in
they are believed to possess, and how they moral standing. Importantly, the harmful
are categorized. character of the animal had an effect on the
When deciding who to care about, minds animal’s moral standing independent of the
matter (see Schein & Gray, Chapter 37, this amount of mind (e.g., intelligence) attrib-
volume; Waytz & Young, Chapter 19, this uted to it.
volume). There are at least two correlated Concerns about the harmful nature of the
dimensions along which people attribute animal raise issues pertaining to human wel-
mind: agency (complex cognition; e.g., intel- fare. By contrast, mind attribution may af-
ligence) and experience (emotion; e.g., capac- fect judgments of moral standing by making
ity to feel pain). Humans and animals differ animals appear more human, thus exploit-
on both dimensions, with animals being ing the care we typically reserve for human
seen as lacking primarily agency but also beings. Anthropomorphizing animals—that
experience, compared with humans (Gray, is, ascribing to them uniquely human traits,
Gray, & Wegner, 2007). Mind attribution is such as social intelligence—generally leads
an important part of deciding which people us to care about them more. Indeed, people
are worthy of moral concern (Gray, Knobe, both report more distress and recommend
Sheskin, Bloom, & Feldman-Barrett, 2011; harsher punishment when led to believe
Loughnan, Haslam, Murnane, et al., 2010). that someone abused an animal similar to
Likewise, minds matter for thinking morally a human (a monkey) versus a dissimilar ani-
about animals (Piazza, Landy, & Goodwin, mal (a beetle; see Plous, 1993). Consistent
2014; Sytsma & Machery, 2012). with this finding, making animals appear
The link between mind attribution to ani- more human-like by closing the human–ani-
mals and moral concern is simply demon- mal divide increases concern for their wel-
strated. In a correlational study, Bastian and fare (Bastian, Costello, Loughnan, & Hod-
colleagues (Bastian, Loughnan, Haslam, & son, 2012).
Radke, 2012) showed that as mind attribu- Although the world is populated by a
tion to animals increased, their perceived plethora of animal species, lay people tend
edibility decreased. Similarly, vegetarians, to organize fauna into a relatively small
whose moral concern for animals at least number of categories or “folk taxa”: pets,
extends to not eating them, attribute to ani- food, and dangerous animals, for example.
mals more mental capacities than do om- These categories are flexible, and the same
nivores (Bastian, Loughnan, et al., 2012; animal can occupy different categories for
Bilewicz, Imhoff, & Drogosz, 2011). Finally, different people and can change categories
in ongoing work, we (Piazza & Loughnan, over time. Consider the case of the wolf
2016) have recently found that experimen- (Canine lupus). Once considered a predator,
tally manipulating an animal’s intelligence widespread agriculture and firearms turned
serves to decrease its perceived edibility, it into a pest, and its near extinction turned
increase condemnation at its consumption, it into protected wildlife. Another example
and increase the amount of guilt people feel would be the rabbit (Leporidae), which has
about eating the animal, though this does transformed from game into pest, pet, and
not apply to animals currently being con- petri dish. It has long been known in psy-
sumed as food in the perceiver’s culture (see chology that categorization shapes judgment
the section on emotion later in the chapter). and decision making (Barsalou, 1990), and
Stated otherwise, mind attribution is impor- this is no exception for animals and mo-
tant both for moral decision making and rality. Bratanova, Loughnan, and Bastian
moral judgments. (2011) presented American participants with
168 M O R A L I T Y, S O C I A L C O G N I T I O N , A N D I D E N T I T Y

an animal native to Papua New Guinea, the driving this effect? We know that people
Bennett’s tree kangaroo (Dendrolagus ben- have a tendency to withdraw mind from
nettianus). Capitalizing on participants’ lack people who are suffering (Kozak, Marsh,
of knowledge about the animal, half were & Wegner, 2006), so perhaps the root lies
manipulated to believe the animal was food, in emphasizing the suffering caused by meat
and half to believe that it was wildlife. They production. Evidence for this account comes
found that compared with categorization as from work showing that having people write
wildlife, being seen as “food” reduced attri- about the origins of meat compared with the
butions of moral concern to the animal. This origins of vegetables causes them to deny an-
occurred despite participants’ not eating the imals more mind and feel emotionally better
animal, minimizing self-interest concerns. It about meat consumption (Bastian, Lough-
appears that simply being categorized as a nan, & Haslam, 2012). If it is the case that
“food animal” is sufficient to diminish an denying food animals minds makes people
animal’s moral standing. feel better, it is little stretch to conclude that
The preceding discussion—in particu- they are motivated to view food animals as
lar, that on categorization—has considered possessing lesser moral standing.
cognition about animals’ minds and moral Just as reducing animals’ minds can be
standing as a relatively cool, cognitive pro- beneficial to people, so too can increasing
cess. We can see that viewing an animal as mind attribution. In the sociality, effectance,
mentally complex increases moral concern, and elicited agent knowledge (SEEK) model
whereas seeing it as food decreases concern. of anthropomorphism, Epley, Waytz, and
As we outline in the next two sections, how- Cacioppo (2007) lay out a series of condi-
ever, motivation and emotion play an impor- tions that will increase the likelihood of
tant role in determining which animals we attributing mind to animals. Two of these
consider worthy of concern, and when. conditions hinge on human needs: the need
to feel socially connected (sociality) and the
need to understand the world (efficacy).
Motivational Influences on Animal
For instance, we attribute more “uniquely
Trait Perception
human” traits to pet animals when we are
Moral judgments and decisions about ani- lonely (Epley, Waytz, Akalis, & Cacioppo,
mals do not take place in a cold, cognitive 2008), and we attribute more mind to a dog
vacuum but are additionally influenced by when we need to understand its behavior
people’s motivations, particularly motiva- (Epley et al., 2008). Where these increases
tions to see oneself in a positive light (Piazza in mind attribution transfer into increased
et al., 2015). We argue that people attribute moral concern waits to be seen.
and deny mind, humanity, and sometimes
moral standing to animals when it is in their
Emotion
interests to do so.
Perhaps the clearest case of people being Animals evoke a range of emotions, from
motivated to alter their perception of ani- fear to compassion. Which emotions get
mals is when they inflict harm on them, evoked is primarily a function of the char-
whether directly or indirectly. Eating meat acteristics people attribute to animals and,
can be one such situation in which people once evoked, emotions guide our moral
are motivated to view animals as relatively judgments and treatment of animals. Fear,
lacking in mind and as possessing lesser disgust, sympathy, and tenderness are emo-
moral standing. In a simple study, Lough- tions in particular that appear to strongly
nan, Haslam, and Bastian (2010) had par- influence the way we treat animals.
ticipants eat either beef or cashew nuts and
then report their moral concern for animals
Fear, Disgust, and Sympathy
in general and cows in particular. Compared
with people who ate nuts, people who ate Research by Piazza et al. (2014) explored
beef reported more constricted moral con- two attributional dimensions pertinent to
cern for animals in general and lower moral the moral standing of animals: harmfulness
status afforded to a cow. What might be and mind. Animals perceived as dangerous
 Thinking Morally about Animals 169

(e.g., spiders, snakes, wolves) tended to elicit 2007). One possible explanation for this dis-
fear and were judged to have lower levels of parity is that the relationship between sym-
moral standing. By contrast, animals per- pathy and intelligence is curvilinear. It may
ceived as highly intelligent and emotional be that human targets are ascribed more
(e.g., dogs, dolphins, elephants) tended to baseline intelligence than animal targets, so
elicit higher levels of sympathy (i.e., concern highly intelligent animals only begin to ap-
for their suffering) and were ascribed higher proach the levels of low intelligent humans
levels of moral standing. (e.g., children). It may be that for sympathy
Disgust is an emotion that is directly per- to be evoked the animal must possess intel-
tinent to the treatment of animals as a food ligence to a degree that approximates the
source. For example, research by Ruby and lower end of the spectrum for humans. This
Heine (2012) found that across cultures the hypothesis awaits empirical testing.
appearance of an animal (whether it was
seen as cute or ugly) was a strong predictor
Tenderness
of whether an animal was seen as edible or
disgusting. Intelligent animals are seen as Tenderness is an emotion we feel in the
less edible, on average, than less intelligent presence of entities that possess neotenous,
animals (Bastian et al., 2012), consistent “cute,” or baby-like features, for example,
with the findings by Piazza and Loughnan large head, protruding forehead, large eyes,
(2016) that intelligent animals tend to be chubby cheeks, and small nose and mouth
afforded moral standing. However, intelli- (Sherman & Haidt, 2011). Such entities
gent animals are not always afforded moral evoke nurturing responses. For example,
standing. As suggested by a motivated cog- human baby faces have been found to elicit
nition perspective (e.g., Dunning, 1999; care motivations and to activate reward re-
Kunda, 1990), people tend to use intelligence gions of the brain (e.g., nucleus accumbens),
information about animals in a manner that particularly for women (Glocker et al., 2009;
promotes their self-interested ends. Recent Sprengelmeyer, et al., 2009). The same goes
studies by the authors (Piazza & Lough- for cute animals. When people view images
nan, 2016) found that, all else equal, people of cute, young animals (e.g., puppies and
think it is wrong to use intelligent animals kittens vs. dogs and cats), they exert more
as food; however, this is not the case when behavioral care, operationalized in terms of
the animal is conventionally used for meat improved performance on a fine-motor task
(see Figure 17.1). In a recent unpublished line and reductions in grip strength (Sherman,
of work, we had participants consider one Haidt, & Coan, 2009).
of three animals: a fictitious, alien animal But does cuteness serve to foster moral at-
they had no exposure to; a tapir, an exotic titudes toward animals? Sherman and Haidt
animal that Westerners do not eat; and a (2011) have argued that cuteness fosters
pig, an animal commonly eaten in Western social engagement rather than care more
cultures. All participants received the same specifically. They argue that cute entities be-
information about the intelligence of the come objects of moral concern by engaging
animal; however, it was only for the pig that positive social attention. Grauerholz (2007)
the information about the animal’s intel- argued that “cute” animal images are some-
ligence was ignored when forming a moral times used to strategically advertise meat
judgment about the animal. Participants in products in a way that enhances positive
the pig condition thought it was less wrong reactions from consumers by presenting a
to use the animal as a food source, and they relatable image of the animal, thus dissociat-
felt less guilt about doing so, compared with ing animal suffering from the meat product.
the other animal conditions. This raises the question of whether cuteness
Interestingly, the experience of sympathy might motivate or demotivate meat con-
toward highly intelligent animals is some- sumption. On the one hand, cuteness might
what discrepant with the data for human raise perceptions of moral standing, thus de-
targets. Research suggests that highly intel- motivating meat consumption. On the other
ligent human targets are afforded respect, hand, cuteness might make the animal less
but not sympathy (Fiske, Cuddy, & Glick, disgusting, motivating meat consumption.
170 M O R A L I T Y, S O C I A L C O G N I T I O N , A N D I D E N T I T Y

A recent study by Piazza, McLatchie, Ole- feeling sympathy for animals used as food
sen, and Tomaszczuk (2016) found evidence (Rothgerber, 2014). This process may be
that cuteness tends to increase an animal’s similar to the way people seek to avoid feel-
moral standing. The authors presented par- ing empathy toward human victims because
ticipants with images of baby and adult of the behavioral implications such feelings
farm animals (e.g., chicks/chickens, piglets/ entail (Shaw, Batson, & Todd, 1994).
pigs) and made ratings of the animals in a
between-subjects design. Baby animals were
Emotion Regulation
rated more cute and elicited tenderness more
than adult animals, and they were also at- Very little is known about how people regu-
tributed greater moral standing, despite late the emotions they feel toward animals,
being perceived as no more intelligent. Fur- or the guilt they might experience as a con-
thermore, cuteness (which highly correlated flicted omnivore. Research on emotion regu-
with feelings of tenderness) and harmful- lation suggests reappraisal is an important
ness independently predicted attributions of process (Gross & Johns, 2003). Rationaliza-
moral standing. From this research we see tion is one form of reappraisal. Rationaliza-
that cuteness is an important factor con- tion involves generating reasons for one’s
tributing to the moral standing of animals, behavior when it is called into question by
orthogonal to harmfulness. However, this others (Haidt, 2001; Mercier, 2011). These
study did not test whether cuteness serves reasons do not have to be thought out ahead
to motivate or demotivate meat consump- of time; they can simply be generated on the
tion. Further studies by Piazza and Lough- spot. At least one study has shown rational-
nan (2016) suggest that, at least for women, ization to be an effective strategy for om-
feeling tenderness for an animal temporarily nivores. Piazza et al. (2015, Study 4) found
suppresses appetite for meat. In one study, that omnivores who highly endorsed various
the authors had participants rate their appe- “4N” justifications for eating meat (that it
tite for a meat dish that was derived from an is Necessary, Natural, Normal, and Nice
adult cow or calf, or no information about to eat meat) tended to experience less guilt
the animal source was given. Providing an about their animal-product consumption
image of the animal along with the meat re- than omnivores who were less persuaded
duced the meat’s appeal, but the effect was by these justifications. Thus rationalization
largest when the animal was a baby, and may be an important mechanism for regu-
reductions in appetite occurred only among lating guilt toward animal suffering.
female participants.
Identity
Moderators of Emotion
Much of the research on morality and ani-
There are important moderators of the emo- mals has focused on the animal; how people
tions people experience toward animals. think and feel about the animal will in-
Vegetarians and vegans have been shown fluence how much they care about it. The
to express greater empathy toward animals preceding discussion of emotion regulation
than omnivores (Preylo & Arikawa, 2008). hints at the important additional factor of
They also exhibit greater activation of em- how people think and feel about themselves.
pathy-related brain regions when viewing People’s interactions with animals will shape
images of animals suffering (Filippi et al., how they see themselves, allowing them to
2010). Individuals who had owned a pet as maintain and enjoy important aspects of
a child also exhibit greater empathy toward their identities. Indeed, people appear to
animals, and this empathy appears to pre- believe that animals can directly contribute
dict meat avoidance practices in adulthood to their identity. Eating aggressive animals
(Rothgerber & Mican, 2014). At the same makes some people think they will become
time, not all individuals who empathize with more aggressive, effectively ingesting not
animals adopt a vegetarian diet. This may only the meat but the mentality of the beast
be because high-empathy omnivores engage (Rozin & Nemeroff, 1990). More broadly—
in “look the other way” strategies to avoid and less literally—eating animals has impli-
 Thinking Morally about Animals 171

cations for our identities, challenging some would seem, the more valid their moral posi-
and bolstering others. tion becomes, which we would expect to be
Recent perspectives in moral psychol- threatening to omnivores, who at least in the
ogy suggest that the morality of others can United States currently outnumber vegetar-
sometimes serve as a threat to one’s own ians and vegans 20:1 (Ruby, 2012). Indeed,
moral identity (Minson & Monin, 2012; a recent correlational study by Piazza and
Monin, Sawyer, & Marquez, 2008). The colleagues (2016) found exactly the pattern
reason is that moral positions have norma- of relationships we might expect if ethical
tive force, that is, they are thought to apply vegetarians pose a moral identity threat to
to everyone, not just the individuals who omnivores. Participants rated the prevalence
profess them. Thus the moral action of one of various groups (among them meat eaters,
individual (or group of individuals) can be semivegetarians, strict vegetarians, and veg-
interpreted as a tacit condemnation of those ans), and responded to a multi-item measure
individuals who fail to do likewise. of vegan-directed prejudice (e.g., “I would
In the domain of animals, this tacit moral be uncomfortable with a strict vegetarian or
condemnation can be observed most clearly vegan teaching my child”). In line with pre-
in the reactions of omnivores toward the dictions, prejudice toward vegans increased
“moral” motivations of vegetarians and veg- as vegans were perceived to be increasingly
ans. Morally motivated vegetarians can pose prevalent in American society. Conversely,
an implicit (and at times explicit) reproach prejudice toward vegans decreased as meat
to omnivores. One response to this reproach eaters were perceived to be increasingly
is to engage in explicit meat-eating justifica- prevalent in society.
tions (Piazza et al., 2015); another response In short, seeing others as treating animals
is to openly derogate ethical vegetarians as more morally than oneself appears to raise
self-righteous or misguided—for example, concerns about one’s moral identity. These
by questioning whether food animals ac- concerns with seeing the self as moral can
tually suffer as vegetarians claim they do manifest in a range of ways, including dero-
(Rothgerber, 2014). gation of animals and of other people.
Is there evidence to support the idea that
omnivores feel morally threatened by ethi-
cal vegetarians? A study by Minson and Empirical Challenges
Monin (2012) showed that omnivores were
more hostile toward vegetarians when they One of the central ideas motivating our per-
thought that vegetarians perceived their spective is that people avoid harming ani-
own group as morally superior to meat eat- mals or recognizing that they harm animals
ers. More direct evidence comes from a re- because doing so would make them feel bad
cent study conducted by one of the authors about themselves. Although there is some
(Piazza & Loughnan, 2016) with a sample evidence that denying meat animals minds
of American omnivores and meat abstain- reduces negative affect (Bastian et al., 2012)
ers. In this study omnivores rated vegetar- and that people imagine harming intelligent
ians as significantly more self-righteous than animals will make people feel bad (Piazza &
meat abstainers, consistent with the idea Loughnan, 2016), at present the argument
that vegetarians pose a particular kind of remains speculative. Do people feel that their
symbolic threat to omnivores—one in which moral self or moral identity is undermined
omnivores perceive vegetarians as claiming when they are reminded how their behavior
a moral high ground with regards to their harms animals? Alternatively, does remind-
eating habits. ing people that they contribute to the suffer-
A motivational approach would predict ing of animals temporarily undermine their
that omnivores become more hostile toward moral self, motivating them to seek out ways
vegetarians insofar as vegetarians are per- of restoring their moral credibility? In short,
ceived to pose a threat to their moral iden- is our treatment of animals meaningfully tied
tity. One way vegetarians might pose such a to our sense of ourselves as moral people? It
threat is by growing in numbers. The more may be that challenges to the moral self is
prevalent ethical vegetarians become, it a point which underlies many of the effects
172 M O R A L I T Y, S O C I A L C O G N I T I O N , A N D I D E N T I T Y

when it comes to thinking morally about animal rights organizations may look to
animals. To the extent that people feel se- find ways of affirming the identity benefits
cure or insecure in their own moral identity, of adopting a reduced- or no-meat diet. The
they may think differently about animals. If second application would be the diabolic
such an account were true, thinking morally opposite: identifying ways to decrease moral
about animals would be inexorably tied to concern for animals used for profit or whose
thinking morally about the self. welfare poses a hurdle to economic interest.
The study of how people think mor- This chapter opened with the observation
ally about animals is still relatively young. that animals exist in the gray area between
At present, we feel the effects identified in humans and objects, at the margins of our
this domain are somewhat decomposed (see moral concern. Other entities reside here as
Figure 17.1). We know, for instance, that well: fetuses, people in comas, violent crimi-
categorization changes judgments of moral nals, homeless people (Gray et al., 2007).
concern and that cuteness increases moral For some people, these entities are clearly
concern. What happens when a cute animal within our scope of moral concern; for other
is categorized as food? We know that seeing people, they are beyond the boundary of en-
an animal as more intelligent increases our tities we need to care about. Perhaps, most
concern for its well-being, and that seeing an importantly, we have shown how moral con-
animal as similar to humans increases our cern for animals is a profoundly malleable
concern for its well-being. What happens process; whether a given animal is offered
when an animal looks a lot like a human moral standing depends on a number of mo-
but is unintelligent or dangerous? What tivational factors, chief among them wheth-
about when it looks, acts, and interacts in er the animal’s suffering has direct implica-
a very different way to humans but is highly tions for the actor’s own moral identity. By
intelligent? Put simply, it may be that some delving deeply into the specific domain of
of these effects more powerfully determine animals and morality we have shown how
our moral concern than others. To inves- a nuanced picture can be painted of human
tigate this possibility, rather than seeking morality, and how this can have practical
new effects, future research could compare implications. Similarly, other cases at the
and contrast these identified effects, finding margins of moral concern may benefit from
the prime movers of our concern for animal this treatment.
welfare. If our ultimate aim were to increase Animals are an important part of our
people’s concern for animals, it is important moral world. Our attitudes range from
to know the major determinants of thinking loving them like family members to mass
morally about animals. slaughter and extinction. We feel that this
is a field in which the psychology of moral-
ity can explain commonplace moral behav-
Extension and Expansion ior. To add to Levi-Strauss, animals are not
only good to think about, but good to think
We see the study of animals and morality as about morally.
an important, real-world domain of human
morality. There are two potential applica- REFERENCES
tions of this work. The first would be to find
ways of increasing moral concern for ani- Amiot, C. E., & Bastian, B. (2015). Toward a
mals. Animal rights organizations are heav- psychology of human–animal relations. Psy-
ily investing in increasing public concern for chological Bulletin, 141, 6–47.
animals, be they wildlife or farm animals. Barsalou, L. W. (1990). Access and inference in
Understanding how presenting, categoriz- categorization. Bulletin of the Psychonomic
Society, 28, 268–271.
ing, and attributing mind to animals can in-
Bastian, B., Loughnan, S., Haslam, N., &
crease concern and how this interacts with Radke, H. R. M. (2012). Don’t mind meat?:
the way people see themselves are important The denial of mind to animals used for human
areas of research which can be employed in consumption. Personality and Social Psychol-
this domain. To take a concrete example, if ogy Bulletin, 38, 247–256.
eating animals is a threat to moral identity, Bilewicz, M., Imhoff, R., & Drogosz, M. (2011).
 Thinking Morally about Animals 173

The humanity of what we eat: Conceptions Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional dog and its ra-
of human uniqueness among vegetarians and tional tail: A social intuitionist approach to
omnivores. European Journal of Social Psy- moral judgment. Psychological Review, 108,
chology, 41, 201–209. 814–834.
Bratanova, B., Loughnan, S., & Bastian, B. Haslam, N., Kashima, Y., Loughnan, S., Shi, J.,
(2011). The effect of categorization as food on & Suitner, C. (2008). Subhuman, inhuman,
the perceived moral standing of animals. Ap- and superhuman: Contrasting humans with
petite, 57, 193–196. nonhumans in three cultures. Social Cogni-
Dunning, D. (1999). A newer look: Motivated tion, 26(2), 248–258.
social cognition and the schematic representa- Kozak, M., Marsh, A., & Wegner, D. (2006).
tion of social concepts. Psychological Inquiry, What do I think you’re doing?: Action identi-
10, 1–11. fication and mind attribution. Journal of Per-
Epley, N., Waytz, A., Akalis, S., & Cacioppo, sonality and Social Psychology, 90, 543–555.
J. T. (2008). When we need a human: Moti- Kunda, Z. (1990). The case for motivated rea-
vational determinants of anthropomorphism. soning. Psychological Bulletin, 108, 480–498.
Social Cognition, 26(2), 143–155. Levi-Strauss, C. (1962). The savage mind. Paris:
Epley, N., Waytz, A., & Cacioppo, J. T. (2007). Librairie Plon.
On seeing human: A three-factor theory of an- Loughnan, S., Haslam, N., & Bastian, B. (2010).
thropomorphism. Psychological Review, 114, The role of meat consumption in the denial of
864–886. moral status and mind to meat animals. Ap-
Festinger, L. A. (1957). A theory of cognitive dis- petite, 55, 156–159.
sonance. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Loughnan, S., Haslam, N., Murnane, T., Vaes,
Press. J., Reynolds, C., & Suitner, C. (2010). Objec-
Filippi, M., Riccitelli, G., Falini, A., Di Salle, tification leads to depersonalization: The de-
F., Vuilleumier, P., Comi, G., & Rocca, M. nial of mind and moral concern to objectified
A. (2010). The brain functional networks as- others. European Journal of Social Psychol-
sociates to human and animal suffering differ ogy, 40, 709–717.
among omnivores, vegetarians and vegans. Mercier, H. (2011). What good is moral reason-
PLOS ONE, 5(5), e10847. ing? Mind and Society, 10(2), 131–148.
Fiske, S. T., Cuddy, A. J. C., & Glick, P. (2007). Minson, J. A., & Monin, B. (2012). Do-gooder
Universal dimensions of social cognition: derogation: Disparaging morally motivated
Warmth and competence. Trends in Cognitive minorities to defuse anticipated reproach. So-
Sciences, 11, 77–83. cial Psychological and Personality Science,
Fiske, S. T., Cuddy, A., Glick, P., & Xu, J. 3(2), 200–207.
(2002). A model of (often mixed) stereotype Monin, B., Sawyer, P. J., & Marquez, M. J.
content: Competence and warmth respectively (2008). The rejection of moral rebels: Resent-
follow from perceived status and competition. ing those who do the right thing. Journal of
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, Personality and Social Psychology, 95(1),
82, 878–902 76–93.
Glocker, M. L., Langleben, D. D., Ruparel, K., Piazza, J., Landy, J. F., & Goodwin, G. P. (2014).
Loughead, J. W., Gur, R. C., & Sachser, N. Cruel nature: Harmfulness as an important,
(2009). Baby schema in infant faces induces overlooked dimension in judgments of moral
cuteness perception and motivation for care- standing. Cognition, 131, 108–124.
taking in adults. Ethology, 115(3), 257–263. Piazza, J., & Loughnan., S. (2016). When meat
Grauerholz, L. (2007). Cute enough to eat: gets personal, animals’ minds matter less: Mo-
The transformation of animals into meat for tivated use of intelligence information in judg-
human consumption in commercialized im- ments of moral standing. Social Psychological
ages. Humanity and Society, 31, 334–354. and Personality Science, 7, 867–874.
Gray, H., Gray, K., & Wegner, D. (2007). Dimen- Piazza, J., McLatchie, N., Olesen, C., & To-
sions of mind perception. Science, 619, 315. maszczuk, M. (2016). [Cuteness promotes
Gray, K., Knobe, J., Sheskin, M., Bloom, P., & moral standing and reduces appetite for meat
Feldman-Barrett, L. F. (2011). More than a among women]. Unpublished raw data.
body: Mind perception and the nature of ob- Piazza, J., Ruby, M. B., Loughnan, S., Luong,
jectification. Journal of Personality and Social M., Kulik, J., Watkins, H. M., & Seigerman,
Psychology, 101, 1207–1220. M. (2015). Rationalizing meat consumption:
Gross, J. J., & John, O. P. (2003). Individual dif- The 4Ns. Appetite, 91,114–128.
ferences in two emotion regulation processes: Plous, S. (1993). Psychological mechanisms in
Implications for affect, relationships, and the human use of animals. Journal of Social
well-being. Journal of Personality and Social Issues, 49, 11–52.
Psychology, 85(2), 348–362. Preylo, B. D., & Arikawa, H. (2008). Compari-
174 M O R A L I T Y, S O C I A L C O G N I T I O N , A N D I D E N T I T Y

son of vegetarians and non-vegetarians on Shaw, L. L., Batson, C. D., & Todd, R. M.
pet attitude and empathy. Anthrozoös, 21(4), (1994). Empathy avoidance: Forestalling feel-
387–395. ing for another in order to escape the moti-
Rothgerber, H. (2014). Efforts to overcome vege- vational consequences. Journal of Personality
tarian-induced dissonance among meat eaters. and Social Psychology, 67(5), 879–887.
Appetite, 79, 32–41. Sherman, G. D., & Haidt, J. (2011). Cuteness
Rothgerber, H., & Mican, F. (2014). Childhood and disgust: The humanizing and dehumaniz-
pet ownership, attachment to pets, and subse- ing effects of emotion. Emotion Review, 3(3),
quent meat avoidance: The mediating role of 1–7.
empathy toward animals. Appetite, 79, 11–17. Sherman, G. D., Haidt, J., & Coan, J. A. (2009).
Rozin, P. (2006). Domain denigration and process Viewing cute images increases behavioral
preference in academic psychology. Perspec- carefulness. Emotion, 9(2), 282–286.
tives on Psychological Science, 1, 365–376. Sprengelmeyer, R., Perrett, D. I., Fagan, E. C.,
Rozin, P., & Nemeroff, C. J. (1990). The laws Cornwell, R. E., Lobmaier, J. S., Sprengelmey-
of sympathetic magic: A psychological analy- er, A., . . . Young, A. W. (2009). The cutest
sis of similarity and contagion. In J. Stigler, little baby face: A hormonal link to sensitivity
R. A. Shweder, & G. Herdt (Eds.), Cultural to cuteness in infant faces. Psychological Sci-
psychology: Essays on comparative human ence, 20(2), 149–154.
development (pp. 205–232). Cambridge, UK: Sytsma, J., & Machery, E. (2012). Two sources
Cambridge University Press. of moral standing. Review of Philosophy and
Ruby, M. B. (2012). Vegetarianism: A blossom- Psychology, 3, 303–324.
ing field of study. Appetite, 58, 141–150. Waytz, A., Gray, K., Epley, N., & Wegner, D.
Ruby, M. B., & Heine, S. (2012). Too close to M. (2010). Causes and consequences of mind
home: Factors predicting meat avoidance. Ap- perception. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 14,
petite, 59, 47–52. 383–388.
PART IV
MORALITY AND
INTERGROUP CONFLICT

Q U E S T I O N S A N S W E R E D I N PA R T I V

CHAPTER 18  Why did moral judgment evolve?

CHAPTER 19  Do people deploy the same moral cognition


across social contexts, or are there critical cleavages within moral cognition?

CHAPTER 20  If humans are innately good, cooperative, fair, and averse
to harming one another, why does widespread intergroup violence continue
to afflict society?

CHAPTER 21  If some stereotypes seem to be universal,


are they necessarily immoral?
C H A P T E R 18

Morality Is for Choosing Sides

Peter DeScioli
Robert Kurzban

Why did moral judgment evolve?

To help people choose sides when conflicts erupt within groups with
complex coalitions and power hierarchies.

Theories of morality have largely tried to ex- What, then, might be the benefits gained
plain the brighter side of behavior, answer- through moral judgments? Consider a situ-
ing questions about why people behave in ation in which a person accuses someone of
ways that are kind, generous, and good. Our witchcraft, such as in Arthur Miller’s The
proposal focuses not on explaining moral Crucible. Specifically, suppose that a young,
behavior but, rather, on explaining moral low-status woman accuses an older, more
judgment. Consider someone reading a prominent woman of witchcraft. Other
news story about a man who pays a woman members of the community can respond in
to have sex with him. Many people would a few different ways.
judge—in an intuitive way (Haidt, 2012)— One obvious move for a self-interested
that both the man’s and woman’s actions are observer is to curry favor with the higher-­
morally wrong. Our interest lies in the ex- status woman. Choosing sides based on sta-
planation for these and similar judgments. tus often occurs in very hierarchical groups
Theories that attempt to explain moral such as the military (Fiske, 1992). It is also
behavior often point to altruism or benefits observed in nonhuman animals: For in-
(de Waal, 1996; Krebs, 2005; Ridley, 1996; stance, hyenas join fights and support the
Wright, 1994). The theory of reciprocal al- higher-status and more formidable fighter
truism (Trivers, 1971), for instance, explains (Holekamp, Sakai, & Lundrigan, 2007).
why people enter into voluntary exchanges This strategy has a downside: It empowers
with one another: to reap the benefits of high-status individuals to win all of their
trade. Such theoretical moves are consid- conflicts and hence gives them an incen-
erably less straightforward for explaining tive to exploit other people; they essentially
moral judgment. For example, condemn- become dictators (Boehm, 1999). Even so,
ing the exchange of sex for money does not individuals can benefit by siding with dicta-
transparently confer benefits to the con- tors because they avoid making powerful en-
demner. emies. However, humans often do the oppo-

177
178 MOR ALIT Y AND INTERGROUP CONFLIC T

site, siding with the lower-status accuser, as prostitution, witchcraft, homicide, or blas-
in the hypothetical (and actual) witchcraft phemy—as established by previous moral
case. When might siding with the lower-sta- debates in the community.
tus accuser be an advantage? The moral side-taking strategy avoids two
A second strategy for choosing sides is key problems with choosing sides based on
based on relationships: Support closer fam- status and alliances. First, observers do not
ily or friends, even if they are lower status. empower dictators because they do not al-
Individuals can gain by supporting allies if ways side with the same people. Second, they
those allies in turn support them in the fu- do not create escalating and expanding alli-
ture. But alliances have a downside too: If ances because observers all choose the same
each disputant has a cohort of close friends, side, provided they use the same moral rules.
then the dispute will expand to include more Moral judgment allows observers to dynam-
people on each side and could be even more ically coordinate their side-taking choices in
costly to both the original disputants and the sense that they all take the same side,
their supporters. Research shows that alli- but they can also dynamically change whom
ances can be extremely damaging at every they support based on the actions each party
scale of conflict, from personal to interna- has taken. Notice that moral side-taking is
tional disputes (Snyder, 1984, 1997; Cooney, effective at coordination only when every-
1998, 2003). one agrees, or at least acknowledges, what
Although humans often support their counts as a morally wrong action.
friends and family in conflicts, they do not Hence, moral judgment adds to the human
always do so. This was the case in The Cru- repertoire of strategies for managing other
cible and in numerous real-world witchcraft people’s conflicts. It does not entirely dis-
accusations. Many societies judge black place bandwagon or alliance strategies be-
magic to be so morally wrong that it gives cause choosing sides is a coordination game,
cause to abandon one’s closest friends and and coordination games have multiple equi-
even to seek their death. Executions for libria (Schelling, 1960). But morality does
witchcraft continue in modern times. In explain why people sometimes oppose pow-
India, for instance, the National Crime Re- erful people and close friends—because mo-
cords Bureau documented 2,097 murders of rality is designed for exactly this purpose, so
accused witches between 2000 and 2012, as to avoid the costs of those strategies.
despite new laws prohibiting witch hunts The side-taking theory explains why moral
(Kapoor, 2015). Around the world, simi- condemnation can be so destructive. Moral
larly fatal judgments regularly occur for pre- condemnation causes great harm to alleged
marital sex, homosexuality, blasphemy, and wrongdoers for harmless or beneficial be-
other harmless offenses that are punishable haviors, including witchcraft, premarital
by death in some societies (Appiah, 2010; sex, homosexuality, interest-bearing loans,
Levy, 1993; Sarhan & Burke, 2009; United and scientific research. Popular theories of
Nations Commission on Human Rights, morality based on cooperation (de Waal,
2000). How could it be advantageous to 1996; Krebs, 2005; Ridley, 1996; Wright,
turn against someone, even family and 1994) predict that moral judgment will gen-
friends, merely because they have (allegedly) erally maximize welfare, but instead many
done something deemed morally wrong by humans seek prison or death for harmless
the community? offenses. In contrast, the side-taking theory
We have proposed (DeScioli & Kurzban, is consistent with this destructive behavior
2013) that the benefit of siding with moralis- because moral judgment functions not to
tic accusers occurs when other third parties promote welfare but to synchronize side-
to the conflict do so as well. Moral judg- taking, even if doing so harms many others.
ment functions as a side-taking strategy and This view of moral judgment explains
provides an alternative strategy to choosing another important moral phenomenon: peo-
sides based on status or relationships. Moral ple’s decisions to comply with moral rules
side-takers choose sides based on actions. even when breaking the rules benefits them.
They oppose the disputant who has taken In a social world in which the community
the more morally wrong action—whether gangs up against wrongdoers, it is costly
 Morality Is for Choosing Sides 179

to engage in prohibited actions. The side- ing their mates. These differences in incen-
taking hypothesis therefore simultaneously tives explain why people differ and disagree
accounts for condemnation as well as con- about moral rules (DeScioli, Massenkoff,
science, psychological mechanisms designed Shaw, Petersen, & Kurzban, 2014; Kurzban
to inhibit actions deemed wrong by the local et al., 2010; Robinson & Kurzban, 2007).
community.
The side-taking theory explains why peo-
ple’s moralistic punishments are aimed at Historical Context
retribution rather than deterrence, as docu-
mented by moral psychology (Carlsmith, The historical context for the side-taking
Darley, & Robinson, 2002). Theories based theory includes two parallel but mostly
on cooperation straightforwardly predict separate research strands: moral psychology
that moralistic punishment will aim at de- and evolutionary theories of morality.
terring harmful behavior. Instead, people Research in moral psychology has focused
seek retribution for wrongdoers indepen- on proximate psychological questions. Stud-
dent of the potential for punishment to deter ies typically examine people’s moral judg-
future violations. The side-taking account ments about someone’s actions (or inactions)
holds that an observer’s retributive motives in controlled vignettes. Researchers tend to
are designed to direct their aggression to- examine issues such as selfish motives ver-
ward the weaker side of a dispute in order sus the greater good, compliance with moral
to convincingly join the stronger side, where rules when anonymous, intentional versus
the stronger side in this case means the side accidental violations, taboo trade-offs be-
with the moral high ground and hence the tween wrongful actions and overall welfare,
majority of supporters. Moralistic punish- and the desire to punish wrongdoers (re-
ment is retributive because it is designed for viewed in Haidt, 2012).
side-taking rather than deterring harm. This research tradition in moral psychol-
The side-taking theory also explains why ogy has been largely silent about the evolu-
moral judgment includes an ideal of impar- tionary functions that explain why humans
tiality. Although people’s judgments are, in make moral judgments at all. Many re-
fact, often biased and partial, people at the searchers either do not address the evolved
same time advocate an ideal of impartiality, functions of moral judgment or refer to ge-
especially for their opponent’s judgments. neric and vague functions, such as the folk
The side-taking hypothesis holds that the wisdom that morality holds society together.
ideal of impartiality functions to decouple In parallel, evolutionary scholars have
moral side-taking from alliances, ultimately viewed morality through the lens of altru-
to avoid the costs of escalating alliances in ism. Starting with Darwin (1871), this was
disputes. primarily a theoretical problem, asking
Finally, this theory illuminates variation how natural selection could favor altruistic
in moral rules across individuals and groups. behavior. Researchers developed models to
If the dynamic coordination view is correct, show how cooperation can evolve, including
then many different moral rules could serve the conditions and abilities it requires. This
the function of synchronizing side-taking, as work yielded an impressive array of theories,
long as the local community agrees on the including kin selection, reciprocity, partner
rules. Different societies have different types choice, and costly signaling. Evolutionary
of conflicts, and people mint new moral researchers tested these models in thousands
rules to cover them. Further, individuals can of empirical studies, often on nonhuman
differ in how they are personally affected animals, and many models have extremely
by particular rules. For instance, people impressive empirical support.
who pursue short-term mating are worse However, very little work in the evolu-
off when promiscuity is moralized and pun- tionary tradition measures, or even engages
ished (Kurzban, Dukes, & Weeden, 2010; with, moral judgment. Researchers with an
Weeden, 2003). Other people who pursue evolutionary perspective have largely as-
long-term mating might benefit from mor- sumed that cooperation and morality are
alizing promiscuity in the interest of guard- the same thing (e.g., de Waal, 1996; Krebs,
180 MOR ALIT Y AND INTERGROUP CONFLIC T

2005; Ridley, 1996; Wright, 1994). Hence The side-taking theory develops addi-
there is a stark divide between moral psy- tional game-theoretic tools to understand
chology, which has proceeded with relatively what is distinctive about human moral judg-
little theory, and evolutionary accounts of ment. Rather than using previous evolution-
morality, largely uninformed by empirical ary models, it develops a new model based
findings from moral psychology. on side-taking games to explain the unique
Haidt (2007, 2012) began to fuse these human behaviors revealed by moral psychol-
two research traditions. He combined moral ogy. It addresses why humans assign moral
psychology, cross-cultural research, and values to actions, announce moral judg-
evolutionary theories to create a set of fun- ments to other individuals, debate moral
damental moral foundations, each ground- rules, and show aggression toward wrong-
ed by different evolutionary models—kin doers. It provides an explanation for why
selection, reciprocity, group cooperation, moral judgment is deontological rather than
dominance hierarchies, and pathogen avoid- consequentialist, why punishment is aimed
ance. The result was an impressive overarch- at retribution rather than deterrence, why
ing theory that had strong appeal both for judgments are held to an ideal of impar-
moral psychologists and for evolutionary tiality, and why moral rules vary over time
researchers. and across cultures. We propose that these
Haidt’s moral foundations theory is an moral phenomena result from an evolved
impressive attempt to reconcile moral psy- strategy for choosing sides in disputes. As
chology with evolution. However, the ac- such, moral judgment is part of a larger rep-
count misses distinctive elements of human ertoire of adaptations for managing one’s
morality. The evolutionary ideas that ani- own and others’ conflicts, including the
mate moral foundations theory apply to cognitive abilities to assess an opponent’s
many different animal species, but moral fighting power, recognize property conven-
judgment is an extreme and unusual—­ tions, and form alliances (DeScioli & Kar-
possibly unique—human trait, analogous to poff, 2015; DeScioli, Karpoff, & De Freitas,
an elephant’s trunk. If researchers applied 2017; DeScioli & Kurzban, 2009b; DeScioli,
only broad theories about animal noses to Rosa, & Gutchess, 2015; DeScioli & Wil-
understand an elephant’s trunk, they would son, 2011).
be missing the trunk’s unique grasping and
communication abilities.
The theories underlying the moral foun- Theoretical Stance
dations explain why people show behaviors
such as parental care, trade, and dominance. The side-taking theory differs from other
But they do not explain why people make theories in how it treats some debates in the
moral judgments about these behaviors. To literature and, more important, in the func-
return to the opening example, reciprocity tions it proposes for moral mechanisms.
theory does not explain why people morally First, on the perennial issue of whether
judge the act of exchanging sex for money, morality is universal or culturally relative,
especially because prostitution is an ex- some scholars assume that an evolutionary
change. Similarly, none of the foundations basis for morality implies that humans will
explain why moral judgment focuses par- have a small set of universal moral rules and,
ticularly on actions and differs in this re- further, that cultural variation undermines
spect from people’s decisions about welfare, evolutionary accounts (e.g., Prinz, 2007).
precautions, economics, and conventions. The side-taking theory, in contrast, holds
Traditional evolutionary models predict that humans possess the evolved ability to
consequentialist rather than deontological create and learn new moral rules so that
mechanisms (DeScioli & Kurzban, 2009a). they can be tailored to new types of conflict.
Last, traditional evolutionary models do not As a result, moral cognition is, in itself, uni-
explain why people disagree about morality versal, while at the same time moral rules
and why they debate the moral rules in their differ across groups and within groups over
community. time. Some rules are more stable than others
 Morality Is for Choosing Sides 181

because they tend to be supported by ma- interacts with a wide array of mechanisms
jorities, such as rules against lying, stealing, specialized for different areas of social life,
and killing, whereas other rules are more including mechanisms for processing kin re-
variable because they receive mixed support, lations, reciprocity, property, hierarchy, and
such as rules about promiscuity and drug coalitions. This is, again, analogous to the
use. complex interactions of apps for e-mail, pho-
Second, there is a related issue about tos, and social networks on modern phones.
whether morality is innate or learned. We Nevertheless, moral cognition is a distinct
take the position that learning cannot occur and unified program organized around the
without innate mechanisms specialized for problem of choosing sides.
learning in that domain (Pinker, 1989), so Last, the side-taking theory differs in the
the usual dichotomy is misleading. The side- functions it proposes for moral cognition.
taking theory holds that moral cognition Broadly, the primary function of moral
includes mechanisms for learning the ac- judgment is not to guide one’s own behav-
tive moral rules in the social environment, ior (conscience) but to judge other people’s
including different rules for different sub- behavior (condemnation). The conscience
groups and types of interactions. It further component of moral judgment is essentially
holds that people do not only passively in- defensive. People morally evaluate their own
ternalize the group’s rules but rather, they potential actions in order to avoid other
actively advocate for self-serving rules and people’s condemnation. Because conscience
readily violate rules when they can get away functions to simulate and avoid condem-
with it. nation, the structure of moral judgment is
Third, there is a debate about whether best understood from the condemner’s per-
moral judgment is intuitive or deliberative. spective. Condemners face the problem of
The side-taking theory holds that moral choosing sides and doing so in a landscape
judgment is largely unconscious, like many of prior loyalties and status hierarchies. The
complex cognitive processes. However, a side-taking theory uses this adaptive prob-
critical part of its function is to persuade lem to understand how moral judgment
other people to take the same side. For this works, differing from cooperation theories
purpose, people have the ability to formu- that view morality as designed to motivate
late their moral judgments into language so good behavior.
they can be announced to others. Moreover,
people can simulate moral debates in their
private thoughts in order to build more con- Evidence
vincing moral arguments. These communi-
cative elements explain why moral judgment There is, of course, a tremendous amount of
has a deliberative component. evidence about how moral judgments oper-
Fourth, there is a question about whether ate. We focus on a few patterns of evidence
moral judgment is a single process or mul- that we think are crucial for inferring the
tiple processes (DeScioli & Kurzban, 2009a; functions of moral judgment. First and fore-
DeScioli, Asao, & Kurzban, 2012). We most, we think any theory of morality must
first note that every major cognitive ability explain why moral judgment focuses on the
includes a large number of processes, just actions people choose rather than only on
as any software application does. The real the consequences they intend.
question is whether moral judgment’s many In moral philosophy, consequentialism
processes are unified by an overarching is the idea that the morality of an act de-
function, just as word processing or e-mail pends only on the consequences of the act
applications have overarching functions. (Sinnott-Armstrong, 2006). In contrast, de-
The side-taking theory holds that moral ontological theories are nonconsequentialist
judgment is indeed unified in this sense be- because they also consider the category of
cause it is structured by the primary func- the action, such as lying or stealing, inde-
tion of choosing sides in disputes. In order pendent of the intended consequences. This
to perform this function, moral cognition allows deontological philosophers such as
182 MOR ALIT Y AND INTERGROUP CONFLIC T

Kant to conclude, for example, that lying is maximize fitness by doing so (e.g., Mock,
morally wrong even if it can save lives (Kant, 2004).
1785/1993). The allocation hypothesis for ejection
Many experiments in moral psychol- makes specific predictions tied to its pro-
ogy show deontological patterns in people’s posed function. A mother bird’s ejection
moral judgments. A well-known example behavior should be sensitive to factors that
is the finding that most people think it is affect costs and benefits, such as the number
immoral to push one person off of a foot- of other eggs, the scarcity of food in the en-
bridge in order to save five people from vironment, the risk of predation, or the age
being killed by a runaway trolley. In this and reproductive potential of the mother.
case, people judge the action of killing to What if, instead, researchers observed
be morally wrong, even if leads to better that a mother’s ejections depended primarily
consequences (fewer deaths). In an interest- on the egg’s color, independent of its qual-
ing contrast, however, most people think it ity or the number of other eggs? This ob-
is permissible to switch the trolley to a side servation would constitute an anomaly left
track, where it will kill one person, to save unexplained by the theory. If it was found
the five people on the main track. These repeatedly, over and over, that the color of
results, and many others like them (Baron, the eggs overrides the cost–benefit calculus
1994; Baron & Spranca, 1997; De Freitas, of kin selection, then the parental allocation
DeScioli, Nemirow, Massenkoff, & Pinker, hypothesis would be called into question.
in press; DeScioli, Bruening, & Kurzban, Recognizing the theory’s failure, research-
2011; DeScioli, Christner, & Kurzban, ers might look further and find that this
2011; Kurzban et al., 2012; Mikhail, 2007; bird species is parasitized by cuckoo eggs
Tetlock, 2003; Waldmann & Dieterich, that tend to differ in color (Brooke & Da-
2007), illustrate that people’s evaluations of vies, 1988). Suppose it turns out that the
the wrongness of actions depends on the de- mother’s ejection behavior is not designed
tails of the actions themselves, as opposed to to optimally distribute resources among her
the intended outcomes (which are the same offspring but rather to remove cuckoo para-
in both the footbridge and switch cases). sites. In this case, the theory’s empirical fail-
This basic observation is not predicted ure would allow researchers to discover an
by many prominent theories of morality. altogether different type of explanation.
We take a moment to come at this prob- Now consider a theory of morality that
lem obliquely because it is easy to overlook. proposes that moral judgments are designed
Consider a different context—parental care. to improve the overall welfare of families,
Kin selection theory explains why some or- friends, or groups (de Waal, 1996; Krebs,
ganisms are designed to provide resources 2005; Ridley, 1996; Wright, 1994). Such
to offspring and also explains how parents theories predict that people should condemn
make trade-offs when allocating resources and desire to punish acts depending on the
across multiple offspring (Hamilton, 1964; welfare consequences. In particular, people
Trivers, 1974). Now imagine that research- should condemn acts that lead to aggregate
ers observed a species of bird in which moth- fitness losses and not condemn acts that lead
ers sometimes eject eggs from the nest. The to fitness gains. The way in which these
researchers propose that this ejection behav- gains and losses are realized—analogous to
ior maximizes inclusive fitness by optimally the color of the eggs—should be irrelevant.
allocating resources to higher quality eggs Evidence that people’s moral judgments
while ejecting lower quality eggs. closely track the way gains are produced, the
Notice first that this is a specific conse- particular actions taken, the means by which
quentialist function: Mothers maximize a goals are sought, is evidence against the wel-
consequence: inclusive fitness. This makes fare-improvement theory. Even worse for the
sense because natural selection is a process theory is the condemnation of actions that
driven by consequences, and organisms are produce obvious and large welfare gains. If
usually consequentialist—most animals do moral judgment were for improving welfare,
not shy from killing, lying, stealing, infanti- pushing the man off of the footbridge should
cide, siblicide, or cannibalism when they can be praiseworthy, not blameworthy.
 Morality Is for Choosing Sides 183

Arguably still worse for altruism theo- vantage them over other people (Aarøe &
ries are moral rules that guarantee welfare Petersen, 2013; DeScioli et al., 2014; Kurz-
losses. Across cultures, moral rules prohibit ban et al., 2010; Petersen, Aarøe, Jensen, &
any number of victimless, mutually profit- Curry, 2014; Tybur, Lieberman, Kurzban,
able transactions. Historically, an obvious & DeScioli, 2013).
example is the prohibition against charging
interest, which prevents mutually profitable
loans. In India, the prohibition against kill- Extension and Expansion
ing cows has long caused substantial harms
(Suri, 2015). Any number of similar rules One area for expansion is investigating how
continue to undermine potential welfare people decide whether to enter conflicts and
gains. which side-taking strategy to use if they do
We suggest that the tremendous array of so. The dynamic coordination hypothesis
data showing that people’s judgments are proposes that morality is designed around
deontological, along with the ubiquity of the problem of taking sides in disputes, but
welfare-destroying moral rules, all consti- it does not require that people always use
tute serious evidence against welfare-based moral judgment to choose sides. In some sit-
theories of morality. uations, one might choose to side with, for
The side-taking hypothesis does not run example, one’s close relative or ally or with
afoul of these problems. This theory re- the higher-status individual. The best strat-
quires that a rule is known and that its viola- egy depends on the details of the situation.
tion can be recognized by observers; because We predict that people will use moral judg-
rules are for coordinated side-taking rather ment to choose sides as a function of fea-
than welfare-enhancement, they can include tures of the situation, such as the magnitude
a wide range of contents, including welfare- of the moral violation, the relative status
destroying contents. In short, deontological of the individuals involved, the number of
judgment is a set of observations that is, we observers to the actions, and other elements
think, fatal for welfare theories but consis- that affect an individual’s costs and benefits
tent with the side-taking theory. in the side-taking game.
There are several other areas of active re- The side-taking proposal also raises the
search that provide evidence relevant to the question of why observers do not always sit
side-taking hypothesis. First, research has out of disputes to avoid any fighting costs to
found that people’s tendency to moralize an themselves. Indeed, if there were no social
issue depends on their power and alliances costs to sitting out, then the dynamic coor-
(Jensen & Petersen, 2011; Petersen, 2013). dination hypothesis would be contradicted,
This evidence supports the idea that moral because players would not have an incentive
judgement is a strategy that people selec- to choose sides in the first place. However,
tively deploy depending on whether they are we suspect that sitting out is often costly
most advantaged when others choose sides and damages preexisting relationships, es-
according to moral judgment, power, or alli- pecially when conflicts include one’s friends
ances. Second, the side-taking theory points and allies. One goal for future research is to
to impartiality as a core feature of moral measure the damage to relationships caused
judgment because it is designed as an alter- by sitting out of conflicts when one’s friends
native to partial alliances. Recent work on and allies are involved. Insofar as one of
fairness judgments points to a similar role the functions of friendship is to cultivate
for impartiality in suppressing alliances in allies when disputes arise (DeScioli, Kurz-
the context of allocating resources (Shaw, ban, Koch, & Liben-Nowell, 2011; DeScioli
2013). Third, the side-taking hypothesis & Kurzban, 2009b; DeScioli & Kurzban,
emphasizes variability in moral rules and 2011), we suspect that failing to come to a
also people’s debates and arguments about friend’s aid in conflicts will indeed damage
which moral rules will structure side-taking these relationships, possibly to the same de-
in their community. Consistent with this gree as siding against one’s friend. If so, then
idea, research shows that people actively when an observer is confronted by a dispute
advocate for the moral rules that most ad- between two of their friends, sitting out
184 MOR ALIT Y AND INTERGROUP CONFLIC T

might, in some cases, be the worst option DeScioli, P., Bruening, R., & Kurzban. R. (2011).
because it damages both relationships. Fur- The omission effect in moral cognition: To-
ther, siding against a friend who is morally ward a functional explanation. Evolution and
wrong (e.g., someone who lied or cheated) Human Behavior, 32, 204–215.
DeScioli, P., Christner, J., & Kurzban, R. (2011).
might not damage that relationship as much The omission strategy. Psychological Science,
as when the friend is in the right, because 22, 442–446.
at least the friend could still count on the DeScioli, P., & Karpoff, R. (2015). People’s
observer’s support when they are not in the judgments about classic property law cases.
wrong in the future. Additional work can Human Nature, 26, 184–209.
examine how observers manage trade-offs DeScioli, P., Karpoff, R., & De Freitas, J. (2017).
between coordinating with other observers Ownership dilemmas: The case of finders ver-
and minimizing damage to their own rela- sus landowners. Cognitive Science, 41, 502–
tionships with each side of the dispute. 522.
DeScioli, P., & Kurzban, R. (2009a). Mysteries
of morality. Cognition, 112, 281–299.
DeScioli, P., & Kurzban, R. (2009b). The alli-
REFERENCES
ance hypothesis for human friendship. PLOS
ONE, 4, e5802.
Aarøe, L., & Petersen, M. B. (2013). Hunger
DeScioli, P., & Kurzban, R. (2011). The compa-
games: Fluctuations in blood glucose levels in-
ny you keep: Friendship decisions from a func-
fluence support for social welfare. Psychologi-
tional perspective. In J. I. Krueger (Ed.), Social
cal Science, 24, 2550–2556.
judgment and decision making (pp. 209–225).
Appiah, K. A. (2010). The honor code: How
New York: Psychology Press.
moral revolutions happen. New York: Norton.
DeScioli, P., & Kurzban, R. (2013). A solution to
Baron, J. (1994). Nonconsequentialist decisions.
the mysteries of morality. Psychological Bul-
Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 17, 1–10. letin, 139, 477–496.
Baron, J., & Spranca, M. (1997). Protected val- DeScioli, P., Kurzban, R., Koch, E. N., & Liben-
ues. Organizational Behavior and Human Nowell, D. (2011). Best friends: Alliances,
Decision Processes, 70, 1–16. friend ranking, and the MySpace social net-
Boehm, C. (1999). Hierarchy in the forest. Cam- work. Perspectives on Psychological Science,
bridge, MA: Harvard University Press. 6, 6–8.
Brooke, M. de L., & Davies, N. B. (1988). Egg DeScioli, P., Massenkoff, M., Shaw, A., Peters-
mimicry by cuckoos Cuculus canorus in rela- en, M. B., & Kurzban, R. (2014). Equity or
tion to discrimination by hosts. Nature, 335, equality?: Moral judgments follow the money.
630–632. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological
Carlsmith, K. M., Darley, J. M., & Robinson, Sciences, 281, 2014–2112.
P. H. (2002). Why do we punish?: Deterrence DeScioli, P., Rosa, N. M., & Gutchess, A. H.
and just deserts as motives for punishment. (2015). A memory advantage for property.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, Evolutionary Psychology, 13, 411–423.
83, 284–299. DeScioli, P., & Wilson, B. (2011). The territorial
Cooney, M. (1998). Warriors and peacemakers: foundations of human property. Evolution
How third parties shape violence. New York: and Human Behavior, 32, 297–304.
New York University Press. Fiske, A. P. (1992). The four elementary forms
Cooney, M. (2003). The privatization of vio- of sociality: Framework for a unified theory
lence. Criminology, 41, 1377–1406. of social relations. Psychological Review, 99,
Darwin, C. (1871). Descent of man, and selec- 689–723.
tion in relation to sex. New York: Appleton. Haidt, J. (2007). The new synthesis in moral psy-
De Freitas, J., DeScioli, P., Nemirow, J., Massen- chology. Science, 316, 998–1002.
koff, M., & Pinker, S. (in press). Kill or die: Haidt, J. (2012). The righteous mind. New York:
Moral judgment alters linguistic coding of Vintage Books.
causality. Journal of Experimental Psychol- Hamilton, W. (1964). The genetic evolution of
ogy: Learning, Memory, and Cognition. social behaviour. Journal of Theoretical Biol-
de Waal, F. B. M. (1996). Good natured: The ori- ogy, 7, 1–52.
gins of right and wrong in humans and other Holekamp, K. E., Sakai, S. T., & Lundrigan, B.
animals. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University L. (2007). Social intelligence in the spotted
Press. hyena (Crocuta crocuta). Philosophical Trans-
DeScioli, P., Asao, K., & Kurzban. R. (2012). actions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sci-
Omissions and byproducts across moral do- ences, 362, 523–538.
mains. PLOS ONE, 7, e46963. Jensen, N. H., & Petersen, M. B. (2011). To defer
 Morality Is for Choosing Sides 185

or to stand up: How offender formidability af- cordance and conflict in intuitions of justice.
fects moral outrage. Evolutionary Psychology, Minnesota Law Review, 91, 1829–1907.
9, 118–136. Sarhan, A., & Burke, J. (2009, September 13).
Kant, I. (1993). Grounding for the metaphysics How Islamist gangs use Internet to track,
of morals (J. W. Ellington, Trans.). Indianapo- torture and kill Iraqi gays. The Guard-
lis, IN: Hackett. (Original work published ian. Retrieved from www.guardian.co.uk/
1785) world/2009/sep/13/iraq-gays-murdered-mili-
Kapoor, M. (2015, March 19). Witch hunting tias.
on the rise across several Indian states. India Schelling, T. C. (1960). The strategy of conflict.
Times. Retrieved from www.indiatimes.com/ Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
news/india/witch-hunting-on-the-rise-across- Shaw, A. (2013). Beyond “to share or not to
several-indian-states-231133.html. share”: The impartiality account of fairness.
Krebs, D. (2005). The evolution of morality. In Current Directions in Psychological Science,
D. M. Buss (Ed.), The handbook of evolution- 22, 413–417.
ary psychology (pp. 747–771). Hoboken, NJ: Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2006). Consequen-
Wiley. tialism. In E. N. Zalta (Principal Ed.) & U.
Kurzban, R., DeScioli, P., & Fein, D. (2012). Nodelman (Senior Ed.), Stanford encyclo-
Hamilton vs. Kant: Pitting adaptations for pedia of philosophy. Stanford, CA: Stanford
altruism against adaptations for moral judg- University. Available at http://plato.stanford.
ment. Evolution and Human Behavior, 33, edu.
323–333. Snyder, G. H. (1984). The security dilemma in
Kurzban, R., Dukes, A., & Weeden, J. (2010). alliance politics. World Politics, 36, 461–495.
Sex, drugs and moral goals: Reproductive Snyder, G. H. (1997). Alliance politics. Ithaca,
strategies and views about recreational drugs. NY: Cornell University Press.
Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Suri, M. (2015, April 17). A ban on beef in India
Sciences, 277, 3501–3508. is not the answer. New York Times. Available
Levy, L. W. (1993). Blasphemy: Verbal offense at http://nyti.ms/1yB4ORa.
against the sacred, from Moses to Salman Tetlock, P. E. (2003). Thinking the unthinkable:
Rushdie. New York: Knopf. Sacred values and taboo cognitions. Trends in
Mikhail, J. (2007). Universal moral grammar: Cognitive Science, 7, 320–324.
Theory, evidence and the future. Trends in Trivers, R. L. (1971). The evolution of reciprocal
Cognitive Sciences, 11, 143–152. altruism. Quarterly Review of Biology, 46,
Mock, D. W. (2004). More than kin and less than 35–57.
kind: The evolution of family conflict. Cam- Trivers, R. L. (1974). Parent–offspring conflict.
bridge, MA: Oxford University Press American Zoologist, 14, 249–264.
Petersen, M. B. (2013). Moralization as pro- Tybur, J. M., Lieberman, D., Kurzban, R., &
tection against exploitation: Do individuals DeScioli, P. (2013). Disgust: Evolved function
without allies moralize more? Evolution and and structure. Psychological Review, 120,
Human Behavior, 34, 78–85. 65–84.
Petersen, M. B., Aarøe, L., Jensen, N. H., & United Nations Commission on Human Rights.
Curry, O. (2014). Social welfare and the psy- (2000). Civil and political rights, including
chology of food sharing: Short-term hunger questions of disappearances and summary ex-
increases support for social welfare. Political ecutions. New York: Author.
Psychology, 35, 757–773. Waldmann, M. R., & Dieterich, J. (2007).
Pinker, S. (1989). Learnability and cognition: Throwing a bomb on a person versus throw-
The acquisition of argument structure. Cam- ing a person on a bomb: Intervention myopia
bridge, MA: MIT Press. in moral intuitions. Psychological Science, 18,
Prinz, J. J. (2007). Is morality innate? In W. Sin- 247–253.
nott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral psychology: Vol. Weeden, J. (2003). Genetic interests, life his-
1. Evolution of morals (pp. 367–406). Cam- tories, and attitudes towards abortion. Un-
bridge, MA: MIT Press. published doctoral dissertation, University of
Ridley, M. (1996). The origins of virtue. London: Pennsylvania, Philadelphia, PA.
Penguin Books. Wright, R. (1994). The moral animal. New York:
Robinson, P. H., & Kurzban, R. (2007). Con- Pantheon.
C H A P T E R 19

Morality for Us versus Them

Adam Waytz
Liane Young

Do people deploy the same moral cognition across social contexts,


or are there critical cleavages within moral cognition?

We propose that conceptualizing moral cognition for close others


as fundamentally different from moral cognition for distant others
can help explain systematic differences in how people deploy social
cognition (e.g., theory of mind), as well as how people apply moral
foundations across different motivational contexts.

Moral cognition—which encompasses our tions; moral judgment depends on an assess-


ability to determine whether an action is ment of internal mental states. For example,
right or wrong—allows us to navigate the innocent intentions in the case of accidents
social world. Critically, we identify actions (e.g., putting poison in a colleague’s coffee
as right or wrong in order to identify agents while believing it to be sugar, inadvertent-
as friendly or hostile and to decide how to ly causing the colleague’s death) decrease
act and react ourselves. In turn, our social blame, whereas malicious intentions even
cognition—our ability to make sense of oth- in the absence of actual harm (e.g., putting
ers and ourselves—supports our capacity for sugar in a colleague’s coffee while believing
moral thinking and doing. That is, our as- it to be poison, enhancing the colleague’s
sessments of others as moral actors depend enjoyment of the coffee) increase blame
on our assessments of others’ mental states, (for reviews, see Young & Dungan 2012;
including their beliefs, intentions, and moti- Young & Tsoi, 2013). Recent work reveals
vations. Attributing minds to others and rea- that mental state information informs moral
soning about the contents of those minds are judgments of not only individuals but also
crucial components of both moral judgment entire groups of people (e.g., corporations,
and social interaction (Gray & Wegner, unions, countries; Waytz & Young 2012;
2009; Gray, Young, & Waytz, 2012; Waytz, Waytz & Young 2014), animals (e.g., Gray,
Gray, Epley, & Wegner, 2010). When deter- Gray, & Wegner, 2007; Piazza, Landy, &
mining whether an individual is friend or Goodwin, 2014; Waytz, Cacioppo, & Epley,
foe, it is insufficient to evaluate agents on 2010), and technology (Waytz, Heafner, &
the basis of their external, observable ac- Epley, 2014).

186
 Morality for Us versus Them 187

In this chapter, we propose that system- of another person’s mind we consider var-
atic differences in how people deploy social ies significantly from moment to moment.
cognition, in particular mental state reason- When approaching a potential romantic
ing (theory of mind; ToM), as well as how partner, we wonder, “Does this person find
people apply moral foundations across dif- me attractive?” When interacting with a
ferent contexts, reflect critical cleavages fussy child, we wonder, “What does this
within moral cognition. Specifically, we person need?” When asking the boss for a
propose that moral cognition as applied to raise, we wonder, “Is this person in a good
individuals we identify as members of our mood?” We propose that, more broadly, the
inner social circle, “us,” is fundamentally aspects of mind we consider differ system-
different from moral cognition as applied to atically depending on whether we are inter-
individuals we identify as outside of our so- acting with close or distant others, targets
cial circle, “them.” that typically activate different motivations.
In this chapter, we survey evidence sug- In one set of studies examining people’s
gesting that people focus on different aspects reasoning about outgroup actions, we found
of mental states, as well as different moral that different motivations elicit selective at-
foundations, depending on their relationship tention to distinct kinds of mental states
with the moral target. In particular, we sug- (Waytz & Young, 2014). In these studies,
gest that people make the following distinc- we experimentally manipulated American
tions when judging close versus distant oth- participants’ motivational aims: to predict
ers. By “close” others, we mean people who the actions of an outgroup country (ef-
are socially close or people with whom we fectance motivation) or to affiliate with the
desire social closeness—those who we feel outgroup country (affiliation motivation).
belong to our ingroups, are similar to us, and We asked people first to write short essays
are likeable. By “distant” others, we mean about either how they might accurately pre-
people who are socially distant or people dict what the country might do in the fu-
with whom we prefer social distance—those ture (effectance) or how they might establish
who we feel belong to our outgroups, are an allegiance with the country (affiliation)
dissimilar to us, and are unlikeable. First, and then to evaluate various characteristics
we propose that when considering close ver- of that country. These judgments included
sus distant others, people focus on different evaluating the importance of attending to
moral characteristics, preferentially seeking the country’s agentive mental states (i.e.,
information about and attending to others’ capacities for planning, intending) and ex-
experience-based mental states (e.g., emo- periential mental states (i.e., capacities for
tions, feelings) versus agency-based mental emotion, feeling; Gray et al., 2007) and also
states (e.g., intentions, plans, goals, beliefs), whether or not the country possessed these
assigning greater moral patiency (i.e., the de- mental states. Across studies, participants
gree to which an individual deserves moral induced to experience effectance motiva-
treatment) versus moral agency (i.e., the tion allocated greater attention to agentive
degree to which an individual is morally re- mental states relative to experiential mental
sponsible for his or her actions), and attrib- states compared with participants induced
uting love-oriented motivations versus hate- to experience affiliation motivation. In addi-
oriented motivations for actions. Second, we tion, we found that people attributed greater
propose that people assign different weight trustworthiness and warmth-based traits
to different moral foundations, focusing when they were motivated by affiliation ver-
more on considerations of loyalty and purity sus by effectance.
for close others and more on considerations People’s preferential perception of close
of fairness and harm for distant others. others in terms of experience and prosocial
motivations and their preferential perception
of distant others in terms of agency and anti-
Moral Characteristics social motivations is also broadly consistent
with the hypothesis that people represent
Effective social interaction requires consid- close versus distant others as different moral
ering others’ minds; however, which aspects archetypes as well. Together with moral
188 MOR ALIT Y AND INTERGROUP CONFLIC T

typecasting theory (Gray & Wegner, 2009), described above (Gray & Wegner, 2009), is
this research suggests that people should rep- consistent with generic ingroup bias, the de-
resent distant others more as moral agents sire to see ingroup members as more moral
(capable of doing good or evil) and close oth- and to treat ingroup members better. Thus
ers more as moral patients (capable of hav- more targeted research is needed to test the
ing good and evil done to them). Based on hypothesis that people perceive close oth-
this distinction, people should focus more ers as moral patients and distant others as
on judgments of moral rights when evalu- moral agents.
ating close others and more on judgments The findings described above suggest that
of moral responsibility when evaluating reasoning about the particular mental states
distant others. Study 4 of our research de- essential for moral cognition is determined
scribed above provides partial support for both by the features of the target and by the
this hypothesis (Waytz & Young, 2014). We motivations of the judge. When interacting
found that people assigned greater moral re- with distant others, the motivation for pre-
sponsibility to an outgroup country in the dicting and anticipating their actions, avoid-
effectance condition but also marginally ing them, or blaming them for wrongdoing
greater moral rights to the outgroup country leads people to attend to the plans, inten-
in the affiliation condition. tions, and goals of others. When interacting
Additional suggestive evidence of this dis- with close others, the motivation for affilia-
tinction between perceiving close others as tion and moral justification can lead people
moral patients and distant others as moral to attend to these mental states as well but
agents comes from Study 7 of Gray and We- also appears to increase people’s desire to
gner’s (2009) work on moral typecasting. understand others’ emotions and feelings,
In this study, they demonstrate that people which are critical components of empathy
treat both good agents (e.g., the Dalai Lama) (Batson, 2011; Zaki & Ochsner, 2012). Thus
and bad agents (e.g., Ted Bundy) more like the different motivations that are typically
moral agents than moral patients (e.g., an activated toward socially close and socially
orphan), inflicting more pain and less plea- distant others drive different applications of
sure on these targets based on the belief that moral cognition to these targets.
agents in general are able to tolerate adverse A recent functional magnetic resonance
experiences. However, in this study people imaging (fMRI) experiment we conducted
nevertheless treated good agents, compared also supports the idea that people attend to
with bad agents, more like moral patients, different aspects of mental states when they
suggesting that people might afford patiency are motivated by cooperation versus com-
to targets with whom they might desire so- petition (Tsoi, Dungan, Waytz, & Young,
cial closeness (relative to targets they might 2016). Participants played a game (mod-
want to avoid). eled after “rock, paper, scissors”) involv-
Yet another study examined this moral ing a series of dyadic interactions requiring
distinction between close and distant oth- participants to think about what their part-
ers by asking American participants to listen ners are thinking. Interactions were either
to ostensible American or Afghan soldiers competitive and zero sum—for example, if
speak about atrocities they committed dur- the participant guesses “paper” and his or
ing war and justifications for these atrocities her partner guesses “rock”, the participant
(Coman, Stone, Castano, & Hirst, 2014). alone wins a monetary reward—or coop-
When prompted to recall information from erative—for example, if the participant and
these narratives, participants recalled fewer his or her partner both guess “paper”, both
of the atrocities committed by and more of parties earn a reward jointly. We found
the justifications for American soldiers com- that, although brain regions for mental state
pared with Afghan soldiers. In other words, reasoning were recruited similarly robustly
people recalled outgroup members more as for both competitive and cooperative tri-
moral agents who inflicted harm on others als, these regions discriminated between
(e.g., tortured enemy soldiers) and ingroup competition and cooperation in their spa-
members more as moral patients, forced to tial patterns of activity. The results suggest
commit atrocities to avoid further attack. that these regions encode information that
Of course, this pattern, along with the one separates competition from cooperation—
 Morality for Us versus Them 189

perhaps the difference between agency- pear to rely on entirely different psychologi-
based and experience-based mental states, cal foundations for what constitutes right
alongside the consideration of an individual and wrong. Moral foundations theory (MFT;
as a moral agent versus a moral patient, as Graham et al., 2013; Haidt & Joseph, 2004;
consistent with the behavioral research pre- Haidt & Graham, 2007) suggests that these
sented above. foundations fall into two types—binding
In another line of work, we have exam- foundations (ingroup loyalty, respect for au-
ined how people attribute a distinct type thority, and purity/sanctity), which empha-
of mental state—motivation—to close and size values that bind and build social groups,
distant others in the context of moral con- and individualizing foundations (care–
flict over political and religious issues. In harm, justice–cheating), which emphasize
particular, we examined real-world conflict the rights of individuals, regardless of group
groups, American Democrats and Republi- membership. These domains appear to be
cans, as well as Israelis and Palestinians in defined by their descriptive content (e.g.,
the Middle East (Waytz, Young, & Ginges, shooting a person belongs to the harm do-
2014), and assessed how people attribute main; taking more than one’s share belongs
different motivations to their ingroups and to the fairness domain). Meanwhile, other
outgroups. In these experiments, we tested researchers highlight the key role of the re-
whether people deliver different assessments lational context of an action (e.g., taking a
of the mental states, namely, the motivations car from a stranger is considered stealing,
underlying conflict for groups with whom while taking a car from a sibling may con-
they typically compete (i.e., outgroups) ver- stitute borrowing; Carnes, Lickel, & Janoff-
sus cooperate (i.e., ingroups). In political and Bulman, 2015; Fiske & Tetlock, 1997; Kurz-
ethnoreligious intergroup conflict, adversar- ban, DeScioli, & Fein, 2012; Rai & Fiske,
ies attributed their own group’s aggression 2011). Applying this context-driven account
to ingroup love more than outgroup hate and to the use of moral foundations, we sug-
their outgroup’s aggression to outgroup hate gest that moral foundations are differently
more than ingroup love. For example, Israe- deployed depending on the identities of the
lis reported that Israelis support bombing parties involved and, importantly, their re-
of Gaza because of their love of Israelis, not lationship. Recent work indicates that when
hatred of Palestinians; and Palestinians at- people consider socially close versus distant
tributed Israeli aggression to outgroup hate others, they focus more on binding founda-
(toward Palestinians) and Palestinian vio- tions relative to individualizing foundations.
lence to ingroup love (toward Palestinians). In particular, people seem to focus on con-
Similarly, both Democrats and Republicans siderations of purity versus harm and loyalty
attributed political conflict initiated by the versus fairness; in addition, individual dif-
opposing party to outgroup hate, but they ferences in endorsement of binding versus
attributed conflict initiated by their own individualizing values track with treatment
party to ingroup love. Critically, this biased of ingroup relative to outgroup members, as
pattern of attribution also increased moral reviewed below.
attitudes and behaviors associated with con- First, recent research examines the rel-
flict intractability, including unwillingness evance of harm and purity norms for dif-
to negotiate and unwillingness to vote for ferent relational contexts. People judge pu-
compromise solutions. Again, these findings rity violations committed within their own
suggest that people place different emphases group and harm violations outside their
on different mental states when reasoning group more harshly (Dungan, Chakroff, &
about the morality of close and distant oth- Young, 2017). In one study, moral condem-
ers. nation increased as the target of a purity vi-
olation became more self-relevant, whereas
the opposite pattern was true for harm. An-
Moral Foundations other study extended this distinction to the
level of groups. People who strongly identi-
Beyond focusing on different mental and fied with their ingroup delivered particularly
moral characteristics when interacting with harsh moral judgments of purity violations
close versus distant others, people also ap- (but not harms) compared with people who
190 MOR ALIT Y AND INTERGROUP CONFLIC T

weakly identified with their ingroup. When ticipants who had written pro-loyalty essays
it comes to purity violations, people may were more likely to keep their mouths shut
be especially harsh on the people closest to in solidarity. However, regardless of condi-
them—those who have the greatest potential tion, participants were less likely to blow
to affect them either indirectly by associa- the whistle on friends and family than on
tion or directly via physical or moral con- strangers and acquaintances, suggesting that
tamination. Indeed, in a third study, across a the foundation of loyalty is far more relevant
wide array of violations varying in severity, for close others.
people judged that it is more morally wrong Another line of work shows that people
to defile (vs. harm) oneself, but it is more describe immoral behavior committed by
morally wrong to harm (vs. defile) another one’s ingroup more in terms of binding
person. Concerns about oneself may track foundations and describe immoral behavior
with concerns about one’s group (ingroup). committed by one’s outgroup in terms of in-
Keeping oneself pure may be advantageous dividualizing foundations (Leidner & Cas-
only insofar as others in close proximity also tano, 2012). When Americans were asked
maintain their purity; thus concerns about to describe American soldiers or Australian
contagion or contamination may apply more soldiers (an outgroup) engaging in wartime
to ingroup members. As such, condemnation atrocities toward Iraqis, they described these
of another person’s impurity may still stem atrocities more in terms of loyalty and au-
from concerns about one’s own purity. thority for American soldiers and more in
Additional evidence supports the account terms of harm and fairness for Australian
that concerns about purity are more salient soldiers.
when one is considering oneself, whereas Finally, convergent evidence indicates that
concerns about harm are more salient when individual differences in endorsement of
one is considering others (Chakroff, Dun- binding values—loyalty, purity, and authori-
gan, & Young, 2013; Rottman, Kelemen, ty—track with the treatment of ingroup ver-
& Young, 2014). This body of research sus outgroup members (Smith, Aquino, Kol-
also shows that mental state reasoning is eva, & Graham, 2014). In particular, people
deployed for moral judgments of harmful who strongly endorsed binding values were
acts to a significantly greater extent than for also more likely to support torturing out-
moral judgments of impure acts (Chakroff, group members posing a critical threat to
Dungan, & Young, 2013; Russell & Giner- ingroup members and to preserve scarce re-
Sorolla, 2011; Young & Saxe, 2011). sources for ingroup members, thereby with-
Second, other moral concerns such as loy- holding them from outgroup members; this
alty as opposed to justice or fairness may pattern, though, was unique to individuals
also apply more to the ingroup. Pilot data reporting a weak moral identity or moral
indicate that people prefer loyal friends and self-concept.
family but value justice and fairness across
group boundaries (Dungan, Waytz, &
Young, 2017). Indeed, recent work on whis- Conclusion
tle-blowing decisions directly reveals the
tension between norms concerning loyalty Gray and Wegner (2009, p. 506) note, “It
(to friends and family who support oneself) is difficult to be moral or immoral alone in
and norms concerning justice and fairness a room.” After all, the primary function of
for all (Waytz, Dungan, & Young, 2013). morality is to make sense of and interact with
In several experiments, we primed partici- the social beings around us. Identifying an
pants with specific moral values—fairness action as right or wrong matters only insofar
versus loyalty. Participants were instructed as we are able to interpret others’ behavior
to write an essay about either the value of as hostile or benevolent and to decide how
fairness over loyalty or the value of loyalty to respond. The many components of moral
over fairness. Participants who had written cognition all operate in the service of social
pro-fairness essays were more likely to blow navigation: Assessments of moral traits and
the whistle on unethical actions committed mental states support evaluations of others’
by other members of their communities. Par- behavior, including judgments of their moral
 Morality for Us versus Them 191

worth and blameworthiness; moral founda- REFERENCES


tions guide intuitive ethics. Yet assessments
of moral and mental traits and applications Batson, C. D. (2011). Altruism in humans. Ox-
of moral foundations, as well as consequent ford, UK: Oxford University Press.
Carnes, N. C., Lickel, B., & Janoff-Bulman, R.
judgments and behaviors, depend crucially
(2015). Shared perceptions: Morality is em-
on the social and motivational context. bedded in social contexts. Personality and So-
Furthermore, as Rai and Fiske (2011) pro- cial Psychology Bulletin, 41(3), 351–362.
pose, people might consider the same indi- Chakroff, A., Dungan, J., & Young, L. (2013).
vidual using different relational models in Harming ourselves and defiling others: What
different situations and therefore apply dif- determines a moral domain? PLOS ONE,
ferent moral motives (e.g., two individuals 8(9), e74434.
might invoke the communal sharing model Coman, A., Stone, C. B., Castano, E., & Hirst,
when exchanging jazz records but the market W. (2014). Justifying atrocities: The effect of
pricing model when one sells the other one a moral-disengagement strategies on socially
bicycle). By the same token, the same inter- shared retrieval-induced forgetting. Psycho-
logical Science, 25(6), 1281–1285.
action partner might occupy close or distant
Dungan, J., Chakroff, A., & Young, L. (2017).
status depending on context. For example, a The relevance of moral norms in distinct re-
salesperson might consider a sales colleague lational contexts: Purity versus harm norms
to be an ally when considering how to best a regulate self-directed actions. PLOS ONE
competing organization, but not when their 12(3), e0173405.
mutual organization offers a Rolex watch Dungan, J., Waytz, A., & Young, L. (2017).
for its salesperson-of-the-month award. Loyalty and fairness within and across group
Given the flexibility of relationship status, boundaries. Manuscript in preparation.
we predict that, over the course of a rela- Fiske, A. P., & Tetlock, P. E. (1997). Taboo trade-
tionship, people might rely differentially on offs: Reactions to transactions that transgress
different moral characteristics and moral the spheres of justice. Political Psychology,
18(2), 255–297.
foundations, as established here. Graham, J., Haidt, J., Koleva, S., Motyl, M., Iyer,
This prediction also helps explain why R., Wojcik, S., & Ditto, P. H. (2013). Moral
when affiliative relationships turn acrimoni- foundations theory: The pragmatic validity of
ous, they become difficult to repair (Keysar, moral pluralism. Advances in Experimental
Converse, Wang, & Epley, 2008; Kramer, Social Psychology, 47, 55–130.
1999; Lount, Zhong, Sivanathan, & Mur- Gray, H. M., Gray, K., & Wegner, D. M. (2007).
nighan, 2008; Waytz et al., 2014): because Dimensions of mind perception. Science,
morality has shifted. When an ally turns even 315(5812), 619–619.
momentarily into an enemy, people shift their Gray, K., & Wegner, D. M. (2009). Moral type-
focus from concerns about the other side’s casting: Divergent perceptions of moral agents
moral rights (patiency) and moral norms and moral patients. Journal of Personality and
Social Psychology, 96(3), 505–520.
concerning social cohesiveness to a focus on Gray, K., Young, L., & Waytz, A. (2012). Mind
concerns about the other side’s moral respon- perception is the essence of morality. Psycho-
sibility and norms concerning individual mo- logical Inquiry, 23(2), 101–124.
rality. This shift in moral focus might then Haidt, J., & Graham, J. (2007). When morality
contribute to a cycle of blame and a desire for opposes justice: Conservatives have moral in-
punishment for the ostensible offender. Per- tuitions that liberals may not recognize. Social
haps more optimistically, in the rarer cases Justice Research, 20(1), 98–116.
of enemies becoming allies, morality should Haidt, J., & Joseph, C. (2004). Intuitive ethics:
shift in a positive direction to reinforce con- How innately prepared intuitions generate
ciliation. For example, when formerly war- culturally variable virtues. Daedalus, 133(4),
ring countries establish a peace treaty, the 55–66.
Keysar, B., Converse, B. A., Wang, J., & Epley,
focus of these parties should shift to moral N. (2008). Reciprocity is not give and take:
rights and establishing social cohesion rather Asymmetric reciprocity to positive and nega-
than finger-pointing over past wrongs. We tive acts. Psychological Science, 19(12), 1280–
welcome future research to test these hypoth- 1286.
eses and to elucidate key differences in moral Kramer, R. M. (1999). Trust and distrust in or-
cognition for “us” versus “them.” ganizations: Emerging perspectives, endur-
192 MOR ALIT Y AND INTERGROUP CONFLIC T

ing questions. Annual Review of Psychology, tance of individual differences in anthropo-


50(1), 569–598. morphism. Perspectives on Psychological Sci-
Kurzban, R., DeScioli, P., & Fein, D. (2012). ence, 5(3), 219–232.
Hamilton vs. Kant: Pitting adaptations for Waytz, A., Dungan, J., & Young, L. (2013). The
altruism against adaptations for moral judg- whistleblower’s dilemma and the fairness–loy-
ment. Evolution and Human Behavior, 33, alty tradeoff. Journal of Experimental Social
323–333. Psychology, 49, 1027–1033.
Leidner, B., & Castano, E. (2012). Morality Waytz, A., Gray, K., Epley, N., & Wegner, D. M.
shifting in the context of intergroup violence. (2010). Causes and consequences of mind per-
European Journal of Social Psychology, 42(1), ception. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 14(8),
82–91. 383–388.
Lount, R. B., Zhong, C., Sivanathan, N., & Waytz, A., Heafner, J., & Epley, N. (2014). The
Murnighan, J. K. (2008). Getting off on the mind in the machine: Anthropomorphism in-
wrong foot: Restoring trust and the timing of creases trust in an autonomous vehicle. Jour-
a breach. Personality and Social Psychology nal of Experimental Social Psychology, 52,
Bulletin, 34, 1601–1612. 113–117.
Piazza, J., Landy, J. F., & Goodwin, G. P. (2014). Waytz, L., & Young, L. (2012). The group-mem-
Cruel nature: Harmfulness as an important, ber mind tradeoff: Attributing mind to groups
overlooked dimension in judgments of moral versus group members. Psychological Science,
standing. Cognition, 131(1), 108–124. 23, 77–85.
Rai, T. S., & Fiske, A. P. (2011). Moral psychol- Waytz, A., & Young, L. (2014). Two motiva-
ogy is relationship regulation: Moral motives tions for two dimensions of mind. Journal of
for unity, hierarchy, equality, and proportion- E xperimental Social Psychology, 55, 278–
­
ality. Psychological Review, 118(1), 57–75. 283.
Rottman, J., Kelemen, D., & Young, L. (2014). Waytz, A., Young, L., & Ginges, J. (2014). A mo-
Tainting the soul: Purity concerns predict tive attribution asymmetry for love versus hate
moral judgments of suicide. Cognition, drives intractable conflict. Proceedings of the
130(2), 217–226. National Academy of Sciences of the USA,
Russell, P. S., & Giner-Sorolla, R. (2011). Moral 111(44), 15687–15692.
anger, but not moral disgust, responds to in- Young, L., & Dungan, J. (2012). Where in the
tentionality. Emotion, 11(2), 233–240. brain is morality?: Everywhere and maybe no-
Smith, I., Aquino, K., Koleva, S., & Graham, where. Social Neuroscience, 7, 1–10.
J. (2014). The moral ties that bind . . . even Young, L., & Saxe, R. (2011). When ignorance
to out-groups: The interactive effect of moral is no excuse: Different roles for intent across
identity and the binding moral foundations. moral domains. Cognition, 120, 202–214.
Psychological Science, 25, 1554–1562. Young, L., & Tsoi, L. (2013). When mental states
Tsoi, L., Dungan, J., Waytz, A., & Young, L. matter, when they don’t, and what that means
(2016). Distinct neural patterns of social cog- for morality. Social and Personality Psychol-
nition for cooperation versus competition. ogy Compass, 7(8), 585–604.
NeuroImage, 137, 86–96. Zaki, J., & Ochsner, K. N. (2012) The neurosci-
Waytz, A., Cacioppo, J., & Epley, N. (2010). ence of empathy: Progress, pitfalls and prom-
Who sees human?: The stability and impor- ise. Nature Neuroscience, 15, 675–680.
CHAPTER 20

Pleasure in Response to Outgroup Pain


as a Motivator of Intergroup Aggression

Mina Cikara

If humans are innately good, cooperative, fair, and averse to


harming one another, why does widespread intergroup violence
continue to afflict society?

Several factors contribute to fomenting aggression between groups;


here I focus on the role of pleasure in response to outgroup pain.

Humans reliably divide their social world Siegel, Dayan, & Dolan, 2014); they even ex-
into us and them. This fundamental ten- hibit physiological aversion responses when
dency is the source of humanity’s greatest the harm they are causing is not real (e.g.,
triumphs but also of its greatest tragedies. shooting a person with a fake gun; Cush-
Banding together allows people to satisfy man, Gray, Gaffey, & Mendes, 2012). These
their own material and psychological needs results are not unique to the lab setting or
(Allport, 1954) and to develop norms and to harming innocent strangers. Analysis of
practices that bolster our most cherished combat activity during the U.S. Civil War
social institutions (e.g., Keltner, 2009; To- and World War I reveal that soldiers would
masello, 2009). However, group living also shoot over the heads of enemy combatants.
results in violence and conflict between Thus harm aversion exerts its effects even in
groups (Cohen & Insko, 2008). According large-scale group conflict (Grossman, 1996).
to one statistic, more than 200 million peo- So how do people eventually overcome their
ple have been killed in acts of genocide, war, aversion to doing harm in order to participate
and other forms of group conflict in the last in intergroup aggression? Several factors are
100 years (Woolf & Hulsizer, 2004). critical for fomenting intergroup violence,
It is difficult to reconcile these statis- including moral disengagement, moral jus-
tics on intergroup violence with the well-­ tification, and dissonance reduction (for an
documented moral prohibitions against excellent review and theoretical integration,
harm that guide most people’s behavior most see Littman & Paluck, 2014; see also Waytz
of the time. In lab studies, people are willing & Young, Chapter 19, this volume). Here I
to pay more to prevent harm to others rela- focus on another complementary mecha-
tive to themselves (Crockett, Kurth-Nelson, nism: pleasure in response to outgroup pain.

193
194 MOR ALIT Y AND INTERGROUP CONFLIC T

Key Terms: Empathy, Schadenfreude, others. If observing outgroup members’ pain


and Harm is consistently accompanied by feeling plea-
sure, people may learn over time to endorse
Empathy refers to the collection of affective and do harm to individual outgroup targets.
and cognitive processes that allow people to
recognize emotional experiences in others,
experience matched sensations and emo- Relevant Debates
tions, and move to alleviate those others’
Ingroup Love versus Outgroup Hate
suffering (Batson, 2009). However, people
as Motivators of Intergroup Aggression
do not empathize with all others all of the
time (nor would it be adaptive if they did). Social categorization is fundamental for
Though it is not often conceptualized as group living. It guides decisions about
an intergroup emotion, empathy is reliably whom to approach or avoid and allows us
moderated by group membership; people to generalize our existing knowledge about
feel less empathy for outgroup relative to in- social groups to novel targets (Bruner,
group members. We refer to this difference 1957). Social categorization also requires
as the intergroup empathy bias (Bruneau, that people categorize themselves (Tajfel &
Cikara, & Saxe, 2017; Cikara, Bruneau, & Turner, 1979). Shifting from an individual
Saxe, 2011; Cikara, Bruneau, Van Bavel, & (“I” or “me”) to a collective (“we” or “us”)
Saxe, 2014). People self-report this bias and self-concept is called social identification
exhibit decreased (and sometimes absent) (Ellemers, 2012). Greater identification en-
physiological responses associated with em- genders greater ingroup favoritism, which
pathy when witnessing outgroup relative to in turn reinforces the boundaries between
ingroup members in physical or emotional “us” and “them” (Tajfel & Turner, 1986;
pain (see Cikara & Van Bavel, 2014, for a for a review, see Hewstone, Rubin, & Wil-
recent review). This bias matters because lis, 2002). Indeed, in the absence of conflict,
the absence of empathy implies a reduction ingroup love is a better predictor of inequi-
in motivation to help those in pain (Zaki & table resource allocation and intergroup bias
Cikara, 2015). that than outgroup hate is (Brewer, 1999).
What is left in the absence of empathy? Ingroup love, however, is not sufficient to
Apathy: indifference toward outgroup suf- ignite intergroup conflict. This is why most
fering. However, it is important to note outgroups elicit indifference rather than ag-
that, although apathy may engender neglect, gression.
it should not promote active harm. An al- Instead, intergroup aggression is driven by
ternative to apathy is the opposite of em- competition over resources and incompat-
pathy: pleasure in response to others’ mis- ibility between groups’ goals: Consider, for
fortunes—Schadenfreude—or displeasure example, the violence against Jews in prewar
in response to others’ triumphs—Glück- Europe or brawling among rival sports fans
schmerz. In contrast to apathy, pleasure and (Campbell, 1965; Fiske & Ruscher, 1993;
pain are feasible motivators of overt inter- Sherif, Harvey, White, Hood, & Sherif,
group aggression. 1961; Sidanius & Pratto, 1999). Competi-
Feeling pleasure in response to outgroup tion transforms indifference into emotions
misfortune is arguably a natural if not such as fear, hatred, and disgust (Chang,
adaptive response in zero-sum environ- Krosch, & Cikara, 2016; Cuddy, Fiske, &
ments: Negative outcomes for “them” in- Glick, 2007; Mackie & Hamilton, 1993).
dicate positive outcomes for “us,” and are These emotions are then used to justify overt
therefore pleasurable. However, experienc- discrimination against outgroups and their
ing Schadenfreude as a passive observer of members (Brewer, 2001). Outgroups are de-
outgroup members’ pain is very different humanized or, worse yet, demonized, which
from being responsible for causing outgroup places them beyond the boundary of justice
members’ pain. Here I propose that inter- that applies to the ingroup (Bar-Tal, 1989;
group Schadenfreude is a natural response Opotow, 2005; Staub, 1989).
that supports the learning of an otherwise The stereotype content model makes spe-
repugnant behavior: actively doing harm to cific predictions about which social groups
 Pleasure in Response to Outgroup Pain as Motivator 195

elicit apathy versus disgust versus threat role. This time, participants said it was most
(Fiske, Cuddy, Glick, & Xu, 2002; Fiske, acceptable to harm competitive, high-status
Chapter 21, this volume). People harbor dis- targets (e.g., wealthy women, businessmen;
gust for groups that are stereotyped as com- Cikara & Fiske, 2011). Thus it appears that
petitive (or exploitative) and low status (e.g., ingroup love is not specific enough to predict
drug addicts, welfare recipients), whereas which social groups will be targeted for ag-
people are threatened by groups that are gression. Instead, the specific outgroups and
stereotyped as competitive but high status their associated stereotypes matter.
(e.g., wealthy professionals, model minori-
ties). We have run several experiments to
Banality of Evil or Virtuous Violence?
see whether “ingroup love” was sufficient
to explain moral exclusion and to harm out- Participation in intergroup violence requires
groups (in which case, all outgroups should that people behave in ways that they would
be treated equivalently) or whether our re- otherwise find aversive. The first several de-
sults were better explained by outgroup hate cades of social psychology were largely dedi-
(which should specifically target competi- cated to understanding the circumstances
tive outgroups). In one experiment, we used that enable people to engage in antisocial
the famous trolley dilemma to investigate behavior. For example, we know that harm-
whether stereotypes motivated people to ful behavior is more likely to arise when
value some social groups’ lives over oth- individuals’ sense of personal responsibil-
ers (Cikara, Farnsworth, Harris, & Fiske, ity is mitigated by obedience to authority
2010). On each trial we assigned different (Milgram, 1965), anonymity (Diener, 1979;
stereotyped targets’ photos to the “sacri- Festinger, Pepitone, & Newcomb, 1952),
ficed” and “saved” roles; we asked partici- or diffusion/displacement of responsibil-
pants to indicate how morally acceptable it ity (Bandura, 1999) and when the salience
was for a third party named Joe to push one of individuals’ own moral standards is low
target (e.g., a drug addict) off a bridge to (Prentice-Dunn & Rogers, 1989). Although
save five others (e.g., five students). Not sur- they are relevant, none of these explanations
prisingly, participants reported that it was is unique to intergroup contexts. Even in the
most acceptable to save cooperative, high- absence of an outgroup, these circumstances
status groups (e.g., Americans and students). could lead individuals in crowds to engage
More important, participants did not value in immoral behavior (e.g., out of individual
different kinds of outgroup members’ lives self-interest). More important, these expla-
equivalently. It was most morally acceptable nations largely adhere to the “banality of
to sacrifice, and least acceptable to save, evil” perspective (Arendt, 1976). By these
competitive, low-status (i.e., disgust) targets. accounts, people are not actively choosing
Specifically, 84% of our respondents said it to act immorally so much as they are reflex-
was acceptable for Joe to push competitive, ively responding to the pressures exerted by
low-status targets off a bridge to save five the situation.
cooperative, high-status targets. This find- An important alternative is the way that
ing is remarkable when juxtaposed with the perpetrators of intergroup harm explic-
finding that 88% of people say this same act itly reframe and/or justify their behavior as
is unacceptable when the targets remain un- serving a greater good (Pinter & Wildschut,
identified (Hauser, Cushman, Young, Jin, & 2012). For example, participants rate torture
Mikhail, 2007). as more acceptable when their own country
Critically, we have found that partici- rather than other countries engages in it
pants’ endorsement of harm shifts to threat- (Tarrant, Branscombe, Warner, & Weston,
ening outgroups when the harm is not fatal. 2012). High identification and coordinated
In one experiment, we asked participants to behavior with the ingroup are critical con-
imagine that they had to decide whether to ditions for acting on behalf of a group in
assign one person to receive painful electric general and for intergroup aggression in
shocks in order to spare another four people. particular (Reicher, Haslam, & Rath, 2008;
On each trial, we assigned different stereo- Cikara & Paluck, 2013). As collective iden-
typed targets’ photos to the “scapegoat” tities become “fused” with one’s individual
196 MOR ALIT Y AND INTERGROUP CONFLIC T

identity, people may act as representatives of of these examples, rivals’ misfortunes are
the group rather than as individual agents cause for pleasure only because fans iden-
(Ellemers, 2012), allowing group goals to tified strongly with their favored team. Of
supplant individual goals. If the ingroup’s course, both of these studies focus on (1)
goals require harming the outgroup, people groups with a history of rivalry and (2)
who are highly identified with the group may Schadenfreude in response to events that are
deliberately choose to endorse or do harm related to the basis for that rivalry (e.g., ask-
because they believe it is the right thing to ing sports fans how they feel about sports-
do (Fiske & Rai, 2015; Reicher et al., 2008; related outcomes). How much information
Rai, Chapter 24, this volume). Said another is necessary to evoke intergroup Schaden-
way, our moral codes may promote fairness freude? Is a history of rivalry required? Does
and prohibition against harm in interper- Schadenfreude extend to events that are ir-
sonal contexts, but we bring different rules relevant to the intergroup competition? One
and expectations to bear on competitive way to address these questions is to examine
intergroup interactions (Cohen, Montoya, the minimal conditions under which partici-
& Insko, 2006; Rhodes & Chalik, 2013). pants exhibit intergroup Schadenfreude.
This is an important perspective because In a series of recent experiments, we found
intergroup Schadenfreude may be one im- that participants exhibited greater Schaden-
portant cue people use to rationalize the ac- freude (and Glückschmerz) toward competi-
ceptability of harming outgroup members. A tive outgroups relative to ingroup members
complete account of intergroup aggression only minutes after being assigned to novel
would have to integrate the contributions groups in competition for $1 (Cikara et al.,
of lower-level affective signals (absence of 2014).
negative and/or presence of positive affect), In the first experiment, we assigned par-
as well as higher-order cognitions reflecting ticipants to novel groups—the Eagles or the
on those signals. Rattlers—purportedly based on their per-
sonalities (in reality, we randomly assigned
them to teams). We also manipulated wheth-
Intergroup Schadenfreude as a Motivator er groups were competitive, cooperative, or
of Intergroup Aggression independently working toward winning a $1
bonus. We told participants that we would
Though several conditions predict Schaden- award bonuses depending on participants’
freude (see Smith, Powell, Combs, & and their teams’ performance in an upcom-
­Schurtz, 2009, and Van Dijk, Ouwerkerk, ing problem-solving challenge. In the com-
Smith, & Cikara, 2015, for reviews), I focus petitive condition, in which only one team
on the effect of intergroup competition could win the bonus, participants reported
here (Cikara & Fiske, 2013). In order for greater Schadenfreude toward outgroup
Schadenfreude to qualify as an intergroup relative to ingroup members, even though
emotion, people must feel it on behalf of the misfortunes were irrelevant to the up-
their group. However, people only appraise coming competition (e.g., “Brendan acci-
events from an intergroup perspective when dentally walked into a glass door”). Inter-
they are highly identified with the ingroup group Schadenfreude was attenuated when
(Mackie, Devos, & Smith, 2000); therefore, groups worked independently for the bonus
Schadenfreude should correlate with group and eliminated when groups were told they
identification. Consistent with this predic- were going to work together to earn the
tion, college basketball fans’ identification bonus. We included unaffiliated targets as a
with their team predicted greater Schaden- baseline in a second experiment, including
freude in response to a rival player’s injury only the competitive condition. We found
(Hoogland et al., 2014). In another study, that participants responded to unaffiliated
hardcore soccer fans smiled more intensely targets (people who did not fit the profile of
when they watched a rival soccer team miss either an Eagle or a Rattler) the same way
a penalty kick relative to when they watched they responded to ingroup targets. These
their favored team make a goal (Boecker, results indicate that, rather than uniquely
Likowski, Pauli, & Weyers, 2015). In both shielding the ingroup from Schadenfreude,
 Pleasure in Response to Outgroup Pain as Motivator 197

people reserve Schadenfreude only for com- 2009). This Schadenfreude–VS association
petitive outgroups (Cikara et al., 2014). It is generalizes to intergroup contexts. For ex-
worth noting that using novel groups has the ample, baseball fans of either the Boston
added benefit of controlling for preexisting Red Sox or New York Yankees, watched
negative attitudes, resentment regarding the their favored team compete with other
outgroup’s past successes (Hareli & Weiner, teams while lying in the fMRI scanner. Fans
2002), and perceptions that past success was of both teams reported pleasure and exhib-
ill gotten (Feather and Sherman, 2002). ited greater activity in the VS when watching
These effects also emerge in more subtle their own team do well and when watching
social contexts. For example, we have found the rival team fail (even when rival failed
that people smile more when targets who are against a third, lower ranked team, the Bal-
merely stereotyped as competitive (e.g., an timore Orioles; Cikara, Botvinick, & Fiske,
investment banker) experience bad events 2011). These findings extend to contexts in
(relative to good events; Cikara & Fiske, which victims are merely associated with the
2012). Together, these results indicate that a rival team. Soccer fans exhibited VS activity
target can evoke these malicious emotional when watching a rival team’s fan receive a
responses in the absence of any personal his- painful electric shock (Hein, Silani, Preus-
tory or direct contact with the perceiver, due choff, Batson, & Singer, 2010). Note that in
only to their group membership and its as- neither case are participants in direct com-
sociated stereotypes. petition. Instead, outgroup failure and pain
Thus, Schadenfreude appears to be a take on a positive value by virtue of partici-
prepared or “natural” response in contexts pants’ affiliation with their favored team.
that are or are perceived as zero-sum. If a These studies provide only correlational
threatening outgroup is unhappy, “we” are evidence, but they suggest an intriguing
pleased; no learning is required. Remem- possibility: that the capacity for intergroup
ber, however, that experiencing pleasure aggression may have developed, in part, by
in response to the observation of outgroup appropriating basic reinforcement-learning
harm is very different from becoming the processes and associated neural circuitry in
first-person agent of harm. Given that group order to overcome harm aversion. Again,
survival may require some members to harm these results are correlational, but greater VS
outgroups on behalf of the ingroup, one in- response to a rival’s suffering in the context
triguing possibility is that Schadenfreude of the baseball and soccer studies described
motivates participation in intergroup ag- above predicted an increased desire to harm
gression by teaching people to overcome the rival team fans (Cikara et al., 2011) and a
aversion to harming outgroup members. decreased willingness to relieve a rival fan’s
pain (by accepting a proportion of the pain
for oneself; Hein et al., 2010). These data
Insights from Cognitive Neuroscience
implicate both the VS’s valuation function—
Many regions of the brain are implicated in evaluating outgroup harm as positive—but
encoding and representing reward, but the also its motivation function—learning to se-
ventral striatum (VS) is associated specifi- lect behaviors that harm the outgroup and
cally with reinforcement learning. By many associated individuals. They also support
accounts, this region supports learning the prediction that the pleasure–harm asso-
stimulus-value associations and acquiring ciation generalizes to individuals merely as-
predictive value representation in the service sociated with the teams under consideration.
of guiding behavior (O’Doherty, 2004). In
other words, this region supports learning
from our experience so we can repeat behav- Implications and Future Directions
iors that yield rewards. There are now sev-
eral functional magnetic resonance imaging It is critical to understand failures of empathy
(fMRI) studies investigating Schadenfreude, and Schadenfreude as they unfold between
all of which find that greater VS engagement groups (as opposed to individuals) because
is correlated with greater Schadenfreude intergroup contexts significantly increase
(e.g., Singer et al., 2006; Takahashi et al., opportunities for violence. First, harm can
198 MOR ALIT Y AND INTERGROUP CONFLIC T

be justified as being morally necessary in the all the mechanisms promoting intergroup
absence of any personal grievance (e.g., in aggression will inform best practices for de-
defense of the ingroup and its values; Fiske fusing it.
& Rai, 2015; Reicher et al., 2008). Second,
the pleasure–pain association generalizes to
entire groups; individuals who have done NOTE
nothing to provoke violence become targets
This chapter is based on an article I wrote for
by virtue of their affiliation with a competi- Current Opinion in Behavioral Sciences (Cikara,
tive, threatening outgroup. 2015).
One outstanding question is whether in-
creased willingness to harm outgroup mem-
bers predicts increased identification with REFERENCES
the ingroup. For example, Littman (2015)
finds that ex-combatants in Uganda and Li- Allport, G. W. (1954). The nature of prejudice.
beria who were abducted by the Lord’s Re- Reading, MA: Addison Wesley.
sistance Army (LRA) as youths and forced Arendt, H. (1976). Eichmann in Jerusalem: A re-
to harm loved ones on its behalf are more port on the banality of evil. London: Penguin.
Bandura, A. (1999). Moral disengagement in the
highly identified with the LRA than ab- perpetration of inhumanities. Personality and
ducted youths who were not forced to harm Social Psychology Review, 3, 193–209.
loved ones. One possibility is that the plea- Bar-Tal, D. (1989). Delegitimization: The ex-
sure of doing outgroup harm may further treme case of stereotyping and prejudice. In
reinforce group identification, creating a D. Bar-Tal, C. Graumann, A. Kruglanski, &
self-perpetuating cycle of collective violence W. Stroebe (Eds.), Stereotyping and prejudice:
(Littman & Paluck, 2014). This is a some- Changing conceptions (pp. 169–182). New
what provocative prediction, because it runs York: Springer-Verlag.
counter to the prediction made by cognitive Batson, C. D. (2009). These things called empa-
dissonance theory. On an overjustification thy: Eight related but distinct phenomena. In
J. Decety & W. J. Ickes (Eds.), The social neu-
account (Deci, Koestner, & Ryan, 1999), de-
roscience of empathy (pp. 3–15). Cambridge,
creased Schadenfreude and increased harm MA: MIT Press.
aversion would predict greater identifica- Boecker, L., Likowski, K. U., Pauli, P., & Wey-
tion with the outgroup, because participants ers, P. (2015). The face of schadenfreude:
have to overcome greater psychological bar- Differentiation of joy and schadenfreude by
riers in order to do harm. Alternatively, the electromyography. Cognition and Emotion,
presence of positive affect in response to 29(6), 1117–1125.
doing harm could also be a source of dis- Brewer, M. B. (1999). The psychology of preju-
sonance. We are presently running studies to dice: Ingroup love and out-group hate? Jour-
adjudicate among these hypotheses. nal of Social Issues, 55(3), 429–444.
Brewer, M. B. (2001). In-group identification
Finally, it would be irresponsible to re-
and intergroup conflict: When does in-group
frain from reiterating that participation love become out-group hate? In R. D. Ash-
in intergroup aggression is a multiply de- more, L. Jussim, & D. Wilder (Eds.), Social
termined phenomenon with many causes identity, inter-group conflict, and conflict re-
and consequences. Intergroup competition, duction (pp. 17–41). New York: Oxford Uni-
group identification, and moral justifica- versity Press.
tions are all motivators of intergroup aggres- Bruneau, E. G., Cikara, M., & Saxe, R. (2017).
sion (at least in humans). However, linking Parochial empathy predicts the reduced altru-
outgroup aggression to reinforcement learn- ism and the endorsement of passive harm. So-
ing expands the reach of our research not cial Psychological and Personality Science.
only to other areas of scientific inquiry (e.g., Bruner, J. S. (1957). On perceptual readiness.
Psychological Review, 64(2), 123–152.
behavioral neuroscience, cognitive neurosci-
Campbell, D. T. (1965). Ethnocentric and other
ence, economics, biology) and other model altruistic motives. In D. Levine (Ed.), Ne-
organisms (e.g., rodent and primate models), braska symposium on motivation (Vol. 13,
but also to political and educational institu- pp. 283–311). Lincoln: University of Nebraska
tions with the power to make and implement Press.
policy. Ultimately, a better understanding of Chang, L. W., Krosch, A. R., & Cikara, M.
 Pleasure in Response to Outgroup Pain as Motivator 199

(2016). Effects of intergroup threat on mind, sion making. Proceedings of the National
brain, and behavior. Current Opinion in Psy- Academy of Sciences of the USA, 111, 17320–
chology, 11, 69–73. 17325.
Cikara, M. (2015). Intergroup Schadenfreude: Cuddy, A. J. C., Fiske, S. T., & Glick, P. (2007).
Motivating participation in collective vio- The BIAS map: Behaviors from intergroup af-
lence. Current Opinion in Behavioral Scienc- fect and stereotypes. Journal of Personality
es, 3, 12–17. and Social Psychology, 92, 631–648.
Cikara, M., Botvinick, M. M., & Fiske, S. T. Cushman, F., Gray, K., Gaffey, A., & Mendes,
(2011). Us versus them: Social identity shapes W. B. (2012). Simulating murder: The aversion
neural responses to intergroup competition to harmful action. Emotion, 12, 2–7.
and harm. Psychological Science, 22, 306– Deci, E. L., Koestner, R., & Ryan, R. M. (1999).
313. A meta-analytic review of experiments exam-
Cikara, M., Bruneau, E. G., & Saxe, R. (2011). ining the effects of extrinsic rewards on intrin-
Us and them: Intergroup failures of empathy. sic motivation. Psychological Bulletin, 125(6),
Current Directions in Psychological Science, 627.
20, 149–153. Diener, E. (1979). Deindividuation, self-aware-
Cikara, M., Bruneau, E. G., Van Bavel, J. J., & ness and disinhibition. Journal of Personality
Saxe, R. (2014). Their pain gives us pleasure: and Social Psychology, 37, 1160–1171.
How intergroup dynamics shape empathic Ellemers, N. (2012). The group self. Science,
failures and counter-empathic responses. 336(6083), 848–852.
Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, Feather, N. T., & Sherman, R. (2002). Envy, re-
55, 110–125. sentment, schadenfreude, and sympathy: Re-
Cikara, M., Farnsworth, R. A., Harris, L. T., & actions to deserved and undeserved achieve-
Fiske, S. T. (2010). On the wrong side of the ment and subsequent failure. Personality and
trolley track: Neural correlates of relative so- Social Psychology Bulletin, 28(7), 953–961.
cial valuation. Social Cognitive and Affective Festinger, L., Pepitone, A., & Newcomb, T.
Neuroscience, 5(4), 404–413. (1952). Some consequences of deindividuation
Cikara, M., & Fiske, S. T. (2011). Bounded em- in a group. Journal of Abnormal and Social
pathy: Neural responses to out-group targets’ Psychology, 47, 382–389.
(mis)fortunes. Journal of Cognitive Neurosci- Fiske, A. P., & Rai, T. S. (2015). Virtuous vio-
ence, 23, 3791–3803. lence: Hurting and killing to create, sustain,
Cikara, M., & Fiske, S. T. (2012). Stereotypes end and honor social relationships. Cam-
and Schadenfreude: Affective and physiologi- bridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
cal markers of pleasure at others’ misfortunes. Fiske, S. T., Cuddy, A. J. C., Glick, P., & Xu, J.
Social Psychological and Personality Science, (2002). A model of (often mixed) stereotype
3, 63–71. content: Competence and warmth respectively
Cikara, M., & Fiske, S. T. (2013). Their pain, follow from perceived status and competition.
our pleasure: Stereotype content and Schaden- Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
freude. Annals of the New York Academy of 82, 878–902.
Sciences, 1299, 52–59. Fiske, S. T., & Ruscher, J. B. (1993). Negative
Cikara, M., & Paluck, E. L. (2013). When going interdependence and prejudice: Whence the
along gets you nowhere and the upside of con- affect? In D. M. Mackie & D. L. Hamilton
flict behaviors. Social and Personality Psy- (Eds.), Affect, cognition, and stereotyping:
chology Compass, 7(8), 559–571. Interactive processes in group perception
Cikara, M., & Van Bavel, J. J. (2014). The neuro- (pp. 239–268). San Diego, CA: Academic
science of intergroup relations: An integrative Press.
review. Perspectives on Psychological Science, Grossman, D. (1996). On killing: The psycholog-
9, 245–274. ical cost of learning to kill in war and society.
Cohen, T. R., & Insko, C. A. (2008). War and New York: Back Bay Books.
peace: Possible approaches to reducing inter- Hareli, S., & Weiner, B. (2002). Dislike and
group conflict. Perspectives on Psychological envy as antecedents of pleasure at another’s
Science, 3(2), 87–93. misfortune. Motivation and Emotion, 26(4),
Cohen, T. R., Montoya, R. M., & Insko, C. A. 257–277.
(2006). Group morality and intergroup rela- Hauser, M., Cushman, F., Young, L., Jin, R.
tions: Cross-cultural and experimental evi- K.-X., & Mikhail, J. (2007). A dissociation
dence. Personality and Social Psychology Bul- between moral judgments and justifications.
letin, 32, 1559–1572. Mind and Language, 22(1), 1–21.
Crockett, M. J., Kurth-Nelson, Z., Siegel, J. Z., Hein, G., Silani, G., Preuschoff, K., Batson, C.
Dayan, P., & Dolan, R. J. (2014). Harm to D., & Singer, T. (2010). Neural responses to
others outweighs harm to self in moral deci- in-group and out-group members’ suffering
200 MOR ALIT Y AND INTERGROUP CONFLIC T

predict individual differences in costly help- egories as markers of intrinsic interpersonal


ing. Neuron, 68, 149–160. obligations. Psychological Science, 24(6),
Hewstone, M., Rubin, M., & Willis, H. (2002). 999–1006.
Intergroup bias. Annual Review of Psychol- Sherif, M., Harvey, O. J., White, B. J., Hood, W.
ogy, 53(1), 575–604. R., & Sherif, C. W. (1961). Intergroup coop-
Hoogland, C. E., Schurtz, D. R., Cooper, C. eration and competition: The Robbers Cave
M., Combs, D. J., Brown, E. G., & Smith, experiment. Norman, OK: University Book
R. H. (2014). The joy of pain and the pain of Exchange.
joy: In-group identification predicts schaden- Sidanius, J., & Pratto, F. (1999). Social domi-
freude and gluckschmerz following rival nance: An intergroup theory of social hierar-
groups’ fortunes. Motivation and Emotion, chy and oppression. New York: Cambridge
39, 260–281. University Press.
Keltner, D. (2009). Born to be good: The science Singer, T., Seymour, B., O’Doherty, J. P.,
of a meaningful life. New York: Norton. Stephan, K. E., Dolan, R. J., & Frith, C. D.
Littman, R. (2015). Perpetrating violence in- (2006). Empathic neural responses are modu-
creases identification with violent groups: lated by the perceived fairness of others. Na-
Survey evidence from former combatants. ture, 439, 466–469.
Manuscript in under review. Smith, R. H., Powell, C. A. J., Combs, D. J. Y., &
Littman, R., & Paluck, E. L. (2014). The cycle of Schurtz, R. D. (2009). Exploring the when and
violence: Understanding individual participa- why of Schadenfreude. Social and Personality
tion in collective violence. Advances in Politi- Psychology Compass, 3, 530–546.
cal Psychology, 36, 79–99. Staub, E. (1989). The roots of evil: The origins
Mackie, D. M., Devos, T., & Smith, E. R. (2000). of genocide and other group violence. New
Intergroup emotions: Explaining offensive York: Cambridge University Press.
action tendencies in an intergroup context. Tajfel, H., & Turner, J. (1979). An integrative
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, theory of intergroup conflict. In W. G. Austin
79(4), 602–616. & S. Worschel (Eds.), The social psychology
Mackie, D. M., & Hamilton, D. (1993). Affect, of intergroup relations (pp. 33–47). Pacific
cognition, and stereotyping. San Diego, CA: Grove, CA: Brooks/Cole.
Academic Press. Tajfel, H., & Turner, J. C. (1986). The social
Milgram, S. (1965). Some conditions of obedi- identity theory of inter group behavior. In S.
ence and disobedience to authority. Human Worchel & W. G. Austin (Eds.), Psychology
Relations, 18, 57–76. of intergroup relations (pp. 7–24). Chicago:
O’Doherty, J. P. (2004). Reward representations Nelson.
and reward-related learning in the human Takahashi, H., Kato, M., Matsuura, M., Mobbs,
brain: Insights from neuroimaging. Current D., Suhara, T., & Okubo, Y. (2009). When
Opinion in Neurobiology, 14(6), 769–776. your gain is my pain and your pain is my gain:
Opotow, S. (2005). Hate, conflict, and moral ex- Neural correlates of envy and Schadenfreude.
clusion. In R. J. Sternberg (Ed.), The psychol- Science, 323, 937–939.
ogy of hate (pp. 121–153). Washington, DC: Tarrant, M., Branscombe, N. R., Warner, R. H.,
American Psychological Association. & Weston, D. (2012). Social identity and per-
Pinter, B., & Wildschut, T. (2012). Self-interest ceptions of torture: It’s moral when we do it.
masquerading as ingroup beneficence: An al- Journal of Experimental Social Psychology,
truistic rationalization explanation of the in- 48(2), 513–518.
terindividual–intergroup discontinuity effect. Tomasello, M. (2009). Why we cooperate. Cam-
Small Group Research, 43, 105–123. bridge, MA: MIT Press.
Prentice-Dunn, S., & Rogers, R. W. (1989). Van Dijk, W. W., Ouwerkerk, J. W., Smith, R.
Deindividuation and the self-regulation of be- H., & Cikara, M. (2015). The role of self-eval-
havior. In P. B. Paulus (Ed.), The psychology of uation and envy in Schadenfreude. European
group influence (2nd ed., pp. 86–109). Hills- Review of Social Psychology, 26, 247–282.
dale, NJ: Erlbaum. Woolf, L. M., & Hulsizer, M. R. (2004). Hate
Reicher, S., Haslam, S. A., & Rath, R. (2008). groups for dummies: How to build a success-
Making a virtue of evil: A five-step social ful hate group. Humanity and Society, 28(1),
identity model of the development of collective 40–62.
hate. Social and Personality Psychology Com- Zaki, J., & Cikara, M. (2015). Addressing em-
pass, 2, 1313–1344. pathic failures. Current Directions in Psycho-
Rhodes, M., & Chalik, L. (2013). Social cat- logical Science, 24, 471–476.
C H A P T E R 21

How Can Universal Stereotypes


Be Immoral?

Susan T. Fiske

If some stereotypes seem to be universal, are they necessarily


immoral?

People around the world are disgusted by homeless people, envy


rich people, and pity older people, not because they deserve it, but
because of people’s universal preoccupations with status and trust.

A Puzzle Spanish are disgusted by beggars, and South


Africans by illegal squatters. Egyptians re-
Our Issue
port disgust toward Bedouins. Why do soci-
Some stereotypes seem to be universal, but eties commonly feel disgusted by their itin-
not because they are true. People around the erant vagrants? Disgust is a moral emotion
world share some prejudices that are argu- that expresses avoiding contamination, and
ably arbitrary (Cuddy et al., 2009; Durante we have some ideas about why this happens.
et al., 2013; Fiske & Durante, 2016). Here’s On the opposite note, why do people usu-
an example: Many societies keep reinventing ally resent the rich? Envy, not disgust, is
moral disgust at people who simply lack an the theme in attitudes toward the rich or
address. Americans report that our society upper class, among Americans, Australians,
finds homeless people disgusting. Belgians, Belgians, Bolivians, Canadians, Chileans,
English, Irish, Italians, Japanese, and Portu- Costa Ricans, Egyptians, English, Greeks,
guese share disgust toward homeless people. Israelis, Lebanese, Mexicans, New Zealand-
Also, Americans, Australians, Belgians, Ital- ers, Peruvians, Spanish, Swiss, Turks, and
ians, and Spanish report disgust about im- Ugandans. Envy is a volatile emotion that
migrants. The Irish are disgusted by roam- condemns the target for having ill-gotten
ing travelers. Greeks, Portuguese, Spanish, gains that should be taken away.
and Swiss think Roma (gypsies) are disgust- A third case example: Why do we pity
ing. Australians and Lebanese likewise view the old? Americans, Australians, Bolivians,
refugees with disgust, as do the Swiss with Canadians, Costa Ricans, English, Greeks,
asylum seekers. Malaysians, Pakistanis, and Indians, Israelis, Italians, Malaysians, Mex-

201
202 MOR ALIT Y AND INTERGROUP CONFLIC T

icans, Portuguese, South Africans, Spanish, Glick, 2007). People are pleased when bad
Swiss, and Ugandans all describe the elderly events happen to them, reactions expressed
as pitiable. And contrary to conventional by both self-report and electromyography of
wisdom, Eastern populations even are more the smile muscles (zygomaticus major; Ci-
negative than Western ones (North & Fiske, kara & Fiske, 2012).
2015). Pity is in effect a moral emotion that This Schadenfreude toward the rich is ar-
promises sympathy, but only as long as its guably dehumanizing because only the en-
targets know their place. vied are its targets among outgroups. Peo-
ple are glad when the high and mighty fall
a notch, and people do not delight in their
Our Constructs: How We Think
good fortune, unlike all other groups, even
about This Puzzle
the disgusting homeless. Dehumanization of
This pattern is disturbing, raising questions the rich portrays them as unfeeling automa-
of good and evil. All three patterns are evil tons (Haslam, 2006), so people judge them
in the sense of denying others their full hu- as lacking in typical human nature, a moral
manity. The answer I present here offers judgment. Observers deny their full human
two primary dimensions for making sense experience.
of other people, and these three exemplars Finally, older people occupy the oppo-
fit three different combinations of the two site quadrant, judged as well intentioned
basic dimensions. One dimension, warmth but incompetent. Pity is a moral evaluation
(trustworthiness), interprets the others’ in- of someone with undeserved bad outcomes
tent for good or ill. The second dimension (Weiner, Perry, & Magnusson, 1988). Elders
(competence) interprets their capacity to lose that pity and sympathy if they reveal
act on those intentions (Fiske, 2015; Fiske, selfish intent: resisting orderly succession
Cuddy, Glick, & Xu, 2002). (not retiring), consuming shared resources
In this model, homeless people appear as (using up social security), or invading gen-
the most extremely negative outgroup, alleg- erational identities (adopting youth culture;
edly low on both warmth and competence. North & Fiske, 2013). Pity is a moral emo-
They are dehumanized in that people have tion (they may deserve better, but only if
difficulty imaging what’s going on inside they adhere to cooperative prescriptions).
their minds and what they do on a typical But pity is also dehumanizing because it dis-
day. The brain’s theory-of-mind network allows their human freedom and disrespects
­responds to them less as people (less medial their human abilities.
prefrontal cortex) and more as disgusting Thus, arguably, three distinct, salient, and
objects (insula; Harris & Fiske, 2006). nearly universal stereotypes express moral
What’s more, people’s reaction to them as judgments and accompanying moral emo-
disgusting is a moral reaction, both blaming tions that enable dehumanization, which it-
them for their incompetence and for their self seems morally problematic. The morali-
exploitative intent (not playing by the rules). ty and moralizing of prejudices touch several
Other groups that have no fixed address also raw nerves in society, now and in the past.
disgust people because they seem to have no
redeeming qualities, and perhaps observers
want to avoid contamination by their stig- Context: Some Debates
ma. Also, someone who lacks an address is
less accountable to and invested in society, Psychological scientists used to treat all
so how can they be trusted or respected? stereotypes as alike, interchangeable for
Rich people, one contrasting case, do research purposes (Fiske, 1998). From the
demand respect for their apparent com- 1940s to the 1960s, prejudiced people alleg-
petence because of their prestige, but they edly had personality defects that generated
seem untrustworthy because they do not broad-based ethnocentrism. In the 1980s
apparently have others’ interests at heart. and 1990s, exciting advances revealed many
People’s ambivalence creates envy and going general and normal processes of stereotyp-
along to get along, because the rich control ing—for example, that stereotypes are more
resources, but the rich also provoke attack automatic, uncontrollable, and widespread
when the chips are down (Cuddy, Fiske, & than lay people think. This era brought the
 How Can Universal Stereotypes Be Immoral? 203

Implicit Association Test (Greenwald & texts may change, the context-to-stereotype
Banaji, 1995), revealing spontaneous nega- principles appear systematic. So they have
tive associations to outgroups, an insight parsimony on their side, in contrast to ad
now part of popular and professional cul- hoc interpretations of the accuracy of each
ture. This era also showed the fundamental specific group stereotype. But they also
categorization of people into ingroup and provide a more nuanced account than mere
outgroup (Turner & Tajfel, 1979), predict- negativity.
ing ingroup favoritism and perceived out- According to the SCM, intergroup inter-
group homogeneity. Many other insights dependence predicts the warmth dimension.
followed from understanding basic social Cooperating groups seem friendly and trust-
cognitive processes of attention, inference, worthy; competing groups seem exploitative
and memory. What these paradigm shifts and untrustworthy. Observers extrapolate
meant was that prejudice is not the product from a particular intergroup structure of
of sick minds but of normal cognition. Nev- interdependence to characteristics of the en-
ertheless, the focus on process treated all tire outgroup. In assessing interdependence,
stereotypes as similar (simply negative). both economic and value cooperation/
The stereotype content model (SCM) of- competition matter here (Kervyn, Fiske, &
fered an alternative perspective, on the Yzerbyt, 2015). Observers in effect mimic
premise that distinct historical and cultural the sentry’s call—“Who goes there, friend
contexts lead to distinct biases (Fiske, 1998). or foe?”—where the foe might have hostile
For example, when Chinese laborers built intent to compete over tangible resources or
American railroads in the mid-19th century, shared values. Only those people who share
they were viewed in animalistic terms. Since resources and values are warm.
their expulsion, Chinese immigrants today Upon deciding the warmth dimension,
are seen as automatons: scientifically tal- one needs to know the others’ ability to
ented and technically savvy. The stereotype enact their benign or ill intent. The com-
content depends on who happens to arrive petence judgment follows from the others’
and what jobs they happen to have, but ob- prestige: High-status groups are presumed
servers apply their context-driven stereo- competent, and low-status ones incompe-
types to an entire ethnicity. Stereotypes are tent. Despite the plausible role of circum-
accidents of history, so they are not all alike, stances, people perceive groups to get what
as groups’ immigration histories differ, for they deserve on the basis of who they are.
example. To the extent that context determines soci-
A contrasting perspective is that stereo- etal rank, this perception ignores arbitrary
types reflect reality—accurate perceptions causes of rank and perceived competence.
of group differences. Scientific debates on Stereotypes are historical accidents, not
this point predate Gordon Allport (1954), enduring truths. But the principles under-
whose brilliant analysis pointed out that we lying them have some apparently universal
have no criteria for so-called accuracy. If two elements.
groups show mean differences, they always
show overlapping distributions, and the ma-
jority of individuals are not well represented Theoretical Stance
by the mean. An expected value may operate
in statistics but not in social life, where dif- The SCM argues for universal human preoc-
ferences are small and wrong assumptions cupations with status and trust. Regarding
costly. Moreover, a single statement that a status, all human organizations develop hi-
group has a certain characteristic raises the erarchies, either overt or subtle (Gruenfeld &
questions: How much? What proportion? Tiedens, 2010). Primates do it; dogs, birds,
Compared to whom? In whose judgment? and bees do it (Fiske, 2010). Social compari-
The SCM offers an alternative to ste- son structures our sociality, creating scorn
reotype accuracy, explaining the cultural downward and envy upward (Fiske, 2011).
origins of stereotypes in the historical mo- Status organizes interactions, giving prior-
ment’s intergroup relations. Principles of so- ity to those on top. In stable hierarchies, the
cial structure, therefore, predict stereotype high-status individuals can relax and neglect
content. Although specific intergroup con- their subordinates, whereas the low-status
204 MOR ALIT Y AND INTERGROUP CONFLIC T

persons must stay vigilant and stand aside. perhaps class), so social structure would
Unstable hierarchies cost the high-status have no causal role in stereotype content.
more, as they must constantly defend their This biological stance might seem to explain
position. In either case, status differences some of the SCM groups.
get reified by attributing competence to the Among our three opening puzzles, older
high-status and incompetence to the low, people seeming incompetent but warm
justifying their respective ranks. Little ac- might be the best case for this biological per-
count is taken of circumstances, opportuni- spective. Yet it would be a blunt approach,
ties, and challenges. because the evidence on both dimensions is
Regarding the other dimension, trust, mixed. For example, although fluid intelli-
interdependence predicts warmth. Again, gence (speed) declines with age, crystallized
human interdependence is universal; no one intelligence (knowledge) grows (Salthouse,
survives and thrives—let alone reproduces— 2012). And older people indeed experience
alone. Patterns of interdependence promi- more positive affect with age (Charles &
nently include cooperation, with shared Carstensen, 2010), making them warmer,
goals wherein each needs the other to gain but their health is worse, giving them cause
the desired outcome, and competition, with for complaint. The biological reality ap-
mutually exclusive goals that each gains only proach is also tenuous because older people
at the other’s expense (Kelley & Thibaut, did not always live so long as they do now to
1978; Rusbult & Van Lange, 2003). Again, show these biologically driven patterns. Be-
the SCM predicts that societal structures get sides, the negative overall elder stereotype is
reified and justified, with cooperative groups more prevalent in countries with aging pop-
seen as intrinsically trustworthy and friend- ulations to manage (North & Fiske, 2015),
ly, competitive groups seen as intrinsically which is more consistent with circumstances
otherwise. Circumstances again are ignored. than sheer biology.
What’s the alternative? In theory, people The biological approach has a harder time
could take more account of groups’ situa- explaining social-class stereotypes (e.g., for
tions that enable status or force interdepen- rich people), unless they are genetically se-
dence of different kinds. Instead, the SCM lected by social Darwinism favoring cold
posits a kind of group-level correspondence competence as a key to success. One might,
bias (Gilbert & Malone, 1995; Jones, 1979), in parallel, explain homelessness as the pur-
in that a group’s structural position and view of biologically incompetent, antisocial
consequent behavior is interpreted to re- individuals. The near-universal cultural pat-
flect their dispositions. For example, if La- terns for these groups’ stereotypes might
tino immigrants enter the United States to make this argument seem more plausible.
fill low-wage jobs, one interpretation is that But homelessness is in fact most often tem-
they are the dregs of their society, taking porary, so how can a group be biologically
away American jobs, so they are inherently predisposed to be vagrant one month and the
incompetent and untrustworthy. An alterna- next month not, under other circumstances?
tive interpretation is that they have to work Moreover, how would one explain cultural
so hard to get here that they are selected for idiosyncrasies regarding other groups—for
effortful ingenuity, and, upon arrival, they example, unemployed people as disgusting
take jobs no one else wants, so they grow the versus pitiable, depending on social welfare
economy. A structural interpretation is that systems? Ambivalent sexist stereotypes of
Mexico’s birthrates and economy created women depend also on social systems (Eagly
conditions that gave young men incentive to & Steffen, 1984; Glick et al., 2000). So a
migrate (and now that their birthrates have purely biological account of group images
fallen and their economy has improved, net reflecting reality is problematic for several
migration is zero; Massey, Durand, & Pren, reasons, even beyond Allport’s (1954) objec-
2014). The moral judgment follows from tions about criteria, noted earlier.
dispositionally interpreting their structural A variant on this position is that prejudic-
place in society. es evolve for functional reasons, dating back
Another theoretical contrast would hold to ancestral adaptations. This argument
that some stereotypes could arguably be works better for gender and age than race
quasi-biological (especially gender, age, race, (Cosmides, Tooby, & Kurzban, 2003), and
 How Can Universal Stereotypes Be Immoral? 205

arguably not at all for other, more recent in- tent but small correlations have averaged r =
group–outgroup distinctions, such as mod- –.32 (Durante et al., 2013). Improving both
ern occupations (e.g., investment bankers). the warmth and competition measures sub-
More compatible social evolutionary per- stantially increases their correlation (Kervyn
spectives argue that group stereotypes pat- et al., 2015). The most reliable correlation
tern themselves after specific types of threat occurs (1) when competition measures in-
to the ingroup (e.g., contamination, betray- clude both economic and values (tangible
al, attack; Cottrell & Neuberg, 2005). Or and symbolic resources), and (2) warmth
that stereotypes are functional reactions to measures include both sociability/friendli-
intergroup relations that vary on relative ness and trustworthiness/morality. Judging
power, relative status, and goal compatibil- competitors as less moral—insincere and
ity (Alexander, Brewer, & Hermann, 1999), untrustworthy—is part of the structure–­
dimensions related to the SCM but more stereotype link.
differentiated (Fiske, Xu, Cuddy, & Glick, The downstream consequences of the
1999; Fiske et al., 2002). The SCM locates structure-driven stereotypes are emotion-
itself away from accuracy claims and toward al prejudices. In our examples, the low-
more structural, functional approaches. warmth–low-competence combination, ex-
emplified by homeless people, reliably elicits
disgust (Fiske et al., 2002). Other members
Evidence for the SCM and for Our of this quadrant, besides people without
Three Cases an address (immigrants, refugees, travel-
ers, Roma, Bedouins), include drug addicts.
Our Evidence
Groups in the cold-but-competent quadrant
We suggest that societies reinvent similar include not only the resented rich but also
stereotypes—particularly for homeless, rich, business people in general and entrepreneur-
or elders—because of similar structures that ial ethnic groups (often Jews and Asians),
cut across cultures. Status predicts compe- all prompting envy. Warm-but-incompetent
tence stereotypes, and interdependence pre- groups, besides older people, include the dis-
dicts warmth stereotypes. The evidence sup- abled and children, all receiving pity.
ports each in turn.
As basic as it is to social life, status trig-
Falsification
gers stereotypes of competence to an aston-
ishing degree around the world. Belief in Although the SCM has been supported
meritocracy is not just an American dream around the world and across the last century
that people get what they deserve. People of measuring stereotypes (Fiske, 2015), crit-
everywhere assume that high-status people ics challenge the warmth dimension (every
are competent (across 36 samples, average r laboratory gets the competence dimen-
= .90, range = .74–.99, all p’s < .001; Duran- sion). First, some suggest that morality, not
te et al., 2013). The correlations are in the warmth, is the key term. The original theory
range of reliabilities, but not because SCM and evidence proposed by Abele and Woj-
studies ask the same question twice. The ciszke (2007) use this term (or communion).
status measure asks about the demographic We have been inclined to lump together as
variables of economic success and job pres- warmth both trustworthiness and sociabili-
tige, whereas the competence measure at- ty, which typically correlate, except for a con
tributes a psychological trait of capability. artist who uses friendliness as a means for
From a moral standpoint, the assumption untrustworthy goals. Admittedly, sociability
that people deserve their status makes a dis- and morality can be separately predictive, es-
positional explanation for both success and pecially in perceiving the ingroup (Brambilla
failure. The rich get credit, and the poor get & Leach, 2014; Goodwin, Piazza, & Rozin,
blame, without regard to circumstance. 2014). The relevant dimensions depend on
Likewise, interdependence structures also level of analysis: Though they are separable,
define social life, triggering stereotypes of friendliness correlates with morality; com-
warmth (friendly, sincere). Beliefs that co- petence correlates with assertiveness (Abele,
operators are nice and trustworthy, whereas Hauke, Peters, Louvet, Szymkow, & Duan,
competitors are mean, are robust. Consis- 2016). As lumpers, not splitters, we prefer
206 MOR ALIT Y AND INTERGROUP CONFLIC T

the overall level of analysis, and we see the Other cultural variants suggest that East
SCM as surviving this challenge but with the Asian countries, with a more active mod-
noted amendments. esty norm, do not promote societal reference
Another challenge views the warmth di- groups (citizens, middle class) to the high–
mension as emerging only from theory, not high quadrant, as Westerners do (Cuddy
spontaneous usage (Koch, Imhoff, Dotsch, et al., 2009). They assign those ingroups a
Unkelbach, & Alves, 2016). Concerned with more neutral location. But because their out-
whether we were inventing these two di- groups land in the usual locations, the SCM
mensions and demonstrating only existence seems supported.
proof (people can array groups by warmth
and competence, but do not necessarily do
Needed Data
so), we conducted a multidimensional scaling
(MDS) study that was more consistent with Some anomalous SCM data come from
generating warmth and competence dimen- high-conflict societies. In Ireland, Israel,
sions than not (Kervyn & Fiske, 2016; see and some Arab countries, the warmth–­
also Yzerbyt, 2016). The older Rosenberg, competence correlation is high, but not be-
Nelson, and Vivekananthan (1968) MDS cause of income equality. Data show that
generates social good–bad × task good–bad, conflict simplifies the SCM space to us (all
which are cognate with the SCM warmth × good) versus them (all bad; Durante, Fiske,
competence. Moreover, also consistent with Gelfand, et al., 2017).
the SCM studies, Durante, Volpato, and Besides examining cultural and histori-
Fiske (2010) independently generated these cal generality, SCM needs exploration at
dimensions from content-analyzing fascist earlier ages. When do children distinguish
descriptions of social groups. Reanalysis of interdependence/warmth and status/compe-
the Katz and Braly (1933) adjectives fits the tence? Arguably, infants recognize good and
same space for historically relevant groups ill intent, as well as status/competence. And
(Bergsieker, Leslie, Constantine, & Fiske, school-age children, as well as street chil-
2012). All these studies speak to support for dren, have generated SCM-compatible data
the SCM dimensions by using other meth- in the Dominican Republic (Anselin, 2004).
ods of generating them. But more data would be better.
Finally, one might argue that the SCM People’s perceptions of animal species
is a WEIRD invention (Henrich, Heine, & (pets, predators, vermin, livestock) follow
Norenzayan, 2010). Indeed, the SCM basic the SCM space (Sevillano & Fiske, 2015),
premises do show cultural variation (Fiske & but perhaps other species see conspecifics in
Durante, 2016). The basic hypothesis is that similar terms. Some attempts to explore the
a society’s groups will array in a two-dimen- warmth and competence dimensions ask the
sional warmth-by-competence space, pro- question, Do dogs do it? Dogs clearly make
ducing a warmth–competence correlation of social comparisons up and down (Range,
approximately zero. Most cultures do pro- Horn, Viranyi, & Huber, 2009), a feature of
duce this pattern, but cultures like the United human status hierarchies that predicts per-
States, with higher income inequality, show ceived competence.
the pattern most clearly. Nations with lower Corporations get sorted into SCM space
income inequality do not differentiate the by their apparent worthy or unworthy
mixed (high–low, low–high) combinations intents and their apparent competence
as clearly. In fact, the warmth–competence (Kervyn, Fiske, & Malone, 2012). Perhaps
correlation is predicted by national income other entities—software? cars?—also vary
inequality (Durante et al., 2013). This fits accordingly. The key is the entity displaying
the idea that the mixed quadrants help jus- intent and capability.
tify status inequality, describing the deserv-
ing and undeserving poor, the deserving and
undeserving rich. Lower income inequality Extension and Expansion:
tends to produce a larger set of ingroups, all Beyond the SCM
eligible for the social safety net, and then
some extreme outgroups (e.g., refugees), low In prejudice, one size does not fit all. Ste-
on both dimensions and beyond the pale. reotyping is not just hating a group (though
 How Can Universal Stereotypes Be Immoral? 207

many of the most deadly biases are precisely Cosmides, L., Tooby, J., & Kurzban, R. (2003).
that). Rather, some systematic and apparent- Perceptions of race. Trends in Cognitive Sci-
ly universal principles apply, with variations. ences, 7(4), 173–179.
From a moral perspective, the apparently Cottrell, C. A., & Neuberg, S. L. (2005). Dif-
ferent emotional reactions to different groups:
main dimensions represent moral judg-
A sociofunctional threat-based approach to
ments that an outgroup has evil intent (low “prejudice.” Journal of Personality and Social
warmth) or lacks drive (low competence). In Psychology, 88(5), 770–789.
either case, they become less deserving, less Cuddy, A. J. C., Fiske, S. T., & Glick, P. (2007).
fully human. The BIAS map: Behaviors from intergroup af-
The tendency to explain group positions fect and stereotypes. Journal of Personality
in terms of stereotypes reifies, essentializes, and Social Psychology, 92, 631–648.
and justifies group differences that may at Cuddy, A. J. C., Fiske, S. T., Kwan, V. S. Y.,
least as much result from circumstance. As Glick, P., Demoulin, S., Leyens, J.-P., . . .
such, stereotyping allows societies to ignore Ziegler, R. (2009). Stereotype content model
these inequalities, or even to support them, across cultures: Towards universal similarities
and some differences. British Journal of Social
immoral responses in themselves. Psychology, 48, 1–33.
Durante, F., Fiske, S. T., Gelfand, M., Crippa,
REFERENCES F., Suttora, C., Stillwell, A., . . . Teymoori, A.
(2017). Ambivalent stereotypes link to peace,
Abele, A. E., Hauke, N., Peters, K., Louvet, E., conflict, and inequality across 38 nations.
Szymkow, A., & Duan, Y. (2016). Facets of Proceedings of the National Academy of Sci-
the fundamental content dimensions: Agency ences of the USA.
with competence and assertiveness—Commu- Durante, F., Fiske, S. T., Kervyn, N., Cuddy, A. J.
nion with warmth, and morality. Frontiers in C., Akande, A., Adetoun, B. E., . . . Storari, C.
Psychology. Available at www.ncbi.nlm.nih. C. (2013). Nations’ income inequality predicts
gov/pmc/articles/PMC5118442. ambivalence in stereotype content: How soci-
Abele, A. E., & Wojciszke, B. (2007). Agency eties mind the gap. British Journal of Social
and communion from the perspective of self Psychology, 52, 726–746.
versus others. Journal of Personality and So- Durante, F., Volpato, C., & Fiske, S. T. (2010).
cial Psychology, 93(5), 751–763. Using the stereotype content model to exam-
Alexander, M. G., Brewer, M. B., & Hermann, ine group depictions in fascism: An archival
R. K. (1999). Images and affect: A functional approach. European Journal of Social Psy-
analysis of out-group stereotypes. Journal chology, 40, 465–483.
of Personality and Social Psychology, 77(1), Eagly, A. H., & Steffen, V. J. (1984). Gender
78–93. stereotypes stem from the distribution of
­
Allport, G. W. (1954). The nature of prejudice. women and men into social roles. Journal
Reading, MA: Addison Wesley. of Personality and Social Psychology, 46(4),
Anselin, I. (2004). Assessing Dominican chil- 735–754.
dren’s views of societal groups: Using the ste- Fiske, S. T. (1998). Stereotyping, prejudice, and
reotype content model. Unpublished senior discrimination. In D. T. Gilbert, S. T. Fiske,
thesis, Princeton University, Princeton, NJ. & G. Lindzey (Eds.), Handbook of social psy-
Bergsieker, H. B., Leslie, L. M., Constantine, chology (4th ed., Vol. 2, pp. 357–411). New
V. S., & Fiske, S. T. (2012). Stereotyping by York: McGraw-Hill.
omission: Eliminate the negative, accentuate Fiske, S. T. (2010). Interpersonal stratifica-
the positive. Journal of Personality and Social tion: Status, power, and subordination. In S.
Psychology, 102(6), 1214–1238. T. Fiske, D. T. Gilbert, & G. Lindzey (Eds.),
Brambilla, M., & Leach, C. W. (2014). On the Handbook of social psychology (5th ed.,
importance of being moral: The distinctive pp. 941–982). New York: Wiley.
role of morality in social judgment. Social Fiske, S. T. (2011). Envy up, scorn down: How
Cognition, 32(4), 397–408. status divides us. New York: Russell Sage
Charles, S. T., & Carstensen, L. L. (2010). Social Foundation.
and emotional aging. Annual Review of Psy- Fiske, S. T. (2015). Intergroup biases: A focus on
chology, 61, 383–409. stereotype content. Current Opinion in Be-
Cikara, M., & Fiske, S. T. (2012). Stereotypes havioral Sciences, 3, 45–50.
and Schadenfreude: Behavioral and physi- Fiske, S. T., Cuddy, A. J., Glick, P., & Xu, J.
ological markers of pleasure at others’ misfor- (2002). A model of (often mixed) stereotype
tunes. Social Psychological and Personality content: Competence and warmth respectively
Science, 3, 63–71. follow from perceived status and competition.
208 MOR ALIT Y AND INTERGROUP CONFLIC T

Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, Kervyn, N., Fiske, S. T., & Malone, C. (2012).
82, 878–902. Brands as intentional agents framework: How
Fiske, S. T., & Durante, F. (2016). Stereotype perceived intentions and ability can map brand
content across cultures: Variations on a few perception. Journal of Consumer Psychology,
themes. In M. J. Gelfand, C.-Y. Chiu, & Y.-Y. 22, 166–176.
Hong (Eds.), Advances in culture and psychol- Kervyn, N., Fiske, S. T., & Yzerbyt, Y. (2015).
ogy (Vol. 6, pp. 209–258). New York: Oxford Foretelling the primary dimension of social
University Press. cognition: Symbolic and realistic threats to-
Fiske, S. T., Xu, J., Cuddy, A. C., & Glick, P. gether predict warmth in the stereotype con-
(1999). (Dis)respecting versus (dis)liking: Sta- tent model. Social Psychology, 46, 36–45.
tus and interdependence predict ambivalent Koch, A., Imhoff, R., Dotsch, R., Unkelbach, C.,
stereotypes of competence and warmth. Jour- & Alves, H. (2016). The ABC of stereotypes
nal of Social Issues, 55, 473–491. about groups: Agency/socio-economic success,
Gilbert, D. T., & Malone, P. S. (1995). The cor- conservative–progressive beliefs, and commu-
respondence bias. Psychological Bulletin, 117, nion. Journal of Personality and Social Psy-
21–38. chology, 110(5), 675–709.
Glick, P., Fiske, S. T., Mladinic, A., Saiz, J. L., Massey, D. S., Durand, J., & Pren, K. A. (2014).
Abrams, D., Masser, B., . . . López, W. (2000). Explaining undocumented migration to the
Beyond prejudice as simple antipathy: Hostile U.S. International Migration Review, 48(4),
and benevolent sexism across cultures. Jour- 1028–1061.
nal of Personality and Social Psychology, 79, North, M. S., & Fiske, S. T. (2013). Act your (old)
763–775. age: Prescriptive, ageist biases over succession,
Goodwin, G. P., Piazza, J., & Rozin, P. (2014). identity, and consumption. Personality and
Moral character predominates in person per- Social Psychology Bulletin, 39(6), 720–734.
ception and evaluation. Journal of Personality North, M. S., & Fiske, S. T. (2015). Modern at-
and Social Psychology, 106(1), 148–168. titudes toward older adults in the aging world:
Greenwald, A. G., & Banaji, M. R. (1995). Im- A cross-cultural meta-analysis. Psychological
plicit social cognition: Attitudes, self-esteem, Bulletin, 141(5), 993–1021.
and stereotypes. Psychological Review, Range, F., Horn, L., Viranyi, Z., & Huber, L.
102(1), 4–27. (2009). The absence of reward induces in-
Gruenfeld, D. H., & Tiedens, L. Z. (2010). Orga- equity aversion in dogs. Proceedings of the
nizational preferences and their consequences. National Academy of Sciences of the USA,
In S. T. Fiske, D. T. Gilbert, & G. Lindzey 106(1), 340–345.
(Eds.), Handbook of social psychology (5th Rosenberg, S., Nelson, C., & Vivekananthan, P.
ed., pp. 1252–1287). New York: Wiley. S. (1968). A multidimensional approach to the
Harris, L. T., & Fiske, S. T. (2006). Dehuman- structure of personality impressions. Journal
izing the lowest of the low: Neuro-imaging re- of Personality and Social Psychology, 9(4),
sponses to extreme outgroups. Psychological 283–294.
Science, 17, 847–853. Rusbult, C. E., & Van Lange, P. A. M. (2003). In-
Haslam, N. (2006). Dehumanization: An inte- terdependence, interaction, and relationships.
grative review. Personality and Social Psychol- Annual Review of Psychology, 54, 351–375.
ogy Review, 10(3), 252–264. Salthouse, T. (2012). Consequences of age-relat-
Henrich, J., Heine, S. J., & Norenzayan, A. ed cognitive declines. Annual Review of Psy-
(2010). The weirdest people in the world? chology, 63, 201–226.
­Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 33(2–3), 61– Sevillano, V., & Fiske, S. T. (2015). Warmth and
83. competence in animals. Journal of Applied So-
Jones, E. E. (1979). The rocky road from acts cial Psychology, 46, 276–293.
to dispositions. American Psychologist, 34, Tajfel, H., & Turner, J. C. (1979). An integrative
107–117. theory of intergroup conflict. In W. G. Austin
Katz, D., & Braly, K. (1933). Racial stereotypes & S. Worchel (Eds.), The social psychology of
of one hundred college students. Journal of intergroup relations (pp. 33–47). Monterey,
Abnormal and Social Psychology, 28(3), 280– CA: Brooks/Cole.
290. Weiner, B., Perry, R. P., & Magnusson, J. (1988).
Kelley, H. H., & Thibaut, J. W. (1978). Interper- An attributional analysis of reactions to stig-
sonal relations: A theory of interdependence. mas. Journal of Personality and Social Psy-
New York: Wiley. chology, 55(5), 738–748.
Kervyn, N., & Fiske, S. T. (2016). SCM in MDS Yzerbyt, V. (2016). SCM MDS II. Université
I. Université Catholic de Louvain-la-neuve, Catholic de Louvain-la-neuve, Belgium. Un-
Belgium. Unpublished manuscript. published manuscript.
PART V
MORALITY AND CULTURE

Q U E S T I O N S A N S W E R E D I N PA R T V

CHAPTER 22  What are the moral intuitions people have,


and why do they have them?

CHAPTER 23  How does motivation underlie morality?

CHAPTER 24  Are there any universally held moral rules that apply
across social–relational contexts?

CHAPTER 25  Why do people care about living up to moral values?

CHAPTER 26  Are moral heroes (e.g., Martin Luther King, Jr.) masterminds
with exceptional moral character, or are they merely symbolic puppets?

CHAPTER 27  Is morality universal?

CHAPTER 28  How does history shape moral values?


CHAPTER 22

Moral Foundations Theory


On the Advantages of Moral Pluralism
over Moral Monism

Jesse Graham
Jonathan Haidt
Matt Motyl
Peter Meindl
Carol Iskiwitch
Marlon Mooijman

What are the moral intuitions people have, and why do they have
them?

Moral foundations theory approaches this question through the four


lenses of nativism, cultural learning, intuitionism, and pluralism.

Moral foundations theory (MFT; Graham et single exposure to the snake-fearing mon-
al., 2013; Haidt & Joseph, 2004) was de- key to be afraid of the snake. These mon-
signed to explain both the variety and uni- keys, though, did not learn to be fearful of
versality of moral judgments. It makes four other stimuli that they may not be “wired”
central claims about morality. to fear, such as flowers (Mineka & Cook,
1988). These findings suggest that the mon-
1.  There is a first draft of the moral mind. keys may be predisposed to learning some
Nativism is the view that the mind is not things and not other things. People may
a blank slate; it is organized in advance of similarly be more prone to learning some
experience. Evolutionary processes created moral values. For example, young children
a first draft of the mind, which is then ed- derive pleasure from fair exchanges and dis-
ited by experience (Marcus, 2004). For ex- pleasure from unfair exchanges, potentially
ample, young Rhesus monkeys who showed because fairness promotes more effective in-
no previous fear of snakes (including plastic teractions between individuals within social
snakes) watched a video of another monkey groups (Tooby, Cosmides, & Barrett, 2005;
reacting fearfully (or not) to a plastic snake. Richerson & Boyd, 2005). Therefore, MFT
The young Rhesus monkeys learned from a is a nativist theory—it proposes that there

211
212 M O R A L I T Y A N D C U LT U R E

is a first draft of the moral mind that devel- the many System 1 and System 2 processes
oped in response to evolutionary pressures that occur when people make moral judg-
and is organized prior to experience. ments during social interactions. But the
SIM says that automatic, System 1 process-
2.  The first draft of the moral mind gets es generally occur first and drive System 2
edited during development within a culture. thinking, particularly when a person needs
MFT is also a cultural theory that describes to invent a justification that can be shared
the “editing process” by which the univer- with others.
sal first draft of the moral mind becomes a
culturally specific and culturally competent 4.  There are many psychological foun-
adult morality. For example, Hindu cul- dations of morality. Lastly, MFT is a plu-
tures emphasize respect for elders and other ralist theory that posits that because there
authorities, as can be seen in the common were numerous adaptive social challenges
practice of children bowing to elders and throughout evolutionary history, there
often touching elders’ feet. By the time these are many different moral foundations that
children reach adulthood, they have gained emerged in response to those challenges.
culturally specific knowledge that may lead Most research to date has concentrated on
them to automatically initiate bowing move- five moral foundations:
ments when encountering elders or other
revered people. In more individualistic and a. Care/harm. Mammals have an un-
secular cultures that do not emphasize re- usually long period of development during
spect for authority, children are not taught which they are dependent upon their care-
to bow to elders. This might make it easier takers. Therefore, caretakers who were more
for them to address authority figures by first sensitive to the needs and distress of their
name or question their authority later in children were more likely to have children
life. These different social practices in dif- who survived into adulthood. This sensitiv-
ferent cultures help explain cultural differ- ity generalizes beyond our own children and
ences in moral values (e.g., Haidt, Koller, can be activated when we learn of other peo-
& Dias, 1993). The social practices are not ple’s children or even see photos of animal
written on a blank slate. It is highly unlikely babies that activate our urges to care and
that there could be a society in which bow- protect, sometimes linked to anger toward
ing and feet-kissing were done as shows of the perpetrator of the harm.
disrespect or contempt or were aimed pri- b. Fairness/cheating. All social ani-
marily at one’s subordinates. Primates have mals interact with each other, and although
an innate toolkit for managing hierarchical there are debates as to whether any nonhu-
relationships, but cultures vary in how they man animals have a sense of “fairness” (see
teach their children to apply these tools. You McAuliffe & Santos, Chapter 40, this vol-
need to know something about this toolkit, ume), there is little debate that the sense of
this “first draft” of the moral mind, as well fairness can be found across human cultures
as the culture in which a mind develops. (Fiske, 1991), that it emerges well before
the age of 5 and possibly before the age of
3.  Intuitions come first. MFT is an intu- 1 (Hamlin, Wynn, & Bloom, 2007; LoBue,
itionist theory that builds on the social in- Chiong, Nishida, DeLoache, & Haidt, 2011;
tuitionist model (SIM; Haidt, 2001). Like see also the chapters in Section IX, this vol-
other types of evaluations, moral judgments ume), and that it is related to the evolution-
happen quickly, often in less than one sec- ary process that Trivers (1971) described in
ond of seeing an action or learning the facts his famous article on reciprocal altruism.
of a case (Haidt, 2001; Zajonc, 1980). These People monitor the behavior and reputations
judgments are associative, automatic, rela-
of others; those linked to cheating become
tively effortless, and rapid, and they rely on
less attractive as partners for future interac-
heuristic processing; they occur by processes
tions.
that many researchers call “System 1” think-
ing (Bruner, 1960; Kahneman, 2011; Sta- c. Loyalty/betrayal. There are finite
novich & West, 2000). The SIM describes resources, and coalitions compete for these
 Moral Foundations Theory 213

resources. The coalitions that are most co- Although most research has focused on
hesive tend to prevail over less cohesive rival these five moral foundations, there likely
coalitions, as Darwin noted in The Descent are many other moral foundations; example
of Man (1871) while wrestling with the candidate foundations under investigation
question of the origins of morality. The in- are liberty/oppression (Haidt, 2012; Iyer,
tuitions generated by this foundation gen- Koleva, Graham, Ditto, & Haidt, 2012), eq-
eralize to brand loyalty, political partisan- uity/undeservingness (Meindl, Iyer, & Gra-
ship, and sports fandom today. When people ham, 2017), and honesty/lying (Graham,
show signs of being disloyal, they are labeled Meindl, Koleva, Iyer, & Johnson, 2015;
as traitors and may be ostracized from their Hofmann, Wisneski, Brandt, & Skitka,
groups or even put to death (e.g., treason is 2014; Iyer, 2010).
an offense punishable by death in the United
States). When people are loyal group mem-
bers, they are extolled as virtuous (e.g., as Historical Context
patriots).
MFT arose from three streams of research:
d. Authority/subversion. Primates
the cultural anthropology of morality, evo-
evolved for life in hierarchies. Nonhuman
lutionary psychology, and the “automaticity
alpha males are generally more like bullies
revolution” within social psychology. Below
than like leaders. Human alphas can go ei-
we highlight some key findings in each area
ther way, but there can be little doubt that
that contributed to the development of MFT.
the psychology of authority is essential for
Until recently, most prominent theories in
understanding human political behavior
moral psychology conceived of the moral do-
(Boehm, 1999; De Waal, 1996). Groups and
main as a set of norms and regulations about
companies that have clear lines of authority,
how individuals should treat other individu-
in which the authority is respected and seen
als; theorists generally focused on concepts
as legitimate, generally function better than
of harm, rights, and justice (e.g., Kohlberg,
leaderless or normless groups or groups with
1969; Turiel, 1983), or care and compassion
autocratic and domineering leadership (Pfef-
(Gilligan, 1982; Hoffman, 1982). However,
fer, 1998; Sherif, 1961). People who do not
Shweder (2008; Shweder, Much, Mahapa-
respect authorities or traditions are often os-
tra, & Park, 1997) proposed that this con-
tracized or punished for insubordination.
ception of morality reflected the distinctly
e. Purity/degradation.1 Pathogens individualistic conception of the self held
and parasites threaten survival, and or- widely in secular Western contexts. Based
ganisms that avoid contact with these con- on his fieldwork in India, Shweder proposed
taminants are more likely to survive than that moral psychology had failed to address
their counterparts. The adaptive pressure much of the moral domain that would re-
to make accurate judgments about disease sult from a more global survey of societies.
risk is especially strong for a group-living People in all cultures may have moral and
species whose diet includes scavenging, as regulatory concepts related to harm, rights,
seems to have been the case for early hu- and justice (which he called the “ethic of
mans. The uniquely human emotion of dis- autonomy”), but in many cultures one can
gust seems well tuned as a “guardian of the also find a concept of self as an office holder
mouth” for a highly social and omnivorous in a social system, related to a set of moral
species (Rozin, Haidt, & McCauley, 2008) and regulatory concepts such as loyalty and
Research on the “behavioral immune sys- duty (which he called the “ethic of com-
tem” (Schaller & Park, 2011) shows that munity”). One can also find conceptions of
contamination concerns can be generalized the self as a vessel for, or bearer of, a divine
to social practices, including being fearful soul or spark, with moral and regulatory no-
of dissimilar others (e.g., immigrants) and tions that preserve one’s purity and sanctity
a rejection of people who do not live in ac- (which he called the “ethic of divinity”).
cordance with the group’s sacred practices Shweder’s pluralistic conception of the
(e.g., LGBTQIA individuals in the eyes of moral domain mapped well onto the mul-
many Christians). tiple findings and theories coming out of
214 M O R A L I T Y A N D C U LT U R E

work on the evolution of moral behavior. each other. Moral Foundations Theory was
Evolutionary psychologists have long held created to go beyond the SIM: Granting that
that innate mental structures, shaped over “intuitions come first,” what exactly are
evolutionary time, predispose humans to these intuitions, where do they come from,
certain behaviors, emotional reactions, and how do they develop, and why does morality
forms of learning. Bowlby’s (1969) attach- vary across cultures?
ment theory was an explicitly evolutionary In an effort to determine the best candi-
theory that rejected the unconstrained learn- dates for the foundations of moral thinking,
ing theories of Freudians and behaviorists. Haidt and Joseph (2004) surveyed anthro-
Trivers’s (1971) classic paper on reciprocal pological and evolutionary approaches to
altruism explained how a set of moral–emo- moral judgment. They searched for the con-
tional responses to cheaters and coopera- cerns, perceptions, and emotional responses
tors could have evolved as the psychological that occur in the accounts of multiple an-
foundations of judgments of fairness. But thropologists (e.g., reciprocity as described
how many of these evolved mechanisms are by Malinowski, 1922/2002) and that also fit
there, and which ones are the most impor- into existing evolutionary frameworks (e.g.,
tant ones for understanding human moral- Trivers’s reciprocal altruism).
ity? Haidt and Joseph (2004) drew from
To begin answering those questions, one Shweder’s theory of moral discourse, Fiske’s
must consider how moral judgments occur (1991) models of interpersonal relationships,
at the cognitive level. It has long been es- Schwartz and Bilsky’s (1990) theory of val-
tablished that there exist two general forms ues, and evolutionary models such as De
of cognition, often called System 1 (fast, ef- Waal’s (1996) “building blocks” of morality
fortless, and intuition-based) and System 2 in other primates. They identified five best
(slower, more effortful, involving conscious candidates—five clear and direct bridges be-
deliberate reasoning; see Bruner & Austin, tween the anthropological and evolutionary
1986; Metcalfe & Mischel, 1999; see review literatures. These five became the original
in Kahneman, 2011). Whereas Kohlberg’s five foundations of MFT, although, as we
(1969) moral psychology focused on Sys- have said, we believe there are others. (For
tem 2 processes, the “automaticity revolu- a review of the history of MFT and the evo-
tion” of the 1990s shifted the focus of the lutionary basis of each foundation, see Gra-
field toward System 1. Bargh and Chartrand ham et al., 2013, and Haidt, 2012, Chapters
(1999), noting the remarkable accuracy of 6–8).
social judgments based on “thin slices” of
behavior (Ambady & Rosenthal, 1992),
questioned whether conscious thinking gen- Theoretical Stance
erally precedes judgments or merely follows
afterward. They wrote: “So it may be, espe- MFT has been critiqued from the standpoint
cially for evaluations and judgments of novel of multiple other theories in moral psychol-
people and objects, that what we think we ogy. Some of these critiques have focused
are doing while consciously deliberating in on MFT’s central claim of nativism (e.g.,
actuality has no effect on the outcome of Suhler & Churchland, 2011). Others have
the judgment, as it has already been made critiqued our embrace of intuitionism (e.g.,
through relatively immediate, automatic Narvaez, 2008). But in the last few years,
means” (Bargh & Chartrand, 1999, p. 475). most critiques have centered on MFT’s tenet
Drawing on this work, Haidt (2001) for- of moral pluralism, with critics proposing
mulated the SIM, which proposed that moral alternative forms of pluralism or decompos-
evaluations generally occur rapidly and de- ing specific foundations. For instance, the
rive from System 1 intuitive processing. Sys- model of moral motives (Janoff-Bulman &
tem 2 plays many roles in moral judgment, Carnes, 2013, and Chapter 23, this volume)
but by its very nature it tends to engage only proposes that—in addition to the five moral
after an initial System 1 evaluation is made, foundations—there also exist group-focused
and it tends to be employed as people engage social justice concerns not covered by care
in (or prepare to engage in) discussion with and fairness. And relationship regulation
 Moral Foundations Theory 215

theory (Rai & Fiske, 2011; Rai, Chapter 24, best candidate. Evidence has been shown for
this volume) argues that you need to exam- the centrality, ubiquity, and prototypicality
ine the social relations in a given context in of harm in (negative) moral judgments (Gray
order to understand the dominant moral mo- et al., 2014; Schein & Gray, 2015a), and this
tivations at play (unity, hierarchy, equality, is quite compatible with MFT (especially in
or proportionality). Others have argued that WEIRD societies; see Haidt et al., 1993).
individual moral foundations as proposed However, no evidence has been found for
by MFT can be multidimensional, with fair- DMT’s more novel claim that all moral judg-
ness being perceived as equality or equity ments work essentially the same at a cogni-
(Meindl et al., 2017) or purity containing tive level and that all morality boils down to
multiple components (Pizarro, 2016). These harm perception (for more on the gulf be-
critiques and resulting debates have been tween DMT’s claims and the evidence, see
fruitful in refining and reconciling different Haidt, Graham, & Ditto, 2015).
pluralist approaches to morality (see also In addition, Gray and colleagues contrast
Graham et al., 2013, Section 4.3). this shape-shifting version of their own
Perhaps the most active debate these days, theory with a straw-man version of MFT
however, is not between different forms of as a theory of five Fodorian modules that
moral pluralism but between moral plural- are completely separate, nonoverlapping,
ism and moral monism. By moral monism domain-specific, and fully encapsulated pro-
we mean theories stating that all morality cessing systems (see also Valdesolo, Chapter
can be boiled down to one thing, whether 10, this volume). But, in fact, MFT employs
that one thing be reasoning about justice the more flexible and overlapping notion of
(Kohlberg, 1969), intuitive moral grammar modularity developed by anthropologists
(Mikhail, 2007), mutualistic fairness intu- Sperber and Hirschfeld (2004). As explained
itions (Baumard, André, & Sperber, 2013), in the main statement on MFT’s modular-
or perceptions of harm within a dyad (Gray, ity, the foundations are developmental con-
Schein, & Ward, 2014). MFT was created structs—they refer to what is innately given
to capture the richness of moral diversity as part of the “first draft” of the evolved
and move moral psychology beyond monist human mind, which then gets elaborated in
moral accounts. Yet the pluralistic nature of culturally specific ways:
morality remains a topic of scientific debate.
For instance, Gray and colleagues (Gray & Each of these five [sets of concerns] is a good
Keeney, 2015; Schein & Gray, 2015a, 2015b, candidate for a Sperber-style learning module.
Chapter 37, this volume) have proposed dy- However, readers who do not like modularity
adic morality theory (DMT), arguing that theories can think of each one as an evolu-
tionary preparedness (Seligman, 1971) to link
the seeming plurality in moral attitudes and
certain patterns of social appraisal to specific
beliefs can be fully explained by perceptions emotional and motivational reactions. All we
of harm. All moral judgments, in this view, insist upon is that the moral mind is partially
are produced by a single process of link- structured in advance of experience so that
ing stimuli to the cognitive template of an five (or more) classes of social concerns are
intentional agent causing harm to a vulner- likely to become moralized during develop-
able patient: “a dyadic template suggests not ment (Haidt & Joseph, 2007, p. 381).
only that perceived suffering is tied to im-
morality, but that all morality is understood Dyadic morality proponents have recently
through the lens of harm” (Gray, Young, & sacrificed much of their parsimony by offer-
Waytz, 2012, p. 108). They apply this frame- ing “harm pluralism” (see Schein & Gray,
work to political psychology, asserting that Chapter 37, this volume). The theory was
“moral disagreements can be understood extremely parsimonious in its original form,
with one simple question: ‘what do liberals wherein all morality boils down to a specific
and conservatives see as harmful?’ ” (Schein harm: “harm involves the perception of two
& Gray, 2015b). We agree that if you had to interacting minds, one mind (an agent) inten-
pick one foundation as the most important tionally causing suffering to another mind (a
single one, in terms of both importance and patient)” (Schein & Gray, 2015a). But now,
prototypicality, Care/harm is probably the with “harm pluralism,” it is unclear whether
216 M O R A L I T Y A N D C U LT U R E

a single template-matching process is still psychologists, then MFT would need to be


being argued for or whether multiple dif- abandoned, too” (Graham et al., 2013).
ferent cognitive templates of harm (physi- Here we examine evidence for one of the
cal–emotional harm, cheating harm, group most contentious of these claims: plural-
harm, disrespect harm, soul harm, etc.) ism. How do we know there are really mul-
are proposed. When harm is stretched and tiple moral foundations and that they don’t
diluted so much that it means any kind of all boil down to one thing, such as justice
moral badness, then DMT becomes little (Kohlberg, 1969) or perceptions of dyadic
more than the claim that moral judgments harm (Gray et al., 2014)? Studies showing
are intrinsically about dyads without pro- differences between harm and impurity
viding any framework for understanding judgments have been critiqued recently by
plurality in moral judgments (e.g., if group the monist argument that impurity is just a
harm, disrespect harm, and soul harm are weird and less severe form of harm and that
the harms that liberals and conservatives impurity is no more than “(perceived) harm
perceive differentially, then how does DMT involving sex” (Gray & Keeney, 2015; see
help explain why they do so?). Is DMT of- also Graham, 2015, on the absence of any
fering a semi-blank-slate theory in which the evidence that harm/impurity differences are
dyadic template is innate, but all knowledge solely attributable to weirdness and severi-
of kinds of harm is learned, and anything ty). So as a test case we examine the evidence
could be taught to kids to be harmful? Or for pluralist conceptions of (im)purity con-
is DMT saying (as MFT does) that there is cerns, contra monist approaches that would
something about evolved bodily processes see them as essentially reducible to harm
that seems to attract moralization in surpris- (e.g., Gray et al., 2014).
ingly similar forms around the world? Does First, Purity/degradation judgments pre-
DMT say that the cultural similarities are a dict important thoughts and behaviors over
coincidence, or do they posit some form of and above Care/harm judgments. For in-
innate preparedness to learn about harm- stance, purity concerns uniquely predict (be-
fulness, cheating, betrayal, disrespect, and yond other foundations and demographics
degradation? If the latter, DMT has lost its such as political ideology) culture-war atti-
claim to parsimony, and it’s no longer clear tudes about gay marriage, euthanasia, abor-
what, if anything, the theory proposes that tion, and pornography (Koleva, Graham,
is really in contrast with MFT. Haidt, Iyer, & Ditto, 2012). Purity also pre-
Dyadic morality could be usefully inte- dicts opposition to stem cell research (Clif-
grated with MFT if one examines harm as ford & Jerit, 2013), environmental attitudes
more central than other foundations with- (Rottman, Kelemen, & Young, 2015), law-
out reducing these foundations to just less suits (Buccafusco & Fagundes, 2015), and
prototypical forms of harm. The empirical social distancing in real-world social net-
evidence in favor of this kind of moral plu- works (Dehghani et al., 2016). Moral con-
ralism is by now very extensive, whereas the cerns about impurity uniquely predict moral
evidence in support of monism is limited and judgments of suicide, far more than do judg-
contested (Graham, 2015; Haidt, Graham, ments about harm (Rottman, Kelemen, &
& Ditto, 2015). We summarize these two Young, 2014a, 2014b). In line with multiple
bodies of evidence in the next section. demonstrations of basic discriminant valid-
ity between the foundations (Graham et al.,
2011), several recent studies showed that
Evidence for MFT’s Pluralism purity judgments are a stronger predictor
over Moral Monism of disgust sensitivity than are judgments re-
lated to any other foundation (Wagemans,
MFT rests on four falsifiable claims about Brandt, & Zeelenberg, 2017). Finally, even
human morality: nativism, cultural learn- responses to sacrificial dilemmas (which
ing, intuitionism, and pluralism. As we require harming one person to avoid harm-
noted previously, “if any of these claims ing several others) are predicted by multiple
is disproved, or is generally abandoned by foundations, not just care/harm:
 Moral Foundations Theory 217

Inconsistent with Moral Dyad Theory, our re- judgments have been proposed, involving
sults did not support the prediction that Harm both feelings and normative information in
concerns would be the unequivocally most concert (Rottman & Kelemen, 2012). Impu-
important predictor of sacrifice endorsement. rity and harm judgments respond in opposite
Consistent with Moral Foundations Theory,
ways to experimental manipulations of ab-
however, multiple moral values are predictive
of sacrifice judgments: Harm and Purity nega- stract–concrete mindsets (Napier & Luguri,
tively predict, and Ingroup positively predicts, 2013) and approach–avoidance motivations
endorsement of harmful action in service of (Cornwell & Higgins, 2013); further, prim-
saving lives, with Harm and Purity explaining ing parental status increases severity of pu-
similar amounts of unique variance. The pres- rity judgments, but not harm judgments
ent study demonstrates the utility of pluralistic (Eibach, Libby, & Ehrlinger, 2009). Purity
accounts of morality, even in moral situations concerns have been shown to function to
in which harm is central. (Crone & Laham, protect the self, while harm concerns func-
2015) tion to protect others (Chakroff, Dungan, &
Young, 2013). A study of the “symbolic pu-
Second, impurity judgments can actively rity of mind” concluded that religious people
do things that harm judgments cannot. felt intuitive disgust at their own heretical
Framing environmental issues in terms of thoughts, a disgust that was “meaningfully
purity (vs. harm) experimentally increased distinct from anger as a moral emotion”
moderate and conservative support for en- (Ritter, Preston, Salomon, & Relihan-John-
vironmental initiatives up to liberal levels son, 2015). Intention has been shown to mat-
(Feinberg & Willer, 2013). Purity framing ter less for impurity than for harm judgments
also reduced polarization on the Affordable (Young & Saxe, 2011), and this is supported
Care Act (Feinberg & Willer, 2015) and in- by the finding that accidental versus inten-
creased conservatives’ liberal attitudes more tional harms produce differential activation
generally (Day, Fiske, Downing, & Trail, in the right temperoparietal junction, while
2014). Group-based discrimination in moral accidental versus intentional purity viola-
judgment has been shown to be specific to tions show no such distinction (Chakroff et
the domain of moral purity: Purity informa- al., 2015). Compared to harm judgments,
tion can experimentally increase both praise impurity judgments involve less condemna-
and condemnation of others (Masicampo, tion of the act itself but more condemnation
Barth, & Ambady, 2014). Similarly, expo- of the actor (Uhlmann & Zhu, 2013); this
sure to purity similarity information can “harmful situations, impure people” attribu-
experimentally reduce social distancing, tion asymmetry for purity versus harm judg-
more so than similarity information related ments has also been found while control-
to any other moral concerns (Dehghani et ling for severity and weirdness (Chakroff &
al., 2016). And studies of the processes of Young, 2015).
moralization through “moral shock” (e.g., Even in their attempt to explain away all
increasing moral convictions about abortion these harm/impurity differences as merely
following graphic pictures of aborted fetus- attributable to weirdness and severity, Gray
es) showed that such moralization is medi- and Keeney (2015) were forced to conclude:
ated by disgust and not by anger or harm “as in Study 2, this suggests that severity
appraisals, disconfirming dyadic morality and weirdness likely do not account for all
on its own terms (Wisneski & Skitka, 2016). differences between harm and impurity sce-
Third, there is growing evidence that narios.” Although more evidence exists for
moral judgments about harm versus impurity some foundation distinctions than others—
operate in different ways at a cognitive level. for example, not much work has been done
These different kinds of judgments have been differentiating loyalty from authority judg-
associated with different facial micro-expres- ments—the evidence on care vs. purity (and
sions (Cannon, Schnall, & White, 2011) and on individualizing vs. binding foundations
neural systems (Parkinson et al., 2011; Was- more generally) clearly supports some form
serman, Chakroff, Saxe, & Young, 2017). of moral pluralism and calls into question
Unique developmental pathways for purity monist theories of moral judgment.
218 M O R A L I T Y A N D C U LT U R E

Extension and Expansion failed to see about conservative morality:


Conservatives care far more about moral is-
The ongoing debates and plurality of ap- sues related to loyalty (e.g., patriotism and
proaches in this Atlas volume demonstrate nationalism), authority (e.g., law and order,
that this is the golden age of the science of respect for parents and the police), and pu-
morality (see also Graham & Valdesolo, in rity (e.g., religious and traditional restric-
press). In its first decade, MFT has substan- tions on sexuality and drug use; perceptions
tially expanded the range of moral concerns of moral decay more generally).
under investigation in moral psychology by America and Europe are now being con-
encouraging researchers to look beyond in- vulsed by political movements whose moral-
dividual harm and fairness. In the next de- ity is quite explicitly based on the loyalty,
cade, we expect that MFT will continue to authority, and purity foundations. These
develop, both theoretically and methodolog- movements embrace the label national-
ically. Following the idea of method-theory ism; some of them even embrace a “blood
codevelopment (Graham et al., 2013), new and soil” version of nationalism that is
constructs (e.g., liberty/oppression concerns) often linked to theories of racial supremacy
are explored as new methods and measures (Graham & Haidt, 2012). In every Western
are developed, such as the recently validated country with a populist rebellion, people are
moral foundations vignettes (Clifford et al., angry at the “globalist” or “cosmopolitan”
2015) and current efforts to update and im- elite and its morality, which seems (to the
prove the Moral Foundations Questionnaire nationalists) to be based primarily on the
(Graham et al., 2011). MFT is also likely to care foundation.
be applied to increasingly more fields outside The year 2016 will long be remembered
of psychology, such as information technol- as the year that the educated elite in many
ogy (Dehghani, Sagae, Sachdeva, & Gratch, Western countries realized that they do not
2014), law (Silver & Silver, 2017), sociology understand the morality of many of their
(Vaisey & Miles, 2014), organizational be- fellow citizens. MFT offers them a way to
havior (Fehr, Yam, & Dang, 2015), sustain- do so; monist theories do not. MFT has of-
ability science (Watkins, Aitken, & Mather, fended intellectuals on the left, who claim
2016), ethics education (Andersen, Zuber, that it legitimizes right-wing moralities by
& Hill, 2015), media studies (Tamborini, dignifying them as real human moralities,
2011), and agricultural ethics (Mäkiniemi, rather than condemning them as patholo-
Pirttilä-Backman, & Pieri, 2014). gies or self-soothing mechanisms. But MFT
Finally, we expect that MFT will con- is not a normative theory of the moral con-
tinue to be useful for understanding po- cerns people should have; it is a descriptive
litical differences and debates. Richard theory of the moral concerns people do have
Shweder and other anthropologists have (Graham, 2014). The simple fact is that
long been arguing that the moral domain every human community, from street gangs
is far broader than what was being studied to corporations to academic fields such as
by researchers coming from a secular West- social psychology, develops a moral order,
ern perspective—what we would now call a moral “matrix,” within which their moral
a WEIRD perspective (Henrich, Heine, & lives take place and their political views are
Norenzayan, 2010). MFT was created to formed.
further develop this insight by offering a Moral psychology is hard because—like
list of specific foundations. MFT was not anthropology—it requires researchers to
created to study political differences, but it step outside their matrix and study other
was immediately put to that use as political matrices without bias. In the process, they
polarization continued to rise in the United often learn a great deal about their home
States and left and right came to seem in- culture. The coming years would be a very
creasingly like separate cultures (Haidt & good time for social scientists to commit
Graham, 2007). MFT has often been used themselves to understanding moralities that
as the basis for advice given to left-leaning are not their own and that they may even
parties to help them see what they often find personally offensive. MFT can help.
 Moral Foundations Theory 219

NOTE Clifford, S., Iyengar, V., Cabeza, R., & Sinnott-


Armstrong, W. (2015). Moral foundations
1. In Graham et al. (2013) we used the label vignettes: A standardized stimulus database
sanctity/degradation for this foundation; here of scenarios based on moral foundations the-
we revert to the more widely used purity/deg- ory.  Behavior Research Methods, 47, 1178–
radation. 1198.
Clifford, S., & Jerit, J. (2013). How words do the
work of politics: Moral foundations theory
REFERENCES and the debate over stem cell research. Journal
of Politics, 75(3), 659–671.
Ambady, N., & Rosenthal, R. (1992). Thin slices Cornwell, J. F., & Higgins, E. T. (2013). Moral-
of expressive behavior as predictors of inter- ity and its relation to political ideology: The
personal consequences: A meta-analysis. Psy- role of promotion and prevention concerns.
chological Bulletin, 111, 256–274. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin,
Andersen, M. L., Zuber, J. M., & Hill, B. D. 39, 1164–1172.
(2015). Moral foundations theory: An explor- Crone, D. L., & Laham, S. M. (2015). Multiple
atory study with accounting and other busi- moral foundations predict responses to sacri-
ness students. Journal of Business Ethics, 132, ficial dilemmas. Personality and Individual
525–538. Differences, 85, 60–65.
Bargh, J. A., & Chartrand, T. L. (1999). The Darwin, C. (1871). The descent of man (2 vols.).
unbearable automaticity of being. American London, 81, 130–131.
Psychologist, 54, 462–479. Day, M. V., Fiske, S. T., Downing, E. L., & Trail,
Baumard, N., André, J. B., & Sperber, D. (2013). T. E. (2014). Shifting liberal and conserva-
A mutualistic approach to morality: The evo- tive attitudes using moral foundations theory.
lution of fairness by partner choice. Behavior- Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin,
al and Brain Sciences, 36(1), 59–78. 40(12), 1559–1573.
Boehm, C. (1999). Hierarchy in the forest: The De Waal, F. B. M. (1996). Good natured: The or-
evolution of egalitarian behavior. Cambridge, igins of right and wrong in humans and other
MA: Harvard University Press. animals. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Bowlby, J. (1969). Attachment and loss: Vol. 1. Press.
Attachment. New York: Basic Books. Dehghani, M., Johnson, K. M., Hoover, J., Sagi,
Bruner, J. S. (1960). The process of education. E., Garten, J., Parmar, N. J., . . . Graham, J.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. (2016). Purity homophily in social networks.
Bruner, J. S., & Austin, G. A. (1986). A study of Journal of Experimental Psychology: Gen-
thinking. Piscataway, NJ: Transaction. eral, 145(3), 366–375.
Buccafusco, C. J., & Fagundes, D. (2015). The Dehghani, M., Sagae, K., Sachdeva, S., & Gratch,
moral psychology of copyright infringement. J. (2014). Analyzing political rhetoric in con-
Minnesota Law Review, 100. Available at servative and liberal weblogs related to the
http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/cf_ dev/AbsBy- construction of the “Ground Zero Mosque.”
Auth.cfm?per_id =429612. Journal of Information Technology and Poli-
Cannon, P. R., Schnall, S., & White, M. (2011). tics, 11, 1–14.
Transgressions and expressions: Affective fa- Eibach, R. P., Libby, L. K., & Ehrlinger, J.
cial muscle activity predicts moral judgments. (2009). Priming family values: How being a
Social Psychological and Personality Science, parent affects moral evaluations of harmless
2(3), 325–331. but offensive acts. Journal of Experimental
Chakroff, A., Dungan, J., Koster-Hale, J., Social Psychology, 45(5), 1160–1163.
Brown, A., Saxe, R., & Young, L. (2015). Fehr, R., Yam, K. C. S., & Dang, C. (2015). Mor-
When minds matter for moral judgment: In- alized leadership: The construction and con-
tent information is neurally encoded for harm- sequences of ethical leader perceptions. Acad-
ful but not impure acts. Social Cognitive and emy of Management Review, 40, 182–209.
Affective Neuroscience, 11, 476–184. Feinberg, M., & Willer, R. (2013). The moral
Chakroff, A., Dungan, J., & Young, L. (2013). roots of environmental attitudes. Psychologi-
Harming ourselves and defiling others: What cal Science, 24(1), 56–62.
determines a moral domain? PLOS ONE, Feinberg, M., & Willer, R. (2015). From gulf to
8(9), e74434. bridge: When Do moral arguments facilitate
Chakroff, A., & Young, L. (2015). Harmful situa- political influence? Personality and Social
tions, impure people: An attribution asymmetry Psychology Bulletin, 41(12), 1665–1681.
across moral domains. Cognition, 136, 30–37. Fiske, A. P. (1991). Structures of social life: The
220 M O R A L I T Y A N D C U LT U R E

four elementary forms of human relations. people are divided by politics and religion.
New York: Free Press. New York: Pantheon.
Gilligan, C. (1982). In a different voice: Psy- Haidt, J., & Graham, J. (2007). When morality
chological theory and women’s development. opposes justice: Conservatives have moral in-
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. tuitions that liberals may not recognize. Social
Graham, J. (2014). Descriptive vs. normative psy- Justice Research, 20, 98–116.
chology. Retrieved March 1, 2017, from www. Haidt, J., Graham, J., & Ditto, P. H. (2015). Dy-
yourmorals.org/blog/2014/12/descriptive-vs- adic morality is the Volkswagen of moral psy-
normative-moral-psychology. chology. Retrieved March 1, 2017, from www.
Graham, J. (2015). Explaining away differences spsp.org/blog/volkswagen-of-morality.
in moral judgment: Comment on Gray and Haidt, J., & Joseph, C. (2004). Intuitive ethics:
Keeney. Social Psychological and Personality How innately prepared intuitions generate
Science, 6, 869–873. culturally variable virtues. Daedalus, 133,
Graham, J., & Haidt, J. (2012). Sacred values 55–66.
and evil adversaries: A moral foundations ap- Haidt, J., & Joseph, C. (2007). The moral mind:
proach. In P. Shaver & M. Mikulincer (Eds.), How five sets of innate intuitions guide the
The social psychology of morality: Exploring development of many culture-specific vir-
the causes of good and evil (pp. 11–31). New tues, and perhaps even modules. The Innate
York: APA Books. Mind, 3, 367–391.
Graham, J., Haidt, J., Koleva, S., Motyl, M., Iyer, Haidt, J., Koller, S., & Dias, M. (1993). Affect,
R., Wojcik, S. P., & Ditto, P. H. (2013). Moral culture, and morality, or is it wrong to eat
foundations theory: The pragmatic validity of your dog? Journal of Personality and Social
moral pluralism. Advances in Experimental Psychology, 65, 613–628.
Social Psychology, 47, 55–130. Hamlin, K., Wynn, K., & Bloom, P. (2007). So-
Graham, J., Haidt, J., & Nosek, B. A. (2009). cial evaluation by preverbal infants. Nature,
Liberals and conservatives rely on different 450, 557–559.
sets of moral foundations. Journal of Person- Henrich, J., Heine, S. J., & Norenzayan, A.
ality and Social Psychology, 96, 1029–1046. (2010). The weirdest people in the world? Be-
Graham, J., Meindl, P., Koleva, S., Iyer, R., & havioral and Brain Sciences, 33, 61–83.
Johnson, K. M. (2015). When values and be- Hoffman, M. L. (1982). Development of pro-
havior conflict: Moral pluralism and intraper- social motivation: Empathy and guilt. In N.
sonal moral hypocrisy. Social and Personality Eisenberg (Ed.), The development of prosocial
Psychology Compass, 9, 158–170. behavior (pp. 218–231). New York: Academic
Graham, J., Nosek, B. A., Haidt, J., Iyer, R., Kol- Press.
eva, S., & Ditto, P. H. (2011). Mapping the Hofmann, W., Wisneski, D. C., Brandt, M. J., &
moral domain. Journal of Personality and So- Skitka, L. J. (2014). Morality in everyday life.
cial Psychology, 101, 366–385. Science, 345(6202), 1340–1343.
Graham, J., & Valdesolo, P. (in press). Morality. Iyer, R. (2010). The case for honesty as a moral
In K. Deaux & M. Snyder (Eds.), The Oxford foundation. Retrieved June 26, 2012, from
handbook of personality and social psychol- www.polipsych.com/2010/12/07/the-case-
ogy. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. for-honesty-as-a-moral-foundation.
Gray, K., & Keeney, J. (2015). Impure, or just Iyer, R., Koleva, S. P., Graham, J., Ditto, P. H.,
weird?: Scenario sampling bias raises ques- & Haidt, J. (2012). Understanding Libertarian
tions about the foundation of morality. Social morality: The psychological roots of an indi-
Psychology and Personality Science, 6, 859– vidualist ideology. PLOS ONE, 7(8), e42366.
868. Janoff-Bulman, R., & Carnes, N. C. (2013). Sur-
Gray, K., Schein, C., & Ward, A. F. (2014). The veying the moral landscape: Moral motives
myth of harmless wrongs in moral cognition: and group-based moralities. Personality and
Automatic dyadic completion from sin to suf- Social Psychology Review, 17(3), 219–236.
fering. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking, fast and slow.
General, 143(4), 1600–1615. New York: Farrar, Strauss, & Giroux.
Gray, K., Young, L., & Waytz, A. (2012) Mind Kohlberg, L. (1969). Stage and sequence: The
perception is the essence of morality. Psycho- cognitive-developmental approach to social-
logical Inquiry, 23, 101–124. ization. In D. A. Goslin (Ed.), Handbook of
Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional dog and its ra- socialization theory and research (pp. 347–
tional tail: A social intuitionist approach to 480). Chicago: Rand McNally.
moral judgment. Psychological Review, 108, Koleva, S., Graham, J., Haidt, J., Iyer, R., &
814–834. Ditto, P. H. (2012). Tracing the threads: How
Haidt, J. (2012). The righteous mind: Why good five moral concerns (especially purity) help
 Moral Foundations Theory 221

explain culture war attitudes. Journal of Re- Pfeffer, J. (1998). The human equation: Build-
search in Personality, 46, 184–194. ing profits by putting people first. Cambridge,
LoBue, V., Chiong, C., Nishida, T., DeLoache, J., MA: Harvard Business Press.
& Haidt, J. (2011). When getting something Pizarro, D. (2016). Disgust and the domain of
good is bad: Even 3-year-olds react to inequal- moral purity. Paper presented at the annual
ity. Social Development, 20(1), 154–170. convention of the Society for Personality and
Mäkiniemi, J. P., Pirttilä-Backman, A. M., & Social Psychology, San Diego, CA.
Pieri, M. (2013). The endorsement of the moral Rai, T. S., & Fiske, A. P. (2011). Moral psychol-
foundations in food-related moral thinking in ogy is relationship regulation: Moral motives
three European countries. Journal of Agricul- for unity, hierarchy, equality, and proportion-
tural and Environmental Ethics, 26, 771–786. ality. Psychological Review, 118, 57–75.
Malinowski, B. (1922/2002). Argonauts of the Richerson, P. J., & Boyd, R. (2005). Not by genes
Western Pacific: An account of native enter- alone: How culture transformed human evo-
prise and adventure in the archipelagoes of lution. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Melanesian New Guinea. New York: Rout- Ritter, R. S., Preston, J. L., Salomon, E., & Re-
ledge. lihan-Johnson, D. (2015). Imagine no religion:
Marcus, G. (2004). The birth of the mind. New Heretical disgust, anger and the symbolic
York: Basic Books. purity of mind. Cognition and Emotion, 30,
Masicampo, E. J., Barth, M., & Ambady, N. 778–796.
(2014). Group-based discrimination in judg- Rottman, J., & Kelemen, D. (2012). Aliens be-
ments of moral purity-related behaviors: Ex- having badly: Children’s acquisition of novel
perimental and archival evidence. Journal of purity-based morals. Cognition, 124, 356–
Experimental Psychology: General, 143(6), 360.
2135–2152. Rottman, J., Kelemen, D., & Young, L. (2014a).
Meindl, P., Iyer, R., & Graham, J. (2017). A plea- Tainting the soul: Purity concerns predict
sure/power principle of justice: Distributive moral judgments of suicide. Cognition, 130,
justice beliefs are guided by societal concerns 217–226.
for pleasure and power. Manuscript submitted Rottman, J., Kelemen, D., & Young, L. (2014b).
for publication. Purity matters more than harm in moral judg-
Metcalfe, J., & Mischel, W. (1999). A hot/cool- ments of suicide: Response to Gray (2014).
system analysis of delay of gratification: Dy- Cognition, 133(1), 332–334.
namics of willpower. Psychological Review, Rottman, J., Kelemen, D., & Young, L. (2015).
106(1), 3. Hindering harm and preserving purity: How
Mikhail, J. (2007). Universal moral grammar: can moral psychology save the planet? Philos-
Theory, evidence and the future. Trends in ophy Compass, 10(2), 134–144.
Cognitive Sciences, 11(4), 143–152. Rozin, P., Haidt, J., & McCauley, C. R. (2008).
Mineka, S., & Cook, M. (1988). Social learning Disgust. In M. Lewis, J. M. Haviland-Jones &
and the acquisition of snake fear in monkeys. L. F. Barrett (Eds.), Handbook of emotions
In T. R. Zentall & J. B. G. Galef (Eds.), Social (3rd ed., pp. 757–776). New York: Guilford
learning: Psychological and biological per- Press.
spectives (pp. 51–74). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Schaller, M., & Park, J. H. (2011). The behav-
Napier, J. L., & Luguri, J. B. (2013). Moral ioral immune system (and why it matters).
mind-sets: Abstract thinking increases a pref- Current Directions in Psychological Science,
erence for “individualizing” over “binding” 20, 99–103.
moral foundations. Social Psychological and Schein, C., & Gray, K. (2015a). The unifying
Personality Science, 4, 754–759. moral dyad: Liberals and conservatives share
Narvaez, D. (2008). The social-intuitionist the same harm-based moral template. Person-
model: Some counter-intuitions. In W. A. Sin- ality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 41(8),
nott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral psychology: Vol. 1147–1163.
2. The cognitive science of morality: Intuition Schein, C., & Gray, K. (2015b). Making sense of
and diversity (pp. 233–240). Cambridge, MA: moral disagreement: Liberals, conservatives,
MIT Press. and the harm-based template they share. Re-
Parkinson, C., Sinnott-Armstrong, W., Koralus, trieved March 1, 2017, from www.spsp.org/
P. E., Mendelovici, A., McGeer, V., & Wheat- blog/making-sense-of-moral.
ley, T. (2011). Is morality unified?: Evidence Schwartz, S. H., & Bilsky, W. (1990). Toward a
that distinct neural systems underlie moral theory of the universal content and structure
judgments of harm, dishonesty, and disgust. of values: Extensions and cross-cultural rep-
Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 23(10), lications. Journal of Personality and Social
3162–3180. Psychology, 58(5), 878–891.
222 M O R A L I T Y A N D C U LT U R E

Seligman, M. E. (1971). Phobias and prepared- tents (pp. 305–337). New York: Oxford Uni-
ness. Behavior Therapy, 2(3), 307–320. versity Press.
Sherif, M., Harvey, O. J., White, B. J., Hood, W., Trivers, R. L. (1971). The evolution of reciprocal
& Sherif, C. (1961/1954). Intergroup conflict altruism. Quarterly Review of Biology, 46,
and cooperation: The Robbers Cave experi- 35– 57.
ment. Norman: University of Oklahoma Insti- Turiel, E. (1983). The development of social
tute of Group Relations. knowledge: Morality and convention. Cam-
Shweder, R. A. (2008). The cultural psychology bridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
of suffering: The many meanings of health Uhlmann, E. L., & Zhu, L. (2013). Acts, per-
in Orissa, India (and elsewhere). Ethos, 36, sons, and intuitions: Person-centered cues and
60–77. gut reactions to harmless transgressions. So-
Shweder, R., Much, N., Mahapatra, M., & cial Psychological and Personality Science, 5,
Park, L. (1997). The “big three” of morality 279–285.
(autonomy, community, divinity) and the “big Vaisey, S., & Miles, A. (2014). Tools from moral
three” explanations of suffering. Morality and psychology for measuring personal moral cul-
Health, 119, 119–169. ture. Theory and Society, 43, 311–332.
Silver, J. R., & Silver, E. (2017). Why are conser- Wagemans, F. M. A., Brandt, M. J., & Zeelen-
vatives more punitive than liberals?: A moral berg, M. (2017). Disgust sensitivity is primar-
foundations approach. Law and Human Be- ily associated with purity-based moral judg-
havior, 41(3), 258. ments. Retrieved from https://osf.io/preprints/
Sperber, D., & Hirschfeld, L. A. (2004). The psyarxiv/tvs2b.
cognitive foundations of cultural stability and Wasserman, E. A., Chakroff, A., Saxe, R., &
diversity.  Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 8(1), Young, L. (2017). Illuminating the conceptual
40–46. structure of the space of moral violations with
Stanovich, K. E., & West, R. F. (2000). Individu- searchlight representational similarity analy-
al difference in reasoning: Implications for the sis. NeuroImage, 159(1), 371–387.
rationality debate? Behavioral and Brain Sci- Watkins, L., Aitken, R., & Mather, D. (2016).
ences, 23, 645–726. Conscientious consumers: A relationship be-
Suhler, C. L., & Churchland, P. (2011). Can in- tween moral foundations, political orienta-
nate, modular “foundations” explain moral- tion and sustainable consumption. Journal of
ity?: Challenges for Haidt’s moral foundations Cleaner Production, 134, 137–146.
theory. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, Wisneski, D. C., & Skitka, L. J. (2016). Moral-
23(9), 2103–2116. ization through moral shock: Exploring emo-
Tamborini, R. (2011). Moral intuition and media tional antecedents to moral conviction. Per-
entertainment. Journal of Media Psychology, sonality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 43,
23, 39–45. 139–150.
Tooby, J., Cosmides, L., & Barrett, H. C. (2005). Young, L., & Saxe, R. (2011). When ignorance
Resolving the debate on innate ideas: Learn- is no excuse: Different roles for intent across
ability constraints and the evolved interpen- moral domains. Cognition, 120, 202–214.
etration of motivational and conceptual func- Zajonc, R. B. (1980). Feeling and thinking: Pref-
tions. In P. Carruthers, S. Laurence, & S. Stich erences need no inferences. American Psychol-
(Eds.), The innate mind: Structure and con- ogist, 35, 151–175.
CHAPTER 23

The Model of Moral Motives


A Map of the Moral Domain

Ronnie Janoff‑Bulman
Nate C. Carnes

How does motivation underlie morality?

The two innate motivations of approach and avoidance interact with


three contexts—intrapersonal, interpersonal, and collective—to yield
six specific and culturally invariant motives.

Motivation is fundamental to morality, the individual, other person, or group;


which involves both an understanding of here the enemy is temptation—that is, act-
right and wrong—of what we should or ing on “bad” desires. In contrast, approach
should not do—and the activation or inhibi- processes, referred to as prescriptive in the
tion of these behaviors. The model of moral moral domain, serve to provide for the well-
motives (MMM; Janoff-Bulman & Carnes, being of the individual, other person, or
2013a, 2013b) has its roots in the most group. Here behaviors must be activated,
basic motivational processes recognized in and motivationally the enemy is apathy—
psychology: approach and avoidance. The that is, failing to act. From the broadest per-
MMM crosses approach and avoidance spective, proscriptive morality is about not
processes with distinct levels of analysis re- harming, and prescriptive morality is about
flecting the focus of one’s moral behavior: helping; these are not simply opposite sides
oneself (intrapersonal), another person (in- of the same coin, because not harming is not
terpersonal), or the group (collective). As the same as helping.
evident in Figure 23.1, this produces six cells Helping and not harming also manifest
with unique moral motives, each reflecting quite differently depending on the target
how to be moral in that context. of one’s behavior. Thus regarding intraper-
The rows of the MMM reflect the two sonal behavior, moderation is a proscriptive
basic motivational processes, which func- morality involving self-restraint, whereas
tionally have divergent outcomes. Avoidance industriousness is a prescriptive moral be-
processes, which we refer to as proscrip- havior involving behavioral activation. One
tive in the moral domain (Janoff-Bulman, might ask how behaviors involving solely the
Sheikh, & Hepp, 2009), serve to protect self could qualify as moral. Here it is impor-

223
224 M O R A L I T Y A N D C U LT U R E

Self Other Group


(Intrapersonal) (Interpersonal) (Collective)
Protect
(Proscriptive Moderation Not Harming Social Order
regulation)
Provide
(Prescriptive Industriousness Helping/Fairness Social Justice
regulation)

FIGURE 23.1.  The model of moral motives.

tant to note that all of morality is fundamen- is social justice. Social order serves to pro-
tally about facilitating social life so that we tect the group from both internal and exter-
can reap its benefits; that is, from a distal nal threats, whether these involve physical
perspective, it is functionally about mak- harm or psychological threats to group iden-
ing the ingroup better off. From a proximal tity. Social order involves a strong emphasis
perspective, moderation protects the indi- on conformity and loyalty in the interests
vidual, but by minimizing overindulgence it of preserving group solidarity and secu-
also serves to preserve the group’s resources. rity. The prescriptive focus on providing is
Similarly, industriousness benefits the hard- evident in social justice, which emphasizes
working individual, but by developing indi- sharing, equality, and communal responsi-
vidual competencies it ultimately provides bility. Social order involves inhibiting self-
advantages to the group. interest and self-expression in the service
The most common, salient forms of mo- of the larger group’s success, whereas social
rality are at play when the target is another justice involves activating prosocial behav-
person, or individuated others. Here pre- iors that serve to increase the overall welfare
scriptive morality includes both helping and of the group. Both social order and social
fairness, while proscriptive morality involves justice are binding moralities, and their re-
not harming; prescriptive morality provides spective binding strategies are discussed
for another, whereas proscriptive morality at greater length below. Most generally,
protects the other. The not harming cell of however, social order binds into relatively
our model resembles the dyadic template of homogeneous, impermeable groups based
morality (Gray, Young, & Waytz, 2012), on shared identities, whereas social justice
which involves a perpetrator who harms a binds people into more inclusive, interdepen-
patient/victim; however, we would argue for dent groups based on shared goals (Janoff-
another basic template of morality resem- Bulman, 2009; Janoff-Bulman & Carnes,
bling the helping cell of our model that in- 2013a; also see Brewer, Hong, & Li, 2004,
volves a helper who provides aid to a patient/ on two forms of group entitativity).
recipient. This prescriptive interpersonal cell Our model explains these two innate pro-
of the MMM also includes fairness, which cesses that are generic from a psychological
involves providing another with his or her perspective and culturally uniform in their
due. It is interesting to recognize that the social function, with a special focus on how
fundamentally human penchant for reci- these processes manifest in different social
procity incorporates rudimentary elements contexts. However, it is important to clarify
of both helping and fairness; returning fa- that our model does not try to explain the
vors or resources involves not just providing many ways in which cultures elaborate on
help to another but help that is proportional these basic processes. Learned cultural in-
to the inputs received from the other. novations, including everything from rituals
The final two cells of the MMM are those and tradition, gossip and reputation, the rule
that refer to the group or collective as the of law, religion, governmental institutions,
target of morality. Here, proscriptive moral- penal systems, leadership, and various forms
ity is social order, and prescriptive morality of tribalism, are woven into moral behavior
 The Model of Moral Motives 225

in different ways from culture to culture (see the subsequent development of the Moral
Richerson & Boyd, 2005, for a comprehen- Foundations Questionnaire (Graham et al.,
sive review of culture and evolution). These 2011), has not only served to catalyze an en-
cultural elaborations on the two basic pro- tire field of morality research but has also
cesses of moral behavior lead to unique soci- led to the virtual reification of MFT and its
eties that emphasize differing moral motives particular foundations.
with differing levels of effectiveness. The development of MFT represented a
bottom-up approach to mapping morality
(see Haidt & Joseph, 2004). Our own at-
Historical Context tempt to map the moral domain reflected a
top-down approach and, in particular, our
The MMM is essentially a map of the moral desire to provide a systematic, theoretical
domain, considered at different levels of underpinning for distinct moral principles;
analysis (intrapersonal, interpersonal, and the dual regulatory perspective represented
collective) and reflecting an explicit ac- in motivational research crossed with the
knowledgment that morality can involve well-worn social psychological categories
distinct motivational processes—both in- of the self, the other, and the group (or, al-
hibition and activation. A dual system of ternatively, the intrapersonal, interpersonal,
self-regulation, which has alternatively been and collective) provided a map that became
framed as activation–inhibition, approach– the MMM. In filling in the six cells of the
avoidance, and appetitive–aversive motiva- model, however, we became increasing
tion—has a long history in psychology and aware of differences between the MMM
has been recognized as central to our un- and MFT, and particularly of possible omis-
derstanding of behavior across diverse psy- sions from MFT.
chological domains (for reviews, see, e.g.,
Carver & Scheier, 2008; Gable, Reiss, &
Elliot, 2003). Interestingly, for years work Theoretical Stance
that was done on prosocial behavior, par-
ticularly in child development (e.g., Eisen- In our own mapping of the moral domain,
berg & Miller, 1987) and social psychology we assumed there would be considerable
(e.g., Batson, 1994), was regarded as a lit- overlap between the MMM and MFT. In the
erature distinct and separate from morality end, as we explain below, it appears that the
research. A different line of research on ego five foundations of MFT fall into only three
depletion and self-control (e.g., Muraven & cells of our model—the two interpersonal
Baumeister, 2000) also has not been well in- cells and the proscriptive group cell (social
tegrated into the morality literature. These order). MFT’s harm/care and fairness/reci-
two strands of research reflect distinct regu- procity foundations fall entirely in the inter-
latory systems— activation and inhibition, personal column of the MMM, with harm/
or prescriptive and proscriptive—that both care straddling both the not harming (pro-
play an important role in morality and are scriptive) and helping/fairness (prescriptive)
integrated into a single model in the MMM. cell, and fairness/reciprocity fitting squarely
Apart from the influence of work on moti- in the latter cell. More important, MFT’s
vation in psychology, the strongest influence three binding moralities are encompassed by
in the development of our model has been social order; they are all essentially cultural
the groundbreaking work of Haidt, Gra- mechanisms that serve the moral motive of
ham, and colleagues (Haidt, 2007, 2008, social order. From our perspective, the cru-
2012; Haidt & Graham, 2007; Haidt & cial omission from MFT is the prescriptive
Joseph, 2004) on moral foundations theory group cell (i.e., social justice), and the bulk
(MFT). The MFT’s five foundations include of our following discussion focuses on the
two that are “individualizing” (i.e., care/ two group-based moralities in the MMM. A
harm, fairness/reciprocity) and three that few words about the other MFT omissions,
are “binding” (i.e., ingroup/loyalty, authori- however, seem warranted, and here we are
ty/respect, and purity/sanctity). This first at- referring to the intrapersonal moral mo-
tempt to map moral principles, coupled with tives—moderation and industriousness.
226 M O R A L I T Y A N D C U LT U R E

Interestingly, the virtue of moderation of the moral domain, not only because they
has been recognized in the major philoso- are commonly recognized as descriptive of
phies of the East and West through the ages. highly moral people, but because they have
More specifically, protecting against excess important moral implications beyond the
via temperance is a core virtue in in Con- self and for the larger collective.
fucianism, Taoism, Buddhism, Hinduism, Of greater concern than the omission of
Athenian philosophy (e.g., Aristotle, Plato), these intrapersonal moralities, however, is
Islam, Judaism, and Christianity (see Dahls- the absence of an important group-based
gaard, Peterson, & Seligman, 2005, on “uni- morality, not only because this could not be
versal virtues”). Thus, in the Analects, Con- accounted for by a difference in focus but
fucius advocates self-control and the need to also because of the role of binding morali-
avoid extravagance, and in Fusul Al-Mad- ties in past discussions of political ideology.
ami, Alfarabi emphasizes the importance of More specifically, Haidt and his colleagues
moderation. Also, in recent research on the (Graham, Haidt, & Nosek, 2009; Gra-
attributes of highly moral people, self-disci- ham et al., 2011; Haidt & Graham, 2007)
pline is recognized as a key virtue (Walker argue that liberals value the individualiz-
& Pitts, 1998). Although the proximal focus ing foundations (harm and fairness) more
is the self, moderation serves to protect the than conservatives, and conservatives value
larger community by minimizing wasteful- the binding foundations (loyalty, authority,
ness and safeguarding the group’s resources. and purity) more than liberals. They claim,
Similarly, industriousness, which benefits in addition, that liberals rely on (only) two
the self, also has implications for the group; moral foundations, whereas conservatives
hard work, persistence, and conscientious- rely on all five foundations, and they con-
ness ultimately serve to advance the com- clude that conservatives understand liberals
munity’s knowledge, skills, and resources. better than liberals understand conservatives
Industriousness is often associated with the (Graham et al., 2009; Haidt, 2007, 2012). In
Protestant ethic, and two valued attributes fact, in Haidt’s (2012) book, the title of the
of highly moral people are hard work and chapter on morality and political ideology is
conscientiousness (Walker & Pitts, 1998). “The Conservative Advantage.”
Interestingly, in two totally separate at- The provocative implication of these
tempts to code open-ended responses about claims is that liberals do not have a bind-
morality, a work ethic category had to be ing morality—that is, they are not group-­
added to the five moral foundations catego- oriented and lack group-based moral con-
ries (Graham, Meindl, Koleva, Iyer, & John- cerns. Yet MFT, we believe, omits a crucial
son, 2015; Hofmann, Wisneski, Brandt, & group-based morality that is heartily em-
Skitka, 2014) braced by liberals, and thus the conclusions
The foci of MFT are other people and the of Haidt and colleagues likely reflect the
group, and it is therefore not surprising that limitations of their own model rather than
the self-focused moralities are not included of a liberal ideology. We argue that there is
in the model. Similarly, the model of moral- a group-focused prescriptive morality and
ity proposed by Rai and Fiske (2011) also claim that it is based in a social justice ori-
omit these intrapersonal virtues, because entation derived from a sense of shared com-
they explicitly focus on the relationships munal responsibility.
between two or more people. Rai and Fiske Social order and social justice are the two
(2011) identify four moral principles, each collective cells of the MMM. Both are bind-
of which follows from a particular kind of ing moralities, but their binding functions
social relationship. That is, unity, hierarchy, reflect different strategies for dealing with
equality, and proportionality follow re- challenges and threats to the group. Most
spectively from communal sharing, author- simply, we argue that social justice advances
ity ranking, equality matching, and market cooperation, whereas social order promotes
pricing. Interestingly, despite their common coordination. The distinction between co-
omission from models of morality focused ordination and cooperation is evident in
on others, moderation and industriousness economic game taxonomies (e.g., DeScioli
are nevertheless moralities that we believe & Kurzban, 2007). Importantly, however,
should be included in a comprehensive map Thomas, DeScioli, Haque, and Pinker (2014)
 The Model of Moral Motives 227

make the point that cooperation is funda- its emphasis on organization and strict norm
mentally a motivational problem, whereas adherence, including conformity and obedi-
coordination is basically an epistemological ence, and its reliance on avoidance-based
problem. The central challenge of coopera- regulation focused on punishment for devi-
tion is that a social actor pays a cost in order ant behavior (see, e.g., Blanton & Christie,
to confer a collective benefit, but the social 2003).
actor should only do this if others cooperate
as well. In contrast, the central challenge of
coordination is that social actors match the Evidence
actions of others, but to do this, social actors
require common knowledge about what ac- The importance of distinguishing between
tions to perform (Thomas et al., 2014). the two group-based moralities becomes ap-
Past work on “solving” cooperation has parent as we explore the empirical evidence
focused primarily on reciprocity and sanc- for both social order and social justice, their
tions (for a review, see Rand & Nowak, association with political ideology, and the
2013) or on individual differences and the extent to which the MFT binding moralities
features of the situation in determining are subsumed by social order and not social
the decision to cooperate (for a review, see justice. Evidence will also be presented that
Parks, Joireman, & Van Lange, 2013). In- supports important distinctions between
terdependence is a theme that unites much fairness and social justice.
of this literature; cooperation is increased to First, by way of background, it seems
the extent that social actors’ outcomes are worth mentioning that early empirical work
more interdependent because of repeated in- on prescriptive versus proscriptive moral-
teractions, social preferences, or social iden- ity found support for important differences
tification. Interdependence helps solve the between these two regulatory orientations.
motivational problem inherent to coopera- In a series of seven studies, Janoff-Bulman
tion. We assert that social justice promotes and colleagues (2009) found that proscrip-
cooperation by emphasizing common goals, tive morality is focused on transgressions,
binding people interdependently, and relying is mandatory and strict, is typically repre-
on approach-based regulation focused on sented in concrete, specific language, and
shared benefits. involves blameworthiness. In contrast,
In contrast, past work on “solving” coor- prescriptive morality is focused on “good
dination has focused on different correlating deeds,” is more discretionary, is represent-
devices such as rules and norms (Van Huyck, ed in more abstract language, and involves
Gillette, & Battalio, 1992), leadership (Cart- credit-worthiness rather than blame. Over-
wright, Gillet, & Van Vugt, 2013), and hier- all, proscriptive moral regulation is condem-
archy (Cooper, DeJong, Forsythe, & Ross, natory, whereas prescriptive moral regula-
1994). These correlating devices help solve tion is commendatory (Janoff-Bulman et al.,
the epistemological problem inherent to co- 2009).
ordination. Recent cross-cultural work on In crossing the two regulatory systems
tight versus loose societies (Gelfand, 2012; with self, other, and group, the six cells of
Gelfand, et al., 2011) found that tight soci- the model are believed to reflect distinct
eties are characterized by strict punishment moral orientations. Using 30 items devel-
for norm violations, low tolerance for devi- oped to assess the six cells of the MMM,
ant behaviors, and strong norm adherence— a confirmatory factor analysis provided
clearly features of a social order group mo- support for the six cells of the model. More
rality. This cross-cultural work also found specifically, the 30 items in the MMM scale
that tight societies generally have a history emerged as six latent constructs correspond-
of severe challenges (e.g., ecological and his- ing to the moral motives hypothesized in the
torical threats) that may have encouraged MMM (Janoff-Bulman & Carnes, 2016). In
these societies to develop strong norms for addition, in this study political orientation
and sanctions on nonconformity, thus en- was associated with the group-based moral
abling them to coordinate social behavior motives, social order and social justice, but
for survival (Gelfand, 2012). We argue that not the self-focused or other-focused mo-
social order advances coordination through tives. As expected, social order was posi-
228 M O R A L I T Y A N D C U LT U R E

tively associated with political conservatism, based morality—a proscriptive social order
whereas social justice was positively associ- morality.
ated with political liberalism. These rela- It is also worth pointing out that the MFT
tionships between political ideology and the fairness foundation and the MMM social
group-based moral motives were replicated justice motive had very different relation-
in a second study, which again found that ships with political ideology. Again, fairness
liberals endorse social justice and conserva- was not associated with political ideology,
tives endorse social order. One group did not whereas social justice was positively asso-
support a group-based, binding morality, ciated with political liberalism (Carnes et
but it was not liberals, as suggested by Haidt al., 2015). Fairness is not the same as social
and colleagues, but instead was libertarians justice. In a recent series of studies, we fo-
(Janoff-Bulman & Carnes, 2016). Libertar- cused on the distinct features of each and
ians endorse individualizing moralities but explored their use in everyday language,
eschew a morality based on collective con- instances when they conflict, their associa-
cerns (also see Iyer, Koleva, Graham, Ditto, tions with each other and with politics, and
& Haidt, 2012). the impact of concrete–abstract construals
The same associations between political (see Bharadwaj & Janoff-Bulman, 2016).
liberalism–conservatism and social justice– We found strong support for treating fair-
social order were found in a different set ness and social justice as unique, indepen-
of studies conducted to explore the role of dent constructs. Fairness is individualizing
context in understanding the use of moral and based in proportionality of inputs and
principles. In this research, we found that to outputs, whereas social justice is based in
a considerable extent, morality is embedded shared group membership and is concerned
in social contexts (Carnes, Lickel, & Janoff- with distributions across the group. Fairness
Bulman, 2015). This research examined the relies on personal identities, whereas social
contextual bases of the MFT moral founda- justice relies on social identities; and the
tions supplemented with the MMM social two principles are uncorrelated. In addition,
order and social justice motives. There was fairness is relatively universal and not asso-
a high degree of consensus regarding the op- ciated with political ideology, whereas social
erative moral principles in different types of justice is associated with political liberalism
groups, with each group type characterized and with more abstract thinking (Bharad-
by a distinct pattern of moral principles. For waj & Janoff-Bulman, 2016). Social justice
example, loyalty was regarded as particular- is simply not the same as fairness and should
ly important in intimacy groups, and fair- not be regarded as subsumed by the fairness
ness was perceived as playing an important foundation in MFT; it is a distinct group-
role in task groups. These contextual effects based morality.
were quite strong; but political ideology did Having posited two distinct, overriding
continue to play a role in the between-sub- group-based moralities, we have become in-
jects investigation (Study 2). Political ideol- terested in the functional roles of social order
ogy was not associated with any of the MFT and social justice. Both are binding morali-
individualizing foundations, but it was asso- ties, but they rely on different strategies to
ciated with the MFT binding foundations, bind the group in response to collective
as well as social order and social justice. threats and challenges. Social order empha-
Once again liberalism was positively associ- sizes conformity and strict norm adherence
ated with social justice. Of particular impor- in the service of coordination, whereas so-
tance was the finding that the three MFT cial justice emphasizes interdependence and
binding foundations—loyalty, authority, collaboration in the service of cooperation.
and purity—had the same relationship with Based on these differences, trust of others is
political ideology as social order, but not likely to differ. More specifically, coopera-
social justice; that is, all were positively as- tion is a viable path to problem solving when
sociated with political conservatism (Carnes trust is present; when it is absent, rule-based
et al., 2015). These findings lend support to coordination is likely to be a more effective
our contention that the binding foundations route to group problem solving. We therefore
of MFT all represent one type of group- expected social justice to be positively asso-
 The Model of Moral Motives 229

ciated with generalized trust of others and ance and compromise in political discourse
social order to be negatively associated with and the broader political arena. At the very
generalized distrust. We found support for least, recognizing the functions of distinct
these different relationships in a recent set of moralities may provide a basis for develop-
studies (Carnes & Janoff-Bulman, 2017), in ing respect for opposing views, even in the
which trust and distrust emerged as distinct context of disagreement.
constructs. Most interesting was the finding
that societal threat actually strengthened the
relationship between social justice and trust. ACKNOWLEDGMENTS

This research was supported by National Science


Foundation Grant Nos. BCS-1053139 (to Ronnie
Extension and Expansion Janoff-Bulman) and DGE-0907995 (to Nate C.
Carnes).
As distinct group-based moralities, social
order and social justice represent different
ways of dealing with societal threats and REFERENCES
challenges in the service of group survival
and well-being. Each may have its own Batson, C. D. (1994). Why act for the public
good?: Four answers. Personality and Social
strengths; social order may be particularly Psychology Bulletin, 20, 603–610.
effective in responding quickly to severe Bharadwaj, P., & Janoff-Bulman, R. (2016).
threats, whereas social justice may be par- Fairness and social justice: Distinct morali-
ticularly effective when seeking cooperation ties. Unpublished manuscript, University of
concerning common goals such as resource Massachusetts, Amherst, MA.
allocation. In the study of morality, it seems Blanton, H., & Christie, C. (2003). Deviance
important to keep in mind that morality is regulation: A theory of identity and action.
a system of shared standards and rules that Review of General Psychology, 7, 115–149.
play a functional role in facilitating group Brewer, M. B., Hong, Y., & Li, Q. (2004). Dy-
living and providing social actors with so- namic entitativity: Perceiving groups as actors.
In V. Yzerbyt, C. M. Judd, & O. Corneille
lutions to problems associated with group (Eds.), The psychology of group perception:
life. Thus one important direction we are Contributions to the study of homogeneity,
currently investigating involves understand- entitativity and essentialism (pp. 25–38). Phil-
ing the specific social problems—such as adelphia: Psychology Press.
cooperation and coordination—that moral- Carnes, N. C., & Janoff-Bulman, R. (2017).
ity “solves” and exactly how different moral Group morality and the function of trust and
motives actually “solve” these problems of distrust. Manuscript submitted for publica-
group living. tion.
The functional role of morality applies to Carnes, N. C., Lickel, B., & Janoff-Bulman, R.
all moral foundations and moral motives— (2015). Shared perceptions: Morality is em-
bedded in social contexts. Personality and So-
they are in the service of group living. Given cial Psychology Bulletin, 41, 351–362.
that the two group-based moralities of the Cartwright, E., Gillet, J., & Van Vugt, M. (2013).
MMM are the domain of political differenc- Leadership by example in the weak-link game.
es, it seems particularly important to better Economic Inquiry, 51, 2028–2043.
understand the functional underpinnings of Carver, C. S., & Scheier, M. F. (2008). Feedback
social order and social justice. Despite the processes in the simultaneous regulation of af-
disdain with which each side of the politi- fect and action. In J. Y. Shah & W. L. Gard-
cal spectrum typically views the other, it is ner (Eds.), Handbook of motivation science
possible that societies in which both types (pp. 308–324). New York: Guilford Press.
of group-based moralities are well repre- Cooper, R., DeJong, D. V., Forsythe, R., & Ross,
T. W. (1994). Alternative institutions for re-
sented are those that can most successfully solving coordination problems: Experimental
respond to diverse challenges and threats evidence on forward induction and preplay
to the group (see Janoff-Bulman & Carnes, communication. In J. W. Friedman (Ed.),
2016). Thus one important implication of Problems of coordination in economic activ-
our perspective is that there are strong social ity (pp. 129–146). New York: Springer.
regulatory reasons for emphasizing toler- Dahlsgaard, K., Peterson, C., & Seligman, M.
230 M O R A L I T Y A N D C U LT U R E

E. P. (2005). Shared virtue: The convergence Hofmann, W., Wisneski, D. C., Brandt, M. J., &
of valued human strengths across culture and Skitka, L. J. (2014). Morality in everyday life.
history. Review of General Psychology, 9, Science, 345, 1340–1343.
203–213. Iyer, R., Koleva, S., Graham, J., Ditto, P. H.,
DeScioli, P., & Kurzban, R. (2007). The games & Haidt, J. (2012). Understanding libertar-
people play. In S. Gangestad & J. Simpson ian morality: The psychological dispositions
(Eds.), Evolution of mind: Fundamental ques- of self-identified libertarians. PLOS ONE, 7,
tions and controversies (pp. 130–136). New e42366.
York: Guilford Press. Janoff-Bulman, R. (2009). To provide or pro-
Eisenberg, N., & Miller, P. A. (1987). The rela- tect: Motivational bases of political liberalism
tion of empathy to prosocial and related be- and conservatism. Psychological Inquiry, 20,
haviors. Psychological Bulletin, 101, 91–119. 120–128.
Gable, S. L., Reis, H. T., & Elliot, A. J. (2003). Janoff-Bulman, R., & Carnes, N. C. (2013a).
Evidence for bivariate systems: An empirical Surveying the moral landscape: Moral motives
test of appetition and aversion across domains. and group-based moralities. Personality and
Journal of Research in Personality, 37, 349– Social Psychology Review, 17, 242–247.
372. Janoff-Bulman, R., & Carnes, N. C. (2013b).
Gelfand, M. J. (2012). Culture’s constraints: In- Moral context matters: A reply to Graham.
ternational differences in the strength of social Personality and Social Psychology Review,
norms. Current Directions in Psychological 17, 242–247.
Science, 21(6), 420–424. Janoff-Bulman, R., & Carnes, N. C. (2016). So-
Gelfand, M. J., Raver, J. L., Nishii, L., Leslie, cial justice and social order: Binding moralities
L. M., Lun, J., Lim, B. C., . . . Yamaguchi, across the political spectrum. PLOS ONE, 11,
S. (2011). Differences between tight and loose e0152479.
cultures: A 33-nation study. Science, 332, Janoff-Bulman, R., Sheikh, S., & Hepp, S. (2009).
1100–1104. Proscriptive versus prescriptive morality: Two
Graham, J., Haidt, J., & Nosek, B. (2009). Lib- faces of moral regulation. Journal of Personal-
erals and conservatives use different sets of ity and Social Psychology, 96, 521–537.
moral foundations. Journal of Personality and Muraven, M. R., & Baumeister, R. F. (2000).
Social Psychology, 96, 1029–1046. Self-regulation and depletion of limited re-
Graham, J., Meindl, P., Koleva, S., Iyer, R., & sources: Does self-control resemble a muscle?
Johnson, K. M. (2015). When values and be- Psychological Bulletin, 126, 247–259.
havior conflict: Moral pluralism and intraper- Parks, C. D., Joireman, J., & Van Lange, P. A.
sonal hypocrisy. Social and Personality Psy- (2013). Cooperation, trust, and antagonism:
chology Compass, 9, 158–170. How public goods are promoted. Psychologi-
Graham, J., Nosek, B. A., Haidt, J., Iyer, R., Kol- cal Science in the Public Interest, 14(3), 119–
eva, S., & Ditto, P. H. (2011). Mapping the 165.
moral domain. Journal of Personality and So- Rai, T. S., & Fiske, A. P. (2011). Moral psychol-
cial Psychology, 101, 366–385. ogy is relationship regulation: Moral motives
Gray, K., Young, L., & Waytz, A., (2012). The for unity, hierarchy, equality, and proportion-
moral dyad: A fundamental template unifying ality. Psychological Review, 118, 57–75.
moral judgment. Psychological Inquiry, 23, Rand, D. G., & Nowak, M. A. (2013). Human
206–215. cooperation. Trends in Cognitive Science, 17,
Haidt, J. (2007). The new synthesis in moral psy- 413–425.
chology. Science, 316, 998–1002. Richerson, P. J., & Boyd, R. (2005). Not by genes
Haidt, J. (2008). Morality. Perspectives on Psy- alone: How culture transformed human evo-
chological Science, 3, 65–72. lution. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Haidt, J. (2012). The righteous mind: Why good Thomas, K. A., DeScioli, P., Haque, O. S., &
people are divided by politics and religion. Pinker, S. (2014). The psychology of coordina-
New York: Pantheon Books. tion and common knowledge. Journal of Per-
Haidt, J., & Graham, J. (2007). When morality sonality and Social Psychology, 107, 657–676.
opposes justice: Conservatives have moral in- Van Huyck, J. B., Gillette, A. B., & Battalio, R.
tuitions that liberals may not recognize. Social C. (1992). Credible assignments in coordina-
Justice Research, 20, 98–116. tion games. Games and Economic Behavior,
Haidt, J., & Joseph, C. (2004, Fall). Intuitive 4, 606–626.
ethics: How innately prepared intuitions gen- Walker, L. J., & Pitts, R. C. (1998). Naturalistic
erate culturally variable virtues. Daedalus, conceptions of moral maturity. Developmen-
pp. 55–66. tal Psychology, 34, 403–419.
CHAPTER 24

Relationship Regulation Theory

Tage S. Rai

Are there any universally held moral rules that apply across social–
relational contexts?

No; instead, there are universal social–relational contexts that entail


competing moral rules, and moral conflicts arise when people use
different social–relational models to navigate the same situation.

Ethics change across different social rela- the term moral to be restricted to reasoning or
tionships. Our expectations about accept- intuitions regarding right and wrong action
able behavior among friends, for example, that are independent of the social–relational
are considerably different from those same contexts in which they occur. From this per-
expectations among coworkers or strangers. spective, judgments can only be “moral” if
In conjunction with anthropologist Alan they are true at all times in all places, and
Fiske, I developed relationship regulation so moral psychologists have been focused
theory (RRT; Rai & Fiske, 2011) to explain on trying to identify such universal truths.
how our sense of right and wrong changes Consequently, studies of moral psychology
when we are interacting in different rela- are often expressly nonrelational, removing
tionships, including those with superiors, any possible influence of knowledge of estab-
subordinates, coworkers, and business part- lished social norms, social relationships with
ners, as well as friends, close loved ones, and and among the actors involved, and con-
strangers. And, relatedly, why individuals, sequences for future social interactions in
social groups, and cultures disagree about order to isolate how moral judgments occur
what is morally right and why these dis- under “ideal” conditions (Mikhail, 2007). In
agreements are so intractable. this framework, variation in moral judgment
Change and disagreement are difficult across social relationships and contexts, such
topics to study in moral psychology, because as when people administer electric shocks to
many moral psychologists have predefined another person when ordered by an author-

231
232 M O R A L I T Y A N D C U LT U R E

ity figure (Milgram, 1963) or when people are activated when people employ different
exhibit preferential treatment toward their social–­relational schemas to navigate other-
ingroups (Tajfel, Billig, Bundy, & Flament, wise identical situations.
1971), can only be explained away as non- What this means is that, in order to un-
moral social biases that compromise correct derstand the bases of our moral psychology,
moral performance. Change is error. Dis- we must begin with the basic kinds of social
agreement is the result of error. The idea is relations people engage in across cultures.
that if everyone simply agreed about the ac- To do so, RRT draws on relational models
tions that took place independent of the con- theory (Fiske, 1992), which develops a tax-
text in which they took place, there would be onomy of four models of social relations
no moral disagreement. that capture the breadth of social life across
RRT is aimed toward reconceptualiz- cultures. RRT extends this work to identify
ing our moral psychology as embedded in four fundamental and distinct moral mo-
social–relational cognition and unpacking tives that drive behavior in these four mod-
the ways in which different social–relation- els for social relations (see Table 24.1).
al contexts entail correspondingly unique When people are relating by market pric-
moral motives and beliefs that can and do ing, they use ratios and rates to make all
conflict. According to this perspective, the goods fungible so that they can be traded
fundamental bases to our moral psychology off against one another; when people are
are not asocial; instead, they are grounded relating using market perspectives, they are
in the cognition we use to regulate our so- motivated by a sense of proportionality to
cial relationships, and fundamentally dif- make moral judgments based on a utilitar-
ferent ways of relating entail fundamentally ian calculation of costs and benefits, even if
different moral obligations and transgres- it means killing others to achieve a greater
sions. From this perspective, any action, good. In the context of fairness, people mo-
including intentional violence and unequal tivated by proportionality believe that goods
treatment, may be perceived as moral or should be distributed based on merit and
immoral depending on the moral motive that there should be proportionate represen-
employed and how the relevant social rela- tation in decision making.
tionship is construed. Moral disagreement When people are relating by equality
arises from competing moral motives that matching, all actors in a relationship are

TABLE 24.1.  Moral Motives in RRT


Social–relational Distributive Procedural
Moral motive model Violence justice justice
Unity Communal To protect ingroup, outsiders Free sharing/ Consensus-based
sharing or contaminated insiders may need-based
be harmed

Hierarchy Authority Leaders may harm Rank-based Superiors decide


ranking subordinates, subordinates
must harm under orders,
violence may sometimes be
used to contest rank

Equality Equality Must respond with violence Equal division Equal


matching in kind representation

Proportionality Market pricing Violence can be traded off Merit-based Proportionate


against other goods and used representation
to sacrifice others for the
greater good
 Relationship Regulation Theory 233

perceived as distinct but equal; when people models capture the breadth of human moral
are relating equally, they are motivated by a life, but cultures and individuals vary in how
sense of equality to match exchanges exactly, they implement them across situations. This
feeling strong obligations to treat everyone differential use of moral motives due to dif-
the same and to reciprocate any violence in ferent social–relational models leads to vast-
kind. In the context of fairness, people mo- ly different beliefs about the acceptability of
tivated by equality believe that goods should violence, the fair distribution of resources,
be distributed equally no matter what and and decision making in procedural justice.
that there should be equal representation in Throughout the chapter, I focus on the
decision making. centrality of harm in theories of moral psy-
When people are relating by authority chology as a way to flesh out these ideas and
ranking, social interactions are characterized make three key contributions of RRT con-
by the salience of hierarchical rank between crete.
superiors and subordinates; when people are
relating hierarchically they are motivated by 1. Virtually every major contemporary the-
a sense of hierarchy in which subordinates ory of moral psychology argues that a (or
must respect, defer to, and obey superiors, the) core foundation of our moral psy-
even if the superior’s commands require chology is a universal prohibition against
them to engage in violence; superiors are intentional harm to others. By arguing
morally entitled to command subordinates that any action, including the infliction
but are also obligated to lead, guide, direct, of intentional harm, can be moral or im-
and protect them. In the context of fairness, moral depending on its social–relational
people motivated by hierarchy believe that context and that most violence is actually
leaders should get preferential treatment and motivated by moral thoughts and senti-
access to goods and should make decisions ments, RRT makes a clear competing
for subordinates. prediction to these other theories, as well
When people are relating by communal as all major theories of violence.
sharing, there is a strong sense of oneness 2. Whether and what kind of action, includ-
and shared essence among everyone in the ing different forms of violence, is deemed
relationship; when people are relating com- morally acceptable and even morally re-
munally they are motivated by a sense of quired changes depending on the moral
unity to protect their ingroups from any motive being employed.
threat to the group’s solidarity, even if it re- 3. Moral disagreements, including those
quires violence. In the context of fairness, over the acceptability of violence, result
people motivated by unity believe that goods from people viewing identical actions
should be shared freely without tracking and through different social–relational mod-
distributed based on need, and that all deci- els that entail competing moral motives.
sions should be made by consensus.
Thus, according to RRT, moral psychol-
ogy is composed of motives to make actual Historical Context
relationships correspond with culturally
implemented ideals of the four social re- The Age of Enlightenment was characterized
lational models. Moral judgment refers to by skepticism of tradition and authority as
evaluations of the actor’s effectiveness at this sources of knowledge and faith in the ability
process based on his or her traits and behav- of reason and logic to explain several aspects
iors. In this framework, moral judgments of human life, including morality (Kram-
are not based on the content of actions at all nick, 1995). As MacIntyre (1981/2007)
(e.g., did the action cause harm, were people has noted, Enlightenment thinkers devel-
treated unequally), but instead are based on oped a rationalist conception of morality as
the moral motives people are using in cor- grounded in abstract, impartial, universal,
respondence with the social–relational mod- logical principles that had the potential to
els they are aiming to satisfy. These moral be reasoned toward a priori of experience
motives and corresponding social–relational through conscious reasoning. The rational-
234 M O R A L I T Y A N D C U LT U R E

ist conception of morality is a prescriptive technical scientific sense specified by RRT,


claim about how we ought to judge and be- in this space. Whereas MFT can be added
have. Contemporary debates in moral psy- to in order to include beliefs that are part
chology, a field aimed toward descriptive of a folk definition of morality but not our
analysis, has largely been characterized by scientific definition, RRT cannot.
arguments over the extent to which the ra- In some cases, RRT is complementary.
tionalist conception of morality is an accu- For example, whereas MFT argues that
rate reflection of how people actually make people care about fairness, RRT can predict
moral judgments. that what people believe to be fair will vary
These arguments focus on two broad depending on the moral motive people are
sets of questions. Some questions exam- using. So if people are motivated by unity,
ine how people process moral judgment, they will believe that goods should be dis-
whereas other questions examine the con- tributed freely and based on need within the
tent of moral judgment. Questions related communal group; if they are motivated by
to “process” are concerned with the mental hierarchy, they will believe that goods should
algorithms people use to connect inputs to be distributed to those highest in rank; if
the output that takes the form of a moral they are motivated by equality, they will
judgment (e.g., conscious reasoning vs. au- believe goods should be distributed equally;
tomatic intuition; domain-general vs. do- and if they are motivated by proportional-
main-specific process). Questions related to ity, they will believe goods should be dis-
content, which is the focus of this chapter, tributed based on merit. In other cases, RRT
examine what the “inputs” that the men- is competing. So whereas MFT argues for
tal algorithms work from actually are. In a unique moral foundation of purity, RRT
other words, what are the bases or criteria argues that purity is tied to communal and
upon which moral judgments are made? authority-based relations. Thus, RRT pre-
If our moral psychology is a system, what dicts that when people are morally offended
problem(s) is it trying to solve? at eating the dead family dog, it is because it
is the family dog, and that moral disgust at
eating dogs in general will be more common
Theoretical Stance in cultures in which dogs are seen as part of
the family. In many cases, acts that are per-
Like the three moral codes (Shweder, Much, ceived as morally wrong in isolation, such as
Mahapatra, & Park, 1997) and moral foun- engaging in a sexual act with a McChicken
dations theory (MFT; Haidt & Joseph, sandwich (Hathaway, 2015), may be seen
2004; Graham et al., 2012), RRT seeks by ingroup members as morally appropriate
to broaden our conception of morality to and even required if the purpose of the act
capture the psychology of people outside is to facilitate group identity, bonding, and
of modern, Western, liberal contexts to in- belonging, as is often the case in fraternities,
clude the moral experiences of those across on sports teams, and in the military (Fiske
cultures and history. Where RRT differs & Rai, 2014; Carnes, Lickel, & Janoff-­
from these theories is that by stating that Bulman, 2015).
moral psychology functions to regulate so- In regard to harm, domain theory (Turiel,
cial relationships, it is aiming to establish 1983), universal moral grammar (Mikhail,
a scientific definition of moral, not a folk 2007), and the harm hypothesis (Gray et al.,
taxonomy of it. Therefore, RRT cannot cap- 2012) argue that a prohibition against in-
ture every aspect of behavior in every folk tentional harm is a (the) core feature of our
concept of morality. For example, individual moral psychology and that people are vio-
choice, particularly as it relates to the con- lent when their moral sense has failed them
cept of “negative liberty” (Berlin, 1969), is somehow. Shweder et al. (1997) and Haidt
amoral in RRT. Freedom in this sense refers and colleagues (Haidt & Joseph, 2004; Gra-
to “freedom from relationships.” It draws a ham, Haidt, & Nosek, 2009) agree that our
line beyond which relationships should not moral psychology includes a prohibition
be regulated. There is no morality, in the against intentional harm but have argued
 Relationship Regulation Theory 235

that there are moral judgments that do not Evidence


involve aversion to harm (or inequality) and
in some cases can compete with aversion The primary prediction of RRT is that what
to harm to ultimately bring harm about. In is moral or immoral is defined by social–­
contrast to all of these approaches, RRT ar- relational context rather than the pure con-
gues that a prohibition against intentional tent of action. For example, there is a uni-
harm is not a foundation of morality at all versal taboo against incest, but what makes
(no action is). In our framework, whether incest immoral is the relationship between
harm is seen as good or ill depends on its the partners, not anything about the sex per
social–­relational context, and when inten- se, and the relations that count as “incest”
tional harm does occur, it does not reflect vary across cultures and history. If anyone
a breakdown in our moral psychology. can find an action that is seen as universally
Rather, in most cases, intentionally harming moral or immoral regardless of its social–
oneself or another person is motivated by relational context, that would falsify the
moral thoughts and sentiments on the part theory. An answer such as “murder” would
of the perpetrator to regulate relationships not qualify as a testable claim because the
with the victims or third parties. We harm term is predefined as immoral by its culture.
when we feel it is righteous to defend our In contrast, an answer such as “intentional
ingroups, to rectify transgressions, to con- killing” is a testable claim.
test positions in a social hierarchy, to initiate The more interesting question is genera-
others into new relationships, and more. tivity: What can the theory do? What new
If RRT generates a clear competing predic- predictions does it provide? To the extent
tion to all other theories of moral psychol- that moral motives vary across social rela-
ogy, it also goes against most major theories tions in the patterns described by RRT and
of violence. Frustration–aggression theories the fairness and violence judgments encom-
view violence as a breakdown in correct passed by each motive cluster together, the
moral functioning, in which a person knows theory is generative. RRT has been instru-
that what he or she is doing is wrong but mental in explaining moral judgment and
does it anyway because his or her self-reg- disagreement in domains including war and
ulatory systems have failed somehow (Dol- conflict, consumer behavior, and organiza-
lard, Miller, Doob, Mowrer, & Sears, 1939; tional behavior. For example, in the context
DeWall, Baumeister, Stillman, & Gailliot, of consumer behavior, McGraw, Schwartz,
2007). Similarly, theories of violence that and Tetlock (2012) have shown how prof-
rest on notions of moral disengagement or it-seeking, which is perceived as fair when
dehumanization assume that violence is a motivated by proportionality in markets, is
mistake that occurs when perpetrators fail perceived as unfair by consumers when ap-
to perceive their victims as fellow human plied by businesses in communal contexts,
beings worthy of moral concern (Bandura, such as churches. In the context of organiza-
1999). According to RRT, violence is not tional behavior, Giessner and Van Quaque-
a mistake; instead, it is often the result of beke (2010) have argued that many conflicts
moral performance. Rational choice and between superiors and subordinates in orga-
instrumental models of violence, which as- nizations are due to the two sides perceiving
sume that violence is simply a behavioral different moral motives to be guiding their
strategy that may be pursued if its benefits working relationship. In my own research,
outweigh its costs relative to nonviolent I have been investigating how priming the
strategies based on a relevant set of utilities schema for a given social relation (e.g., com-
(Felson & Tedeschi, 1993), are theoretical- munal) leads to greater support for fairness
ly compatible with RRT’s view of violence and violence judgments tied to its corre-
as morally motivated. But where RRT can sponding moral motive (e.g., unity-based
add to the rational–instrumental account is support for need-based distribution and vio-
by providing insight into what the principal lence toward outgroups).
relevant utilities are; namely, moral thoughts In regard to harm, Alan Fiske and I ana-
and sentiments. lyzed violent practices across cultures and
236 M O R A L I T Y A N D C U LT U R E

history in our book Virtuous Violence: Hurt- kind of proportional thinking, in which the
ing and Killing to Create, Sustain, End, and goal is to achieve the greatest good for the
Honor Social Relationships (2014). These greatest number and violence is acceptable if
practices included war, torture, genocide, the benefits outweigh the costs, is the stated
honor killing, animal and human sacrifice, justification for torture, the use of kill ratios
homicide, suicide, intimate partner violence, in military decision making, and the willing-
rape, corporal punishment, execution, trial ness to incur collateral damage that results
by combat, police brutality, hazing, castra- in the deaths of innocent civilians. Nor must
tion, dueling, feuding, contact sports, the the trade-offs only be in human lives. De-
violence immortalized by gods and heroes, cisions regarding military spending budgets
and more. What we found is that across are predicated on the necessity of assigning
practices, across cultures, and throughout a monetary worth to a soldier’s life—both
historical periods, the primary motivations the ones we wish to protect and the ones we
underlying acts of violence are inherently wish to kill.
moral. By moral, I mean that people are vio- Equality underlies the eye-for-an-eye,
lent because they feel their violence is jus- tooth-for-a-tooth violence that character-
tified, obligatory, and praiseworthy. They izes everyday confrontations in which some-
know they are harming fully human beings, one feels entitled to retaliate or “hit back”
and they believe they should do it. Violence after they have first been hit. In some cases,
does not result from a psychopathic lack of equality-motivated violence may be directed
morality; it emerges out of the exercise of toward anyone in the perpetrator’s relevant
moral rights and obligations by perpetrators social group, and these acts are seen as mor-
and their social groups. ally justified on the part of perpetrators and
People everywhere kill in self-defense, to observers. Blood feuds between gangs and
protect the people they love or to get clos- clans persist precisely because victims of an
er to them, to punish a transgression or to attack feel that they can attack anyone in the
make reparations, as retaliation for a previ- perpetrator’s group. For example, following
ous attack, to establish a strong reputation an attack by the Abdel-Halim clan on the
in order to prevent future attacks, and in El-Hanashat clan in Egypt that resulted in
obedience to God and other authorities. In twenty-two fatalities in 2002, a surviving
almost every case, we have found that the vi- El-Hanashat stated “no matter what sacri-
olent act is perceived as obligatory, just, and fices it takes, we are determined to kill as
even praiseworthy by the perpetrators, many many of them [Abdel-Halims] as were mur-
local observers, and, in some cases, the vic- dered” (Halawi, 2002). In the extreme, vic-
tims themselves. Across practices, we find tims may attack members of the perpetra-
that the purpose of violence is to regulate tors’ group who had absolutely nothing to
important social relationships, either to the do with the original attack. This is the inher-
victim or to third parties that deeply matter ent logic behind terrorist attacks that target
to the perpetrator. And in all cases, perpe- civilians. Most recently, victims of ISIS have
trators are using violence to create, conduct, been forced to don orange jumpsuits during
sustain, enhance, transform, honor, protect, their beheadings and burnings to symbolize
redress, repair, end, and mourn valued rela- that their deaths are retribution for the pris-
tionships. Of course, there are many differ- oners being held at Guantanamo Bay (La-
ent sorts of relationships, and so violence to mothe, 2014).
serve any of those purposes will be unique in The hierarchy-based morality that people
different relationships. use when authority ranking motivates the
Proportionality when market pricing violent punishment of children by parents,
is central to all modern war planning. As enlisted men by officers, citizens by police
Harry Truman put it when describing his and other authorities, and humans by gods.
decision to drop the atomic bomb on Hi- As one policeman put it after fighting erupt-
roshima and Nagasaki in World War II, ed between protesters and police in Berkeley,
“a quarter of a million of the flower of our California, “if the parents of these cocksuck-
young manhood was worth a couple of Japa- ers had beat ‘em when they were young, we
nese cities” (Alperovitz, 1996, p. 516). This wouldn’t have to now. . . . There’s a whole
 Relationship Regulation Theory 237

bunch of these assholes who’ve learned some driven by communal unity, it is also used to
respect for law and order tonight” (Stark, create communal unity within relationships;
1972, p. 61). In addition to punishment, this kind of violence is endemic to brutal ini-
rank-motivated violence often creates, ne- tiation rites and hazing, both of which re-
gotiates, or reasserts a hierarchical relation- move an individual from a previous life and
ship. Men in honor cultures, mafias, and integrate him or her into a new one. As one
gangs, medieval knights, and youths in all mother described her reasons for initiating
cultures have fought to establish their rank her daughter into womanhood through the
in what they perceived as legitimately con- practice of female circumcision:
testable hierarchies. Honor, valor, and ad-
miration accrue to those who are victorious, I thought of their future. The woman who is
whereas those who do not fight are shamed circumcised behaves in a way that forces peo-
and excluded. As one bar fighter describes ple around her to respect her. . . . Pharaonic
circumcision ensures the woman’s strong place
how backing down from a fight would feel,
in the family. She is very trustworthy because
“I’d feel guilty. I’d feel weak. I’d feel like I she does not allow men to take advantage of
let myself down. I’d feel like I let anybody her. She is her own person, even for the man
else that was involved down” (Copes, Hoch- she is married to. This is a source of respect
stetler, & Forsyth, 2013, p. 12). and I think it is more important than how
It may be difficult to imagine how violence painful it is. The wound heals, but the rela-
that elevates a person’s status and provides tionships remain strong.” (Abusharaf, 2001,
him or her with selfish benefits could possi- 131–132)
bly be morally motivated because we have a
tendency to associate morality with selfless- In this example, the mother wants what
ness and altruism. But morality has always is best for her daughter and is working to
been selfish. For thousands of years many raise a woman who holds the values that are
people have been committed to kindness and deemed morally correct in her culture. The
peace because they fear God’s wrath and “perpetrator” loves the “victim” dearly, and
want to go to heaven and not to hell. Any- any explanation that attempts to account for
time someone does what is right in order to her violence in terms of “disengagement” or
avoid being shamed, to alleviate their guilt, “dehumanization” fails to capture the love,
or to restore their honor in the eyes of their care, and compassion that actually motivate
community, their act is selfish, but none- the act.
theless moral. And if we acknowledge that Together, these models for social relations
violence that restores honor can be morally and their moral motives capture the differ-
motivated, then by extension, violence that ent ways in which perpetrators are driven to
enhances honor, status, and esteem in the hurt and kill. Many of the acts are ones that
eyes of one’s community has the potential to modern liberal Americans would deem hid-
be morally motivated as well. eous, repugnant, immoral, and evil. But no
People relating communally are motivated matter how heinous these actions may seem
by unity to engage in violence out of loyalty to us, the fact is that perpetrators’ actions
to each other. They will fight because their are motivated by moral thoughts and senti-
fellow group members are fighting, and if ments which are often shared by their social
one of them is attacked, they will feel like groups.
they have all been attacked and will col- This claim could be falsified in a few
lectively avenge their compatriot. Acts of ways. First, if the majority of violence was
genocide occur when communal groups are committed by people who lack the capacity
morally motivated to maintain their ingroup for moral emotions, that would invalidate
unity against what is believed to be the our theory. Although it is true that psycho-
contamination of an outgroup. In contrast, paths commit more than their fair share of
honor killings are intended to cleanse a fam- violence given the less than 1% base rate
ily of contamination from one of their own, of psychopathy in the population (Coid,
allowing them to reestablish their communal Yang, Ullrich, Roberts, & Hare, 2009),
relationship with the larger community that they still only account for a fraction of vio-
has shunned them. While violence is often lent crime—typically less than 10% (Coid,
238 M O R A L I T Y A N D C U LT U R E

Yang, Ullrich, Roberts, Moran, et al., 2009). the same way that compensating people for
Second, if most violence reflected crimes doing their civic duty of donating blood can
of convenience against random strangers, reduce the likelihood of donation (Frey &
such as when an addict attacks someone Oberholzer-Gee, 1997). Finally, using first-
because he or she needs money for drugs, person narratives of violent experiences, I
that would work against our account of vio- am finding that for violence that people do
lence as morally motivated. But in spite of not want to engage in but feel that they are
our fears, these crimes are statistically rare; morally obligated to, greater self-control
strangers commit only a small fraction of leads to more, not less, violence.
murders (U.S. Department of Justice Federal
Bureau of Investigation, 2010). Still, some
critics might argue that when perpetrators Extension and Expansion
claim their actions were morally motivated,
these statements only reflect post hoc ratio- Some definitions slow progress. In moral
nales meant to mitigate blame. But if per- psychology, a set of ideas drawn from post-
petrators really wanted to mitigate blame to Enlightenment Western prescriptive philos-
avoid punishment from the law, they would ophy has clouded our ability to understand
claim that the crime did not happen or that the bases of moral judgment. To honestly
they were not in their right minds and that investigate moral psychology, we must com-
they regretted it deeply. Instead, perpetra- pletely separate our own prescriptive eth-
tors often brag about their violent actions, ics from our theory building. RRT is my
and their local social groups often express attempt to do that. It argues that there is a
explicit support for the violence, citing that universal structure to our moral psychology,
the victims deserved what they got (Kubrin but that it is implemented differently across
& Weitzer, 2003). Even when perpetra- social relations in ways that lead to extreme
tors’ statements are post hoc justifications moral diversity across cultures and history.
meant to excuse, they are still important, The most important implication of this
because they reveal the moral standards of work is to show that moral disagreements
those being appealed to. Thus the leaders reflect genuinely different social–relational
of ISIS may actually be cladding their vic- perspectives and motives rather than the ac-
tims in orange jumpsuits and claiming that tions of “evil” people or errors and biases in
the beheadings are retaliatory for nonmoral, judgment on the part of those we disagree
instrumental propaganda purposes, rather with. It shows that, when people are vio-
than out of genuine moral motives, but the lent, it is because they believe it is right, and
strategy can only be effective if their stated therefore focusing on increasing the material
reasons resonate with moral opinions held consequences of violence, providing body
by their followers and others in the region. cameras to record behavior, improving self-
Experimentally, we are beginning to test control, or improving mental health care
RRT’s generative predictions regarding vio- may not be as effective as community-based
lence in a number of interesting ways. For interventions that work to shift moral atti-
example, using political attitude surveys and tudes and make clear to potential perpetra-
behavioral experiments, we have shown that tors that their violence hurts social relation-
dehumanization of victims only increases ships important to them.
violence motivated by instrumental reasons Long term, we know that people engage in
or personal gain. Dehumanization does not various kinds of social relationships across
increase violence motivated by moral rea- cultures and organizations, and my research
sons, such as revenge, because morally mo- has found that these social relationships
tivated perpetrators wish to harm complete imply very different rules and expectations
human beings (Rai, Valdesolo, & Graham, about fairness and the acceptability of vio-
2017). In another set of experiments, I have lence. However, the question of why there
found that adding an extrinsic material in- are these different types of relationships and
centive to commit violence can “crowd out” social structures and under what conditions
intrinsic moral motives to commit violence, one is likely to predominate over another is
leading to a reduced likelihood of violence in still to be explored. For example, why do
 Relationship Regulation Theory 239

people freely share hunting and fishing terri- DeWall, C. N., Baumeister, R. F., Stillman, T. F.,
tories more often than gardens, share water & Gailliot, M. T. (2007). Violence restrained:
more than food, or share more in areas with Effects of self-regulation and its depletion on
fewer organized social structures? When do aggression. Journal of Experimental Social
Psychology, 43, 62–76.
people rely on simple moral rules such as “do
Dollard, J., Miller, N. E., Doob, L. W., Mowrer,
no harm” versus relying on more complex O. H., & Sears, R. R. (1939). Frustration and
moral rules such as “calculate all utilities aggression. New Haven, CT: Yale University
on a common metric to determine the op- Press.
timal choice”? My collaborators and I have Felson, R. B., & Tedeschi, J. T. (1993). Aggres-
already started to investigate these questions sion and violence: Social interactionist per-
through analytic modeling approaches, in spectives. Washington, DC: American Psycho-
which we have identified factors such as logical Association.
the interdependence among individuals, Fiske, A. P. (1992). The four elementary forms
the returns on resources, and the costs of of sociality: Framework for a unified theory
social interaction as critical components to of social relations. Psychological Review, 99,
689–723.
the emergence of different social structures
Fiske, A. P., & Rai, T. S. (2014). Virtuous vio-
(Nettle, Panchanathan, Rai, & Fiske, 2011). lence: Hurting and killing to create, sustain,
The next step is to experimentally manipu- end, and honor social relationships. Cam-
late these factors and examine whether they bridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
lead to the emergence of different kinds of Frey, B. S., & Oberholzer-Gee, F. (1997). The
social relations and the downstream moral cost of price incentives: An empirical analysis
motives they entail. This line of research will of motivation crowding-out. American Eco-
ultimately develop a more complete theory nomic Review, 87, 746–755.
of social relations than any that currently Giessner, S., & Van Quaquebeke, N. (2010).
exist. Using a relational models perspective to un-
derstand normatively appropriate conduct in
ethical leadership. Journal of Business Ethics,
REFERENCES 95, 43–55.
Graham, J., Haidt, J., Koleva, S., Motyl, M., Iyer,
Abusharaf, R. M. (2001). Virtuous cuts: Female R., Wojcik, S. P., & Ditto, P. H. (2012). Moral
genital circumcision in an African ontology. foundations theory: The pragmatic validity of
Differences, 12, 112–140. moral pluralism. Advances in Experimental
Alperovitz, G. (1996). The decision to use the Social Psychology, 47, 55–130.
atomic bomb. New York: Vintage. Graham, J., Haidt, J., & Nosek, B. A. (2009).
Bandura, A. (1999). Moral disengagement in the Liberals and conservatives rely on different
perpetration of inhumanities. Personality and sets of moral foundations. Journal of Person-
Social Psychology Review, 3, 193–209. ality and Social Psychology, 96, 1029–1046.
Berlin, I. (1969). Four essays on liberty (Vol. 5). Gray, K., Young, L., & Waytz, A. (2012). Mind
Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. perception is the essence of morality. Psycho-
Carnes, N. C., Lickel, B., & Janoff-Bulman, R. logical Inquiry, 23, 101–124.
(2015). Shared perceptions: Morality is em- Haidt, J., & Joseph, C. (2004). Intuitive ethics:
bedded in social contexts. Personality and So- How innately prepared intuitions generate
cial Psychology Bulletin, 41, 351–362. culturally variable virtues. Daedalus, 133,
Coid, J., Yang, M., Ullrich, S., Roberts, A., & 55–66.
Hare, R. D. (2009). Prevalence and correlates Halawi, J. (2002, August 15). “Honour”
of psychopathic traits in the household popu- drenched in blood. Al-Ahram Weekly. Avail-
lation of Great Britain. International Journal able at www.masress.com/en/ahramweek-
of Law and Psychiatry, 32, 65–73. ly/22698.
Coid, J., Yang, M., Ullrich, S., Roberts, A., Hathaway, J. (2015, June 3). Junior varsity base-
Moran, P., Bebbington, P., . . . Hare, R. ball team allegedly made love to McChicken
(2009b). Psychopathy among prisoners in Eng- sandwich. Gawker. Retrieved from http://
land and Wales. International Journal of Law gawker.com/junior-varsity-baseball-team-al-
and Psychiatry, 32, 134–141. legedly-made-love-to-mcc-1708834430.
Copes, H., Hochstetler, A., & Forsyth, C. J. Kramnick, I. (Ed.). (1995). The portable Enlight-
(2013). Peaceful warriors: Codes for violence enment reader. New York: Penguin Books.
among adult male bar fighters. Criminology, Kubrin, C. E., & Weitzer, R. (2003). Retaliato-
51, 761–794. ry homicide: Concentrated disadvantage and
240 M O R A L I T Y A N D C U LT U R E

neighborhood culture. Social Problems, 50, ogy is relationship regulation: Moral motives
157–180. for unity, hierarchy, equality, and proportion-
Lamothe, D. (2014, August 28). Once again, mil- ality. Psychological Review, 118, 57–75.
itants use Guantanamo-inspired orange suit Rai, T. S., Valdesolo, P., & Graham, J. (2017).
in an execution. Washington Post. Retrieved Dehumanization increases instrumental vio-
from www.washingtonpost.com/news/check- lence, but not moral violence. Proceedings
point/wp/2014/08/28/once-again-militants- of the National Academy of Sciences, 114,
use-guantanamos-orange-jumpsuit-in-an-ex- 8511–8516.
ecution. Shweder, R. A., Much, N. C., Mahapatra, M.,
MacIntyre, A. (2007). After virtue (3rd ed.). & Park, L. (1997). The “big three” of moral-
Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame ity (autonomy, community, and divinity), and
Press. (Original work published 1981) the “big three” explanations of suffering. In A.
McGraw, A. P., Schwartz, J. A., & Tetlock, P. E. Brandt & P. Rozin (Eds.), Morality and health
(2012). From the commercial to the commu- (pp. 119–169). New York: Routledge.
nal: Reframing taboo trade-offs in religious Stark, R. (1972). Police riots: Collective violence
and pharmaceutical marketing. Journal of and law enforcement. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth.
Consumer Research, 39, 157–173. Tajfel, H., Billig, M. G., Bundy, R. P., & Fla-
Mikhail, J. (2007). Universal moral grammar: ment, C. (1971). Social categorization and
Theory, evidence and the future. Trends in intergroup behaviour. European Journal of
Cognitive Sciences, 11(4), 143–152. Social Psychology, 1, 149–178.
Milgram, S. (1963). Behavioral study of obedi- Turiel, E. (1983). The development of social
ence. Journal of Abnormal and Social Psy- knowledge: Morality and convention. Cam-
chology, 67(4), 371–378. bridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Nettle, D., Panchanathan, K., Rai, T. S., & Fiske, U.S. Department of Justice Federal Bureau of In-
A. P. (2011). The evolution of giving, sharing, vestigation. (2010). Crime in the United States,
and lotteries. Current Anthropology, 52(5), 2009: Expanded homicide data. Retrieved
747–756. from www2.fbi.gov/ucr/cius2009/offenses/
Rai, T. S., & Fiske, A. P. (2011). Moral psychol- expanded_information/homicide.html.
CHAPTER 25

A Stairway to Heaven
A Terror Management Theory Perspective
on Morality

Andrea M. Yetzer
Tom Pyszczynski
Jeff Greenberg

Why do people care about living up to moral values?

From a terror management perspective, they care because doing so


enables them to view themselves as enduring, significant contribu‑
tors to a meaningful world who will continue to exist after death,
either literally by qualifying for an afterlife, or symbolically, by con‑
tributing to something greater than themselves that will last forever.

Although the question of whether gods and ment theory (TMT; Solomon, Greenberg, &
religion are necessary for morality has been Pyszczynski, 1991, 2015) brings to the dis-
debated for centuries, the relationship be- cussion of morality and religion by focusing
tween religion and morality has received on the interplay of evolved tendencies found
surprisingly little attention in recent psy- in other species with the fruits of the sophis-
chological discussions of morality. On the ticated intellect uniquely characteristic of
one hand, many religious traditions view humankind and the existential problems to
morality as emanating from God and moral which these abilities gave rise. TMT posits
behavior as functioning to please him. On that dawning awareness of the inevitability
the other, most contemporary social psy- of death inspired monumental changes in
chological theories of religion view belief in the nature and function of morality for our
gods and religion as by-products of human species.
cognitive proclivities that evolved to serve The current zeitgeist in moral psychology
other functions, and some argue that, in and reflects two rather distinct conceptions of
of itself, religion serves no adaptive func- what drives moral thought and action. The
tion and often promotes harmful and im- moral reasoning perspective (e.g., Kohlberg,
moral behavior (e.g., Dawkins, 2006). This 1969; Piaget, 1932/1965), which dominated
chapter is focused on what terror manage- psychology for much of the 20th century,

241
242 M O R A L I T Y A N D C U LT U R E

emphasizes relatively rational moral think- gested that the seeds of morality emerged
ing that occurs with varying levels of so- as evolutionary adaptations that promoted
phistication, guided by the moral teachings order and social harmony among animals
and traditions of one’s culture. The more living in groups, which facilitated the sur-
recent moral intuitionist perspective (e.g., vival and reproduction necessary for gene
Graham et al., 2013; Haidt & Joseph, 2004; perpetuation. Indeed, behaviors that reflect
Shweder, Much, Mahapatra, & Park, 1997) caring for others, sharing, group protection,
emphasizes intuitive moral emotions that deference to leaders, and disgust have been
evolved because they facilitate group living documented in a variety of species, includ-
and social harmony and were adapted by ing chimpanzees, gorillas, wolves, and even
cultures over the course of human history to bats (Bekoff & Pierce, 2009). This idea of
meet their own particular needs. Although deep evolutionary roots of morality fits well
these perspectives emphasize different as- with Shweder et al.’s, (1997) observation
pects of morality, most psychologists agree that, despite cultural variations in expres-
that moral thought and behavior involve sion, human cultures exhibit a limited set
both rational and intuitive processes. of moral proclivities that encompasses most
TMT posits that moral values are part of of what is relevant to moral concerns. These
the cultural worldviews that protect people ideas were integrated by Haidt and col-
from anxiety triggered by their awareness leagues (Haidt & Joseph, 2004, 2007) into
of the certainty of death and that these moral foundations theory (MFT), which
worldviews set forth the standards from posits that human morality is rooted in a
which moral behavior is both enacted and set of deeply rooted moral intuitions that
evaluated. Further, because individuals are evolved to facilitate group living and that
socialized into their culture’s worldview, were later institutionalized in specific ways
beginning shortly after birth and continu- by different cultures, leading to a set of five
ing through the remainder of their lives, or six universal moral foundations. From the
morality is manifested in culturally and perspective of MFT, although all human be-
individually variable ways. Although vari- ings share these universal moral intuitions,
able in composition, the formation of cul- people differ in terms of which are empha-
tural worldviews and their standards for sized and how they are implemented.
moral behavior and moral judgment operate TMT sheds light on the forces that
through a universal human process designed changed moral functioning as our species
to maintain a sense of meaning and safety evolved into modern humans. It also sheds
that provides protection against anxiety and light on long-standing disputes about the na-
the hope of transcending death. The purpose ture of morality. In particular, it addresses
of this chapter is to use TMT to shed light the relationship between gods, religion, and
on the nature and function of moral thought morality. As cultures developed and their
and behavior. moral prescriptions evolved, they formed
narratives to explain why particular things
were moral or immoral, with religion and
The Biological Roots of Morality gods emerging to legitimize and institution-
alize these narratives. TMT fits well with
People have long believed that morality is a theories that view morality as an evolution-
uniquely human characteristic, perhaps re- ary adaptation that humankind shares with
flecting the special affection the deity feels other group-living species, but posits that
for our species. Earlier generations of moral the emergence of increasingly sophisticated
psychologists posited that morality requires intellectual abilities led to a seismic real-
cognitive capacities unique to our species ization of the inevitability of death, which
and that only relatively few people possess changed the way morality functions in our
enough of these capacities to reason at the species. Our ancestors coped with the ter-
highest moral level. However, more recent ror that their dawning awareness of death
theorizing views morality as rooted in so- produced by generating cultural worldviews
cial proclivities that humankind shares with that gave meaning to life and enduring
many other species. De Waal (1996) sug- value and significance to themselves. These
 A Terror Management Theory Perspective 243

worldviews transformed the primitive moral erwise adaptive sophisticated intellect led to
intuitions of their prehuman ancestors into awareness of the inevitability of death—the
linguistically elaborated moral values that basic, undeniable fact that life will cease
provided a stairway to heaven through someday and that death may come at any
which they could attain literal immortal- time or for many reasons. This awareness
ity and extended the impact of reputational gives rise to the potential for overwhelming
concerns into the hope for the symbolic im- terror, because it runs counter to the multi-
mortality that comes with being remem- ple biological, physiological, and psycholog-
bered as a good person after one has died. ical systems geared toward survival. If left
Indeed, awareness of death transformed the unbridled, this potential for terror would
relationship of individuals to groups, in that drastically hinder our species’ capacity for
groups are something larger and more en- adaptive functioning and be extremely un-
during than oneself that continues to exist pleasant for individual human beings.
after one has gone. TMT posits that our ancestors used the
same cognitive capacities that made them
aware of death to manage their terror by
Terror Management Theory shaping ways of construing reality to de-
fuse the threat. The problem with death is
TMT was most directly inspired by the that it can be forestalled for only so long—
work of Ernest Becker (1971, 1973, 1975), awareness of this inevitability is the essence
a cultural anthropologist who attempted to of the human existential dilemma. Because
integrate ideas from the social sciences and nothing can be done to change this ultimate
humanities to shed light on what he believed truth, our ancestors molded their under-
were the essential aspects of human nature, standing of reality to cope with the problem
drawing on the ideas of Otto Rank, William of inevitable death. Given how little was
James, George Herbert Mead, Friedrich Ni- known about the workings of the world,
etzsche, Sigmund Freud, and many others. death-denying ideas easily won out over less
TMT infuses Becker’s insights into contem- optimistic ones. Ideas about life and death
porary thinking in experimental social, cog- that helped deny this unfortunate truth were
nitive, developmental, and personality psy- especially appealing, likely to be spread, and
chology to provide an integrative framework eventually constituted cultural worldviews
for thinking about the role of evolution and that provided order, meaning, and perma-
culture in contemporary psychological func- nence to people’s conceptions of the world
tioning. TMT focuses on what self-esteem and their lives within it. Thus the poten-
is, why it’s so desperately needed, and the tial for terror that resulted from awareness
role that awareness of the inevitability of of the inevitability of death influenced the
death plays in diverse aspects of life, espe- nature of the ideas that became accepted as
cially those that bear no obvious relation to worldly and other-worldly wisdom.
the problem of mortality. Inventing cultural worldviews that imbue
TMT (Solomon et al., 1991, 2015) begins life with cosmic meaning in which human
with a consideration of how human beings beings played a significant role that does not
are both similar to and different from other end with physical death was the centerpiece
animals. Like all other species, humans are of our ancestors’ solution to their existential
powerfully motivated to continue living and dilemma. A sense of personal significance,
reproduce; in one way or another, all bodily self-esteem, was attained by viewing oneself
and motivational systems function to facili- as living up to the standards of value pre-
tate survival and reproduction, which makes scribed by one’s worldview. Thus self-esteem
it possible to pass genes on to future genera- is a cultural creation that requires exempli-
tions. However, our species evolved unique fying what is valued by one’s culture. Being
cognitive capacities for the use of symbols, a valued member of a meaningful and en-
autonoetic thought, and self-awareness that during universe makes it possible to tran-
provided increased flexibility in behavior scend death.
that enabled us to survive and prosper in di- TMT posits that our ancestors used their
verse and changing environments. This oth- ingenuity to invent a world of ideas in which
244 M O R A L I T Y A N D C U LT U R E

death is defeated and that this humanly cre- the physical world. Said differently, culture
ated spiritual dimension continues to man- affords human beings opportunities to be
age existential terror to this day. These cul- part of something greater than themselves
tural innovations drastically changed the through various group memberships, such
way our species lives, from animals coping as family, political, ethnic, national, or even
with the demands of external reality to sym- sports team affiliations. Individual contri-
bolic beings who live in a world of beliefs and butions such as works of art, literature, or
values (i.e., cultural worldviews) designed to science, contributing to the welfare of one’s
elevate them above the rest of nature. This group, and having children are all means
explains why the mental and spiritual di- to live on through these groups, as well as
mensions of existence are generally valued through the history and continued devel-
above the physical ones and why people pre- opment of the world we leave behind when
fer to think of themselves as distinct from we die. Despite their differences, the hope
and superior to other animals (for a recent of both literal and symbolic immortality re-
review of research on people’s denial of their quires living up to the moral standards of
animal nature, see Goldenberg, 2012). Be- one’s cultural worldview—which enables
cause bodies undeniably die and decay, we one to view oneself as a valuable participant
humans must be more than bodies; thus we in a meaningful reality. This is the essence
construe ourselves as spiritual and moral be- of self-esteem.
ings for whom physical existence is a mere All worldviews are individualized inter-
step toward a more perfect form of existence pretations of cultural constructions that
that is eternal and unlimited. provide meaning and safety; thus they dif-
TMT posits that people protect themselves fer across individuals due to variations in
from death-related fear with a cultural anxi- information and experience that begin with
ety buffer that consists of three components: socialization and continue over the course of
cultural worldviews that explain the nature life. TMT suggests that one’s cultural world-
of reality; self-esteem that enables people to view begins developing shortly after birth,
view themselves as beings of primary value; beginning with the reliance on our initial
and close personal attachment relationships attachment figures (for a review, see Miku-
that validate one’s cultural worldview and lincer, Florian, & Hirschberger, 2004), and
self-esteem. Cultural worldviews are com- then matures over the course of one’s psy-
prised of personally held values, morals, and chological development as we learn about
beliefs about the world that establish order, the world through parents, peers, teachers,
meaning, and permanence to life. Cultur- religious and political leaders, and others,
al worldviews provide the standards that eventually emerging as one’s own individu-
moral behavior should reflect, and against alized worldview. What initially emerges
which moral judgments are made. Whether from reliance on primary attachment fig-
it is moral to eat dogs, to masturbate, to ures to quell innate emotional reactions to
wear revealing clothing, to drink alcohol, or things that threaten one’s continued exis-
to have multiple spouses varies from culture tence gradually transitions to a desire for
to culture. Living up to these cultural stan- approval from one’s parents and significant
dards through carefully conducted behavior others, and then to a more general desire to
provides the sense of self-esteem that gives be a good and valuable person in the eyes of
one hope of literal and symbolic immortal- both other members of one’s culture and, in
ity. most cases, one’s God. Thus we are social-
Typically linked to the culture’s religious ized to strive for self-esteem by living up to
beliefs, literal immortality is the belief that the moral standards of the worldview that
life extends beyond the physical world into we come to accept as reality. When we do,
some form of afterlife, such as heaven, rein- we feel that we are enduringly significant
carnation, or nirvana. Symbolic immortal- symbolic beings, valued and protected, and
ity, on the other hand, is the hope of tran- worthy of living on literally or symbolically
scending physical death by living on in the beyond our physical deaths.
hearts and minds of the living, or by leav- The development of one’s worldview and
ing tangible artifacts of one’s existence in one’s sense of value within it reflects the old
 A Terror Management Theory Perspective 245

adage, “it takes a village.” Our worldview done to reverse the reality of human mortal-
and sense of value within it are living enti- ity, our ancestors adapted their understand-
ties that require social consensus and con- ing of the world to create an imagined re-
stant validation to maintain one’s faith that ality in which death could be transcended.
the world really is as we believe it to be, and This usually entailed construing themselves
that we really are the valued persons we be- as spiritual beings with souls who would
lieve ourselves to be. Because the beliefs and continue to exist after death.
values of our worldviews are human cre- As others have suggested (e.g., Atran,
ations that do not typically reflect observ- 2002; Boyer, 2001), early humans probably
able objective experience and often actually attributed mind and intent to inanimate as-
run counter to observable reality, our faith pects of nature, which led them to imagine
in them requires that our communities share an invisible dimension that controlled the
our beliefs and values and agree that we are natural world. With dawning awareness of
indeed living up to them. Without such cer- death, they used the concept of an immor-
tainty, our worldviews and self-esteem are tal soul as a way of distancing themselves
unable to effectively protect us from anxiety. from their mortal nature. Over time, they
As Skitka and colleagues (Skitka, Bau- gradually made the spirits more powerful,
man, & Sargis, 2005) have shown, moral transforming them into deities who con-
beliefs and behavior are the most important trolled life, death, and admission to the
determinant of people’s evaluations of both afterlife. These imaginary beings were im-
self and others. This probably reflects the bued with human characteristics that were
critical role that moral intuitions played in probably inspired by experience with pow-
regulating the behavior of our prehuman erful humans, such as their own parents,
ancestors, which likely continued to be of tribal leaders, and kings, leading to concep-
paramount importance throughout human tions of gods who are demanding, egotis-
history. Social animals require ways of tic, and sometimes cruel on the one hand,
regulating their behavior to facilitate coop- but compassionate and caring on the other.
eration, minimize conflict, and promote the As Feuerbach (1841/1989) famously put it,
interests of one’s own group over others. It “Man created God in his own image.” For
seems likely that, in addition to communi- a more thorough presentation of the TMT
cating ways to adapt to the physical environ- analysis of the emergence of specific charac-
ment, emerging human linguistic capacities teristics of gods and religion, see Pyszczyn-
were also used to help regulate interpersonal ski, Solomon, and Greenberg (2015; Pyszc-
behavior; moral injunctions and imperatives zynski, 2016). Of course we acknowledge
were likely to be more effective if they could that, like all theories of early human history,
be communicated with others. But when our analysis is speculative and likely to be
human intelligence reached the point at difficult to assess empirically. But the func-
which awareness of the inevitability of death tional aspects of this analysis are consistent
emerged, it set in motion changes in human with experimental findings regarding con-
functioning in general and morality in par- temporary human functioning.
ticular that forever altered the nature of our From the perspective of TMT, moral be-
species and the moral principles that regu- havior and moral judgment are central com-
late our behavior. Human beings became ponents of this anxiety buffering system.
cultural animals (Greenberg, Pyszczynski, Because being certain of the validity of our
& Solomon, 1986). Although many species worldviews is needed to protect us from
show signs of fear in response to threats to death anxiety, we like those who endorse
continued existence, we humans are unique our views and dislike those who challenge
in our awareness that death is our inevitable or violate them. If confidence in our cultural
fate. Although fear in response to threats worldview and self-esteem is our main line
that can be avoided or escaped is adaptive of defense against existential terror, and we
because it motivates behavior to escape the attain this confidence through the consensu-
threatening situation, fear in response to a al validation provided by others, then those
future event for which there is no solution with different worldviews and who do not
is not. Because there is nothing that can be value us highly must clearly be wrong and
246 M O R A L I T Y A N D C U LT U R E

be judged accordingly. Those who violate that dawning awareness of the inevitability
the moral dictates of our culture challenge of death among early modern humans fun-
their validity. A person who fails to abide damentally transformed the nature of mo-
by moral principles is implicitly suggesting rality by adding an important new function:
that these principles do not always apply; feeling protected from and transcendent of
because these principles are essential for our death by conceiving self as a valued contribu-
victory over death, moral transgressors must tor to a meaningful world rather than a vul-
be punished accordingly. And because our nerable, purely material animal fated only to
own immortality, both literal and symbolic, obliteration upon death. As moral beings, we
depends on being a valued participant in the can live on either literally through an endur-
meaningful reality provided by our culture, ing soul, symbolically through being revered
we are compelled to live up to the moral pre- and remembered contributors to the world,
scriptions that we have accepted as a fabric and most often, in both ways. Through mo-
our reality. Thus, because of the important rality, we learned whether we were pleasing
terror management function morality serves, the gods and also serving our ancestors and
we are highly motivated to uphold morality descendants and our tribes and nations. In
in ourselves and others. this way, doing the right thing became much
A large body of research consisting of more than just getting along with those with
over 500 studies conducted in more than 30 whom we interacted in our daily lives; it be-
countries worldwide has provided converg- came a way to warrant an eternal place in
ing support for the fundamental proposi- the world. Consequently, people could now
tions of TMT. This research has shown that justify behavior that deviated from the wish-
(1) bolstering worldviews, self-esteem, or es of powerful others; people could view
attachments reduce self-reported anxiety, behavior that offended local authorities as
physiological arousal, and anxiety-related serving more important purposes.
behavior in threatening situation; (2) re- This in no ways implies that morality lost
minders of death increase striving to main- its function of maintaining harmony within
tain one’s worldview, self-esteem and close groups. Indeed, social moral conventions
relationships; (3) threats to worldviews, self- probably served as important inspiration for
esteem, attachments increase death-thought the character and preferences of the spirit
accessibility (DTA); (4) boosts to any of world that our ancestors created. Because
these components reduce the effect of death moral behavior was so highly valued by
reminders on DTA, worldview defense, self- one’s group, people assumed that the gods
esteem striving, or attachment seeking; and shared these preferences. Indeed, ideas about
(5) evidence for the existence of an afterlife what pleased the all-knowing gods may have
reduce the effects of mortality salience (MS) originated in the preferences of powerful
on worldview defense and self-esteem striv- humans, such as parents, tribal leaders, and
ing. For more thorough reviews, see Burke, kings. This could help explain the demand-
Martens, and Faucher (2010), Greenberg, ing, jealous, egotistic, and vindictive nature
Vail, and Pyszczynski (2014), or Pyszczyn- of the gods that our ancestors created, a
ski et al. (2015). tendency that led to inspiring musings from
comedians such as George Carlin and Louis
C. K.: “Religion has actually convinced
TMT Contributions to Understanding people . . . that there’s an invisible man who
Human Morality lives in the sky who watches everything you
do, every minute of every day. And who has
Most contemporary theories of morality em- a special list of ten things he does not want
phasize the role that morality plays in facili- you to do. And if you do any of these ten
tating cooperation and minimizing conflict things, he has a special place, full of fire and
within groups and success in competition smoke and burning torture and anguish,
with other groups (e.g., Graham et al., 2013; where he will send you to remain and suf-
Haidt & Joseph, 2004; Norenzayan et al., fer and burn and choke and scream and cry,
2016). While not disputing this important forever and ever, till the end of time. But he
social function of morality, TMT suggests loves you!” (Carlin, 2002, p. 28)
 A Terror Management Theory Perspective 247

Indeed, this new function for morality in ity. Thus moral values are an integral part of
the context of an invisible dimension of spir- culturally shared conceptions of reality that
its and deities brought with it a new function set standards for behavior through which
for other people—that of validating the ex- individuals evaluate themselves and others;
istence of these death-defeating entities that people gain anxiety-buffering self-esteem
cannot be directly observed. As Festinger to the extent their behavior is seen as mea-
(1957) pointed out, people are especially suring up to the culture’s moral standards
dependent on the views of others when it (Skitka et al., 2005).
comes to domains in which there are no
clear physical referents. Since gods, spirits,
and other-worldly dimensions cannot be ob- Empirical Evidence for Death Awareness
served, people are especially dependent on in Moral Behavior and Judgment
others who share their beliefs in such things
to give them confidence in their existence. The literature supporting the fundamental
We agree with many that religions func- propositions of TMT is considerable, but
tion, in part, to promote group solidarity several studies illustrate that thoughts of
by bringing people together into a world of death inspire reactions in accordance with
fictive kinship. However, TMT views aware- rudiments of morality, including responses to
ness of death as the catalyst for the develop- perpetrators and victims of moral transgres-
ment and elaboration of spiritual worlds in sions, and increased adherence to the moral
which moral goodness is rewarded. These foundations posited by MFT. The very first
belief systems required people to come to- TMT study demonstrated that reminders of
gether to provide the social validation that death influence moral judgments, leading
belief in such invisible entities requires. For judges to set higher bond for a woman ar-
a discussion of how the pursuit of death- rested for prostitution (Rosenblatt, Green-
denying spiritual beliefs may have led to the berg, Solomon, Pyszczynski, & Lyon, 1989),
emergence of both architecture and agricul- which can be construed as a violation of the
ture as a way of feeding the large number of sanctity/degradation foundation. In a simi-
workers that were needed to build ancient lar vein, a study by Landau and colleagues
temples at Göbekli Tepe and Catahouluk, (2006) demonstrated that death reminders
which precede any known signs of agricul- led to an increase in negative evaluations of
ture by at least 1,000 years, see Solomon et sexually provocative women. Florian and
al. (2015) and Schmidt (2010). Mikulincer (1997) found that MS led to
We view the TMT perspective as comple- more severe ratings of diverse moral trans-
mentary to other contemporary theories of gressions (e.g., someone who steals money
human morality. Whereas TMT adds an from a designated education fund), as well
existential dimension to the social adapta- as harsher punishment recommendations
tionist underpinnings of MFT, MFT points for transgressors. From an MFT perspec-
to the role of intuitions that evolved in our tive, Florian and Mikulincer’s transgressor
prehuman ancestors as providing inspira- violated morals associated with care/harm
tion for the preferences they attributed to the and fairness.
gods they invented to help them cope with Indeed, there is a large body of evidence
the terror that resulted from realization of supporting the role of fear of death in each
their mortal nature. The idea that cultures of the moral foundations posited by MFT
built on evolved preverbal intuitions helps (for a review, see Kesebir & Pyszczynski,
explain the specific content of worldviews, 2011). When care-related values are salient,
for example, why concerns about caring, MS increases prosocial behavior (e.g., Jonas,
fairness, authority, group loyalty, and purity Sullivan, & Greenberg, 2013). Regarding
are so ubiquitous in human cultures. Human the fairness/cheating foundation, research
verbal capacities made it possible to embed has found that death-related cognitions are
these intuitions in death-denying narrative more accessible when learning about in-
stories that explained their origins, justified nocent victims who have been severely in-
their existence, and added a new incentive jured than victims whose condition was
for following them—the hope of immortal- due to their own actions (Hirschberger,
248 M O R A L I T Y A N D C U LT U R E

2006); conversely, derogation of the victim eral immortality is connected with religious
of a random tragedy increased when death beliefs as they provide a path for living be-
is salient (Landau, Greenberg, & Solomon, yond physical death and symbolic immor-
2004). Additionally, as justice is central to tality is tied to identification with the cul-
the fairness foundation, research has shown ture and valued contributions to it. Indeed,
that MS increases the appeal of justice-based research has found that death reminders
arguments for military action and support increase belief in an afterlife (e.g., Batson
for violence, even if the benefits of using & Stocks, 2004; Osarchuk & Tatz, 1973);
such force is low (Hirschberger et al., 2016). other research has shown increases in DTA
With regard to the sanctity/degradation following challenges to one’s religious be-
foundation, many studies have shown death liefs (Schimel, Hayes, Williams, & Jahrig,
reminders increase disgust responses (for a 2007). Similarly, MS increases nationalism,
review, see Goldenberg, 2012)—the charac- defense of one’s culture, and striving to live
teristic emotion related to this foundation. up to the values of one’s culture (e.g., Jonas
For example, research has found increases et al., 2008). Furthermore, disrespectfully
in emotional reactions to disgust primes handling a religious object or a culturally
following MS, as well as increases in DTA valued object (a flag) led to greater distress
when primed with disgusting pictures (Cox, following MS (Greenberg, Simon, Porteus,
Goldenberg, Pyszczynski, & Weise, 2007; Pyszczynski, & Solomon, 1995), as well
see also Goldenberg et al., 2001). as increased support for violence against
In terms of loyalty/betrayal, Castano and other nations among American religious
Dechesne (2005) reviewed a large body of fundamentalists and American conserva-
evidence showing that MS increases ingroup tives (Pyszczynski, Greenberg, Solomon,
favoritism, outgroup hostility, perceptions & Maxfield, 2006; Rothschild, Abdollahi,
of group entitativity, and stereotyping. Inter- & Pyszczynski, 2009). Yet in Rothschild et
estingly, research has shown that thoughts of al. (2009), the effects of MS on support for
death highlight differences between liberals political violence were reversed when par-
and conservatives in their reliance on par- ticipants were primed with compassionate
ticular moral foundations (Bassett, van Ton- values linked to Jesus in the New Testament.
geren, Green, Sonntag, & Kilpatrick, 2014; These findings were replicated in a follow-up
see also Graham, Haidt, & Nosek, 2009), study with Iranian religious fundamental-
thus illustrating death concerns play a role ists, with Koran-connected compassionate
in ingroup members consensually validating value primes leading to decreases in support
moral values that are part of their shared for military action against the United States.
worldview. Related to the authority/subver-
sion foundation, death reminders have been
found to inspire more deference to authority. Future Directions for TMT
Cohen, Solomon, Maxfield, Pyszczynski,
and Greenberg (2004) found that following So where does the TMT analysis of morality
MS, support for leaders who proclaimed the go from here? As noted above, a substantial
unique value of the ingroup increased. Addi- body of research has already documented
tional research has shown that MS increased the role of death concerns in diverse aspects
support for a local political candidate who of morality. However, the analysis presented
promoted a sense of symbolic immortality in here raises some intriguing new questions.
the community (Shepherd, Kay, Landau, & If awareness of death created a new func-
Keefer, 2011)—further demonstrating how tion for humankind’s moral (and immoral)
shared conceptions of reality play a vital role behavior, this should affect the way moral
in death transcendence. concerns impinge on thought and action.
TMT suggests that moral behavior and Death concerns would be expected to in-
moral judgment serve terror management crease the impact of religious and afterlife
functions through the promise of symbolic concerns for behavior, and thoughts of God
or literal immortality to moral conform- and the afterlife would be expected to in-
ists and derogation or punishment of moral fluence the specific moral concerns that in-
transgressors. As previously discussed, lit- fluence behavior. Similarly, death concerns
 A Terror Management Theory Perspective 249

should shift people’s moral attitudes and ac- remains), or bearing witness to (e.g., wit-
tions toward establishing a positive legacy nessing the rape of friend) an atrocious event
for future generations, something recent re- that violates one’s deeply held moral values
search is beginning to find (e.g., Maxfield et or expectations. Traumatic experiences such
al., 2014). In general, we would expect that as these can disrupt the capacity of one’s
sanctity/degradation concerns specified by worldview and self-esteem to provide pro-
MFT would take on extra importance under tection against anxiety, perhaps leading to
such circumstances. This also raises ques- PTSD symptoms in some cases, or a collapse
tions about how sanctity/degradation and of moral self-regulation, the experience of
ties with immortality granting belief systems depression or even antisocial behavior in
are incorporated into various specific moral others. Better understanding of the role of
concerns: Does the meaning of concerns morality in managing death-related anxiety
about caring, fairness, authority, loyalty, and traumatic sequelae could thus shed light
and cleanliness change when these values on many of the important problems our so-
are linked to God, an afterlife, and con- ciety is currently facing.
tributing to one’s legacy and future genera-
tions? No doubt there is substantial cultural
REFERENCES
variability in how these connections play
out, both within broad cultural groups and Atran, S. (2002). In gods we trust: The evolu-
within specific subcultural groups. There tionary landscape of religion. New York: Ox-
are also likely important individual differ- ford University Press.
ences in the way specific members of these Bassett, J. F., Van Tongeren, D. R., Green, J. D.,
cultural groups respond to the competing Sonntag, M. E., & Kilpatrick, H. (2014). The
demands placed on them by the moral teach- interactive effects of mortality salience and po-
ings of their cultures. Important questions litical orientation on moral judgments. British
also arise regarding how religious–cultural Journal of Social Psychology, 54(2), 306–323.
precepts affect the behavior of nonbelievers Batson, C. D., & Stocks, E. L. (2004). Religion:
Its core psychological function. In J. Green-
and people alienated from the mainstream berg, S. L. Koole, & T. Pyszczynski (Eds.),
secular culture. How do those who have Handbook of experimental existential psy-
rejected religious and cultural beliefs after chology (pp. 141–155). New York: Guilford
being socialized into them as children differ Press.
from those who have sustained the beliefs Becker, E. (1971). The birth and death of mean-
they were raised to accept? ing: An interdisciplinary perspective on the
Another potentially fruitful direction for problem of man (2nd ed.). New York: Free
future research may lie in applying these Press.
ideas to better understand the psychologi- Becker, E. (1973). The denial of death. New
cal processes set in motion by traumatic life York: Free Press.
Becker, E. (1975). Escape from evil. New York:
events. Anxiety buffer disruption theory Free Press.
(ABDT; Pyszczynski & Kesebir, 2011) sug- Bekoff, M., & Pierce, J. (2009). Wild justice: The
gests that traumatic experiences produce moral lives of animals. Chicago: University of
their devastating consequences by leading Chicago Press.
to a breakdown in the normal functioning Boyer, P. (2001). Religion explained: The evo-
of the anxiety buffering system. This leaves lutionary origins of religious thought. New
the affected individuals unable to effec- York: Basic Books.
tively manage their fears, essentially naked Burke, B. L., Martens, A., & Faucher, E. H.
in the face of a devastating confrontation (2010). Two decades of terror management
with death. Recent theories of trauma em- theory: A meta-analysis of mortality salience
research. Personality and Social Psychology
phasize the role of moral injury in adverse Review, 14, 155–195.
psychological outcomes, such as posttrau- Carlin, G. (2001). Napalm and Silly Putty. New
matic stress disorder (PTSD) symptoms York: Hyperion Books.
(e.g., Litz et al., 2009). Briefly, moral injury Castano, E., & Dechesne, M. (2005). On defeat-
results from the experience of perpetrating ing death: Group reification and social iden-
(e.g., killing another human being), indi- tification as immortality strategies. European
rectly experiencing (e.g., handling human Review of Social Psychology, 16, 221–255.
250 M O R A L I T Y A N D C U LT U R E

Cohen, F., Solomon, S., Maxfield, M., Pyszc- Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin,
zynski, T., & Greenberg, J. (2004). Fatal at- 21, 1221–1228.
traction: The effects of mortality salience on Greenberg, J., Vail, K., & Pyszczynski, T. (2014).
evaluations of charismatic, task-oriented, and Terror management theory and research: How
relationship-oriented leaders. Psychological the desire for death transcendence drives our
Science, 15, 846–851. strivings for meaning and significance. Ad-
Cox, C. R., Goldenberg, J. L., Pyszczynski, T., vances in Motivation Science, 1, 85–134.
& Weise, D. (2007). Disgust, creatureliness Haidt, J., & Joseph, C. (2004) Intuitive ethics:
and the accessibility of death-related thoughts. How innately prepared intuitions generate
European Journal of Social Psychology, 37, culturally variable virtues. Daedalus, 133,
494–507. 55–66.
Dawkins, R. (2006). The God delusion. Boston: Haidt, J., & Joseph, C. (2007). The moral mind:
Houghton Mifflin. How five sets of innate intuitions guide the
De Waal, F. B. (1996). Good natured: The ori- development of many culture-specific virtues,
gins of right and wrong in humans and other and perhaps even modules. In P. Carruthers, S.
animals. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Laurence, & S. Stich (Eds.), The innate mind
Press. (Vol. 3, pp. 367–391). New York: Oxford Uni-
Festinger, L. (1957). A theory of cognitive dis- versity Press.
sonance. Evanston, IL: Row Peterson. Hirschberger, G. (2006). Terror management
Feuerbach, L. A. (1989). The essence of Christi- and attributions of blame to innocent victims:
anity (G. Eliot, Trans.). New York: Prometheus Reconciling compassionate and defensive re-
Books. (Original work published 1941) sponses. Journal of Personality and Social
Florian, V., & Mikulincer, M. (1997). Fear of Psychology, 91, 832–844.
death and the judgment of social transgres- Hirschberger, G., Pyszczynski, T., Ein-Dor, T.,
sions: A multidimensional test of terror man- Shani Sherman, T., Kadah, E., Kesebir, P., &
agement theory. Journal of Personality and Park, Y. C. (2016). Fear of death amplifies re-
Social Psychology, 73, 369–380. tributive justice motivations and encourages
Goldenberg, J. L. (2012). A body of terror: De- political violence. Peace and Conflict: Journal
nial of death and the creaturely body. In P. of Peace Psychology, 22, 67–74.
R. Shaver & M. Mikulincer (Eds.), Meaning, Jonas, E., Martens, A., Niesta, D., Fritsche, I.,
mortality, and choice: The social psychology Sullivan, D., & Greenberg, J. (2008). Focus
of existential concerns (pp. 93–110). Wash- theory of normative conduct and terror man-
ington, DC: American Psychological Associa- agement theory: The interactive impact of
tion. mortality salience and norm salience on social
Goldenberg, J. L., Pyszczynski, T., Greenberg, judgment. Journal of Personality and Social
J., Solomon, S., Kluck, B., & Cornwell, R. Psychology, 95, 1239–1251.
(2001). I am not an animal: Mortality sa- Jonas, E., Sullivan, D., & Greenberg, J. (2013).
lience, disgust, and the denial of human crea- Generosity, greed, norms, and death: Differen-
tureliness. Journal of Experimental Psychol- tial effects of mortality salience on charitable
ogy: General, 130, 427–435. behavior. Journal of Economic Psychology,
Graham, J., Haidt, J., Koleva, S., Motyl, M., 35, 47–57.
Iyer, R., Wojcik, S., & Ditto, P. H. (2013). Kesebir, P., & Pyszczynski, T. (2011). A moral–
Moral foundations theory: The pragmatic va- existential account of the psychological factors
lidity of moral pluralism. In P. Devine & A. fostering intergroup conflict. Social and Per-
Plant (Eds.), Advances in experimental social sonality Psychology Compass, 5, 878–890.
psychology (Vol. 47, pp. 55–130). San Diego, Kohlberg, L. (1969). Stage and sequence: The
CA: Academic Press. cognitive-developmental approach to social-
Graham, J., Haidt, J., & Nosek, B. A. (2009). ization. In D. A. Goslin (Ed.), Handbook of
Liberals and conservatives rely on different socialization theory and research (pp. 347–
sets of moral foundations. Journal of Person- 480). Chicago: Rand McNally.
ality and Social Psychology, 96, 1029–1046. Landau, M. J., Goldenberg, J. L., Greenberg, J.,
Greenberg, J., Pyszczynski, T., & Solomon, S. Gillath, O., Solomon, S., Cox, C., . . . Pyszc-
(1986). The causes and consequences of a need zynski, T. (2006). The siren’s call: Terror man-
for self-esteem: A terror management theory. agement and the threat of men’s sexual attrac-
Public Self and Private Self, 189, 189–212. tion to women. Journal of Personality and
Greenberg, J., Simon, L., Porteus, J., Pyszczyn- Social Psychology, 90, 129–146.
ski, T., & Solomon, S. (1995). Evidence of a Landau, M. J., Greenberg, J., & Solomon, S.
terror management function of cultural icons: (2004). The motivational underpinnings of
The effects of mortality salience on the inap- religion. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 27,
propriate use of cherished cultural symbols. 743–744.
 A Terror Management Theory Perspective 251

Litz, B. T., Stein, N., Delaney, E., Lebowitz, L., theory: From genesis to revelation. In M.
Nash, W. P., Silva, C., & Maguen, S. (2009). Zanna & J. Olson (Eds.), Advances in experi-
Moral injury and moral repair in war veterans: mental social psychology (Vol. 52, pp. 1–70).
A preliminary model and intervention strate- Waltham, MA: Academic Press.
gy. Clinical Psychology Review, 29, 695–706. Rosenblatt, A., Greenberg, J., Solomon, S., Pyszc-
Maxfield, M., Greenberg, J., Pyszczynski, T., zynski, T., & Lyon, D. (1989). Evidence for ter-
Weise, D., Kosloff, S., Soenke, M., . . . Blat- ror management theory: I. The effects of mor-
ter, J. (2014). Increases in generative concern tality salience on reactions to those who violate
among older adults following reminders of or uphold cultural values. Journal of Personal-
mortality. International Journal of Aging and ity and Social Psychology, 57, 681–690.
Human Development, 79, 1–21. Rothschild, Z., Abdollahi, A., & Pyszczynski,
Mikulincer, M., Florian, V., & Hirschberger, G. T. (2009). Does peace have a prayer?: The ef-
(2004). The terror of death and the quest for fect of mortality salience, compassionate val-
love: An existential perspective on close rela- ues and religious fundamentalism on hostility
tionships. In J. Greenberg, S. L. Koole, & T. toward out-groups. Journal of Experimental
Pyszczynski (Eds.), Handbook of experimen- Social Psychology, 45, 816–827.
tal existential psychology (pp. 287–304). New Schimel, J., Hayes, J., Williams, T. J., & Jahrig,
York: Guilford Press. J. (2007). Is death really the worm at the core?:
Norenzayan, A., Shariff, A. F., Gervais, W. M., Converging evidence that worldview threat in-
Willard, A. K., McNamara, R. A., Slinger- creases death-thought accessibility. Journal of
land, E., & Henrich, J. (2016). The cultural Personality and Social Psychology, 92, 789–
evolution of prosocial religions. Behavioral 803.
and Brain Sciences, 39, 1–86. Shepherd, S., Kay, A. C., Landau, M. J., & Keef-
Osarchuk, M., & Tatz, S. J. (1973). Effect of in- er, L. A. (2011). Evidence for the specificity
duced fear of death on belief in afterlife. Jour- of control motivations in worldview defense:
nal of Personality and Social Psychology, 27, Distinguishing compensatory control from un-
256–260. certainty management and terror management
Piaget, J. (1965). The moral judgement of the processes. Journal of Experimental Social
child (M. Gabain, Trans.). New York: Free Psychology, 47, 949–958.
Press. (Original work published 1932) Schmidt, K. (2010). Göbekli Tepe—the Stone
Pyszczynski, T. (2016). God save us: A terror Age Sanctuaries: New results of ongoing ex-
management perspective on morality. In J. cavations with a special focus on sculptures
P. Forgas, L. Jussim, & P. A. M. von Lange and high reliefs. Documenta Praehistorica,
(Eds.), The social psychology of morality: The 37, 239–256.
Sydney Symposium of Social Psychology (Vol. Shweder, R. A., Much, N. C., Mahapatra, M. &
18, pp. 21–39). New York: Routledge. Park, L. (1997). The “big three” of morality
Pyszczynski, T., Abdollahi, A., Solomon, S., (autonomy, community, divinity) and the “big
Greenberg, J., Cohen, F., & Weise, D. (2006). three” explanations of suffering. In A. M.
Mortality salience, martyrdom, and military Brandt & P. Rozin (Eds.), Morality and health
might: The Great Satan versus the Axis of Evil. (pp. 119–169). New York: Routledge.
Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, Skitka, L. J., Bauman, C. W., & Sargis, E. G.
32, 525–537. (2005). Moral conviction: Another contribu-
Pyszczynski, T., Greenberg, J., Solomon, S., & tor to attitude strength or something more?
Maxfield, M. (2006). On the unique psycho- Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
logical import of the human awareness of 88, 895–917.
mortality: Theme and variations. Psychologi- Solomon, S., Greenberg, J., & Pyszczynski, T.
cal Inquiry, 17, 328–356. (1991). A terror management theory of social
Pyszczynski, T., & Kesebir, P. (2011). Anxiety behavior: The psychological functions of self-
buffer disruption theory: A terror manage- esteem and cultural worldviews. Advances in
ment account of posttraumatic stress disorder. Experimental Social Psychology, 24, 93–159.
Anxiety, Stress, and Coping, 24, 3–26. Solomon, S., Greenberg, J., & Pyszczynski, T.
Pyszczynski, T., Solomon, S., & Greenberg, J. (2015). The worm at the core: The role of
(2015). Thirty years of terror management death in life. New York: Random House.
CHAPTER 26

Moral Heroes Are Puppets

Jeremy A. Frimer

Are moral heroes (e.g., Martin Luther King, Jr.) masterminds


with exceptional moral character, or are they merely
symbolic puppets?

Exploiting attribution biases in observers, I suggest that followers


manufacture moral heroes out of ordinary persons by encouraging
charismatic speeches and propagating heroic images.

As the United States invaded Iraq and tor- leaders congratulated Obama on his award.
tured prisoners in Guantanamo Bay, pro- However, not everyone did. One sober crit-
gressive-minded Americans prayed for a ic and former Nobel Peace Prize Laureate,
champion, a moral hero to save the country’s Lech Walesa, noted the baselessness of the
collective soul. A young, charismatic sena- award, asking, “So soon? Too early. He has
tor from Illinois emerged. With little in the no contribution so far” (Chazan & Macdon-
way of executive experience and yet much in ald, 2009).
the way of oratory prowess, Barack Obama Walesa’s words were prescient. Soon came
shared a message of change, hope, and com- Obama’s fall—from deity to banality. By
passion that intoxicated and mobilized the most metrics, Obama was, quite simply, an
political Left. Pundits likened him to John F. average president. Seven years into his presi-
Kennedy and Martin Luther King, Jr., two dency, Obama’s public approval ratings sat
of the great American moral heroes of the at approximately 45%, which are remark-
20th century (Burns, 2008). Obama won the ably unremarkable for U.S. presidents at that
presidency in 2008 and then a Nobel Peace point in their tenure (“Presidential Approval
Prize 9 months later. The savior had arrived. Ratings—Barack Obama,” 2015). Experts
Many people quickly praised Obama’s rank Obama 18th among the 43 presidents,
moral greatness. Illustratively, the closing just behind George H. W. Bush (Rotting-
date for nominations for the Nobel Peace haus & Vaughn, 2015). Is it possible that the
Prize that Obama went on to win was just public, pundits, and even the Nobel Com-
12 days into his presidency. Many world mittee mistook a mediocre man for a moral

252
 Moral Heroes Are Puppets 253

mastermind? If so, how did so many people everyday intuitions about personality are
form an inflated impression of Obama? wrong—behavior is far more a product of
This chapter presents the view that situational pressures than it is of enduring
Obama’s story is representative and illustra- dispositions. Personality psychologists (e.g.,
tive of the ascendance of ordinary persons Bem & Allen, 1974; Funder & Ozer 1983)
to moral heroism and the basic social cogni- counterargued, leading to a standoff.
tive processes underlying these transforma- All-encompassing generalizations about
tions. In the eyes of followers, oratory and whether dispositions or situations are re-
visual campaigns can transform an other- sponsible for behavior are now rare. Cur-
wise ordinary person into a moral hero. This rent theories tend to be interactionist in na-
view challenges a common notion, both in ture—behavior is primarily the result of the
the population and among some research- dynamic interplay between individuals and
ers, that moral leaders are innately great situational forces (e.g., Fleeson, 2004). That
persons—intelligent, skillful, wise, and al- is, moral heroism is likely the product of the
truistic at heart (Kinsella, Ritchie, & Igou, right person (disposition) being in the right
2015). I present the view that this roman- place and time (situation). Precisely which
ticized notion of moral heroes is overblown dispositional characteristics, external forces,
and that much of moral heroism is a social and causal processes between them underlie
construction. Moral heroes, like Obama, moral heroism remains a point a departure
may be charismatic orators who communi- among scholars.
cate the right message with the right look for
their time and place (Bligh & Kohles, 2009).
The perception of moral heroism may only Theoretical Stance
be skin deep, not extending beyond these
superficial characteristics. Simply put, the Rooted in trait theory (Allport, 1937; Cat-
moral hero may be less like a mastermind tell, 1950; Murray 1938; see Ozer & Benet-
and more like a puppet. Martinez, 2006, for a review) and heavier
on the dispositional side is what I will infor-
mally call the “mastermind theory”—that
Historical Context moral heroes have a strong moral character,
which includes compelling moral reasoning
For centuries, scholars have debated just how (Kohlberg, 1984) and a heartwarming life
much individual brilliance is responsible for story (McAdams & Guo, 2015; Colby &
the influence that leaders seem to have. The Damon, 1992). Personal development or tal-
original “great man” theory of leadership ent is a necessary prerequisite for becoming
proposed that a small number of excep- a moral hero.
tional individuals (e.g., Napoleon, Martin I will call the alternative view, which is
Luther King, Jr.) is responsible for most of consistent with the social identity approach
the important changes in history. According (Tajfel & Turner, 1979), the “puppet theo-
to the great man theory, these individuals ry.” The puppet theory suggests that groups
had that “special something,” which may manufacture moral heroes out of otherwise
have included intelligence, altruism, skill, ordinary persons to symbolize the cause
and charisma; these personal qualities al- and unite followers. The Monty Python
lowed the hero to change the course of his- film, Life of Brian, satirized the life of Jesus
tory (Carlyle, 1840; Woods, 1913). Contra Christ and captured the essence of the pup-
this dispositional account were theories that pet theory. Brian was a Jewish rebel; while
attributed the apparent greatness of these running from Roman soldiers, he stumbled
figures to their historical context and to a bi- into a line of mystics and prophets. To avoid
directional relationship with their followers being detected, Brian mumbled nonsensical
(James, 1880; Spencer, 1896; Weber, 1947). blessings, which had the unintended effect of
The debate surfaced in more generalized drawing a devoted following. Brian became
form in social and personality psychology a living deity, ending with his crucifixion.
when Walter Mischel (1968) critiqued per- In the puppet theory, dispositional pre-
sonality psychology. Mischel suggested that requisites for moral heroism are only skin
254 M O R A L I T Y A N D C U LT U R E

deep, limited to impression management pressions may optimize the performance of


functions such as oratory skills and physi- followers (de Luque, Washburn, Waldman,
cal appearance. Followers play an often un- & House 2008).
recognized and important role in the lives
of moral heroes. The puppet theory is also
consistent with evolutionary accounts posit- Evidence
ing that maintaining hierarchy (A. P. Fiske,
1992) and sacralizing mundane objects or Next, I describe evidence that supports the
people (Atran & Norenzayan, 2004; Tet- puppet theory, in form of two modes by
lock, 2003) binds followers into cooperative which followers prop up moral heroes.
groups, which tend to out-compete discor-
dant groups and lone individuals for scant
The Hero’s Speech
resources. The puppet theory suggests that
followers romanticize and elevate a person First, I suggest that followers prop up moral
to the status of moral hero because doing so heroes by encouraging them to make emo-
confers upon group members an adaptive tionally stirring, charismatic, prosocial
advantage. speeches. These speeches may cause audi-
Sacralizing an object, a practice, or a per- ences to form an impression that the speaker
son binds people together, but it may achieve is a moral hero. To experience this phenom-
this end by suppressing rational thought enon, recall Obama’s speech at the 2004
processes (Haidt, 2012). Communication Democratic National Convention (DNC)
surrounding moral heroes exploits the un- that launched him on the world stage:
critical thinking of starstruck followers,
deceiving them into becoming loyal group If there’s a child on the south side of Chicago
members. Observers effectively apply the who can’t read, that matters to me, even if it’s
“duck test” when encountering potential not my child. If there’s a senior citizen some-
where who can’t pay for her prescription and
moral heroes—if it looks like a duck, and has to choose between medicine and the rent,
quacks like a duck, and walks like a duck, that makes my life poorer, even if it’s not my
then it is probably a duck. Analogously, if grandmother. If there’s an Arab American
someone talks like a moral hero and looks family being rounded up without benefit of
like a moral hero, then he or she must be a an attorney or due process, that threatens my
moral hero. The duck test may be especially civil liberties.
likely to fail in the detection of moral he-
roes because of the incentive structure built Obama and moral heroes tell tear-jerk-
into impression formation. To maximize ing, morally elevating stories that may seem
both social and material rewards, people do unique. However, these speeches conform
best when they appear moral to others while to a pattern. The hero’s story begins with a
behaving selfishly in private (Batson, 2008; childhood mentor who leads the young hero
Frimer, Schaefer, & Oakes, 2014; Shariff to witness the suffering of others. Through
& Norenzayan, 2007; von Hippel & Triv- this experience, the budding moral hero de-
ers, 2011). The costs associated with sending velops a clear moral purpose and decides to
such an elaborate signal of their moral virtue repair the problems through some altruis-
(Lyons, 2005) may be worth it to the hero: tic goal pursuit (McAdams & Guo, 2015;
heroes tend to have lots of children (Rusch, McNamee & Wesolik, 2014; Walker &
­
Leunissen, & van Vugt, 2015). Frimer, 2007).
The perception of moral heroism may also These stirring remarks tick all the boxes
benefit followers by serving a symbolic and in the charismatic speech checklist, which
motivational function (Allison & Goethals, include: a shared history and identity; praise
2010; Pfeffer, 1981). Moral heroes tend to for followers’ agency; similarities between
emerge during times of crisis (Bligh, Kohles, followers and the leader; shared moral val-
& Meindl, 2004; Haslam et al., 2001; Pillai ues, long term goals, faith, and hope. And
& Meindl, 1998; Weber, 1947). Even though they avoid pitfalls such as discussing indi-
followers may hold erroneously romanti- viduals’ self-interest, instrumental think-
cized impressions of their leaders, these im- ing, and short-term goals (Shamir, Arthur,
 Moral Heroes Are Puppets 255

& House, 1994). Communicating a message can intentionally manipulate an audience’s


that resonates with a group’s core values perceptions of them and rally cause-promot-
and oratory skills are critical components of ing behavior merely by delivering a charis-
a charismatic speech (Awamleh & Gardner, matic speech.
1999; Frimer, Biesanz, Walker, & MacKin-
lay, 2013).
The Hero Pose
Evidence is accumulating that these
speeches are effective at convincing audienc- Portraiture is a second mode by which fol-
es of the speaker’s greatness but reveal sur- lowers manufacture moral heroes. Once
prisingly little about the speaker’s character. again, the story of Barack Obama is illus-
Independent of their behavior as leaders, trative. As Obama ran for the presidency
politicians gain approval from the popula- in 2008, an image symbolizing his message
tion simply by communicating in a prosocial and his campaign went viral. Above the
manner. A recent study found that prosocial words hope, change, or progress was a styl-
language during floor debates in the U.S. ized blue-and-red portrait of Obama, gazing
Congress predicts public approval 6 months pensively upwards and to his left (the view-
later (Frimer, Aquino, Gebauer, Zhu, & er’s right).
Oakes, 2015). In fact, prosocial language is This gaze turns out to be the quintes-
the best single explanation for why Ameri- sential posture of the moral hero. Images
cans approve or disapprove of their govern- of other moral heroes, such as Martin Lu-
ment—surpassing other explanations such ther King, Jr., Mother Teresa, and Nelson
as Congressional productivity and conflict, Mandela, also depict them with this posture
the economy, and world events. more often than one would expect merely
In laboratory studies, delivering a proso- by chance and more often than images of
cial speech changes how an audience per- such celebrities as Elvis Presley, Brad Pitt,
ceives the speaker, creating expectations and Marilyn Monroe do (Frimer & Sinclair,
that the prosocial speaker will behave gen- 2016). This curious tendency for images to
erously toward a stranger. However, people depict heroes gazing up and to the viewer’s
who deliver prosocial speeches turn out to be right may be the result of their ideologically
no more likely to behave generously toward minded followers selecting and propagating
a stranger than people who use less flowery these specific images to promote the com-
language (Frimer, Zhu, & Decter-Frain, mon cause. When tasked with selecting a
2016). Ordinary people are surprisingly flex- single image of a leader to go on a poster
ible with their words, able to ramp up the to represent the social cause, people tend to
prosocial language when they like (Frimer select the up-and-right posture (Frimer &
et al., 2015). Talk seems to be a deceptively Sinclair, 2016).
poor harbinger of action and personal virtue. What do these followers perceive in these
Underlying this misattribution is a generic up-and-right poses that make the depicted
psychological process. Prosocial speeches individual seem so heroic? One possibility is
may build false impressions because of the that these poses make the subject seem calm
correspondence bias, whereby audiences and rational. The left cerebral hemisphere,
make dispositional inferences from small which is more responsible for voluntary
verbal displays, even when the audience is emotional displays, controls the muscles on
aware of the situational forces that led to the left side of the face (Rinn, 1984). Stem-
the speech (Jones & Harris, 1967). Audi- ming from this basic left–right asymmetry
ences default to making dispositional infer- in neurological functioning, the right side of
ences because the speaker is in plain view the face may be less emotionally expressive
(perceptually salient), whereas the forces than the left (e.g., Sackeim, Gur, & Saucy,
that coaxed the speaker into saying what he 1978). Perhaps followers select up-and-right
or she did are invisible (Gilbert & Malone, posed images of their leaders to portray the
1995). The present findings suggest that subject as rational and calm, and thus ready
speeches serve a distinctly social function— to make good decisions as a leader.
to persuade others (S. T. Fiske, 1992). Future At a semantic level, the hero’s gaze (up
research should investigate whether people and to the viewer’s right) may also activate
256 M O R A L I T Y A N D C U LT U R E

a system of conceptual metaphors that link and Mary Beth Cahill, who selected Obama
intrinsically meaningless directions to per- to give the 2004 DNC speech, and Shepard
sonal virtue (Lakoff & Johnson, 1980). The Fairey, the artist behind the stylized red-
horizontal dimension is steeped in meta- and-blue portrait of an inspirationally gaz-
phor, with the right being superior to the ing Obama. How the larger group also plays
left. This evident in terms such as righteous, a causal role also remains unclear. A final
the term right, meaning “correct,” and the extension is to devise and test procedures for
Latin word sinister, meaning “left.” More- minimizing the persuasive effects endemic in
over, the vertical dimension also carries moral heroism, to facilitate leadership selec-
evaluative tones, with up being better than tion based on substantive action (e.g., track
down. This is evident in such terms as uplift- record) and less so on baseless persuasive
ing, reach for the skies, and heaven above tactics.
(Haidt & Algoe, 2004). The term upright When asked to name famous moral heroes
neatly summarizes the metaphorically supe- of recent years, Americans list Martin Lu-
rior direction. Resultantly, looking upward ther King, Jr., Nelson Mandela, Mohandas
and looking rightward (in the viewer’s ref- Gandhi, and John F. Kennedy—but rarely
erence) makes a person look warm, compe- Obama (Frimer & Sinclair, 2016). What
tent, proud, and optimistic (but not more at- did the former individuals do that Obama
tractive; Frimer & Sinclair, 2016). did not? Perhaps Obama did something that
The hero gaze may also communicate a that the others did not, which caused his
sense of agency—that the moral hero has fall from grace. Whereas the classic moral
the capacity to make things happen. People heroes died by an assassin’s bullet or were
conceive of agents as being on the left. When incarcerated, Obama actually had to show
asked to draw an event in which a circle his character—he took office.
pushes a square, people tend to draw the
circle (the agent) to the left of the square (the
patient; Chatterjee, Southwood, & Basilico, REFERENCES
1999). By depicting the hero facing toward
Allison, S. T., & Goethals, G. R. (2010) Heroes:
the viewer’s right, the viewer may perceive What they do and why we need them. New
the hero as agentic. Future research should York: Oxford University Press
investigate the underlying perceptual mech- Allport, G. W. (1937). Personality: A psychologi-
anisms responsible for the hero pose and test cal interpretation. Oxford, UK: Holt.
whether seeing the hero pose can mobilize Atran, S., & Norenzayan, A. (2004). Religion’s
cause-promoting behavior from followers. evolutionary landscape: Counterintuition,
commitment, compassion, communion. Be-
havioral and Brain Sciences, 27, 713–770.
Extension and Expansion Awamleh, R., & Gardner, W. L. (1999). Percep-
tions of leader charisma and effectiveness: The
effects of vision content, delivery, and organi-
What evidence would falsify the puppet zational performance. Leadership Quarterly,
theory? A finding that budding moral heroes 10, 345–373.
have character strengths that are unrelated Batson, C. D. (2008). Moral masquerades: Ex-
to impression management, such as unob- perimental exploration of the nature of moral
trusive measures of altruism, honesty, and motivation. Phenomenology and the Cogni-
empathy, would constitute falsifying evi- tive Sciences, 7, 51–66.
dence. Bem, D. J., & Allen, A. (1974). On predicting
An expansion of the theory is to investigate some of the people some of the time: The
other mechanisms by which groups create search for cross-situational consistencies in
the perception of moral heroism. One prom- behavior. Psychological Review, 81, 506–520.
Bligh, M. C., & Kohles, J. C. (2009). The endur-
ising avenue is the giving of awards (e.g., the ing allure of charisma: How Barack Obama
Nobel Peace Prize, the Carnegie Medal). A won the historic 2008 presidential election.
second expansion is to work out how critical Leadership Quarterly, 20, 483–492.
followers select and prop up moral heroes. Bligh, M. C., Kohles, J. C., & Meindl, J. R.
In the case of Obama, these active followers (2004). Charisma under crisis: Presidential
may have been people such as Jack Corrigan leadership, rhetoric, and media responses be-
 Moral Heroes Are Puppets 257

fore and after the September 11th terrorist at- look up and to the viewer’s right. Personality
tacks. Leadership Quarterly, 15, 211–239. and Social Psychology Bulletin, 42, 400–410.
Burns, P. J. (2008, December 7). Kennedy, King, Frimer, J. A., Zhu, L., & Decter-Frain, A. (2016).
and now Obama. Huffington Post. Available Do givers leak their social motives through
at www.huffingtonpost.com/peter-j-burns/ what they talk about?: Maybe not. Manu-
kennedy-king-and-now-obam_ b_ 141914. script submitted for publication.
html. Funder, D. C., & Ozer, D. J. (1983). Behavior as
Carlyle, T. (1840). On heroes, hero-worship and a function of the situation. Journal of Person-
the heroic in history. London: Chapman & ality and Social Psychology, 44, 107–112.
Hall. Gilbert, D. T., & Malone, P. S. (1995). The cor-
Cattell, R. B. (1950). Personality: A systematic respondence bias. Psychological Bulletin, 117,
theoretical and factual study. New York: Mc- 21–38.
Graw-Hill. Haidt, J. (2012). The righteous mind: Why good
Chatterjee, A., Southwood, M. H., & Basilico, people are divided by politics and religion.
D. (1999). Verbs, events and spatial represen- New York: Random House.
tations. Neuropsychologia, 37(4), 395–402. Haidt, J., & Algoe, S. (2004). Moral amplifica-
Chazan, G., & Macdonald, A. (2009, October 11). tion and the emotions that attach us to saints
Nobel committee’s decision courts controver- and demons. In J. Greenberg, S. L. Koole, & T.
sy. Wall Street Journal. Retrieved from www. Pyszczynski (Eds.), Handbook of experimen-
wsj.com/articles/SB125509603349176083. tal existential psychology (pp. 322–335). New
Colby, A., & Damon, W. (1992). Some do care: York: Guilford Press.
Contemporary lives of moral commitment. Haslam, S. A., Platow, M. J., Turner, J. C., Reyn-
New York: Free Press. olds, K. J., McGarty, C., Oakes, P. J., . . .
de Luque, M. S., Washburn, N. T., Waldman, D. Veenstra, K. (2001). Social identity and the ro-
A., & House, R. J. (2008). Unrequited profit: mance of leadership: The importance of being
How stakeholder and economic values relate seen to be “doing it for us.” Group Processes
to subordinates’ perceptions of leadership and and Intergroup Relations, 4, 191–205.
firm performance. Administrative Science James, W. (1880). Great men, great thoughts
Quarterly, 53, 626–654. and the environment. Atlantic Monthly, 46,
Fiske, A. P. (1992). The four elementary forms 441–459.
of sociality: Framework for a unified theory Jones, E. E., & Harris, V. A. (1967). The attri-
of social relations. Psychological Review, 99, bution of attitudes. Journal of Experimental
689–723. Social Psychology, 3, 1–24.
Fiske, S. T. (1992). Thinking is for doing: Por- Kinsella, E. L., Ritchie, T. D., & Igou, E. R.
traits of social cognition from Daguerreotype (2015). Zeroing in on heroes: A prototype
to laserphoto. Journal of Personality and So- analysis of hero features. Journal of Personal-
cial Psychology, 63, 877–889. ity and Social Psychology, 108, 114–127.
Fleeson, W. (2004). Moving personality beyond Kohlberg, L. (1984). Essays on moral develop-
the person–situation debate: The challenge ment: Vol. 2. The psychology of moral devel-
and the opportunity of within-person vari- opment. San Francisco: Harper & Row.
ability. Current Directions in Psychological Lakoff, G., & Johnson, M. (1980). The meta-
Science, 13, 83–87. phorical structure of the human conceptual
Frimer, J. A., Aquino, K., Gebauer, J. E., Zhu, system. Cognitive Science, 4, 195–208.
L., & Oakes, H. (2015). A decline in proso- Lyons, M. T. (2005). Who are the heroes?: Char-
cial language helps explain public disapproval acteristics of people who rescue others. Jour-
of the U.S. Congress. Proceedings of the Na- nal of Cultural and Evolutionary Psychology,
tional Academy of Sciences of the USA, 112, 3, 245–254.
6591–6594. McAdams, D. P., & Guo, J. (2015). Narrating
Frimer, J. A., Biesanz, J. C., Walker, L. J., & the generative life. Psychological Science, 26,
MacKinlay, C. W. (2013). Liberals and con- 475–483.
servatives rely on common moral foundations McNamee, S., & Wesolik, F. (2014). Heroic be-
when making moral judgments about influen- havior of Carnegie Medal heroes: Parental in-
tial people. Journal of Personality and Social fluence and expectations. Peace and Conflict:
Psychology, 104, 1040–1059. Journal of Peace Psychology, 20, 171–173.
Frimer, J. A., Schaefer, N. K., & Oakes, H. Mischel, W. (1968). Personality and assessment.
(2014). Moral actor, selfish agent. Journal of London: Wiley,
Personality and Social Psychology, 106, 790– Murray, H. A. (1938). Explorations in personal-
802. ity. New York: Oxford University Press
Frimer, J. A., & Sinclair, L. (2016). Moral heroes Ozer, D. J., & Benet-Martínez, V. (2006). Per-
258 M O R A L I T Y A N D C U LT U R E

sonality and the prediction of consequential Sackeim, H. A., Gur, R. C., & Saucy, M. C.
outcomes. Annual Review of Psychology, 57, (1978). Emotions are expressed more intense-
401–421. ly on the left side of the face. Science, 202,
Pfeffer, J. (1981). Management as symbolic ac- 434–436.
tion: The creation and maintenance of orga- Shamir, B., Arthur, M. B., & House, R. J.
nizational paradigms. In L. L. Cummings & (1994). The rhetoric of charismatic leadership:
B. M. Staw (Eds.), Research in organizational A theoretical extension, a case study, and im-
behavior (Vol. 3, pp. 1–52). Greenwich, CT: plications for research. Leadership Quarterly,
JAI Press. 5, 25–42.
Pillai, R., & Meindl, J. R. (1998). Context and Shariff, A. F., & Norenzayan, A. (2007). God
charisma: A “meso” level examination of the is watching you: Priming God concepts in-
relationship of organic structure, collectivism, creases prosocial behavior in an anonymous
and crisis to charismatic leadership. Journal of economic game. Psychological Science, 18,
Management, 24, 643–671. 803–809.
Presidential approval ratings—Barack Obama. Spencer, H. (1896). The study of sociology. New
(2015). Retrieved from www.gallup.com/ York: Appleton.
poll/116479/barack-obama-presidential-job- Tajfel, H., & Turner, J. C. (1979). An integrative
approval.aspx. theory of intergroup conflict. In W. G. Austin
Rinn, W. E. (1984). The neuropsychology of fa- & S. Worchel (Eds.), The social psychology of
cial expression: A review of the neurological intergroup relations (pp. 33–47). Monterey,
and psychological mechanisms for producing CA: Brooks/Cole.
facial expressions. Psychological Bulletin, 95, Tetlock, P. E. (2003). Thinking the unthinkable:
52–77. Sacred values and taboo cognitions. Trends in
Rottinghaus, B., & Vaughn, J. (2015, Febru- Cognitive Sciences, 7, 320–324.
ary 16). New rankings of U.S. presidents von Hippel, W., & Trivers, R. (2011). The evolu-
put Lincoln at no. 1, Obama at 18; Ken- tion and psychology of self-deception. Behav-
nedy judged the most overrated. Washington ioral and Brain Sciences, 34, 1–16.
Post. Retrieved from www.washingtonpost. Walker, L. J., & Frimer, J. A. (2007). Moral per-
com /news/monkey-cage/wp/ 2015/ 02 /16/ sonality of brave and caring exemplars. Jour-
new-ranking-of-u-s-presidents-puts-lincoln- nal of Personality and Social Psychology, 93,
1- obama-18 -kennedy-judged- most- over- 845–860.
rated/?utm_term=.5e599c4ec05f. Weber, M. (1947). The theory of social and eco-
Rusch, H., Leunissen, J. M., & van Vugt, M. nomic organization. New York: Free Press.
(2015). Historical and experimental evidence Woods, F. A. (1913). The influence of monarchs:
of sexual selection for war heroism. Evolution Steps in a new science of history. New York:
and Human Behavior, 36, 367–373. Macmillan.
CHAPTER 27

Morality
A Historical Invention

Edouard Machery

Is morality universal?

According to the historicist view of morality presented in this chapter,


morality is a learned, culturally specific phenomenon; the distinction
between moral judgment and other normative judgments is not a
product of evolution, but it is rather a historical invention that reuses
a motley of evolved processes and must be relearned by children
generation after generation.

Morality is often taken to be a fundamen- draw this distinction: Although they may be
tal building block of cognition on a par unable to define what makes a norm moral
with folk psychology, the intuitive theory or an action morally wrong (in contrast to
of agents, and folk biology, all of which just wrong), Westerners have no difficulty
are universal and the products of evolu- classifying an assertion such as “Thou shall
tion. This fundamentalist view dominates not kill” as expressing a moral norm and as-
theorizing about morality at the intersec- sertions such as “Look left before crossing
tion of anthropology and evolutionary bi- the street” and “Men should wear a tie at
ology, and it has been extremely influential work” as expressing nonmoral norms. But is
in moral psychology and social cognitive this distinction innate and universal, or is it
neuroscience. An important consequence of rather learned and culturally specific?
the fundamentalist view of morality is the The historicist view proposes that moral-
claim that people across cultures and times ity is culturally specific—morality is only
intuitively distinguish two types of norms found in some cultures—and instead of
(i.e., attitudes about what one ought to do being a product of evolution, it is a product
or not to do, about what is permissible or of particular, still ill-understood, historical
impermissible, or about whether an action, circumstances. Developmentally, children
a person, or a character trait is bad or good, learn to single out a subset of norms and
right or wrong): moral norms and nonmoral values, which comes to constitute the moral
norms. There is no doubt that Westerners domain. These norms acquire a distinctive

259
260 M O R A L I T Y A N D C U LT U R E

motivational, emotional, and cognitive role. tional, and emotional role of these norms
From a cognitive point of view, morality de- draws on universal, evolved components of
pends on a subset of the cognitive process- social and normative cognition.
es, emotions, and motivational structures
involved in social cognition. One can thus
draw an analogy between morality and the Historical Context
capacity to play chess: Chess playing relies
on evolved, universal cognitive processes The historicist view of morality was in part
(visual recognition, spatial memory, etc.), developed in reaction to an ever-growing
but it is not a product of evolution; it is the literature at the intersection of evolutionary
outcome of particular historical and cultur- biology, anthropology, psychology, and phi-
al conditions, and people must learn to play losophy (e.g., Singer, 1981, 2000; Boehm,
chess. 1982, 1999; Alexander, 1987; Ruse, 1986;
Social behavior depends on a complex Dennett, 1995; Kitcher, 1998; Wilson, 2002;
set of evolved processes, many of which are Joyce, 2006; Street, 2006). Contributors to
homologous to processes found in other this literature set themselves the task of ex-
species, and some of which are only found plaining morality in evolutionary terms—
among human beings. These social process- their goal is then to provide plausible, al-
es involved emotions (e.g., anger), emotional beit admittedly speculative, scenarios that
processes (e.g., empathy), and motivational would explain why natural selection would
structures (e.g., a motivation to help people have favored morality—or to determine
in need). Of central importance for human the philosophical significance of the evo-
social behavior is normative cognition, a lution of morality. A pervasive problem in
universal, evolved building block of human this literature is that the notion of morality
cognition. Normative cognition involves the typically remains unexplained (Machery &
capacity to make normative judgments; a Stich, 2013; Stich, Chapter 55, this volume).
memory store for norms one is committed Sometimes evolutionary-minded scientists
to; a learning system for norms; a set of mo- use “morality” to refer, more or less explic-
tivational structures, including a motivation itly, to phenomena distinct from morality,
to comply with the norms one endorses and such as psychological altruism, behavioral
a motivation to punish norm violators; and altruism (Alexander, 1987), or fairness
emotions (e.g., outrage or disgust elicited by (Baumard, André, & Sperber, 2013). Other
norm violation, admiration or even awe at times, it remains entirely unclear what this
normative behaviors, guilt and shame elic- trait is—morality—that is to be explained in
ited by one’s own norm violations). Some evolutionary terms.
components of normative cognition may The second impulse for the development of
be specific to the domain of norms, others the historicist view of morality comes from
may be domain-general: Among the latter, the cultural and demographic research on
outrage elicited by norm violation is, for in- morality associated with Richard Shweder,
stance, just a form of anger, and the memory Jonathan Haidt, and Paul Rozin on the one
store for norms is probably not a dedicated, hand (e.g., Rozin, Lowery, Imada, & Haidt,
dissociable memory store. Normative cogni- 1999) and with Jonathan Haidt and Jesse
tion is universal, develops early and reliably, Graham on the other hand (e.g., Haidt &
and may well be specific to human beings. Joseph, 2004; Graham et al., 2013; Haidt,
In some cultures, morality builds up on 2012). This body of research—in particu-
normative cognition and on other compo- lar, Rozin et al.’s CAD model or Graham
nents of social cognition. Relying probably and Haidt’s moral foundations theory—­
on the cues provided by their social environ- purports to show that the domain of moral-
ment (parents and peers), children single out ity—roughly, what counts as a moral norm,
a subset of norms among the norms that are motivation, or value—varies across demo-
prevalent in their environment and learn to graphic groups in a predictable manner. For
treat these norms in a distinctive manner. instance, American conservatives are said
These norms come to constitute the moral to moralize a broader set of values than lib-
domain. The distinctive cognitive, motiva- erals, including values related to loyalty to
 Morality: A Historical Invention 261

one’s group (e.g., patriotism) and author- 1983), from a very early age on (2 1/2 years
ity (e.g., Graham, Haidt, & Nosek, 2009). in some studies), people distinguish two
That people value different things across de- kinds of wrong action. Those actions (e.g.,
mographic groups (e.g., across cultures) or hitting another child) that are judged worse
that there are different norms across groups are also judged to be authority-independent
is not really surprising, although the extent (they would still be wrong if the relevant au-
of this variation may be unexpected. What thority allowed people to act this way) and to
is surprising is the claim that the moral do- be wrong everywhere; finally, people justify
main varies as a function of demographic their opinion that these actions are wrong
variables. However, establishing that claim by appealing to considerations of harm,
requires a distinction between moral val- justice, or rights. Turiel and colleagues call
ues and nonmoral values or between moral the norms prohibiting these actions “moral
norms and nonmoral norms, and psycholo- norms.” By contrast, those actions (e.g., leav-
gists and anthropologists committed to ing the classroom without asking permission)
the cultural and demographic research on that are judged to be less wrong are judged
morality have often been silent about how to be authority-dependent (they would not
to draw this distinction. Some definitions be wrong if the relevant authority allowed
identify morality with the whole normative people to act this way) and to be wrong only
domain, others are stipulative and, thus, ar- locally; finally, people justify their opinion
bitrary. that these actions are wrong by appealing
To determine whether morality is a trait to authority and convention. Turiel and col-
that evolved and to determine whether the leagues call the norms prohibiting these ac-
moral domain genuinely varies across cul- tions “conventional norms.” On the basis
tures and demographic groups requires of their substantial empirical research, they
delineating the moral domain: identifying argue that the distinction between moral and
what distinguishes moral norms from other conventional norms is a universal and, plau-
norms (such as etiquette norms, coordi- sibly, ancient feature of the human mind.
nation norms, and prudential norms) and Turiel and colleagues’ moral domain the-
moral values from other values (Machery, ory has been widely endorsed (e.g., Blair,
2012). Attempting to delineate the moral 1995; Nichols, 2004), but recent findings
domain raises at least three distinct clusters suggest that the separation of wrong ac-
of empirical questions: tions into two kinds is an artifact of the re-
stricted class of actions used by Turiel and
1. Do moral norms differ from other kinds colleagues to distinguish moral and con-
of norms, and in what ways? Do people ventional norms. When a larger class of ac-
treat them differently, and how? tions is used, the different features that are
2. Is this distinction universal and ancient? meant to characterize moral and nonmoral
3. Where does this distinction come from? norms (wrongness, authority-dependence,
Is it an adaptation? If so, what is its func- universality, justification type) come apart,
tion and what is its phylogeny? Or, rath- and the conjunction of these properties fail
er, is it a cultural invention? to distinguish moral from nonmoral norms
(Shweder, Mahapatra, & Miller, 1987;
The historicist view of morality grew out Haidt, Koller, & Dias, 1993; Kelly, Stich,
of the failures of previous attempts to an- Haley, Eng, & Fessler, 2007).
swer these questions and out of new research More recently, Nichols (2004) has ar-
aimed at delineating the moral domain. gued that the distinction between moral and
nonmoral norms is to be drawn in terms of
emotions. Nichols distinguishes two types
Theoretical Stance of norms: affect-backed norms and norms
that are not backed by affect. The former
The historicist view stands in sharp con- prohibit actions that independently elicit an
trast with previous attempts to delineate the emotional reaction. “Thou shall not kill”
moral domain. According to Turiel and col- expresses an affect-backed norm because it
leagues’ moral domain theory (e.g., Turiel, prohibits an action—that is, murder—that
262 M O R A L I T Y A N D C U LT U R E

elicits a negative emotional reaction. “Wear one’s policy views, difficulty in resolving
a tie at work” does not express an affect- conflict, intolerance of disagreement, will-
backed norm because the sight of people ingness to use violence, willingness to flout
who do not wear a tie at work does not elicit the law, and immunity to the influence of
any emotional reaction. group majority opinion (see Skitka, 2010,
Nichols’s (2004) proposal for delineat- for a review). Using Asch’s paradigm (1951,
ing the moral domain—sentimental rules 1955), Lisciandra, Postma-Nilsenová, and
theory—is undermined by the following Colombo (2013) have also shown that West-
dilemma. Either being an affect-backed ern participants’ opinions are less likely
norm is sufficient for being moral, or it is to be influenced by group opinion when it
not. It cannot be sufficient because, as Nich- bears on a moral issue. Wright, Cullum, and
ols (2002) shows, there are affect-backed Schwab (2008) examined how people split
norms—namely, etiquette norms forbidding a windfall profit between themselves and
disgusting actions—that are not moral. On other participants who disagree with them
the other hand, if being an affect-backed about a particular issue and found that peo-
norm is not sufficient for being moral, Nich- ple split less fairly when they view the topic
ols seems unable to explain the phenomenon of disagreement as moral.
of moralization, which happens when an This body of evidence suggests that
action or a trait previously judged morally Westerners’ distinction between moral and
neutral (e.g., smoking or obesity) becomes nonmoral norms is more than just verbal:
morally wrong because it starts eliciting a Rather, it marks distinct psychological con-
negative emotion (e.g., Rozin, Markwith, & structs. But do other cultures draw a similar
Stoess, 1997; Rozin, 1999). distinction? And does it have the same psy-
Finally, Gray, Young, and Waytz (2012) chological significance?
have recently proposed that norms against The first body of evidence to support the
inflicting pain constitute the essence of the claim that the domain of morality is cultur-
moral domain (for another recent propos- ally specific and the product of particular
al, see Sousa, Holbrook, & Piazza, 2009). historical circumstances comes from linguis-
However, this proposal does not do justice tics. In line with the proposal that normative
to moral norms against victimless actions, cognition is a fundamental building block of
such as incest prohibition and other taboos. cognition, deontic modals—that is, words
Any account that ignores this kind of norms translating ought—and translations of the
or that relegates them to the periphery of the normative predicates good and bad are ap-
moral domain is unsatisfying (but see Gray, parently found in every language (Wierz-
Schein, & Ward, 2014, for discussion). bicka, 2001, 167–169; Wierzbicka, 2007).
By contrast, expressions related to the moral
domain in the United States are not found
Evidence in all languages. Whereas judgments about
whether something is “right” and “wrong”
Norms that Westerners recognize as moral in the United States are tightly connected
form a distinct psychological kind (Skitka, to whether the action belongs to the moral
Bauman, & Sargis, 2005; Skitka, Bauman, domain (Skitka, 2010), translations of right
& Mullen, 2008; Skitka, 2010). Although and wrong are not found in every language.
recognizing a norm as moral correlates Furthermore, many languages do not have a
with attitude strength, for Westerners moral translation of moral and thus do not lexical-
norms are not simply strongly endorsed ize the distinction between moral and non-
norms (i.e., norms Westerners are certain moral norms (Wierzbicka, 2007, p. 68). If
of), norms about subjectively important is- the moral domain were a fundamental fea-
sues, or norms that are connected to their ture of human cognition, we would expect
self-concept. Variance in whether norms are the distinction between moral and nonmoral
viewed as moral contributes to explaining a norms to be lexicalized in every language, as
large range of phenomena among Western- are deontic modals and the distinction be-
ers: motivation to act politically to promote tween good and bad.
 Morality: A Historical Invention 263

The second body of evidence comes from Extension and Expansion


an ongoing research program meant to de-
termine how people divide the norms they The historicist view of morality has impor-
endorse into different kinds (see Machery, tant consequences for moral philosophy.
2012, for a description). In line with the Over the last 30 years, philosophers have
psychological evidence reviewed above, un- appealed to the alleged evolution of moral-
published preliminary results suggest that ity to either “debunk” morality—that is, to
Americans draw a sharp distinction between support the view that we are not justified
moral and nonmoral norms and also distin- in holding our moral beliefs—or to defend
guish different kinds of moral and nonmoral morality (for the former, see, e.g., Ruse,
norms. In contrast, Indian participants do 1986; Joyce, 2006; Street, 2006; for the
not seem to draw the distinction between latter, see, e.g., Rottschaefer, 1998). These
moral and nonmoral norms, suggesting that arguments turn out to be futile if morality
the moral domain may not be a universal. did not evolve (Machery & Mallon, 2010).
Much additional evidence needs to be col- There is naturally a sense in which morality
lected to support the historicist view of mo- evolved: Just like any other human trait—
rality. Anthropological and cross-cultural for example, chess, driving, or scientific
information remains insufficient to be fully cognition—it rests on evolved psychological
confident that the distinction between moral capacities and processes. Exactly as chess
and nonmoral norms is only culturally and relies on spatial memory and means–end
historically local. reasoning—psychological capacities with a
The historical details remain entirely un- deep phylogeny—morality relies on evolved
known: What historical circumstances re- capacities, including human normative cog-
sulted in the singling out of a distinct set of nition. However, if the claim that morality
norms and the creation of the moral domain? evolved means nothing more than this, it
Can the moral domain be traced back to an- fails to have the striking implications moral
cient Greece or to Judaism and Christianity? philosophers have typically had in mind.
Or perhaps it is a more recent historical de- Morality exerts a strong, distinct pull
velopment, possibly connected to the rise of on Westerners (Wright et al., 2008; Skitka,
an individual-centered social life. It may also 2010): They care distinctively about the
have emerged in response to the weakening moral norms tagged as moral, and they are
of traditional justifications for norms such particularly upset when moral norms hap-
as religion—people are motivated to comply pen to be violated. It’s no accident that, in
with their norms because these norms have the film An Inconvenient Truth, Al Gore
been given to them by their god or gods— described acting against climate change in
and tradition—people are motivated to com- moral terms, or that American Conserva-
ply with their norms because their ancestors tive Christians called their movement “the
have always complied with them. The weak- Moral Majority.” Morality also motivates
ening of religion and tradition in Western Westerners, often leading them to condemn
cultures (and possibly in other cultures) may ways of life different from their own. Moral-
have led to the emergence of an alternative izers want the moral order to prevail around
way of thinking about norms and of being them—think of American Conservative
motivated by them. Christians describing same-sex marriage as
It is also important to understand the fac- a moral abomination—as well as far from
tors that lead to the carving of a moral do- them! They go around lecturing people, at
main within the domain of norms. Is having home and around the world, about how they
a monotheistic, personal god a factor related should live. And not only do they lecture
to the emergence of a moral domain? The people, moralizers are also sometimes ready
existence of a capitalist market? Or some- to use violence to impose their moral order.
thing else? Answering these questions will The historicist view of morality highlights
be easier if morality emerged in several cul- the historical and parochial nature of mo-
tures rather than in a single culture (Levine rality: If it is correct, it could have been the
et al., 2016). case that Westerners did not form a moral
264 M O R A L I T Y A N D C U LT U R E

domain at all, and many cultures have not people are divided by politics and religion.
formed such a domain. The contingent and New York: Vintage.
parochial nature of morality should at the Haidt, J., & Joseph, C. (2004). Intuitive ethics:
very least lead us to subject the motivational How innately prepared intuitions generate
culturally variable virtues. Daedalus, 133,
pull of morality and the emotions it elicits 55–66.
to severe scrutiny: Westerners’ moral emo- Haidt, J., Koller, S., & Dias, M. (1993). Affect,
tions and their moral motivation may not be culture, and morality, or is it wrong to eat
justified. The historicist view of morality has your dog? Journal of Personality and Social
thus the potential to undermine the intoler- Psychology, 65, 613–628.
ance that moralizing often breeds. Joyce, R. A. (2006). The evolution of morality.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Kelly, D., Stich, S. P., Haley, K. J., Eng, S. J., &
REFERENCES Fessler, D. M. T. (2007). Harm, affect, and
the moral/conventional distinction. Mind and
Alexander R. D. (1987). The biology of moral Language, 22, 117–131.
systems. Hawthorne, NY: Aldine de Gruyter. Kitcher, P. (1998). Psychological altruism, evolu-
Asch, S. (1951). Effects of group pressure on the tionary origins, and moral rules. Philosophi-
modification and distortion of judgments. In cal Studies, 98, 283–316.
H. Guetzkow (Ed.), Groups, leadership and Levine, S., Rottman, J., Taylor, D., O’Neill, E.,
men (pp. 177–190). Pittsburgh, PA: Carnegie Stich, S. P., & Machery, E. (2016, June). The
Press. moral domain across religions. Paper pre-
Asch, S. (1955). Opinions and social pressure. sented at the annual meeting of the Society for
Scientific American, 193, 33–35. Philosophy and Psychology, Duke University,
Baumard, N., André, J. B., & Sperber, D. (2013). Durham, NC.
A mutualistic approach to morality: The evo- Lisciandra, C., Postma-Nilsenová, M., & Co-
lution of fairness by partner choice. Behavior- lombo, M. (2013). Conformorality: A study
al and Brain Sciences, 36, 59–78. on group conditioning of normative judgment.
Blair, R. J. R. (1995). A cognitive developmental Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 4,
approach to morality: Investigating the psy- 751–764.
chopath. Cognition, 57, 1–29. Machery, E. (2012). Delineating the moral do-
Boehm, C. (1982). The evolutionary develop- main. In The Baltic International Yearbook
ment of morality as an effect of dominance of Cognition, Logic and Communication:
behavior and conflict interference. Journal of Vol. 7. Morality and the cognitive sciences.
Social and Biological Structures, 5, 413–421. Available at http://dx.doi.org/10.4148/biyclc.
Boehm, C. (1999). Hierarchy in the forest: The v7i0.1777.
evolution of egalitarian behavior. Cambridge, Machery, E., & Mallon, R. (2010). Evolution of
MA: Harvard University Press. morality. In J. M. Doris & the Moral Psychol-
Dennett, D. C. (1995). Darwin’s dangerous idea: ogy Research Group (Eds.), The moral psy-
Evolution and the meanings of life. New York: chology handbook (pp. 3–46). Oxford, UK:
Simon & Schuster. Oxford University Press.
Graham, J., Haidt, J., Koleva, S., Motyl, M., Iyer, Machery, E., & Stich, S. P. (2013). You can’t have
R., Wojcik, S. P., & Ditto, P. H. (2013). Moral it both ways. Behavioral and Brain Sciences,
foundations theory: The pragmatic validity of 36, 95.
moral pluralism. Advances in Experimental Nichols, S. (2002). Norms with feeling: Towards
Social Psychology, 47, 55–130. a psychological account of moral judgment.
Graham, J., Haidt, J., & Nosek, B. A. (2009). Cognition, 84, 221–236.
Liberals and conservatives rely on different Nichols, S. (2004). Sentimental rules: On the
sets of moral foundations. Journal of Person- natural foundations of moral judgment. New
ality and Social Psychology, 96, 1029. York: Oxford University Press.
Gray, K., Schein, C., & Ward, A. F. (2014). The Rottschaefer, W. A. (1998). The biology and
myth of harmless wrongs in moral cognition: psychology of moral agency. New York: Cam-
Automatic dyadic completion from sin to suf- bridge University Press.
fering. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Rozin, P. (1999). The process of moralization.
General, 143, 1600–1615. Psychological Science, 10, 218–221.
Gray, K., Young, L., & Waytz, A. (2012). Mind Rozin, P., Lowery, L., Imada, S., & Haidt, J.
perception is the essence of morality. Psycho- (1999). The CAD triad hypothesis: A map-
logical Inquiry, 23, 101–124. ping between three moral emotions (contempt,
Haidt, J. (2012). The righteous mind: Why good anger, disgust) and three moral codes (com-
 Morality: A Historical Invention 265

munity, autonomy, divinity). Journal of Per- Skitka, L. J., Bauman, C. W., & Sargis, E. G.
sonality and Social Psychology, 76, 574–586. (2005). Moral conviction: Another contribu-
Rozin, P., Markwith, M., & Stoess, C. (1997). tor to attitude strength or something more?
Moralization and becoming a vegetarian: The Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
transformation of preferences into values and 88, 895–917.
the recruitment of disgust. Psychological Sci- Sousa, P., Holbrook, C., & Piazza, J. (2009). The
ence, 8, 67–73. morality of harm. Cognition, 113, 80–92.
Ruse, M. (1986). Taking Darwin seriously. Ox- Street, S. (2006). A Darwinian dilemma for re-
ford, UK: Blackwell. alist theories of value. Philosophical Studies,
Shweder, R. A., Mahapatra, M., & Miller, J. 127, 109–166.
(1987). Culture and moral development. In J. Turiel, E. (1983). The development of social
Kagan & S. Lamb (Eds.), The emergence of knowledge. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge Uni-
morality in young children (pp. 1–82). Chi- versity Press.
cago: University of Chicago Press. Wierzbicka, A. (2001). What did Jesus mean?:
Singer, P. (1981). The expanding circle: Ethics Explaining the Sermon on the Mount and the
and sociobiology. Oxford, UK: Oxford Uni- Parables in simple and universal human con-
versity Press. cepts. New York: Oxford University Press.
Singer, P. (2000). A Darwinian left: Politics, Wierzbicka, A. (2007). Moral sense. Journal of
evolution, and cooperation. New Haven, CT: Social, Evolutionary, and Cultural Psychol-
Yale University Press. ogy, 1, 66–85.
Skitka, L. J. (2010). The psychology of moral Wilson, D. S. (2002). Darwin’s cathedral: Evolu-
conviction. Social and Personality Psychology tion, religion and the nature of society. Chi-
Compass, 4, 2672–2681. cago: University of Chicago Press.
Skitka, L. J., Bauman, C. W., & Mullen, E. Wright, J. C., Cullum, J., & Schwab, N. (2008).
(2008). Morality and justice: An expanded The cognitive and affective dimensions of
theoretical perspective and review. In K. A. moral conviction: Implications for attitudi-
Hedgvedt & J. Clay-Warner (Eds.), Advances nal and behavioral measures of interpersonal
in group processes (Vol. 25, pp. 1–27). Bing- tolerance. Personality and Social Psychology
ley, UK: Emerald Group. Bulletin, 34, 1461–1476.
CHAPTER 28

The History of Moral Norms

Jesse J. Prinz

How does history shape moral values?

There are several different theoretical perspectives on moral change,


and each has led to lines of evidence that shed light on the nature of
morality.

The cognitive sciences tend to focus on syn- Historical Context


chronic methods: studying mental life here
and now in living populations. Occasionally, The idea that history matters when trying
work is also done exploring evolutionary ac- to understand morality has long been rec-
counts, which is an especially popular ap- ognized in philosophical ethics. I illustrate
proach when it comes to studying morals. with several examples
Far less frequent is work on the history of In the Leviathan (1968), Thomas Hobbes
morals. This is, in part, because history is argues that human beings are naturally
difficult to study using psychological meth- disposed to exist in a state of war of all
ods. This neglect is unfortunate, however, against all, and that we erect powerful gov-
because changes over historical time can ernments (monarchies) to impose law and
deepen our understanding of moral psychol- order. Thus Hobbes combines psychological
ogy. Like evolutionary approaches, histori- egoism—the view that we are motivated by
cal approaches help us understand both the self-interest—with a social contract theory;
mechanisms of morality and their function. by giving authority to a sovereign, we best
But historical approaches also shed light on protect ourselves. On this view, obedience
moral learning, sociocultural contributors to authority is not a natural instinct but the
to moral norms, transformations over time, result of a historical process.
and moral conflict. In this chapter, I consid- David Hume presents an opposing view
er relevant work in philosophy and cultural in his Treatise Concerning Human Nature
history, as well as research in the social sci- (1978). He believes that we are naturally be-
ences: anthropology, behavioral economics, nevolent rather than purely selfish but that
political science, sociology, and psychology. our benevolence is applied most readily to
Working together, these fields can deepen our near and dear. Thus natural benevolence
our understanding of how morality works. is not enough to ensure that we will respect

266
 The History of Moral Norms 267

the property of strangers. To ensure safety ing psychology. The examples illustrate how
and security, we must cultivate moral regard historical analyses can shed light on motiva-
for unrelated others. Hume believes that tions underlying morality and moral change.
moral rules are grounded in sentiments of Empirical methods can contribute to adju-
approval and disapproval. Therefore, secu- dicating historical hypotheses and their psy-
rity demands that we all come to disapprove chological commitments.
of injustice in the case of unrelated third
parties. We do this by adopting a general
point of view, which assesses the merit of Theoretical Stance
an action not from our own perspective but
from a more generic point of view. Crucially, Broad theoretical perspectives can be culled
this is not a natural instinct but must be so- from these philosophical traditions, and
cially conditioned. Thus Hume calls justice each remains operative in contemporary re-
an “artificial virtue.” search.
A different historical approach is advo- Hobbes sees the emergence of morality as
cated by Karl Marx in Capital (1982) and a rational solution to a coordination prob-
other writings. According to the standard lem. We have to figure out how to get along
synthesis (see, e.g., Laibman, 1984), Marx with others. We want to maximize our own
sees the history of society progressing lot but realize that others want the same,
through a series of stages: primitive commu- and the result is a bad outcome for all. This
nism, slave society, feudalism, capitalism, prefigures game-theoretical approaches to
socialism, and stateless, global communism. morality, according to which sanctions can
Each stage transition is driven by changes in promote cooperation despite a constant in-
material conditions. For example, primitive centive to defect (Kavka, 1986). Game-the-
communism leads to resource surpluses as oretical approaches are sometimes presented
subsistence technologies improve, and that as models of historical change (Richerson &
leads to stratification and slavery. For pres- Boyd, 1998), and they have also been used
ent purposes, the crucial thing to note is that to model evolutionary processes (Axelrod,
Marx sees values (which he often discusses 1984). Traditionally, game theory assumes
under the rubric of “ideology”) as shifting rational choice: Each agent will aim to max-
over historical time. For example, we transi- imize individual utility. This assumption has
tion from egalitarian to hierarchical as we not held up well empirically. Rational-choice
move from primitive communism to slave- models are vulnerable to free-rider problems
based economies and feudalism. (it predicts people will defect whenever they
Hobbes, Hume, and Marx each deliver can personally profit), and they fail to ap-
vindicating narratives: Morality makes preciate the power of social norms (e.g., we
progress over history. A very different view reject unfair offers in economic games even
is promulgated by Friedrich Nietzsche in On if we stand to gain). Therefore game-theo-
the Genealogy of Morality (1994). Nietzsche retical models now include incentive struc-
focuses on what he calls Christian values, tures based on norms. Such models are still
including ascetic ideals (poverty, modesty, Hobbesian, as they imply that norms are
chastity, restraint, etc.) and the idea that the means by which we increase coopera-
punishment is matter of holding people re- tion and overcome conflict. This basic idea
sponsible. He argues that Christian moral- is also integral to a broader family of models
ity derives from the resentment that early that aim to explain the why people work to-
Christians had toward their Roman oppres- gether and form cohesive societies. I use the
sors. Romans valued indulgence and excess, term conflict and coordination to subsume
and they punished people because they ex- these theoretical approaches.
perienced joy in venting power. When Chris- Hume’s account draws attention to the
tians gained control, they turned the Roman role of emotions in morality. This is a popu-
virtues into vices out of spite. lar approach in contemporary moral psy-
Each of these historical approaches pos- chology (e.g., Haidt, 2001), and some atten-
its factors that drive moral change, and each tion has been paid to the role of emotions
makes different claims about the underly- in moral change (e.g., Rozin, Markwith, &
268 M O R A L I T Y A N D C U LT U R E

Stoess, 1997; Nichols, 2002). Emotions have This aligns with the empirical finding that
also been investigated by political scientists, different historical trajectories lead to deeply
historians, and sociologists. Elias’s (2000) entrenched ideologies that are grounded in
classic study of the “civilizing process” ex- grand narratives and mistaken for absolute
plores the way shame and embarrassment truths (Freeden, 1996). Research on ideol-
have been marshaled since the Middle Ages ogy in political science relates to psychologi-
to regulate public displays of natural bodily cal work on polarization and group conflict
functions, such as spitting, nose blowing, (Abramowitz & Saunders, 2008).
excretion, and sex. According to the theoret- These theoretical orientations are, to some
ical model suggested by this tradition, there extent, competing, but they can also be com-
are certain sentiments that we have natu- bined. For example, some game-theoretical
rally, and these will be effective in promot- models make reference to rational choice,
ing moral reform and predictive of which emotions, and material conditions (e.g., Gin-
values endure over time. Hume also predicts tis, Fehr, Bowles, & Boyd, 2005). In some
that sympathy can play a role in broadening cases, the same historical transformation
moral concern for others. has been explained in several different ways.
The Marxian approach has more recent This has given rise to theoretical debates,
adherents as well. It is a major inspiration as I discuss in the case of slavery and abo-
behind materialist anthropology, which em- lition. There are also mixed accounts that
phasizes the impact of technological change recognize multiple factors in moral change
on social arrangements and values (Harris, (e.g., Blackburn, 1988, appeals to economic
1989). Within history, too, there are efforts factors, power struggles, and philanthropic
to explain transformations with reference to sentiments to explain the end of slavery).
changes in economic factors (e.g., Williams,
1944). Likewise, some sociologists empha-
size structure over culture in explaining the Evidence
endurance and endorsement of unequal re-
source distributions (e.g., Kluegel & Smith, Theoretical accounts of moral change are
1986). There is also work in political science often supported by empirical work of various
looking at the impact of industrialization on kinds, ranging from historical case studies to
values (Inglehart, 1997). population surveys, modeling with econom-
Nietzsche’s genealogical approach is less ic games, and laboratory experiments. Here,
frequently invoked in contemporary social some examples are used to illustrate the di-
science, though it has been championed by versity of methods, time scales, and explana-
influential social theorists, most notably tions that have been offered. The theoreti-
Foucault (1977), who picks up on the idea cal orientations introduced above are used
that progress is often illusion. He describes to frame this survey, bearing in mind that
the transition from judicial torture to the many researchers’ theoretical commitments
penitentiary as a new system of domination are merely implicit or open to explanatory
that uses discipline and surveillance rather pluralism. The study of historical change is
than public spectacle and pain. Another the- too vast and varied to allow for a system-
oretical insight that emerges from Nietzsche atic analysis, so the divisions used here bring
is the importance of power struggles in shap- some order to an otherwise unwieldy field
ing moral change. Such conflicts lead to the of inquiry.
construction of new concepts and new bina-
ries, such as the Christian contrast between
Moral Diversity and Transformation
good and evil. Some historians of ideas
advance theses of this kind. For example, Before reviewing evidence concerning the
Pearce (1988) explores the contrast between nature of moral change, it will help to point
savagism and civilization that was used to out that values do in fact vary and trans-
justify westward expansion in American form. If moral values were the same every-
and genocide of its indigenous populations. where and constant, it would be difficult
Nietzsche also observes that we tend to mis- to motivate historical inquiry. Moral diver-
take contingent values for enduring truths. sity and transformation are easy to establish
 The History of Moral Norms 269

by looking at the contemporary world and (Hopton, 2007). It emerged out of medieval
changes over the last century. trials by combat and dissipated after World
There are many subcultures that continue War I. There were occasional revivals be-
to promote traditional moral practices that tween the wars, in South America and Nazi
are now highly regulated by most nations. Germany, for example, but the practice died
Consider honor killing, which claims an es- out thereafter. The change coincided with
timated 5,000 lives each year, though the a decline in the military aristocracy and
actual figure may be much higher due to with a general decline in honor culture in
underreporting (United Nations Population the West (though see Appiah, 2010, for an
Fund, 2000). Methods including beating, argument that dueling simply lost its honor-
stabbing, decapitation, and stoning. The able veneer).
victims are overwhelmingly young women, Another moral change that took place in
and the perpetrators are overwhelmingly recent history is women’s suffrage. Though
male relatives, especially fathers and broth- denial of women’s suffrage was sometimes
ers. In many cases, the victim is killed for presented as a prudential issue based on
marrying someone who is not approved of pseudoscientific beliefs about gender differ-
by her family, and in some cases the victim is ences, voting became widely regarded as a
killed for having been the victim of a sexual moral matter, expressed in the language of
assault. Another example is child marriage. rights. A century ago, few women could vote
Most nations place an 18-year minimum on in national elections. In 1900, only 1% of
marriage without special permission, yet the world’s nations allowed women to vote,
some 15 million girls get married below that as compared with the 19% in which men
age each year. Well over 200 million married could vote; by 1950, the number exceeded
women today said their vows before their 40% for women and 50% for men; and, by
15th birthdays (Save the Children, 2016). the 1990s, 96% of the world’s nations held
In the West, where honor killing and child elections, and suffrage was granted to both
marriage are less common, we are shocked women and men in all of them (Ramirez,
by such statistics, though we must bear Soysal, & Shanahan, 1997). Since then, the
in mind that much of our behavior would few outlier nations—Oman, Qatar, Saudi
shock members of more traditional societies. Arabia, and United Arab Emirates—have
Indeed, behaviors that are commonplace in held elections, at least municipally, and
Western societies include many that would women were able to vote. This trend shows
be regarded as warranting honor killing a fivefold increase in democratic practices
within those subcultures that carry out this overall, but the change for women has been
practice. far more dramatic: in 1892, no country gave
We must also acknowledge that there is a women the right to vote in national elec-
tremendous amount of moral diversity with- tions, and now women can vote everywhere.
in Western culture. This is nowhere more Institutionalized discrimination against
apparent than in partisan politics. Political women remains widespread, but there has
divisions are often moral divisions, and in- been a revolutionary change in values and
dividuals raised in the same nation divide policies with respect to suffrage.
on many moral matters, including capital To give one final example, consider chang-
punishment, abortion, and lesbian, gay, bi- ing attitudes toward overt imperialism. The
sexual, and transgender (LGBT) rights. All 19th century saw a consolidation of power
of these debates have changed over time, in Europe as nation states took form in the
with legal reforms reflecting dramatic alter- wake of the Napoleonic wars. Meanwhile,
nations in moral outlook. the United States became the biggest econo-
It is easy to find other moral issues that my in the world. This set the stage for an age
have undergone significant change over of empire, in which Western powers—and
the last century or so, sometimes at an in- subsequently Asian powers—actively sought
ternational scale. One curious example is to expand territorial boundaries, conquering
dueling, which became a common practice as much as they could, including much of the
among the European upper classes between African continent. People in the conquer-
the Renaissance and the early 20th century ing nations spoke proudly of empire build-
270 M O R A L I T Y A N D C U LT U R E

ing, and moral arguments were advanced Other researchers have tried to model a
to justify conquest. By the end of the 20th social change that occurred long before the
century, attitudes had changed. Imperialism emergence of empires: the transition from
continues, of course, but through cultural small bands of individuals to larger scale so-
influence, coercive trade agreements, inter- cieties with hundreds of members. From the
national policing, puppet governments, and perspective of traditional evolutionary the-
provisional occupations. “Empire” has be- ory, large-scale societies are a puzzle. With
come a bad word (Cox, 2004). Now, overt small groups, cooperation is promoted by
territorial expansion is demonized (Kuwait, kin selection (helping close relatives; Ham-
Crimea), and foreign invasion must be pre- ilton, 1964) and reciprocal altruism (helping
sented as defense or liberation. those who help us; Trivers, 1971). Both in-
crease prospects for our genes. With larger
groups, we must cooperate with unrelated
Conflict and Coordination
strangers, including some who may never
The foregoing examples confirm that values have an opportunity to reciprocate. There
change historically, but theoretical accounts are two effective ways to promote such be-
are needed to explain such changes, and em- havior: indirect reciprocity (cases in which
pirical evidence is needed to support theories. benefits conferred on one person spread to
One class of theories explores conflicts (e.g., others, benefiting the group as a whole), and
crime, war, competition) and forms of social altruistic punishment (punishing anyone
coordination that emerge in their wake (e.g., who defects, even at some personal cost, re-
cooperation and coercive control). Some au- gardless of whether or not you are the victim
thors construct mathematical models and of the defection). Biological evolution has a
compare their models with actual historical hard time accounting for either, as they re-
trends. For example, Gartzke and Rohner quire that individuals incur costs without di-
(2010) attempt to explain the expansion and rect benefit, but cultural group selection has
dissolution of empires using such variables been postulated as a possible explanation
as military technology, military costs, need (Mesoudi & Jensen, 2012). For example,
for resources, available labor, market free- Henrich and Boyd (2001) propose a model
dom, and threat of insurrection. They claim in which a weak tendency toward social
that historical facts about the rise and fall of conformity, coupled with a small amount
empires relate to such variables; territorial of punishment behavior, leads to a spread
expansion helps economies grow, but then of altruistic punishment; groups in which
leads to diminishing returns and decoloniza- this happens then outperform other groups,
tion. leading to the stabilization of punishment
A different model is advanced by Turchin norms. Empirical tests using economic
(2006), who focuses on “metaethnic fron- games have confirmed that altruistic punish-
tiers”—places where competition between ment occurs and increases cooperation (Fehr
groups is particularly intense. This leads to & Gächter, 2002); altruistic punishment
war, according to Turchin, and war leads to increases in contexts of group competition
increased intersocietal cooperation, plant- (Rebers & Koopmans, 2012); and it is also
ing the seeds for empire. Instability comes more prevalent in large societies (Marlowe
when gaps increase between ruling elites et al., 2008).
and the masses. Turchin applies his theories It must be noted that many researchers
to numerous historical cases: Romans, Nor- working within the Hobbesian conflict and
mans, Carolingians, Mongols, Muscovites, coordination cohesion tradition tell progress
and Americans, among others. In other narratives: they claim that we are getting
work, he uses mathematical models to cap- more peaceful over time. An extreme case of
ture sweeping historical changes (Turchin, this is Pinker (2011), who charts reductions
2003). The approach is reductionist, which in crime, homicide, and war fatalities, and
makes traditional historians squeamish, but he argues that the Leviathan (i.e., a stronger
Turchin makes efforts to accommodate un- state) plays a significant role in this change.
expected one-off events such as the Black But optimism is not shared by all. Critics
Death. argue that Pinker overestimates violence
 The History of Moral Norms 271

in small-scale societies (Ferguson, 2013), time was positively related to core disgust,
misses upward trends in crime (Walby, Tow- suggesting that emotions play a role in the
ers, & Francis, 2016), and underestimates cultural transmission of norms.
20th-century war fatalities (Kolbert, 2011). Other examples can be found in the an-
Turchin (2006) cautions that periods of nals of cultural history. Consider foot bind-
peace are often temporary (the Pax Romana ing, which was practiced in China for a mil-
lasted just over 200 years). lennium (Ping, 2000). The origins of foot
binding are something of a mystery, but
its disappearance is well documented, as it
Emotions
happened over the course of a few decades
Emotions are another factor implicated in the early 20th century. One study, based
in the history of values. For David Hume, on a 1929 survey in Tinghsien, reports that
values are constituted by our emotional at- bound feet were found in 99.2% of women
titudes, so changing values requires emo- over 40, in about 60% of women ages 20–
tional change. There has been much research 24, in under 20% of women between 15
on morally relevant emotions, including and 19, and in none of the girls under 10,
research on how these wax and wane over which is over the age when the procedure
time (Frevert, 2011). Other historical inves- was traditionally initiated (Gamble, 1943).
tigations explore the changing role of love This pattern shows a strikingly fast cultural
in marriage norms (Reddy, 2010), the emer- change, going from near universality among
gence of sympathy (Gaston, 2010), the role women to total elimination, with some
of anger in activism (Lamb-Books, 2016), major drops in 5-year periods. This was a
and political uses of fear (Bourke, 2006). period of economic and political change in
Other studies look at the role of emotions China, which witnessed a rapid increase in
in the psychological process of moralization. foreign contact. Some efforts to eliminate
One example is Rozin et al.’s (1997) work foot binding were spearheaded by foreign-
on moral vegetarianism. As compared with ers, but there were also local movements. In
people who become vegetarian for health rea- the present context, attention must be paid
sons, moral vegetarians show higher levels of to the methods used to change values. At the
disgust toward eating meat, and they endorse turn of the 20th century, a British woman
more reasons for avoiding meat. Rozin et al. named Alicia Little founded the T’ien tsu
interpret these findings as showing emotional hui (Natural Foot Society), which aimed to
mediation of the moral value attention must convince Chinese women that bound feet
be paid to. Rozin and Singh (1999) also look are unnatural and hence repellant. Efforts
at the role of emotion in the moralization of to vilify bound feet as unnatural can also be
smoking. They find that moral attitudes to- found among Chinese reformers, dating as
ward cigarettes correlate with disgust and far back as the 18th century. Drucker (1981)
increase across three generations. catalogues arguments from the critic Li Ju-
In another study involving disgust, Nich- chen, which include the charge that binding
ols (2002) examines the history of etiquette feet tampers with the natural order, violates
norms. The Renaissance philosopher Desid- human nature, degrades the upper classes,
erius Erasmus (1530/1985) wrote a highly makes women move unsteadily, and causes
influential etiquette manual, which contains illness. Notice that each of these arguments
rules that vary in their current standing; could instill disgust.
some still ring true (“Turn away when spit- Efforts to enact moral change by recruit-
ting”) and others have lost their relevance ing emotions are not limited to disgust. A
(“If given a napkin, put it over either the wider range can be found in the work of
left shoulder or the left forearm”). Using historians who study the antislavery move-
this manual, Nichols had coders rate items ments. Slavery is now regarded as perhaps
on two dimensions: Does the norm continue the greatest of all evils. Yet it was practiced
to hold? And does the behavior it describes from ancient times to the present day. With
elicit core disgust? “Core disgust” is disgust the colonization of the Americas, it grew in
elicited by bodily products and fluids. Nich- scale and acquired a racial pretext. By the
ols found that preservation over historical turn of 19th century, slavery was a central
272 M O R A L I T Y A N D C U LT U R E

component of the most profitable industries Other emotions were recruited as well.
in Brazil, the United States, and the Carib- Opponents of slavery described the institu-
bean. By the end of the century, the institu- tion as a grave sin, which may have elicited
tion had been outlawed in all of these places, shame and guilt, and they also called on
and popular opinion had shifted. There are white people to sympathize with slaves. The
many theories of how this happened, and famous emblem of the antislavery move-
many factors that may have contributed, but ments shows a slave in chains emblazoned
there is no doubt that emotions played an with the words “Am I not a man and a
important role in the rhetoric of those who brother?” Much has been written about such
fought for abolition. appeals to sympathy, which were inspired
One factor in public discourse about slav- by British moralists such as Adam Smith
ery was fear. Slavery is an extreme form of (Carey, 2005). Also prevalent were appeals
violence against persons and human dignity; to anger and righteous indignation. Woods
it requires brutality to enforce. The inevita- (2015) illustrates the trend in the discourse
ble result is insurrection. According to one of the English abolitionists Thomas Clark-
count, there were 250 slave revolts in Amer- son and William Wilberforce. One might
ica and countless more plots, outbreaks, and also suppose that anger and indignation
reprisals (Aptheker, 1943, p. 162). There played a role in motivating slave uprisings.
were also many thousands of escapes. Afri- Curiously, such terms appear infrequently
can captives mutinied on slave ships, as well, in slave narratives, and anger is most often
on as many as 10% of the voyages across the attributed to slave masters and mistresses
Atlantic (Richardson, 2001). This pattern in these texts (Andrews & Gates, 2000). In
was repeated wherever there were slaves, a classic study of the Haitian Revolution,
with major revolts in Brazil and throughout James (1938) notes that the slaves were less
the Caribbean: Barbados, Curaçao, Domi- vengeful than their masters. Perhaps emo-
nica, Grenada, Guyana, Jamaica, Puerto tions such as determination and hope ani-
Rico, and throughout the Virgin Islands mated the slaves who fought oppression, and
and West Indies. The most successful revolt those efforts helped to awaken white anxi-
was carried out in Haiti—then the French ety and conscience.
island of Saint Domingue. Slaves managed
to oust French colonists and gain indepen-
Material Factors
dence. They also managed to defeat the
French army and expel forces from England Emotions help to explain the psychological
and Spain. All these insurrections caused mechanisms behind moral change, but some
tremendous fear in whites. They were used authors seek to explain large-scale societal
to justify even more oppressive treatment of factors as well. Those who follow in the ma-
slaves (Horne, 2015), but they also played a terialist tradition popularized by Marx tend
role in abolition. Thomas Jefferson was very to focus on economic variables.
anxious about slave revolts, and he enacted For example, Williams (1944) offers a
embargos against Haiti after the revolution classic explanation of British abolitionism
there to prevent knowledge of their success that draws attention to changing profit mar-
from spreading (Matthewson, 1995). Soon gins. At first, slavery in the New World was
after, he encouraged Congress to ban the in- a boon to the British economy, and it helped
ternational slave trade, reducing the chance finance industrialization, but then, as sugar
that rebellious Africans and those who knew prices fell, slave industries were losing value,
about Caribbean uprisings would enter U.S. and Britain shifted toward a wage-based in-
soil. Leading abolitionists expressed fear as dustrial economy. This account has been a
well. William Lloyd Garrison used fear of challenge to those who think that humani-
insurrection to argue for immediate aboli- tarian motives drove abolition (Drescher,
tion in the United States rather than gradu- 1977), but evidence suggests that economic
alism (Abzug, 1970), and Thomas Fowell changes may have played a role (e.g., Ryden,
Buxton invoked fear to lobby effectively for 2001). Economic arguments have often been
abolition in the British parliament (Mat- given to explain why slavery was abolished
thews, 2006). in the American North and also why it per-
 The History of Moral Norms 273

sisted so long (McManus, 1973). There are contingencies of revolution and conquest de-
also economic accounts, based on demo- termined which countries ended up on either
graphic data, of the shift from European in- side of this divide. Citizens in both camps
dentured servitude to African chattel slavery were then socialized to believe in their own
in early British America (Menard, 1980). moral superiority. Another example is mass
Economic models have been used to ex- incarceration. There are now more African
amine many other moral attitudes. The con- Americans in jail or on probation or parole
trast between farming and herding econo- than were enslaved in 1850 (Alexander,
mies has been used to explain differences in 2010). These numbers reflect policies that
attitudes toward violence in African societ- have a moral character—especially drug
ies (Edgerton, 1971) and in North America laws—but their net effect is the preservation
(Cohen & Nisbett, 1994). Talhelm et al. of a racially based power imbalance.
(2014) credit rice farming with collectivism, Western democracy has also been sub-
as compared with individualism. Morris jected to a power-theoretical analysis. Many
(2015) argues that the transition from farm- people believe that Western systems of gov-
ing to fossil fuels ushered in democracy and ernment are fair because they are demo-
gender equality. Harris (1989) sketches ma- cratic, but defenders of the “elite theory”
terialistic explanations of many moralized argue that power is hoarded by members
practices: incest, cannibalism, male domi- of a ruling class (Higley & Burton, 2006).
nance, and others. Consistent with this, Gilens and Page (2014)
There are also economic accounts of collected opinions about nearly 2,000 U.S.
changes in marriage norms. Scheidel (2009) policies and found widespread endorsements
argues that the transition from polygamy to among economic elites and business inter-
monogamy resulted from a reduction in male ests; in contrast, the preferences of average
income inequality after the fall of the Greek citizens showed no relationship to public
palace system. Coontz (2004) credits indus- policy. They conclude that the United States
trialization with the rise of marriages based is an oligarchy.
on love. Werner (1979) argues that tolerance
for gay relationships increases with the cost
of child rearing. Eagly and Wood (1999) ex- Extension and Expansion
amine the relationship between increasing
gender equality in relationships and the eco- The foregoing examples illustrate the diver-
nomic empowerment of women. sity of research programs that aim to iden-
Some critics worry that materialist expla- tify and explain changes in values. These
nations are overly deterministic, but analy- operate at different levels of analysis, cover
ses such as these do provide evidence for many time scales, and deploy a wide range
correlations between values and economic of methods, including social history, demog-
variables, indicating some impact in certain raphy, national polling, game-­ theoretical
cases. modeling, and laboratory experiments.
There are also different theoretical ap-
proaches, as emphasized here. These are
Power
often presented as competitors; for example,
Another approach to moral change focuses economic factors are sometimes contrasted
on power arrangements. These can be linked with changes in cultural ideals; emotion is
to economic variables, but there is also evi- contrasted with utility maximization; con-
dence that values can be affected by con- tingent power struggles are contrasted with
tingent historical factors in which different law-like changes. But mixed models are easy
groups struggle for control. Such conflicts to imagine, with causal arrows in all direc-
can give rise to illusory beliefs about prog- tions.
ress. This explanatory framework has been From the perspective of moral psychol-
less intensively studied by social scientists, ogy, the phenomenon of historical change
but possible examples can be identified. has several lessons to offer. It reminds us
Consider the Cold War. Capitalism and that values can shift and are not completely
communism are economic systems, but the determined by biology. It can shed light on
274 M O R A L I T Y A N D C U LT U R E

the mechanisms of moral learning, includ- Eagly, A. H., & Wood, W. (1999). The origins
ing emotions. It can also expose factors that of sex differences in human behavior: Evolved
lead harmful values to become entrenched, dispositions versus social roles. American Psy-
such as ingroup bias and profit motives. chologist, 54, 408–423.
Edgerton, R. B. (1971). The individual in cul-
Historical analyses can also be informed tural adaptation: A study of four East Afri-
by psychological research, leading to richer can peoples. Berkeley: University of California
explanations of societal change. The cogni- Press.
tive sciences have tended to neglect histori- Elias, N. (2000). The civilizing process (E. Jeph-
cal approaches, and historians often neglect cott, Trans.). Malden, MA: Blackwell. (Origi-
psychology, but there is much to learn from nal work published 1939)
their intersection. Erasmus, D. (1985). On good manners for boys.
In J. Sowards (Ed.), Collected works of Eras-
mus (Vol. 25, pp. 269–290). Toronto, On-
REFERENCES tario, Canada: University of Toronto Press.
(Original work published 1530)
Abramowitz, A. I., & Saunders, K. L. (2008). Is Fehr, E., & Gächter, S. (2002). Altruistic punish-
polarization a myth? Journal of Politics, 70, ment in humans. Nature, 415, 137–140.
542–555. Ferguson, B. (2013). Pinker’s list: Exaggerat-
Abzug, R. H. (1970). The influence of Garriso- ing prehistoric war mortality. In D. Fry (Ed.),
nian abolitionists’ fears of slave violence on War, peace and human nature (pp. 112–131).
the antislavery argument, 1829–40. Journal Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
of Negro History, 55, 15–26. Foucault, M. (1977). Discipline and punish: The
Alexander, M. (2010). The new Jim Crow: Mass birth of the prison (A. M. Sheridan-Smith,
incarceration in the age of colorblindness. Trans.). New York: Vintage.
New York: New Press. Freeden, M. (1996). Ideologies and political
Andrews, W. L., & Gates, H. L. (Eds.). (2000). theory: A conceptual approach. Oxford, UK:
Slave narratives. New York: Penguin. Oxford University Press.
Appiah, K. A. (2010). The honor code: How Frevert, U. (2011). Emotions in history: Lost and
moral revolutions happen. New York: Nor- found. Budapest, Hungary: Central European
ton. University Press.
Aptheker, H. (1943). American Negro slave re- Gamble, S. D. (1943). The disappearance of foot-
volts. New York: Columbia University Press. binding in Tinghsien. American Journal of So-
Axelrod, R. (1984). The evolution of coopera- ciology, 49, 181–183.
tion. New York: Basic Books. Gartzke, E., & Rohner, D. (2010). The political
Blackburn, R. (1988). The overthrow of colonial economy of imperialism, decolonization and
slavery, 1776–1848. New York: Verso. development. British Journal of Political Sci-
Bourke, E. (2006). Fear: A cultural history. Em- ence, 41, 525–556.
eryville, CA: Counterpoint. Gaston, S. (2010). The impossibility of sympa-
Carey, B. (2005). British abolitionism and the thy. Eighteenth Century, 51, 129–152.
rhetoric of sensibility: Writing, sentiment, Gilens, M., & Page, B. (2014). Testing theories of
and slavery, 1760–1807. London: Palgrave. American politics: Elites, interest groups, and
Cohen, D., & Nisbett, R. E. (1994). Self-pro- average citizens. Perspectives on Politics, 12,
tection and the culture of honor: Explaining 564–581.
Southern violence. Personality and Social Psy- Gintis, H., Fehr, E., Bowles, S., & Boyd, R.
chology Bulletin, 20, 551–567. (2005). Moral sentiments and material inter-
Coontz, S. (2004). The world historical transfor- ests: The foundations of cooperation in eco-
mation of marriage. Journal of Marriage and nomic life. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Family, 66, 974–979. Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional dog and its ra-
Cox, M. (2004). Empire, imperialism and the tional tail: A social intuitionist approach to
Bush doctrine. Review of International Stud- moral judgment. Psychological Review, 108,
ies, 30, 585–608. 814–834.
Drescher, S. (1977). Econocide: British slavery Hamilton, W. D. (1964). The genetical evolution
in the era of abolition. Chapel Hill, NC: Uni- of social behavior. Journal of Theoretical Bi-
versity of North Carolina Press. ology, 7, 1–52.
Drucker, A. R. (1981). The influence of Western Harris, M. (1989). Our kind. New York: Harper
women on the anti-footbinding movement, Collins.
1840–1911. Historical Reflections, 8, 179– Henrich, J., & Boyd, R. (2001). Why people pun-
199. ish defectors: Weak conformist transmission
 The History of Moral Norms 275

can stabilize costly enforcement of norms in Mesoudi, A., & Jensen, K. (2012). Culture and
cooperative dilemmas. Journal of Theoretical the evolution of human sociality. In J. Vonk
Biology, 208, 79–89. & T. Shackelford (Eds.), The Oxford hand-
Higley, J., & Burton, M. (2006). Elite founda- book of comparative evolutionary psychology
tions of liberal democracy. Lanham, MD: (pp. 419–433). Oxford, UK: Oxford Univer-
Rowman & Littlefield. sity Press.
Hobbes, T. (1968). Leviathan (C. B. MacPher- Morris, I. (2015). Foragers, farmers, and fossil
son, Ed.). New York: Penguin. (Original work fuels: How human values evolve. Princeton,
published 1651) NJ: Princeton University Press.
Hopton, R. (2007). Pistols at dawn: A history of Nichols, S. (2002). On the genealogy of norms: A
dueling. London: Piatkus Books. case for the role of emotion in cultural evolu-
Horne, G. (2015). Confronting black Jacobins: tion. Philosophy of Science, 69, 234–255.
The U.S., the Haitian Revolution, and the ori- Nietzsche, F. (1994). On the genealogy of mo-
gins of the Dominican Republic. New York: rality (C. Diethe, Trans.). Cambridge, UK:
New York University Press. Cambridge University Press. (Original work
Hume, D. (1978). A treatise of human nature (P. published 1887)
H. Nidditch, Ed.). Oxford, UK: Oxford Uni- Pearce, R. H. (1988). Savagism and civilization:
versity Press. (Original work published 1739) A study of the Indian and the American mind.
Inglehart, R. (1997). Modernization and post- Berkeley: University of California Press.
modernization: Cultural, economic, and po- Ping, W. (2000). Aching for beauty: Footbinding
litical change in 43 societies. Princeton, NJ: in China. Minneapolis: University of Minne-
Princeton University Press. sota Press.
James, C. L. R. (1938). The Black Jacobins: Pinker, S. (2011). The better angels of our nature:
Toussaint L’Ouverture and the San Domingo Why violence has declined. New York: Viking.
Revolution. New York: Vintage Books. Ramirez, F. O., Soysal, Y., & Shanahan, S.
Kavka, G. (1986). Hobbesean moral and politi- (1997). The changing logic of political citizen-
cal theory. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University ship: Cross-national acquisition of women’s
Press. suffrage rights, 1890 to 1990. American So-
Kluegel, J. R., & Smith, E. R. (1986). Be- ciological Review, 62, 735–745.
liefs about inequality. New York: Walter de Rebers, S., & Koopmans, R. (2012) Altruistic
Gruyter. punishment and between-group competition.
Kolbert, E. (2011). Peace in our time. New York- Human Nature, 23, 173–190.
er, 87(30), 75–78. Reddy, W. (2010). The rule of love: The history
Laibman, D. (1984). Modes of production and of Western romantic love in comparative per-
theories of transition. Science and Society, 48, spective. In L. Passerini, L. Ellena, & A. C.
257–294. T. Goeppert (Eds.), New dangerous liaisons:
Lamb-Books, B. (2016). Angry abolitionists and Discourses on Europe and love in the twenti-
the rhetoric of slavery: Moral emotions in so- eth century (pp. 33–57). New York: Berghahn
cial movements. New York: Palgrave. Books.
Marlowe, F., Berbesque, J. C., Barr, A., Barrett, Richardson, D. (2001). Shipboard revolts, Af-
C., Bolyanatz, A., Cardenas, J. C., . . . Tracer, D. rican authority and the Atlantic slave trade.
(2008). More “altruistic” punishment in larger William and Mary Quarterly, 58, 69–92.
societies. Proceedings of the National Academy Richerson, P., & Boyd, R. (1998). The evolution
of Sciences of the USA, 275, 587–590. of ultrasociality. In I. Eibl-Eibesfeldt & F. K.
Marx, K. (1982), Capital: A critique of political Salter (Eds.), Indoctrinability, ideology and
economy (B. Fowkes, Trans.). New York: Pen- warfare. New York: Berghahn Books.
guin Books. (Original work published 1867) Rozin, P., Markwith, M., & Stoess, C. (1997).
Matthews, G. (2006). Caribbean slave revolts Moralization: Becoming a vegetarian, the
and the British abolitionist movement. Baton conversion of preferences into values and the
Rouge: Louisiana State University Press. recruitment of disgust. Psychological Science,
Matthewson, T. (1995). Jefferson and Haiti. 8, 67–73.
Journal of Southern History, 61, 209–248. Rozin, P., & Singh, L. (1999). The moralization
McManus, E. J. (1973). Black bondage in the of cigarette smoking in America. Journal of
North. Syracuse, NY: Syracuse University Consumer Behavior, 8, 321–337.
Press. Ryden, D. (2001). Does decline make sense?: The
Menard, R. R. (1980). The tobacco industry in West Indian economy and the abolition of the
the Chesapeake colonies, 1617–1730: An in- slave trade. Journal of Interdisciplinary His-
terpretation. Research in Economic History, tory, 31, 347–374.
5, 109–177. Save the Children. (2016). Every last girl: Free
276 M O R A L I T Y A N D C U LT U R E

to live, free to learn, free from harm. London: world population 2000: Lives together, worlds
Author. apart: Men and women in a time of change.
Scheidel, W. (2009). A peculiar institution?: Gre- Available at www.unfpa.org/swp/2000/eng-
co-Roman monogamy in global context. His- lish/index.html.
tory of the Family, 14, 280–291. Walby, S., Towers, J., & Francis, B. (2016). Is
Talhelm, T., Zhang, X., Oishi, S., Shimin, C., violent crime increasing or decreasing?: A new
Duan, D., Lan, X., & Kitayama, S. (2014). methodology to measure repeat attacks mak-
Large-scale psychological differences within ing visible the significance of gender and do-
China explained by rice versus wheat agricul- mestic relations. British Journal of Criminol-
ture. Science, 344, 603–608. ogy, 56, 1203–1234.
Trivers, R. L. (1971). The evolution of reciprocal Werner, D. (1979). A cross-cultural perspective
altruism. Quarterly Review of Biology, 46, on theory and research on male homosexual-
34–57. ity. Journal of Homosexuality, 4, 345–362.
Turchin, P. (2003). Historical dynamics: Why Williams, E. (1944). Capitalism and slavery.
states rise and fall. Princeton, NJ: Princeton Chapel Hill, NC: University of North Caro-
University Press. lina Press.
Turchin, P. (2006). War and peace and war: The Woods, M. E. (2015). A theory of moral out-
life cycles of imperial nations. New York: Pi rage: Indignation and eighteenth-century Brit-
Press. ish abolitionism. Slavery and Abolition, 36,
United Nations Population Fund. (2000). State of 662–683.
PART VI
MORALITY AND THE BODY

Q U E S T I O N S A N S W E R E D I N PA R T V I

CHAPTER 29  How is morality revealed in the body?

CHAPTER 30  What is the nature of moral psychological processing?


CHAPTER 29

The Moralization of the Body


Protecting and Expanding the Boundaries of the Self

Gabriela Pavarini
Simone Schnall

How is morality revealed in the body?

Protecting the body coincides with a desire to keep resources for


the self, whereas breaking these boundaries (e.g., through physical
touch) coincides with a desire to share with others.

Visible and mobile, my body is a thing among hand, may induce a strong sense of repulsion
things; it is one of them. It is caught in the fabric and a desire to protect the psychological and
of the world, and its cohesion is that of a thing. physical boundaries of the self. Individuals
But, because it moves itself and sees, it holds things therefore experience an ongoing process of
in a circle around itself. subjectively redefining their physical and
—M erleau -Ponty (1964, p. 163)
psychological boundaries, whereby other
people are either kept separate, rejected, and
Human minds reside in fleshy, physical bod- condemned or brought closer, incorporated,
ies. Concrete and clearly delineated, the body and united with the self. Human morality
separates internal, private experience from unfolds in this dynamic process of protect-
external objects and people. It is the space ing and expanding the boundaries of the
where awareness simultaneously arises from self.
internally generated streams (e.g., heart rate) At its essence, morality can be viewed
and external pathways or the “circle around as concerning resource allocation. “Being
itself” (e.g., vision, smell). Our senses con- moral” normally refers to the willingness
vey that other beings are exterior to one- to allocate personal resources to others.
self and that our boundaries separate the This includes helping others achieve their
self from others. Processes such as physical goals, comforting them, and sharing valu-
closeness, touch, or synchronicity may blur able goods such as food and information
those boundaries and induce feelings of (Eisenberg, Fabes, & Spinrad, 2006; Toma-
being together and united as “one” (Gallace sello & Vaish, 2013; Warneken & Toma-
& Spence, 2010; Paladino, Mazzurega, Pa- sello, 2009). Therefore, a substantial part of
vani, & Schubert, 2010). Exposure to cues our everyday morality involves decisions on
of contamination and injury, on the other whether to keep our psychological, physical,

279
280 M O R A L I T Y A N D T H E B O DY

and material resources to ourselves or, in- ings such as disgust, anger, or happiness and
stead, give them away. For social life to be that these feelings guide how morally right
sustainable, human groups develop a shared or wrong individuals judge these actions to
understanding of who possesses what and be (Cannon, Schnall, & White, 2011; Rozin,
the extent to which these resources are dis- Lowery, Imada, & Haidt, 1999; Schnall,
tributed and shared. In the present chap- Haidt, Clore, & Jordan, 2008; for a review,
ter we demonstrate how the negotiation of see Schnall, 2017).
psychological and material resources with Beyond emotions, other physical prop-
others is grounded in processes of the physi- erties of the body also map onto abstract
cal body, such as those that support disease moral concepts. As one example, moral im-
avoidance. In what follows, we discuss the purity is mapped onto physical impurity,
historical roots of our approach, its theoreti- such that engaging in morally reprehensible
cal standpoint, and the accruing empirical acts induces a desire to physically cleanse
evidence in support of it. one’s body (Zhong & Liljenquist, 2006),
and feelings of physical disgust are indica-
tive of moral condemnation (Schnall, Haidt,
Historical Context and Theoretical Stance et al., 2008). Physical closeness is mapped
onto subjective closeness and the sharing
Broadly speaking, our approach is based of moral essences with others. Touching a
on views of cognition as grounded or em- saintly, virtuous person makes one feel mor-
bodied in several different ways, including ally upright, whereas approaching an im-
simulations, situated action, and bodily moral other makes one feel sinful (Nemeroff
states (e.g., emotions). This view opposes & Rozin, 1994; Newman, Diesendruck, &
traditional theories of cognition that assume Bloom, 2011).
that knowledge is stored in amodal, seman- Embodied morality assumes, therefore,
tic memory systems separate from systems that the body is a source domain for com-
that support perception, action, and intro- plex ethical concepts. In this chapter, we
spection. The embodied approach emerged advance the idea that fundamental elements
from efforts in several different disciplines, of human morality unfold in the process of
such as cognitive linguistics (Lakoff & John- protecting and expanding physical bound-
son, 1980, 1999), anthropology (Hutchins, aries of the self. There is extensive evidence
1995), neuroscience (Damasio, 1994), phi- that humans strive to protect their bodily
losophy (Prinz, 2002) and psychology (Bar- container, keeping a distance from potential
salou & Wiemer-Hastings, 2005; Schwarz, contaminants and other threats to body in-
2000; Smith & Semin, 2004). Across dis- tegrity. As we aim to demonstrate, this pro-
ciplines, this novel approach has received cess of safeguarding one’s physical bodily
consistent empirical support (see Landau, boundaries is intrinsically linked to the
Meier, & Keefer, 2010; Meier, Schnall, process of keeping one’s material and psy-
Schwarz, & Bargh, 2012; Niedenthal, Bar- chological resources to oneself (i.e., an un-
salou, Winkielman, Krauth-Gruber, & Ric, willingness to connect and share with oth-
2005, for reviews). ers). On the flip side, greater willingness to
In the moral domain, the social intuition- break those boundaries (e.g., through physi-
ist model (Haidt, 2001; also see Nichols, cal touch) coincides with a subjective sense
2004; Prinz, 2007, for similar approaches) of closeness and a desire to share one’s own
suggests that, just like other types of judg- resources with others.
ments, moral judgments are guided by feel-
ings and intuitions. This view contrasts with
purely rationalist approaches to morality Evidence
(Kohlberg, Levine, & Hewer, 1983; Nucci
Morality as the Protection
& Turiel, 1978) and is inspired by philo-
of One’s Boundaries
sophical traditions suggesting a central role
for emotions in human morals (e.g., Hume, Humans have a fundamental tendency to
1777/1960). Several studies have shown that protect their bodies against illness, disease,
morally relevant actions trigger strong feel- and contamination. Beyond physiological
 The Moralization of the Body 281

immune responses, human beings are also evolved to protect one’s physical body pre-
equipped with a sophisticated set of psycho- dict morally relevant cognition and behavior.
logical mechanisms, the behavioral immune Possibly driven by the same mechanism,
system (Murray & Schaller, 2016; Schaller actions that potentially harm or physically
& Park, 2011). This system serves as a first contaminate one’s body in the absence of any
line of defense against pathogens. For exam- obvious interpersonal connotation are mor-
ple, newborn babies spontaneously wrinkle alized. Those include, among others, lack of
their noses and turn down the corners of hygiene, excessive food ingestion (Sheikh,
their mouths when given a bitter solution, Botindari, & White, 2013), smoking (Rozin
in an involuntary attempt to prevent tox- & Singh, 1999), and suicide (Rottman, Kele-
ins and pathogens from entering their bod- men, & Young, 2014b). All these actions
ies (Rosenstein & Oster, 1988). Individuals are often referred to as “wrong” and “im-
are highly sensitive to morphological and moral.” Indeed, suicide is still considered a
olfactory cues that connote the presence of crime in many places throughout the world
pathogens and promptly react when exposed (Stephan, 2016). In the same vein, individu-
to potentially harmful substances, such as a als strongly condemn actions that trigger a
stranger’s pus-oozing sore or maggots crawl- sense of repulsion, such as cannibalism, in-
ing inside one’s meal (Curtis, Aunger, & cest, and bestiality, even when the act is pri-
Rabie, 2004; Curtis, de Barra, & Aunger, vate and arguably harmless to others (Haidt,
2011; Curtis & Biran, 2001; Rozin, Lowery, Bjorklund, & Murphy, 2000; Haidt, Koller,
& Ebert, 1994; Schaller, Miller, Gervais, & Dias, 1993; Haidt & Hersh, 2001). Final-
Yager, & Chen, 2010). Even subtle cues of ly, the same cognitive-enhancing drug was
potential pathogen infection trigger a chain judged as more morally reprehensible when
of reactions that include a sense of disgust administered through an injection, cuing
and revulsion and avoidant behavioral ten- potential bodily harm to the individual,
dencies. than if taken as a pill (Scheske & Schnall,
Because many diseases are transmitted 2012). All these examples illustrate how the
as a result of interpersonal encounters, the strong avoidant tendency triggered by slight
perceived threat of infection may reduce cues of bodily threat may take the form of
people’s inclination for social interaction. abstract moral values and raise a condemna-
Indeed, a study found that levels of ex- tory eyebrow.
traversion were lower among populations These examples also suggest that moral-
with high prevalence of infectious diseases ity goes beyond concerns about harm and
(Schaller & Murray, 2008). At the indi- fairness. Even though people’s justifications
vidual level, participants who were chroni- of moral judgments may include appeals to
cally worried about germ contamination or harm, they are often not the true causes of
primed with pathogen salience also reported those judgments. Feelings of disgust toward
being less extroverted (Duncan, Schaller, & taboo-breaking actions or bodily norm
Park, 2009; Mortensen, Becker, Ackerman, violations are predicted neither by harm
Neuberg, & Kenrick, 2010, but see Kupfer & to others (Giner-Sorolla, Bosson, Caswell,
Tybur, 2017). Critically, the salience of po- & Hettinger, 2012; Gutierrez & Giner-
tential contaminants also predicts discrimi- Sorolla, 2007) nor by intentionality (Astuti
natory behavior against people who appear & Bloch, 2015; Russell & Giner-Sorolla,
likely to transmit new pathogens or whose 2011b; Young & Tsoi, 2013). Moreover,
appearance is somewhat atypical. When the judgments of impure, disgusting acts are
threat posed by infectious pathogens is made very distinct from other moral judgments:
salient, participants report greater prejudice They are less elaborately justified (Russell
against people who are obese or have physi- & Giner-­Sorolla, 2011c) and more resistant
cal disabilities (Park, Faulkner, & Schaller, to contradicting evidence (Russell & Giner-
2003; Park, Schaller, & Crandall, 2007) Sorolla, 2011a), and they involve a unique
and toward outgroup members (Faulkner, set of neural systems (Borg, Lieberman, &
Schaller, Park, & Duncan, 2004; Navarrete, Kiehl, 2008; Parkinson et al., 2011).
Fessler, & Eng, 2007). These findings sug- In light of the above evidence, we argue
gest that psychological mechanisms that that the condemnation of impurity is a re-
282 M O R A L I T Y A N D T H E B O DY

flection of people’s high sensitivity and purity. The specific ways in which different
fundamental aversion to cues of illness and cultures elaborate purity concerns are com-
contamination (see Chakroff, Dungan, & plex, diverse, and intertwined with several
Young, 2013; Inbar & Pizarro, 2014; Tybur, other factors, including specific dynamics
Lieberman, Kurzban, & DeScioli, 2013, of power and status maintenance in a par-
for similar views). Although moral actions ticular society. Nevertheless, the fact that
in the purity domain do not cause direct virtually every culture across history places
or intentional harm to others, individuals purity-related practices in the sphere of mo-
who engage in actions that potentially risk rality hints at some evolutionary basis for
the safety and integrity of their own bodies those concerns (see Haidt & Joseph, 2007).
are arguably more likely to carry and trans- Physical disgust may have been not only
mit pathogens. In other words, even though co-opted to promote harsh judgments of ac-
so-called impure actions do not cause any tions that connote impurity but also to moral
direct interpersonal harm, affiliating with violations in general. Already at the age of
perpetrators of these actions may in some 6, children consistently call moral viola-
cases represent a risk to the purity of one’s tions “disgusting,” and more so than merely
own body in the long run. In this context, negative events (Danovitch & Bloom, 2009).
feelings of disgust and the condemnation of They also consider severe violations (e.g.,
those actions effectively keep “impure oth- “stealing money from a little kid”) more dis-
ers” away, protecting the self from potential gusting than less severe ones (e.g., “stealing
physical contamination. a candy from the supermarket”; Stevenson,
Disgust is such a powerful response that Oaten, Case, Repacholi, & Wagland, 2010).
even completely neutral actions become Interestingly, one study found that parents’
moralized when coupled with it. In one physical disgust in reaction to items such as
study, for example, 7-year-olds rated un- ice cream with ketchup predicted children’s
usual, morally neutral actions (e.g., cov- reactions to sociomoral elicitors outside the
ering one’s head with sticks) as morally purity domain, suggesting that parental
wrong when the action had been described physical disgust shapes children’s rejection
as disgusting (and coupled with a disgusting of transgressors in general (Stevenson et al.,
smell) or unnatural, but not when described 2010).
as “boring” (Rottman & Kelemen, 2012). Adults as well as children identify moral
These results indicate that children acquire violations as “disgusting” and display spon-
moral beliefs about neutral actions associ- taneous expressions of physical distaste in
ated with repulsion and disgust in an easy reaction to unfair actions (Cannon et al.,
and effortless manner. Such moralizing ef- 2011; Chapman, Kim, Susskind, & Ander-
fects of disgust on neutral actions have also son, 2009). Similarly, individuals highly sen-
been shown in samples of adults (Chapman sitive to disgust judge moral transgressions
& Anderson, 2014; Horberg, Oveis, Keltner, to be more wrong than those who are less
& Cohen, 2009; Wheatley & Haidt, 2005), disgust sensitive (Chapman & Anderson,
which points to people’s general reliance on 2014; Horberg et al., 2009). Finally, a series
feelings of disgust guiding their social judg- of studies suggested that extraneous feelings
ments. of disgust induced by hypnosis (Wheatley &
Last but not least, we find it important Haidt, 2005), noxious smells, dirty spaces,
to note that there are multiple layers of cul- disgusting video clips (Schnall, Haidt, et al.,
tural meaning associated with moral impu- 2008), disgusting noises (Seidel & Prinz,
rity. Beyond individual concerns related to 2013), or bitter drinks (Eskine, Kacinik, &
the protection of one’s physical body, there Prinz, 2011) rendered harsher moral judg-
are several societal (e.g., religious) factors ments in several moral domains, particular-
underlying judgments of “impure actions” ly for participants highly sensitive to bodily
such as incest and suicide. These factors are cues.
not discussed in this present chapter, but we Why does the effect of disgust extend
point out that concerns surrounding bodily to moral judgments beyond purity, given
harm and contamination are not the only that these transgressions are unrelated to
factor responsible for the moralization of im- physical infection? As suggested elsewhere
 The Moralization of the Body 283

(Schnall, 2017), it is possible that the state to establishing potential alliances with this
of physical disgust leads to a general mind- player. On the other hand, they would also
set of resource scarcity and increased at- wish to accept the offer, as this would maxi-
tempts to maximize personal resources. mize their own material resources because a
Individuals may wish to keep a distance low offer is better than nothing at all.
from “impure” others but may also want to A careful analysis of the literature sup-
make sure they do not affiliate with self- ports these predictions. When the person
interested partners who may exhaust their who made the unfair offer was salient—for
resources. Therefore, it makes sense that example, if participants could see the other
they would react more strongly to cues in- player behind an opaque wall—participants
dicating that others are selfish, unfair, dis- feeling disgusted were less likely to accept
honest, or uncooperative, given that those the other player’s offer than those who were
people would likely deplete them of their not experiencing disgust (Harlé & San-
resources. These strong reactions lead them fey, 2010; Moretti & di Pellegrino, 2010).
to judge their transgressions more harshly Their rejection was probably an attempt to
and prevent them from establishing poten- avoid establishing any cooperative alliances
tially costly partnerships. with a self-interested party. On the other
If this suggestion were true, one would hand, when the unfair offer was made by
expect that participants experiencing dis- an anonymous proposer, participants tested
gust would not only avoid contact with self- in a smelly room were in fact more likely to
ish others but also act selfishly themselves, accept the offer in comparison with those
in order to maximize their own resources. who made the decision in a neutrally scented
Indeed, a recent series of studies observed environment (Bonini et al., 2011). Hence
that participants who had been primed with disgusted individuals act in ways that maxi-
disgust by watching a video clip or han- mize their personal resources but also mini-
dling products such as antidiarrheic medi- mize potential physical connections with
cine were more likely to cheat on a game self-interested parties.
than those in the neutral condition (Wint- In sum, this section provides evidence
erich, Mittal, & Morales, 2014). Equally, a supporting the idea that the psychological
related study found that participants who system that sets the boundaries of the physi-
had been primed with facial expressions of cal body also sets boundaries of the moral
disgust were more likely to cheat on a dice- domain. First, perceived threat of physical
rolling task, particularly if they were highly infection reduces people’s inclination for so-
sensitive to disgust (Lim, Ho, & Mullette-­ cial interaction (Schaller & Murray, 2008)
Gillman, 2015). In sum, the feeling that and triggers strong avoidant tendencies that
protects the physical boundaries of the self may take the form of abstract moral values
facilitates immoral action in order to protect such as one’s views on immigration laws
one’s material resources. (Faulkner et al., 2004). Second, actions that
The present suggestion poses an inter- potentially harm or physically contaminate
esting paradox in the context of economic one’s body in the absence of any obvious
games such as the Ultimatum Game. In interpersonal harm, such as excessive food
this game, participants are asked to decide ingestion and suicide, often become moral-
whether to accept or reject another partici- ized (Rottman, Kelemen, & Young, 2014a;
pant’s monetary offers, which are either fair Sheikh et al., 2013). Indeed, even completely
or unfair splits of a total amount (e.g., $5 neutral actions are judged as “wrong” when
each vs. $9 for one participant and $1 for the coupled with disgust (Rottman & Kele-
other). If the participant rejects the offer, nei- men, 2012). Lastly, the effects of disgust on
ther party receives any funds. Unfair splits moral behavior and moral judgments extend
are normally rejected in an attempt to ex- beyond the domain of purity (Chapman &
press one’s disapproval of the other person’s Anderson, 2014), which suggests that physi-
unfair behavior. Based on previous evidence, cal disgust may lead to a general mindset of
one may predict that disgusted participants scarcity. This mindset may in turn lead to
would be particularly disapproving of the increased attempts to maximize personal re-
other player’s unfair behavior and averse sources, a hypothesis that is consistent with
284 M O R A L I T Y A N D T H E B O DY

current empirical evidence (e.g., Winterich When bodies are clean, cooperative alli-
et al., 2014). ances become more likely. An accruing line
of evidence suggests that cleanliness facili-
tates approach and is used as information
Morality as the Expansion
about other people’s moral character. A field
of One’s Boundaries
experiment, for instance, found that the
One of the most effective ways of protect- neater, cleaner, and better dressed criminal
ing one’s body against physical and biologi- defendants were in court, the more lenient
cal contamination is physical cleanliness. was the punishment applied to them (Stew-
Washing the self physically removes poten- art, 1985). Similarly, unconscious activation
tial pathogens from one’s skin, enhancing of cleanliness concepts in an experimental
both individual and group fitness (Curtis context led to more lenient judgments of
et al., 2011; Curtis, 2003). Perhaps due to other people’s transgressions (Huang, 2014;
its crucial importance to group survival, Schnall, Benton, & Harvey, 2008). Further-
actions that promote the physical purity of more, studies in the domain of interpersonal
one’s body are moralized. In the same way relationships indicate that nonsmokers are
that actions that potentially harm one’s rated as more trustworthy than smokers
body, such as cannibalism or lack of hy- (Seiter, Weger, Merrill, McKenna, & Sand-
giene, are referred to as “morally wrong,” ers, 2010). Keeping clean and groomed is
actions that physically clean one’s body or also a tactic to attract romantic partners
protect it against contamination are called (Aunger et al., 2010; Buss, 1988). All in all,
“virtuous.” These actions include bathing, these findings suggest that actions that ac-
abstaining from sexual activity, and hand tively protect the body against pathogens or
washing, which are at the core of several disease inspire positive social judgments and
prescriptive faiths (Durkheim, 1912; Haidt partnership.
& Graham, 2006; Haidt & Joseph, 2007). Whereas disgust leads to attempts to
Whereas other people’s “impure” actions maximize personal resources, a sense of
invoke a sense of moral disgust and outrage, cleanliness motivates prosocial behavior. In
actions that promote the purity of their bodies a field study, passengers in a clean-scented
trigger flashes of positive affect. For example, train compartment were less likely to leave
participants asked to imagine positive behav- garbage (e.g., used cups) on the seats and
ior in the purity domain, such as keeping one’s on the floor (de Lange, Debets, Ruitenburg,
house clean and tidy and resisting temptations & Holland, 2012). Similar effects apply
to unhealthy foods, showed relaxation of the to prosocial behaviors beyond the purity
inside brow (i.e., the corrugator supercilii domain. Critically, participants who com-
muscle), suggesting decreased negative affect, pleted an experiment in a clean-scented or
and muscle relaxation directly predicted the orderly room were more likely to reciprocate
extent to which they approved of those behav- trust and to donate to charity relative to
iors (Cannon et al., 2011). participants in a neutrally scented or disor-
In a parallel to the moralization of impure derly room (Liljenquist, Zhong, & Galinsky,
acts, positive actions in the purity domain 2010; Vohs, Redden, & Rahinel, 2013). In
are very distinct from other types of virtue, other words, disgust signals resource scar-
including kindness, loyalty, respect, and city, whereas reminders of cleanliness signal
fairness (Graham et al., 2009; Haidt & Jo- that the environment is safe to give personal
seph, 2007). These actions differ in the fun- resources away and establish new coopera-
damental sense that they do not bear direct, tive alliances.
intentional consequences to other people’s Given that physical cleanliness is linked
well-being. From a broader perspective, to virtue, it is not surprising that individuals
however, if pathogens are spread by physical physically wash themselves in attempts to re-
contact, safeguarding one’s own body from gain moral self-worth and other people’s ap-
contaminants protects other people’s bod- proval after a moral transgression. Indeed,
ies from getting physically contaminated, in a seminal study, people who had recalled
especially when individuals are expected to past unethical deeds (vs. neutral events)
interact closely. found cleansing products and antiseptic
 The Moralization of the Body 285

wipes especially appealing (Zhong & Liljen- someone else’s intentionally directed benefit
quist, 2006), a finding referred to as the create a desire to physically approach the per-
“Macbeth effect.” This tendency to physi- son who provided the benefit (Hertenstein,
cally wash away one’s sins has been repli- Keltner, App, Bulleit, & Jaskolka, 2006; Mc-
cated in several different contexts (de Zav- Cullough, Kilpatrick, Emmons, & Larson,
ala, Waldzus, & Cypryanska, 2014; Denke, 2001). Witnessing uncommon expressions
Rotte, Heinze, & Schaefer, 2014; Gollwitzer of selflessness directed to third parties ren-
& Melzer, 2012; Lee & Schwarz, 2010; for ders similar effects. Critically, breastfeeding
a review, see West & Zhong, 2015). mothers who had watched a moving video
In the same vein, participants who had clip about a selfless character were more likely
their moral standing called into question by to hug and nurse their babies compared with
either an unethical recall or exposure to an- mothers who had watched a comedy (Silvers
other person’s superior moral standing did & Haidt, 2008). These examples suggest that
not feel as threatened or regretful when this witnessing other people’s expressions of vir-
was associated with a physical cleansing in- tue toward the self or others motivate indi-
tervention (Cramwinckel, van Dijk, Scheep- viduals to physically connect their bodies to
ers, & van den Bos, 2013; Lee, Tang, Wan, other people’s bodies.
Mai, & Liu, 2015; Reuven, Liberman, & Tactile contact, in turn, redefines psycho-
Dar, 2014; Xu, Bègue, & Bushman, 2014). logical boundaries and shapes sociomoral
Physically cleansing the surface of one’s body relationships. Several studies have shown,
thus alleviates the distressing consequences for example, that even light and brief tactile
of unethical behavior, such as feelings of contacts (e.g., a pat on the back) between
guilt, as well as threats to one’s moral self- adults increases compliance and helping be-
image. Given that people intuitively make havior, such as giving back a dime left in a
more positive judgments of those who look phone booth (Brockner, Pressman, Cabitt,
“clean” and less likely to transmit pathogens, & Moran, 1982; Guéguen, 2004; Horn-
this physical cleansing intervention possibly ik, 1987; Hornik & Ellis, 1988; Willis &
helps in regaining others’ approval. In other Hamm, 1980). This suggests that physically
words, it prepares the individual to reengage uniting the surfaces of one’s body to anoth-
with others in a physical and moral sense. er’s leads to a greater willingness to share
When individuals engage with others in material resources with others. A soft touch
a positive fashion, this connection is often on the back can also shift people’s social
translated into physical proximity, making judgments. Participants who were touched
individuals more vulnerable to transmitted on the back by the clerks while checking out
pathogens. It makes sense, therefore, that books at the library attributed more positive
humans would be selective of whom they ap- traits (e.g., “helpful”) to the library person-
proach and whom they allow to approach. nel than they did when no contact had oc-
Of special importance to this chapter, these curred (Fisher, Rytting, & Heslin, 1976).
decisions to either physically avoid or ap- Similar effects of touch on person perception
proach others seem to be related to judg- have been observed in several other contexts
ments of moral character. Social grooming, (Erceau & Guéguen, 2007; Hornik, 1992;
for example, which involves direct contact Steward & Lupfer, 1987), including inter-
with skin flakes and debris of others, is personal attraction and courtship (Guéguen,
more frequent among psychologically close 2007, 2010).
individuals who also share material resourc- Touch is our first sense to develop, and
es such as food (Dunbar, 2010; Roubová, the skin is arguably our most basic means
Konená, milauer, & Wallner, 2015; see of contact with the external world (Field,
also Schnall, 2011). 2014). Babies depend on long and sustained
Whereas watching others being selfish in- bodily contact with the mother for survival,
vokes repulsion and a desire to physically including locomotion, regulation of body
distance oneself from the target, witnessing temperature, and nursing. It is thus unsur-
someone giving away their resources to others prising that touch develops as a crucial sig-
triggers strong approach tendencies. Feelings nal of trust and security and prepares indi-
of gratitude induced by being the recipient of viduals to establish cooperative alliances.
286 M O R A L I T Y A N D T H E B O DY

Beyond touch, actually incorporating mote or potentially taint the physical purity
other people’s bodily substances into one’s of the body are given the abstract status of
own bodily envelope is a strong cue for sub- “moral” or “immoral,” including excessive
jective intimacy (Fiske, 2004). For instance, food ingestion, suicide, and incest. The mor-
adult pairs eating together are perceived alization of such acts means that implicit
as more intimate, close, and attracted to processes that arise from a highly sensitive
each other when the context involves feed- behavioral system of defense against body
ing and potential transfer of germs com- injury and contamination are implicated in
pared to when such contact is absent (Alley, real-life moral decisions. Similar process-
2012; Miller, Rozin, & Fiske, 1998). At a es probably ground moral opinions about
group level, exchanges of food and com- many other contemporary human practices
munal feasts signal alliance, solidarity, and that relate to the body, including prostitu-
group membership (Johnson, White, Boyd, tion, organ trading, abortion, surrogacy,
& Cohen, 2011; Rozin, 1990). Sharing per- and many others. When actual interpersonal
sonal objects, such as pieces of clothing and harm is absent, are feelings of disgust and
toothbrushes (Brooks, Dai, & Schweitzer, aversion valid bases for the legal regulation
2014; Curtis et al., 2004; Gentina, 2014; of these actions? How are these intuitive
Miller et al., 1998), also constitutes bonds processes functionally connected to con-
of trust between non-kin. In accordance scious deliberation and analysis?
with an embodied cognitive approach, these We further present evidence that the ex-
examples suggest that physical processes tent to which one’s own body is clean or
relevant to the purity of the body create an dirty, physically strong or vulnerable, pre-
ontological scaffold for the development of dicts how one interacts with and evaluates
morally relevant behavior and judgments. others. It predicts not only whether indi-
In sum, this section provides evidence that viduals behave in a sociable and extroverted
psychological systems designed to keep one’s fashion but also their attitudes toward obese
body clean and regulating physical proxim- people, homosexuals, people with disabili-
ity to others also define boundaries in the ties, immigrants, and many other groups.
moral domain. First, physical cleanliness is These findings elegantly demonstrate that
used as a cue to judge who is a friend and moral judgments are rooted in people’s bod-
who is a foe (e.g., Stewart, 1985) and affects ies and that the rationale behind these judg-
our own sense of moral worth (Cramwinck- ments is not always available to conscious
el et al., 2013; Lee et al., 2015). Second, acts consideration. Critically, they weaken the
that actively promote physical purity are certainty we strive for in making relevant
often moralized and have the abstract sta- moral decisions and point to the importance
tus of virtue conferred upon them (Haidt of acknowledging and understanding the in-
& Graham, 2006; Haidt & Joseph, 2007). fluence of such implicit processes in moral
Third, the process of sharing material and decisions that affect the lives of many.
psychological resources with others is con- Human morality concerns abstract ideas
nected to the blur of physical bodily bound- about what is wrong and evil, right and
aries, for example, through touch or the commendable. It is also about regulating
sharing of bodily substances (Alley, 2012; our personal relationships with others (Rai
Hertenstein et al., 2006). Therefore, pro- & Fiske, 2011), and distinguishing friends
cesses of the physical body related to clean- from foes (Hamlin, 2014). Finally, it is about
liness and proximity to others are directly making decisions on what personal resourc-
relevant to social judgments and morally rel- es to give away, when, and to whom (Eisen-
evant behavior. berg et al., 2006; Tomasello & Vaish, 2013;
Warneken & Tomasello, 2009). This moral
system sustains the formation of successful
Extension and Expansion alliances and the cooperation required for
sustainable group living. Nonetheless, one
There are several provocative implications must not forget that humans navigate the
of this embodied morality approach. We social sphere in concrete, material bodies
present evidence that practices that pro- and that moral decisions often result in ap-
 The Moralization of the Body 287

proaching or avoiding others in a physical Cannon, P. R., Schnall, S., & White, M. (2011).
sense. It is, therefore, hardly surprising that Transgressions and expressions: Affective fa-
a complex system dedicated to regulating the cial muscle activity predicts moral judgments.
physical boundaries and purity of the body Social Psychological and Personality Science,
2, 325–331.
implicitly unfolds while we make abstract
Chakroff, A., Dungan, J., & Young, L. (2013).
decisions about other people and the conse- Harming ourselves and defiling others: What
quences of their actions. As Merleau-Ponty determines a moral domain? PLOS ONE, 8,
(1962, p. 146) pointed out, “the body is our e74434.
general medium for having a world,” and, as Chapman, H. A., & Anderson, A. K. (2014).
demonstrated, it is through the body that we Trait physical disgust is related to moral judg-
make judgments and act in the moral world ments outside of the purity domain. Emotion,
we share with others. 14, 341–348.
Chapman, H. A., Kim, D. A., Susskind, J. M., &
Anderson, A. K. (2009). In bad taste: Evidence
REFERENCES for the oral origins of moral disgust. Science,
323, 1222–1226.
Alley, T. R. (2012). Contaminated and uncon- Cramwinckel, F. M., van Dijk, E., Scheepers, D.,
taminated feeding influence perceived inti- & van den Bos, K. (2013). The threat of moral
macy in mixed-sex dyads. Appetite, 58, 1041– refusers for one’s self-concept and the protec-
1045. tive function of physical cleansing. Journal of
Astuti, R., & Bloch, M. (2015). The causal cog- Experimental Social Psychology, 49, 1049–
nition of wrong doing: Incest, intentionality, 1058.
and morality. Frontiers in Psychology, 6. Curtis, V. (2003). Talking dirty: How to save a
Aunger, R., Schmidt, W.-P., Ranpura, A., million lives. International Journal of Envi-
Coombes, Y., Maina, P. M., Matiko, C. N., & ronmental Health Research, 13, S73–S79.
Curtis, V. (2010). Three kinds of psychologi- Curtis, V., Aunger, R., & Rabie, T. (2004). Evi-
cal determinants for hand-washing behaviour dence that disgust evolved to protect from risk
in Kenya. Social Science and Medicine, 70, of disease. Proceedings: Biological Sciences
383–391. (Biology Letters), 277, 131–133.
Barsalou, L. W., & Wiemer-Hastings, K. (2005). Curtis, V., & Biran, A. (2001). Dirt, disgust, and
Situating abstract concepts. In D. Pecher & disease: Is hygiene in our genes? Perspectives
R. Zwaan (Eds.), Grounding cognition: The in Biology and Medicine, 44, 17–31.
role of perception and action in memory, lan- Curtis, V., de Barra, M., & Aunger, R. (2011).
guage, and thought (pp. 129–163). New York: Disgust as an adaptive system for disease
Cambridge University Press. avoidance behaviour. Philosophical Transac-
Bonini, N., Hadjichristidis, C., Mazzocco, K., tions of the Royal Society of London: Series
Demattè, M. L., Zampini, M., Sbarbati, A., B. Biological Sciences, 366, 389–401.
& Magon, S. (2011). Pecunia olet: The role Damasio, A. R. (1994). Descartes’ error: Emo-
of incidental disgust in the ultimatum game. tion, rationality and the human brain. New
Emotion, 11, 965–969. York: Putnam.
Borg, J. S., Lieberman, D., & Kiehl, K. A. (2008). Danovitch, J., & Bloom, P. (2009). Children’s
Infection, incest, and iniquity: Investigating extension of disgust to physical and moral
the neural correlates of disgust and moral- events. Emotion, 9, 107–112.
ity. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 20, de Lange, M. A., Debets, L. W., Ruitenburg, K.,
1529–1546. & Holland, R. W. (2012). Making less of a
Brockner, J., Pressman, B., Cabitt, J., & Moran, mess: Scent exposure as a tool for behavioral
P. (1982). Nonverbal intimacy, sex, and com- change. Social Influence, 7, 90–97.
pliance: A field study. Journal of Nonverbal de Zavala, A., Waldzus, S., & Cypryanska, M.
Behavior, 6, 253–258. (2014). Prejudice towards gay men and a need
Brooks, A. W., Dai, H., & Schweitzer, M. E. for physical cleansing. Journal of Experimen-
(2014). I’m sorry about the rain!: Superfluous tal Social Psychology, 54, 1–10.
apologies demonstrate empathic concern and Denke, C., Rotte, M., Heinze, H.-J., & Schaefer,
increase trust. Social Psychological and Per- M. (2014). Lying and the subsequent desire for
sonality Science, 5, 467–474. toothpaste: Activity in the somatosensory cor-
Buss, D. M. (1988). The evolution of human in- tex predicts embodiment of the moral-purity
trasexual competition: Tactics of mate attrac- metaphor. Cerebral Cortex, 26, 477–484.
tion. Journal of Personality and Social Psy- Dunbar, R. I. M. (2010). The social role of touch
chology, 54, 616–628. in humans and primates: Behavioural func-
288 M O R A L I T Y A N D T H E B O DY

tion and neurobiological mechanisms. Neu- moral fondations. Journal of Personality and
roscience and Biobehavioral Reviews, 34, Social Psychology, 96, 1029–1046.
260–268. Guéguen, N. (2004). Nonverbal encouragement
Duncan, L. A., Schaller, M., & Park, J. H. of participation in a course: The effect of
(2009). Perceived vulnerability to disease: touching. Social Psychology of Education, 7,
Development and validation of a 15-item self- 89–98.
report instrument. Personality and Individual Guéguen, N. (2007). Courtship compliance: The
Differences, 47, 541–546. effect of touch on women’s behavior. Social In-
Durkheim, E. (1912). The elementary forms of fluence, 2, 81–97.
religious life. New York: Free Press. Guéguen, N. (2010). The effect of a woman’s in-
Eisenberg, N., Fabes, R. A., & Spinrad, T. cidental tactile contact on men’s later behav-
(2006). Prosocial development. In N. Eisen- ior. Social Behavior and Personality: An In-
berg (Ed.), Handbook of child psychology: So- ternational Journal, 38, 257–266.
cial, emotional, and personality development Gutierrez, R., & Giner-Sorolla, R. (2007).
(pp. 646–718). Hoboken, NJ: Wiley. Anger, disgust, and presumption of harm as
Erceau, D., & Guéguen, N. (2007). Tactile con- reactions to taboo-breaking behaviors. Emo-
tact and evaluation of the toucher. Journal of tion, 7, 853–868.
Social Psychology, 147, 441–444. Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional dog and its ra-
Eskine, K. J., Kacinik, N. A., & Prinz, J. (2011). tional tail: A social intuitionist approach to
A bad taste in the mouth: Gustatory disgust moral judgment. Psychological Review, 108,
influences moral judgment. Psychological Sci- 814–834.
ence, 22, 295–299. Haidt, J., Bjorklund, F., & Murphy, S. (2000).
Faulkner, J., Schaller, M., Park, J. H., & Dun- Moral dumbfounding: When intuition finds
can, L. A. (2004). Evolved disease-avoidance no reason. Unpublished manuscript.
mechanisms and contemporary xenophobic Haidt, J., & Graham, J. (2006). Planet of the
attitudes. Group Processes and Intergroup Durkheimians, where community, authority,
Relations, 7, 333–353. and sacredness are foundations of morality. In
Field, T. (2014). Touch. Cambridge, MA: MIT J. Jost, A. C. Kay, & H. Thorisdotti (Eds.), So-
Press. cial and psychological bases of ideology and
Fisher, J. D., Rytting, M., & Heslin, R. (1976). system justification (pp. 371–401). New York:
Hands touching hands: Affective and evalua- Oxford University Press.
tive effects of an interpersonal touch. Sociom- Haidt, J., & Hersh, M. A. (2001). Sexual mo-
etry, 39, 416–421. rality: The cultures and emotions of conserva-
Fiske, A. P. (2004). Four modes of constituting tives and liberals. Journal of Applied Social
relationships: Consubstantial assimilation; Psychology, 31, 191–221.
space, magnitude, time, and force; concrete Haidt, J., & Joseph, C. (2007). The moral mind:
procedures; abstract symbolism. In N. Haslam How 5 sets of innate intuitions guide the de-
(Ed.), Relational models theory: A contempo- velopment of many culture-specific virtues,
rary overview (pp. 61–146). Mahwah, NJ: Erl- and perhaps even modules. In P. Carruthers, S.
baum. Laurence, & S. Stich (Eds.), The innate mind
Gallace, A., & Spence, C. (2010). The science of (pp. 367–391). New York: Oxford University
interpersonal touch: An overview. Neurosci- Press.
ence and Biobehavioral Reviews, 34, 246– Haidt, J., Koller, S. H., & Dias, M. G. (1993).
259. Affect, culture, and morality, or is it wrong to
Gentina, E. (2014). Understanding the effects of eat your dog? Journal of Personality and So-
adolescent girls’ social positions within peer cial Psychology, 65, 613–628.
groups on exchange practices. Journal of Con- Hamlin, J. K. (2014). The origins of human mo-
sumer Behaviour, 13, 73–80. rality: Complex socio-moral evaluations by
Giner-Sorolla, R., Bosson, J. K., Caswell, T. A., preverbal infants. In J. Decety & Y. Christen
& Hettinger, V. E. (2012). Emotions in sex- (Eds.), New frontiers in social neuroscience
ual morality: Testing the separate elicitors of (pp. 165–188). New York: Springer.
anger and disgust. Cognition and Emotion, Harlé, K. M., & Sanfey, A. G. (2010). Effects of
26, 1208–1222. approach and withdrawal motivation on in-
Gollwitzer, M., & Melzer, A. (2012). Macbeth teractive economic decisions. Cognition and
and the joystick: Evidence for moral cleansing Emotion, 24, 1456–1465.
after playing a violent video game. Journal of Hertenstein, M. J., Keltner, D., App, B., Bul-
Experimental Social Psychology, 48, 1356– leit, B. A., & Jaskolka, A. R. (2006). Touch
1360. communicates distinct emotions. Emotion, 6,
Graham, J., Haidt, J., & Nosek, B. (2009). Lib- 528–533.
erals and conservatives use different sets of Horberg, E. J., Oveis, C., Keltner, D., & Cohen,
 The Moralization of the Body 289

A. B. (2009). Disgust and the moralization of Lim, J., Ho, P. M., & Mullette-Gillman, O. A.
purity. Journal of Personality and Social Psy- (2015). Modulation of incentivized dishon-
chology, 97, 963–976. esty by disgust facial expressions. Frontiers in
Hornik, J. (1987). The effect of touch and gaze Neuroscience, 9, 250.
upon compliance and interest of interviewees. McCullough, M. E., Kilpatrick, S. D., Emmons, R.
Journal of Social Psychology, 127, 681–683. A., & Larson, D. B. (2001). Is gratitude a moral
Hornik, J. (1992). Tactile stimulation and con- affect? Psychological Bulletin, 127, 249–266.
sumer response. Journal of Consumer Re- Meier, B. P., Schnall, S., Schwarz, N., & Bargh,
search, 19, 449–458. J. A. (2012). Embodiment in social psychol-
Hornik, J., & Ellis, S. (1988). Strategies to se- ogy. Topics in Cognitive Science, 4, 705–716.
cure compliance for a mall intercept interview. Merleau-Ponty, M. (1962). Phenomenology of
Public Opinion Quarterly, 52, 539–551. perception. London: Routledge.
Huang, J. L. (2014). Does cleanliness influence Merleau-Ponty, M. (1964). The primacy of per-
moral judgments?: Response effort moder- ception: and other essays on phenomenologi-
ates the effect of cleanliness priming on moral cal psychology, the philosophy of art, history
judgments. Frontiers in Psychology, 5, 1276. and politics. Evanston, IL: Northwestern Uni-
Hume, D. (1960). An enquiry concerning the versity Press.
principles of morals. La Salle, IL: Open Court. Miller, L., Rozin, P., & Fiske, A. P. (1998). Food
(Original work published 1777). sharing and feeding another person suggest in-
Hutchins, E. (1995). Cognition in the wild. Cam- timacy: Two studies of American college stu-
bridge, MA: MIT Press. dents. European Journal of Social Psychology,
Inbar, Y., & Pizarro, D. A. (2014). Pollution and 28, 423–436.
purity in moral and political judgment. In J. Moretti, L., & di Pellegrino, G. (2010). Disgust
Wright & H. Sarkissian (Eds.), Advances in selectively modulates reciprocal fairness in
experimental moral psychology (pp. 112– economic interactions. Emotion, 10, 169–180.
129). London: Bloosmbury Academic. Mortensen, C. R., Becker, D. V., Ackerman, J.
Johnson, K. A., White, A. E., Boyd, B. M., & M., Neuberg, S. L., & Kenrick, D. T. (2010).
Cohen, A. B. (2011). Matzah, meat, milk, and Infection breeds reticence: The effects of dis-
mana: Psychological influences on religio-cul- ease salience on self-perceptions of personality
tural food practices. Journal of Cross-Cultur- and behavioral avoidance tendencies. Psycho-
al Psychology, 42, 1421–1436. logical Science, 21, 440–447.
Kohlberg, L., Levine, C., & Hewer, A. (1983). Murray, D. R., & Schaller, M. (2016). The be-
Moral stages: A current formulation and a re- havioral immune system: Implications for so-
sponse to critics. Basel, Switzerland: Karger. cial cognition, social interaction, and social
Kupfer, T. R., & Tybur, J. M. (2017). Pathogen influence. Advances in Experimental Social
disgust and interpersonal personality. Person- Psychology, 53, 75–129.
ality and Individual Differences, 116, 379– Navarrete, C. D., Fessler, D. M. T., & Eng, S.
384. J. (2007). Elevated ethnocentrism in the first
Lakoff, G., & Johnson, M. (1980). Metaphors trimester of pregnancy. Evolution and Human
we live by. Chicago: Chicago University Press. Behavior, 28, 60–65.
Lakoff, G., & Johnson, M. (1999). Philosophy Nemeroff, C., & Rozin, P. (1994). The contagion
in the flesh: The embodied mind and its chal- concept in adult thinking in the United States:
lenge to Western thought. New York: Basic Transmission of germs and of interpersonal in-
Books. fluence. Ethos, 22, 158–186.
Landau, M. J., Meier, B. P., & Keefer, L. A. Newman, G. E., Diesendruck, G., & Bloom, P.
(2010). A metaphor-enriched social cognition. (2011). Celebrity contagion and the value of
Psychological Bulletin, 136, 1045–1067. objects. Journal of Consumer Research, 38,
Lee, S. W. S., & Schwarz, N. (2010). Dirty hands 215–228.
and dirty mouths: Embodiment of the moral- Nichols, S. (2004). Sentimental rules: On the
purity metaphor is specific to the motor mo- natural foundations of moral judgment. New
dality involved in moral transgression. Psy- York: Oxford University Press.
chological Science, 21, 1423–1425. Niedenthal, P. M., Barsalou, L. W., Winkielman,
Lee, S. W. S., Tang, H., Wan, J., Mai, X., & Liu, P., Krauth-Gruber, S., & Ric, F. (2005). Em-
C. (2015). A cultural look at moral purity: bodiment in attitudes, social perception, and
Wiping the face clean. Frontiers in Psychol- emotion. Personality and Social Psychology
ogy, 6. Review, 9, 184–211.
Liljenquist, K., Zhong, C.-B., & Galinsky, A. D. Nucci, L. P., & Turiel, E. (1978). Social interac-
(2010). The smell of virtue: Clean scents pro- tions and the development of social concepts
mote reciprocity and charity. Psychological in preschool children. Child Development, 49,
Science, 21, 381–383. 400–407.
290 M O R A L I T Y A N D T H E B O DY

Paladino, M.-P., Mazzurega, M., Pavani, F., & Rozin, P., Lowery, L., & Ebert, R. (1994). Va-
Schubert, T. W. (2010). Synchronous multisen- rieties of disgust faces and the structure of
sory stimulation blurs self–other boundaries. disgust. Journal of Personality and Social Psy-
Psychological Science, 21, 1202–1207. chology, 66, 870–881.
Park, J. H., Faulkner, J., & Schaller, M. (2003). Rozin, P., Lowery, L., Imada, S., & Haidt, J.
Evolved disease-avoidance processes and con- (1999). The CAD triad hypothesis: A map-
temporary anti-social behavior: Prejudicial at- ping between three moral emotions (contempt,
titudes and avoidance of people with physical anger, disgust) and three moral codes (com-
disabilities. Journal of Nonverbal Behavior, munity, autonomy, divinity). Journal of Per-
27, 65–87. sonality and Social Psychology, 76, 574–586.
Park, J. H., Schaller, M., & Crandall, C. S. Rozin, P., & Singh, L. (1999). The moraliza-
(2007). Pathogen-avoidance mechanisms and tion of cigarette smoking in the United States.
the stigmatization of obese people. Evolution Journal of Consumer Psychology, 8, 321–337.
and Human Behavior, 28, 410–414. Russell, P. S., & Giner-Sorolla, R. (2011a). Moral
Parkinson, C., Sinnott-Armstrong, W., Koralus, anger is more flexible than moral disgust. So-
P. E., Mendelovici, A., McGeer, V., & Wheat- cial Psychological and Personality Science, 2,
ley, T. (2011). Is morality unified?: Evidence 360–364.
that distinct neural systems underlie moral Russell, P. S., & Giner-Sorolla, R. (2011b).
judgments of harm, dishonesty, and disgust. Moral anger, but not moral disgust, responds
Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 23, 3162– to intentionality. Emotion, 11, 233–240.
3180. Russell, P. S., & Giner-Sorolla, R. (2011c). So-
Prinz, J. (2002). Furnishing the mind. Cam- cial justifications for moral emotions: When
bridge, MA: MIT Press. reasons for disgust are less elaborated than for
Prinz, J. (2007). The emotional construction of anger. Emotion, 11, 637–646.
morals. New York: Oxford University Press. Schaller, M., Miller, G. E., Gervais, W. M.,
Rai, T. S., & Fiske, A. P. (2011). Moral psychol- Yager, S., & Chen, E. (2010). Mere visual per-
ogy is relationship regulation: Moral motives ception of other people’s disease symptoms fa-
for unity, hierarchy, equality, and proportion- cilitates a more aggressive immune response.
ality. Psychological Review, 118, 57–75. Psychological Science, 21, 649–652.
Reuven, O., Liberman, N., & Dar, R. (2014). Schaller, M., & Murray, D. R. (2008). Pathogens,
The effect of physical cleaning on threatened personality, and culture: Disease prevalence
morality in individuals with obsessive–com- predicts worldwide variability in sociosexual-
pulsive disorder. Clinical Psychological Sci- ity, extraversion, and openness to experience.
ence, 2, 224–229. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
Rosenstein, D., & Oster, H. (1988). Differential 95, 212–221.
facial responses to four basic tastes in new- Schaller, M., & Park, J. H. (2011). The behav-
borns. Child Development, 59, 1555–1568. ioral immune system (and why it matters).
Rottman, J., & Kelemen, D. (2012). Aliens be- Current Directions in Psychological Science,
having badly: Children’s acquisition of novel 20, 99–103.
purity-based morals. Cognition, 124, 356– Scheske, C., & Schnall, S. (2012). The ethics
360. of “smart drugs”: Moral judgments about
Rottman, J., Kelemen, D., & Young, L. (2014a). healthy people’s use of cognitive-enhancing
Purity matters more than harm in moral judg- drugs. Basic and Applied Social Psychology,
ments of suicide: Response to Gray (2014). 34, 508–515.
Cognition, 133, 332–334. Schnall, S. (2011). Clean, proper and tidy are
Rottman, J., Kelemen, D., & Young, L. (2014b). more than the absence of dirty, disgusting and
Tainting the soul: Purity concerns predict wrong. Emotion Review, 3, 264–266.
moral judgments of suicide. Cognition, 130, Schnall, S. (2017). Disgust as embodied loss aver-
217–226. sion. European Review of Social Psychology,
Roubová, V., Konená, M., milauer, P., & Wall- 28, 50–94.
ner, B. (2015). Whom to groom and for what?: Schnall, S., Benton, J., & Harvey, S. (2008).
Patterns of grooming in female Barbary ma- With a clean conscience: Cleanliness reduces
caques (Macaca sylvanus). PLOS ONE, 10, the severity of moral judgments. Psychological
e0117298. Science, 19, 1219–1222.
Rozin, P. (1990). Social and moral aspects of Schnall, S., Haidt, J., Clore, G. L., & Jordan, A.
food and eating. In I. Rock (Ed.), The legacy of H. (2008). Disgust as embodied moral judg-
Solomon Asch: Essays in cognition and social ment. Personality and Social Psychology Bul-
psychology (pp. 97–110). New York: Psychol- letin, 34, 1096–1109.
ogy Press. Schwarz, N. (2000). Emotion, cognition, and
 The Moralization of the Body 291

decision making. Cognition and Emotion, 14, human cooperation and morality. Annual Re-
433–440. view of Psychology, 64, 231–255.
Seidel, A., & Prinz, J. (2013). Sound morality: Tybur, J. M., Lieberman, D., Kurzban, R., &
Irritating and icky noises amplify judgments DeScioli, P. (2013). Disgust: Evolved function
in divergent moral domains. Cognition, 127, and structure. Psychological Review, 120,
1–5. 65–84.
Seiter, J. S., Weger, H., Merrill, M. L., McKenna, Vohs, K. D., Redden, J. P., & Rahinel, R. (2013).
M. R., & Sanders, M. L. (2010). Nonsmok- Physical order produces healthy choices, gen-
ers’ perceptions of cigarette smokers’ credibil- erosity, and conventionality, whereas disorder
ity, likeability, attractiveness, considerateness, produces creativity. Psychological Science, 24,
cleanliness, and healthiness. Communication 1860–1867.
Research Reports, 27, 143–158. Warneken, F., & Tomasello, M. (2009). Variet-
Sheikh, S., Botindari, L., & White, E. (2013). ies of altruism in children and chimpanzees.
Embodied metaphors and emotions in the Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 13, 397–402.
moralization of restrained eating practices. West, C., & Zhong, C.-B. (2015). Moral cleans-
Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, ing. Current Opinions in Psychology, 6, 221–
49, 509–513. 225.
Silvers, J. A., & Haidt, J. (2008). Moral elevation Wheatley, T., & Haidt, J. (2005). Hypnotic dis-
can induce nursing. Emotion, 8, 291–295. gust makes moral judgments more severe. Psy-
Smith, E. R., & Semin, G. R. (2004). Socially chological Science, 16, 780–784.
situated cognition: Cognition in its social con- Willis, F. N., & Hamm, H. K. (1980). The use
text. Advances in Experimental Social Psy- of interpersonal touch in securing compli-
chology, 36, 53–117. ance.  Journal of Nonverbal Behavior, 5, 49–
Stephan, S. (2016). Rational suicide, irrational 55.
laws: Examining current approaches to sui- Winterich, K. P., Mittal, V., & Morales, A. C.
cide in policy and law. New York: Oxford (2014). Protect thyself: How affective self-pro-
University Press. tection increases self-interested, unethical be-
Stevenson, R. J., Oaten, M. J., Case, T. I., Repa- havior. Organizational Behavior and Human
choli, B. M., & Wagland, P. (2010). Children’s Decision Processes, 125, 151–161.
response to adult disgust elicitors: Develop- Xu, H., Bègue, L., & Bushman, B. J. (2014).
ment and acquisition. Developmental Psy- Washing the guilt away: Effects of personal
chology, 46, 165–177. versus vicarious cleansing on guilty feelings
Steward, A. L., & Lupfer, M. (1987). Touching and prosocial behavior. Frontiers in Human
as teaching: The effect of touch on students’ Neuroscience, 8, 97.
perceptions and performance. Journal of Ap- Young, L., & Tsoi, L. (2013). When mental states
plied Social Psychology, 17, 800–809. matter, when they don’t, and what that means
Stewart, J. E. (1985). Appearance and punish- for morality. Social and Personality Psychol-
ment: The attraction-leniency effect in the ogy Compass, 7, 585–604.
courtroom. Journal of Social Psychology, Zhong, C.-B., & Liljenquist, K. (2006). Wash-
125, 373–378. ing away your sins: Threatened morality and
Tomasello, M., & Vaish, A. (2013). Origins of physical cleansing. Science, 313, 1451–1452.
CHAPTER 30

Grounded Morality

Simon M. Laham
Justin J. Kelly

What is the nature of moral psychological processing?

Grounded approaches suggest that a full understanding of moral


phenomena must consider the way that mental representations and
psychological processes are shaped by the physical bodies and envi‑
ronments in which they operate.

Moral phenomena, from moral concepts structured; second, that moral psychologi-
to psychological processes (such as moral cal processes (such as moral perception and
perception or categorization) to moral judg- judgment) are at least partially informed by
ments, decisions, and behaviors can only afferent feedback from the body; and, third,
be fully understood by taking a grounded that moral phenomena are best studied and
approach to moral psychology. Ground- conceptualized with reference to the tem-
ed approaches can be thought of as broad poral, spatial, and social contexts in which
frameworks that take seriously the fact that they are embedded or situated. Thus moral
psychological concepts, processes, and out- cognition is best conceived of as being meta-
puts are (at least partially) shaped by the phorically structured, embodied, and em-
way our physical bodies interact with the bedded.
world. In contrast to classical accounts of The implications of such assumptions
cognition as computation over amodal rep- are manifold and require new conceptual,
resentations, grounded accounts conceive theoretical, and empirical approaches to the
of cognition as multimodal simulation and study of moral psychology. Although such
emphasize the role of bodily states and the considerations are unlikely to be sufficient
body–environment nexus in thinking and for a comprehensive account of the psychol-
feeling (see Barsalou, 2008, for a review). ogy of morality, they are certainly necessary.
The term grounded cognition (sometimes
embodied cognition) is ambiguous (Gold-
man & de Vignemont, 2009; Wilson, 2002); Historical Context
we focus here on three senses of the term.
First, we hold that moral concepts (such as Grounded approaches are usually best un-
justice and goodness) are metaphorically derstood in contrast to standard or classical

292
 Grounded Morality 293

accounts of cognition. The central assump- in social psychology also had a distinctly
tion of classical accounts is that thinking is embodied flavor, emphasizing the role of ac-
information processing—computations per- tion in attitude acquisition and processing
formed over amodal mental representations. (Allport, 1935).
Such representations are abstract, often In contemporary cognitive science, a wide
quasi-linguistic symbols that bear no intrin- variety of theories fall under the umbrella of
sic relationships to the physical or functional grounded cognition. Some emphasize meta-
features of their referents. This view of cog- phors as the building blocks of abstract con-
nition came to prominence with the cogni- cepts (e.g., Lakoff & Johnson, 1980), others
tive revolution, during which the computer posit simulation and reenactment as con-
metaphor of mind and functionalism justi- stitutive of thought (e.g., Barsalou, 1999),
fied a psychology in which the software of and yet others stress the situated, contex-
the mind was deemed largely independent tual constraints on cognitive processes (e.g.,
of the hardware of the body (see Gardner, Smith & Semin, 2007). Although such var-
1985, for a historical account of the cogni- ied accounts share some features, they differ
tive revolution). on others (see Wilson, 2002, for a review).
In stark contrast to classical accounts, As such, there is no single theory of ground-
grounded approaches seek to put the mind ed cognition. Rather, these varied efforts are
and body back together (see Barsalou, best thought of as specific theoretical instan-
2008; Glenberg, 2010; Niedenthal, Barsa- tiations of a general framework that holds
lou, Winkielman, Krauth-Gruber, & Ric, that the functions performed by the brain
2005, for reviews). One common feature of can only fully be understood if we appreci-
grounded approaches (of which there are a ate the facts that (1) bodies house brains and
variety) is that they conceive of thought as (2) bodies interact with particular social–
involving modal representations. These are spatial–temporal environments. In what fol-
representations utilized by specific modal lows, we argue that moral psychology would
systems (e.g., perceptual, motor, introspec- benefit from appreciating these facts.
tive) and are thought to retain something of
the physical and functional features of their
referents (see Goldman & de Vignemont, Theoretical Stance
2009). On this account, concepts (even ab-
stract concepts) are multimodal (not amo- In light of these basic properties of grounded
dal) representations, and thinking is simu- approaches, the three senses of grounded we
lation—offline reenactment of sensory and note above are worth explicating here, with
motor experience. particular reference to moral psychology.
Such approaches have garnered increased These concepts are introduced here but are
attention in psychology of late, but they are not fully explored until the following sec-
not all that new in the history of thought. tion.
Grounded accounts of the mind have deep Certain theories of grounded cognition
historical roots in the Western philosophi- suggest that abstract concepts, including
cal tradition. The views of the ancients were moral concepts such as goodness, justice,
distinctly grounded, holding knowledge to and divinity, which do not have any obvious
be represented modally and via imagery (see sensory or motor features, can nevertheless
Barsalou, 1999). The British empiricists, be accommodated within a multimodal rep-
too, endorsed philosophies of mind similar resentational system because they are meta-
to contemporary theories of grounded cog- phorically grounded in the concrete world
nition (see Boroditsky & Prinz, 2008). Even of sense and action (see Landau, Meier,
within psychology, early conceptions of & Keefer, 2010, for a review). Conceptual
mental constructs had a distinctly grounded metaphor theory (Lakoff & Johnson, 1980),
flavor. Galton (1884), for example, defined for example, states that abstract concepts
attitudes in terms of body posture, and Dar- are understood via analogical extensions of
win (1872/1904) similarly featured posture sensory and motor experience. Our experi-
and other motor responses in his definition ence with the everyday physical world—
of the construct. Early accounts of attitudes the world of spatial relations, temperature,
294 M O R A L I T Y A N D T H E B O DY

weight, direction, size—forms the basis of partly constituted by motor representations


our understanding of more abstract, non- of actions typically performed on the object
physical elements of our moral worlds. Prop- (e.g., pulling toward the self). Thus, activat-
erties of these physical source domains (and ing a representation of the object involves
relations among such properties) are ex- the motor representation of pulling, which
tended to abstract target domains. Divinity, facilitates the overt pulling response. In a
for example, is spatially up (Meier, Hauser, similar way, to the extent that moral atti-
Robinson, Friesen, & Schjeldahl, 2007), tude objects are processed using multimodal
as is moral (Meier, Sellbom, & Wygant, representations partly constituted by motor
2007), whereas bad and immoral are down representations, the performance of certain
(Meier & Robinson, 2004). Importantly, on actions during moral stimulus processing
many grounded cognition accounts, think- may influence moral cognition and moral
ing about goodness and badness involves judgment.
(among other things) the reenactment of On the third sense of grounded that we
the sensory and motor experiences involved are using here, moral cognition is embedded
with spatial verticality. Abstract concepts (or situated) to the extent that it depends
are thus grounded in our sensory and motor upon the social–physical environment in
experiences of the world. which it takes place. This is not a new idea
A related implication of some grounded for social psychologists (see Meier, Schnall,
approaches is that moral cognition—which Schwarz & Bargh, 2012; Smith & Semin,
involves reenactment of sensory–motor ex- 2007), but the centrality of context seems
periences related to the source domains of to have been overlooked in much moral psy-
abstract moral concepts—will be influenced chological theorizing. Moral thought and its
by afferent feedback from the body. To the outputs are malleable and sensitive to con-
extent that modality-specific motor repre- textual cues. And although moral psychol-
sentations partly constitute moral concepts, ogy is replete with examples of the context
engaging in certain actions (or covertly sim- sensitivity of moral judgments (see Sinnott-
ulating them) is likely to play a causal role in Armstrong, 2008, and below for reviews),
moral thought. If goodness is partly consti- most researchers do not treat such effects as
tuted by motor representations of up, then integral to their theories but rather as noise
engaging in physical, upward movements, that masks more stable moral preferences
for example, should potentiate the goodness (cf., Rai & Fiske, 2011).
concept. Moral cognition is thus embod- Taken together, these three senses of
ied to the extent that body-related mental grounded suggest theorizing in moral psy-
representations (pertaining to morphology, chology that (1) treats abstract moral con-
posture, and action) are causally implicated cepts as metaphorically structured, (at least
in cognitive processing. Action (and action partially) grounded in concrete source do-
representation) is not simply an output of a mains; (2) holds that moral cognition is in-
cognitive process but a causal component of fluenced by afferent bodily feedback; and
the process itself. (3) builds the context-sensitivity of moral
Research on embodied attitudes is illus- cognition, judgment, and behavior into the
trative of this point. Work on the affective bedrock of theory.
compatibility effect shows that behavioral Such theorizing is not prevalent in moral
responses to valenced stimuli are facilitated psychology. The majority of extant accounts
when there is a match between the valence in the domain either implicitly or explicitly
of a stimulus and the valence of the response draw on classical cognition or are ambigu-
(see Laham, Kashima, Dix, & Wheeler, ous on the nature of the representations and
2015, for a review). Arm flexion, for example processes implicated in moral phenomena.
(when framed as approach), is facilitated in Haidt’s social intuitionist model (Haidt,
response to positive stimuli, and arm exten- 2001), for example, posits roles for intuitive
sion (when framed as avoidance) is facilitat- and deliberative processes in moral judg-
ed in response to negative stimuli. According ment and emphasizes “gut reactions” (which
to grounded cognition accounts, the mental may very well be realized in multimodal
representation of a favored attitude object is representations), but the nature of these rep-
 Grounded Morality 295

resentations and processes is not fully expli- ent stages of development. Work on moral
cated. Greene’s dual-process model (Greene, metaphors has yielded numerous demonstra-
Sommerville, Nystrom, Darley, & Cohen, tions of proof of concept (despite some rep-
2001) also gives roles to intuitive, affective, licability concerns) and now requires theo-
and deliberative processes in moral dilemma retical development and integration. Work
resolution but, again, is silent about the na- on embodied morality, however, has yet to
ture of the representations over which such sufficiently demonstrate the existence of key
processes may operate. Another prominent effects. Research on the context specificity
theory in moral psychology, universal moral of moral judgment and behavior abounds,
grammar (UMG; Mikhail, 2007), is an ex- but such effects have yet to be integrated
plicitly computational theory that does not into theories stressing embeddedness as a
clearly make room for grounded representa- theoretically central notion.
tions or processes.
Theories that take metaphor, embodi-
Metaphors and Morality
ment, and embeddedness seriously may have
numerous advantages over those that do not. The majority of work demonstrating that
Not only might such theories better accom- abstract moral concepts are metaphorically
modate the range of empirical findings out- grounded in nonmoral source domains uses
lined herein, but they have numerous extra- a metaphorical transfer methodology (see
empirical virtues. Landau et al., 2010, for a review). This in-
First, they are generative. Grounded ap- volves manipulating psychological states re-
proaches are productive of a range of hy- lated to the source (or target) domain and
potheses not readily derivable from classi- observing whether effects are observed in
cal cognition accounts. It is difficult to see, the target (or source) domain that are con-
for example, how afferent bodily feedback sistent with the metaphoric relation. This
effects might be predicted from classi- technique has provided support for the fol-
cal cognition accounts of moral judgment. lowing conceptual moral metaphors: good is
And although classical accounts may very up–bad is down (e.g., Meier & Robinson,
well be able to accommodate such findings 2004); good is right–bad is left (for right-
post hoc, it is more difficult to see how they handers, the reverse for left-handers; Casas-
would generate such predictions a priori (see anto, 2009); moral is bright–immoral is dark
Niedenthal et al., 2005, for a similar point (Meier, Robinson, & Clore, 2004); morality
in the domain of social psychology). is cleanliness (e.g., Lee & Schwarz, 2010);
Second, grounded approaches may better divinity is up (Meier et al., 2007); power-
serve to integrate or unify (moral) psycho- ful is up–powerless is down (e.g., Schubert,
logical sciences (Glenberg, 2010). As Meier 2005), and many others (see Landau et al.,
et al. (2012) note, grounded approaches use 2010, for a review).
a conceptual vocabulary that enables poten- This research suggests that at least some
tial integration of evolutionary and devel- concepts involved in moral cognition are (at
opmental approaches with mechanistic ac- least partially) metaphorically grounded in
counts of cognition. Notions of phylogenetic concrete source domains. At the moment,
and ontogenetic scaffolding are more easily however, work on moral metaphors is piece-
interpretable within frameworks that read- meal and consists of a host of demonstra-
ily ground complex, abstract concepts (the tion studies with little attempt at theoreti-
province of adult humans) in sensory–motor cal integration (a concern echoed in Meier
experience. et al., 2012; Landau et al., 2010). What
is needed is a mechanistic account of how
conceptual metaphors are formed and rep-
Evidence resented and how they operate in moral
judgment and decision making. Such ac-
Research on each of the three different counts may help to answer important ques-
senses of grounded morality—metaphori- tions about conceptual metaphors of moral-
cally structured moral concepts, embodied ity: Are all moral concepts metaphorically
morality, embedded morality—is at differ- structured? Are some moral concepts only
296 M O R A L I T Y A N D T H E B O DY

partially metaphorically structured? More effect resonating with the findings of Chap-
deeply: Are conceptual metaphors a conse- man et al. (2009). This activity was correlat-
quence of, constitutive of, or epiphenomenal ed with condemnation of purity and fairness
to moral cognition? What are the limits of violations. Corrugator activity was increased
metaphorical structuring? by harm violations and was also associated
Answering this last question, which in- with moral judgments about harm.
volves identifying boundary conditions to It is not clear from such findings, how-
metaphorical structuring, may be useful not ever, whether facial muscle activity (or men-
only in specifying theory but also in mak- tal representations thereof) play a causal
ing sense of the replicability problem in this role in moral cognition (a requirement of
area. Certain studies on moral metaphors many embodied accounts; see Goldman &
(e.g., Zhong & Liljenquist’s [2006] work on de ­Vignemont, 2009); facial muscle activity
morality and cleanliness) have proved diffi- could be simply epiphenomenal. To explore
cult to replicate (see Earp, Everett, Madva, such a possibility, one must move beyond
& Hamlin, 2014; Fayard, Bassi, Bernstein, correlational designs.
& Roberts, 2009; Johnson, Cheung, & One strategy would be to use interfer-
Donnellan, 2014). Having an idea of theo- ence paradigms. Noninvasive interference
retically specified boundaries to conceptual with facial expressions is commonly done
metaphor may give us an a priori sense of by placing a pen across participants’ teeth
what kinds of metaphors are likely to exist and lips, which enforces a “neutral” facial
within the moral domain. expression. This technique, used in the well-
known humor studies of Strack, Martin,
and Stepper (1988), is now well established
Bodies and Morality
(Niedenthal, 2007; Niedenthal, Brauer, Hal-
Whereas moral metaphor work requires the- berstadt, & Innes-Ker, 2001; Oberman,
ory development, moral embodiment work Winkielman, & Ramachandran, 2007) as
requires demonstration studies. To date, a means of testing the causal role of facial
there is little research that explicitly links af- feedback in emotion processing. By compar-
ferent body feedback causally to moral cog- ing groups that do versus do not have certain
nition. facial muscles obstructed, one can test the
There is some correlational evidence, claim that facial feedback is causally impli-
however, suggestive of the role of afferent cated in moral judgment.
feedback in the moral domain (Chapman, The face, of course, is not the only source
Kim, Susskind & Anderson, 2009; Cannon, of peripheral afferent feedback that may
Schnall, & White, 2011; Whitton, Henry, play a role in the moral domain. Work on
Rendall, & Grisham, 2014). Various stud- attitudes, for example, has demonstrated the
ies have monitored facial muscle activity via role of flexion and extension arm movements
electromyography (EMG) during the pre- in both the processing of valenced informa-
sentation of moral stimuli. Chapman et al. tion and attitude acquisition (e.g., Laham et
(2009), for example, measured EMG activ- al., 2015). Given that morally relevant stim-
ity during fair and unfair offers in the Ulti- uli are typically strongly valenced and that
matum Game. Activity of the levator labii moral judgments are essentially attitudes
muscles, responsible for wrinkling up the (e.g., X is good; X is wrong), one might pre-
nose in disgust, was strongly elicited by un- dict that flexion and extension arm move-
fair offers. ments (suitably contextually framed) might
Cannon et al. (2011) used EMG to mea- (1) differentially influence the processing
sure facial expressions in response to a va- of moral stimuli and (2) play a role in the
riety of moral violations. Electrodes were acquisition of moral attitudes. Additional
placed over three sites: levator labii (i.e., work might involve the study of individual
facial disgust), zygomaticus (i.e., smiling/ differences in morphology and of postural
positive affect), and corrugator muscles (i.e., variations in moral cognition. Work on em-
frowning/facial anger). The researchers ob- bodied morality is in its early phases, and
served increased facial disgust in response numerous avenues are open for future dem-
to purity and fairness violations, the latter onstration studies.
 Grounded Morality 297

Contexts and Morality tional contexts in which moral foundational


violations and values are processed influence
Moral judgments, like other social judg-
judgments about such violations and values.
ments, are context dependent (see Sinnott-
There are many other contextual factors
Armstrong, 2008, for a review). Situational
that influence moral judgments. What is
factors such as decision frames (e.g., Laham,
needed is a move in theorizing to take these
2009), processing fluency (e.g., Laham,
effects seriously, not to view them merely as
Alter, & Goodwin, 2009), and even word-
noise. Moral cognition is situated, or embed-
ing (e.g., Petrinovich & O’Neill, 1996) all ded, in social–physical environments. This is
influence moral judgments. not just to say, tritely, that any particular in-
Yet, while contextual effects abound in stance of moral cognition takes place in par-
moral psychology, broader theories of mo- ticular social–spatial–temporal milieus but
rality tend to downplay their theoretical that the particulars of the milieu influence
import. Moral foundations theory (MFT; the very nature of moral cognition. Theo-
Haidt & Joseph, 2004; Haidt, 2012), for ries of moral cognition need to place context
example, posits the existence of five (or six) specificity more centrally.
moral value domains that guide the major-
ity of our moral judgments: care/harm, fair-
ness/cheating, loyalty/betrayal, authority/ Extension and Expansion
subversion, sanctity/degradation (and per-
haps liberty/oppression). Although this the- We have explored three senses of grounded
ory recognizes a plurality of values, it does in this chapter and have considered how
not focus on the flexibility with which such research in each of these domains might
values are applied in judgments. progress. There are numerous other senses
Moral values and preferences may be less of grounded that may also have implications
stable than we think. Work on self-persua- for research in moral cognition, some of
sion (e.g., Briñol, McCaslin, & Petty, 2012) which have been explored elsewhere. Prinz
and audience design (or the saying is believ- (2007), for example, suggests that moral
ing effect; e.g., Higgins & Rholes, 1978), for concepts are grounded in emotions—that
example, suggests that attitudes are influ- “the concepts of right and wrong are con-
enced by the social contexts in which they stituted by a variety of emotions of praise
are processed. There is no reason to expect and blame” (Boroditsky & Prinz, 2008,
moral preferences to be immune to such ef- p. 104)—and work on simulation accounts
fects. of theory of mind (e.g., Goldman, 2006)
Take relational context: Ample work have clear implications for the role of multi-
shows that various aspects of our psychol- modal reenactment in the kinds of empathic
ogy are attuned to the relational contexts in processes central to moral cognition.
which we are embedded (Fiske, 1991). Moral There are two additional ways in which
judgments, decisions, and behaviors are em- moral cognition may be grounded: It is time
bedded within particular relationships (Rai pressured, and it may involve offloading of
& Fiske, 2011), and this fact changes the work onto the environment (Wilson, 2002).
way that foundational moral values mani- Although embeddedness is typically taken
fest. Rai and Fiske (2011) argue that people to mean merely context specific, there is a
pursue different moral motives in different deeper sense in which moral cognition is
relational contexts—unity in communal situated or embedded within social–­spatial–
sharing relationships, equality in equality temporal milieus. Moral perception, catego-
matching relationships, hierarchy in author- rization, decision making, and so on all take
ity ranking relationships, and proportion- place “online” and in “real time”—each
ality in market pricing relationships. What process requires time-constrained respon-
this means is that moral concerns will be siveness to the environment, ongoing in-
different in different social–relational con- formation collection, and updating. To the
texts. In numerous recent studies, Simpson extent that laboratory contexts implement
and Laham (2015a, 2015b; also Simpson, “artificial time”—for example, unlimited
Laham, & Fiske, 2016) found that the rela- time to decide whether one will engage a
298 M O R A L I T Y A N D T H E B O DY

perpetrator—lab results may give a mislead- that moral cognition is for moral action and
ing characterization of moral cognition. Al- that the body–environment nexus shapes the
though time pressure has been used as a ma- very nature of moral thought.
nipulation in moral psychological research
(e.g., Suter & Hertwig, 2011), it is typically REFERENCES
employed within classical-cognition dual-
process accounts and does not often feature Allport, G. W. (1935). Attitudes. In C. Murchin-
centrally in theorizing. More attention could son (Ed.), A handbook of social psychology
be paid to the time course of moral cognition (pp. 798–844). Worcester, MA: Clark Univer-
and the implications of implementing differ- sity Press.
ent time constraints within the laboratory. Barsalou, L. W. (1999). Perceptual symbol sys-
A more radical notion of embeddedness tems. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 22,
construes cognition as distributed not only 577–660.
Barsalou, L. W. (2008). Grounded cognition.
within minds but also across minds and Annual Review of Psychology, 59, 617–645.
environments (e.g., Clark, 1999; Hutchins, Boroditsky, L., & Prinz, J. (2008). What thoughts
1995). On such accounts, what does the are made of. In G. R. Semin & E. R. Smith
thinking is the organism–environment sys- (Eds.), Embodied grounding: Social, cogni-
tem, not the organism itself. Whereas such tive, affective and neuroscientific approaches
approaches raise numerous ontological ques- (pp. 98–115). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge
tions, the less radical notion that we offload University Press.
cognitive work onto the environment is Briñol, P., McCaslin, M. J., & Petty, R. E.
not so problematic (Wilson, 2002). Dur- (2012). Self-generated persuasion: Effects of
the target and direction of arguments. Jour-
ing problem solving, for example, we may nal of Personality and Social Psychology, 102,
engage in epistemic actions, using the envi- 925–940.
ronment to do some of our thinking for us Cannon, P. R., Schnall, S., & White, M. (2011).
(e.g., Kirsh & Maglio, 1994). One intriguing Transgressions and expressions: Affective fa-
possibility is that we might offload moral cial muscle activity predicts moral judgments.
work onto the environment. Schwartz and Social Psychology and Personality Science,
Sharpe (2011), for example, claim that the 2(3), 325–331.
prevalence of ethical rules and guidelines in Casasanto, D. (2009). Embodiment of abstract
the workplace may constitute an offloading concepts: Good and bad in right- and left-
handers. Journal of Experimental Psychology:
of moral decision making onto the environ- General, 138, 351–367.
ment. Moral judgment and decision making Chapman, H. A., Kim, D. A., Susskind, J. M., &
becomes less about a reflective weighing of Anderson, A. K. (2009). In bad taste: Evidence
the moral costs and benefits of certain ac- for the oral origins of moral disgust. Science,
tions and more a mindless adherence to ex- 323, 1222–1226.
ternally represented rules. Clark, A. (1999). An embodied cognitive science.
Taken together, the implications of the Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 3, 345–351.
various senses of groundedness explored Darwin, C. (1904). The expression of emotion in
throughout this chapter are potentially man and animals. London: Murray. (Original
work published 1872)
radical. What they suggest is that theories Earp, B. D., Everett, J. A. C., Madva, E. N., &
of moral cognition need to incorporate the Hamlin, J. K. (2014). Out, damned spot: Can
facts that moral thought and action happen the “Macbeth effect” be replicated? Basic and
in particular, time-constrained situations Applied Social Psychology, 36, 91–98.
and are implemented in a cognitive system Fayard, J. V., Bassi, A. K., Bernstein, D. M., &
using representations that are multimodal Roberts, B. W. (2009). Is cleanliness next to
and grounded, by metaphoric relation, to godliness? Dispelling old wives’ tales: Failure
concrete base domains. We do not think that to replicate Zhong and Liljenquist (2006).
grounded approaches will prove sufficient to Journal of Articles in Support of the Null Hy-
pothesis, 6, 21–30.
provide a complete picture of moral cogni- Fiske, A. P. (1991). Structures of social life: The
tion—theoretical tools from other frame- four elementary forms of human relations.
works may also be necessary. However, we New York: Free Press.
do not think that a comprehensive account Galton, F. (1884). Measurement of character.
of moral psychology can ignore the notions Fortnightly Review, 42, 179–185.
 Grounded Morality 299

Gardner, H. (1985). The mind’s new science: A (2010). A metaphor-enriched social cognition.
history of the cognitive revolution. New York: Psychological Bulletin, 136, 1045–1067.
Basic Books. Lee, S. W., & Schwarz, N. (2010). Dirty hands
Glenberg, A. M. (2010). Embodiment as a uni- and dirty mouths: Embodiment of the moral-
fying perspective for psychology. Wiley Inter- purity metaphor is specific to the motor mo-
disciplinary Reviews: Cognitive Science, 1, dality involved in moral transgression. Psy-
586–596. chological Science, 21, 1423–1425.
Goldman, A. (2006). Simulating minds: The Meier, B. P., Hauser, D. J., Robinson, M. D., Fri-
philosophy, psychology and neuroscience of esen, C. K., & Schjeldahl, K. (2007). What’s
mindreading. Oxford, UK: Oxford University “up” with God?: Vertical space as a represen-
Press. tation of the divine. Journal of Personality
Goldman, A., & de Vignemont, F. (2009). Is so- and Social Psychology, 93, 699–710.
cial cognition embodied? Trends in Cognitive Meier, B. P., & Robinson, M. D. (2004). Why
Sciences, 13, 154–159. the sunny side is up. Psychological Science, 15,
Greene, J. D., Sommerville, R. B., Nystrom, L. 243–247.
E., Darley, J. M., & Cohen, J. D. (2001). An Meier, B. P., Robinson, M. D., & Clore, G. L.
fMRI investigation of emotional engagement (2004). Why good guys wear white: Auto­
in moral judgment. Science, 293, 2105–2108. matic inferences about stimulus valence based
Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional dog and its ratio- on brightness. Psychological Science, 15,
nal tail. Psychological Review, 108, 814–834. 82–87.
Haidt, J. (2012). The righteous mind: Why good Meier, B. P., Schnall, S., Schwarz, N., & Bargh, J.
people are divided by politics and religion. A. (2012). Embodiment in social psychology.
New York: Pantheon. Topics in Cognitive Science, 4(4), 705–716.
Haidt, J., & Joseph, C. (2004). Intuitive ethics: Meier, B. P., Sellbom, M., & Wygant, D. B.
How innately prepared intuitions generate (2007). Failing to take the moral high ground:
culturally variable virtues. Daedalus, 133, Psychopathy and the vertical representation of
55–66. morality. Personality and Individual Differ-
Higgins, E. T., & Rholes, W. S. (1978). “Saying is ences, 43(4), 757–767.
believing”: Effects of message modification on Mikhail, J. (2007). Universal moral grammar:
memory and liking for the person perceived. Theory, evidence and the future. Trends in
Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, Cognitive Sciences, 11, 143–152.
14, 363–378. Niedenthal, P. M. (2007). Embodying emotion.
Hutchins, E. (1995). Cognition in the wild. Cam- Science, 316, 1002–1005.
bridge, MA: MIT Press. Niedenthal, P. M., Barsalou, L. W., Winkielman,
Johnson, D. J., Cheung, F., & Donnellan, M. B. P., Krauth-Gruber, S., & Ric, F. (2005). Em-
(2014). Does cleanliness influence moral judg- bodiment in attitudes, social perception and
ments?: A direct replication of Schnall, Ben- emotion. Personality and Social Psychological
ton, and Harvey (2008). Social Psychology, Review, 9, 184–211.
45(3), 209–215. Niedenthal, P. M., Brauer, M., Halberstadt, J.
Kirsh, D., & Maglio, P. (1994). On distinguish- B., & Innes-Ker, A. H. (2001). When did her
ing epistemic from pragmatic action. Cogni- smile drop?: Facial mimicry and the influences
tive Science, 18, 513–549. of emotional state on the detection of change
Laham, S. M. (2009). Expanding the moral cir- in emotional expression. Cognition and Emo-
cle: Inclusion and exclusion mindsets and the tion, 15(6), 853–864.
circle of moral regard. Journal of Experimen- Oberman, L. M., Winkielman, P., & Ramachan-
tal Social Psychology, 45, 250–253. dran, V. S. (2007). Face to face: Blocking facial
Laham, S. M., Alter, A. L., & Goodwin, G. mimicry can selectively impair recognition of
(2009). Easy on the mind, easy on the wrong- emotional expressions. Social Neuroscience,
doer: Discrepantly fluent violations are 2(3–4), 167–178.
deemed less morally wrong. Cognition, 112, Petrinovich, L., & O’Neill, P. (1996). Influence
462–466. of wording and framing effects on moral in-
Laham, S. M., Kashima, Y., Dix, J., & Wheeler, tuitions. Ethology and Sociobiology, 17, 145–
M. (2015). A meta-analysis of the facilitation 171.
of arm flexion and extension movements as a Prinz, J. J. (2007). The emotional construction
function of stimulus valence. Cognition and of morals. Oxford, UK: Oxford University
Emotion, 29, 1069–1090. Press.
Lakoff, G., & Johnson, M. (1980). Metaphors Rai, S. T., & Fiske, A. P. (2011). Moral psychol-
we live by. Chicago: University of Chicago ogy is relationship regulation: Moral motives
Press. for unity, hierarchy, equality, and proportion-
Landau, M. J., Meier, B. P., & Keefer, L. A. ality. Psychological Review, 118, 57–75.
300 M O R A L I T Y A N D T H E B O DY

Schubert, T. W. (2005). Your highness: Verti- ence of morality: Intuition and diversity
cal positions as perceptual symbols of power. (pp. 47–76). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, Smith, E. R., & Semin, G. R. (2007). Situated
89, 1–21. social cognition. Current Directions in Psy-
Schwartz, B., & Sharpe, K. (2011). Practical wis- chological Science, 16, 132–135.
dom. New York: Riverhead Books. Strack, F., Martin, L. L., & Stepper, S. (1988).
Simpson, A., & Laham, S. M. (2015a). Differ- Inhibiting and facilitating conditions of the
ent relational models underlie prototypical left human smile: A nonobtrusive test of the facial
and right positions on social issues. European feedback hypothesis. Journal of Personality
Journal of Social Psychology, 45, 204–217. and Social Psychology, 54, 768–777.
Simpson, A., & Laham, S. M. (2015b). Indi- Suter, R. S., & Hertwig, R. (2011). Time and
vidual differences in relational construal are moral judgment. Cognition, 119, 454–458.
associated with variability in moral judgment. Whitton, A. E., Henry, J. D., Rendell, P. G., &
Personality and Individual Differences, 74, Grisham, J. R. (2014). Disgust, but not anger
49–54. provocation, enhances levator labii superioris
Simpson, A., Laham, S. M., & Fiske, A. P. activity during exposure to moral transgres-
(2016). Wrongness in different relationships: sions. Biological Psychology, 96, 48–56.
Relational context effects on moral judg- Wilson, M. (2002). Six views of embodied cog-
ment.  Journal of Social Psychology, 156, nition. Psychonomic Bulletin and Review, 9,
594–609. 625–636.
Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2008). Framing moral Zhong, C., & Liljenquist, K. (2006). Wash-
intuitions. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), ing away your sins: Threatened morality and
Moral psychology: Vol. 2. The cognitive sci- physical cleansing. Science, 313, 1451–1452.
PART VII
MORALITY AND BELIEFS

Q U E S T I O N S A N S W E R E D I N PA R T V I I

CHAPTER 31  How do people answer the question of why good


and bad people exist and why good and bad events occur?

CHAPTER 32  To what extent do ordinary individuals regard moral beliefs


as capturing objective truths about morality, and how do their views
about this predict other attitudes and behaviors?

CHAPTER 33  Is morality intuitive or deliberative?

CHAPTER 34  Does moral psychology need a workable concept of free will?

CHAPTER 35  How do religious and secular institutions make us moral?

CHAPTER 36  Why are intelligent design arguments so moralized?


C H A P T E R 31

Moral Vitalism

Brock Bastian

How do people answer the question of why good and bad people
exist and why good and bad events occur?

Moral vitalism is a lay belief that good and evil forces exist in the
natural world; it provides an answer for why good and bad things
happen, shapes how people respond to these events, and may be
especially pronounced in capricious contexts.

The role of spiritual beliefs in moral rea- how they influence moral cognition and be-
soning and judgment have been sorely over- havior.
looked. To date, links between morality and Moral vitalism is understood to be a lay
spirituality have been drawn by focusing on theory that people rely on to understand
how a belief in God may shape thinking and their worlds. To this extent, a belief that
behavior (e.g., Shariff & Norenzayan, 2007) there are forces of good and evil in the nat-
but have not sought to penetrate into the ural world is attractive because it provides
nature of spiritual cognition. Other work people with a convenient explanation for
has focused on issues of sanctity or purity, why good and bad things happen, as well
linking spirituality to concerns over biologi- as what makes people good or bad. People
cal contamination (e.g., Haidt & Joseph, who endorse a belief in moral vitalism agree
2004), yet how this translates into specific with statements such as “There are underly-
moral beliefs that contribute to purity con- ing forces of good and evil in this world”;
cerns within the moral domain has not been “Either the forces of good or the forces of
specified. Moral vitalism captures a mode evil are responsible for most of the events in
of thinking that assumes that good and evil the world today”; and “The forces of good
are active forces that can exert a profound and evil often motivate human behavior.” In
influence on people and events. It is a lay this way moral vitalism acts as a heuristic
theory that embraces the dual beliefs that for navigating the complex world of moral
forces of good and evil (1) actually exist and judgment and behavior. Like other lay theo-
(2) may cause moral and immoral events to ries, moral vitalism may often be largely im-
occur. As such, the theory of moral vital- plicit and poorly articulated. As such, people
ism aims to understand how spiritual beliefs may assume that good and evil are actual
within the moral domain are structured and objective phenomena that are manifested

303
304 M O R A L I T Y A N D B E L I E F S

in the world and that possess power, force, to explain observable events. This type of
and intentionality, yet be unable to specify reasoning is not only evident within many
why or how this is so. This understanding traditional belief systems (Atran et al., 2002;
of good and evil may, in turn, shape how Frazer, 1890/1959), but also within early
people reason about morally relevant events, scientific and psychological theorizing (Jung
yet they may lack insight into the influence 1917/1983; Bechtel & Richardson, 1998),
of these beliefs. and remains prominent within children’s
In terms of how moral vitalism may af- naïve understandings of biology (Inagaki
fect moral reasoning, it is argued that this & Hatano, 2004; Morris, Taplin, & Gel-
should be especially apparent in how people man, 2000). For instance, the notion of “life
reason about issues concerning moral conta- force” often provides a convenient place-
gion and contamination—that is, concerns holder for understanding how things grow
about the potential influence of nonmate- or what makes the body work. Vitalism is a
rial good and evil forces being transferred form of reasoning that shares many similari-
between people. For instance, Bastian et al. ties with psychological essentialism in that it
(2015) found that moral vitalists tend to be functions to provide causal explanations for
concerned about having direct or indirect observable phenomena and is evident in con-
contact with immoral others, due to the pos- texts in which more scientific or mechanistic
sibility of contagion or contamination. This understandings are lacking.
effect also extended beyond the physical do- By introducing the notion of lay theories of
main. Moral vitalists were also concerned underlying spiritual forces into the domain
over their own mental purity and felt sus- of moral cognition, moral vitalism brings
ceptible to the forces of evil when entertain- a novel perspective to how we think about
ing immoral thoughts. To this extent, moral current debates within the field of moral
vitalists view immoral essences—the forces psychology. For instance, it suggests that at
of evil—as having the capacity to “infect” least some of our moral reasoning is born
and corrupt people’s minds and bodies. This from our desire to make sense of the world.
need not happen through physical contact That is, morality can arise as a function of
but may also occur through mental con- our need to predict and understand our envi-
tent alone. As such, moral vitalists entertain ronment. This diverges from some accounts
a naïve model of spirit possession and are that view morality as arising from the need
concerned about the possibility of being pos- to protect persons, groups, or norms (such as
sessed by the forces of evil: Having immoral moral foundations theory; Haidt & Joseph,
thoughts is dangerous because it invites the 2004). However, it shares some similarities
influence of evil in one’s life. with other accounts that emphasize the role
The concept of moral vitalism aims to of sense making in the context of harm (such
uncover an important dimension of moral as the notion of dyadic completion; Gray,
understanding that manifests itself within Young, & Waytz, 2012). Yet it goes beyond
everyday moral cognition. It aims to take ac- such accounts by suggesting that, in efforts
count of the role of spiritual belief within the to understand their worlds, people often rely
moral domain by focusing on core underly- on beliefs that have explanatory power. Be-
ing assumptions rather than specific tenets yond completing a moral dyad of victim and
of religious or political belief. As such it al- perpetrator, moral vitalism serves to explain
lows a deeper understanding of how these why there are victims and perpetrators in
assumptions may shape moral reasoning and the first place. To this extent, it provides a
an analysis of these beliefs across a spectrum filler explanation, or a placeholder concept,
of religious, nonreligious, and politically di- for why morally relevant events occur.
verse populations. As a formal theory, moral vitalism re-
flects a basic form of cognition (belief) that
is likely universal and probably arose as an
Historical Context explanation for life-threatening events, such
as disease, in contexts in which other (i.e.,
Vitalistic thinking refers to the tendency to more scientific) explanations were not avail-
attribute force, power, or causality to some able. As such, it is likely to be evident across
nonmaterial “spirit” or “soul-stuff” in order a range of cultures, and yet it is also likely to
 Moral Vitalism 305

be reinforced within particular cultural con- derlying reality of the moral world. A belief
texts. For instance, in capricious contexts, in moral vitalism is not measured by how
moral vitalism may be heightened, as it pro- people make moral judgments, but it may
vides a convenient answer to otherwise in- provide an explanation for why they make
coherent and unpredictable events. As such, such judgements. Moral vitalism is perhaps
it is likely that moral vitalism may become most closely aligned with the purity dimen-
more pronounced in contexts in which inter- sion of MFT, given a similar emphasis on
group conflict is common or may be relied concerns regarding purity and contagion.
on to understand especially heinous crimes. In fact, we might expect similar origins of
When people feel they lack a clear explana- both purity concerns and moral vitalism—
tion for how or why harmful events arise, specifically, biological disease (Haidt & Jo-
moral vitalism may become a default strat- seph, 2004; van Leeuwen, Park, Koenig, &
egy that allows making sense of the world. Graham, 2012). From a moral vitalism per-
Moral vitalism may be reinforced within spective, one would predict that these beliefs
contexts in which such beliefs have been de- may have formed to explain the capricious
veloped into more elaborate forms of spiri- effects of disease on human health—deaths
tual tradition, such as in contexts where were understood to be the direct result of the
religious belief is especially prominent. In forces of evil. Indeed, this kind of thinking
these contexts, people have developed more is not uncommon in the current age, with
complex and anthropomorphized under- some blaming God, or a failure to be pro-
standings of good and evil (such as gods and tected by God, for their ill health (see Gray
devils), therefore a reliance on these forces & Wegner, 2010). As such, moral vitalism
of good and evil for understanding morally may help to explain how concerns over dis-
relevant events will be especially common. ease were transformed into moral concerns
The construct of moral vitalism sits to the over purity.
side of a clear-cut debate over intuition ver- Comparing moral vitalism to theories fo-
sus cognition. The reason is that, as a theo- cusing on the attribution of moral character
ry, it is not defined by moral judgment but (e.g., Goodwin, 2015) also highlights some
rather by a belief in the underlying nature important differences and similarities. For
of the moral world. To this extent, it throws instance, moral vitalists see moral action as
a new light on many current approaches to in part determined by forces that are inde-
understanding morality, suggesting that mo- pendent of people. To the extent that moral
rality may be as much characterized by a set vitalists also endorse a naïve model of spirit
of beliefs about the nature of the world as it possession (see Bastian et al., 2015), they are
is by the basis on which people make moral also likely to endorse a naïve model of exor-
judgments. From the perspective of moral vi- cism: People can be not only be lured by evil,
talism, moral judgment is simply the output but they can also be reformed from evil. It
of a more basic set of beliefs about the un- is likely that for the moral vitalist evil ac-
derlying nature of what it means to be right tions are understood to be less the result of
or wrong. intentional action on behalf of the individu-
al than a result of evil forces residing in the
world and within people. As such, the moral
Theoretical Stance vitalist is likely to afford moral character a
less salient explanatory role. Supportive of
Moral vitalism captures a lay theory or naïve this, moral vitalism appears to be relatively
thinking and its influence on the moral do- distinct from a similar construct focusing
main. As such, it shares some similarities on pure good and evil recently published by
with theories that emphasize intuitionist Webster and Saucier (2013) that focuses on
thinking—such as moral foundations theo- purely good or evil people, as opposed to
ry (MFT; Graham, Haidt, & Nosek, 2009; purely good or evil forces (see Bastian et al.,
Haidt & Joseph, 2004). Still, there are im- 2015).
portant differences. Whereas MFT focuses Also interesting to consider is the link
on intuitions within the domain of moral between moral vitalism and previous work
judgment—such as “is it wrong?”—moral on moral cleansing. The literature on moral
vitalism focuses on a belief regarding the un- cleansing suggests that the link between
306 M O R A L I T Y A N D B E L I E F S

physical and moral disgust is embodied, deed, given that it plays a central role in how
and thus people may be motivated to physi- people understand their worlds, even having
cally cleanse when they are reminded of this belief challenged may represent a sig-
their own immoral behavior (see Zhong & nificant existential threat. People are likely
Liljenquist, 2006). Other work suggests that to endorse this lay theory or not and are un-
after an immoral act people may engage in likely to change their beliefs regarding moral
moral behavior in order to regain their sense vitalism based on their exposure to a spe-
of moral worth (Sachdeva, Iliev, & Medin, cific immoral deed. Although it is possible
2009). From a moral vitalism perspective, that moral vitalism may be heightened (or
immoral behavior may be viewed as plac- become more chronically accessible) in con-
ing one at risk of being influenced or pos- texts characterized by high levels of threat, it
sessed by the forces of evil, and compensa- is relied on to make sense of apparent harm
tory actions may be understood as attempts in general, rather than triggered by specific
to guard against this possibility. Moral vi- instances of harm doing.
talists may be especially likely to engage in
these compensatory forms of action. It is
also likely, however, that for moral vital- Evidence
ists, compensatory action may be as much
symbolic as concrete: It is not only about Bastian et al. (2015) provide initial evi-
compensating for actual harm done but dence for the construct of moral vitalism in
also about protecting oneself from the influ- terms of its measurement and also its pre-
ence of evil. Symbolic actions may thus be dictive validity. After establishing a reliable
more heavily weighted by moral vitalists in and valid measure of moral vitalism beliefs,
achieving compensation. Bastian and colleagues examined whether
It is also interesting to consider the con- moral vitalists indeed do view the world as
nection between moral vitalism and dual- containing moral forces that can possess and
process theories of moral judgment (e.g., influence people. Specifically, they provided
Greene, Sommerville, Nystrom, Darley, & participants with two vignettes. The first
Cohen, 2001). Given their reliance on no- was about John, a decent man, but who, for
tions of pure good and evil, moral vitalists a $10 bet, signed a piece of paper saying he
are likely to see moral judgments as rela- would sell his soul to the devil and then post-
tively clear-cut and, as such, are more likely ed it on the Internet. The second was about
to be deontological in their moral reasoning. Kristen, an adventurous young woman who
Moreover, they may be especially likely to participated in a séance. In both cases, moral
see any immoral act, whether justified on vitalists viewed these actions as dangerous
utilitarian grounds (such as in the case of and as increasing the likelihood of the indi-
the Heinz dilemma) or not, as putting the vidual in question being possessed by evil,
individual at risk of evil. and they believed that the individual’s char-
Finally, moral vitalism shares some simi- acter would change for the worse. From this
larities with an understanding of morality as perspective, by engaging in spiritually risky
arising from the process of dyadic comple- behavior, they ran the risk of being influ-
tion (Gray et al., 2012). Dyadic completion enced by evil and therefore were viewed as
suggests that, in view of a victim, people will more likely to have lustful thoughts, to lie, to
seek to attribute blame to someone, even to cheat, and to become aggressive. This study
God. Just so, moral vitalism suggests that a shows that not only do moral vitalists worry
belief in the forces of good and evil is often about the potential influence of evil, but
relied on in contexts where the causes of they also believe that evil can have tangible
good and bad actions or outcomes are un- effects on a person’s behavior and that these
certain or unclear. Yet, although moral vital- effects may even extend beyond the imme-
ism does indicate a form of dyadic thinking diate context, more broadly shaping the
(good vs. evil), the belief in such forces does person for the worse. Critically, these asso-
not rely on the existence of a specific immor- ciations emerged independent of religiosity,
al act. A belief in moral vitalism is likely to suggesting that moral vitalism is capturing
be relatively stable across most contexts. In- a specific construct within moral cognition
 Moral Vitalism 307

that, although associated with religiosity, is predicted the extent to which people thought
not defined by it. that evil had been playing a role in produc-
In a follow-up study, Bastian and col- ing their immoral thoughts. Participants
leagues (2015) demonstrated that moral were then told that they would next read
vitalists were especially concerned about a short informational piece and that they
moral contagion and would be less likely to could choose between two different essays.
consume food that had been touched by im- One essay was titled “Strategies to control
moral people. They were told that a choco- your thoughts: Five ways to keep unwanted
late biscuit or an apple was either clean, had thoughts at bay,” and the other essay was
been lying on the floor of the supermarket, titled “Letting your thoughts rule: How to
had been recovered from a thief who had maintain an open and flexible mind.” Moral
stolen the items, or had been taken from the vitalists were more likely to choose the essay
shopping basket of a known child molester on thought control, indicating that they felt
before apprehension by police. Moral vital- threatened by their immoral thoughts and
ists rated how disgusting it would be to eat felt the need to find ways of controlling
each item. There was an overall association those thoughts.
between moral vitalism and increased dis- To date, the evidence suggests that moral
gust; however, this was especially clear in vitalism captures a lay theory that uniquely
the case of the items that had been in con- shapes how people reason within the moral
tact with immoral others. Controlling for in- domain. Our theory suggests that these be-
dividual differences in disgust sensitivity, as liefs should be related to other work on pu-
well as self-rated disgust associated with eat- rity, such as that focused on MFT. A link
ing the food when it had been on the floor, between moral vitalism and the purity do-
moral vitalism remained a unique predictor main of the moral foundations question-
of disgust associated with eating food items naire would indeed support the proposed
that had been in contact with immoral oth- role of moral vitalism in motivating con-
ers (thief or child molester). cerns over contamination and contagion.
These findings support the link between Just so, showing that moral vitalists are es-
moral vitalism and concerns over moral pecially likely to engage in physical cleans-
contagion through secondary contact. If ing-–type behavior in response to immoral
there are forces of evil in the world, then actions would further highlight this link.
it is possible that this evil could be passed Furthermore, demonstrating that moral
through direct or indirect physical contact. vitalists might be more likely to engage in
The theory of moral vitalism suggests, how- compensatory actions, such as performing
ever, that the forces of evil may not only be moral deeds in response to reminders of im-
transferred between people but may also be moral action, would provide support to the
capable of infecting and corrupting people’s notion that moral vitalists are concerned
minds. Just as signing a piece of paper that about maintaining their moral integrity,
says you will sell your soul to the devil is which, in turn, serves to guard against the
believed to lead to possession by the forces possibility of moral corruption. Finding that
of evil, entertaining immoral thoughts may moral vitalism was especially predictive of
also leave this door open to such influences. symbolic responses rather than more con-
Bastian and colleagues tested this possibil- crete responses (in cases of both cleansing
ity by asking people to think about a “sin and compensatory action) would highlight
of the flesh” (“something bodily that you the specific contribution of these beliefs and
enjoyed doing in the moment but felt guilty the associated motivation to protect oneself
about doing or feels ‘dirty’ to think about”). from metaphysical forces of evil.
They were then asked to complete a task in
which they were instructed to let their minds
wander for a short period of time, noting Extension and Expansion
how many times their thoughts returned to
the sin. Next, they were asked to indicate Our work on moral vitalism is only just be-
whether they felt that the forces of evil had ginning. A key question in this work is how
influenced their thoughts. Moral vitalism these beliefs may play into the ways in which
308 M O R A L I T Y A N D B E L I E F S

people understand ideological differences. predictor of group-based action, it may be


We suggest that moral vitalists are likely a strong predictor of a willingness to make
to struggle with exposure to ideologically sacrifices to protect sacred values (e.g., Gin-
diverse environments. The reason is that a ges, Atran, Medin, & Shikaki, 2007).
person’s ideological system reflects basic te- By developing a focus on specific spiritual
nets about what is right or wrong and how beliefs, moral vitalism opens the door to
one should live one’s life. For the moral vi- new insights and novel approaches to under-
talist, living the right way means that he or standing how people structure their moral
she is in touch with the forces of good in the worlds. To this extent, moral vitalism serves
world, and living the wrong way means that to build a bridge between work on religious
he or she is susceptible to the forces of evil. belief and work on moral cognition, pro-
In the case in which disagreements exist over viding a template for theory building that
what is right or wrong, the moral vitalist is integrates with but also challenges current
likely to view those whose worldviews differ models and themes within the field of moral
in fundamental ways as harbingers of evil. psychology.
Just so, they are likely to imbue their own
ideological commitments with the forces
of good. From this starting point, conflicts REFERENCES
over “how to live” become disputes about
Atran, S., Medin, D., Ross, N., Lynch, E., Vap-
the “good in us” versus the “evil in them,” narksy, V., Ek’, E., . . . Baran, M. (2002).
ensuring that both ideological commitments Folkecology, cultural epidemiology, and the
and ideological conflicts are heavily weight- spirit of the commons: A garden experiment in
ed in the moral vitalists’ understanding of the Maya lowlands, 1991–2001. Current An-
the world they live in. thropology, 43, 421–450.
In some ways, our approach to linking a Bastian, B., Bain, P., Buhrmester, M. D., Gómez,
belief in moral vitalism to an understand- Á., Vázquez, A., Knight, C. G., & Swann, W.
ing of ideologically based group differences B. J. (2015). Moral vitalism: Seeing good and
shares similarities with work on psychologi- evil as real, agentic forces. Personality and So-
cial Psychology Bulletin, 41(8), 1069–1081.
cal essentialism (Bastian & Haslam, 2006;
Bastian, B., & Haslam, N. (2006). Psychologi-
Haslam, Rothschild, & Ernst, 2000; Pren- cal essentialism and stereotype endorsement.
tice & Miller, 2006). Just as biological es- Journal of Experimental Social Psychology,
sentialists come to view social categories as 42, 228–235.
indicative of an underlying causal biological Bechtel, W., & Richardson, R. C. (1998). Vital-
essence, moral vitalists come to view ideo- ism. In E. Craig (Ed.), Routledge encyclopedia
logical categories as indicative of an under- of philosophy (pp. 639–643). London: Rout-
lying causal moral essence. This suggests a ledge
number of parallels between moral vital- Frazer, J. G. (1959). The golden bough: A study
ism and psychological essentialism in un- in magic and religion (T. H. Gaster, Ed.). New
York: Macmillan. (Original work published
derstanding the influence of lay theories on
1890).
social categorization and intergroup dynam- Ginges, J., Atran, S., Medin, D., & Shikaki, K.
ics. For instance, just as essentialists seek (2007). Sacred bounds on rational resolution
to maintain their own groups’ biological of violent political conflict. Proceedings of the
purity (Wagner et al., 2010), moral vitalists National Academy of Sciences of the USA,
are likely to seek to maintain their groups’ 104(18), 7357–7360.
moral purity. Goodwin, G. P. (2015). Moral character in per-
Of interest, also, is the link between son perception. Current Directions in Psycho-
moral vitalism and group commitment. logical Science, 24(1), 38–44.
Compared with constructs such as identity Graham, J., Haidt, J., & Nosek, B. (2009). Liber-
als and conservatives rely on different sets of
fusion (Swann, Jetten, Gómez, Whitehouse, moral foundations. Journal of Personality and
& Bastian, 2012), which predict a willing- Social Psychology, 96, 1029–1046.
ness to fight and die for the group, it is likely Gray, K., & Wegner, D. M. (2010). Blaming God
that moral vitalists are more likely to remain for our pain: Human suffering and the divine
committed to their values or beliefs. Al- mind. Personality and Social Psychology Re-
though moral vitalism may not be a strong view, 14, 7–16.
 Moral Vitalism 309

Gray, K., Young, L., & Waytz, A. (2012). Mind Sinning saints and saintly sinners: The para-
perception is the essence of morality. Psycho- dox of moral self-regulation. Psychological
logical Inquiry, 23(2), 101–124. Science, 20, 523–528.
Greene, J. D., Sommerville, R. B., Nystrom, L. Shariff, A. F., & Norenzayan, A. (2007). God is
E., Darley, J. M., & Cohen, J. D. (2001). An watching you: Priming God concepts increases
fMRI investigation of emotional engagement prosocial behavior in an anonymous economic
in moral judgment. Science, 293, 2105–2108. game. Psychological Science, 18, 803–809.
Haidt, J., & Joseph, C. (2004). Intuitive ethics: Swann, W. B., Jr,, Jetten, J., Gómez, A., White-
How innately prepared intuitions generate house, H., & Bastian, B. (2012). When group
culturally variable virtues. Daedalus, 133(4), membership gets personal: A theory of iden-
55–66. tity fusion. Psychological Review, 119, 441–
Haslam, N., Rothschild, L., & Ernst, D. (2000). 456.
Essentialist beliefs about social categories. van Leeuwen, F., Park, J. H., Koenig, B. L., &
British Journal of Social Psychology, 39, 113– Graham, J. (2012). Regional variation in
127. pathogen prevalence predicts endorsement of
Inagaki, K., & Hatano, G. (2004). Vitalistic cau- group-focused moral concerns. Evolution and
sality in young children’s naive biology. Trends Human Behavior, 33, 429–437.
in Cognitive Science, 8, 356–362. Wagner, W., Kronberger, N., Nagata, M., Sen,
Jung, C. G. (1983). Excerpts from On the psy- R., Holtz, P., & Palacios, F. F. (2010). Essen-
chology of the unconscious: Two essays. In tialist theory of “hybrids”: From animal kinds
A. Storr (Ed.), The essential Jung (pp. 68–71). to ethnic categories and race. Asian Journal of
Princeton: Princeton University Press. (Origi- Social Psychology, 13, 232–246.
nal work published 1917) Webster, R. J., & Saucier, D. A. (2013). Angels
Morris, S. C., Taplin, J. E., & Gelman, S. A. and demons are among us: Assessing individu-
(2000). Vitalism in naive biological thinking. al differences in belief in pure evil and belief in
Developmental Psychology, 36, 582–595. pure good. Personality and Social Psychology
Prentice, D. A., & Miller, D. T. (2006). Essen- Bulletin, 39, 1455–1470.
tializing differences between women and men. Zhong, C. B., & Liljenquist, K. (2006). Wash-
Psychological Science, 17, 129–135. ing away your sins: Threatened morality and
Sachdeva, S., Iliev, R., & Medin, D. L. (2009). physical cleansing. Science, 313, 1451–1452.
CHAPTER 32

The Objectivity of Moral Beliefs

Geoffrey P. Goodwin

To what extent do ordinary individuals regard moral beliefs as


capturing objective truths about morality, and how do their views
about this predict other attitudes and behaviors?

Ordinary people typically regard moral beliefs about the wrongness


of harmful or unjust acts as objectively true and the extent to which
they do so predicts both moral intolerance and moral commitment.

Do ordinary individuals regard their moral one party thinks the act is wrong, whereas
beliefs as representing objective facts about the other thinks it is permissible. The key
the world? Or do they instead regard their question is whether subjects think that one
moral beliefs as expressing mere personal party must be mistaken, as with ordinary
preferences or tastes? Questions about the factual disagreements, or whether they in-
objectivity of moral beliefs have perplexed stead allow that neither party need be mis-
philosophers for centuries. Recently, or- taken, as if the conflict were one of brute
dinary individuals’ “meta-ethical” beliefs preference or taste. The conclusion that at
about these issues have been investigated. least one party must be mistaken implies
This research informs philosophical analysis that people see the issue in question as ob-
and provides psychological insight into the jective. The data that emerge from existing
nature of everyday moral cognition. It also studies using this method are robust, but
reveals novel ways in which meta-ethical their interpretation is not yet settled. My
beliefs may influence moral tolerance and aim in this chapter is to survey and interpret
commitment. the literature as it currently stands and to
A basic method used to assess the per- point to new research opportunities.
ceived objectivity of people’s moral beliefs
is to probe their understanding of divergent
moral opinions (see e.g., Goodwin & Dar- Terminology
ley, 2008; Nichols, 2004; Wainryb, Shaw,
Langley, Cottam, & Lewis, 2004). For in- During the 20th century, a variety of moral
stance, subjects might be presented a situa- skepticisms came to populate the philo-
tion in which two parties diverge on whether sophical literature. A common feature of
a particular act of theft is morally wrong— these skeptical views is their denial of the

310
 The Objectivity of Moral Beliefs 311

claim that ordinary moral beliefs represent may not be morally true for another person
objectively true facts about the world.1 But or group, and so the claim that moral beliefs
the way these skeptical views come to this capture something objectively true about the
conclusion varies widely. One sort of skepti- world is denied. A useful analogy for moral
cal view, variously labeled as expressivism, relativism is that the claim “January is a
emotivism, or more broadly, noncognitiv- winter month” may simultaneously be true
ism, denies that moral beliefs are candidates in one hemisphere of the world but false in
for truth in the first place (they are not “truth another (see Sarkissian, Park, Tien, Wright,
apt”; see Sinnott-Armstrong, 2006). Ac- & Knobe, 2011)—according to moral rela-
cording to this sort of view, moral beliefs are tivism, this dependence on context holds for
mere expressions of emotion or attitude and the truth of moral beliefs as well.
so do not purport to represent any assertion In contrast to each of these skeptical
that could be either true or false (e.g., Ayer, views, moral objectivism posits that some
1936; Stevenson, 1944). On these views, an moral assertions represent objective truths
assertion that “stealing is wrong” is simply independent of any particular system of ap-
an expression of disapproval, which can nei- praisal. This idea has been philosophically
ther be true nor false (in the same way that controversial. Yet, many philosophers, even
an expression of applause, or booing, at the those who deny moral objectivism, have
end of a musical concert, can be neither true assumed that moral objectivism is the best
nor false). A closely related view—prescrip- approximation of ordinary individuals’ me-
tivism—is that moral beliefs are essentially ta-ethical views and have built this assump-
normative commands or prescriptions— tion into their theorizing (e.g., Smith, 1994;
which also cannot be true or false (Hare, Mackie, 1977). This widespread assumption
1952, 1981). is often thought to have the consequence
In contrast, moral nihilists take a differ- of shifting the burden of proof onto moral
ent skeptical tack. They do not deny that skeptics, who must not only argue positively
moral claims could, in principle, be true or for their own skeptical views, but must also
false. But they deny that any moral claims account for, and explain away, the objectiv-
are, in fact, true because no moral proper- ist views of ordinary folk (see e.g., Sayre-
ties exist. A famous articulation of this view McCord, 1986).
is found in Mackie’s (1977) “error theory,” However, whereas traditional analytical
which claimed that, although moral beliefs philosophers have been content to rely on
could in principle be true, they are in fact their own assumptions about ordinary indi-
all false. Related views claim that moral viduals’ moral cognition, modern empirical-
beliefs could, in principle, be true or false, ly minded philosophers have confronted the
but none in fact have the property of being psychological reality directly. In this way,
true or false (Joyce, 2001). Thus, whereas their investigations intersect with those of
noncognitivism denies moral truth aptness, moral psychologists, whose interest in moral
nihilism, which is cognitivist, simply denies objectivity is grounded not in the desire to
moral truth (and sometimes falsehood; see inform philosophical debate, per se, but in
Sinnott-Armstrong, 2006, 2011). the desire to understand ordinary moral
A final sort of moral skepticism denies cognition.
neither moral truth aptness nor moral truth,
but argues that moral truth is fundamentally
relative to a particular local system of ap- Relation to Other Psychological Research
praisal. Moral subjectivism is the idea that
moral truth must be assessed relative to an Psychological research on moral objectiv-
individual appraiser. Moral relativism is the ity is connected with (though distinct from)
idea that moral truth must be assessed rela- research on several other aspects of moral
tive to a particular culture, society, or group cognition, including “moral mandates”
(e.g., Harman, 1975; for clear descriptions (Skitka, Bauman, & Sargis, 2005), “pro-
of moral relativism, see Gowans, 2015; tected” or “sacred” values (Baron & Spran-
Shafer-Landau, 2003, 2004). In either case, ca, 1997; Tetlock, 2003; Tetlock, Kristel,
what is morally true for one person or group Elson, Green, & Lerner, 2000), and “naïve
312 M O R A L I T Y A N D B E L I E F S

realism,” (Ross & Ward, 1996). Most perti- ed, rather than a belief in an objective moral
nently, it connects closely with Elliot Turiel’s fact. A moral subjectivist might make a simi-
developmental work investigating children’s lar response. Only moral relativists would be
tendency to treat their moral beliefs as hav- moved to change their response in the face of
ing warrant independent of immediate au- an altered normative regime. As such, Tu-
thority or cultural norms (Turiel, 1978, riel’s procedure does not clearly distinguish
1983; Turiel, Hildenbrandt, & Wainryb, objectivists from nonobjectivists (nor was it
1991). It is worth scrutinizing the relation intended to); it assesses the perceived scope
between these research streams so as to best or generalizability of meta-ethical beliefs
appreciate how they complement rather than but not their perceived objectivity (see also
overlap with one another. Goodwin & Darley, 2010).
Turiel and colleagues’ research investi-
gated whether moral actions that children
regard as wrong, such as one child hitting Theories and Findings Regarding
another, are still judged wrong when a rel- Lay Meta‑Ethics
evant authority figure, or an alternative cul-
ture, deems them acceptable (or “okay”). In contrast, current methods of measuring
Children typically judged that such actions meta-ethical beliefs—which call for subjects
were still wrong even under such modified to indicate whether a moral disagreement
conditions, essentially stipulating that their implies that at least one of the disagree-
wrongness was independent of local author- ing parties must be mistaken—distinguish
ity and culture. In contrast, research on objectivists from nonobjectivists (though
moral objectivity presents subjects (usually these methods are not sensitive enough to
adults) with a moral disagreement and asks distinguish between the rich variety of non-
whether such disagreement implies that at objectivist positions outlined earlier). They
least one of the two parties must be mistak- differ from prior methods, which measured
en—thereby implying that the issue at stake meta-ethical views at the dispositional level
is an objective one (Goodwin & Darley, and which failed to distinguish meta-ethical
2008, 2012; Sarkissian et al., 2011). Vari- from first-order views (e.g., Forsyth, 1980,
ants on this procedure have asked subjects 1981; Forsyth & Berger, 1982; see Goodwin
whether they think there can be a correct & Darley, 2010, for a critique).
answer regarding the disagreement (Good- One theory of lay meta-ethics is that
win & Darley, 2008, 2012). people are moral objectivists about a ca-
Turiel’s procedure reveals important as- nonical set of moral beliefs pertaining to the
pects of children’s moral thought, but it does wrongness of harmful or unjust acts. Early
not speak directly to questions about moral evidence for this view emerged from a pio-
objectivity. It calls only for what philoso- neering study by Nichols (2004), in which
phers refer to as a “first order” judgment of subjects indicated which of two parties was
moral wrongness, whereas the procedures correct in the wake of a disagreement over
used in research on moral objectivity call a moral transgression. Respondents also
for a “second order” judgment of the moral had the option of indicating that there is
truth, falsehood, correctness, or mistaken- simply no fact of the matter as to who was
ness of a first-order moral judgment. In say- correct. Results varied from one experi-
ing that a particular action is “still wrong,” ment to the next, depending on the nature
independent of any backing by a relevant of the transgression. But, in the most well-
authority or cultural norm, children are not powered study, almost three-quarters of the
necessarily indicating a belief in an objec- subjects responded as moral objectivists in
tive moral truth. To see this, consider what response to a disagreement over the wrong-
a noncognitivist (e.g., an emotivist) might ness of hitting another person (Study 3).
say in response to Turiel’s probe—under a Using a slightly different method, Wainryb
changed normative regime, they may also in- et al. (2004) found evidence that children of
dicate that the behavior in question is “still ages 5, 7, and 9 tended to approach moral
wrong,” intending to convey only that their disagreements in an objectivist fashion, indi-
expression of disapproval would be unabat- cating that there was only one right answer
 The Objectivity of Moral Beliefs 313

to a moral disagreement (see also Nichols & almost as objectivist as their responses re-
Folds-Bennett, 2003). garding basic matters of empirical fact (e.g.,
Goodwin and Darley (2008) expanded whether Boston is north of Los Angeles).
upon this research by surveying a wider These differences were observed while sta-
range of moral beliefs and by using a slightly tistically controlling for differences across
different procedure. Subjects were presented the categories in terms of how strongly (or
with an ostensible disagreement over a moral extremely) the first-order beliefs were held.
issue, in which another person in the experi- However, as Nichols (2004) had also sug-
ment had allegedly come to a different con- gested, Goodwin and Darley (2008) ob-
clusion than they themselves had regarding served considerable variation in the objec-
a canonical moral issue (e.g., that robbery tivity subjects attributed to different moral
or murder is wrong). They were asked to beliefs. This issue was explored more fully
indicate whether the other person (or them- in Goodwin and Darley (2012), who found
selves) was mistaken, or whether instead nei- that beliefs about the wrongness (or badness)
ther party need be mistaken, 2 and whether of negative acts were seen as more objective
there could be a correct answer regarding than beliefs about the rightness (or good-
the issue. Owing to their high intercorrela- ness) of positive acts, both when control-
tion, these two variables were combined into ling for, and equating for, first-order judg-
a single measure of objectivity. Two further ment extremity. Wrongness is seen as a more
methodological precautions were added. objective moral property than goodness or
Subjects were asked to indicate why they rightness. Moral beliefs about the wrong-
thought the other person could have come to ness of harmful or unjust acts were seen as
a different conclusion. These responses were especially objective, but the wrongness of
carefully scrutinized to ensure that subjects’ even some purely “symbolic,” nonharmful
assumed reason for the disagreement was acts, such as discreetly urinating on a memo-
not that the other person had made different rial, was also regarded as highly objective.
factual assumptions about the act in ques- This research, therefore, shows that ordi-
tion (e.g., regarding its underlying motiva- nary individuals appear to be “meta-ethical
tion or likely consequences). Any postulated pluralists,” attributing objectivity to some
difference of this sort might have led subjects but not all moral beliefs (see Gill, 2008,
to think that the other person had a different 2009, for philosophical endorsement of such
action in mind, implying that the disagree- a pluralist position). Wright, Grandjean, and
ment that had arisen was not genuine. In McWhite (2013) provided further support
the rare cases where subjects did make such for meta-ethical pluralism, showing that in-
interpretations, these data were eliminated. dividuals provide diverging assessments of
How strongly subjects agreed with the first- objectivity even among a set of moral beliefs
order moral beliefs was also measured, and that they themselves (and not the research-
this measure of belief extremity was con- ers) had designated as “moral.”
trolled for in the main statistical analyses. Other research on this topic has ex-
The main upshot of these analyses was plored whether individual differences in
that subjects typically indicated highly ob- personality, religiosity, or cognitive style
jectivist responses regarding canonical might account for some of the variation in
moral disagreements about harm or injustice the perceived objectivity of moral beliefs.
(e.g., in response to disagreements over the Grounding morality in a divine being ap-
wrongness of cheating, stealing, or harming pears to predict greater moral objectivity
another person). That is, subjects typically (Goodwin & Darley, 2008), whereas greater
indicated that the other party was mistak- openness to experience predicts lesser moral
en in the face of the disagreement and that objectivity (Feltz & Cokely, 2008). Age is
there was indeed a correct answer to the also an important predictor. Nichols (2004)
issue in question. Their responses to moral found that within a sample of undergraduate
disagreements were more objectivist than subjects, years in college predicted lowered
their responses to disagreements over social objectivity ratings (Study 2, although this
conventional violations (e.g., the “wrong- finding was not observed in a later study,
ness” of wearing pajamas to a lecture), and Study 3). Beebe and Sackris (2016) similar-
314 M O R A L I T Y A N D B E L I E F S

ly found that college-age subjects were less individuals from the same culture disagreed
likely than both younger and older subjects elicited objectivist responses on average, just
to respond as moral objectivists. However, as in previous research. But the two cross-
all of the existing evidence on individual cultural cases elicited less objectivist re-
differences comes from cross-sectional cor- sponses. This was especially pronounced in
relational designs, rather than longitudinal the alien (Pentar) case, for which responses
or experimental designs, and most of the were located at, or slightly below, the mid-
existing studies have not robustly controlled point of a scale assessing agreement with
for possible third-variable confounds. More the idea that one of the disagreeing parties
research is needed to determine the likely “must be wrong.”
causal pathways more conclusively. Two features of Sarkissian and colleagues’
(2011) data appear to provide evidence of
moral relativism. First, in the cases of cross-
Challenge to the Standard View cultural disagreement, there is the low abso-
lute level of agreement with the item assess-
Taken as a whole, the research just described ing whether one of the disagreeing parties
appears to indicate that ordinary individu- must be mistaken—in the most exotic case
als are moral objectivists about at least a (the alien Pentars), responses trended to-
limited class of canonical moral transgres- ward the “disagree” end of the scale, thus
sions, notwithstanding their overall meta- implying a nonobjectivist position. Second,
ethical pluralism. However, this conclusion there is the relative difference between all
has recently been contested. Sarkissian and three conditions—the fact that the degree of
colleagues (2011) argued that the possibil- cultural difference between the disagreeing
ity of a deeper lay moral relativism had not parties moderated subjects’ responses indi-
been explored fully. Although people may cates that they were indeed sensitive to the
indicate that a mistake has been made if frame of reference according to which moral
two parties from within the same moral beliefs are evaluated—thus implying a rela-
culture disagree, this does not mean they tivistic stance. The methodology of these
would respond similarly if the two parties studies is extremely clever and represents an
were from different moral cultures. If sub- important challenge to the standard objec-
jects no longer provide objectivist responses tivist interpretation.
to disagreements of that sort, it would pro- Yet, as intriguing as this evidence is, the
vide evidence that they are, in fact, moral conclusions Sarkissian et al. (2011) draw
relativists deep down. To explore this idea, may be contested. Sousa, Piazza, and Good-
Sarkissian and colleagues examined how win (2017) argue that subjects’ responses
people judge disagreements between ap- may have been moderated by the degree of
praisers from radically different moral cul- cultural distance between the two disagree-
tures. The disagreements concerned canoni- ing parties, not because they were relativ-
cal moral harms, such as stabbing someone ists deep down but, rather, because they
else with a knife or killing someone. In one assumed that the respective judges were
case, an American student disagreed with interpreting the described actions in funda-
a member of the “Mamilons,” a remote mentally different ways. In Sarkissian et al.’s
Amazonian tribe. In an even more exotic (2011) studies, the actions were described in
case, an American student disagreed with a very sparse terms, leaving room for a vari-
member of the “Pentars,” an alien species ety of interpretations. In one case, there was
that has “a very different sort of psychology disagreement over the moral wrongness of
from human beings” in that “they are not the following action: “Dylan buys an expen-
at all interested in friendship or love” and sive new knife and tests its sharpness by ran-
“their main goal is simply to increase the domly stabbing a passerby on the street.” In
total number of equilateral pentagons in the another case, the action was: “Horace finds
universe” (p. 488). Sarkissian et al. (2011) his youngest child extremely unattractive
compared responses to these two cases with and therefore kills him.” At first glance,
responses to a case in which two American these action descriptions may seem relatively
observers disagreed. The case in which two straightforward. But they, in fact, contain
 The Objectivity of Moral Beliefs 315

many potential ambiguities—nothing is said Connection to Behavior


or implied about the reason or motivation
for the action (e.g., whether it was selfishly Meta-ethical beliefs have recently been ex-
or prosocially motivated—for instance, it plored in connection with two important
might have served to protect the community practical issues: moral tolerance and moral
from an unspecified threat), nor about the commitment. A priori, it is not entirely obvi-
moral status or consent of the apparent vic- ous what meta-ethical stance ought to pre-
tim (e.g., whether the victim had done any- dict greater tolerance. Some philosophers
thing to deserve harsh treatment, or whether have drawn a link between nonobjectivist
the act was against the victim’s will). This positions and an ethic of moral tolerance,
therefore leaves room for the possibility that assuming that moral relativists (for instance)
subjects attributed quite different interpreta- would be more likely to endorse toler-
tions of the actions to different observers. ance and noninterference when it comes to
Any apparent disagreement between the two other cultures’ questionable moral practices
observers would therefore dissolve—not be- (Gowans, 2015). However, other philoso-
cause the subjects are truly moral relativists phers have noted that moral objectivists may
but, rather, because they assumed the dis- in fact be more open-minded in relation to
agreeing parties were rendering judgments other people who disagree with them over
about fundamentally different actions and moral issues; rather than treating moral dis-
were therefore meeting at cross-purposes. In agreements as irresolvable clashes of brute
that case, both parties could be judged cor- preferences, objectivists believe that there is
rect without implying a relativistic stance. a true fact of the matter as to who is correct,
Indeed, Sousa et al. (2017) demonstrate that and so they should be receptive to new infor-
when these actions are described in more mation that might legitimately change their
precise ways so as to eliminate these criti- view (Snare, 1992). The existing research
cal ambiguities, subjects’ responses return to conducted on this issue has supported only
being objectivist. the first view—moral objectivists do appear
In a related vein, the fact that the alien to be less tolerant of divergent moral opin-
Pentars’ psychology is so far removed from ions than nonobjectivists. Framed more pos-
ordinary human psychology may cause sub- itively, this research shows that moral objec-
jects to wonder whether the Pentars are even tivism predicts greater moral conviction and
capable of understanding that some of the steadfastness. Goodwin and Darley (2012)
actions described may thwart the interests found that objectivism predicted greater dis-
of the victim. If the Pentars were incapable comfort with another person who disagreed
of understanding this, it would again appear with subjects’ own moral positions concern-
that their moral judgments concern a funda- ing the wrongness of various actions, even
mentally different action (i.e., one that did after controlling for subjects’ first-order
not impinge on the interests of the victim), judgments of how wrong the actions were.
thus dissolving any ostensible disagreement Similarly, Wright, McWhite, and Grandjean
they might appear to have with an Ameri- (2014) found that objectivists were more
can observer. Here, too, Sousa et al. (2017) likely to indicate attitudinal intolerance to-
showed that when the aliens are described ward a disagreeing other person (discomfort
as being capable of understanding that the with that person’s beliefs) and were also less
actions did impinge on the interests of the inclined to help that person if they were in
victim, even while other aspects of their psy- need (a quasi-behavioral measure). As in
chology are very remote, objectivist rather other areas of this literature, the evidence
than relativist responding is the norm. This for the link between objectivism and intoler-
debate is not yet resolved, but at this stage, ance is correlational only and does not yet
it appears that there are still good reasons to establish a causal claim.
favor the view that lay individuals typically Moral objectivity may also predict greater
hold an objectivist position about canonical commitment to acting morally. This pos-
moral transgressions, notwithstanding con- sibility has been explored in two comple-
siderable variability across issues and across mentary ways. Young and Durwin (2013)
individuals. postulated that greater moral objectivity
316 M O R A L I T Y A N D B E L I E F S

leads to greater prosociality. In two experi- moral relativism or control subjects. Across
ments, they stopped passersby in the street, the two experiments, the relative influence of
priming some of them with moral objectiv- the experimental conditions varied with re-
ism (or, in their terminology, “moral real- spect to the control condition—only relativ-
ism”) by asking: “Do you agree that some ism deviated from control in Study 1, where-
things are just morally right or wrong, good as only objectivism deviated from control in
or bad, wherever you happen to be from in Study 2. Rai and Holyoak (2013) speculate
the world?” and others with nonobjectivism that the difference rests in subjects’ differ-
(“antirealism”) by asking: “Do you agree ent initial predispositions toward the acts in
that our morals and values are shaped by question. In Study 1, subjects were initially
our culture and upbringing, so that there predisposed not to cheat, and so exposure
are no absolute right answers to any moral to moral relativism weakened this tendency
questions?” When primed with objectivism, (exposure to objectivism did not alter the
subjects were more likely to donate money to existing tendency). In contrast, in Study 2,
a charity of their choice (Study 1) and more subjects were initially predisposed to engage
inclined to donate higher amounts (Study in the infraction, which exposure to moral
2)3, compared with subjects in the antireal- objectivism blocked, but which exposure to
ism and control conditions. It therefore ap- relativism did not affect. It therefore seems
pears that greater objectivism may lead to from this research that moral objectivism
more prosocial behaviors. protects against dishonesty.
Rai and Holyoak (2013) explored a re- Overall, this research makes a valuable
lated idea, namely that greater objectivism contribution by exploring ways that meta-
inclines people not to cheat in a context in ethical beliefs may contribute to real moral
which doing so would be personally advan- behaviors and attitudes. It suggests that
tageous and undetectable. Subjects were ran- moral objectivism may lead to greater moral
domly assigned to one of three conditions. commitment, prosociality, and conviction—
In the objectivism (or, in the researchers’ characteristics that may be valuable in many
terms, “absolutism”) condition, they read circumstances, though not unerringly. No-
a moral argument denouncing the practice tably, researchers have also speculated
of female genital mutilation, which called that moral objectivism may fuel repugnant
for strong intervention to end it, and which antisocial moral commitments, including
was laced with reference to objective moral those that underlie terrorist acts (Ginges &
truths. In the relativism condition, subjects Atran, 2009, 2011; Ginges, Atran, Medin,
read a moral argument advocating tolerance & Shikaki, 2007).
of female genital mutilation based on the in-
escapable relativity of moral truths. Subjects
in the control condition read a neutral pas- Ways to Advance Behavioral Research
sage. Subsequently, all subjects self-reported
the outcome of a dice roll that determined However, two important limitations exist
their monetary payment for the experiment, with the present experimental investigations
and were afforded an opportunity to misre- of the causal influence of moral objectiv-
port their score with impunity. The results ism on behavior. In none of the Young and
showed that only subjects in the moral rela- Durwin (2011) or Rai and Holyoak (2013)
tivism condition were more likely to report studies were manipulation checks included,
higher scores than would be expected by and so there is no direct evidence that the
chance. Their scores were also significantly experimental manipulations actually moved
higher than the scores reported by subjects subjects’ meta-ethical beliefs. Moreover, in
in the other two conditions (which did not both studies, there are significant concerns
differ from one another). A subsequent ex- about experimenter demand. In Young and
periment showed that subjects primed with Durwin’s (2013) study, the procedure is
moral objectivism were less likely to indicate highly suggestive. subjects are asked a very
willingness to perform a minor moral infrac- pointed question about the fundamental na-
tion (purchasing an item for an incorrectly ture of morality, which indicates how the
low listed price) than subjects primed with requestor is likely to respond to a refusal to
 The Objectivity of Moral Beliefs 317

donate money; in the objectivism case (“Do moral commitment, conviction, and intoler-
you agree that some things are just morally ance. This area of research illustrates how a
right or wrong, good or bad, wherever you fundamental philosophical issue—far from
happen to be from in the world?”), the re- being removed from everyday life—in fact
questor could be presumed to respond in a plays out in concrete ways in the moral cog-
more negative and intolerant manner to a nition and behavior of ordinary individuals.
refusal to donate. This factor, rather than
any change in subjects’ meta-ethical beliefs,
may account for the results. A similar con- ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
cern applies to Rai and Holyoak’s (2013)
I thank Dena Gromet and Jesse Graham for valu-
studies. By conveying a meta-ethical stance able comments on an earlier draft of this chapter.
to subjects, the experimenters may have un-
wittingly conveyed information about how
they would likely react (publicly or privately) NOTES
if the participant were to cheat (Study 1) or
to indicate antisocial intentions (Study 2)— 1. In accordance with the focus in the existing
namely, less permissively in the objectivism empirical literature, here I am focusing only
condition and more permissively in the rela- on “metaphysical” moral skepticism, which
denies that any moral beliefs can be true.
tivism condition. Once again, it is not clear “Epistemological” moral skepticism is dis-
that a change in subjects’ meta-ethical be- tinct, in that it denies or questions whether
liefs is actually what caused their change in any moral beliefs can be justified or known
behavior, as opposed to a change in their (see Sinnott-Armstrong, 2006). The two can
beliefs about the experimenter’s wishes.4 Fu- come apart because one might deny moral
ture investigations would be well served to knowledge without denying moral truth
address this issue rigorously. One strategy (though the reverse is not plausible; for fur-
may be to present priming information in ther discussion, see Sinnott-Armstrong, 2006,
such a way that it is clear that the research- 2011).
ers are not endorsing the meta-ethical posi- 2. Goodwin and Darley (2008, 2012) framed
the disagreements as being between the par-
tion in question. It would also be important ticipant him- or herself and another person,
to measure whether priming information though other research has asked subjects
actually changes meta-ethical beliefs, which to comment on disagreements they are not
is not yet known from the existing studies. personally involved in (e.g., Nichols, 2004;
Sarkissian et al., 2011). Both methods have
relative strengths and weaknesses; the first-
Conclusion person method allows an assessment of be-
liefs the experimenters know the subjects care
Questions about the perceived objectivity about, whereas the third-person method re-
of ordinary individuals’ moral beliefs have moves potential distortions that might emerge
from having one’s own, expressed moral be-
yielded several important discoveries. The liefs challenged.
present state of research indicates that peo- 3. Study 2 in this investigation did not replicate
ple typically take objectivist stances toward the finding that subjects primed with objec-
canonical moral issues concerning the inflic- tivism were more likely to donate at all, but
tion of harm or injustice, at least when con- it showed that among those who donated,
sidering moral disagreements within their individuals primed with objectivism donated
own moral culture. Some symbolic, victim- more.
less, moral transgressions are also perceived 4. This criticism does not depend on subjects
in an objectivist way. The picture is less clear being concerned solely about their behavior
when it comes to moral disagreements that being detected and brought to their atten-
tion by the experimenter. Subjects’ behavior
cut across moral cultures, but there is reason may also be influenced simply by their know-
for optimism that this controversy will reach ing how negatively the experimenter would
an empirical resolution. Exciting research react privately, or even by their knowing that
has begun to explore the behavioral impli- their behavior goes against the experimenter’s
cations of meta-ethical stances, suggesting wishes (regardless of whether the experiment-
that moral objectivism may predict greater er would ever find out about it).
318 M O R A L I T Y A N D B E L I E F S

REFERENCES jective than others? Journal of Experimental


Social Psychology, 48, 250–256.
Ayer, A. J. (1936). Language, truth, and logic. Gowans, C. (2015). Moral relativism. In E. N.
London: Gollancz. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of phi-
Baron, J., & Spranca, M. (1997). Protected val- losophy. Stanford, CA: Metaphysics Research
ues. Organizational Behavior and Human Lab, Center for the Study of Language and
Decision Processes, 70, 1–16. Information, Stanford University. Available
Beebe, A., & Sackris, D. (2016). Moral objectiv- at https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/moral-
ism across the lifespan. Philosophical Psychol- relativism.
ogy, 29, 912–929. Hare, R. M. (1952). The language of morals. Ox-
Feltz, A., & Cokely, E. T. (2008). The fragment- ford, UK: Clarendon Press.
ed folk: More evidence of stable individual Hare, R. M. (1981). Moral thinking. Oxford,
differences in moral judgments and folk in- UK: Clarendon Press.
tuitions. In B. C. Love, K. McRae, & V. M. Harman, G. (1975). Moral relativism defended.
Sloutsky (Eds.), Proceedings of the 30th an- Philosophical Review, 84, 3–22.
nual conference of the Cognitive Science So- Joyce, R. (2001). The myth of morality. Cam-
ciety (pp. 1771–1776). Austin, TX: Cognitive bridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Science Society. Mackie, J. (1977). Ethics: Inventing right and
Forsyth, D. R. (1980). A taxonomy of ethical wrong. London: Penguin.
ideologies. Journal of Personality and Social Nichols, S. (2004). After objectivity: An empiri-
Psychology, 39, 175–184. cal study of moral judgment. Philosophical
Forsyth, D. R. (1981). Moral judgment: The in- Psychology, 17, 3–26.
fluence of ethical ideology. Personality and Nichols, S., & Folds-Bennett, T. (2003). Are chil-
Social Psychology Bulletin, 7, 218–223. dren moral objectivists? Children’s judgments
Forsyth, D. R., & Berger, R. E. (1982). The ef- about moral and response-dependent proper-
fects of ethical ideology on moral behavior. ties. Cognition, 90, B23–B32.
Journal of Social Psychology, 117, 53–56. Rai, T. S., & Holyoak, K. J. (2013). Exposure to
Gill, M. B. (2008). Metaethical variability, inco- moral relativism compromises moral behavior.
herence, and error. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong Journal of Experimental Social Psychology,
(Ed.), Moral psychology: Vol. 2. The cognitive 49, 995–1001.
science of morality: Intuition and diversity Ross, L., & Ward, A. (1996). Naive realism in
(pp. 387–401). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. everyday life: Implications for social conflict
Gill, M. B. (2009). Indeterminacy and variabil- and misunderstanding. In T. Brown, E. S.
ity in meta-ethics. Philosophical Studies, 145, Reed, & E. Turiel (Eds.), Values and knowl-
215–234. edge (pp. 103–135). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Ginges, J., & Atran, S. (2009). What motivates Sarkissian, H., Park, J., Tien, D., Wright, J. C.,
participation in violent political action: Selec- & Knobe, J. (2011). Folk moral relativism.
tive incentives or parochial altruism? Annals Mind and Language, 26, 482–505.
of the New York Academy of Sciences, 1167, Sayre-McCord, G. (1986). The many moral
115–123. realisms. Southern Journal of Philosophy,
Ginges, J., & Atran, S. (2011). War as a moral 24(Suppl.), 1–22.
imperative (not just practical politics by other Shafer-Landau, R. (2003). Moral realism: A de-
means). Proceedings of the Biological Scienc- fense. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
es, 278, 2930–2938. Shafer-Landau, R. (2004). Whatever happened
Ginges, J., Atran, S., Medin, D., & Shikaki, K. to good and evil? Oxford, UK: Oxford Uni-
(2007). Sacred bounds on rational resolution versity Press.
of violent political conflict. Proceedings of the Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2006). Moral skepti-
National Academy of Sciences of the USA, cisms. New York: Oxford University Press.
104, 7357–7360. Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2011). Moral skep­
Goodwin, G. P., & Darley, J. M. (2008). The ticism. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford
psychology of meta-ethics: Exploring objectiv- ency­ clopedia of philosophy. Stanford, CA:
ism. Cognition, 106, 1339–1366. Metaphysics Research Lab, Center for the
Goodwin, G. P., & Darley, J. M. (2010). The Study of Language and Information, Stan-
perceived objectivity of ethical beliefs: Psy- ford University. Retrieved from http://plato.
chological findings and implications for public stanford.edu/archives/fall2011/entries/skepti-
policy. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, cism-moral.
1, 1–28. Skitka, L. J., Bauman, C. W., & Sargis, E. G.
Goodwin, G. P., & Darley, J. M. (2012). Why are (2005). Moral conviction: Another contribu-
some moral beliefs perceived to be more ob- tor to attitude strength or something more?
 The Objectivity of Moral Beliefs 319

Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, Turiel, E., Hildenbrandt, C., & Wainryb, C.
88, 895–917. (1991). Judging social issues: Difficulties, in-
Smith, M. (1994). The moral problem. Oxford, consistencies, and consistencies. Monographs
UK: Blackwell. of the Society for Research in Child Develop-
Snare, F. (1992). The nature of moral thinking. ment, 56, 1–103.
London: Routledge. Wainryb, C., Shaw, L. A., Langley, M., Cottam,
Sousa, P., Piazza, J., & Goodwin, G. P. (2017). K., & Lewis, R. (2004). Children’s thinking
Folk moral objectivism. Manuscript in prepa- about diversity of belief in the early school
ration. years: Judgments of relativism, tolerance, and
Stevenson, C. (1944). Ethics and language. New disagreeing persons. Child Development, 75,
Haven, CT: Yale University Press. 687–703.
Tetlock, P. E. (2003). Thinking the unthinkable: Wright, J. C., Grandjean, P., & McWhite, C.
Sacred values and taboo cognitions. Trends in (2013). The role of dispositional vs. situation-
Cognitive Sciences, 7, 320–324. al threat-sensitivity in our moral judgments.
Tetlock, P. E., Kristel, O. V., Elson, B., Green, Journal of Moral Education, 42, 383–397.
M., & Lerner, J. (2000). The psychology of Wright, J. C., McWhite, C., & Grandjean, P.
the unthinkable: Taboo trade-offs, forbidden (2014). The cognitive mechanisms of intoler-
base rates, and heretical counterfactuals. Jour- ance: Do our meta-ethical commitments mat-
nal of Personality and Social Psychology, 78, ter? In T. Lombrozo, S. Nichols, & J. Knobe
853–870. (Eds.), Oxford studies in experimental philos-
Turiel, E. (1978). Social regulations and domains ophy (Vol. 1, pp. 28–61). New York: Oxford
of social concepts. In W. Damon (Ed.), New di- University Press.
rections for child development: Vol. 1. Social Young, L., & Durwin, A. J. (2013). Moral real-
cognition (pp. 45–74). New York: Gardner. ism as moral motivation: The impact of meta-
Turiel, E. (1983). The development of social ethics on everyday decision-making. Journal
knowledge. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge Uni- of Experimental Social Psychology, 49, 302–
versity press. 306.
CH A P TER 33

Folk Theories in the Moral Domain

Sara Gottlieb
Tania Lombrozo

Is morality intuitive or deliberative?

This distinction can obscure the role of folk moral theories in moral
judgment; judgments may arise “intuitively” yet result from abstract
theoretical and philosophical commitments that participate in “delib‑
erative” reasoning.

Context to respect patient autonomy” (Snyder & Sul-


masy, p. 211), the Hippocratic Oath requires
Physician-assisted suicide was, according that physicians follow a tradition of healing
to the Gallup Poll, the most controversial and comfort and never intentionally bring
social issue in 2010: 46% of the individu- about the death of any patient. They wrote,
als surveyed indicated that it was morally “Just as society can direct that no one has
acceptable, and a matching 46% indicated the ‘right’ to sell himself or herself into slav-
that it was morally wrong (Saad, 2010). It ery, so too can society direct that no one has
remained controversial in 2012 when Mas- a ‘right’ to assistance with suicide” (p. 212).
sachusetts voted against the Death with This example illustrates one process by
Dignity Act by a narrow 1%. And in 2014, which moral judgments can be reached:
the issue regained momentum in the media through the explicit consideration and
with Brittany Maynard, the terminally ill weighing of relevant moral principles, such
29-year-old who publicly documented the as respecting patient rights or adhering to
decision to take her own life. natural law concerning time of death. But is
Individuals support or oppose physician- this how the respondents to the 2010 Gallup
assisted suicide for a variety of reasons. The Poll reached their judgments, as well? Tra-
American College of Physicians put forth ditional and more contemporary accounts
an official stance in a 2001 position paper, of moral judgment offer different responses.
stating that although “arguments support- According to more traditional accounts,
ing physician-assisted suicide highlight the such as those grounded in classic work by
duty to relieve patient suffering or stem Kohlberg (Kohlberg, 1969; Turiel, 1983),
from a vigorous understanding of the duty moral judgments typically result from a

320
 Folk Theories in the Moral Domain 321

process of explicit moral reasoning—or and contemporary accounts of moral judg-


“deliberation”—akin to that offered by the ment from social psychology, but also draws
American College of Physicians. More re- on research from both cognitive and devel-
cent accounts, such as Haidt’s (2001) social opmental psychology on intuitive theories of
intuitionist model, however, challenge the the natural world.
idea that moral justifications are causally re- To argue for this proposal, we first pro-
sponsible for their corresponding judgments. vide a brief review of evidence that has been
Instead, they argue that moral judgment is used to support the dual-process perspective
a fundamentally “intuitive” phenomenon, in moral psychology. We then suggest that
with a large literature suggesting that moral the distinction between intuitive and delib-
attitudes on issues related to sanctity of life, erative processing is potentially problematic
which typically divide liberal and conserva- when it comes to describing the role of more
tive voters, are guided by affect—most nota- abstract commitments in moral judgment, as
bly disgust (Inbar, Pizarro, & Bloom, 2012; in the example of physician-assisted suicide
Inbar, Pizarro, Knobe, & Bloom, 2009; and intuitive dualism. To make sense of such
Inbar, Pizarro, Iyer, & Haidt, 2012; Inbar, cases, we turn to literature on intuitive theo-
Pizarro, & Bloom, 2012). ries in other domains and argue for “folk
These opposing approaches differ critical- theories” that play a role in shaping moral
ly on the emphasis they place on deliberative judgment. We then present evidence for this
versus intuitive processes, a distinction that position, including our own recent work,
has paved the way for widespread “dual-sys- which documents systematic relationships
tems” or “dual-process” accounts of moral between people’s metaphysical and epis-
reasoning (Greene, 2007; Greene, Sommer- temic commitments, on the one hand, and
ville, Nystrom, Darley, & Cohen, 2001; their intuitive judgments concerning bioethi-
Greene, Morelli, Lowenberg, Nystrom, & cal issues such as physician-assisted suicide,
Cohen, 2008; Greene, Nystrom, Engell, on the other.
Darley, & Cohen, 2004). In this chapter
we argue that, although dual-­ systems ap-
proaches have been useful in many ways, a Intuition versus Deliberation:
sharp boundary between intuition and de- A Dual‑Process Perspective
liberation potentially obscures important
phenomena in moral judgment. In particu- Dual-process theories, of which there are
lar, we argue that, in many cases, moral many (Evans & Stanovich, 2013), typically
judgments can arise “intuitively” yet result differentiate two types of thinking: one in-
from abstract and coherent theoretical com- tuitive and the other deliberative. Intuition
mitments that participate in “deliberative” and deliberation typically map onto mental
reasoning. One example comes from the processes underlying decision making and
case of physician-assisted suicide, which im- behavior differentiated according to whether
plicitly ties a terminally ill patient’s deciding they operate automatically or in a controlled
mind to her failing body. For this and other manner. This distinction, in turn, can be
issues that bear on the sanctity of life, moral operationalized either behaviorally—with
judgments could depend not only on affect automatic processes manifesting themselves
but also on relatively abstract and coher- under cognitive load or time pressure—or
ent metaphysical commitments concerning by isolating distinct neural correlates (e.g.,
the relationship between the mind and the the ventromedial prefrontal cortex [vmPFC]
body—what has typically been referred to vs. dorsolateral prefrontal cortex [DLPFC]
as “intuitive dualism” in the psychological for automatic vs. controlled processes in the
literature (Bloom, 2004a; Greene, 2011). We case of deontological vs. utilitarian judg-
propose that theoretical commitments such ment; Greene et al., 2001; Greene et al.,
as those embodied in intuitive dualism play 2004). The distinction between automatic
an important role in moral judgment, but in and controlled processes and, correspond-
a manner that cross-cuts the traditional in- ingly, between intuitive and deliberative
tuition–deliberation divide. This hybrid pro- judgments has been particularly influential
posal borrows insights from both traditional in moral psychology.
322 M O R A L I T Y A N D B E L I E F S

Although there are many flavors of dual- evidence for brain processes associated with
process theories (see Evans & Stanovich, cognitive control (e.g., DLPFC) in utilitarian
2013), most agree in linking intuitive versus moral judgment. These initial findings sup-
deliberative processing with the pairs of op- ported the idea that deontological judgments
posing attributes identified in Table 33.1. emerge from “intuition” (with an important
Evidence for the distinction between intui- role for automatic emotional processing)
tive and deliberative processing accordingly and utilitarian judgments from more con-
focuses on these attributes, with particular trolled deliberation.
emphasis on the first three. Subsequent work has backed up the as-
Initial support for dual-process approach- sociation between deontology and more
es to the moral domain came from func- intuitive processing, on the one hand, and
tional neuroimaging studies investigating between utilitarian judgments and delib-
the extent to which brain processes associ- eration, on the other (Paxton, Ungar, &
ated with emotion (e.g., vmPFC, amygdala) Greene, 2012). For example, patients with
are engaged in response to different kinds frontotemporal dementia (characterized by
of moral dilemmas (Greene et al., 2001; “emotional blunting”) are three times more
Greene et al., 2004). For example, Greene likely than healthy controls to answer in
and colleagues presented participants with favor of pushing the man off the footbridge
variants on trolley car problems, such as the for utilitarian benefit (Mendez, Anderson,
hypothetical footbridge case, in which a par- & Shapira, 2005). At the cellular level, cital-
ticipant must decide whether it is permissible opram, a selective serotonin reuptake inhibi-
to push one person in front of a train to pre- tor (SSRI), increases the availability of sero-
vent the train from hitting five others. Sce- tonin in the bloodstream, thereby increasing
narios of this sort create a tension between certain emotional responses and deontologi-
deontological bases for judgments, which cal moral judgment, whereas antianxiety
reflect rights and duties, and utilitarian drugs such as lorazepam can reduce deon-
bases for judgment, which require favoring tological inclinations (Perkins et al., 2013).
the greater good. Greene et al. (2001) found And, at a behavioral level, utilitarian judg-
that “personal” moral dilemmas—those like ments are more affected by cognitive load
the footbridge case that involve causing di- (Greene et al., 2008; Trémolière, Neys, &
rect harm, often through touch—tended to Bonnefon, 2012), associated with longer
elicit neural activity associated with emo- decision time (Suter & Hertwig, 2011), and
tion. In contrast, Greene et al. (2004) found associated with reflective, as opposed to in-
tuitive, mindsets (Paxton et al., 2012).
One implication of dual-process approach-
TABLE 33.1.  Attributes of Intuitive es is that moral judgments (which reflect a
and Deliberative Processing mix of intuition and deliberation) can seri-
Intuitive Deliberative ously depart from moral justifications (which
fall on the side of deliberation). And, in fact,
Process Automatic Controlled
there is evidence that the two diverge. Haidt
Speed of Fast Slow (2001), for example, argues for a phenom-
processing enon he calls “moral dumbfounding,” which
Role of affect Often high Often low
refers to an individual’s inability to produce
moral justifications for moral judgments. As
Level of Nonconscious Conscious evidence, he presents the case of Mark and
consciousness Julie—siblings who decide to engage in con-
Representation Contextualized Abstract sensual sex, use protection, and find that it
brings them closer together. An overwhelm-
Accuracy “Good Often high ing number of individuals find this wrong,
enough” but when probed for reasons why, fail to
Evolutionary Distant Recent produce reliable justifications. Haidt (2001)
origin claims that “moral reasoning does not cause
moral judgment; rather, moral reasoning is
Type of belief Implicit Explicit
usually a post hoc construction, generated
 Folk Theories in the Moral Domain 323

after a judgment has been reached” (p. 814). man & Valcarcel, 2012), novel theories are
Other empirical work similarly suggests also acquired through everyday experience
that moral justifications are not responsible (e.g., Kempton, 1986; Vosniadou & Brewer,
for their corresponding moral judgments 1994) and through formal education (e.g.,
(Hauser, Cushman, Young, Jin, & Mikhail, Shtulman & Calabi, 2013). We refer to such
2007) and that even when individuals can theories as “folk theories,” both to differen-
provide justifications, they sometimes fail to tiate them from full-fledged scientific theo-
recognize the full set of factors that influ- ries and to avoid the implication that such
enced their judgments (Cushman, Young, & theories are necessarily “intuitive” in the
Hauser, 2006). dual-systems sense.
Dual-systems approaches can also accom- Folk theories are characterized along
modate cases in which moral judgments and three dimensions: structural, functional,
moral justifications systematically cohere— and dynamic (Gopnik & Wellman, 2012;
the approach does not reject the possibility Gopnik & Meltzoff, 1997). At a structural
that moral justifications can sometimes in- level, folk theories specify law-like regulari-
fluence judgments or that justifications will ties and involve coherent, abstract, and typi-
match judgments because they are gener- cally causal representations of the world. At
ated post hoc. A bigger challenge for most a functional level, theories support impor-
dual-systems approaches would come from tant judgments and behaviors, including pre-
evidence for representational structures dictions, explanations, counterfactuals, and
that blur the crucial distinction between interventions. And at a dynamic level, folk
“intuitive” and “deliberate” processing. A theories are revised in light of new evidence.
candidate for such a structure comes from These features differentiate folk theories
research in cognitive and developmental psy- from other kinds of mental representations,
chology that aims to characterize people’s such as heuristics, networks of semantic as-
intuitive theories of the natural world, such sociation, or simple schemas.
as folk psychological, folk biological, and The characteristic structural, functional,
folk physical beliefs. As we detail in the next and dynamic properties of folk theories po-
section, “intuitive” theories don’t fit neatly tentially muddy the distinction between in-
on a single side of the intuitive–­deliberative tuitive and deliberative. Some characteristics
divide. of folk theories put them on the “intuitive”
end, and it is not a coincidence that they are
sometimes called intuitive theories: They
Drawing an Analogy to Folk
often generate judgments quickly and are
Scientific Theories
cognitively opaque in the sense that they op-
A broad literature in cognitive and devel- erate over representations and processes that
opmental psychology suggests that children are not necessarily explicitly available. They
hold rich intuitive theories of the world even are also often invoked to explain errors. On
before they begin formal education (e.g., the other hand, they have some characteris-
Carey, 2000; Keil, 2011). In the domain of tics that align them with deliberation. At a
physics, for example, students hold theories structural level, they tend to involve fairly
grounded in the belief that forces transfer abstract representations. At a functional
from one object to another upon contact level, they support explanations that involve
and must dissipate before those objects cease explicit appeal to theoretical content. And
moving (Clement, 1982; McCloskey, 1983). at a functional level, they are responsive to
In the domain of biology, children hold in- evidence and argumentation—learning pro-
tuitive theories of adaptation grounded in a cesses more naturally associated with delib-
belief that all members of a species evolve eration. So how do folk theories fit into a du-
together such that each individual organ- al-systems approach to the moral domain?
ism will produce offspring that are better Most approaches to moral psychology
adapted than the parent was at birth (Shtul- recognize an important role for folk theo-
man, 2006; Shtulman & Schulz, 2008). ries in analyzing or structuring the input to
Although these initial theories continue to moral judgment. For example, moral judg-
play a role throughout the lifespan (Shtul- ments can depend critically on causal analy-
324 M O R A L I T Y A N D B E L I E F S

ses predicated on folk physical assumptions volves morally relevant distinctions, such as
and on analyses of an agent’s intentions that that between agent and patient.
depend on folk psychological mechanisms Functionally, folk moral theories should
(e.g., Cushman, 2008). (Exceptions to this at least partially govern more implicit moral
generalization include approaches that deny judgments, such as judgments concerning
the existence of folk theories altogether or which actions (interventions) are morally
that reject the premise that folk scientific permissible. This is what Lombrozo (2009)
analysis “precedes” moral analysis, e.g., found in a study investigating whether indi-
Knobe, 2010.) But we wish to suggest some- viduals’ explicit utilitarian and deontologi-
thing stronger: that folk theories not only cal moral commitments predict “intuitive”
structure the input to moral judgment but moral responses to trolley car problems.
can also embody theoretical commitments Those participants with explicit utilitar-
that play a role in explicit moral delibera- ian moral preferences were more likely not
tion and in “educating” moral intuitions. only to judge action in trolley car scenarios
This process can occur in two ways: if the (all of which involved sacrificing one life for
theories themselves contain moral content, five) more permissible but also to offer more
or if the theories involve general commit- consistent judgments when two scenarios
ments—such as dualism—that inform and were presented side-by-side—a manipula-
constrain moral judgments. In the next sec- tion that’s been shown to facilitate the ex-
tions, we provide evidence for both of these traction and application of rules (Gentner &
possibilities. Medina, 1998).
Finally, moral theories should have dy-
namic properties—they should change in
Evidence for Folk Moral Theories: response to evidence through a process of
The Building Blocks theory revision. Haidt (2001) influentially
suggested that moral intuitions drive moral
What might intuitive moral theories look reasoning “just as surely as a dog wags its
like? Such theories can be understood as a tail” (p. 830). But others have suggested
special type of folk theory specifically within that moral intuitions are dynamic and open
the moral domain. At a structural level, folk to revision, in perhaps subtle ways. Pizarro
moral theories should be abstract and rule- and Bloom (2003) proposed that individuals
based in nature. At a functional level, folk “educate” moral intuitions either through
moral theories should support moral judg- the mere act of thinking or through selec-
ments and justification. And at a dynamic tively exposing themselves to certain experi-
level, moral theories should be responsive to ences in the world. The former mechanism
new evidence, be it through direct instruc- for theory change falls squarely on the side
tion or more implicit learning mechanisms. of deliberation: Humans can engage in com-
We review evidence for each of these in turn. plex courses of private reflection, activat-
Structurally, there is good evidence that ing new and sometimes contradictory intu-
at least some moral “rules” are represented itions. Over time, deliberation of this kind
in terms of fairly abstract causal structure could “tune” intuitions to conform to the
(Mikhail, 2011; Waldmann & Dieterich, outputs of more deliberative reasoning (see
2007) and formulated over fairly abstract also Railton, 2014).
concepts, even in early childhood (Hamlin, Individuals can also dynamically alter
2013). For example, Waldmann and Diet- intuitions in more indirect ways—for in-
erich (2007) found that individuals are more stance, by controlling their experiences, thus
willing to accept a utilitarian trade-off that exerting distal control to shift intuitions. Ev-
involves harming a few individuals to save a idence for this comes from work on implicit
greater number of people if the intervention racial attitudes and the ease with which au-
is targeted at the agent and not the patient. tomatic judgments can be manipulated by a
These findings suggest not only that moral variety of explicit techniques. For instance,
“rules” are formulated over abstract causal participants exposed to positive African
structure but also that the causal analysis in- American exemplars, both in the laboratory
 Folk Theories in the Moral Domain 325

and in a formal course on racism taught by vegetarianism provides an instructive ex-


an African American professor, exhibit re- ample. At a structural level, we know that
duced implicit biases (Dasgupta & Green- moral vegetarianism is supported by rela-
wald, 2001; Rudman, Ashmore, & Gary, tively abstract beliefs that can be explicitly
2001), and, in light of this, an individual articulated and applied. Beardsworth and
could set out to systematically alter her en- Keil (1992), for example, found that moral
vironment. Studies of this sort illustrate the vegetarians can explicitly identify moti-
porous boundaries between intuitive and de- vations for their view, citing concerns for
liberative processes; intuitions can be tuned animal welfare or a utilitarian concern for
up, in both the presence and the absence of environmental sustainability, both of which
new experiential data from the world, and, reflect broad-ranging commitments. At a
although this “learning” process may be ini- functional level, we know that these beliefs
tiated by deliberative choice in a distal sense, guide behavior (i.e., food choices) but also
the learned intuitions could subsequently re- explanations, predictions, and other judg-
spond in relatively fast and automatic ways. ments. Vegetarians, for instance, are more
likely to conceive of animals as possessing
a wider range of mental states—including
Folk Moral Theories as Theories
the ability to experience pain and suffer-
So far we’ve provided isolated examples of ing (Bastian, Loughnan, Haslam, & Radke,
theory-like structural, functional, and dy- 2012).
namic characteristics within the moral do- And, finally, at a dynamic level, there’s
main. However, such isolated examples are good reason to believe that beliefs about
insufficient to support the stronger claim vegetarianism are susceptible to delibera-
that people possess moral theories as such. tion and argumentation (e.g., cases of chil-
For this stronger claim, we would want ad- dren who become vegetarian independently
ditional evidence that these isolated theory- of their parents, often through discussions
like elements are integrated into a somewhat with other kids; Hussar & Harris, 2010),
coherent whole. For instance, we would but also that explicit commitments to veg-
want evidence that the consequentialist com- etarianism can have long-term effects on an
mitments that predict trolley car judgments automatic affective response: disgust. Many
in Lombrozo (2009) are relatively abstract vegetarians report feeling disgusted at the
(a structural property) and responsive to mere thought of eating meat (Rozin, Mark-
evidence (a dynamic property) and that they with, & Stoess, 1997), which would, from an
engage with other relevant moral beliefs. emotivist account, suggest that vegetarians
Systematic coherence is often treated as have higher levels of dispositional sensitivity
one of the most compelling sources of evi- to disgust than nonvegetarians. However,
dence for folk theories as distinct from other research suggests that disgust does not, at
mental representations. For instance, in the least initially, play a causal role in the deci-
domain of biology, Slaughter and Lyons sion to become vegetarian: although feelings
(2003) taught preschool-age children about of disgust toward meat eating increase over
the functional roles of different organs in the course of being vegetarian, those who re-
the body and found that this influenced port being motivated by moral concerns (as
their conceptions of death, suggesting a opposed to health concerns) do not report
coherent and interconnected set of biologi- high dispositional levels of disgust sensitiv-
cal beliefs related to bodily function. With ity (Fessler, Arguello, Mekdara, & Macias,
adults, Shtulman (2006) found that students 2003), challenging the idea that affective
tended to hold relatively coherent “transfor- intuitions are the primary drivers of moral
mational” or “variational” views of natural judgment. This line of research thus suggests
selection, rather than clusters of unrelated that moral vegetarians’ disgust reactions to
beliefs. Do we have evidence for such coher- meat eating are a by-product of, as opposed
ence in the moral domain? to a cause of, their moral theories. The moral
Little work has focused on questions of theory has arguably “educated” or “tuned”
coherence directly, but the study of moral the individual’s affective responses.
326 M O R A L I T Y A N D B E L I E F S

The case or moral vegetarianism provides a mind or soul. Bloom (2004a, 2006) argues
a nice example of how a folk moral theory that we are intuitive dualists who separate
(in this case about animal rights or welfare) the physical body from the nonphysical
can blur the boundary between intuitive and mind; Bloom (2004a) argues that “we do not
deliberative processing, with some affective feel as if we are bodies, we feel as if we occu-
and automatic components, and others that py them” (p. 191), and that this dualist ten-
are clearly abstract and explicit. It’s impor- dency has implications for moral judgment.
tant to note, however, that not all represen- Greene (2011) similarly explains that “the
tations with moral content will necessarily debate over abortion is ultimately a meta-
conform to the structure of a folk theory. In physical one. The question is not whether a
fact, some findings argue against theory-like fertilized egg is alive, but whether it is host to
representations for some moral content. For a ‘human life,’ i.e., a human soul. Without a
example, Goodwin and Darley (2008) found soul in balance, there is no abortion debate.
that individuals vary in their meta-ethical Likewise for the debates over human stem
commitments to moral objectivism, but that cell research and euthanasia” (p. 21).
judgments also depend strongly on con- Dualism has historically been associated
crete features of specific moral judgments, with metaphysical commitments about the
such as their content and valence (Goodwin relationship between the mind and the ma-
& Darley, 2012). In other words, it could terial. For instance, the Stanford Encyclope-
be misleading to classify some people as dia of Philosophy (Robinson, 2011) defines
“moral objectivists” and some as “moral dualism as “the theory that the mental and
relativists,” where the label is taken to re- the physical—or mind and body or mind
flect an abstractly represented commitment and brain—are, in some sense, radically
with broad and systematic scope. Instead, a different kinds of thing.” Within psychol-
given individual will appear to be objectiv- ogy, however, the term intuitive dualism has
ist in some contexts and relativist in others been used to cast a much wider net. Scales
(see also Sarkissian, Park, Tien, Wright, & that have been designed to measure intui-
Knobe, 2011; Uttich, Tsai, & Lombrozo, tive dualist tendencies (Stanovich, 1989)
2014), suggesting that judgments result from are not restricted to items that involve the
a more contextualized process or representa- relationship between the mind and the body
tion. More research is needed to truly test but also include concepts related to religious
the “theory-like” credentials of meta-ethical beliefs in a soul or afterlife (e.g., “My con-
commitments concerning objectivism, but sciousness will survive the disintegration of
the example raises an important point: Even my physical body”) and more general views
if some moral judgments result from men- about determinism and reduction in science
tal representations that we can properly call (e.g., “Knowledge of the mind will forever
theories, it doesn’t follow that all do. In fact, be beyond the understanding of sciences like
it’s quite likely that moral judgments are sup- physics, neurophysiology, and psychology”).
ported by a host of representational formats. Similarly, experimental manipulations of
Having considered the case of vegetarian- dualist beliefs (Preston, Ritter, & Hepler,
ism—which involves moral commitments 2013) involve vignettes that also vary in de-
affecting moral judgment—we now move terminism, free will, and reductionist expla-
into evidence from our own work that il- nations for the human mind.
lustrates a role for high-level philosophical In recent work (Gottlieb & Lombrozo,
commitments in moral judgment. in preparation), we have created the Dual-
ism+ Scale, designed to measure both nar-
row metaphysical beliefs related to dualism
The Case of Intuitive Dualism and related but conceptually distinct beliefs,
such as those concerning a soul, determin-
Debates over sanctity of life bioethical issues ism, scientific reductionism, and epistemo-
(e.g., abortion, physician-assisted suicide) logical beliefs about the scope of science in
often hang critically on the question of when explaining mental life (see Table 33.2). We
a mere bundle of cells comes to have (or lose) find that Dualism+ scores are predictive of
 Folk Theories in the Moral Domain 327

TABLE 33.2.  The Five Components disgust sensitivity (Inbar et al., 2009). They
of the Dualism+ Scale, as Supported are thus canonical examples of moral judg-
by a Factor Analysis, along ments that are more affective, automatic,
with a Representative Item from Each and “intuitive” in nature.
Religious “Every person has a soul.” Our study also included a measure of dis-
commitments to a gust sensitivity (Haidt, McCauley, & Rozin,
soul; afterlife beliefs 1994, modified by Olatunji et al., 2007),
which revealed that those individuals who
Scope of science in “Explaining everything are opposed to describing the mind in scien-
explaining the mind that makes us human in
strictly scientific terms in tific terms display high levels of disgust sensi-
some way decreases the tivity, even while statistically controlling for
value of life.” political conservatism and religiosity—two
factors that have been strongly linked to dis-
Free will “People always have the gust sensitivity (Inbar et al., 2009; Terrizzi,
ability to do otherwise.” Shook, & Ventis, 2012). Just as moral veg-
Determinism “People’s choices and etarianism can recruit disgust at the thought
actions must happen of eating meat, it could be that beliefs about
precisely the way they do the scope of science can result in a disgust
because of laws of nature response to stimuli that implicitly or explic-
and the way things were in itly violate those commitments, such as phy-
the distant past.” sician-assisted suicide. Alternatively, it could
Mind–brain identity “Minds are not the same as be that opposition to scientific descriptions
brains.” of the mind is itself caused by disgust, which
can be elicited by a reminder that the human
mind is nothing beyond its physical compo-
five highly controversial bioethical issues nents (see Rozin, Haidt, & McCauley, 1999,
that, as Greene (2006) suggested, hinge for relevant discussion on animal reminder
critically on philosophical commitments: disgust). Future experimental work—which
abortion, physician-assisted suicide, clon- isolates the direct effect of reductionist de-
ing humans, cloning animals, and research scriptions of the mind on state levels of dis-
using embryonic stem cells. However, the gust (and vice versa)—will be useful in teas-
component of the Dualism+ scale that drives ing apart these two pathways.
this relationship is not about the metaphys- In sum, our initial findings on the rela-
ics of the mind–brain relationship itself tionship between Dualism+ and views on
(“mind–brain identity”), but about the scope sanctity of life bioethical issues, such as
of science and the affective consequences of physician-assisted suicide, suggest a moder-
providing scientific explanations (“scope ate relationship between philosophical com-
of science in explaining the mind”; see also mitments and bioethical views. However,
Gottlieb & Lombrozo, in press): We found the philosophical commitments related to
that participants’ scope of science subscore bioethical views concern the scope of sci-
significantly predicted bioethical judgments, ence, not the mind–body relationship (nar-
even when controlling for individual dif- rowly construed). Although further research
ferences in political orientation, religiosity, is certainly required, our findings are consis-
disgust sensitivity, and cognitive style (Fred- tent with the basic proposal that theory-like
erick, 2005). commitments—in this case relatively broad
This finding suggests a causal relationship and abstract epistemic commitments about
between commitments concerning the scope science—affect moral judgments, likely in
of science and bioethical judgments, but it automatic and (in this case) affectively laden
could be that—as with vegetarianism—the ways. Like the example of vegetarianism—
relationship is mediated by affective pro- and the examples from the preceding sec-
cesses. In fact, bioethical attitudes fall into tion—this points to the possibility of mental
a class of purity-based sociopolitical issues representations that take the form of folk
that are affected by individual differences in theories that interact with moral judgment
328 M O R A L I T Y A N D B E L I E F S

and that cross-cut the traditional distinction First, one of the most compelling forms
between intuition and deliberation. of evidence for folk theories—as distinct
from other forms of mental representation—
comes in the coherence of the mental repre-
Future Directions sentation. It’s also coherence between intui-
tive and deliberative elements that arguably
We have argued for the reality of folk moral poses the greatest challenge to dual-process
theories—a form of mental representation approaches. But to what extent are folk
distinct from those typically acknowledged moral theories coherent? Or, to complicate
by dual-systems approaches. Drawing upon matters further, in what form are they co-
work from cognitive development and cog- herent, and is this form of coherence a true
nitive psychology, we suggest that folk theo- challenge to dual-process approaches?
ries can involve abstract commitments with Second, how do education and affect in-
structural, functional, and dynamic ele- teract in the dynamic tuning of moral judg-
ments that blur the distinction between in- ment? Our evidence for the role of epistemo-
tuition and deliberation. In particular, folk logical commitments in bioethical judgment
theories can involve abstract representations complements Pizarro and Bloom’s (2003)
that can be explicitly and deliberatively en- proposal that various forms of distal control
gaged but that can also be applied in rela- can revise and reshape the nature of moral
tively automatic and implicit ways. intuitions. This view suggests that individu-
Many elements of our proposal are not als who oppose scientifically reductionist
in conflict with traditional dual-process descriptions of the mind may actively avoid
approaches. A dual-process theorist can certain forms of education (such as neuro-
readily accommodate both intuitive and scientific education) or even purposefully
deliberative elements to moral judgment, engage in religious dialogue that argues
with corresponding mental representations against a reductionist picture of human
and processes for each. Moreover, such a nature. On the other hand, if these same
perspective can accommodate interaction individuals actively engage with neurosci-
between systems and change over time. In ence, they could experience a dampened
its weakest form, our evidence is merely a emotional response due to a shift in underly-
warning that the intuition–deliberation dis- ing moral intuitions that accrues over time.
tinction can potentially obscure the nature We could test this hypothesis by gathering
of moral judgment by discounting the con- longitudinal data on how science education
tributions of theory-like elements, some of influences metaphysical and epistemological
which are intuitive and some of which are commitments, both at intuitive and more
deliberative. But in its stronger form, our po- explicit levels, and therefore how it affects
sition argues for the existence of a complex bioethical judgments. This empirical ques-
form of representation—a folk theory—that tion is especially relevant in a culture that
is not merely a collection of elements from is becoming increasingly “scientific” and re-
an intuitive system and elements from a de- ductionist in nature (Farah & Hook, 2013).
liberative system but, instead, a coherent Although Bloom (2004b) is skeptical of the
representation that does not find a natural extent to which neuroscientific explanations
home in either system. can revise dualist intuitions, conceiving of
The evidence we’ve marshaled is sugges- these commitments as a more general form
tive but arguably falls short of establishing of folk theory suggests that they may be re-
this stronger position. In part, the reason vised in light of new experiential data.
for this is that research has not approached In sum, we have argued in favor of a
moral judgment with the aim of testing the unique role for theory-like representations
presence and boundaries of folk theories. in moral judgment that cross-cut the intui-
Thus many questions remain open, and we tive–deliberative distinction. And although
see the value of our proposal in part as a this view is relatively new to the moral psy-
spur to further research. We conclude by chology literature, it draws heavily upon
highlighting two directions for such research the literature on folk theories of the natural
that we see as especially valuable. world, which can be explicit and law-like in
 Folk Theories in the Moral Domain 329

principle but engaged in implicit ways. We Farah, M. J., & Hook, C. J. (2013). The seduc-
suggest that this approach is useful in mak- tive allure of “seductive allure.” Perspectives
ing sense of intuitions regarding fantastical on Psychological Science, 8(1), 88–90.
variants on trolley-car dilemmas and other Fessler, D. M., Arguello, A. P., Mekdara, J. M.,
& Macias, R. (2003). Disgust sensitivity and
high-conflict scenarios invoked for moral
meat consumption: A test of an emotivist ac-
psychology research. But more important, count of moral vegetarianism. Appetite, 41(1),
and certainly more timely, this approach 31–41.
provides insight into the real-world judg- Frederick, S. (2005). Cognitive reflection and de-
ments that divide individuals when it comes cision making. Journal of Economic Perspec-
to matters of life and death, such as in cases tives, 19, 25–42.
of physician-assisted suicide. Gentner, D., & Medina, J. (1998). Similarity
and the development of rules. Cognition, 65,
263–297.
REFERENCES Goodwin, G. P., & Darley, J. M. (2008). The
psychology of meta-ethics: Exploring objectiv-
Bastian, B., Loughnan, S., Haslam, N., & ism. Cognition, 106(3), 1339–1366.
Radke, H. R. (2012). Don’t mind meat? The Goodwin, G. P., & Darley, J. M. (2012). Why are
denial of mind to animals used for human con- some moral beliefs perceived to be more ob-
sumption. Personality and Social Psychology jective than others? Journal of Experimental
Bulletin, 38(2), 247–256. Social Psychology, 48(1), 250–256.
Beardsworth, A., & Keil, T. (1992). The vegetar- Gopnik, A., & Meltzoff, A. N. (1997). Words,
ian option: Varieties, conversions, motives and thoughts, and theories. Cambridge, MA: MIT
careers. Sociological Review, 40(2), 253–293. Press.
Bloom, P. (2004a). Descartes’ baby: How the Gopnik, A., & Wellman, H. M. (2012). Re-
science of child development explains what constructing constructivism: Causal models,
makes us human. New York: Basic Books. Bayesian learning mechanisms, and the theory
Bloom, P. (2004b). Natural-born dualists. Edge. theory. Psychological Bulletin, 138(6), 1085–
Available at www.edge.org/conversation/ 1108.
paul_bloom-natural-born-dualists. Gottlieb, S. & Lombrozo, T. (in preparation).
Bloom, P. (2006). Seduced by the flickering lights Dissociable components of mind-body dualist
of the brain. Seed Magazine, 27. Available at attitudes predict bioethical judgments. Manu-
http://seedmagazine.com/content/article/ script in preparation.
seduced_ by_ the_flickering_ lights_ of_ the_ Gottlieb, S., & Lombrozo, T. (in press). Can sci-
brain. ence explain the human mind? Intuitive judg-
Carey, S. (2000). Science education as conceptu- ments about the limits of science. Psychologi-
al change. Journal of Applied Developmental cal Science.
Psychology, 21(1), 13–19. Greene, J. D. (2007). The secret joke of Kant’s
Clement, J. (1982). Students’ preconceptions in soul. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral
introductory mechanics. American Journal of psychology (Vol. 3, pp. 35–80). Cambridge,
Physics, 50(1), 66–71. MA: MIT Press.
Cushman, F. (2008). Crime and punishment: Greene, J. D. (2011). Social neuroscience and the
Distinguishing the roles of causal and inten- soul’s last stand. In A. Todorov, S. T. Fiske, &
tional analyses in moral judgment. Cognition, D. A. Prentice (Eds.), Social neuroscience: To-
108(2), 353–380. ward understanding the underpinnings of the
Cushman, F., Young, L., & Hauser, M. (2006). social mind (pp. 263–273). New York: Oxford
The role of conscious reasoning and intuition University Press.
in moral judgment: Testing three principles of Greene, J. D., Morelli, S. A., Lowenberg, K.,
harm. Psychological Science, 17(12), 1082– Nystrom, L. E., & Cohen, J. D. (2008). Cog-
1089. nitive load selectively interferes with utilitar-
Dasgupta, N., & Greenwald, A. G. (2001). On ian moral judgment. Cognition, 107(3), 1144–
the malleability of automatic attitudes: Com- 1154.
bating automatic prejudice with images of Greene, J. D., Nystrom, L. E., Engell, A. D., Dar-
admired and disliked individuals. Journal of ley, J. M., & Cohen, J. D. (2004). The neu-
Personality and Social Psychology, 81(5), 800. ral bases of cognitive conflict and control in
Evans, J. S. B., & Stanovich, K. E. (2013). Dual- moral judgment. Neuron, 44(2), 389–400.
process theories of higher cognition: Advanc- Greene, J. D., Sommerville, R. B., Nystrom, L.
ing the debate. Perspectives on Psychological E., Darley, J. M., & Cohen, J. D. (2001). An
Science, 8(3), 223–241. fMRI investigation of emotional engagement
330 M O R A L I T Y A N D B E L I E F S

in moral judgment. Science, 293(5537), 2105– Olatunji, B. O., Williams, N. L., Tolin, D. F.,
2108. Abramowitz, J. S., Sawchuk, C. N., Lohr,
Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional dog and its ra- J. M., & Elwood, L. S. (2007). The Disgust
tional tail: A social intuitionist approach to Scale: Item analysis, factor structure, and sug-
moral judgment. Psychological Review, 108, gestions for refinement. Psychological Assess-
814–834. ment, 19(3), 281–297.
Haidt, J., McCauley, C., & Rozin, P. (1994). In- Paxton, J. M., Ungar, L., & Greene, J. D. (2012).
dividual differences in sensitivity to disgust: A Reflection and reasoning in moral judgment.
scale sampling seven domains of disgust elici- Cognitive Science, 36(1), 163–177.
tors. Personality and Individual Differences, Perkins, A. M., Leonard, A. M., Weaver, K.,
16(5), 701–713. Dalton, J. A., Mehta, M. A., Kumari, V., . . .
Hamlin, J. K. (2013). Moral judgment and action Ettinger, U. (2013). A dose of ruthlessness:
in preverbal infants and toddlers: Evidence for ­Interpersonal moral judgment is hardened by
an innate moral core. Current Directions in the anti-anxiety drug lorazepam. Journal of
Psychological Science, 22(3), 186–193. Experimental Psychology: General, 142(3),
Hauser, M., Cushman, F., Young, L., Jin, R., & 612.
Mikhail, J. (2007). A dissociation between Pizarro, D. A., & Bloom, P. (2003). The intel-
moral judgments and justifications. Mind and ligence of the moral intuitions: A comment
Language, 22(1), 1–21. on Haidt (2001). Psychological Review, 110,
Hussar, K. M., & Harris, P. L. (2010). Children 193–196.
who choose not to eat meat: A study of early Preston, J. L., Ritter, R. S., & Hepler, J. (2013).
moral decision-making. Social Development, Neuroscience and the soul: Competing expla-
19(3), 627–641. nations for the human experience. Cognition,
Inbar, Y., Pizarro, D. A., & Bloom, P. (2012). 127(1), 31–37.
Disgusting smells cause decreased liking of Railton, P. (2014). The affective dog and its ra-
gay men. Emotion, 12, 23–27. tional tale: Intuition and attunement. Ethics,
Inbar, Y., Pizarro, D., Iyer, R., & Haidt, J. (2012). 124(4), 813–859.
Disgust sensitivity, political conservatism, and Robinson, H. (2011). Dualism. In E. N. Zalta
voting. Social Psychological and Personality (Ed.), Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy.
Science, 3(5), 537–544. Stanford, CA: Metaphysics Research Lab,
Inbar, Y., Pizarro, D. A., Knobe, J., & Bloom, Center for the Study of Language and Infor-
P. (2009). Disgust sensitivity predicts intuitive mation, Stanford University. Retrieved from
disapproval of gays. Emotion, 9(3), 435. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2011/
Keil, F. C. (2011). Science starts early. Science, entries/dualism.
331(6020), 1022–1023. Rozin, P., Haidt, J., & McCauley, C. R. (1999).
Kempton, W. (1986). Two theories of home heat Disgust: The body and soul emotion. In T.
control. Cognitive Science, 10(1), 75–90. Dalgleish & M. Power (Eds.), Handbook of
Knobe, J. (2010). Person as scientist, person cognition and emotion (pp. 429–445). Chich-
as moralist. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, ester, UK: Wiley.
33(4), 315–329. Rozin, P., Markwith, M., & Stoess, C. (1997).
Kohlberg, L. (1969). Stage and sequence: The Moralization and becoming a vegetarian: The
cognitive-developmental approach to social- transformation of preferences into values and
ization. In D. A. Goslin (Ed.), Handbook of the recruitment of disgust. Psychological Sci-
socialization theory and research (pp. 151– ence, 8(2), 67–73.
235). New York: Academic Press. Rudman, L. A., Ashmore, R. D., & Gary, M. L.
Lombrozo, T. (2009). The role of moral commit- (2001). “Unlearning” automatic biases: The
ments in moral judgment. Cognitive Science, malleability of implicit stereotypes and preju-
33(2), 273–286. dice. Journal of Personality and Social Psy-
McCloskey, M. (1983). Naive theories of motion. chology, 81, 856–868.
Available at www.researchgate.net/publica- Saad, L. (2010). Four moral issues sharply di-
tion/239563618_Naive_theories_of_motion. vide Americans. Available at www.gallup.
Mendez, M. F., Anderson, E., & Shapira, J. S. com/poll/137357/four-moral-issues-sharply-
(2005). An investigation of moral judgement divide-americans.aspx.
in frontotemporal dementia. Cognitive and Sarkissian, H., Park, J., Tien, D., Wright, J. C.,
Behavioral Neurology, 18(4), 193–197. & Knobe, J. (2011). Folk moral relativism.
Mikhail, J. (2011). Elements of moral cognition: Mind and Language, 26(4), 482–505.
Rawls’ linguistic analogy and the cognitive Shtulman, A. (2006). Qualitative differences
science of moral and legal judgment. Cam- between naive and scientific theories of evolu-
bridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. tion. Cognitive Psychology, 52, 170–194.
 Folk Theories in the Moral Domain 331

Shtulman, A., & Calabi, P. (2013). Tuition vs. Terrizzi, J. A., Jr., Shook, N. J., & Ventis, W. L.
intuition: Effects of instruction on naive theo- (2012). Religious conservatism: An evolution-
ries of evolution. Merrill–Palmer Quarterly, arily evoked disease-avoidance strategy. Reli-
59, 141–167. gion, Brain and Behavior, 2(2), 105–120.
Shtulman, A., & Schulz, L. (2008). The relation Trémolière, B., De Neys, W., & Bonnefon, J.
between essentialist beliefs and evolution- F. (2012). Mortality salience and morality:
ary reasoning. Cognitive Science, 32, 1049– Thinking about death makes people less utili-
1062. tarian. Cognition, 124(3), 379–384.
Shtulman, A., & Valcarcel, J. (2012). Scientific Turiel, E. (1983). The development of social
knowledge suppresses but does not supplant knowledge: Morality and convention. Cam-
earlier intuitions. Cognition, 124, 209–215. bridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Slaughter, V., & Lyons, M. (2003). Learning Uttich, K., Tsai, G., & Lombrozo, T. (2014).
about life and death in early childhood. Cog- Exploring metaethical commitments: Moral
nitive Psychology, 46(1), 1–30. objectivity and moral progress. Advances in
Snyder, L., & Sulmasy, D. P. (2001). Physician- Experimental Moral Psychology, 188–208.
assisted suicide. Annals of Internal Medicine, Vosniadou, S., & Brewer, W. F. (1994). Mental
135(3), 209–216. models of the day/night cycle. Cognitive Sci-
Stanovich, K. E. (1989). Implicit philosophies of ence, 18(1), 123–183.
mind: The dualism scale and its relation to re- Waldmann, M. R., & Dieterich, J. H. (2007).
ligiosity and belief in extrasensory perception. Throwing a bomb on a person versus throw-
Journal of Psychology, 123(1), 5–23. ing a person on a bomb: Intervention myopia
Suter, R. S., & Hertwig, R. (2011). Time and in moral intuitions. Psychological Science,
moral judgment. Cognition, 119(3), 454–458. 18(3), 247–253.
CHAPTER 34

Free Will and Moral Psychology

Roy F. Baumeister

Does moral psychology need a workable concept of free will?

Yes; free will is about being able to act differently in the same situa‑
tion, which is also the basis of moral judgment and exhortation.

The nature of morality is one of the grand, behavior. He observed that randomly break-
eternal questions. The question of free will ing from established patterns can be adap-
is another. These are highly interrelated tive for foiling predators—thus grounding
questions, even though psychologists have free will firmly in the context of biological
tended to treat them separately. My own in- evolution (the opposite of Montague). Third,
tellectual pursuits have led me to moral psy- elsewhere, a team of philosophers and psy-
chology by way of the question of free will. chologists came up with a quite different
The purpose of this brief chapter is to elu- definition as a basis for a research grant
cidate the centrally important and powerful competition: Free will is the basis or capac-
overlap between free will theory and moral ity for free action, which means that the per-
psychology. son could act in different ways in the same
Free will is a contentious term. Much ac- situation (Haggard, Mele, O’Connor, &
rimonious debate about free will persists be- Vohs, 2010). It is easy to see why three seri-
cause people use wildly different definitions, ous scholars holding those three definitions
so they are arguing about different things. (and each assuming that the group shares his
For example, Montague (2008, p. R584) definition, rather than using three different
defined free will as “the idea that we make ones) might disagree vehemently and even
choices and have thoughts independent of doubt each other’s wisdom. The definition
anything remotely resembling a physical by Haggard and colleagues (2010) does not
process” and “a close cousin to the idea of assume anything like a soul, for example,
the soul.” He and some others have treated so naturally Montague’s objections would
free will as a kind of exemption from cau- seem absurdly irrelevant to Haggard and
sality. No wonder he regarded the notion as colleagues (2010).
unscientific, even antiscientific! Meanwhile, In my experience, people who disagree
another biologist, Brembs (2010), under- severely about free will frequently turn out
stood free will as random, unpredictable to agree to a great extent about how human

332
 Free Will and Moral Psychology 333

behavior actually occurs. The question of presuppose that the person could have acted
freedom is thus just a semantic issue based differently. It would be absurd to blame
on definitions. The more interesting ques- someone for failing to do the impossible.
tions, to me, are how that kind of behavior When it is clear that a person could not have
actually occurs, rather than whether or in acted differently, others tend not to moralize
what sense it deserves the title of “free will.” or judge. Indeed, some people try to escape
In short, my professional interest is in from guilt by arguing that they could not
understanding how human behavior comes have done otherwise (e.g., Baumeister, Still-
about, and so arguments about definitions well, & Wotman, 1990). The fact that that
are peripheral. But one cannot discuss some- argument works is based on the assumption
thing without defining it, so it is necessary of free will: If I was not free to act different-
to choose a definition. I follow the one pro- ly, I cannot be blamed. Blame rests on the
posed by Haggard et al. (2010), as outlined basic assumption of free will, namely, that I
above—namely, being able to act in differ- could have done something else, something
ent ways in the same situation. My goal is better.
to develop a scientific theory of free will (see I also understand free will as something
Baumeister, 2008; Baumeister & Monroe, specific to humankind. Brembs’s (2010) em-
2014). On that basis, the theory is causal (so phasis on random behavior was stimulated
no exemption from causality). Scientific the- partly by his and colleagues’ research on
ories also do not invoke supernatural forces, random behavior in fruit flies, which was
so souls as causal agents are also excluded. covered in the mass media as evidence sug-
The goal is to understand human agency gesting that fruit flies enjoyed free will. But
and choice. most scholars balk at ascribing free will to
In other words, most scholars agree that such simple species, as do I. Even so, scien-
human action is brought about by some tists should probably resist the philosophi-
remarkable capacities. It evolved from the cal preference for all-or-nothing judgments,
simpler forms of agency that many other such as whether people have free will or not.
animals have, which guide their choices and Agency likely evolved in a series of steps,
actions. It adds something extra, such as the and freedom is not absolute but on a contin-
ability to incorporate language and complex uum (like the vast majority of psychological
ideas into the causation of action. That is variables and processes!).
what people call free will. One can argue Let us consider, therefore, how the human
endlessly about whether it deserves that defi- free will evolved out of the agentic capa-
nition, but to me the more interesting ques- bilities of simpler animals, and what new
tion is how to explain it. features were added. Human choice may
Morality is an important component of indeed share many key features, processes,
this extra kind of complex ideation that hu- and biological substrates with what simpler
mans incorporate into causing action. They animals do. However, it is also qualitatively
do so pretty much uniquely among mam- different in crucial ways. The ability to base
mals. For example, sometimes a wild ani- behavior on moral reasoning is an important
mal gets loose in suburbia and kills a human one of these. Early humans discovered moral
being. The authorities capture the animal rules, and their social life selected in favor of
and sometimes put it to death, sometimes people who were able to use those rules to
not—but in neither case do they first put it guide their behavior.
on trial, as they would if it were a morally Morality was discovered, whereas religion
responsible being. Its fate does not depend, was invented. Most if not all world societies
for example, on whether it perpetrated harm have religions, and they have quite different
as premeditated intention or as impulse. and incompatible content: If one group’s god
My point of departure is that moral prin- is the only god, then the other gods wor-
ciples presuppose free will, or something shiped by other groups cannot exist. Most,
pretty close to it. A moral judgment is es- if not all, societies have morals, too. But un-
sentially a judgment about whether someone like religion, these various cultural moral
should have acted differently. To say that systems are quite similar and compatible
someone should have acted differently is to with each other. They prescribe and prohibit
334 M O R A L I T Y A N D B E L I E F S

mostly the same actions, except for a few de- conveniently useful answer to that, insofar
tails that often lack any basis or that are on a as many religions attribute moral rules to
continuum on which agreement is desirable divine commands. (This itself seems to have
and there is no single optimal point, such as been a discovered solution, because early
sexual morality. (Even with sex, there are human societies had both religion and mo-
plenty of similarities across cultures.) rality but did not link them; Norenzayan et
Moral rules are in a sense bottom-up, al., 2014). One should obey the moral rules
despite being discovered. (Indeed, religion because a god said so.1 The question of why
tends to be top-down, originating in some one should bother doing what a god says to
particular set of teachings and ostensible do somehow does not come up. The top-
revelations. It may be generally true that dis- down nature of religion means that there is
covered realities are bottom-up whereas in- a top, namely a god, beyond which one does
vented ones are top-down.) Moral dilemmas not seek a higher authority.
do not all have correct answers, as would MacIntyre’s (1981) analysis of the mod-
presumably happen if all were derived from ern moral dilemma emphasizes precisely
some overarching system. (Laws, where this point. In medieval Europe, there were
there is a central adjudicating body, suppos- three key conceptual foundations: a view of
edly have correct resolutions: In principle untutored human nature, a view of human
the law does prescribe at least one legally perfectability linked to religious salvation,
correct way to act in any given situation.) and a set of moral rules that show how the
They originate in the requirements of social person can move from the one state to the
systems, and these various requirements are other. Without religion, the salvation com-
not all fully compatible. It is hard to imag- ponent is gone, leaving only the vision of un-
ine a society whose response to the Judeo- tutored human nature a set of moral rules,
Christian Ten Commandments would be, but with no real reason to obey them (other
“Oh, our moral rules are exactly the op- than social pressure). MacIntyre said much
posite!” Social systems function best when of recent moral philosophy has groped for
people refrain from killing, lying, stealing, a replacement for salvation, to give people
and the like. Pretty much every society dis- such a reason to obey the moral rules. In a
covers this. When one travels to a new coun- sense, modern moral philosophy has strug-
try with a very different culture, one may gled to solve an unsolvable problem.
have to learn the religious beliefs and prac- In this analysis, moral principles are not
tices, but usually one can assume that the themselves a product of evolution. But the
basic moral rules are the same as back home. capacity to guide behavior by morality cer-
The fact that moral rules are quite similar tainly is. An advanced form of agency, of be-
across cultures supports the view that they havior control, is a major part of that. That
were discovered rather than invented. They is, humankind evolved something that some
represent solutions to problems of collective people call free will—and did so at least in
action, and the same solutions are discov- part because it enabled people to behave
ered everywhere, not unlike the way that morally.
arithmetic was discovered independently Animal agency presumably evolved in
by many different cultures who nonetheless an amoral context and for amoral reasons.
found that the same calculations yielded the Animals evolved the ability to make choices
same answers. so as to survive and reproduce better. The
The question with morality is not what the origins of the central nervous system are in
rules are, because most societies largely agree locomotion and digestion, thus (to oversim-
on the rules. The question is why should one plify) to control moving around so as to eat
obey them. In particular, many moral rules (Ghysen, 2003).
boil down to restraining self-interest in favor Human free will is mostly a moral instru-
of doing what is good for the social group ment, that is, a set of cognitive capabilities
and system—but why should one not pur- related to behavior control that evolved to
sue self-interest, as nature designed brains to deal with moral issues so as to maintain a
do? Religion has at many times provided a good moral reputation, essential for attract-
 Free Will and Moral Psychology 335

ing others. The central themes of human In this view, the origins of what people
evolution are involved here, as recently elu- call free will are neither in random behav-
cidated by Tomasello (2014). Cooperation ior nor in rational choice, but in self-control:
with non-kin is quite rare in other primates, One has to inhibit the natural impulse to get
but it is central to human social life. Co- all that one can for oneself, so as instead to
operation creates vulnerability: One works share resources with others. To do that, one
with another, who may be tempted to be- has to use self-control, the “moral muscle”
tray the cooperation for his or her own ad- (Baumeister & Exline, 1999), so as to act
vantage. Most animals would betray. For in ways that others will respect as morally
example, if two creatures work together to virtuous.
chase prey, and one catches it, that one will Striking evidence of the interpersonal
consume the prey rather than sharing. This basis for moral behavior was provided by
is natural: The animal is hungry and it has Engelmann, Herrmann, and Tomasello
captured food, so of course the natural and (2012). They confronted adult chimpanzees
adaptive next action is to eat it. Advanced and 5-year-old human children with a be-
self-control is needed to resist that tempta- havioral dilemma that involved sharing and
tion. And why should it? The crucial answer stealing. Some confronted this alone, while
to that question is something only humans others did so in the presence of conspecif-
seem to understand. If you betray another’s ics. The chimpanzees’ moral behavior was
trust, then that other will not trust you next the same regardless of the presence of other
time. In a human society in which social in- chimps. Human children behaved more mor-
formation is shared (i.e., gossip), the one you ally when others were watching than when
betrayed will tell others, and they will not alone. Thus, by 5 years of age, human chil-
trust you either. You will not be able to get dren are concerned about their moral repu-
others to cooperate with you, and insofar as tation in a way that adult chimps are not.
survival depends on cooperation, you will be If free will evolved partly to serve moral
in mortal danger. In a cooperative society, purposes, then people would use the concept
your very survival depends on being able to of free will especially in connection with
overcome the natural impulse to betray the making moral judgments. Some evidence for
cooperative partner. This is key selection this was provided by Clark and colleagues
factor in the evolution of self-control, which (2014). Their work was based on Nietzsche’s
in turn is a major component of what people (1889/1954) somewhat flippant claim that
call free will. the concept of free will was invented as a
Hence we are descended from the hu- basis for condemning and punishing other
mans who mastered enough self-control to people for immoral actions. Clark et al.
overcome selfish temptations so as to coop- (2014) showed that people’s belief in free
erate. More broadly, as Tomasello (2014) will increased when they were exposed to
elaborates, successful humans had to be immoral misdeeds by other people. This
concerned about their moral reputation, at confirms the observation I made earlier in
least in the sense that they had to base their this essay: Moral judgments essentially as-
actions on getting others to perceive them as sert that the person should have acted dif-
trustworthy partners for cooperative acts. ferently. And that assumes that the person
My hypothesis is that the need to sustain could have done so, which is the essence of
a good reputation, so as to attract coopera- the Haggard et al. (2010) definition of free
tive partners, was the basis for the discovery will.
of morality. Early humans needed guidelines The literature on free will has been greatly
to know what would make them morally at- swayed, and in my view egregiously misled
tractive to others, not because of religion or (see also Mele, 2009), by the classic studies
idealism or whatever, but as a matter of sur- by Libet (1985, 2004). In those studies, par-
vival. Reciprocating favors, keeping prom- ticipants were told to make a random choice
ises, sharing, and other virtues reflect the of when to initiate a finger or wrist move-
discovery that such patterns of behavior will ment, and to note the exact time on a clock
ensure future opportunities for cooperation. that registered milliseconds. The findings in-
336 M O R A L I T Y A N D B E L I E F S

dicated that brain activity commenced prior relationship, the more that belief in free will
to when people recorded that they had made increased forgiveness. Belief in free will led
the decision. to harsh condemnation mainly when there
Libet’s findings can be useful and thought- was no close relationship.
provoking in some contexts, but they have All of this fits perfectly with the idea of
nothing to do with free will. One key reason free will as a moral agency that evolved for
is that choosing randomly to make a mean- human moral culture. With strangers and
ingless response is totally divorced from the hypothetical persons, one’s interest is to pro-
natural, evolved function of human agency. mote moral behavior so as to maintain the
In fact, the instructions to participants in social system’s ability to function smoothly
the study specified that they should not plan and effectively. Morality only works if most
when to make the movement—thereby re- of the people respect its rules most of the
moving the last possible vestige of anything time, and the more uniformly people con-
that free will would be useful for. form to moral rules, the better the system
Free will evolved in part (and a big part) works for everyone, because trust and coop-
to enable people to make moral choices. Li- eration are facilitated. As Clark et al. (2014)
bet’s procedures were thoroughly stripped showed, belief in free will is motivated by
of any moral aspect. I am not surprised that the wish to uphold the social rules by pun-
brain activity preceded the recollection of ishing people who break them.
conscious “decision,” not that that means With a close relationship partner, how-
all that much. (Indeed, if we assume that ever, one’s interest is in maintaining the
all conscious thought is the result of brain relationship. It is therefore more important
processes, then brain activity would always to forgive the person so that the relation-
precede a conscious thought.) I hypothesize ship can continue. Crucially, too, one wants
that conscious thought about moral choices to believe that the partner can change. The
would yield brain patterns quite different purpose of moral condemnation of a partner
from those associated with the decision to is not to affirm abstract rules for society in
make a meaningless finger movement.2 Neu- general (as in the stranger judgments), but,
roscientists interested in morality should rather, it is to convince the partner to change
start there. so as to facilitate a good relationship (again,
Forgiveness offers another sphere in with trust and cooperation).
which to investigate and elucidate the moral To conclude: Moral psychology and free
aspects of free will. Shariff et al. (2014) will theory have much to offer each other,
showed that people who disbelieved in free and indeed neither really works without the
will recommended more lenient sentences other. Moral judgment assumes that the
to hypothetical criminals than believers person could act otherwise in that situation
did. They also condemned people who had (and perhaps should have). Free will evolved
transgressed against them personally less, in to enable people to make moral choices, not
autobiographical data. These findings seem random ones. Societies have promoted belief
to suggest that belief in free will reduces in free will because that belief enables them
forgiveness. If people do not have free will to function better.
and their behavior is determined, it seems
unfair to punish them for their misdeeds to
the same extent as if they had freely chosen NOTES
to misbehave.
However, other evidence suggests that 1. And perhaps because the god will kick your
within close relationships, the opposite pat- ass if you disobey his rules.
2. To be sure, there are automatic moral re-
tern is found: Belief in free will leads to more sponses, especially in well-socialized humans.
forgiveness (for review, see Baumeister & Humans are willing to try trusting and coop-
Brewer, 2012). A follow-up analysis on the eration. Conscious thought might come into
Shariff et al. (2014) data revealed that be- play when one is offered a cooperative part-
lief in free will interacted with relationship nership by someone who has betrayed others
closeness to determine blame. The closer the in the past.
 Free Will and Moral Psychology 337

REFERENCES Haggard, P., Mele, A., O’Connor, T., & Vohs,


K. (2010). Lexicon of key terms. Available
Baumeister, R. F. (2008). Free will in scientific at www.freewillandscience.com/wp/?page_
psychology. Perspectives on Psychological Sci- id=63.
ence, 3, 14–19. Libet, B. (1985). Unconscious cerebral initia-
Baumeister, R. F., & Brewer, L. E. (2012). Believ- tive and the role of conscious will in volun-
ing versus disbelieving in free will: Correlates tary action. Behavior and Brain Sciences, 8,
and consequences. Personality and Social Psy- 529–566.
chology Compass, 6(10), 736–745. Libet, B. (2004). Mind time: The temporal factor
Baumeister, R. F., & Exline, J. (1999). Virtue, in consciousness. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
personality, and social relations: Self-control University Press.
as the moral muscle. Journal of Personality, MacIntyre, A. (1981). After virtue. Notre Dame,
67, 1165–1194. IN: Notre Dame University Press.
Baumeister, R. F., & Monroe, A. E. (2014). Re- Mele, A. R. (2009). Effective intentions: The
cent research on free will: Conceptualizations, power of conscious will. New York: Oxford
beliefs, and processes. Advances in Experi- University Press.
mental Social Psychology, 50, 1–52. Montague, R. P. (2008). Free will. Current Biol-
Brembs, B. (2010). Towards a scientific concept ogy, 18, R584–R585.
of free will as a biological trait: Spontaneous Nietzsche, F. (1954). Twilight of the idols (W.
actions and decision-making in invertebrates. Kaufmann, Trans.). New York: Penguin
Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Books. (Original work published 1889)
Sciences. Available at http://rspb.royalsoci- Norenzayan, A., Shariff, A. F., Gervais, W. M.,
etypublishing.org/content/early/2010/12/14/ Willard, A. K., McNamara, R. A., Slinger-
rspb.2010.2325. land, E., & Henrich, J. (2014). The cultural
Clark, C. J., Luguri, J. B., Ditto, P. H., Knobe, evolution of prosocial religions. Behavioral
J., Shariff, A. F., & Baumeister, R. F. (2014). and Brain Sciences. Available at www2.psych.
Free to punish: A motivated account of free ubc.ca/~ara/Manuscripts/2016%20Noren-
will belief. Journal of Personality and Social zayan%20cultural%20evolution.pdf.
Psychology, 106, 501–513. Shariff, A. F., Greene, J. D., Karremans, J. C., Lu-
Engelmann, J. M., Herrmann, E., & Tomasello, guri, J., Clark, C. J., Schooler, J. W., . . . Vohs, K.
M. (2012). Five-year-olds, but not chimpan- D. (2014). Free will and punishment: A mecha-
zees, attempt to manage their reputations. nistic view of human nature reduces retribution.
PLOS ONE, 7, 1–7. Psychological Science, 25, 1563–1570.
Ghysen, A. (2003). The origin and evolution of Tomasello, M. (2014). The natural history of
the nervous system. International Journal of human thinking. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
Developmental Biology, 47, 555–562. University Press.
CH A P TER 35

The Geographies of Religious


and Nonreligious Morality

Brett Mercier
Azim Shariff

How do religious and secular institutions make us moral?

To encourage us to put group interest ahead of self-interest, religious


and secular institutions use related but distinct mechanisms which
activate our evolved sensitivity to reputational concerns.

Our Growing Moral Habitat Bender, 1995), laying the groundwork for


an agricultural revolution. Facing already
For the first 95% of its existence, Homo increasing population sizes and declining
sapiens’ moral habitat comfortably fit in a game availability (Barker, 2009), nomadic
small island. Our species shared some of this bands of hunter–gatherers began to settle
territory with other animals that, over time, into communities and multiply further. The
had evolved to cooperate with each other larger group sizes, division of labor, and
under a constrained set of circumstances. the expanded possibilities for accumulating
Human and nonhuman animals largely static and unequal wealth all represented a
overlapped in their reliance on kin selection dramatic shift in human lifestyles. The tra-
and direct reciprocity. As our species’ cog- ditional, evolved mechanisms of kin selec-
nitive and linguistic faculties developed, we tion and reciprocity could not on their own
expanded our moral territory to include new support these new circumstances and larger
lands containing reputation-based indirect population (Henrich, 2004). Thus the simple
reciprocity. But for hundreds of thousands resources of the moral habitat that humans
of years, our ancestors did not venture much had hitherto enjoyed for generations became
beyond this moral island. strained, and our species struck out to find
The beginning of the Neolithic epoch new moral territories.
kicked off a great age of moral exploration. Many brave moral explorers found them-
As the last ice age receded, the air became selves seduced by the fabled lost continent
more highly oxygenated (Jaccard, Galbraith, of genetic group selection. Theoretically, ge-
Froelicher, & Gruber, 2014), and a previ- netic group selection relies on certain evolu-
ously variable climate stabilized (Sowers & tionary conditions—including intense group

338
 The Geographies of Religious and Nonreligious Morality 339

competition with very limited genetic mix- they volunteer (Campbell & Yonish, 2003),
ing between those groups—that were absent participate in social change organizations
during the critical period of human history. (Guo, Webb, Abzug, & Peck, 2013), donate
But other explorers were more successful, blood (Brooks, 2003), and give money to
forging out west toward a vast supercon- religious charities, to nonreligious charities
tinental cluster called Culture. There they (Brooks, 2006; Wuthnow, 1999), and to
found two vast continents of moral territo- friends and family who are in need (Brooks,
ries, each relying on different sets of insti- 2003). Controlling for relevant factors such
tutions. Following North (1990), we define as age and income, religiosity is related to
institutions as rules or norms that attempt lower levels of self-reported criminal behav-
to govern human actions and the means by ior such as theft, property crimes, and drug
which these rules are enforced. On one con- use (Baier & Wright, 2001; Evans, Cullen,
tinent, Religionia, the institutions promot- Dunaway, & Burton, 1995). Although this
ing ethical behavior were built on beliefs, research suggests that religious institutions
teaching, and rituals rooted in supernatural contribute to prosocial behavior, it is based
assumptions. The other continent—Secular- only on individuals’ self-reports of their own
ia—was characterized by nonsupernatural behavior. To overcome this limitation, re-
secular institutions. This chapter explores searchers have measured prosocial behavior
and compares the geography of these two in laboratory experiments, such as economic
moral continents. games or artificially created opportunities
for helping. Unlike on self-report measures,
a meta-analysis of these studies revealed no
Religionia relationship between religion and prosocial
behavior (Kramer, Kelly, & Shariff, 2017).
In retrospect, Religionia seems like an obvi- Why not? One possibility is that religious
ous place where morality was to be found. In individuals overreport their level of proso-
fact, many—including Voltaire (1727/1977), ciality to present themselves in a positive
Dostoyevsky (1880/2014) and even George way. Consistent with this explanation, re-
Washington (Spalding & Garrity, 1996)— search has shown that religious individuals
have argued that religion represents a central are more likely to respond to questions in so-
and indispensable core of morality. Today, cially desirable ways (Sedikides & Gebauer,
this belief is still common. For the (slight) 2010). However, the discrepancy between
majority of Americans, one of the common the findings for self-report and behavioral
and core features of religions—the belief in measures of prosociality may also be par-
God—is a necessary precondition for being tially explained by situational factors. That
a moral person (Pew Research Center, 2014). is, religion may momentarily affect proso-
This number is even higher in other parts of cial behavior in ways that are not captured
the world, reaching 99% in such places as in the laboratory studies that use religion
Indonesia and Ghana. Though some coun- merely as an individual-difference vari-
tries, such as those in Western Europe, see able. In other words, the effect of religion
much smaller proportions, global intuitions on prosocial behavior may be explained by
about the connection between religion and certain features of the religious situation
morality are strong. But a scientifically in- rather than religious disposition. Instead of
formed understanding about what and simply relying on dispositional religiosity to
whether religion offered to our moral habi- encourage people toward prosocial behavior
tat has only come relatively recently. across all situations, one may better capture
Modern researchers have done much to religion’s prosocial effect by simulating the
map the geography of Religionia. Surveys in “religious situation” in the lab. In support
a number of different countries have found of this, a meta-analysis found that reminders
that the more religious an individual is, the of religious concepts, such as unscrambling
more he or she reports engaging in proso- words related to religious concepts (Shariff
cial behaviors (Koenig, McGue, Krueger, & Norenzayan, 2007), reading Bible verses
& Bouchard, 2007; Monsma, 2007; Smidt, (Carpenter & Marshall, 2009), or hearing
1999). Religious people are more likely to say the Muslim prayer call (Aveyard, 2014; Du-
340 M O R A L I T Y A N D B E L I E F S

haime, 2014), reliably make the religious— men, 2004) which left humans prone to be-
but not the nonreligious—behave more lief in supernatural watchers. The extreme
prosocially (Shariff, Willard, Andersen, & sensitivity to reputational concerns (itself the
Norenzayan, 2015). This increased pro- evolutionary product of a reciprocity-based
sociality in response to religious situations morality) made it easy for humans to begin
has been demonstrated in a variety of dif- acting as though these supernatural watch-
ferent domains, including increasing dona- ers could see if they were being naughty or
tions to charity (Malhotra, 2010), generosity nice.
(Shariff & Norenzayan, 2007), and honesty Several converging lines of evidence have
(Randolph-Seng & Nielsen, 2007) and de- isolated that it is the monitoring and puni-
creasing hypocrisy (Carpenter & Marshall, tive aspect agents that serves as the active
2009), cheating (Aveyard, 2014), and porn ingredient in encouraging normative behav-
consumption (Edelman, 2009). ior.
The connection between religion and mo- As group sizes increase, and the need for
rality, although tenuous in the infancy of cultural crutches for cooperation intensify,
religion, has grown stronger through the the gods grow larger and more moralis-
process of cultural evolution sifting through tic (Roes & Raymond, 2003; Watts et al.,
the varieties of religious experience that 2015). Situations that further exacerbate
emerged throughout the world. Through the need for cooperation—such as resource
the differential survival and transmission scarcity—are also associated with the pres-
of certain beliefs, teachings, and rituals, ence of more powerful monitoring deities
“winners” that proved mentally sticky and (Botero et al., 2014). For example, even after
socially useful have persisted. Those ideas controlling for relevant variables, the belief
that failed to catch on, be it through being in Hell—but not in Heaven—predicts lower
overly counterintuitive (such as the Order of crime rates and, in developing countries,
the Solar Temple, which mixed Christianity, stronger economic growth (Shariff & Rhem-
UFOs, New Age philosophy, and Freemason tulla, 2012; Barro & McCleary, 2003). In
rituals) or socially detrimental (such as uni- a multisite, cross-cultural study, Purzycki et
versal celibacy among the Shakers), were di- al. (2016) measured how adherents to a vari-
minished or extinguished altogether. ety of different religions living in several dif-
Thus the initial shores of Religionia of- ferent countries behaved in an anonymous
fered little in terms of habitable moral terri- resource allocation task. Controlling for a
tory, but nonetheless held a promise of better variety of different factors, such as econom-
lands. Anthropologists and archaeologists ic differences between countries, people who
have found that early religions and those still reported greater belief in gods that are mor-
practiced by small bands of foragers tend to alistic, knowledgeable, and punitive were
be nonmoralistic, with relatively small gods more fair and honest in their allocations to
with weak abilities (Boehm, 2008; Peoples, others.
Duda, & Marlowe, 2016; Roes & Ray- Lab studies have found similar conclu-
mond, 2003; Stark, 2001; Swanson, 1960). sions. For example, students who believed in
As the explorers pushed further inland, they a punitive God were less likely to cheat on
discovered more bountiful resources. The an academic task, and those who believed
emergence of specific religious beliefs—first, in a forgiving God were more likely to cheat
afterlife beliefs and later morally punitive su- (Shariff & Norenzayan, 2011). Recently, it
pernatural and monitoring agents (i.e. “high has been shown that priming the punitive
gods”)—proved particularly powerful in aspects of God increases prosocial inten-
galvanizing cooperation and rule following. tions, but God concepts stripped of their
The effectiveness of supernatural watching punitive elements have a much more cir-
and punishment relied on a number of exist- cumscribed effect (Yilmaz & Bahçekapili,
ing human adaptations, including a hyper- 2015). Meanwhile, limited research suggests
sensitivity to detecting agency (Barrett & that not only might the supernatural “car-
Johnson, 2003) and a bias toward seeing the rot” fail to evoke prosocial behavior, but it
world in terms of design and purpose (Kele- may actually compromise such behavior. Re-
 The Geographies of Religious and Nonreligious Morality 341

ligious participants asked to reflect on God’s itions about violence turned out to be accu-
forgiving nature were more likely to cheat rate. Periods of history in which there were
and steal than those in control conditions no forms of government to regulate behavior
(DeBono, Shariff, Poole, & Muraven, 2017). appear to have been as violent and chaotic
Part of what made the belief in punitive as Hobbes predicted they would be. Foren-
supernatural agents a particularly fruitful sic analysis of the remains of people living
area in our moral habitat was its linkages in societies without organized forms of gov-
to other aspects that made up the cultural ernment or religion, such as ancient hunter–
“packages” that we call religions. For ex- gatherers (Mithen, 1999), have indicated
ample, tying these agent beliefs to morally that even the most peaceful of these societies
dependent afterlife beliefs, to sets of rituals were much more violent than modern indus-
that deepened faith and communicate shared trialized societies (McCall & Shields, 2008;
beliefs, to sacred values that made violations See Figure 35.1).
a threat to meaning and identity, all en- However, as with Religionia, the coastal
hanced the power that the beliefs in punitive territory discovered by early explorers of
gods would have had on its own. Indeed, the Secularia was of limited value, and it took
religions of Religionia grew more effective the explorers a long time to reach the re-
by connecting vast areas of different terri- source-rich territory that is occupied by
tory, making those areas more than the sum modern states.
of their parts (see Shariff & Mercier, 2016, In early groups of hunter–gatherers, con-
for a more in-depth discussion of this point). flict resolution was generally left to the
parties involved. The human tendency for
revenge, particularly the desire to seek le-
Secularia thal retaliation in response to the death
of a relative, led these groups to have high
But Religionia was not the only new moral rates of killing and blood feuds between ge-
territory discovered by the intrepid human netically related groups (Boehm, 1984). In
explorers. Further north, humans found these largely egalitarian groups, the earliest
land that allowed them to layer their small- forms of third-party mediation consisted of
scale moralities with secular institutions. other members’ attempts to resolve a con-
Like those claiming that religion is neces- flict, such as by distracting the participants
sary for morality, many have argued that or, in serious cases, encouraging one of the
secular institutions are necessary to enforce parties to leave the group (Boehm, 2012).
cooperation—perhaps none so notably as After the agricultural revolution made this
the political philosopher Thomas Hobbes. type of mobility impractical, groups began
Hobbes (1651–1974) observed that people’s to give their leaders increasing authority to
interests often conflict with those of others, mediate disputes, which reduced revenge-
and, if not deterred by some outside force, based feuding (Ericksen & Horton, 1992).
people tend to resolve these conflicts though This increase in authority, which became he-
violence. To prevent these conflicts from reditary, combined with the development of
creating a state of perpetual violence, he ar- social stratification facilitated by the greater
gued that people should enter into a social potential for material wealth, laid the foun-
contract by which they cede their rights to dation for the development of early state
a powerful sovereign authority in exchange societies (Johnson & Earle, 2000). As these
for protection. This authority could punish state societies began to grow in size, they
those who use violence, reducing the incen- eventually developed military forces paid for
tive to use it as a means of resolving con- with taxation, giving them a much greater
flicts. And for Hobbes, this sovereign au- ability to enforce and monitor mediation de-
thority had to be secular, so it could apply to cisions (Boehm, 2012).
all members of society, not just the members To determine how effective these state so-
of a particular religion. cieties were at preventing violence, we can
Although he lacked the empirical evidence compare contemporaneous societies that
available to modern scholars, Hobbes’s intu- were at different points of state develop-
342
FIGURE 35.1.  War deaths per 100,000 people per year. From The Better Angels of Our Nature: Why Violence Has Declined, by Steven Pinker,
Copyright © 2011 by Steven Pinker. Used by permission of Viking Books, an imprint of Penguin Publishing group, a division of Penguin Ran-
dom House LLC. All rights reserved. Any third party use of this material, outside of this publication, is prohibited. Interested parties must
apply directly to Penguin Random House LLC for permission. Sources: Nonstate: Hewa and Goila from Gat, 2006; others from Keeley, 1996.
Central Mexico, Germany, Russia, France, Japan: Keeley, 1996. United States in the 20th Century: Leland and Oboroceanu, 2010. World in
20th century: White, 2011; World in 2005: Human Security Report Project, 2008. Reproduced by permission of Penguin Books Ltd.
 The Geographies of Religious and Nonreligious Morality 343

ment. Doing so indicates that, for a given party punishment for breaking laws increas-
moment in history, those societies that had es, so does the compliance with those laws
established state governments had signifi- (Cusson, 1993; Nagin & Paternoster, 1991;
cantly lower rates of violence (Steckel & Paternoster, 1987).
Rose, 2002). Likewise, when ungoverned As with religious institutions, the chal-
areas come under state control, they typical- lenges posed by large groups and limited
ly experience significant reductions in crime resources led societies to develop secular in-
and violence (Wiessner, 2010). stitutions, such as property rights, to deter
Although it took until the 16th century “free riding.” One problem groups face as
for Hobbes to write about the social con- they increase in size is referred to as the
tract, the earliest formal social contracts “tragedy of the commons” (Hardin, 1968).
can be traced back to the development of When a finite resource is shared or “com-
citizenship in ancient Greece. Citizenship mon” to a group of people, each individual
can be loosely defined as a contract between benefits from using the resource. However,
an individual and society in which the indi- the cost of depleting of the resource is shared
vidual provides services, such as taxes, mili- across the entire community, meaning each
tary service, or civic duties in exchange for individual’s gain from using the resource ex-
entitlement to specific rights and protections ceeds his or her depletion cost, and everyone
from a government (Isin & Turner, 2007). has an incentive to use the resource until it
In its earliest forms, such as in ancient Ath- is depleted. Although reputational concerns
ens, these protections basically consisted of can prevent this exploitation in small groups
a government-provided military force tasked (Milinski, Semmann, & Krambeck, 2002),
with maintaining order, whereas things like it is unlikely to do so in large groups, where
investigating crimes were left up to individ- peoples’ reputations are unknown or cannot
ual members of society (Hunter, 1994). The be remembered.
modern idea of a stand-alone government- Although ownership among early hunter–
sponsored police force designed to protect gatherers was restricted to things that could
and serve individual citizens did not emerge be easily transported, such as tools and
until the early 19th century, with the cre- weapons, the development of agriculture
ation of the Metropolitan Police Service in provided a means of signaling unambiguous
London (Monkkonen, 1992). The success of possession of land, facilitating the extension
this force led it to be emulated throughout of ownership to territory (Krier, 2009). Indi-
the world (Emsley, 2014). vidual ownership of land worked as a deter-
Third-party mediation in secular institu- rent to the free riding that occurs in commu-
tions—which includes the surveillance, ap- nal agriculture, in which individuals have
prehension, judgment, and punishment of an incentive to reap more than their fair
codified normative transgressions—contin- share of a combined harvest. One solution
ues to be an important aspect in promot- to Hardin’s (1968) tragedy of the commons
ing cooperation today. Studies have shown is to carve the commons up and give people
that increases in the number of police in dominion over a slice. Thus the concept of
a society decreases the amount of crime property, defined as a claim of possession
(Levitt, 2002; Skogan & Frydl, 2004), as enforced by the state, gained traction (Pipes,
do increases in other methods of surveil- 2007). In addition to deterring free riding
lance: cameras that reduce auto theft and and the overuse of resources, enforcement
shootings (Caplan, Kennedy, & Petrossian, of property rights encourages exchange and
2011; Ratcliffe, Taniguchi, & Taylor, 2009), investment (Demsetz, 1967; North, 1990),
photo radar that decreases rates of speed- making enforcement of property rights
ing (Bloch, 1998; Chen, Wilson, Meckle, & one of the most important determinants of
Cooper, 2000), and random breath tests and economic growth (Knack & Keefer, 1995).
increased surveillance that reduce rates of Indeed, Ferguson (2011) argues that well-
drinking and driving (Homel, Carseldine, & enforced and widespread property rights
Kearns, 1988; Ross, 1984). Overall, as the played a central role in the rise of the United
perceived certainty and magnitude of third- States as an economic superpower, whereas
344
FIGURE 35.2.  Religious importance (World Values Survey, 2014) and the rule of law index (Kaufmann, Kraay, & Mastruzzi, 2011) by country.
 The Geographies of Religious and Nonreligious Morality 345

similar societies without widespread proper- Comparing the Continents


ty rights, such as nations in South America,
struggled. We should not belabor the metaphor of sep-
However, not all common resources can arate continents too much. In truth, there is
be divided into pieces. When common pool much trade on the isthmus between the con-
resources were difficult or impossible to tinents; many societies experienced much
privatize, many societies developed institu- overlap and interaction between these two
tions that restricted the use of these resources different moral institutions. A good example
to prevent depletion (Ostrom, 1990). These is the monogamous marriage norm. This was
types of institutions have successfully regu- a moral norm (aimed particularly at those
lated the use of a diverse range of common powerful men who had the option of violat-
resources, including common pasture for ing it) that spread because of Christianity
farm animals (Netting, 1981), forestry land but succeeded because it offered societies a
(McKean, 1992), and access to water (Saleth way to reduce violent competition between
& Dinar, 2004). In contrast, there are a males within the group (Henrich, Boyd &
number of cases in which failure to establish Richerson, 2012). Though the origins of the
an institution to regulate a common resource norm were rooted in religious institutions,
led to depletion: Beaver stocks during the fur the norm became legally codified by secular
trade (Berkes, 1999) and whale stocks dur- governments to the point where a religion
ing the nineteenth century (Davis, Gallman, without it—Mormonism—was forced by
& Gleiter, 2007) are just two examples. the local secular institutions to adopt it.
Finally, an important step in the evolution That all said, secular and religious mo-
of secular institutions was the development ralities have often operated in a hydraulic
of “the rule of law,” under which all individ- fashion: More of one meant less of the other.
uals in a society—including the lawmakers Countries that have a higher quality of secu-
and leaders—are subject to the same, stable lar institutions (as measured by level of eco-
code of laws (in contrast to systems in which nomic development) tend to have citizens
certain authorities are exempt from the law, who are less religious (McCleary & Barro,
such as a dictatorship). By preventing rulers 2006). Similarly, the stronger the rule of law
from abusing their power, the rule of law is in a country, the smaller is the share of
has been shown to increase human rights individuals saying that religion is an impor-
protections (Cross, 1999) and to lower levels tant part of their life (Berggren & Bjørns-
of government corruption (Kimbro, 2002). kov, 2013; See Figure 35.2).
The rule of law is also valuable because it This hydraulic relationship occurs with
signals that the rules are predictable, consis- institutions promoting financial security as
tent, and fairly applied, and thus worth fol- well; the better a country’s social safety net,
lowing (North, 1990). Research has found the less religious individuals in that coun-
that for individuals who have had contact try tend to be (Inglehart & Norris, 2004).
with the legal system, judgments about the When trust in the government is threatened,
fairness of the decision process and about such as during periods of political instabil-
the motives of authorities were the best ity, commitment to religion increases, and
predictors of people’s willingness to accept when belief in God’s control over the world
the decision made, regardless of the type of is threatened, people desire a more con-
contact or the legal authority involved (Tyler trolling government (Kay, Shepherd, Blatz,
& Huo, 2002). Other research on media- Chua, & Galinsky, 2010).
tion has found that the more people perceive There are also a number of key differ-
mediation processes to be fair, the more ences separating the two continents. When
likely they are to comply with the outcome rules are perceived to be established and
of mediation (Pruitt, Peirce, McGillicuddy, enforced by divine commandment, they
Welton, & Castrianno, 1993). Overall, the tend to be seen as more sacred and invio-
extent to which people perceive that laws lable than rules based on nonreligious roots
are being fairly applied to everyone is the (Piazza & Landy, 2013). For example, non-
best predictor of compliance with those laws religious people are more willing than the
(Tyler, 2003). religious to violate a moral rule when doing
346 M O R A L I T Y A N D B E L I E F S

so leads to a positive outcome, such as kill- ence and insensitive to outcomes, can be a
ing one person to save several others (Sze- valuable resource in intergroup conflict. In
kely, Opre, & Miu, 2015). When asked why a historical analysis of asymmetric conflicts,
moral violations are wrong, religious peo- Mack (1975) argues that resolve is an impor-
ple are more likely to endorse rule-based tant factor that has often allowed a weaker
explanations (e.g. “Infidelity is wrong”), power to defeat an otherwise much stronger
while the nonreligious are more likely to adversary. In line with this finding, research-
endorse consequence-based explanations ers have argued that sacred values have given
(e.g. “Infidelity could hurt one’s partner groups such as the Islamic State the resolve
if they find out”; Piazza, 2012). Similarly, to overcome numerous opponents with or-
feelings of compassion tend to have a stron- ders of magnitude more military personnel
ger influence on the moral decisions of the and weaponry (Atran, Sheikh, & Gomez,
nonreligious than the religious (Saslow et 2014).
al., 2013). Thus, whereas the religious tend Viewing rules as the sacred result of di-
to make “deontological” moral decisions vine commands can also be a powerful mo-
based on whether or not a given action tivation to adhere to them. In support of
violates a moral rule, the nonreligious are this idea, people who view rules in a deon-
more likely to make “utilitarian” decisions tological way are less likely to violate these
based on a consideration of the consequenc- rules (Xu & Ma, 2015). Other research has
es of particular actions. found that priming people to think about
Religious rules also are more likely to be morality as objective increases donations to
considered “sacred values” (Sheikh, Ginges, charity (Young & Durwin, 2013), whereas
Coman, & Atran, 2012), meaning they are priming people to think about morality as
believed to possess “transcendental signifi- subjective increases cheating (Rai & Holy-
cance that precludes comparisons, trade- oak, 2013).
offs, or indeed any mingling with secular Although sacred values can be valuable in
values” (Tetlock, Kristel, Elson, Green, & intergroup conflicts, they can also present
Lerner, 2000, p. 853). Individuals who hold a significant barrier to conflict resolution.
sacred values consider it wrong to even con- As the intractability of the Jewish–­Palestine
sider trading sacred values for material in- conflict can attest, when two different
centives, and offers to do so often backfire groups hold conflicting, nonnegotiable sa-
by increasing commitment to a sacred value cred values, disagreements can be very dif-
(Tetlock et al., 2000). For example, one study ficult to resolve.
presented individuals involved in the Israeli– Religious and secular institutions also
Palestinian conflict with a potential peace differ in the scope of their application. As
deal involving the exchange of sacred values discussed earlier, religious situations only
(e.g., land for peace). Although individu- make the religious more prosocial, suggest-
als generally did not support the deal, add- ing that Hobbes was correct in his criticism
ing an additional financial incentive (in the that religious institutions would not apply
form of $1 billion in reparations) increased to everyone. Currently there are estimated
moral outrage and support for violent op- 750 million nonbelievers worldwide (Zuck-
position to the deal (Ginges, Atran, Medin, erman, 2007) and the proportion of nonbe-
& Shikaki, 2007). Other research has dem- lievers in almost all industrialized nations
onstrated that Palestinians who view issues has been steadily increasing over the last
in the Israeli–Palestinian conflict as sacred century (Voas, 2008). This nonuniversal ap-
were more resistant to social influence on plication of religious institutions represents
these issues and were less likely to consider a significant limitation to their ability to en-
opportunities to exit the conflict (Sheikh, force cooperation.
Ginges, & Atran, 2013). Similarly, among Secular institutions, on the other hand,
Jewish residents of the West Bank, support cannot be ignored through disbelief. When
for violent action against Palestinians is un- governments pass laws, they apply to all
related to the perceived effectiveness of that members of society, even those who disagree
action (Ginges & Atran, 2011). This type with them. In a demonstration of this, one
of resolve, which is immune to social influ- study found that, although religious primes
 The Geographies of Religious and Nonreligious Morality 347

only made the religious more prosocial, sec- REFERENCES


ular primes increased prosociality among
both the religious and the nonreligious Ashton, P., Petteruti, A., & Walsh, N. (2012).
(Shariff & Norenzayan, 2007). Rethinking the blues: How we police in the
U.S. and at what cost. Washington, DC: Jus-
The universal applicability of secular in-
tice Policy Institute.
stitutions also comes at a significant cost. Atran, S., Sheikh, H., & Gomez, A. (2014). De-
For example, the United States alone spends voted actors sacrifice for close comrades and
an estimated $100 billion per year on law sacred cause. Proceedings of the National
enforcement (Ashton, Petteruti, & Walsh, Academy of Sciences of the USA, 111(50),
2012). While relying on supernatural en- 17702–17703.
forcement is not entirely cost-free—the nec- Aveyard, M. E. (2014). A call to honesty: Ex-
essary demonstrations of commitment to re- tending religious priming of moral behavior to
ligions are often quite costly—having one’s Middle Eastern Muslims. PLOS ONE, 9(7),
transgressions deterred by an invisible om- e99447.
niscient agent can be substantially cheaper Baier, C. J., & Wright, B. R. (2001). “If you love
me, keep my commandments”: A meta-analy-
than the secular alternative.
sis of the effect of religion on crime. Journal
of Research in Crime and Delinquency, 38(1),
3–21.
Charting the Course Forward Barker, G. (2009). The agricultural revolution in
prehistory: Why did foragers become farmers?
Compelling research has recently shown New York: Oxford University Press.
how religiosity’s long-known salutary ef- Barrett, J. L., & Johnson, A. H. (2003). The role
fects on health and happiness are moderated of control in attributing intentional agency to
by country-level features. In places where inanimate objects. Journal of Cognition and
life is difficult, religion is positively asso- Culture, 3(3), 208–217.
ciated with both happiness and longevity. Barro, R. J., & McCleary, R. (2003). Religion
and economic growth (Working Paper No.
But in places where life is easier and where 9682). Cambridge, MA: National Bureau of
religion is less of a social norm, the effect Economic Research. Available at www.nber.
is flat. Though the data do not yet exist, org/papers/w9682.pdf.
something similar may exist for the relation- Berggren, N., & Bjørnskov, C. (2013). Does re-
ship between religion and morality. Religion ligiosity promote property rights and the rule
may serve a critical function for encourag- of law? Journal of Institutional Economics,
ing norm-following in less developed parts 9(02), 161–185.
of the world. In places where secular insti- Berkes, F. (1999). Sacred ecology: Traditional
tutions have been sufficiently built, they ecological knowledge and resource manage-
may do sufficient moral work as to render ment. Philadelphia: Taylor & Francis.
the religion morally unnecessary. In a way, Bloch, S. (1998). Comparative study of speed
reduction effects of photo-radar and speed
this would complete the life cycle arc of display boards. Transportation Research Re-
Religionia. Religious institutions began by cord: Journal of the Transportation Research
providing groups with valuable advantages Board, 1640, 27–36.
at a time when secular institutions were un- Boehm, C. (1984). Blood revenge: The enact-
able to do so, facilitating the development of ment and management of conflict in Mon-
large-scale societies. However, as these soci- tenegro and other tribal societies. Lawrence:
eties develop secular institutions capable of University Press of Kansas.
effectively enforcing cooperation without re- Boehm, C. (2008). Purposive social selection and
ligion, religion—especially the parts of reli- the evolution of human altruism. Cross-Cul-
gion like supernatural punishment that may tural Research, 42(4), 319–352.
exist for the primary purpose of enforcing Boehm, C. (2012). Ancestral hierarchy and con-
flict. Science, 336(6083), 844–847.
cooperation—may become less prevalent. Botero, C. A., Gardner, B., Kirby, K. R., Bulbu-
Whether the next step in our species’ moral lia, J., Gavin, M. C., & Gray, R. D. (2014).
journey is to vacate Religionia entirely, to The ecology of religious beliefs. Proceedings
settle in the more fertile lands up North, re- of the National Academy of Sciences of the
mains a matter of open, heated, and conse- USA, 111(47), 16784–16789.
quential debate. Brooks, A. C. (2003). Religious faith and chari-
348 M O R A L I T Y A N D B E L I E F S

table giving. Policy Review, 121. Available feuds”: Cross-cultural variations in kin group
at www.hoover.org/research/religious-faith- vengeance. Cross-Cultural Research, 26(1–4),
and-charitable-giving. 57–85.
Brooks, A. C. (2006). Who really cares: The sur- Evans, T. D., Cullen, F. T., Dunaway, R. G., &
prising truth about compassionate conserva- Burton, V. S. (1995). Religion and crime reex-
tism—America’s charity divide—who gives, amined: The impact of religion, secular con-
who doesn’t, and why it matters. New York: trols, and social ecology on adult criminality.
Basic Books. Criminology, 33(2), 195–224.
Campbell, D. E., & Yonish, S. J. (2003). Reli- Ferguson, N. (2011). Civilization: The West and
gion and volunteering in America. In C. Smidt the rest. New York: Penguin Group.
(Ed.), Religion as social capital: Producing the Gat, A. (2006). War in human civilization. New
common good (pp. 87–106). Waco, TX: Bay- York: Oxford University Press.
lor University Press. Ginges, J., & Atran, S. (2011). War as a moral
Caplan, J. M., Kennedy, L. W., & Petrossian, imperative (not just practical politics by other
G. (2011). Police-monitored CCTV cameras means). Proceedings of the Royal Society of
in Newark, NJ: A quasi-experimental test of London: B. Biological Sciences, 278(1720),
crime deterrence. Journal of Experimental 2930–2938.
Criminology, 7(3), 255–274. Ginges, J., Atran, S., Medin, D., & Shikaki, K.
Carpenter, T. P., & Marshall, M. A. (2009). An (2007). Sacred bounds on rational resolution
examination of religious priming and intrin- of violent political conflict. Proceedings of the
sic religious motivation in the moral hypocrisy National Academy of Sciences of the USA,
paradigm. Journal for the Scientific Study of 104(18), 7357–7360.
Religion, 48(2), 386–393. Guo, C., Webb, N. J., Abzug, R., & Peck, L. R.
Chen, G., Wilson, J., Meckle, W., & Cooper, P. (2013). Religious affiliation, religious atten-
(2000). Evaluation of photo radar program in dance, and participation in social change or-
British Columbia. Accident Analysis and Pre- ganizations. Nonprofit and Voluntary Sector
vention, 32(4), 517–526. Quarterly, 42(1), 34–58.
Cross, F. B. (1999). The relevance of law in Hardin, G. (1968). The tragedy of the commons.
human rights protection. International Re- Science, 162, 1243–1248
view of Law and Economics, 19(1), 87–98. Henrich, J. (2004). Cultural group selection, co-
Cusson, M. (1993). Situational deterrence: Fear evolutionary processes and large-scale coop-
during the criminal event. Crime Prevention eration. Journal of Economic Behavior and
Studies, 1, 55–68. Organization, 53(1), 3–35.
Davis, L. E., Gallman, R. E., & Gleiter, K. Henrich, J., Boyd, R., & Richerson, P. J. (2012).
(2007). In pursuit of Leviathan: Technol- The puzzle of monogamous marriage. Philo-
ogy, institutions, productivity, and profits in sophical Transactions of the Royal Society: B.
American whaling, 1816–1906. Chicago: Uni- Biological Sciences, 367(1589), 657–669.
versity of Chicago Press. Hobbes, T. (1974). Leviathan. New York: Pen-
DeBono, A., Shariff, A., Poole, S., & Muraven, guin. (Original work published 1651)
M. (in press). Forgive us our trespasses: Prim- Homel, R., Carseldine, D., & Kearns, I. (1988).
ing a forgiving (but not a punishing) God in- Drink-driving countermeasures in Australia.
creases unethical behavior. Psychology of Re- Alcohol, Drugs, and Driving, 4(2), 113–144.
ligion and Spirituality. Human Security Report Project. (2008). Min-
Demsetz, H. (1967). Toward a theory of prop- iatlas of human security. Washington, DC:
erty rights. American Economic Review, 57, World Bank.
347–358. Hunter, V. J. (1994). Policing Athens: Social con-
Dostoyevsky, F. (2014). The brothers Karamazov trol in the Attic lawsuits, 420–320 b .c . Princ-
(C. Garnett, Trans.). New York: Lowell Press. eton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
(Original work published 1880) Inglehart, R., & Norris, P. (2004). Sacred and
Duhaime, E. (2014). Did religion facilitate the secular: Religion and politics worldwide.
evolution of large-scale cooperative societ- Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
ies? Unpublished master’s thesis, University of Isin, E. F., & Turner, B. S. (2007). Investigating
Cambridge, Cambridge, UK. citizenship: An agenda for citizenship studies.
Edelman, B. (2009). Markets: Red light states: Citizenship Studies, 11(1), 5–17.
Who buys online adult entertainment? Journal Jaccard, S. L., Galbraith, E. D., Froelicher, T. L.,
of Economic Perspectives, 23(1), 209–220. & Gruber, N. (2014). Ocean (de)oxygenation
Emsley, C. (2014). The English police: A political across the last deglaciation. Oceanography,
and social history. New York: Routledge. 27(2), 26–35.
Ericksen, K. P., & Horton, H. (1992). “Blood Johnson, A. W., & Earle, T. K. (2000). The
 The Geographies of Religious and Nonreligious Morality 349

evolution of human societies: From foraging McCall, G. S., & Shields, N. (2008). Examin-
group to agrarian state. Stanford, CA: Stan- ing the evidence from small-scale societies and
ford University Press. early prehistory and implications for modern
Kaufmann, D., Kraay, A., & Mastruzzi, M. theories of aggression and violence. Aggres-
(2011). The worldwide governance indicators: sion and Violent Behavior, 13(1), 1–9.
Methodology and analytical issues. Hague McCleary, R. M., & Barro, R. J. (2006). Reli-
Journal on the Rule of Law, 3(2), 220–246. gion and economy. Journal of Economic Per-
Kay, A. C., Shepherd, S., Blatz, C. W., Chua, spectives, 20(2), 49–72.
S. N., & Galinsky, A. D. (2010). For God McKean, M. A. (1992). Success on the commons:
(or) country: The hydraulic relation between A comparative examination of institutions
government instability and belief in religious for common property resource management.
sources of control. Journal of Personality and Journal of Theoretical Politics, 4(3), 247–281.
Social Psychology, 99(5), 725–739. Milinski, M., Semmann, D., & Krambeck, H. J.
Keeley, L. H. (1996). War before civilization: (2002). Reputation helps solve the “tragedy of
The myth of the peaceful savage. New York: the commons.” Nature, 415(6870), 424–426.
Oxford University Press. Mithen, S. (1999). Symbolism and the supernat-
Kelemen, D. (2004). Are children “intuitive ural. In R. Dunbar, C. Knight, & C. Power
theists”? Reasoning about purpose and de-
­ (Eds.), The evolution of culture: A historical
sign in nature. Psychological Science, 15(5), and scientific overview (pp. 147–171). New
295–301. Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press.
Kimbro, M. B. (2002). A cross-country empirical Monkkonen, E. H. (1992). History of urban po-
investigation of corruption and its relationship lice. Crime and Justice, 15, 547–580.
to economic, cultural, and monitoring institu- Monsma, S. V. (2007). Religion and philanthrop-
tions: An examination of the role of account- ic giving and volunteering: Building blocks for
ing and financial statements quality. Journal civic responsibility. Interdisciplinary Journal
of Accounting, Auditing and Finance, 17(4), of Research on Religion, 3, 2–28.
325–350. Nagin, D. S., & Paternoster, R. (1991). Preven-
Knack, S., & Keefer, P. (1995). Institutions and tive effects of the perceived risk of arrest: Test-
economic performance: Cross-country tests ing an expanded conception of deterrence.
using alternative institutional measures. Eco- Criminology, 29, 561–587.
nomics and Politics, 7(3), 207–227. Netting, R. M. (1981). Balancing on an Alp:
Koenig, L. B., McGue, M., Krueger, R. F., & Ecological change and continuity in a Swiss
Bouchard, T. J. (2007). Religiousness, antiso- mountain community. Cambridge, UK: Cam-
cial behavior, and altruism: Genetic and envi- bridge University Press
ronmental mediation. Journal of Personality, North, D. C. (1990). Institutions, institutional
75(2), 265–290. change and economic performance. Cam-
Kramer, S. R., Kelly, J., & Shariff, A. F. (2017). bridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Religious prosociality: A meta-analysis. Man- Ostrom, E. (1990). Governing the commons.
uscript in preparation. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Krier, J. E. (2009). Evolutionary theory and the Paternoster, R. (1987). The deterrent effect of
origin of property rights. Cornell Law Re- the perceived certainty and severity of punish-
view, 95, 139–160. ment: A review of the evidence and issues. Jus-
Leland, A., & Oboroceanu, M. J. (2010). Ameri- tice Quarterly, 4(2), 173–217.
can war and military operations casualties: Peoples, H. C., Duda, P., & Marlowe, F. W.
Lists and statistics. Washington, DC: Con- (2016). Hunter-gatherers and the origins of re-
gressional Research Service. Retrieved from: ligion. Human Nature, 27, 261–282.
http://fpc.state.gov/documents/organiza- Pew Research Center. (2014). Worldwide,
tion/139347.pdf. many see belief in God as essential to mo-
Levitt, S. D. (2002). Using electoral cycles in po- rality. Retrieved from www.pewglobal.
lice hiring to estimate the effects of police on org/2014/03/13/worldwide-many-see-belief-
crime: Reply. American Economic Review, in-god-as-essential-to-morality.
92(4), 1244–1250. Piazza, J. (2012). “If you love me keep my com-
Mack, A. (1975). Why big nations lose small mandments”: Religiosity increases preference
wars: The politics of asymmetric conflict. for rule-based moral arguments. International
World Politics, 27(2), 175–200. Journal for the Psychology of Religion, 22(4),
Malhotra, D. (2010). (When) are religious people 285–302.
nicer?: Religious salience and the “Sunday ef- Piazza, J., & Landy, J. F. (2013). “Lean not on
fect” on pro-social behavior. Judgment and your own understanding”: Belief that morality
Decision Making, 5, 138–143. is founded on divine authority and non-util-
350 M O R A L I T Y A N D B E L I E F S

itarian moral thinking. Judgment and Deci- gods make good people: Different views of
sion Making, 8(6), 639–661. God predict cheating behavior. International
Pinker, S. (2011). The better angels of our na- Journal for the Psychology of Religion, 21(2),
ture: The decline of violence in history and its 85–96.
causes. London, UK: Penguin. Shariff, A. F., & Rhemtulla, M. (2012). Diver-
Pipes, R. (2007). Property and freedom. New gent effects of beliefs in heaven and hell on na-
York: Vintage. tional crime rates. PLOS ONE, 7(6), e39048.
Pruitt, D. G., Peirce, R. S., McGillicuddy, N. B., Shariff, A. F., Willard, A. K., Andersen, T., &
Welton, G. L., & Castrianno, L. M. (1993). Norenzayan, A. (2015). Religious priming:
Long-term success in mediation. Law and A meta-analysis with a focus on prosociality.
Human Behavior, 17(3), 313–330. Personality and Social Psychology Review,
Purzycki, B. G., Apicella, C., Atkinson, Q. D., 20, 27–48.
Cohen, E., McNamara, R. A., Willard, A. Sheikh, H., Ginges, J., & Atran, S. (2013). Sa-
K., . . . Henrich, J. (2016). Moralistic gods, cred values in the Israeli–Palestinian conflict:
supernatural punishment and the expansion of Resistance to social influence, temporal dis-
human sociality. Nature, 530, 327–330. counting, and exit strategies. Annals of the
Rai, T. S., & Holyoak, K. J. (2013). Exposure to New York Academy of Sciences, 1299(1),
moral relativism compromises moral behavior. 11–24.
Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, Sheikh, H., Ginges, J., Coman, A., & Atran, S.
49(6), 995–1001. (2012). Religion, group threat and sacred val-
Randolph-Seng, B., & Nielsen, M. E. (2007). ues. Judgment and Decision Making, 7(2),
Honesty: One effect of primed religious repre- 110–118.
sentations. International Journal for the Psy- Skogan, W., & Frydl, K. (Eds.). (2004). Fairness
chology of Religion, 17(4), 303–315. and effectiveness in policing: The evidence.
Ratcliffe, J. H., Taniguchi, T., & Taylor, R. B. Washington, DC: National Academies Press.
(2009). The crime reduction effects of public Smidt, C. (1999). Religion and civic engagement:
CCTV cameras: A multi-method spatial ap- A comparative analysis. Annals of the Ameri-
proach. Justice Quarterly, 26(4), 746–770. can Academy of Political and Social Science,
Roes, F. L., & Raymond, M. (2003). Belief in 565(1), 176–192.
moralizing gods. Evolution and Human Be- Sowers, T., & Bender, M. (1995). Climate re-
havior, 24(2), 126–135. cords covering the last deglaciation. Science,
Ross, H. L. (1984). Social control through de- 269(5221), 210.
terrence: Drinking-and-driving laws. Annual Spalding, M., & Garrity, P. J. (1996). A sacred
Review of Sociology, 10(1), 21–35. union of citizens: George Washington’s Fare-
Saleth, R. M., & Dinar, A. (2004). The institu- well Address and the American character.
tional economics of water: A cross-country Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
analysis of institutions and performance. Stark, R. (2001) Gods, rituals, and the moral
Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar. order. Journal for the Scientific Study of Reli-
Saslow, L. R., Willer, R., Feinberg, M., Piff, P. gion, 40, 619–636.
K., Clark, K., Keltner, D., & Saturn, S. R. Steckel, R. H., & Rose, J. C. (2002). The back-
(2013). My brother’s keeper?: Compassion bone of history: Health and nutrition in the
predicts generosity more among less religious Western hemisphere. Cambridge, UK: Cam-
individuals. Social Psychological and Person- bridge University Press.
ality Science, 4(1), 31–38. Swanson, G. E. (1960). The birth of the gods:
Sedikides, C., & Gebauer, J. E. (2010). Religiosi- The origin of primitive beliefs. Ann Arbor:
ty as self-enhancement: A meta-analysis of the University of Michigan Press.
relation between socially desirable responding Szekely, R. D., Opre, A., & Miu, A. C. (2015).
and religiosity. Personality and Social Psy- Religiosity enhances emotion and deontologi-
chology Review, 14, 17–36. cal choice in moral dilemmas. Personality and
Shariff, A. F., & Mercier, B. (2016). The evolu- Individual Differences, 79, 104–109.
tion of religion and morality. In J. R. Liddle Tetlock, P. E., Kristel, O. V., Elson, S. B., Green,
& T. K. Shackelford (Eds.), The Oxford hand- M. C., & Lerner, J. S. (2000). The psychology
book of evolutionary psychology and religion. of the unthinkable: Taboo trade-offs, forbid-
New York: Oxford University Press. den base rates, and heretical counterfactuals.
Shariff, A. F., & Norenzayan, A. (2007). God is Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
watching you: Priming God concepts increases 78(5), 853–870.
prosocial behavior in an anonymous economic Tyler, T. R. (2003). Procedural justice, legiti-
game. Psychological Science, 18(9), 803–809. macy, and the effective rule of law. Crime and
Shariff, A. F., & Norenzayan, A. (2011). Mean Justice, 30, 283–357.
 The Geographies of Religious and Nonreligious Morality 351

Tyler, T. R., & Huo, Y. (2002). Trust in the law: Available at www.worldvaluessurvey.org/
Encouraging public cooperation with the po- WVSDocumentationWV6.jsp.
lice and courts. New York: Russell Sage Foun- Wuthnow, R. (1999). Mobilizing civic engage-
dation. ment: The changing impact of religious in-
Voas, D. (2008). The continuing secular transi- volvement. In T. Skocpol & M. P. Fiorina
tion. In D. Pollack & D. V. A. Olson (Eds.), (Eds.), Civic engagement in American democ-
The role of religion in modern societies racy (pp. 331–363). Washington, DC: Brook-
(pp. 25–49). New York: Taylor & Francis. ings Institution Press.
Voltaire. (1977). The portable Voltaire (B. R. Xu, Z. X., & Ma, H. K. (2015). How can a de-
Redman, Trans.). New York: Penguin Books. ontological decision lead to moral behavior?:
(Original work published 1727) The moderating role of moral identity. Journal
Watts, J., Greenhill, S. J., Atkinson, Q. D., Cur- of Business Ethics, 137, 537–549.
rie, T. E., Bulbulia, J., & Gray, R. D. (2015). Yilmaz, O., & Bahçekapili, H. G. (2015). With-
Broad supernatural punishment but not mor- out God, everything is permitted?: The recip-
alizing high gods precede the evolution of po- rocal influence of religious and meta-ethical
litical complexity in Austronesia. Proceedings beliefs. Journal of Experimental Social Psy-
of the Royal Society of London B, 282(1804), chology, 58, 95–100.
2014–2556. Young, L., & Durwin, A. J. (2013). Moral real-
White, M. (2011). The great big book of horrible ism as moral motivation: The impact of meta-
things. The definitive chronicle of history’s ethics on everyday decision-making. Journal
100 worst atrocities. New York: Norton. of Experimental Social Psychology, 49(2),
Wiessner, P. F. (2010). Youths, elders, and the 302–306.
wages of war in Enga province, Papua New Zuckerman, P. (2007). Atheism: Contempo-
Guinea. Canberra: Australian National Uni- rary numbers and patterns. In M. Martin
versity. (Ed.), The Cambridge companion to atheism
World Values Survey Association. (2014). World (pp. 47– 66). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge Uni-
Values Survey, Wave 6, 2010–2014 [Data file]. versity Press.
CHAPTER 36

The Egocentric Teleological Bias


How Self‑Serving Morality Shapes Perceptions
of Intelligent Design

Jesse L. Preston

Why are intelligent design arguments so moralized?

Egocentric biases foster a false perception of “suspicious serendipity”


and so create illusions of intelligent design with self-serving moral
judgments.

The argument from design is one of the Intelligent Design: A Brief History


most common proofs offered for the ex-
istence of God. Essentially, the argument One favorite example of the design argu-
comes down to an observation of complexi- ment is the amazing human eye. Socrates
ty and order in the world, in life, and in our suggested the correspondence between
universe and an inference that this is far too parts of the human body (e.g., the eyelids
much order and complexity to have come protecting the eyeballs) was a clear sign of
about by random chance. Rather, such per- “clever planning.” The naturalist William
fect orchestration implies some invisible Paley (1802) compared the complexity of the
hand conducting the orchestra—that is, human eye to finding a watch on the beach:
God. Intelligent design arguments are also “Suppose I had found a watch upon the
highly moralized, in part because of the ground, and it should be inquired how the
obvious connection to religious belief. But watch happened to be in that place . . . the
also, they hinge on an implicit perception inference, we think is inevitable: the watch
of a moral purpose in that design. Here I must have had a maker, and been designed
argue that egocentric biases (centered on for a purpose.” Just as the intricate func-
the self, humans, earth, and life) are key tions of a pocket watch implies there was a
to creating illusions of intelligent design, watchmaker responsible for its design, Paley
by creating a strong sense of “suspicious argued, so does the fitness of species to the
serendipity”: simultaneously enhancing the demands of their environment imply design
perceived unlikeliness and benefit of one’s by God. Design arguments are a specific in-
own personal outcomes. stance of teleological reasoning (Kelemen,

352
 Egocentric Teleological Bias 353

1999), a tendency to see any kind of func- chance and a big splash create a kind of
tional outcome as being created for that suspicious serendipity—a positive outcome
purpose—whether they were designed or that seems too good to be true. Teleological
not. For example, young children might ac- reasoning solves the problem of unexplained
curately perceive that a chair is “for sitting” patterns by attributing it to goal-directed be-
but also that a large rock might be “for sit- havior.
ting” as well (Kelemen, 1999; Keleman & However, converging lines of research
DiYanni, 2005). The tendency toward teleo- in psychology suggest that apparent design
logical thinking has implications for intui- may sometimes be illusory (Lombrozo,
tive interpretations of evolution as guided by Shtulman, & Weisberg, 2006). We perceive
God (rather than natural selection). By see- order and patterns in events, sometimes
ing the fit between various species and their where they do not exist (such as optical il-
environment (the long neck of a giraffe, the lusions). People have poor understanding
thick fur of a polar bear), it easy to infer in- of what true randomness really looks like
tention and design. Modern versions of the (Gilovich, 1991; Wagenaar, 1972), and so
argument (e.g., “intelligent design theory”; may make inferences of order where there is
Dembski, 2004) also point to the apparent really just a more aesthetic version of disor-
irreducible biological complexity of the eye der. Egocentric biases are partly responsible
and other organic structure (Behe, 1996), for creating illusions of design, by simulta-
and a universe that seems to be fine-tuned neously enhancing the perceived unlikeliness
for life (Barrow & Tipler, 1988; White, and benefit of one’s own personal outcomes.
2000). First, egocentrism blinds us to alternate re-
There is something genuinely compelling alities, the other ways that things could be
to the argument: How else could a thing than the particular arrangement we present-
so complex and useful (whether a pocket ly enjoy. This also includes an ignorance of
watch, an eye, or a universe) come about by other ways that events and outcomes could
accident? Ultimately the design argument arrange themselves to be “fine-tuned.” Sec-
does not hinge on the specific details and ond, egocentrism increases the sense of rele-
data, but how much an outcome seems to be vance for personal outcomes relative to other
designed. The experience itself is the argu- events—it is about all about me. Events seem
ment. People are skilled at drawing causal to revolve around the self, and events which
connections under uncertainty (Tversky & favor oneself seem much more significant
Kahneman, 1980; Weiner, 1985), and the and of greater impact overall than those
kinds of causes people tend to infer match that affect other people. Egocentric biases
the outcome (White, 2009)—that is, big thereby create suspicious serendipity by cre-
events cause big effects and good reasons for ating systematic illusions of order centered
good outcomes (LeBoeuf & Norton, 2012). on one’s own experience.
Design inferences are a special kind of ex- Important here, egocentric biases are not
planation that is reserved for those effects just centered on the individual self, but may
that seem most designed, in particular those be observed at radiating levels around the
that seem very unlikely to occur by chance self, for example, anthropocentrism, geo-
(e.g., arise from multiple conjunctive events centricism, and biocentrism (see Table 36.1).
and patterns of “nonrandom” action such For example, an anthropocentric perspective
as longer streaks in the “hot-hand” effect; places humans at the top of the animal king-
Caruso, Waytz, & Epley, 2010), and whose dom, separate from lower beasts and closer
outcomes seem to satisfy some goal (Luo, & to images of God. Here I describe how each
Baillargeon, 2005): In other words, a small of these different levels of egocentrism is as-
chance combined with a big splash. Design sociated with a corresponding illusion of
inferences are especially likely when the design, by making the outcome seem more
outcome that is particularly favorable, or “special” and therefore deserving of an in-
seems to satisfy a goal. And so there is an tentional cause. I discuss each of these levels
important moral component to the design of egocentrism, the illusions of intelligent de-
inference, that we see design where there is sign associated with each bias, and the moral
something helpful. When combined, a small implications of each of these biases.
354 M O R A L I T Y A N D B E L I E F S

TABLE 36.1.  Egocentric Biases and Their Corresponding Illusions of Design


Bias Design illusion Moral implications
Egocentrism Personal life events are “meant to be.” System justification
Consciousness as the soul Victim blaming

Anthropocentrism Humans are created in God’s image. Dehumanization

Geocentricism Classic: Earth as the center of the Universe. Environmental apathy


Neo-geocentricism: Earth as a special habitat for life

Biocentrism Anthropic principle (fine-tuned universe) Life is sacred.

Egocentrism 1989), and the belief in “synchronicity”


supports the intuition that coincidences are
Each of us is located in a particular self, and meaningful and must be intended for some
it is from this self that one sees and acts on reason (Jung, 2010). For example, a chance
the world. Egocentrism refers to the difficul- meeting of two strangers on a train could
ty we all experience in stepping outside our lead to a conversation, a date, a marriage, and
own perspective to consider others’ points of later a family. For these two people, it may be
view, or to view our own position more ob- tempting to perceive their chance meeting as
jectively (Piaget, 2013; Zuckerman, Kernis, fate, as the odds against meeting each other
Guarnera, Murphy, & Rappoport, 1983). seem so infinitesimal. But if they had not met,
For example, young children are notoriously it is also likely they might find a different ro-
egocentric and fail to understand that oth- mance and destiny elsewhere. Any one given
ers’ beliefs or perspectives might differ from meeting and romance may be itself very un-
their own (Piaget, 2013). Being able to over- likely, but the general prospects of love and
come the egocentric perspective is a develop- romance are very high. Likewise, consider a
mental hallmark of cognitive maturity. But person who has just won the lottery. From his
in some ways the egocentric perspective is or her point of view, this is a highly unlikely
an inescapable bias, because we are all teth- event (and indeed it is) and also very favor-
ered to our own minds and personal point able. It is not uncommon for lottery winners
of view on the world. Consciousness is itself to thank God and praise His generosity and
inherently egocentric, and the phenomenal wisdom in providing such a blessed windfall.
experience of mind as a point of view en- But a person reading the online article about
hances mind–body dualism and the belief in the lottery winner may be more cynical. After
a personal “soul” (Preston, Gray, & Wegner, all, although the odds of any one person win-
2006). Though we mostly grow out of the ning a lottery are low, the odds of someone
childish forms of egocentrism, we are still winning are very high. Winning a lottery is
biased toward our own perspective; we just really only remarkable to the winner.
become better able to adjust for it in adult- To the recipient, an unexpected good out-
hood (Epley, Morewedge, & Keysar, 2004). come serves a function, and so seems to ful-
One side effect of being stuck in our own fill a purpose. Indeed, when people underes-
point of view is that we tend to interpret our timate the how their own actions facilitate
own life events as more special than others, pleasant outcomes, they can attribute the
particularly the coincidences and chance oc- outcome to some benevolent external agent
currences that become life-altering events. (Gilbert, Brown, Pinel, & Wilson, 2000).
For example, people higher in trait egocen- People also believe more strongly in personal
trism are also higher on judgments of psychic miracles than miracles for others (Proudfoot
causes for coincidence (Moore, Thalbourne, & Shaver, 1975; Spilka, Shaver, & Kirkpat-
& Storm, 2010). But in general, people tend rick, 1985), and events seem more “miracu-
to think of their own coincidences as more lous” when one is personally affected by the
surprising than others’ coincidences (Falk, outcome (Ransom & Alicke, 2012).
 Egocentric Teleological Bias 355

Moral Consequences one. The original form was cautious, mak-


ing the point only on the last page. It was
For the most part, belief in synchronicity
this particular point that aroused the most
and things as “meant to be” may be a harm-
offense. For all our pretenses of superior-
less and pleasant illusion. But this is because,
ity—the civility, mind, morality—we are not
for the most part, the unexpected events we
as high and mighty as we thought.
experience in our lives are relatively harm- Despite widespread (though not universal)
less and pleasant. It’s nice to think that the acceptance of evolution by natural selection,
good things that happen to us happen for there is still an implicit separation between
a reason (Taylor & Brown, 1988). But not humans and other species—we see spe-
all things that happen are nice, and the flip cies most similar to ourselves as possessing
side of belief in personal miracles and fate is greater intelligence (Morewedge, Preston,
the belief in a just world (Lerner & Miller, & Wegner, 2007) and diminish the experi-
1978). If we believe in fate and divine jus- ences of species different from us. Animals
tice, how are we to make sense to chaos and that look like us—even robots—seem more
tragedy? When tragedy strikes us personally, intelligent (Broadbent et al., 2013). The per-
we may also see it as caused by God (Gray & vasiveness of the bias is revealed by the fact
Wegner, 2010), perhaps to teach us some im- that when people attempt to include other
portant life lesson (Bering, 2002). But trag- animals, they tend to do so by adopting an
edies observed from a distance can reinforce anthropocentric stance—that animals are
system justification (Jost, Banaji, & Nosek, like people (Tyler, 2003). In trying to iden-
2004) and victim blaming (Lerner & Sim- tify what makes us special, some scientists
mons, 1966), a general lack of sympathy for have pointed to our larger frontal lobes
the strife experienced by others. that make us smart, opposable thumbs that
allow us to use tools, use of grammar and
language to communicate, and ability to
Anthropocentrism transmit knowledge through culture. For
better or for worse, those traits have brought
Recently the Working Group of the An- humans to where we are now able to effec-
thropocene argued that we have entered tively dominate the planet and all its species
the Anthropocene age—where the Earth with a world population of over 7 billion.
is dominated by human activity (Kolbert, But this is constantly being challenged by
2011). But through our short history as a ideas that other species have intelligences
species, we humans have long granted our- that we have been unaware of or cannot
selves a special status among species. The comprehend—for example, dolphins, chim-
dominance of humans over other animals panzees, bees, and ants may each have cog-
has long been interpreted as a position of nition and means of communication that we
privilege among life forms, that we are not cannot fathom (Beck, 2013). Sure, a dolphin
just fitter, but better. Humans are unique in may not score well on the SATs, but there is
that they are often depicted as the image of no way of knowing what intelligence tests of
God. The strongest challenge to this anthro- other species we would fail.
pocentric bias is still Charles Darwin’s On
the Origin of Species (1859). It was here that
Darwin described a way that a natural ran- Moral Consequences
dom process can systematically bring about Humans are seen as a privileged and special
order and function: natural selection. Natu- species, the favorite of all of God’s creation.
ral selection was a threat to the design argu- Humans are seen as so remarkable, that we
ment not just because it offered an alterna- must be imperfect versions of the gods—
tive hypothesis to creationism, but because it or rather that gods are perfected humans.
directly challenged the notion that apparent This closeness to the divine is not just in
design implies a designer. Natural selection appearance, but humans are perceived to
directly challenged anthropocentric biases have greater have free will, complex emo-
because it implied humans are not a privi- tions, mind, consciousness, and a soul—
leged species, just currently an advantaged Godly traits that we do not necessarily share
356 M O R A L I T Y A N D B E L I E F S

with our animal friends. Dehumanization it all. Still, like any great illusion, geocentri-
(Haslam, 2006) takes away these traits away cism persists despite the fact that we know
from others, which grants a “full” human it’s not true—we still define our days by sun-
the moral right to treat those without these set and sunrise, not earthset and earthrise.
features harshly. This has implications for While this classic form of geocentricism
our treatment of other animals, as well as is now almost universally rejected, there is
our treatment of other humans that we deny still a pervasive form of neo-geocentricism
full “human” capacity. emphasizing the specialness of planet Earth.
Earth is located in the “Goldilocks zone”
relative to the sun, seen as producing tem-
Geocentricism peratures “just right” for life (Rampino &
Caldeira, 1994). Earth also has some other
For millennia, humans had been tracking key features that make life as we know it
the motion of stars and planets in the night possible—an ozone layer and magnetic field
sky, but assumed that that we (or the Earth) to counter radiation, an oxygen-rich atmo-
stood at the epicenter for this great celestial sphere, plenty of water, and daily orbit to
circumambulation. It was not until 1543 regulate temperature. Thus, despite its unre-
when Copernicus introduced the heliocen- markable address in the universe, the Earth
tric model with the publication of On the retains its remarkable status as a unique
Revolutions of the Heavenly Spheres that habitat for life.
this idea was properly challenged. The prob- Today, the search for other Earth-like
lem of geocentricism sparked one of the most planets poses one challenge to the idea that
explosive and infamous conflicts between Earth is special. At present, a small hand-
science and religion to date. Interestingly, at ful of such planets have been found that
the time there was no explicit biblical doc- may be able to support life as we know it.
trine of an Earth-centered universe, but a But the idea that Earth is special is also bi-
few scant references to the world not moving ased by the notion that we expect life to be
(Psalm 96:10; Psalm 93:1). But the idea of a “life-as-we-know-it”—that is, life elsewhere
universe centered on Earth fit well with the exists in relatively the same conditions as
idea of a designer Earth made by God as the life on Earth. Carl Sagan (1973) noted, for
home of His favorite creation: humankind. example, that we have a “carbon chauvin-
In spite of the importance of Copernicus’s ism” when it comes to looking for extrater-
work, it was only published after his death, restrial life, because we assume that life on
for fear of Church response. other planets ought to be made of the same
The change from geocentric to helio- stuff as we are. Likewise, the search for life
centric model was a scientific revolution—­ may be biased by temperature chauvinism,
shedding off the outdated ideas for new oxygen chauvinism, and other egocentric
exciting ones—but also a revolution in our limitations of imagination of other possible
own perspective taking in science. It marks forms of life.
the moment that science became “grown
up.” In addition to being the paradigm of
Moral Consequences
paradigm shifts, geocentricism is also an apt
analogy for egocentric biases in general—it One moral consequence of neo-geocentri-
represents the ignorant perspective that one cism is the idea that nature itself somehow
is the center of the universe, and that every- strives to maintain an equilibrium suited for
thing revolves around you. In fact, from our sustaining life. The specialness of Earth as
point of view on Earth, that is exactly what a home for life contributes to the concept
it looks like- all other heavenly bodies ap- of Earth as “mother nature” or “Gaia,” an
pear to move in predictable patterns around intentional life-giving entity. In studies of
us. Without the aid of science and technol- teleological reasoning, sentences with ex-
ogy, we lack the perspective to see our own plicit Gaia or Earth-preservation content
movement in space relative to these other are more likely to be endorsed, even without
objects. And so from a naïve point of view time pressure (Kelemen & Rosset, 2009).
it appears as though Earth is the middle of The consequence of the geocentric belief in
 Egocentric Teleological Bias 357

the specialness of Earth is that, ironically, posits that ours is just one of innumerable
people may underestimate human impact on (possibly infinite) universes, each of which
the Earth and our capacity for irreparable may have its own laws of physics. Given an
harm to the delicate balance it holds for life. infinite number of universes with an infi-
If Mother Nature is perceived to restore bal- nite array of physical properties, the odds
ance and act to protect her own well-being, of finding one life-supporting universe sky-
then she has the ability to “take care of her- rocket from virtually impossible to virtually
self.” This kind of reasoning is a common inevitable. From this point of view, no one
theme among liberal climate change deniers, universe is any less likely than the others;
that it is somehow absurd to think that we it had to turn out some way. Our universe
humans could destroy the mighty power of happens to be one of the lucky universes fit
our Mother Nature. to support life as we know it. But, from our
egocentric point of view it seems more than
mere luck. We are holding the winning lotto
Biocentrism ticket of universes, but like all lottery win-
ners it seems just too unlikely and special
The final level of egocentrism I discuss is bio- to be anything less than a gift from God.
centrism—the egocentric emphasis on life And, like the proverbial lottery winner,
over all other forms. However, this level of this reasoning falls prey to the retrospective
egocentrism may also be universe-centrism, gambler’s fallacy (Oppenheimer & Monin,
as it relates to a belief in our own universe 2009), where rare/extraordinary events are
is particularly special and designed. These presumed to occur as part of a longer se-
both relate to the anthropic principle (Bar- quence of occurrences. For example, people
row & Tipler, 1988)—which highlights that estimate that a gambler who just rolled three
in order to be able to develop sentient life 6’s in dice has been playing for longer than
forms (like ourselves), our universe needs to a gambler who rolled 2, 4, and 5. People do
have the specific set of parameters and laws understand that streaks and rare events do
it does, and any deviation from those pa- happen occasionally. So when confronted
rameters would mean render the evolution with a rare event, we seek to normalize it
of life impossible by placing it in a series of more mundane
There are different versions of the an- events. In the case of the fine-tuned universe
thropic principle—the strong anthropic argument: Just because our universe appears
principle implies a designer—that the uni- to be particularly unlikely does not mean
verse was somehow compelled to create life we know anything about the likelihood that
(Barrow & Tipler, 1988), but the weak an- other universes exist (Hacking, 1987). How-
thropic principle version merely points out ever, we may perceive the other universes to
the egocentric nature of the problem: The occur with high frequency to make sense of
ostensible “fine-tuning” is due to the fact our “special” universe occurring even once.
that our own observation self-selects us One way to increase the odds of life even
into a universe where life must be allowed further, Lee Smolin (2007) has proposed a
to exist (Carter, 1974/2011; the anthropic theory of “fecund universes” that life-sup-
bias, Bostrom, 2002). As it happens, there porting universes are more likely to occur
exists a universe that can support life, but than not. The theory supposes that black
if there were not we would not know any holes provide a way for universes to repro-
better. We therefore should not be surprised duce by recycling material from one uni-
that the universe falls within the narrow verse into a new one. Black holes draw in
range of natural laws that allow conscious matter and produce baby universes on the
life to exist; otherwise, we would not be here other side, with the same laws of physics as
to make that observation. its parent universe. As it turns out, many
Arguments against the strong anthropic of the same “fine-tuned” laws of physics
principle usually come in the form of nor- that create the cosmic conditions for a life-
malizing the apparent improbability of our supporting universe (e.g., rate of expansion,
life-supporting universe. One way to change gravitational constant) also create the cos-
the probability is the multiverse theory, that mic conditions necessary to produce black
358 M O R A L I T Y A N D B E L I E F S

holes. So, while universes that cannot sup- Barrow, J. D., & Tipler, F. J. (1986). The an-
port life also tend to be unhealthy universes thropic cosmological principle. New York:
that die young, healthy life-supporting uni- Oxford University Press.
verse are more also likely to have black holes, Beck, J. (2013). Why we can’t say what animals
think. Philosophical Psychology, 26(4), 520–
and so are better able to reproduce. Thus, 546.
universes that are able to sustain life have Behe, M. J. (1996). Darwin’s black box: The bio-
a tidy means of cosmological natural selec- chemical challenge to evolution. New York:
tion. This would mean more life-supporting Touchstone Books.
universes than not, increasing the chances of Bering, J. M. (2002). The existential theory of
finding oneself in such a universe consider- mind. Review of General Psychology, 6, 3–24.
ably (Smolin, 2007). Bostrom, N. (2002). Anthropic bias: Observa-
tion selection effects in science and philoso-
phy. New York: Routledge.
Moral Consequences Broadbent, E., Kumar, V., Li, X., Sollers, J., III,
Stafford, R. Q., MacDonald, B. A., & Wegner,
Opponents of the idea of a fine-tuned uni- D. M. (2013). Robots with display screens: A
verse aim to deflate the argument from de- robot with a more humanlike face display is
sign by changing the apparent probability. perceived to have more mind and a better per-
If odds are high, then it does not need the sonality. PLOS ONE, 8(8), e72589.
directed hand of an intentional being. But Carter, B. (2011). Large number coincidences
another approach is to question whether a and the anthropic principle in cosmology.
life-supporting universe is actually special General Relativity and Gravitation, 43(11),
enough product to warrant a design expla- 3225–3233. (Original work published 1974)
nation. This is a tricky assumption to over- Caruso, E. M., Waytz, A., & Epley, N. (2010).
come because the idea life is special seems The intentional mind and the hot hand: Per-
ceiving intentions makes streaks seem likely to
so obviously true. But I suggest this is just continue. Cognition, 116, 149–153.
one more form of egocentrism: We think Darwin, C. (1859). On the origin of species. Lon-
life is special because we are things that are don: John Murray.
alive and isn’t that nice for us. The natural Dembski, W. A. (2004). The design revolution.
corollary of the belief that life is special is Nottingham, UK: Intervarsity Press.
that life is “sacred” in principle and needs to Epley, N., Morewedge, C., & Keysar, B. (2004).
be protected. Though I argue it is certainly Perspective taking in children and adults:
a bias, it is perhaps the most fundamental Equivalent egocentrism but differential cor-
of all moral principles we hold, that guides rection. Journal of Experimental Social Psy-
chology, 40, 760–768.
all kinds of moral judgments covering issues
Falk, R. (1989). Judgment of coincidences: Mine
from war, abortion, euthanasia, and murder. versus yours. American Journal of Psychol-
ogy, 102, 477–493.
Gilbert, D. T., Brown, R. P., Pinel, E. C., &
Conclusion Wilson, T. D. (2000). The illusion of external
agency. Journal of Personality and Social Psy-
Just as the gravity of massive objects bends chology, 79, 690–700.
the appearance of light toward the mass, the Gilovich, T. (1991). How we know what isn’t so:
egocentric point of view distorts perception The fallibility of human reason in everyday
around the self. Egocentric biases can cre- life. New York: Free Press.
Gray, K., & Wegner, D. M. (2010). Blaming God
ate pervasive illusions of design by creating
for our pain: Human suffering and the divine
a sense of suspicious serendipity: one’s own mind. Personality and Social Psychology Re-
favorable outcomes seem more favorable, view, 14, 7–16.
and less likely. And so it seems like the life, Hacking, I. (1987). The inverse gambler’s falla-
the world, and the universe was made for us, cy: The argument from design: The anthropic
because it suits us just so perfectly. principle applied to Wheeler universes. Mind,
96, 331–340.
Haslam, N. (2006). Dehumanization: An inte-
REFERENCES grative review. Personality and Social Psychol-
ogy Review, 10(3), 252–264.
Adams, D. (1988). The salmon of doubt. New Jost, J. T., Banaji, M. R., & Nosek, B. A. (2004).
York: Random House. A decade of system justification theory: Ac-
 Egocentric Teleological Bias 359

cumulated evidence of conscious and uncon- Piaget, J. (2013). The construction of reality in
scious bolstering of the status quo. Political the child. New York: Basic Books.
Psychology, 25(6), 881–919. Preston, J., Gray, K., & Wegner, D. M. (2006).
Jung, C. G. (2010). Synchronicity: An acausal The Godfather of soul. Behavioral and Brain
connecting principle. In G. Adler & R. F. C. Sciences, 29(05), 482–483.
Hull (Trans.), Collected works of C. G. Jung: Proudfoot, W., & Shaver, P. (1975). Attribution
Vol. 8. Structure and dynamics of the psyche. theory and the psychology of religion. Jour-
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. nal for the Scientific Study of Religion, 24,
Kelemen, D. (1999). Why are rocks pointy?: Chil- 317–330.
dren’s preference for teleological explanations Rampino, M. R., & Caldeira, K. (1994). The
of the natural world. Developmental Psychol- Goldilocks problem: Climatic evolution and
ogy, 35, 1440–1452. long-term habitability of terrestrial planets.
Kelemen, D., & DiYanni, C. (2005). Intuitions Annual Review of Astronomy and Astrophys-
about origins: Purpose and intelligent design ics, 32(1), 83–114.
in children’s reasoning about nature. Journal Ransom, M. R., & Alicke, M. D. (2012). It’s a
of Cognition and Development, 6, 3–31. miracle: Separating the miraculous from the
Kelemen, D., & Rosset, E. (2009). The human mundane. Archive for the Psychology of Reli-
function compunction: Teleological explana- gion, 34(2), 243–275.
tion in adults. Cognition, 111(1), 138–143. Sagan, C. (1973). Carl Sagan’s cosmic connec-
Kolbert, E. (2011). Enter the Anthropocene: Age tion: An extraterrestrial perspective. Cam-
of man. National Geographic, 219(3), 60. bridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
LeBoeuf, R. A., & Norton, M. I. (2012). Conse- Smolin, L. (2007). Scientific alternatives to the
quence–cause matching: Looking to the conse- anthropic principle. In B. Carr (Ed.), Universe
quences of events to infer their causes. Journal or multiverse? (pp. 323–366). Cambridge,
of Consumer Research, 39, 128–141. UK: Cambridge University Press.
Lerner, M. J., & Miller, D. T. (1978). Just world Spilka, B., Shaver, P., & Kirkpatrick, L. A.
research and the attribution process: Looking (1985). A general attribution theory for the
back and ahead. Psychological Bulletin, 85, psychology of religion. Journal for the Scien-
1030–1051. tific Study of Religion, 24, 1–20.
Lerner, M. J., & Simmons, C. H. (1966). Observ- Taylor, S. E., & Brown, J. D. (1988). Illusion and
er’s reaction to the “innocent victim”: Com- well-being: A social psychological perspective
passion or rejection? Journal of Personality on mental health. Psychological Bulletin, 103,
and Social Psychology, 4(2), 203–210. 193–210.
Lombrozo, T., Shtulman, A., & Weisberg, M. Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1980). Causal
(2006). The intelligent design controversy: schemas in judgments under uncertainty. In
Lessons from psychology and education. M. Fishbein (Ed.), Progress in social psychol-
Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 10, 56–57. ogy (pp. 49–72). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Luo, Y., & Baillargeon, R. (2005). Can a self- Tyler, T. (2003). If horses had hands . . . . Society
propelled box have a goal?: Psychological rea- and Animals, 11(3), 267–281.
soning in 5-month-old infants. Psychological Wagenaar, W. A. (1972). Generation of random
Science, 16, 601–608. sequences by human subjects: A critical sur-
Moore, T., Thalbourne, M. A., & Storm, L. vey of literature. Psychological Bulletin, 77,
(2010). A study on coincidences. Australian 65–72.
Journal of Parapsychology, 10(2), 154. Weiner, B. (1985). “Spontaneous” causal think-
Morewedge, C. K., Preston, J., & Wegner, D. M. ing. Psychological Bulletin, 97, 74–84.
(2007). Timescale bias in the attribution of White, P. A. (2009). Property transmission: An
mind. Journal of Personality and Social Psy- explanatory account of the role of similarity
chology, 93, 1–11. information in causal inference. Psychological
Oppenheimer, D. M., & Monin, B. (2009). Bulletin, 135, 774–793.
The retrospective gambler’s fallacy: Unlikely White, R. (2000). Fine-tuning and multiple uni-
events, constructing the past, and multiple verses. Noûs, 34, 260–276.
universes. Judgment and Decision Making, Zuckerman, M., Kernis, M. H., Guarnera, S. M.,
4(5), 326–334. Murphy, J. F. & Rappoport, L. (1983). The
Paley, W. (1802). Natural theology: Or, evidenc- egocentric bias: Seeing oneself as cause and
es of the existence and attributes of the deity. target of others’ behavior. Journal of Person-
London: J. Faulder. ality, 51, 621–630.
PART VIII
DYNAMIC MORAL JUDGMENT

Q U E S T I O N S A N S W E R E D I N PA R T V I I I

CHAPTER 37  What explains whether acts—from masturbation and


homosexuality to smoking and meat eating—are seen as personal
preferences or as moral wrongs?

CHAPTER 38  How do people deal with a morally complex


and contradictory world?

CHAPTER 39  What is blame, and why do people blame so liberally even
when there are compelling reasons to mitigate it?
C H A P T E R 37

Moralization
How Acts Become Wrong

Chelsea Schein
Kurt Gray

What explains whether acts—from masturbation and


homosexuality to smoking and meat eating—are seen as personal
preferences or as moral wrongs?

According to the theory of dyadic morality, the answer is perceived


harm.

What Makes an Act Wrong? The Question of Moralization

Morality evolves. Nowhere is this evolution The history of masturbation might seem
more apparent than in the shifting norms frivolous, but understanding the basis of
regarding the morality of masturbation (La- moralization—the movement of a prievious-
queur, 2003). In the ancient world, mastur- ly neutral act into the moral sphere (Rozin,
bation was not only tolerated but celebrated 1999)—and demoralization—the movement
as a way to increase fertility. Ancient Egyp- of an act out of the moral sphere—is of ut-
tians even told tales of the God Atum who al- most importance. Given morality’s connec-
legedly created the world through masturba- tion to the law, understanding moraliza-
tion. While Judeo-Christian societies never tion is central to questions of moral rights,
quite celebrated masturbation, the Bible and freedom and imprisonment, and even life
early Judeo-Christian scholars were largely and death. Indeed, the moralization of con-
silent on the topic. Autoeroticism remained sensual sexual acts continues to have grave
in the moral background until the Enlight- consequences—being gay is punishable by
enment, when there was widespread moral death in 12 countries and illegal in 66 others
panic concerning the ills of masturbation. (Cameron & Berkowitz, 2015).
Why is self-pleasure celebrated at one time The theory of dyadic morality (TDM)
but seen as a serious sin at another? The an- proposes that changes in moral judgment
swer may lie with perceptions of harm. over time are driven by changes in perceived

363
364 DY N A M I C M O R A L J U D G M E N T

harm. In the context of masturbation, such Malle, 2012; Nichols, 2002; Sripada &
harm may seem preposterous, but, as we ex- Stich, 2007) are judged as immoral to the
plore, what matters for morality is percep- extent that they exemplify the dyadic tem-
tions of harm. plate. In other words, acts are wrong to the
With masturbation, perceptions of harm extent that they involve harm—a very spe-
were induced through a 1720 pamphlet ti- cific, dyadic kind of harm. Consistent with
tled “Onania, or, The Heinous Sin of Self this idea, more harmful acts are judged as
Pollution, and all its Frightful Consequenc- more immoral, and both greater suffering
es,” which contained pseudoscientific claims and greater intentionality lead to more moral
about the dangers of masturbation. These condemnation (Hart & Honoré, 1985).
apparent dangers ignited a moral panic in Murder is more immoral than attempted
the United States and Europe that lasted for killing, and a calculated, planned slaughter
two centuries, which in turn inspired even is more immoral than a lover’s rage-induced
more perceptions of harm. One well-regard- homicide (for reviews, see Gray, Waytz, &
ed doctor claimed that, “neither the plague, Young, 2012; Gray, Young, & Waytz, 2012;
nor war, nor small-pox, nor similar diseases, Schein & Gray, 2017).
have produced results so disastrous to hu- Importantly, the harm of dyadic moral-
manity as the pernicious habit of Onanism” ity is not the objective, reasoned, rationalist
(Dr. Adam Clarke, quoted in Kellogg, 1890, harm historically debated by psychologists
p. 233). In fact, the moral panic surrounding (Haidt, 2001; Kohlberg, 1969). Instead,
masturbation only really began to quell with harm is subjective, emotional, and intui-
the normalization of sex by pioneers such as tive—it is a matter of perception. The sub-
Alfred Kinsey—that is, when it was seen as jectivity of perceived harm means that some
more harmless. can see masturbation (or homosexuality) as
Inspired by historical examples, this chap- “clearly” harmful—for example, causing
ter proposes that perceptions of harm are damage to children—whereas others can see
key in understanding why certain acts enter these acts as “clearly” harmless. Whether
the moral sphere. We start first with a brief an act seems harmful drives whether it is
overview of the TDM and address how it viewed as a personal preference or a grave
sheds light on moralization. We then explore sin.
the broader historical context and contrast At the heart of dyadic morality are the
dyadic morality’s predictions with those of two complementary processes of dyadic
other theories. Next, we review the evidence comparison and dyadic completion. Dyad-
on moralization and highlight where more ic comparison can be summed up as what
empirical research is needed. Finally, we seems harmful is immoral (Schein & Gray,
explore implications for a divided political 2015). Dyadic morality predicts that acts are
world. compared with a cognitive template of harm,
with closer matches resulting in more robust
moral judgment. That is, acts are judged as
The Theory of Dyadic Morality immoral to the extent that they seem harm-
ful (Schein & Gray, 2015). If we told you
The TDM is an evolutionary inspired and that act X involves a man intentionally caus-
culturally pluralistic theory of moral cogni- ing harm to a little girl, you would think it
tion (Schein & Gray, 2017). It proposes that immoral because it seems to involve harm.
moral cognition revolves around a unifying On the flip side, dyadic completion pre-
cognitive template, called the moral dyad, dicts that what is immoral seems harmful
which consists of an intentional agent caus- (Gray, Schein, & Ward, 2014). Once judg-
ing damage to a vulnerable patient. This ments of immorality have been made, per-
template is built on perceptions of two inter- ceptions align to make acts consistent with
acting minds, a “thinking doer” capable of the dyadic template—that is, to more clearly
intending (the moral agent) and a “vulner- involve an intentional agent causing damage
able feeler” capable of suffering (the moral to a suffering patient (Clark, Chen, & Ditto,
patient; Wegner & Gray, 2016). 2015; DeScioli, Gilbert, & Kurzban, 2012;
Dyadic morality suggests that negative Gray et al., 2014; Liu & Ditto, 2013). If we
norm violations (Monroe, Guglielmo, & were to tell you that an act X was extremely
Moralization 365

immoral, you would automatically assume once it was a lifestyle choice, the recogni-
that the act is harmful and produces victims tion that children suffer from secondhand
(Liu & Ditto, 2013). smoke pulled smoking into the dyadic loop
(Rozin, 1999)—and made it seem immoral.
The perceived suffering of children is evident
Moralization Is Driven by the Dyadic Loop in moral debates against homosexuality,
masturbation, pornography, and smoking
Combined, dyadic comparison and dyadic (Comer, 2012; Laqueur, 2004; Pierce, 2001).
completion form the dyadic loop (Schein & Of course, suffering alone is not typically
Gray, 2014, 2016), a dynamic feedback cycle immoral, which is why moralization involves
that mutually amplifies perceptions of harm the perception of intentional agents who
(i.e., harmification) and immorality (i.e., perpetrate that suffering. The moralization
moralization). (See Figure 37.1.) In the dyad- of smoking received a large push when peo-
ic loop, initial perceptions of harm activate ple realized that tobacco companies were in-
perceptions of immorality, which in turn tentionally hiding the dangers of cigarettes.
activate more perceptions of harm, which This same perceived malice is partially be-
lead to increased perceptions of immorality, hind moral opposition to genetically modi-
which lead to increased perceptions of harm, fied organisms (GMOs), as people see large
and so on. corporations as intentionally doing harm to
It is the dyadic loop that drives moraliza- reap a profit (Bollinger, 2014). Perceptions
tion. Acts that are initially ambiguously im- of malicious agency can then lead to addi-
moral or harmful get drawn into the gravita- tional perceptions of suffering, and then to
tional pull of the dyadic loop, which drives even harsher moral judgments in an ongoing
complementary perceptions of harm and “creep” of perceived harm (Haslam, 2016)
immorality. Typically this process is initi- and immorality (Schein & Gray, 2016).
ated by the perception of suffering patients, More succinctly, we can say that harmifica-
who are often children (Schein, Goranson, tion leads to moralization; moralization in
& Gray, 2015). Consider smoking: Where turn leads to more harmification.

FIGURE 37.1. The dyadic loop is a dynamic feedback cycle in which the processes of dyadic comparison
and dyadic completion mutually reinforce each other, leading to moralization and “harmification”—
and therefore to political polarization. Reprinted with permission from Gray and Schein (2017).
366 DY N A M I C M O R A L J U D G M E N T

Demoralization lations (e.g., hitting another child) based on


the presence of harm (Smetana, 1985; Tu-
Dyadic morality predicts that harm is also
riel, Killen, & Helwig, 1987).
central to demoralization, such that reduced
However, anthropological research
perceptions of harm should reduce moral
seemed to challenge this centrality of harm
condemnation—an idea borne out in his-
(Shweder, Mahapatra, & Miller, 1987). Al-
torical trends. Once Kinsey and other sex- though both Indians and Americans morally
positive scholars revealed masturbation to condemned canonically harmful acts such
be harmless—and even healthy—it began as stealing and killing, some Brahmin Indi-
to leave the moral domain, at least for most ans also condemned acts that lacked clear
liberals (Day, 2013). The same is becoming objective harm, such as an eldest son eating
true of gay marriage, as research reveals that chicken after his father’s death. If morality is
children raised by gay parents are no worse about harm, how can people condemn these
off than those of straight parents (Patterson, objectively harmless acts?
2006). Vaping also seems more morally ac- Inspired by this anthropological research,
ceptable than smoking, in large part because moral foundations theory (MFT; Haidt,
it is unclear whether it causes harm (Palaz- 2012) argued that morality is grounded in
zolo, 2013). a set of innate yet culturally shaped moral
Of course, because harm is subjective and “foundations,” of which harm is only one.
intuitive, its perception can persist in the One can think of moral foundations as
face of even “objective” evidence otherwise. cognitive modules, which are like “little
In the case of gay marriage, even opponents switches in the brains of all animals” which
who were aware of the social science data are “triggered” by specific moral “inputs”
about children raised by gay parents nev- (Haidt, 2012, p. 123). According to MFT,
ertheless saw irreparable harm to children the Indians in Shweder’s study condemned
from changing the definition of marriage the eldest son’s chicken eating because it ac-
(Obergefell v. Hodges, 2015). tivated a distinct “purity module.” Although
Although dyadic morality suggests that there is very little evidence for these distinct
demoralization occurs through deharmifica- moral “foundations” (Gray & Keeney, 2015;
tion, the dyadic loop has a kind of cognitive Schein & Gray, 2017), MFT nicely high-
gravity (i.e., it is an attractor state; Schein lights cultural pluralism and the moral con-
& Gray, 2014; Spivey & Dale, 2004), which demnation of acts which seem—at least to
suggests that it is easier for acts to become Western eyes—rather harmless.
moralized than demoralized (Schein & Gray, Although dyadic morality acknowledges
2016). This explains why people raised in a that people morally condemn diverse acts, it
strict religious household may still get an denies that they are truly harmless, because
implicit twinge of immorality (and harm) harm is a matter of intuitive perception.
when contemplating masturbation, even if Take the example of consensual incest, a ca-
they rationally think it a matter of personal nonical “harmless wrong” in moral psychol-
preference. ogy (Haidt, 2001). Although this act may be
designed to be “objectively” harmless, par-
ticipants still see harm in this act, as well as
Historical Context others (Royzman, Kim, & Leeman, 2015).
Importantly, these perceptions occur within
The importance of harm in moralization is milliseconds (Gray et al., 2014) and exqui-
rooted in classic moral philosophy and moral sitely predict subsequent moral judgments
psychology (Bentham, 1879; Mill, 1861). In- (Schein & Gray, 2015).
formed by the classic moral philosophies of Some have argued that TDM denies plu-
Kant and Mill, early developmental models ralism, but, arguably, dyadic morality ad-
of morality focused upon justice and harm vocates for even more pluralism than MFT,
(Kohlberg, 1969; Piaget, 1932), and their as it suggests that both morality and harm
studies found that young children differenti- are sensitive to cultural construction (Weg-
ate violations of social convention (e.g., not ner & Gray, 2016). Philosophers (Rachels,
raising one’s hand in class) from moral vio- 1986) and psychologists (Asch, 1952; Turiel,
 Moralization 367

Hildebrandt, Wainryb, & Saltzstein, 1991) (Rozin, 1999), and genetically modified
have long recognized that understanding foods (Scott, Inbar, & Rozin, 2016; though
moral judgments requires taking into con- see Gray & Schein, 2016) are labeled as im-
sideration the “situational meaning” (Asch, moral to the extent that they activate feel-
1952) or “informational assumptions” (Tu- ings of disgust. The “disgust as moralizer”
riel et al., 1991) within a given culture. account is intuitive, as many popular argu-
Consider again the case of Brahmin Indi- ments against gay marriage appeal to the
ans condemning postfuneral chicken eating. violation of natural order (e.g. “God created
This culture also believes that when the son Adam and Eve not Adam and Steve”) or vis-
eats meat, it will pollute his dead father’s ceral disgust (Nussbaum, 2010). However,
soul, condemning him to eternal suffering recent evidence suggests that harm is a more
(Shweder, 2012). Thus this celebrated exam- important moralizer than disgust.
ple does not reveal the importance of harm-
less wrongs, but instead the importance of
perceptions of harm—and the link from Evidence
harm to immorality. TDM further suggests
that focusing on the perceptual nature of At first glance, there seems to be clear evi-
harm is imperative for understanding mor- dence in favor of the disgust-as-moralizer
alization. account. Studies reveal that disgust am-
plifies moral condemnation of ostensibly
harmless acts such as gay marriage and eat-
Theoretical Stance ing a dead dog (Inbar et al., 2012; Wheatley
& Haidt, 2005; Schnall, Haidt, Clore, &
That harm can drive moral condemnation Jordan, 2008); however, these results suffer
is uncontroversial, as research has long il- from multiple problems.
lustrated that perceptions of interpersonal First, they may not be replicable: A recent
harm differentiate violations of conven- meta-analysis (Landy & Goodwin, 2015)
tional norms from moral wrongs in both and a large-sample, independent replication
children (Smetana, 1985; Turiel et al., 1987) attempt (Johnson et al., 2016) both failed
and adults (Huebner, Lee, & Hauser, 2010). to replicate the causal impact of incidental
However, dyadic morality argues that per- disgust on moral judgment. Second, these
ceived harm is the best—and most proxi- results hint only that disgust can amplify
mal—predictor of moralization, even for moral condemnation (shifting an act from
ostensibly “harmless” violations. somewhat immoral to very immoral), rather
Of course, there might be other pathways than actually causing moralization (trans-
that contribute to moralization. For exam- forming an act from nonmoral to moral;
ple, an act can simply be labeled as immoral Pizarro, Inbar, & Helion, 2011). Third, dy-
through testimony of a parent or persuasive adic morality suggests that these acts are not
demagogue (Sripada & Stich, 2007; Harris harmless at all, because harm is a matter of
& Koenig, 2006). However, TDM suggests perception. Fourth, these studies use a very
that even when this top-down labeling oc- small subset of acts and do not compare
curs, harm is indelibly activated (DeScioli immoral disgusting acts (selling children
et al., 2012; Clark et al., 2015; Gray et al., tainted blood) to nonmoral disgusting acts
2014), which is important for making this (vomiting on yourself).
moral judgment intuitive. Dyadic morality suggests that harm—not
Although all moral psychologists likely disgust—is the key driver of moralization,
agree that harm can cause and reinforce a prediction supported by our recent re-
moral judgments, there are still questions search. In one study, we asked participants
about whether harm causes the moral con- to rate the immorality, harmfulness, and
demnation of “purity” violations, such as disgustingness of 24 different disgusting
eating odd food, cursing God, or even having actions (adapted from Tybur, Lieberman,
sex with a dead chicken (Haidt, 2001). Ac- & Griskevicius, 2009) including sexually
cording to MFT, issues such as gay marriage disgusting acts (e.g., performing oral sex),
(Inbar, Pizarro, & Bloom, 2012), smoking pathogen-related disgusting acts (e.g., seeing
368 DY N A M I C M O R A L J U D G M E N T

a cockroach run across the floor), and moral was the most powerful route to moralization
violations (e.g., deceiving a friend). We (Rottman et al., 2017). When children were
found that perceptions of harm best differ- told that an ostensibly harmless act never-
entiated the disgusting immoral violations theless hurt others, they robustly judged that
from the merely disgusting acts (Schein, Rit- act as immoral—even 3 months later. These
ter, & Gray, 2016). In two other studies, we results reveal that although moral informa-
asked participants to rate the immorality tion can be learned directly through testi-
of gay marriage and sacrilegious thoughts. mony, it persists intuitively through percep-
Although feelings of disgust did predict rat- tions of harm.
ings of immorality, these ratings were fully
mediated by perceptions of harm (Schein et
al., 2016). In other words, disgusting acts Extensions and Implications
are moralized to the extent that they seem
harmful, consistent with dyadic morality From changing norms on masturbation and
Careful thought suggests that disgust alone homosexuality to the increased condemna-
cannot be the source of moralization, as there tion of smoking, there are ample historical
are many acts that evoke disgust that are not examples of acts shifting from personal pref-
immoral, such as cleaning up your child’s di- erences to moral concerns and back again.
arrhea. What distinguishes the merely gross Using history as inspiration, we suggest that
from the morally wrong are perceptions of moral psychology should empirically test
harm, an idea supported by research on per- predictors of shifting moral attitudes; dyad-
ceptions of GMOs (Scott et al., 2016). In this ic morality predicts that an association with
study, which contained a representative sam- harm should be a highly effective way for an
ple of Americans, participants were opposed act to enter the moral sphere.
to GMOs to the extent that they saw them Studying changes in morality over time
as harmful—even those participants who be- can also provide an insight into moral polar-
lieved that their moral judgments were unre- ization. Differing initial assumptions about
lated to harm (Gray & Schein, 2016). the harmfulness of a given act can activate
One of the cleanest examinations of mor- differing perceptions of immorality, which
alization investigates the impact of testimony the dyadic loop can entrench via comple-
upon the moral judgments of 7-year-olds ex- mentary perceptions of harm and immoral-
posed to novel and ostensibly harmless acts, ity—and lead to intense disagreement across
such as aliens on a different planet “covering politics or religion. Importantly, although
their heads with sticks” or “sprinkling blue perceptions of harm can cause polarization,
water into a big puddle” (Rottman, Young, they may also provide the seeds of potential
& Kelemen, 2017). Researchers manipulat- reconcilation.
ed either the presence of disgust feelings (via In the midst of bitter political discourse,
fart spray) or the presence of testimony of it is tempting to conclude that liberals and
anger or disgust (e.g., “that act is disgust- conservatives have fundamentally differ-
ing”). Although researchers found no effect ent moral minds. However, dyadic morality
of incidental disgust upon moral judgments, suggests that there is not an insurmountable
they did find an effect of testimony. When moral chasm across politics. Instead, our
children were told that an act was bad— research reveals that for both liberals and
through either anger and disgust—they conservatives, perceptions of harm serves
rated it as more immoral. Importantly, there as a common currency, or lingua franca, for
was no difference between anger and disgust morality (Schein & Gray, 2015).
testimonies. Given that harm can serve as a common
Even more importantly, both kinds of tes- language, focusing on the relative harms and
timony engendered substantial perceptions merits of a particular act provides one model
of harm—and the extent to which children for productive moral dialogue (Greene,
linked acts to harm was the best predictor 2013). The Theory of Dyadic Morality may
of moralization, consistent with TDM. A therefore help to remind us that our moral
follow-up study revealed that giving chil- opponents are not monsters, but instead are
dren testimony about an act’s harmfulness good people who just see harm differently.
 Moralization 369

REFERENCES to moral judgment. Psychological Review,


108(4), 814–834.
Asch, S. E. (1952). Social psychology. Englewood Haidt, J. (2012). The righteous mind: Why good
Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall. people are divided by politics and religion.
Bentham, J. (1879). An introduction to the prin- New York: Pantheon Books.
ciples of morals and legislation. Oxford, UK: Harris, P. L., & Koenig, M. A. (2006). Trust in
Clarendon Press. testimony: How children learn about science
Bollinger, T. (2014). Exposed: GMOs and Fran- and religion. Child Development, 77(3), 505–
ken-Foods: How your daily diet could cause 524.
cancer. Retrieved from www.thetruthabout- Hart, H. L. A., & Honoré, T. (1985). Causation
cancer.com. in the law (2nd ed.). New York: Oxford Uni-
Cameron, D., & Berkowitz, B. (2015, June 26). versity Press.
The state of gay rights around the world. Haslam, N. (2016). Concept creep: Psychology’s
Retrieved from www.washingtonpost.com/ expanding concepts of harm and pathology.
graphics/world/gay-rights. Psychological Inquiry, 27(1), 1–17.
Clark, C. J., Chen, E. E., & Ditto, P. H. (2015). Huebner, B., Lee, J. J., & Hauser, M. D. (2010).
Moral coherence processes: Constructing cul- The moral–conventional distinction in mature
pability and consequences. Current Opinion moral competence. Journal of Cognition and
in Psychology, 6, 123–128. Culture, 10(1), 1–26.
Comer, M. (2012, April 24). Anti-gay N.C. pas- Inbar, Y., Pizarro, D., & Bloom, P. (2012). Dis-
tor: Amendment One defeat will cause “nu- gusting smells cause decreased liking of gay
clear holocaust” [Blog post]. Retrieved Feb- men. Emotion, 12(1), 23–27.
ruary 13, 2013, from http://interstateq.com/ Johnson, D. J., Wortman, J., Cheung, F., Hein,
archives/5216. M., Lucas, R. E., Donnellan, M. B., . . . Narr,
Day, N. (2013, June 21). How to address the R. K. (2016). The effects of disgust on moral
masturbating child. The Atlantic. Retrieved judgments: Testing moderators. Social Psycho-
from www.theatlantic.com/health/ar- logical and Personality Science, 7, 640–647.
chive/2013/06/how-to-address-the-mastur- Kellogg, J. H. (1890). Plain facts for old and
bating-child/277026. young: Embracing the natural history and hy-
DeScioli, P., Gilbert, S., & Kurzban, R. (2012). giene of organic life. Burlington, IA: Segner.
Indelible victims and persistent punishers in Kohlberg, L. (1969). Stage and sequence: The
moral cognition. Psychological Inquiry, 23(2), cognitive-developmental approach to social-
143–149. ization. In T. Mischel (Ed.), Cognitive de-
Gray, K., & Keeney, J. E. (2015). Disconfirming velopment and epistemology (pp. 151–235).
moral foundations theory on its own terms: New York: Academic Press.
Reply to Graham (2015). Social Psychological Landy, J. F., & Goodwin, G. P. (2015). Does
and Personality Science, 6, 874–877. incidental disgust amplify moral judgment?:
Gray, K., & Schein, C. (2016). No absolutism A meta-analytic review of experimental evi-
here: Harm predicts moral judgment 30× dence. Perspectives on Psychological Science,
better than disgust—Commentary on Scott, 10(4), 518–536.
Inbar, & Rozin (2015). Perspectives on Psy- Laqueur, T. W. (2003). Solitary sex?: A cultural
chological Science, 11(3), 325–329. history of masturbation. New York: Zone
Gray, K., Schein, C., & Ward, A. F. (2014). The Books.
myth of harmless wrongs in moral cognition: Liu, B., & Ditto, P. H. (2013). What dilemma?:
Automatic dyadic completion from sin to suf- Moral evaluation shapes factual belief. Social
fering. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Psychological and Personality Science, 4(3),
General, 143(4), 1600–1615. 316–323.
Gray, K., Waytz, A., & Young, L. (2012). The Mill, J. S. (1861). Utilitarianism. New York: Ox-
moral dyad: A fundamental template unifying ford University Press.
moral judgment. Psychological Inquiry, 23, Monroe, A. E., Guglielmo, S., & Malle, B. F.
206–215. (2012). Morality goes beyond mind percep-
Gray, K., Young, L., & Waytz, A. (2012). Mind tion. Psychological Inquiry, 23(2), 179–184.
perception is the essence of morality. Psycho- Nichols, S. (2002). Norms with feeling: Towards
logical Inquiry, 23, 101–124. a psychological account of moral judgment.
Greene, J. D. (2013). Moral tribes: Emotion, rea- Cognition, 84(2), 221–236.
son, and the gap between us and them. New Nussbaum, M. C. (2010). From disgust to hu-
York: Penguin. manity: Sexual orientation and constitutional
Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional dog and its ra- law. New York: Oxford University Press.
tional tail: A social intuitionist approach Obergefell v. Hodges, 135 S. Ct. 2071 (2015).
370 DY N A M I C M O R A L J U D G M E N T

Retrieved from www.supremecourt.gov/ Schein, C., Ritter, R., & Gray, K. (2016). Harm
opinions/14pdf/14-556_ 3204.pdf. mediates the disgust–immorality link. Emo-
Palazzolo, D. L. (2013). Electronic cigarettes and tion, 16, 862–876.
vaping: A new challenge in clinical medicine Schnall, S., Haidt, J., Clore, G. L., & Jordan, A.
and public health: A literature review. Fron- H. (2008). Disgust as embodied moral judg-
tiers in Public Health, 1, 56. Available at www. ment. Personality and Social Psychology Bul-
ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC3859972. letin, 34(8), 1096–1109.
Patterson, C. J. (2006). Children of lesbian and Scott, S., Inbar, Y., & Rozin, P. (2016). Evidence
gay parents. Current Directions in Psychologi- for absolute moral opposition to genetically
cal Science, 15(5), 241–244. modified food in the United States. Perspec-
Piaget, J. (1932). The moral judgment of the tives on Psychological Science, 11, 315–324.
child. New York: Harcourt Brace. Shweder, R. A. (2012). Relativism and universal-
Pierce, J. (2001, May 4). Opponents of pornog- ism. In D. Fassin (Ed.), A companion to moral
raphy contend it’s not “harmless” or victim- anthropology (pp. 85–102). Hoboken, NJ:
less. Retrieved October 16, 2015, from www. Wiley.
bpnews.net/10832/opponents-of-pornogra- Shweder, R. A., Mahapatra, M., & Miller, J.
phy-contend-its-not-harmless-or-victimless. (1987). Culture and moral development. In J.
Pizarro, D., Inbar, Y., & Helion, C. (2011). On Kagan & S. Lamb (Eds.), The emergence of
disgust and moral judgment. Emotion Re- morality in young children (pp. 1–83). Chi-
view, 3(3), 267–268. cago: University of Chicago Press.
Rachels, J. (1986). The elements of moral philos- Smetana, J. G. (1985). Preschool children’s con-
ophy. Philadelphia: Temple University Press. ceptions of transgressions: Effects of varying
Rottman, J., Young, L., & Kelemen, D. (2017). moral and conventional domain-related at-
The impact of testimony on children’s mor- tributes. Developmental Psychology, 21(1),
alization of novel actions. Emotion, 17(5), 18–29.
811–827. Spivey, M. J., & Dale, R. (2004). On the conti-
Royzman, E., Kim, K., & Leeman, R. F. (2015). nuity of mind: Toward a dynamical account
The curious tale of Julie and Mark: Unraveling of cognition. In B. Ross (Ed.), Psychology of
the moral dumbfounding effect. Judgment and learning and motivation (Vol. 45, pp. 87–142).
Decision Making, 10(4), 296–313. Cambridge, MA: Academic Press.
Rozin, P. (1999). The process of moralization. Sripada, C. S., & Stich, S. (2007). A framework
Psychological Science, 10(3), 218–221. for the psychology of norms. In P. Carruthers,
Schein, C., Goranson, A., & Gray, K. (2015). S. Laurence, & S. Stich (Eds.), The innate
The uncensored truth about morality. Psy- mind: Vol. 2. Culture and cognition (pp. 280–
chologist, 28(12), 982–985. 301). New York: Oxford University Press.
Schein, C., & Gray, K. (2014). The prototype Turiel, E., Hildebrandt, C., Wainryb, C., &
model of blame: Freeing moral cognition from Saltzstein, H. D. (1991). Judging social issues:
linearity and little boxes. Psychological Inqui- Difficulties, inconsistencies, and consistencies.
ry, 25(2), 236–240. Monographs of the Society for Research in
Schein, C., & Gray, K. (2015). The unifying Child Development, 56(2), 1–116.
moral dyad: Liberals and conservatives share Turiel, E., Killen, M., & Helwig, C. C. (1987).
the same harm-based moral template. Person- Morality: Its structure, functions, and vaga-
ality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 41(8), ries. In J. Kagan & S. Lamb (Eds.), The emer-
1147–1163. gence of morality in young children (pp. 155–
Schein, C., & Gray, K. (2016). Moralization and 243). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
harmification: The dyadic loop explains how Tybur, J. M., Lieberman, D., & Griskevicius, V.
the innocuous becomes harmful and wrong. (2009). Microbes, mating, and morality: Indi-
Psychological Inquiry, 27(1), 62–65. vidual differences in three functional domains
Schein, C., & Gray, K. (2017). The theory of of disgust. Journal of Personality and Social
dyadic morality: Reinventing moral judgment Psychology, 97(1), 103–122.
by redefining harm. Personality and Social Wegner, D. M., & Gray, K. (2016). The mind
Psychology Review. [Epub ahead of print] club: Who thinks, what feels, and why it mat-
Available at www.researchgate.net/publica- ters. New York: Viking.
tion/316926091_The_Theory_ of_ Dyadic_ Wheatley, T., & Haidt, J. (2005). Hypnotic dis-
Morality_ Reinventing_ Moral_ Judgment_ gust makes moral judgments more severe. Psy-
by_Redefining_Harm. chological Science, 16(10), 780–784.
CHAPTER 38

Moral Coherence Processes


and Denial of Moral Complexity

Brittany S. Liu
Sean P. Wojcik
Peter H. Ditto

How do people deal with a morally complex and contradictory


world?

Moral judgment is an intuitive phenomenon, best understood as a


process of implicit meaning making that often results in the denial of
moral complexity and the shaping of descriptive beliefs to be consis‑
tent with prescriptive intuitions.

In May 2015, legislators in Nebraska made fective in improving the public good. Rather
headlines when they overrode their gover- than recognizing the inherent moral trade-
nor’s veto of a bill to ban the death penalty, offs that have made capital punishment
making capital punishment illegal in the a divisive political issue for decades in the
state. Advocates for the ban argued that the United States, both sides in Nebraska’s re-
death penalty is neither moral nor effective, cent flare-up believe they are in a win–win
“It’s not pro-life, it’s not limited govern- situation, with both morality and the facts
ment, and doesn’t deter crime” (“Killing it,” clearly on their side.
2015). Nebraska Governor Pete Ricketts, on Scholars have long recognized individuals’
the other hand, argued that, in fact, capital tendency to mold seemingly contradictory
punishment was both: “as a Catholic, I’m information about their social world into a
confident that [capital punishment] aligns coherent whole (Cooper, 2007). Moral judg-
with Catholic catechism and that this aligns ment, we suggest, is no different, and in this
with public safety” (Bellware, 2015). chapter we explore how a desire for moral
What we find fascinating about debates coherence can lead to the denial of moral
like this is that the two opposing camps complexity and encourage people to shape
both believe they hit the rhetorical jackpot. their descriptive understanding of the world
Not only do both sides believe that their to fit their prescriptive understanding of it.
view of the death penalty has the moral high Moreover, we argue that people’s tendency
ground, but both also believe the evidence to conflate moral and practical good plays a
shows that their position would be most ef- crucial role in exacerbating political conflict

371
372 DY N A M I C M O R A L J U D G M E N T

by leading individuals and groups with dif- toward a point of maximal internal consis-
fering moral values to hold differing factual tency or “coherence.” That is, a coherence
beliefs as well. perspective depicts people as striving to
organize and integrate available informa-
tion in a way that includes both “rational”
Historical Context bottom-up influences (e.g., adjusting conclu-
sions to fit facts) and less rational top-down
Leon Festinger’s (1957) seminal volume ones (e.g., adjusting facts to fit conclusions).
on cognitive dissonance theory reflected a Coherence was originally conceived of in
deeper Zeitgeist in psychology, recognizing terms of the logical consistency between be-
that humans are fundamentally motivated lief elements, but later work has conceptu-
to simplify and organize their social worlds alized coherence more broadly, recognizing
(Abelson, 1968). Over the years, new theo- that people do not merely favor beliefs that
ries have challenged, amended, or extended fit together logically but are consistent at an
specific aspects of Festinger’s original treat- affective or evaluative level as well (Simon,
ment (e.g., Bem, 1972; Harmon-Jones, Amo- Stenstrom, & Read, 2015; Thagard, 2006).
dio, Harmon-Jones, 2009; Simon, Snow, & Importantly, the idea that individuals ad-
Read, 2004; Steele, 1988), but all embrace just beliefs to maintain a coherent and com-
the core notion that individuals strive to forting view of the world has not been lost
construct an internally consistent world in on researchers interested in moral reason-
which beliefs and feelings about oneself and ing. Struck by people’s inclination to blame
others fit together coherently. victims of misfortune for their own fate,
The desire for cognitive consistency can Melvin Lerner (Lerner & Simmons, 1966;
motivate rational, evidence-based reason- Lerner, 1980) traced this tendency to a core
ing, such as when individuals adjust a gen- desire to live in a just world—a world where
eral belief based on incoming factual in- people get what they deserve and deserve
formation relevant to that belief. But the what they get. Unfortunately, maintaining
popularity of cognitive consistency theories belief in a world of just deserts often re-
has flowed primarily from their prediction quires people to adjust attributions of blame
of motivated or “backward” forms of rea- and responsibility such that victims seem
soning in which normative decision pro- to deserve the misfortunes that befall them
cesses are, in effect, reverse engineered to (Bieneck & Krahé, 2011; Kleinke & Meyer,
produce the coherent pattern of beliefs that 1990; Lerner & Miller, 1978).
people desire. Cognitive dissonance theory, At a broader level, the social intuitionist
for example, rose in prominence above its view of moral judgment posits a similar ten-
many theoretical competitors largely be- dency to recruit beliefs that support moral
cause of a series of ingenious experiments feelings (Haidt, 2001, 2012). Building on
demonstrating how the normative process the philosophy of Hume (1740/1985) and
of attitudes guiding behavior could be re- the psychology of Zajonc (1980), the intu-
versed, producing counterintuitive effects itionist view of moral judgment argues that
in which behavior seemed to guide atti- moral evaluation is not the principled affair
tudes instead (e.g., Aronson & Mills, 1959; envisioned in the theories of Kohlberg (1969)
Festinger & Carlsmith, 1959). and Turiel (1983). Rather, moral evaluations
Research on explanatory coherence pro- most typically result from “gut” reactions
cesses explicitly incorporates this notion that people support post hoc by recruiting
of multidirectional influence into theories principles consistent with their moral intu-
of cognitive consistency (Read, Vanman, itions in order to explain and justify them to
& Miller, 1997; Thagard, 2004). Drawing others (Haidt, Koller, & Dias, 1993).
inspiration from work on neural networks
and parallel constraint satisfaction process-
es (Simon, Pham, Le, & Holyoak, 2001), Theoretical Stance
coherence-based models adopt a dynamic
view of consistency seeking in which beliefs, Our conceptualization of moral coherence
feelings, goals, and actions mutually influ- processes builds on this prior work and can
ence each other and are adjusted iteratively be described in three key assertions.
 Moral Coherence Processes 373

Moral Judgments Are Subject are judged as moral or immoral in and of


to Coherence Pressures themselves, independent of their conse-
quences. Consider the footbridge variation
There is little reason to assume that moral
of the famous trolley dilemma. Most people
and nonmoral judgments involve fundamen-
faced with this dilemma respond that push-
tally different psychological processes. In
ing a large man in front of an oncoming
particular, there is good reason to expect train is immoral, even when sacrificing this
moral judgment to be highly susceptible to one life would save the lives of many others
the motivated reasoning processes that have (Thomson, 1985). This notion that certain
been well documented across a wide variety acts (and objects) are “sacred” or “protect-
of social judgments (Ditto, Pizarro, & Tan- ed” from normal cost–benefit calculations is
nenbaum, 2009; Kunda, 1990). Moral judg- seen by many as an essential aspect of moral
ments are inherently evaluative; they are thinking (Atran, Axelrod, & Davis, 2007;
judgments about whether acts (and the peo- Baron & Spranca, 1997; Bartels & Medin,
ple who engage in them) are good (morally) 2007; Tetlock, 2003), and it forms the basis
or bad (morally). Moral reasoning is never for the kinds of principled moral stands that
value-neutral; moral judgment is moral eval- people typically see as both admirable and
uation. Moreover, moral evaluation is a par- inspirational, even when the outcomes they
ticularly important kind of evaluation for produce are less than ideal.
both individuals and social groups. Likely
due to the crucial role of moral evaluation in
promoting cooperative group behavior (Fehr Complexity 2: Moral Culpability
& Gächter, 2002; Haidt, 2012; Henrich Despite our preference for a morally just
et al., 2006), few topics inflame passions world in which only bad acts result in bad
like questions of right and wrong, and few outcomes and bad things only happen to bad
things drive our impressions of others more people, morally bad outcomes do not neces-
than their moral virtues and moral failings. sarily imply either a morally culpable actor
In short, morality is something that people or a morally deserving victim. An act is only
think about often and care about deeply itself morally bad if the consequences are
(Hofmann, Wisneski, Brandt, & Skitka, something the actor intended, caused, and
2014; Skitka, Bauman, & Sargis, 2005), controlled (Malle & Knobe, 1997; Shaver,
and so it should be little surprise that moral 1985). If a driver’s brakes fail, causing the
judgments are fertile ground for motivated, death of an innocent pedestrian, the out-
coherence-based reasoning. come is tragic, but no moral shadow is cast
upon the driver as long as the brake mal-
Incoherence Is a Frequent Feature function is judged to be “accidental” (i.e.,
of Moral Evaluation the driver did not intend, cause, or have con-
trol over the mechanical failure). Similarly,
A coherent moral view is one in which the being struck by a runaway car should ratio-
moral quality of actors and their acts match- nally have no implications for the deceased
es the moral quality of the outcomes they pedestrian’s moral status.
produce. But the potential for moral inco-
herence is high because of two complexities
in the relation between the morality of ac- Coherence Pressures Shape Factual Beliefs
tors/acts and the morality of outcomes. to Support Moral Intuitions
How, then, do people respond to what is
Complexity 1: Moral Stands often a morally incoherent world? Over a
half century of psychological research sug-
The acts people perceive as most moral are gests that mental conflict of this kind is
not always the acts that produce the best unstable and tends to initiate cognitive pro-
consequences. Classic moral dilemmas, for cesses that resolve or minimize feelings of in-
example, typically pit consequentialist in- consistency (Abelson, 1968; Festinger, 1957;
tuitions, in which the act that produces Read et al., 1997). Interestingly, however, the
the best consequences seems most moral, notion that people strive to resolve feelings of
against deontological ones, in which acts moral conflict, just as they strive to reduce
374 DY N A M I C M O R A L J U D G M E N T

other forms of cognitive inconsistency, is not the actor’s intentions, desires, and level of
well recognized in contemporary research control in a way that supports an attribution
on moral judgment. For example, in research of blame. Similarly, if an individual is the
involving moral dilemmas such as the foot- victim of bad consequences, there should be
bridge problem, individuals are faced with a some desire to see that victim as deserving of
no-win choice between endorsing a morally those consequences.
distasteful act (e.g., killing an innocent man) Overall, a desire for coherent patterns of
and rejecting that act and with it the compel- moral beliefs works to dampen down moral
ling logic of a favorable cost–benefit analysis complexity and promote a morally consil-
(e.g., one casualty is better than five). The ient worldview in which the morality of ac-
clear (if implicit) assumption in this research tors and acts matches the consequences they
tradition is that individuals struggle their produce. Coherence processes often produce
way to either a deontological or a consequen- normatively appropriate judgments, such as
tialist conclusion, and then simply live with evaluating acts as more moral to the extent
the unavoidable downside of their either–or that they produce morally beneficial out-
decision (cf., Greene et al., 2004). comes or attributing greater moral blame
A coherence perspective, however, pre- to actors who intend and desire morally bad
dicts instead that people should struggle to outcomes. But they can also motivate back-
resolve the conflict between deontological ward forms of reasoning in which descrip-
and consequentialist intuitions (Ditto & Liu, tive beliefs about the positivity or negativity
2011). Because the implicit nature of moral of outcomes, or about an individual’s degree
intuitions makes them difficult to change, of intention or control over his or her behav-
coherence pressures should operate primar- ior, are altered in ways that support moral
ily to bring beliefs about the costs and bene- intuitions and motivations.
fits of a given action in line with an individu-
al’s gut moral reactions. Thus, an individual
experiencing strong moral distaste toward Evidence
pushing an innocent man to his death might
inflate the moral costs of that action (e.g., Our own research on moral coherence pro-
vividly imagine the pain and suffering the cesses has focused primarily on people’s
act would inflict on the individual and his tendency to coordinate beliefs about the mo-
loved ones) and minimize the moral benefits rality of acts with beliefs about the conse-
(e.g., reconsider the likelihood that a single quences of those acts. An extensive literature
man is actually large enough to stop the on motivated judgments of culpability and
train from killing the others on the tracks). control in moral evaluation, however, also
This type of “motivated consequentialism” supports the moral coherence perspective. In
(Liu & Ditto, 2013) would incline people the following sections, we first review evi-
toward coherent, conflict-free moral beliefs dence for moral coherence processes in these
in which the act that feels right morally is two domains before identifying several other
also the act that produces the most favorable moral judgment phenomena that can be sub-
practical consequences. sumed under the moral coherence banner.
A similar process should operate in judg-
ments of moral culpability. If an individual’s
Coherence and Consequences
behavior results in consequences perceived
as immoral (e.g., harm to other persons, In our initial studies of moral coherence,
animals, the environment), a coherence per- we sought to directly examine whether
spective predicts that observers will be most people tend to deny morally complex views
comfortable if they can blame that indi- of acts and their consequences and instead
vidual for those bad consequences (i.e., the construct a reality in which moral and fac-
bad consequences did not occur randomly tual beliefs fit together. In one study (Liu
but were caused by a malevolent actor or & Ditto, 2013), we surveyed over 1,500
a deserving target). Because moral blame participants concerning their moral beliefs
requires that actors be held responsible for about four controversial issues (capital pun-
their behavior, coherence pressures should ishment, embryonic stem cell research, en-
operate to adjust descriptive beliefs about hanced interrogation, and condom educa-
 Moral Coherence Processes 375

tion for high school students). We first asked ists, that those who see the death penalty as
for evaluations of the “inherent” (i.e., deon- morally wrong believe it is wrong because
tological) morality of relevant policies; that they believe it has few benefits and many
is, to what extent an act is morally bad or costs. In order to directly test the key moral
good independent of its consequences (e.g., coherence proposition that moral intuitions
the death penalty is morally wrong even if actually shape factual beliefs, we devised an
it prevents violent crime). We then asked a experimental design in which moral intu-
series of questions assessing factual beliefs itions were manipulated and their effect on
about the costs and benefits surrounding cost–benefit beliefs examined (Liu & Ditto,
these issues (e.g., the deterrent efficacy of 2013). We measured participants’ moral and
capital punishment, the likelihood of wrong- factual beliefs about capital punishment
ful convictions). Judgments across all four before and after they read an essay advo-
issues showed an identical pattern. Although cating either for the inherent morality or
moral feelings about the issues varied sub- inherent immorality of capital punishment.
stantially across people, individual partici- Importantly, the essays contained only pure-
pants seldom experienced these controver- ly deontological arguments for or against
sial issues as inherently dilemmic. Rather, the death penalty, with neither essay includ-
a strong and consistent relation was found ing any mention of capital punishment’s po-
for judgments about each issue, such that the tential costs or benefits. The essays success-
more an act was seen as inherently immoral, fully changed moral evaluations of capital
the more participants expected it to produce punishment; those reading the anti-capital
few benefits and substantial costs. punishment essay came to see the death pen-
Other data support the robustness of this alty as more immoral, and those reading the
pattern. We have found the identical pattern pro–capital punishment essay came to see
of morality-consequences coordination in the death penalty as more moral. More cru-
judgments about global warming, marijua- cially, the essays also changed participants’
na use, vegetarianism, casual sex, and same- beliefs about the effectiveness of the death
sex marriage. With same-sex marriage, for penalty, even though no information about
example, the more participants believed effectiveness was included in the essays. As
it was inherently morally right, the more predicted, participants tipped toward seeing
they believed that legalizing same-sex mar- capital punishment as inherently immoral
riage would confer economic benefits and also moved toward believing that it had
the more they disagreed that it would open greater costs (e.g., innocents were more like-
legal avenues for other nontraditional mar- ly to be executed) and fewer benefits (e.g.,
riages, such as polygamy. The same pattern it was unlikely to prevent crime), whereas
also holds when individuals judge artificial those encouraged to see capital punishment
moral scenarios, such as the footbridge di- as inherently moral moved toward believing
lemma. Compared with people who believed it had greater benefits and fewer costs. This
that pushing the large man onto the tracks effect is not limited to capital punishment.
was morally acceptable, people who found Ames and Lee (2015) found that people’s
it inherently immoral to sacrifice one life to moral intuitions about enhanced interroga-
save others also believed that sacrificing the tions shaped their interpretations of facts.
man would result in a lower probability of Participants read a scenario in which a ter-
success at stopping the trolley and that the rorist plot was foiled thanks to coerced and
man’s pain would be more severe (Liu & noncoerced information from an interroga-
Ditto, 2013). What is notable about all of tion. Participants who believed enhanced
these findings is how few people acknowl- interrogations are morally acceptable also
edge a complicated moral world in which thought the coerced information was more
morally good acts can have negative trade- valuable than noncoerced information.
offs. Instead, most of us seem to experience In sum, these studies demonstrate across
a simpler, more coherent moral world in a wide variety of real and artificial moral
which the acts we see as most moral are also dilemmas that people perceive a strong con-
the acts we believe yield the best outcomes. nection between moral goodness and prac-
One might argue that the findings above tical effectiveness and that, consistent with
simply reflect people as good consequential- the logic of moral coherence, people alter
376 DY N A M I C M O R A L J U D G M E N T

their factual beliefs about the costs and ben- led people to increase not only their belief
efits of actions to fit their moral evaluation that those specific actions were freely chosen
of those actions. but also their belief that all of humankind is
capable of free action. In one example, stu-
dents who believed a fellow classmate had
Coherence and Culpability
cheated on an exam reported higher belief
Moral evaluations also involve descriptive on a measure of free will belief than students
beliefs about the extent to which actions not informed of a cheating incident. Even
are intended, caused, and controlled by the when people are told to assume a completely
actor. The normative principle that people deterministic universe, they will absolve an
should receive blame only for behavior that individual of moral responsibility for mor-
they intend, cause, and control is well repre- ally neutral acts but insist that a person com-
sented in both the legal system and the judg- mitting a morally heinous act (e.g., murder-
ments of everyday people (Aspinwall, Brown, ing his family) is still morally responsible for
& Tabery, 2012; Shariff et al., 2014). But a that action (Nichols & Knobe, 2007).
wealth of research demonstrates that people In sum, research on judgments of culpa-
engage in the reverse inference process as bility provides strong support for the opera-
well: When motivated to blame and punish tion of coherence processes in moral judg-
others, people construct morally culpable ment. In a coherent world, morally bad
agents by adjusting their descriptive beliefs outcomes only result from morally bad acts,
about intention, causation, and control. and people adjust their beliefs about blame,
Infants as young as 6 months old attribute responsibility, and control to fit this pattern.
more agency for bad outcomes than for good
ones (Hamlin & Baron, 2014), and a simi-
Additional Evidence Consistent
lar asymmetry has been found repeatedly in
with Moral Coherence
studies on adults’ attributions of intention.
Research on the “side-effect effect,” for ex- In this section we briefly review several
ample, demonstrates that incidental effects other lines of research in moral psychology
of identical actions are perceived as more that are consistent with a moral coherence
intended when those side effects are mor- perspective.
ally bad (e.g., harmful to the environment)
than when they are morally good (e.g., help-
Outcome Bias
ful to the environment; Knobe, 2003; Knobe
& Burra, 2006; Leslie, Knobe, & Cohen, Highly related to research on moral culpa-
2006; Pettit & Knobe, 2009). bility is a separate literature on outcome
People who perform morally harmful ac- bias in moral judgment (Allison, Mackie,
tions are also perceived as having more con- & Messick, 1996; Baron & Hershey, 1988;
trol over and being more causally responsible Gino, Shu, & Bazerman, 2010; Mazzocco,
for outcomes compared with those who per- Alicke, & Davis, 2004; Walster, 1966).
form morally ambiguous or positive actions People’s tendency to use the consequences of
(Alicke, 2000; Cushman, Knobe, & Sinnott- acts to judge their morality is both a feature
Armstrong, 2008; Phillips & Knobe, 2009). of moral reasoning—it is the foundational
In one clever demonstration of this effect, a normative principle underlying a conse-
young man involved in a traffic accident was quentialist moral ethic—and a bug—in that
seen as more causally responsible for the ac- it leads to irrational patterns of judgment
cident when he was rushing home to hide a such as identical acts being evaluated dif-
vial of cocaine from his parents than when ferently depending on the severity of their
he was rushing home to hide their anniver- consequences. Walster (1966), for example,
sary present (Alicke, 1992). gave participants identical descriptions of a
Importantly, the desire to assign respon- driver whose parked car accidentally rolled
sibility for immoral actions can extend to backward down a hill, but manipulated the
the human capacity for moral responsibil- severity of the consequences. The driver
ity in general. Clark et al. (2014) found that was judged more harshly (more careless and
exposure to the immoral actions of others more responsible) when the very same ac-
 Moral Coherence Processes 377

tion fortuitously had minor consequences and participants told that a man left a res-
(it hit a tree stump and dented the fender) taurant without paying his bill on purpose
than when the consequences were more remembered the total bill being higher than
serious (it rolled into a store, injuring two did participants who were told the man did
people). This pattern is robust (Mazzocco it by accident (Pizarro, Laney, Morris, &
et al., 2004) and nicely demonstrates the Loftus, 2006). Similarly, Gray (2012) found
kind of multidirectional influence captured that shocks hurt less, massages seem more
by the coherence perspective. In our origi- pleasurable, and candy tastes sweeter when
nal work on motivated cost–benefit analyses the shocking, massaging, and candy giving
(Liu & Ditto, 2013), people infer the severity is said to be well rather than ill intentioned.
of consequences from moral evaluations of
the action. The outcome bias shows the op-
Biased Assimilation
posite pattern of influence (the morality of
an action is inferred from the severity of its A long line of research documents people’s
consequences). tendency to derogate factual information
that conflicts with their moral values (e.g.,
Ames & Lee, 2015; Lord & Taylor, 2009).
Dyadic Completion
People treat scientific evidence that supports
The dyadic view of morality championed morally distasteful policies as less valid than
by Gray and colleagues (Gray, Waytz, & identical evidence that supports more mor-
Young, 2012; Gray & Wegner, 2009) posits ally acceptable policies (e.g., Lord, Ross, &
a process of post hoc belief construction that Lepper, 1979) and downplay the seriousness
is very similar to our broader view of moral of issues (e.g., climate change) surround-
coherence. Gray argues for a fundamental ing policies that clash with moral world
dyadic template underlying all moral judg- views (e.g., government regulation of emis-
ments in which one individual (the agent) sion levels; Campbell & Kay, 2014; Kahan,
acts in a way that intentionally harms or Braman, Slovic, Gastil, & Cohen, 2007;
helps a second individual (the patient). If Kahan, Jenkins-Smith, & Braman, 2011).
either component of this dyadic template is When people cannot defend their moral be-
not readily available (i.e., there is no obvi- liefs by dismissing research or downplaying
ous agent or patient), people construct them the severity of problems, they often resort
through a process Gray calls dyadic comple- to framing their beliefs as not amenable to
tion. That is, exposure to harmed patients scientific study (Friesen, Campbell, & Kay,
(e.g., victims of a natural disaster) motivates 2015; Munro, 2010). These strategies allow
the construction of a culpable agent (e.g., an individual to maintain a coherent moral
God; Gray & Wegner, 2010), and exposure worldview in which one’s moral beliefs are
to agents or acts perceived as morally offen- supported (or at least not contradicted) by
sive (e.g., masturbation) motivates the con- scientific evidence.
struction of patients who have been harmed
(e.g., the masturbator him- or herself; Gray,
Additional Evidence Needed to Support
Schein, & Ward, 2014).
Moral Coherence
Although a wealth of research in moral
Intentional Harm
psychology is subsumable under the label
Several studies have shown that people per- of moral coherence, less research has been
ceive intentional acts as having more ex- done to test its predictions directly and
treme consequences than unintentional acts specifically. In particular, additional ex-
(Ames & Fiske, 2013; Gray, 2012), a pattern perimental research would help to better un-
consistent with a moral coherence perspec- derstand the causal relation between moral
tive (the worse the actor is judged morally, intuitions and cost–benefit beliefs. Ideally,
the worse the consequences of his or her this work would examine the relation across
actions should be). People give higher dol- multiple moral issues and various methods
lar estimates for intentional damages than of manipulating moral intuitions and moti-
unintentional ones (Ames & Fiske, 2013), vations. Research on moral coherence could
378 DY N A M I C M O R A L J U D G M E N T

also build on research examining coherence coherent world in which the morality of ac-
processes in other domains (e.g., evaluations tors, acts, and outcomes align.
of legal evidence), which has sometimes used Moral coherence processes have both the-
experimental designs in which judgments oretical and practical implications. Theoret-
are assessed at multiple time points to track ically, moral coherence challenges the field’s
iterative changes in belief elements over time prevailing hydraulic view of consequentialist
(e.g., Simon et al., 2001; Simon et al., 2015), and deontological judgment (Ditto & Liu,
a key prediction of coherence-based models. 2011; Liu & Ditto, 2013). Like the intuition-
Another important focus for future re- ist view of moral judgment from which it
search should be identifying important mod- derives, our moral coherence view suggests
erators and boundary conditions of moral that, rather than reasoning their way to
coherence processes. Liu and Ditto (2013), moral conclusions using either deontologi-
for example, identified three consistent cal or consequentialist logic, people’s moral
moderators of the relation between moral justifications are guided by visceral reac-
evaluation and factual beliefs. Greater moral tions about rightness or wrongness (Haidt,
conviction about an issue, greater self-per- 2001). As such, rather than choosing either
ceived knowledge about the issue, and great- a deontological or consequentialist path to a
er political conservatism were all found to moral evaluation—the view endorsed either
be associated with a “tighter” coordination implicitly or explicitly by virtually all con-
between moral and factual beliefs. Identify- temporary research in moral psychology—a
ing moderators is helpful both practically (to moral coherence view suggests that people
understand the ecological conditions under should be inclined to embrace any justifica-
which one would expect research findings to tion that coheres with and supports their
apply and not apply) and theoretically (mod- moral intuitions, whether that justification
erators often provide hints about the nature is a broad deontological principle, informa-
of underlying psychological processes). tion about consequences, or both. As Baron
Finally, moral coherence makes a number and Spranca (1997) cleverly noted, “people
of interesting predictions that can be ex- want to have their non-utilitarian cake and
plored about everyday phenomena in which eat it too.” Our data confirm that people sel-
prescriptive and descriptive judgments might dom advocate a solely deontological position
become intertwined. Do people judge the but, rather, support their seemingly princi-
attractiveness of moral villains and moral pled views with motivated consequentialist
exemplars differently? How about the objec- crutches.
tive humor of a morally distasteful versus At the practical level, the desire for moral
morally neutral joke? Will people evaluate coherence can perturb how people ascribe
products from morally admirable compa- moral culpability. One unfortunate example
nies as more effective (or of better quality is a common tendency to see victims of rape,
generally) than identical products from com- poverty, and other misfortunes as partly re-
panies seen in a more negative moral light? sponsible for their own circumstances (Lern-
er, 1980; Ryan, 1971). But moral coherence
can affect judgments about perpetrators as
Conclusion well. A wealth of research now shows that
the more morally repugnant an act, the more
Morality is about hard choices. Moral de- intention and control is attributed to the per-
cisions often involve situations in which petrator (Alicke, 2000; Clark et al., 2014).
something bad must be done to produce This may help explain why decisions about
something good, and they frequently con- whether to try young defendants as adults
front individuals with dilemmas about doing often seem more a function of the abhor-
the “right” thing, when doing the “wrong” rence of the crime than of factors related to
thing would be easier or even produce a bet- their ability to comprehend and control their
ter outcome. The moral coherence processes actions (Ghetti & Redlich, 2001).
we have described explain how people make Finally, moral coherence processes also
difficult moral choices easier by rejecting help make sense of the immense challenges
this complexity in favor of a simpler, more facing fruitful bipartisan cooperation in the
 Moral Coherence Processes 379

corrosive, hyperpartisan atmosphere of con- (2012). The double-edged sword: Does bio-
temporary American politics. Liberals and mechanism increase or decrease judges’ sen-
conservatives have well-documented differ- tencing of psychopaths? Science, 337(6096),
ences in their moral sensibilities that pres- 846–849.
Atran, S., Axelrod, R., & Davis, R. (2007). Sa-
ent challenges to political compromise (e.g.,
cred barriers to conflict resolution. Science,
Graham et al., 2013), but it often seems as 317, 1039–1040.
though liberals and conservatives have dif- Baron, J., & Hershey, J. C. (1988). Outcome bias
ferent factual realities as well. Whether it in decision evaluation. Journal of Personality
is the existence of anthropogenic climate and Social Psychology, 54(4), 569–579.
change, or whether capital punishment de- Baron, J., & Spranca, M. (1997). Protected val-
ters future crime, liberals and conservatives ues. Organizational Behavior and Human
often bring to the discussion their own quite Decision Processes, 70, 1–16.
different sets of facts. Our desire for a mor- Bartels, D. M., & Medin, D. L. (2007). Are mor-
ally coherent world can lead to a false align- ally-motivated decision makers insensitive to
the consequences of their choices? Psychologi-
ment of prescriptive and descriptive beliefs
cal Science, 18, 24–28.
that can exacerbate conflict in morally di- Bellware, K. (2015, May 26). Nebraska Gov.
verse societies. It is difficult enough to re- Pete Ricketts vetoes bill that would repeal
solve differences of moral opinion, but when the death penalty. Huffington Post. Retrieved
differing moral beliefs affect the interpreta- from www.huffingtonpost.com/2015/05/26/
tion of science, evidence, and facts, bridging nebraska-death-penalty-veto_ n_ 7445592.
moral divides becomes exponentially more html.
challenging. Bem, D. J. (1972). Self-perception theory. In L.
Berkowitz (Ed.), Advances in experimental so-
cial psychology (Vol. 6, pp. 1–62). New York:
REFERENCES Academic Press.
Bieneck, S., & Krahé, B. (2011). Blaming the vic-
Abelson, R. P. (1968). Psychological implication. tim and exonerating the perpetrator in cases
In R. P. Abelson, E. Aronson, W. J. McGuire, of rape and robbery: Is there a double stan-
T. M. Newcomb, M. J. Rosenberg, & P. H. dard? Journal of Interpersonal Violence, 26,
Tannenbaum (Eds.), Theories of cognitive 1785–1797.
consistency: A sourcebook (pp. 112–139). Campbell, T. H., & Kay, A. C. (2014). Solution
Chicago: Rand McNally. aversion: On the relation between ideology
Alicke, M. D. (1992). Culpable causation. Jour- and motivated disbelief. Journal of Personal-
nal of Personality and Social Psychology, 63, ity and Social Psychology, 107(5), 809–824.
368–378. Clark, C. J., Luguri, J. B., Ditto, P. H., Knobe,
Alicke, M. D. (2000). Culpable control and the J., Shariff, A. F., & Baumeister, R. F. (2014).
psychology of blame. Psychological Bulletin, Free to punish: A motivated account of free
126, 556–574. will belief. Journal of Personality and Social
Allison, S. T., Mackie, D. M., & Messick, D. M. Psychology, 106, 501–513.
(1996). Outcome biases in social perception: Cooper, J. (2007). Cognitive dissonance: Fifty
Implications for dispositional inference, atti- years of a classic theory. Thousand Oaks, CA:
tude change, stereotyping, and social behav- SAGE.
ior. Advances in Experimental Social Psychol- Cushman, F., Knobe, J., & Sinnott-Armstrong, W.
ogy, 28, 53–94. (2008). Moral appraisals affect doing/allowing
Ames, D. L., & Fiske, S. T. (2013). Intentional judgments. Cognition, 108(1), 281–289.
harms are worse, even when they’re not. Psy- Ditto, P. H., & Liu, B. (2011). Deontological dis-
chological Science, 24, 1755–1762. sonance and the consequentialist crutch. In M.
Ames, D. R., & Lee, A. J. (2015). Tortured be- Mikulincer & P. Shaver (Eds.), The social psy-
liefs: How and when prior support for torture chology of morality: Exploring the causes of
skews the perceived value of coerced informa- good and evil (pp. 51–70). Washington, DC:
tion. Journal of Experimental Social Psychol- American Psychological Association.
ogy, 60, 86–92. Ditto, P. H., Pizarro, D. A., & Tannenbaum, D.
Aronson, E., & Mills, J. (1959). The effect of se- (2009). Motivated moral reasoning. In D. M.
verity of initiation on liking for a group. Jour- Bartels, C. W. Bauman, L. J. Skitka, & D. L.
nal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, 59, Medin (Eds.), The psychology of learning and
177–181. motivation (Vol. 50, pp. 307–338). Burling-
Aspinwall, L. G., Brown, T. R., & Tabery, J. ton, MA: Academic Press.
380 DY N A M I C M O R A L J U D G M E N T

Fehr, E., & Gächter, S. (2002). Altruistic punish- people are divided by politics and religion.
ment in humans. Nature, 415(6868), 137–140. New York: Pantheon.
Festinger, L. (1957). A theory of cognitive dis- Haidt, J., Koller, S. H., & Dias, M. G. (1993).
sonance. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Affect, culture, and morality, or is it wrong to
Press. eat your dog? Journal of Personality and So-
Festinger, L., & Carlsmith, J. M. (1959). Cog- cial Psychology, 65, 613–628.
nitive consequences of forced compliance. Hamlin, J. K., & Baron, A. S. (2014). Agency at-
Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, tribution in infancy: Evidence for a negativity
58(2), 203–210. bias. PLOS ONE, 9(5), e96112.
Friesen, J. P., Campbell, T. H., & Kay, A. C. Harmon-Jones, E., Amodio, D. M., & Harmon-
(2015). The psychological advantage of unfal- Jones, C. (2009). Action-based model of disso-
sifiability: The appeal of untestable religious nance: A review, integration, and expansion of
and political ideologies. Journal of Personality conceptions of cognitive conflict. Advances in
and Social Psychology, 108, 515–529. Experimental Social Psychology, 41, 119–166.
Ghetti, S., & Redlich, A. D. (2001). Reactions Henrich, J., McElreath, R., Barr, A., Ensminger,
to youth crime: Perceptions of accountability J., Barrett, C., Bolyanatz, A., . . . Ziker, J.
and competency. Behavioral Sciences and the (2006). Costly punishment across human so-
Law, 19, 33–53. cieties. Science, 312, 1767–1770.
Gino, F., Shu, L. L., & Bazerman, M. H. (2010). Hofmann, W., Wisneski, D. C., Brandt, M. J., &
Nameless + harmless = blameless: When seem- Skitka, L. J. (2014). Morality in everyday life.
ingly irrelevant factors influence judgment Science, 345(6202), 1340–1343.
of (un)ethical behavior. Organizational Be- Hume, D. (1985). A treatise of human nature.
havior and Human Decision Processes, 111, London: Penguin. (Original work published
102–115. 1740)
Graham, J., Haidt, J., Koleva, S., Motyl, M., Iyer, Kahan, D. M., Braman, D., Slovic, P., Gastil, J.,
R., Wojcik, S. P., & Ditto, P. H. (2013). Moral & Cohen, G. L. (2007). The second national
foundations theory: The pragmatic validity of risk and culture study: Making sense of—and
moral pluralism. Advances in Experimental making progress in—the American culture
Social Psychology, 47, 55–130. war of fact. Harvard Law School Program on
Gray, K. (2012). The power of good intentions: Risk Regulation (Research Paper No. 08–26).
Perceived benevolence soothes pain, increases Available at https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/pa-
pleasure, and improves taste. Social Psycho- pers.cfm?abstract_id=1017189.
logical and Personality Science, 3, 639–645. Kahan, D. M., Jenkins-Smith, H., & Braman, D.
Gray, K., Schein, C., & Ward, A. F. (2014). The (2011). Cultural cognition of scientific consen-
myth of harmless wrongs in moral cognition: sus. Journal of Risk Research, 14, 147–174.
Automatic dyadic completion from sin to suf- Killing it: Nebraska’s ban is another sign of
fering. Journal of Experimental Psychology: the decline in support for the death penalty.
General, 143, 1600–1615. (2015, May 30). The Economist. Retrieved
Gray, K., Waytz, A., & Young, L. (2012). The from www.economist.com/news/united-
moral dyad: A fundamental template unifying states/ 21652277-nebraskas-ban-another-
moral judgment. Psychological Inquiry, 23, sign-decline-support-death-penalty-killing-it.
206–215. Kleinke, C., & Meyer, C. (1990). Evaluation of
Gray, K., & Wegner, D. M. (2009). Moral type- rape victims by men and women with high
casting: Divergent perceptions of moral agents and low beliefs in a just world. Psychology of
and moral patients. Journal of Personality and Women Quarterly, 4, 343–353.
Social Psychology, 96, 505–520. Knobe, J. (2003). Intentional action and side-
Gray, K., & Wegner, D. M. (2010). Blaming God effects in ordinary language. Analysis, 63,
for our pain: Human suffering and the divine 190–193.
mind. Personality and Social Psychology Re- Knobe, J., & Burra, A. (2006). The folk concepts
view, 14, 7–16. of intention and intentional action: A cross-
Greene, J. D., Nystrom, L. E., Engell, A. D., cultural study. Journal of Cognition and Cul-
Darley, J. D., & Cohen, J. D. (2004). The neu- ture, 6(1), 113–132.
ral bases of cognitive conflict and control in Kohlberg, L. (1969). Stage and sequence: The
moral judgment. Neuron, 44, 389–400. cognitive-developmental approach to social-
Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional dog and its ra- ization. In D. A. Goslin (Ed.), Handbook of
tional tail: A social intuitionist approach to socialization theory and research (pp. 347–
moral judgment. Psychological Review, 108, 489). Chicago: Rand McNally.
814–834. Kunda, Z. (1990). The case for motivated rea-
Haidt, J. (2012). The righteous mind: Why good soning. Psychological Bulletin, 108, 480–498.
 Moral Coherence Processes 381

Lerner, M. (1980). The belief in a just world: (Re)introducing cognitive dynamics to social
A fundamental delusion. New York: Plenum psychology. Personality and Social Psychol-
Press. ogy Review, 1, 26–53.
Lerner, M., & Miller, D. (1978). Just world re- Ryan, W. (1971). Blaming the victim. New York:
search and the attribution process: Looking Pantheon.
back and ahead. Psychological Bulletin, 85, Shariff, A. F., Greene, J. D., Karremans, J. C.,
1030–1051. Luguri, J. B., Clark, C. J., Schooler, J. W., . . .
Lerner, M. J., & Simmons, C. H. (1966). Observ- Vohs, K. D. (2014). Free will and punishment:
er’s reaction to the “innocent victim”: Com- A mechanistic view of human nature reduces
passion or rejection? Journal of Personality retribution. Psychological Science, 25, 1563–
and Social Psychology, 4, 203–210. 1570.
Leslie, A. M., Knobe, J., & Cohen, A. (2006). Shaver, K. G. (1985). The attribution of blame:
Acting intentionally and the side-effect effect: Causality, responsibility, and blameworthi-
Theory of mind and moral judgment. Psycho- ness. New York: Springer-Verlag.
logical Science, 17, 421–427. Simon, D., Pham, L. B., Le, Q. A., & Holyoak,
Liu, B. S., & Ditto, P. H. (2013). What dilem- K. J. (2001). The emergence of coherence over
ma?: Moral evaluation shapes factual beliefs. the course of decision making. Journal of Ex-
Social Psychological and Personality Science, perimental Psychology: Learning, Memory,
4, 316–323. and Cognition, 27, 1250–1260.
Lord, C. G., Ross, L., & Lepper, M. R. (1979). Simon, D., Snow, C. J., & Read, S. J. (2004).
Biased assimilation and attitude polarization: The redux of cognitive consistency theories:
The effects of prior theories on subsequently Evidence judgments by constraint satisfaction.
considered evidence. Journal of Personality Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
and Social Psychology, 37, 2098–2109. 86, 814–837.
Lord, C. G., & Taylor, C. A. (2009). Biased as- Simon, D., Stenstrom, D. M., & Read, S. J.
similation: Effects of assumptions and expec- (2015). The coherence effect: Blending cold
tations on the interpretation of new evidence. and hot cognitions. Journal of Personality and
Social and Personality Psychology Compass, Social Psychology, 109, 369–394.
3(5), 827–841. Skitka, L. J., Bauman, C. W., & Sargis, E. G.
Malle, B. F., & Knobe, J. (1997). The folk con- (2005). Moral conviction: Another contribu-
cept of intentionality. Journal of Experimen- tor to attitude strength or something more?
tal Social Psychology, 33(2), 101–121. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
Mazzocco, P. J., Alicke, M. D., & Davis, T. L. 8, 895–917.
(2004). On the robustness of outcome bias: No Steele, C. M. (1988). The psychology of self-af-
constraint by prior culpability. Basic and Ap- firmation: Sustaining the integrity of the self.
plied Social Psychology, 26, 131–146. Advances in Experimental Social Psychology,
Munro, G. D. (2010). The scientific impotence 21, 261–302.
excuse: Discounting belief-threatening scien- Tetlock, P. E. (2003). Thinking about the un-
tific abstracts. Journal of Applied Social Psy- thinkable: Coping with secular encroachments
chology, 40, 579–600. on sacred values. Trends in Cognitive Science,
Nichols, S., & Knobe, J. (2007). Moral responsi- 7, 320–324.
bility and determinism: The cognitive science Thagard, P. (2004). Coherence in thought and
of folk intuitions. Nous, 41, 663–685. action. Boston: MIT Press.
Pettit, D., & Knobe, J. (2009). The pervasive im- Thagard, P. (2006). Hot thought: Mechanisms
pact of moral judgment. Mind and Language, and applications of emotional cognition.
24(5), 586–604. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Phillips, J., & Knobe, J. (2009). Moral judgments Thomson, J. J. (1985). The trolley problem. Yale
and intuitions about freedom. Psychological Law Journal, 94, 1395–1415.
Inquiry, 20, 30–36. Turiel, E. (1983). The development of social
Pizarro, D. A., Laney, C., Morris, E. K., & Lof- knowledge: Morality and convention. Cam-
tus, E. F. (2006). Ripple effects in memory: bridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.
Judgments of moral blame can distort mem- Walster, E. (1966). Assignment of responsibility
ory for events. Memory and Cognition, 34, for an accident. Journal of Personality and So-
550–555. cial Psychology, 3, 73–79.
Read, S. J., Vanman, E. J., & Miller, L. C. Zajonc, R. B. (1980). Feeling and thinking: Pref-
(1997). Connectionism, parallel constraint erences need no inferences. American Psychol-
satisfaction processes, and gestalt principles: ogist, 35, 151–175.
CHAPTER 39

What Is Blame and Why Do We Love It?

Mark D. Alicke
Ross Rogers
Sarah Taylor

What is blame, and why do people blame so liberally even when


there are compelling reasons to mitigate it?

Blame is an automatic species of moral judgment in which eviden‑


tial criteria are revised to support an initial blame hypothesis—this
“blame validation” mode can overwhelm tendencies toward mitiga‑
tion and forgiveness.

Near the end of Anthony Burgess’s (1962) ishment, and incarceration are banished;
novel A Clockwork Orange, Alex, the hy- instead, much as in B. F. Skinner’s Walden
perviolent 15-year-old hero, is “cured” of Two (Skinner & Hayes, 1976), society is
his sickness by behavioral psychologists perfected to the point where harmful and of-
using classical conditioning. To demonstrate fensive behaviors virtually disappear, mak-
the effectiveness of the treatment, a beauti- ing blame irrelevant.
ful, scantily clad woman is paraded before Before considering whether we could
him, and just as his predilections for rape or should eliminate blame (the answer is
and murder surface, he becomes physically no!—but more about that later), it is neces-
ill and unable to act on his instincts. For the sary first to address the more fundamental
scientists, this is further proof that Alex was question of what blame is, a question that
a blameless victim of society—one whose neither we nor anyone else has yet answered
behavior could be rectified with an admix- very clearly. The reason that blame is diffi-
ture of progressive social reform and behav- cult to define is that it is both a hypothesis
ior modification. that is subject to updating as new data are
Burgess’s picture of a dystopian future received and a relatively quick summary
satirizes the liberal view of criminality as judgment. Blame can be as reflexive as in
an accidental by-product of misguided par- the classic Harry Nilsson (1972) tearjerker:
enting and ineffective social institutions. In “You’re breaking my heart, you’re tearing it
Burgess’s prospective world, blame, pun- apart, so fuck you” or as lengthy a process

382
 What Is Blame? 383

as in an eight-month jury trial that requires initial evaluative reaction, would presum-
sifting through mountains of contradictory ably rescind their judgment and recognize
evidence. that whatever happened was an excusable
It is also important to clarify whether blip that can be attributed to unusual or
blame refers to an offense that is known to uncontrollable circumstances. Blame that
have occurred or to one that is still in ques- perseveres, therefore, impugns the character
tion. Most theories of blame, including the of the harm doer. Although forgiveness may
culpable control model of blame (CCM; occur over time, blame places a permanent
Alicke, 2000), focus on the former question, stain—even if only a smudge—on impres-
as issues related to establishing whether an sions of the blamed individual’s trustworthi-
offense actually occurred fall more naturally ness and reliability.
under the auspices of responsibility attribu- One might legitimately wonder why, if
tion. Accordingly, in the following discus- blame derives from social selection pres-
sion, we assume a potentially blameworthy sures, it is so much more intense on the part
behavior or behavior pattern and consider of the individual who is directly harmed
first the process of ascribing blame and then than it is for observers. The simple answer
whether and when blame is an effective is that individual selection pressures super-
means of social control. sede group considerations. Although the
prosperity of the group facilitates individu-
al survival, it still takes a back seat to the
Blame’s Evolutionary Heritage needs of self and kin. Nevertheless, third-
party punishment, which entails punishing
Evolutionary perspectives on social behavior others at cost to oneself, is a routine, and
assume that moral judgment originates in probably unique, facet of human social con-
the need to monitor and punish group mem- trol (Kahneman, Knetsch, & Thaler, 1986;
bers who threaten the group’s interests by Turillo, Folger, Lavelle, Umphress, & Gee,
violating established norms. As the anthro- 2002), and blame is the judgment that legiti-
pologist Christopher Boehm argues: “when mizes its application.
band members started to form consensual Explanations that reference historical sur-
moral opinions and punished deviant behav- vival needs run the risk of deemphasizing
iors and rewarded prosocial ones a new ele- aspects of human cognition and culture that
ment was added to human evolution” (2012, transform the nature of mechanisms that
p. 83). The element that Boehm refers to is originated to solve specific adaptive prob-
social selection of characteristics, especially lems. Although it makes good sense to trace
altruism, that advance the individual’s and, blame’s origins to needs for social control,
by proxy, the group’s survival prospects. and although such needs elucidate many fac-
Moral behavior, therefore, involves com- ets of blame, blame varies across times and
pliance with implicit or explicit behavioral cultures in ways that require additional ex-
guidelines, and moral judgment is the assess- planation. Furthermore, human capacities
ment of whether a group member has met or of memory, language, and imagination alter
violated these prescriptions. not only the nature of blame, retribution,
From the social selection perspective, peo- and forgiveness but also the ways in which
ple are blameworthy when they defect from these actions and emotions are manifested
group standards in a way that threatens or in social situations and the circumstances
could threaten the group’s well-being. The that hinder or facilitate them. Human blood
act of blaming, however, transcends blame- feuds, for example, fueled by enhanced
worthiness. Blame registers to oneself, and/ memory and imagery processes, have ex-
or signals to others, that the actions and tended for generations (Baumeister, 1999).
character of a group member are potentially No other species is capable of carrying on
detrimental to the general welfare. Blame is vendettas against families, clans, nations, or
not simply a judgment, therefore, but also a religious groups in this way. Most important
form of direct or indirect social control. for present purposes is the fact that blame,
Blame presupposes a character flaw or as a derivative of moral judgment, is unique-
limitation. Without this, observers, after an ly human and can be applied to harmless
384 DY N A M I C M O R A L J U D G M E N T

offenses based on ideological grounds, vis- criterial for blame but are a canonical fea-
ceral reactions, and complex emotions such ture of it (McGeer, 2013).
as feelings of envy or relative deprivation. In a recent book that explores the evolu-
Thus, whereas blame originated in moral tionary heritage and neurobiology of pun-
judgment, it is applied to perceived offenses ishment, Hoffman (2014) argues that blame
(such as breaking a heart in the Harry Nils- occurs the moment we think that a person
son song) that lie outside the bounds of what has committed a wrong and that mitigation
are normally considered moral issues. will occur much later. This is the bedrock as-
sumption of the CCM; in contrast to blame
models that precede (Shaver, 1985) and suc-
Spontaneous Evaluations ceed (Malle, Guglielmo, & Monroe, 2014)
and Reactive Attitudes: it, the CCM assumes that blame occurs nat-
Hypotheses about Blame urally and automatically and that mitigation
is the more difficult and complicated task.
P. F. Strawson’s relatively short paper titled A more precise way to depict the processes
“Freedom and Resentment” is probably of blame and mitigation or exoneration,
the most influential philosophical paper however, is to say that blame is a hypoth-
on blame (1962). Strawson introduced the esis that occurs immediately upon witness-
phrase “reactive attitudes” to refer to sen- ing a harmful or offensive action and that it
timents such as gratitude, resentment, and is subject to modification (i.e., mitigation or
indignation that occur spontaneously in exoneration) upon further consideration and
response to praiseworthy or censorious ac- evidence. In some instances, strong prior
tions. Strawson follows a long philosophi- understanding of social situations negate
cal tradition, represented most prominently blame almost immediately. People generally
in the moral philosophy of David Hume, in know what accidents look like, for example,
emphasizing the emotional component in and after an immediate anger response at
moral judgment and blame. For Hume, the being thwacked in the face by a branch that
emotional component was nearly sovereign: the hiker in front of us let go, we immedi-
“The mind of man is so formed by nature, ately recognize that he didn’t realize we were
that, upon the appearance of certain charac- so close behind and hold no grudge.
ters, dispositions, and actions it immediately More generally, it is in humans’ and other
feels the sentiment of approbation or blame; animals’ interest to be able quickly to distin-
nor are there any emotions more essential to guish intentional from unintentional harms:
its frame or constitution” (1748/2007, p. 74). Obviously, zebras who know that lions want
to eat them have an advantage over peace-
and-love zebras who think that all animals
Inclining toward Blame are God’s children. Conversely, fleeing from
or shunning others who intend to help us is
Using a terminology adapted to social- also a costly strategy.
psychological research on automatic at- Akin to Pascal’s famous wager about God,
titude activation (Fazio, 1989), we refer to it makes sense to err on the side of inten-
Strawson’s reactive attitudes as spontaneous tionality and blame. Of the two mistakes in
evaluations (Alicke, 2000). As described in Pascal’s fourfold table (assuming that God
the CCM, spontaneous evaluations are at- exists when he doesn’t; assuming that God
titudinal reactions that do not necessarily doesn’t exist when he does), the latter is pre-
entail emotions; rather, they are positive or sumably more harmful, assuming the venge-
negative evaluations of the actors involved in ful (and somewhat neurotic) deity of the Old
the event, their characters and values, their Testament who demands recognition and al-
actions, and the consequences of those ac- legiance. (Of course, if God doesn’t give a fig
tions. Although emotions are not a neces- whether you believe in him or not, then the
sary component of spontaneous evaluations, former mistake means that you will spend
they typically accompany them and modu- a lifetime passing up enticing opportunities
late the strength of the reaction. Or, as one in his name, which seems like a worse mis-
philosopher has stated it, emotions are not take—but this is a different question for a
 What Is Blame? 385

different paper.) In this same vein, assum- is a black Olympic athlete with an IQ of
ing harmful intentions is a safer policy than 175 and a family history of perfect physical
assuming benevolence, although there is, of and mental health and that she is going to
course, a price to be paid for unsubstanti- have triplets. Having scored this incredible
ated accusations, grudges, and, even worse, coup in the human gene pool, do we expect
unfounded retaliation. As Pinker states the the family to commence with the party an-
case: “good and evil are asymmetrical: there nouncements? Maybe, but maybe not. Not
are more ways to harm people than to help only do humans establish moral rules and
them, and harmful acts can hurt them to a social norms that seem irrelevant or con-
greater degree than virtuous acts can make tradictory to inclusive fitness concerns, but
them better off” (2003, p. 10). they expect people to stick to them.
According to the CCM, three elements
of control are most important in assessing
Elements of Perceived Control blame: behavior control, causal control, and
outcome control. Behavior control—also
Still, the assumption that people are pre- termed “intention of action”—is thwarted
disposed to blame obviously does not claim by reflexes, accidents, and lack of access
that they fail completely to consider evi- to information and norms. We would not
dence about intentionality, causation, and blame an epileptic who caused property
mitigating and extenuating circumstances in damage while having a grand mal seizure,
evaluating behavior. The CCM assumes that nor would we blame a foreign tourist who
the relationship between the spontaneous insulted his host because someone misin-
evaluations that incline toward blame and formed him about local norms as a practical
rational and deliberate evaluation of the evi- joke. Each of these actions is unintentional
dence is a compensatory one: In the absence in the sense that the behavior sequence was
of valenced reactions to the event, the state not initiated purposively or knowingly.
of the evidence drives the ultimate blame Causal control judgments are complicated
judgment. When spontaneous negative eval- by the fact that many causal conditions, in-
uations are strong, however, and are ignited cluding necessity and sufficiency, proximity
by heightened emotions, evidence will be in space in time to the outcome, and abnor-
skewed in a manner that supports the initial mal or counterfactual conditions, among
blame hypothesis—what Alicke, Rose, and others, are potentially relevant for blame.
Bloom (2011) have called a “blame valida- Causal control is reduced or negated by in-
tion” mode of information processing, akin tervening circumstances and by other com-
to confirmatory hypothesis testing. peting causes that reduce the actor’s unique
Although the assumptions about the pri- impact on the outcome.
macy of evaluation and blame validation Outcome control refers to whether the
processing have received most of the atten- event’s consequences occurred in the man-
tion in our empirical work, the CCM was ner that the actor desired and/or foresaw.
designed also to provide a view of evidence The absence of behavior control also indi-
evaluation grounded in perceptions of per- cates the absence of outcome control: People
sonal control. Blame, like morality more cannot be said to have controlled the out-
generally, is predicated on the assumption comes of actions that occurred accidentally,
that people can exercise control over their even if they desired them. There are, how-
needs and desires. Only a lunatic (and there ever, many ways in which intentional behav-
are some out there) would blame their cat iors can lead to outcomes that were unfore-
for returning pregnant after a night on the seen, undesired, or both, and also ways in
prowl, but many teen-age daughters would which intended outcomes can be thwarted
be deprived of the same leniency: The cat (i.e., failed attempts). Perhaps the most inter-
cannot consciously monitor and override esting cases that have been studied are those
her desires, but the daughter presumably in which people achieve desired outcomes in
can. Suppose, however, that the daughter, unforeseen ways (e.g., Pizarro, Uhlmann, &
a 15-year-old wealthy white debutante, re- Bloom, 2003). We have shown in a recent
monstrates with her parents that the father study, for example, that a pilot who is forced
386 DY N A M I C M O R A L J U D G M E N T

at gunpoint to fly a plane to Cuba is seen than if their incapacities developed due
to have had more control, and to be more to circumstances outside of their control
blameworthy, if the hijacking fortuitously (Alicke & Davis, 1990).
allows him to reunite with a girlfriend than • The mutability of an outcome influences
if this outcome does not occur, even though blame only if a decision maker was culpa-
his behavioral freedom was equally compro- ble in the events leading up to the harmful
mised in both conditions (Rogers et al., in outcome (Alicke, Davis, Buckingham, &
preparation). Zell, 2008).
In Anglo-American law and most ratio- • Socially unattractive actors are blamed
nal perspectives on moral decision making, more for harmful outcomes than social-
something very close to behavior, causal, ly attractive actors, but this effect is re-
and outcome control (without these labels) duced if extenuating circumstances are
are the decision criteria that are prescribed presented before participants learn about
for determining blame. A major assumption the facts that establish the person’s dis-
of the CCM is that reactions to unfavorable likable character than if they learn about
personalities, actions, and outcomes lead these circumstances after the unfavorable
observers to alter their perceptions of these dispositional information has had time to
decision criteria. In other words, observers’ fester (Alicke & Zell, 2009).
distaste for elements of the action sequence • Participants who learn of negative out-
and/or the people involved leads them to comes and first assess a defendant’s legal
evaluate these criteria in a way that justifies responsibility for a negligent homicide
the blame attribution they favor (see Alicke, charge see the facts of the case as more
2000). indicative of guilt than do participants
Many empirical studies now strongly sup- who do not assess legal responsibility
port the primacy of evaluative reactions in until after they evaluate the facts, suggest-
determining blame and its criteria (such as ing that the former participants justify or
intent and causation). Among these findings validate their blame attributions by alter-
from our own lab are the following. ing their perception of the facts (Alicke,
Davis, & Pezzo, 1994).
• A person who is driving over the speed • People who do good, counternormative
limit to hide a vial of cocaine is viewed things are blamed less for harmful out-
as a more significant cause of an accident comes than are those who do bad, nor-
than one who is driving at the same speed mative things, showing that evaluative
in the same circumstances to hide an an- “goodness–badness” matters more in
niversary present (Alicke, 1992, Study 1). causal citation than normativity (Alicke et
• People are seen as more causal for later al., 2011, Study 2).
events in an extended causal chain when
their initial motives are negative versus To date, research designed to test assump-
positive (Alicke, 1992, Study 4). tions of the CCM have concentrated largely
• A homeowner who shoots an intruder on judgments of causation, as causal judg-
is blamed more when the intruder turns ment was the central concern of the attribu-
out to be his daughter’s boyfriend than tional theories from which interest in blame
when he is a dangerous criminal (Alicke and responsibility first arose among social
& Davis, 1989); and judgments about psychologists. In recent studies, we have
the homeowner’s causal influence on the been extending our research to the other
victim’s death are mediated by blame at- main blame criterion—intent. Interest in this
tributions, but blame is not mediated by topic has exploded among psychologists and
causation (Alicke et al., 2011). philosophers, much of the research being di-
• Individuals whose capacities are dimin- rected at Joshua Knobe’s “side effect” prob-
ished (e.g., psychosis, anxiety disorder) lem (Knobe & Fraser, 2008). Side effects, or
are blamed more when these incapacities peripheral consequences, are outcomes that
lead to harm if these individuals contrib- decision makers realize will probably occur
uted to the development of the incapac- if they pursue their focal goal but either
ity (e.g., by experimenting with drugs) don’t care about or are willing to accept to
 What Is Blame? 387

achieve their primary goal. From the CCM their desire to blame. If, however, they sim-
perspective, the “Knobe effect,” the finding ply alter their judgments about causation,
that people ascribe more intentionality for intent, foresight, mitigation, and so on only
negative than for positive side effects, is due when they are explicitly asked about these
to participants having more negative reac- criteria, it suggests that their blame attribu-
tions to a decision maker who expresses a tions are largely emotion-driven and rela-
lack of concern for harmful consequences tively independent of the state of the evi-
(Alicke, 2008). dence.
In our present research, we have been in-
terested in what is probably the more com-
mon peripheral effect problem, that is, one Is It Bad to Blame? Should We Stop?
in which the peripheral consequence is un-
foreseen. In a recent study, for example, we Western cultural institutions—Christianity
described a journalist—Joan—who desired and the mental health community being the
either to help or impede her friend’s chances most prominent—advocate forgiveness and
of getting hired for a high-status job. In both almost uniformly condemn blame. Self-help
cases, prior to her friend’s interview, Joan se- books on blame endorse these views with
cretly slipped a sedative in her drink. In the titles such as: “Ending the Blame Game”;
good-Joan case, the sedative was intended to “Beyond Blame: Freeing Yourself from the
increase her friend’s chances (it was known Most Toxic Form of Emotional Bullsh*t”;
that the interviewer preferred calm employ- “Stop Blaming, Start Loving!”; and “Be-
ees), whereas in the bad-Joan case, the seda- yond Blame: A New Way of Resolving Con-
tive was intended to undermine her friend’s flicts in Relationships.” Clearly, there is little
chances (it was known that the interviewer benefit to holding on to useless grudges or
preferred more hyper, energetic employees). exacting ill-advised retribution.
In both instances, however, Joan’s friend Nevertheless, when cultural prescriptions
had an unforeseen allergic reaction to the clash with our fundamental human nature,
sedative and became very ill. Despite neither there are always questions about both the
character having knowledge of her allergy, soundness of these prescriptions and their
bad Joan’s unrelated motive—to prevent her feasibility. Religious views that discourage
friend from getting the job—led to height- sex outside of marriage, for example, have
ened ascriptions of intent and blame for her probably had at least a modest civilizing
friend’s illness. function throughout Western history, espe-
One important unresolved issue in stud- cially in promoting stable family arrange-
ies designed to test CCM assumptions con- ments, but have also made people feel guilty
cerns the conditions under which changes about a behavior that is as natural as eating
in the decision criteria mediate blame ef- and drinking, with especially punitive con-
fects or when they simply represent post sequences for women. And, of course, even
hoc justifications of blame attributions that with images of hellfire and damnation lurk-
have already been made. So far, we have ing in the background, even the most pious
been unable to find a consistent pattern: seem to circumvent these religious prescrip-
Sometimes judgments of causation or in- tions quite adeptly.
tention mediate blame, sometimes they do Blame instincts are less entertaining than
not. Both of these paths pose problems for sexual ones, but they are probably as natu-
the administration of justice in everyday so- ral and immediate. Cultural perspectives
cial life and in the law, although the latter on blame and forgiveness generally deem-
seems more pernicious. If people react unfa- phasize the benefits of the former and the
vorably based on their emotions or personal liabilities of the latter. Philosophers, by con-
biases and later, after considering the data trast, have noted that refraining from blame
regarding behavioral, causal, and outcome indicates a failure to take morality seriously
control, alter either their perceptions of the (Coates & Tognazzini, 2013). Furthermore,
evidence or their threshold for how much blame is an assertion of individual rights,
evidence is needed to blame, there is at least an injured party’s way of saying that she
the possibility that the facts might override or he is someone who will not be taken ad-
388 DY N A M I C M O R A L J U D G M E N T

vantage of. Conversely, failure to blame can There is good reason to believe that future
reflect an unwillingness to take a stand on developments in the biological and social
important moral matters. What would it sciences will bring into sharper relief the ge-
mean, for example, to cringe upon hearing netic and environmental determinants of be-
a person utter racial epithets but to decide havior and, even more importantly, augment
that you just can’t blame him for it? To put our ability to predict the outcome of their
it succinctly, “to foreswear blame is to fail interaction in specific situations. Harking
to value what we ought to value” (Franklin, back to the A Clockwork Orange example
2013). with which we began, the moral question
In his book on the evolution of forgive- about Alex is whether he is a victim of his
ness, McCullough (2008) notes that nation- nature and environment or whether he has
al surveys have revealed forgiveness to be the freely chosen to be a violent criminal. As
fourth most valued personal quality, which science moves closer to identifying the influ-
is perhaps unsurprising given its widespread ences that contribute to violent and aggres-
endorsement. The New Testament is filled sive behavior and, indeed, to any harmful or
with homilies about forgiveness, such as offensive actions, will people stop blaming
in Matthew 18:22–23: “Then Peter came those who exhibit them?
and said to Him, ‘Lord, how often shall my This question relates to the familiar philo-
brother sin against me and I forgive him? sophical debate between compatibilist and
Up to seven times?’ Jesus said to him, ‘I do incompatibilist positions on responsibility:
not say to you up to seven times, but up to If behavior is completely determined, can
seventy times seven.’ ” But as Bertrand Rus- anyone be held morally responsible for their
sell (1957) noted in comparing the moral- actions? In the simplest case, compatibilists
ity of Jesus unfavorably to that of Socrates, say yes, incompatibilists say no. Nonphilos-
Jesus was quite capable of vindictive fury, as ophers seem unimpressed by this issue. Ap-
in Matthew 13:41, “The Son of Man shall parently, the vast majority of people believe
send forth his angels, and they shall gather in free will in the diverse cultures in which
out of His kingdom all things that offend, it has been assessed, including the United
and them which do iniquity, and shall cast States, Hong Kong, India, and Colombia
them into a furnace of fire; there shall be (Sarkissian, Chatterjee, DeBrigard, Knobe,
wailing and gnashing of teeth.” So while the Nichols, & Sirker, 2010). Furthermore, and
New Testament may be the most influential most important, even when people believe
endorsement of forgiveness in Western cul- that an action is fully causally determined,
tures, it is by no means a universal one. they continue to ascribe moral responsibility
Psychologists, beginning at least as far (Nahmias, Morris, Nadelhoffer, & Turner,
back as Karen Horney (1937), have also 2006). From the CCM perspective, these
highlighted the evils of blame and trumpet- findings demonstrate that the strong need
ed the virtues of forgiveness. McCullough to blame supersedes abstract philosophical
(2008) notes that vindictiveness underlies considerations, an assumption that has re-
many of the personality disorders in the Di- cently been supported in an impressive series
agnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental of studies on free will and moral responsibil-
Disorders, Fifth Edition (DSM-5). One of ity by Clark and colleagues (2014).
the reasons for this, however, is that per-
sonality disorders in the DSM are almost all
externalizing disorders that involve harm to Conclusions
others—such as narcissism, passive–aggres-
siveness, and psychopathy. From a cogni- In this chapter we reviewed the psychologi-
tive-behavioral perspective, self-blame and cal functions that blame subserves and the
low self-esteem are the primary causes of process by which it occurs. We argued that
depression, which is the most common of even when complex reasoning processes are
all psychological problems. In many circum- engaged to make ultimate decisions about
stances, self-blame is a natural consequence blameworthiness, they are likely to be heav-
of failing to blame others who deserve it. ily influenced by initial blame hypotheses,
 What Is Blame? 389

especially when these are driven by strong Alicke, M. D., & Rose, D. (2012). Causal devi-
reactions of disapprobation for the actors ance. Personality and Social Psychology Com-
involved, their behavior, or for the con- pass, 6, 723–725.
sequences that ensue. Psychologists have Alicke, M. D., Rose, D., & Bloom, D. (2011).
Causation, norm violation, and culpable con-
tended to view individual blame instances
trol. Journal of Philosophy, 108, 670–696.
as rational problems to be solved, problems Alicke, M. D., & Zell, E. (2009). Social attrac-
that involve grappling with information tiveness and blame. Journal of Applied Social
about desires, motives, beliefs, causal paths, Psychology, 39, 2089–2105.
and the connection among all these with the American Psychiatric Association. (2013). Diag-
chain of consequences that behavior sets into nostic and statistical manual of mental disor-
motion. We are on board with all this but ders: DSM-5. Arlington, VA: Author.
emphasize that from a functional, evolution- Baumeister, R. F. (1999). Evil: Inside human vio-
ary perspective, blame reflects the standards lence and cruelty. New York: Freeman.
of conduct by which the group lives and con- Boehm, C. (2012). Moral origins: The evolution
tributes to maintaining order and solidarity. of virtue, altruism, and shame. New York:
Basic Books.
Those who violate the rules and are detected Burgess, A. (1962). A clockwork orange. New
are unlikely to find solace in the fact that York: Norton.
genetic and environmental influences con- Clark, C. J., Luguri, J. B., Ditto, P. H., Knobe,
tributed to their behavior and may even have J., Shariff, A. F., & Baumeister, R. F. (2014).
fully determined it. When you screw up, Free to punish: A motivated account of free
you, not your genes or your environment, will belief. Journal of Personality and Social
will be blamed and called to account. And Psychology, 106, 501–513.
for those whose moral functioning is on a Coates, D. J., & Tognazzini, N. A. (Eds.). (2013).
par with Alex’s in A Clockwork Orange, the Blame: Its nature and norms. New York: Ox-
world’s best defense attorney accompanied ford University Press.
Fazio, R. H. (1989). On the power and functional-
by a stellar crew of philosophers, psycholo-
ity of attitudes: The role of attitude accessibility.
gists, sociologists, and neuroscientists is un- In A. R. Pratkanis, S. J. Breckler, & A. G. Gre-
likely to sway the average juror with impec- enwald (Eds.), Attitude structure and function
cable arguments for incompatibilism. (pp. 153–179). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum
Franklin, F. E. (2013). Valuing blame. In D. J.
REFERENCES Coates & N. A. Tognazzini (Eds.), Blame: Its
nature and norms (pp. 207–223). New York:
Alicke, M. D. (1992). Culpable causation. Jour- Oxford University Press.
nal of Personality and Social Psychology, 63, Hoffman, M. B. (2014). The punisher’s brain:
368–378. The evolution of judge and jury. New York:
Alicke, M. D. (2000). Culpable control and the Cambridge University Press.
psychology of blame. Psychological Bulletin, Horney, K. (1937). The neurotic personality of
126(4), 556–574. our time. New York: Norton.
Alicke, M. D. (2008). Blaming badly. Journal of Hume, D. (1978). A treatise of human nature.
Cognition and Culture, 8, 179–186. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. (Origi-
Alicke, M. D., & Davis, T. L. (1989). The role of nal work published 1739)
a posteriori victim information in judgments Hume, D. (2007). An enquiry concerning human
of blame and sanction. Journal of Experimen- understanding. Oxford, UK: Oxford Univer-
tal Social Psychology, 25, 362–377. sity Press. (Original work published 1748).
Alicke, M. D., & Davis, T. L. (1990). Capacity Kahneman, D., Knetsch, J. L., & Thaler, R. H.
responsibility in social evaluation. Personality (1986). Fairness and the assumptions of eco-
and Social Psychology Bulletin, 16, 465–474. nomics. Journal of Business, 59, 285–300.
Alicke, M. D., Davis, T. L., Buckingham, J. T., & Knobe, J., & Fraser, B. (2008). Causal judgments
Zell, E. (2008). Culpable control and counter- and moral judgment: Two experiments. In
factual reasoning in the psychology of blame. W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral psychol-
Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, ogy: Vol. 2. The cognitive science of morality
34, 1371–1381. (pp. 441–447). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Alicke, M. D., Davis, T. L., & Pezzo, M. V. Malle, B. F., Guglielmo, S., & Monroe, A. E.
(1994). A posteriori adjustment of a priori de- (2014). A theory of blame. Psychological In-
cision criteria. Social Cognition, 12, 281–308. quiry, 25, 147–186.
390 DY N A M I C M O R A L J U D G M E N T

McCullough, M. (2008). Beyond revenge: The Near hits, (un)lucky strikes, and ascription of
evolution of the forgiveness instinct. New intent and blame.
York: Wiley. Russell, B. (1957). Why I am not a Christian:
McGeer, V. (2013). Civilizing blame. In D. J. And other essays on religion and related sub-
Coates & N. A. Tognazzini (Eds.), Blame: Its jects. New York: Simon & Schuster.
nature and norms (pp. 162–188). New York: Sarkissian, H., Chatterjee, A., DeBrigard, F.,
Oxford University Press. Knobe, J., Nichols, S., & Sirker, S. (2010). Is
Nahmias, E., Morris, S., Nadelhoffer, T., & belief in free will a cultural universal? Mind
Turner, J. (2006). Is incompatibilism intuitive? and Language, 25, 346–358.
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Shaver, K. G. (1985). The attribution of blame:
73, 28–53. Causality, responsibility, and blameworthi-
Nilsson, H. (1972). You’re breaking my heart. ness. New York: Springer-Verlag.
On Son of Smilsson [CD]. London: RCA. Skinner, B. F., & Hayes, J. (1976). Walden two.
Pinker, S. (2003). The blank slate: The modern New York: Macmillan.
denial of human nature. New York: Penguin. Strawson, P. F. (1962). Freedom and resentment.
Pizarro, D. A., Uhlmann, E., & Bloom, P. (2003). Proceedings of the British Academy, 48, 1–25.
Causal deviance and the attribution of moral Turillo, C. J., Folger, R., Lavelle, J. J., Umphress,
responsibility. Journal of Experimental Social E. E., & Gee, J. O. (2002). Is virtue its own
Psychology, 39, 653–660. reward?: Self-sacrificial decisions for the sake
Rogers, R., Alicke, M. D., Taylor, S. G., Rose, of fairness. Organizational Behavior and
D., Davis, T. L., & Bloom, D. (in preparation). Human Decision Processes, 89, 839–865.
PART I X
DEVELOPMENTAL AND EVOLUTIONARY
ROOTS OF MORALITY

Q U E S T I O N S A N S W E R E D I N PA R T I X

CHAPTER 40  Are fairness concerns unique to the human species?

CHAPTER 41  How does the capacity to make moral evaluations develop?

CHAPTER 42  What are the origins of human altruism?

CHAPTER 43  How and when do fairness concerns emerge


over the course of development?

CHAPTER 44  What is the most essential innate psychological mechanism


underlying morality?

CHAPTER 45  What are the rules and patterns guiding the rapid, automatic,
and unconscious processes of moral judgment?

CHAPTER 46  What is the best comprehensive theory


for understanding moral development?
CHAPTER 40

Do Animals Have a Sense of Fairness?

Katherine McAuliffe
Laurie R. Santos

Are fairness concerns unique to the human species?

Recent work on inequity aversion in nonhuman animals demon‑


strates that other species react to unfairness—at least in some situa‑
tions; but these new studies also hint that animal fairness concerns
may differ in important ways from those of humans.

The Origins of Human Fairness Concerns to cases of disadvantageous inequity—in


which the individual in question has less of a
One hallmark of human morality is our reward than someone else—as well as cases
strong sense of fairness. People sacrifice of advantageous inequity, in which the in-
absolute rewards to ensure that rewards dividual in question has more of a reward
are distributed fairly. Indeed, a large body than another person (Dawes, Fowler, John-
of work in behavioral economics demon- son, McElreath, & Smirnov, 2007; Fehr &
strates that people are inequity averse—we Schmidt, 1999; Loewenstein, Thompson, &
tend to avoid outcomes that lead to unfair Bazerman, 1989).
distributions of resources (Fehr & Schmidt, Recent research in developmental psy-
1999). The degree of human inequity aver- chology has shown that an aversion to in-
sion sometimes leads our species to seem- equality may emerge without extensive ex-
ingly irrational choices: In some cases, perience or explicit instruction (for a review,
people would rather receive nothing than see Blake, McAuliffe, & Warneken, 2014;
accept an unfair division of resources (Güth, Sommerville & Ziv, Chapter 43, this vol-
Schmittberger, & Schwarze, 1982; Yam- ume). By 15 months of age, infants expect
agishi et al., 2009) and are willing to incur other agents to distribute resources equally
costs to ensure that others are treated fairly among other individuals (Geraci & Su-
in third-party situations as well (e.g., Fehr rian, 2011; Schmidt & Sommerville, 2011;
& Fischbacher, 2004). Finally, and perhaps Sloane, Baillargeon, & Premack, 2012). By
most surprisingly, our species is averse to 4 years of age, children—like their adult
situations involving inequity even in cases in counterparts—would rather receive nothing
which we ourselves benefit from the unequal than accept a disadvantageously unfair divi-
distributions. Adult humans react negatively sion of rewards (Blake & McAuliffe, 2011;

393
394 D E V E L O P M E N TA L A N D E VO L U T I O N A RY R O O T S O F M O R A L I T Y

McAuliffe, Blake, & Warneken, 2014; Shaw hibit fairness concerns. In their now-famous
& Olson, 2012). Finally, recent cross-cultur- test of inequity aversion, they allowed two
al work suggests that fairness concerns ap- brown capuchin monkeys (Cebus apella) to
pear across human societies, although what trade tokens with a human experimenter for
constitutes a fair offer varies considerably food rewards. The subject monkey always
across cultures (Henrich et al., 2005). The received a low-quality reward (a piece of
potency, early emergence, and universal- cucumber) for her reward, but the experi-
ity of human fairness raises an important menters varied the reward given to the sec-
question about its origins in the human lin- ond partner monkey. In one condition—the
eage: Are concepts of what is and is not fair equity condition—both monkeys received a
unique to our species, or can we see their cucumber as a reward. In the second condi-
roots in other species? tion, however—the inequity condition—the
Here, we explore whether our own aver- subject monkey received a cucumber while
sion to unfairness is unique to humans. To her partner received a more desirable grape.
examine this issue, we review recent work Brosnan and de Waal (2003) then tested how
examining whether nonhuman animals the subject monkey reacted to these different
react negatively to unfair outcomes. Study- reward distributions. They found that sub-
ing animals’ reactions to unfair reward dis- ject monkeys were less inclined to trade and
tributions not only allows us to answer the more likely to reject the cucumber reward
question of whether fairness is unique to in the inequity condition compared with the
humans but also helps us begin to under- equity condition. Brosnan and de Waal in-
stand the selective forces that have shaped terpreted these patterns of performance as
the human sense of fairness. In this chapter, evidence that capuchin monkeys show sensi-
we first examine the history of work on ani- tivity to unfair pay for equal work and thus
mal fairness concerns, reviewing over a de- that capuchins are averse to reward inequity.
cade’s worth of work on inequity aversion in A number of studies have now built on
a number of animal species. We then discuss Brosnan and de Waal’s (2003) initial test of
a framework for making sense of these re- inequity aversion by investigating inequity
sults. Specifically, we explore whether these aversion in both capuchins and other ani-
findings truly demonstrate human-like ineq- mals. Although some of these studies have
uity aversion. We argue that, although other observed inequity aversion effects in capu-
species react to cases of inequity, other spe- chins (van Wolkenten, Brosnan, & de Waal,
cies’ responses to apparent unfairness may 2007) and other primate species (Brosnan,
be supported by mechanisms that are very Schiff, & de Waal, 2005; Hopper, Schapiro,
different from those in humans. Lambeth, & Brosnan, 2011; Massen, van
den Berg, Spruijt, & Sterck, 2012), other
studies have failed to find similar levels of
Historical Context: Previous Studies inequity aversion, both in capuchins (McAu-
of Inequity Aversion in Animals liffe et al., 2015; Roma, Silberberg, Rug-
giero, & Suomi, 2006; Silberberg, Roma,
The past decade has seen a surge of work Ruggiero, & Suomi, 2006) and in other
testing fairness concerns in nonhuman spe- primates (Bräuer, Call, & Tomasello, 2006,
cies (see review in Bräuer & Hanus, 2012; 2009; McAuliffe, Shelton, & Stone, 2014;
Brosnan, 2006). Specifically, these studies Neiworth, Johnson, Whillock, Greenberg,
have asked whether any nonhuman ani- & Brown, 2009). Some of these follow-up
mals (hereafter animals) show an aversion studies have offered alternative explana-
to unequal payoff distributions. To date, tions for the rejections of inequity observed
the vast majority of work on inequity aver- in the original Brosnan and de Waal (2003)
sion in animals has focused on disadvanta- task. For instance, a conceptual replication
geously inequitable payoff distributions, as by Roma and colleagues (2006) observed
it is likely that this is the kind of unequal that capuchins were insensitive to what their
situation that animals may find most aver- partners received in an inequity task and in-
sive. In a landmark paper, Brosnan and de stead showed an aversion to cases in which
Waal (2003) first tested whether animals ex- their own food switched from high to low
 Do Animals Have a Sense of Fairness? 395

quality. Specifically, they showed that sub- condition in which the higher reward was
jects would reject cucumbers if they had re- merely out of the subjects’ reach.
ceived grapes in previous sessions. Based on
this finding, Roma and colleagues argued
that rejections purported to be due to ineq- Theoretical Stance: How Social Are
uity aversion could instead be due to frustra- Animal Inequity Responses?
tion at having received better rewards in the
Social and Nonsocial Hypotheses
past. Note that a similar frustration account
for the Evolution of Inequity Aversion
could also explain Brosnan and de Waal’s
(2003) inequity aversion results, because As the above results suggest, there is still
monkeys participated as both subjects and some controversy concerning whether pri-
partners and thus moved from sessions in mates’ reactions to unfair payoff distribu-
which they were receiving grapes to sessions tions are specifically social phenomena.
in which they were receiving cucumbers. In This issue is important for two reasons.
a similar vein, Dubreuil, Gentile, and Vis- First, human adults and children find ineq-
alberghi (2006) showed that capuchin mon- uity more aversive in social compared with
keys’ rejections were not dependent on their nonsocial settings (McAuliffe, Blake, Kim,
partners’ rewards but rather on the presence Wrangham, & Warneken, 2013; Ostoji &
of more preferred, but inaccessible, rewards. Clayton, 2013); if nonhuman animals truly
Finally, McAuliffe and colleagues (2015) show human-like inequity aversion, we
found that capuchins’ rejections of both should expect a similar pattern in animals as
high- and low-quality rewards were very well as some nonhuman species. Second, the
rare overall and were not specific to the con- extent to which nonhuman animals show
ditions in which subjects received unequal inequity aversion in nonsocial settings bears
rewards for performing the same task. directly on the two main classes of theoreti-
Although it is hard to perfectly explain cal explanations that have been proposed
the inconsistencies seen in animals’ perfor- to explain why inequity aversion evolved
mance on inequity aversion tasks, the crux (McAuliffe et al., 2013). In the next section,
of the inconsistencies across studies lies in we review these two different theoretical
the extent to which inequity aversion occurs accounts, examining how each account fits
specifically in social situations. For example, with the available empirical evidence.
in their original study, Brosnan and de Waal The first class of explanations for the evo-
(2003) tested how monkeys would react in a lution of inequity aversion posits that ineq-
nonsocial version of their original inequity uity aversion evolved specifically for social
scenario. In this nonsocial control condi- situations—it evolved as a means of regu-
tion, the subject monkey received a cucum- lating payoffs from collective action (social
ber for trading his token, but every time he hypothesis; Brosnan, 2006, 2011). Under
did so a grape was placed into an adjacent this view, inequity aversion evolved to solve
empty enclosure. Interestingly, Brosnan and the fundamental problem of cooperation—
de Waal (2003) found that subject monkeys preventing free riders from benefiting from
do show reluctance to trade in this nonso- the contributions of others. Under this view,
cial condition but report that effects in this animals might develop negative responses to
condition are still somewhat smaller and less situations in which conspecifics take more
robust over time than the reluctance to trade than their fair share (i.e., inequity aversion)
observed in the inequity condition (see also of the spoils of collective action, which could
later analysis in Brosnan & de Waal, 2004). then help to solve this free-riding problem.
Other investigators, however, have failed to A second class of theoretical accounts—
find such a robust difference between social which we will collectively refer to here as
and nonsocial conditions. For example, as the nonsocial hypothesis—explains inequity
discussed above, Dubreuil and colleagues aversion as a more domain-general phenom-
(2006) did not find a difference in the rate enon. Under this account, inequity aversion
of capuchins’ rejection of a small reward be- has nonsocial roots and evolved as part of a
tween a condition in which a second mon- more general response for tracking reward
key received a higher reward and a control distributions (Chen & Santos, 2006). Under
396 D E V E L O P M E N TA L A N D E VO L U T I O N A RY R O O T S O F M O R A L I T Y

this view, the tendency to exhibit aversive re- animals should care about equity not just in
sponses to receiving a bad deal when better cases in which they are disadvantaged but
deals are available is beneficial in that it mo- also in cases in which they are advantaged;
tivates individuals to increase their foraging that is, in which they have more than their
effort to extract the best possible resources fair share of a common resource. In contrast
from their environment. Consider, for exam- to the nonsocial hypothesis, the social hy-
ple, a foraging individual who comes upon pothesis uniquely predicts that animals—
a patch of food. Before beginning to forage like humans—may show aversion to cases of
in this patch, however, the individual sees advantageous inequity as well. In the follow-
a better patch of food off in the distance. ing sections, we review empirical results for
In this scenario, it would behoove the for- inequity aversion across taxa with the aim of
ager to “reject” its current patch in favor gaining insight into whether one hypothesis
of the more desirable patch. As such, suc- is more plausible than the other.
cessful animal foragers may have developed
psychological mechanisms (e.g., a feeling of
Empirical Evidence for the Social
“frustration”) when they receive rewards
and Nonsocial Hypotheses
that are less than other expected or avail-
able rewards. Indeed, numerous findings in Some suggestive support for the social hy-
comparative cognition suggest that animals pothesis comes from studies that have di-
experience frustration when they receive a rectly compared inequity aversion responses
reward that was smaller than the one they in cooperative versus noncooperative pri-
expected (e.g., Freidin, Cuello, & Kacel- mate species. For example, some research
nik, 2009; Santos, Sulkowski, Spaepen, & teams have tested inequity aversion re-
Hauser, 2002; Tinklepaugh, 1928). Note, sponses in both capuchin monkeys—a very
however, that such “frustration” responses cooperative species—and squirrel monkeys
would have nothing to do with a response to (Saimiri sciureus and Saimiri boliviensis),
inequity per se but would rather be born of a which are considered to be noncoopera-
drive to optimize resource extraction from a tive (see Brosnan & de Waal, 2003; Talbot,
given environment. Freeman, Williams, & Brosnan, 2011). This
While the social and the nonsocial hy- comparison and others like it (see Brosnan,
potheses of inequity aversion differ in their 2011, for a review) have suggested that co-
explanations for the emergence of inequity operative primates tend to show more nega-
aversion, it is worth noting that the two hy- tive responses to inequity than noncoopera-
potheses are not entirely mutually exclusive. tive species. Although such findings at first
Indeed, a phenomenon as complex as ineq- glance hint at a compelling link between co-
uity aversion almost surely involves at least operation and inequity aversion, they should
some domain-general mechanisms that are be interpreted with caution for two reasons.
commonly deployed in social interactions. First, although many researchers have stud-
Nevertheless, these two classes of explana- ied cooperative species (e.g., Brosnan et al.,
tions make importantly different predic- 2005; Brosnan & de Waal, 2003; Massen et
tions about the taxonomic distribution and al., 2012; Range, Horn, Viranyi, & Huber,
robustness of inequity aversion. First, if in- 2009; Wascher & Bugnyar, 2013), relatively
equity aversion evolved as a means of regu- few studies have examined inequity aversion
lating cooperation, as the social hypothesis in noncooperative species. The distribution
argues, then we should only observe ineq- of positive evidence for inequity aversion
uity aversions in cooperative species. If, on could therefore be an artifact of sampling
the other hand, inequity aversion is an in- bias. Second, and perhaps more worryingly,
stantiation of a more generalized mechanism several studies have tested inequity aver-
for tracking relative payoff distributions, it sion in cooperative primate species and have
should be spread broadly across different failed to provide evidence for it (Bräuer et
taxa. Second, if inequity aversion evolved al., 2006; McAuliffe et al., 2015; McAu-
as a means of stabilizing cooperation, as it liffe, Shelton, & Stone, 2014; Neiworth et
is theorized to have done in humans, then al., 2009).
 Do Animals Have a Sense of Fairness? 397

In a recent attempt to better understand be simulated in the lab by presenting clean-


the link between inequity aversion and co- ers with Plexiglass plates (which simulate cli-
operation, researchers have begun shifting ent fish) covered in fish flake (less preferred
their focus away from testing primates and food, akin to ectoparasites) or prawn (pre-
toward cooperative species found in other ferred food, akin to client mucus). Raihani
taxonomic groups. Studying inequity aver- and colleagues presented pairs of cleaners
sion in nonprimates has yielded more mixed with a task that was rewarded with access
evidence for the social hypothesis. For ex- to a Plexiglass plate, one side of which could
ample, Range and colleagues (Range et al., be accessed by the subject and the other
2009; Range, Leitner, & Viranyi, 2012) test- side by a partner. In equity treatments, the
ed whether domestic dogs would show ineq- subject performed a task that resulted in an
uity aversion in a task modeled after the ca- equal payoff for subject and partner. In the
puchin inequity paradigm described above. inequity cases, the subject performed a task
Domestic dogs show extensive intra- and that delivered a more desirable reward to
interspecies cooperation and are thought to the partner than to the subject. Raihani and
have evolved from a cooperative wolf-like colleagues showed that subjects’ propensity
ancestor. Dogs thus provide an ideal nonpri- to perform the task was unaffected by their
mate model in which to investigate whether partner’s payoff, suggesting that cleaner
cooperative species are particularly prone fish—despite their extensive intra- and in-
to inequity aversion. Range et al. (2009) terspecies cooperation—are not inequity
allowed dogs to perform a command (give averse. Thus, when work on dogs and fish is
paw) in exchange for a treat. They found that considered together, it is clear that, at least
dogs were less willing to give a paw for no so far, work on cooperative nonprimate spe-
reward when their partner was getting a re- cies has not borne out the predictions of the
ward than when neither individual received social hypothesis.
a reward. These results were interpreted Whereas the social hypothesis for the
as evidence that dogs show a rudimentary evolution of inequity aversion has garnered
form of inequity aversion, at least in cases weak support at best, the nonsocial hypoth-
in which a partner receives a reward while esis has received indirect support from a
the subject receives nothing. Although these number of lines of evidence. For instance, as
and other findings from studies of coopera- mentioned above, capuchin monkeys show
tive animals have strengthened the theorized negative responses both when their partners
link between inequity aversion and coopera- receive a more favorable reward and when
tion in animals, it is important to note that a more favorable reward is placed inacces-
at least two attempts to induce an inequity sibly (Brosnan & de Waal, 2003). In this
aversion effect in dogs have been unsuccess- way, several researchers have argued that
ful (Horowitz, 2012; McAuliffe, under re- nonsocial domain-general psychological
view), suggesting that inequity aversion in mechanisms such as frustration can explain
dogs may be expressed only under specific animals’ negative responses in situations of
conditions. inequity (Hopper et al., 2011; Roma et al.,
Providing further suggestive evidence 2006; Silberberg et al., 2006). Moreover, the
against the social hypothesis are findings frustration explanation does not preclude
showing that inequity aversion is absent in the potentially important effects of social in-
at least one cooperative nonprimate species. formation. Indeed, it is entirely possible that
Raihani, McAuliffe, Brosnan, and Bshary individuals may notice potentially better re-
(2012) tested inequity aversion in coop- wards in situations in which a conspecific
erative cleaner fish (Labroides dimidiatus). has access to those better rewards compared
These fish cooperate in male–female pairs with cases in which those better rewards
to clean client fish. During cleaning interac- are simply present (for a similar effect in
tions, cleaners feed against their preference humans thinking about their own payoffs,
for the protective mucus that covers clients see Solnick & Hemenway, 1998). Under this
and instead eat the ectoparasites that para- explanation, stronger frustration effects in
sitize client fish. This feeding dilemma can social contexts would make sense given that
398 D E V E L O P M E N TA L A N D E VO L U T I O N A RY R O O T S O F M O R A L I T Y

social partners are likely to provide reliable 2007; Güth et al., 1982; McAuliffe, Blake,
information about what resource payoffs are & Warneken, 2014; but see Yamagishi et
available in a given environment. al., 2009). By contrast, rejections in the
In our view, the current weight of evi- standard animal inequity aversion task have
dence for inequity aversion in animals falls no effect on partners’ payoffs (see Henrich,
slightly in favor of the nonsocial hypothesis. 2004) and, as such, do not create equality.
Inequity aversion responses are not clearly Indeed, a recent study with capuchin mon-
present only in cooperative species, nor are keys designed to better mirror human ineq-
responses to inequity specifically social. We uity aversion tasks showed no evidence for
therefore argue that current evidence sug- inequity aversion in capuchins and also no
gests that apparent disadvantageous ineq- evidence that capuchins attempted to create
uity aversion in animals most likely relies on more even payoffs (McAuliffe et al., 2015).
domain-general mechanisms for estimating This finding suggests that animal rejections
the relative value of different resource distri- of inequity differ substantively from those
butions. Under this view, animals sometimes of humans and raise the intriguing question
respond most strongly to disadvantageous of why animals are rejecting at all. Second,
inequity in social settings (e.g., Brosnan & whereas adults and older children show an
de Waal 2003, 2004) because such cases aversion to both disadvantageous and ad-
are more attentionally salient. We therefore vantageous inequity, advantageous inequity
contend that inequity aversion has nonsocial aversion is very rare if not entirely absent in
roots in animals but has been co-opted for animals (Brosnan et al., 2005; Brosnan &
use in the social domain. de Waal, 2014; Horowitz, 2012; McAuliffe
Note that this domain-general interpre- et al., 2015; Sheskin, Ashayeri, Skerry, &
tation of animal inequity aversion sheds Santos, 2014). The prevalence of both forms
important light on the potential origins of on inequity aversion in humans supports
inequity aversion and fairness concerns in the idea that inequity aversion is a means
the human lineage. Based on findings from of achieving equality in humans, whereas in
animals, it would seem reasonable to suspect animals it is a means of avoiding bad deals.
that disadvantageous inequity aversion has a Finally, humans care so much about avoid-
similarly nonsocial history in our own spe- ing inequity that they will punish unfair
cies but that for some reason—perhaps due resource allocations in both second-party
to the specific demands of collective action (Güth et al., 1982; Raihani & McAuliffe,
in humans—it became closely linked with 2012b) and third-party (Fehr & Fischbach-
cooperation. er, 2004) contexts. By contrast, in animals,
there is little evidence that unfairness mo-
tivates punishment (Jensen, Call, & Toma-
What Sets Human Fairness Apart sello, 2007; Raihani & McAuliffe, 2012a;
from Animal “Fairness”? Riedl, Jensen, Call, & Tomasello, 2012).

Studies of inequity aversion in animals have


suggested that disadvantageous inequity Conclusion: What Have We Learned
aversion may have nonsocial roots in other from Studies of Inequity Aversion
species and perhaps even our own species, in Animals?
but clearly the human sense of fairness is
a richly social concept. What features of Returning to the question posed in this ar-
human inequity aversion make it so richly ticle’s title—Do animals have a sense of fair-
social compared with what we see in ani- ness?—the answer appears to be a tentative,
mals? In our view, at least three features of “not really.” At the very least, nonhuman
human inequity aversion set it apart from in- animals do not seem to have what one might
equity aversion in other species. First, when want to consider a “human-like” sense of
human adults reject inequity, they typically fairness. To date, there is little evidence that
do so to affect others’ payoffs and, more spe- animals have a preference for equality per
cifically, to achieve equality (Dawes et al., se; instead, animals’ performance on so-
 Do Animals Have a Sense of Fairness? 399

called inequity aversion tasks appears to be actions to inequity and their implications for
more consistent with a desire to avoid poor fairness. Social Justice Research, 19(2), 153–
payoffs relative to the range of available 185.
payoffs. By contrast, humans show a strong Brosnan, S. F. (2011). A hypothesis of the co-
evolution of cooperation and responses to
preference for equality, sacrificing personal
inequity. Frontiers in Neuroscience, 5. Avail-
gain to achieve equality from both sides of able at www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/
inequity (Blake & McAuliffe, 2011; Dawes PMC3077916.
et al., 2007). Brosnan, S. F., & de Waal, F. (2003). Monkeys
Given that animals do not seem to have a reject unequal pay. Nature, 425(6955), 297–
human-like sense of fairness, what has the 299.
huge amount of work on animal inequity Brosnan, S. F., & de Waal, F. B. (2004). Animal
aversion taught us about our own human- behaviour: Fair refusal by capuchin monkeys.
like sense of fairness? We argue that work Nature, 428(6979), 140.
on animal inequity aversion has taught us Brosnan, S. F., & de Waal, F. B. M. (2014).
Evolution of responses to (un)fairness.
two important lessons. The first is that some
Science, 346(6207), 1251776. Avail-
elements of our reactions to distributional able at http://science.sciencemag.org/con-
inequity are likely deeply rooted in our evo- tent/346/6207/1251776.
lutionary past and, by extension, are most Brosnan, S. F., Schiff, H. C., & de Waal, F. B. M.
likely innate in humans. Second, based on (2005). Tolerance for inequity may increase
current evidence, it seems reasonable to sus- with social closeness in chimpanzees. Proceed-
pect that the origins of some aspects of the ings of the Royal Society: B. Biological Sci-
human sense of fairness are built on generic ences, 272(1560), 253–258.
processes that are generally useful in helping Chen, M. K., & Santos, L. R. (2006). Some
animals navigate their ecological and social thoughts on the adaptive function of inequity
aversion: An alternative to Brosnan’s social
environments. Work on animals has also
hypothesis. Social Justice Research, 19(2),
helped focus the direction of future work on 201–207.
understanding why humans, more so than Dawes, C. T., Fowler, J. H., Johnson, T., McEl-
other species, have a preference for equality reath, R., & Smirnov, O. (2007). Egalitarian
per se. Answering this question will shed im- motives in humans. Nature, 446(7137), 794–
portant light on what makes human fairness 796.
so unique. Dubreuil, D., Gentile, M. S., & Visalberghi, E.
(2006). Are capuchin monkeys (Cebus apel-
la) inequity averse? Proceedings of the Royal
REFERENCES Society: B. Biological Sciences, 273(1591),
1223–1228.
Blake, P. R., & McAuliffe, K. (2011). I had so Fehr, E., & Fischbacher, U. (2004). Third-party
much it didn’t seem fair: Eight-year-olds re- punishment and social norms. Evolution and
ject two forms of inequity. Cognition, 120(2), Human Behavior, 25(2), 63–87.
215–224. Fehr, E., & Schmidt, K. M. (1999). A theory of
Blake, P. R., McAuliffe, K., & Warneken, F. fairness, competition, and cooperation. Quar-
(2014). The developmental origins of fairness: terly Journal of Economics, 114(3), 817–868.
The knowledge–behavior gap. Trends in Cog- Freidin, E., Cuello, M. I., & Kacelnik, A. (2009).
nitive Sciences, 18(11), 559–561. Successive negative contrast in a bird: Star-
Bräuer, J., Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2006). lings’ behaviour after unpredictable negative
Are apes really inequity averse? Proceedings changes in food quality. Animal Behaviour,
of the Royal Society: B. Biological Sciences, 77(4), 857–865.
273(1605), 3123–3128. Geraci, A., & Surian, L. (2011). The develop-
Bräuer, J., Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2009). Are mental roots of fairness: Infants’ reactions to
apes inequity averse?: New data on the token- equal and unequal distributions of resources.
exchange paradigm. American Journal of Pri- Developmental Science, 14(5), 1012–1020.
matology, 71(2), 175–181. Güth, W., Schmittberger, R., & Schwarze, B.
Bräuer, J., & Hanus, D. (2012). Fairness in non- (1982). An experimental analysis of ultima-
human primates? Social Justice Research, tum bargaining. Journal of Economic Behav-
25(3), 256–276. ior and Organization, 3(4), 367–388.
Brosnan, S. F. (2006). Nonhuman species’ re- Henrich, J. (2004). Animal behaviour: Inequity
400 D E V E L O P M E N TA L A N D E VO L U T I O N A RY R O O T S O F M O R A L I T Y

aversion in capuchins? Nature, 428(6979), aversion in human adults: Testing behavioural


139; discussion 140. criteria from comparative cognition. Animal
Henrich, J., Boyd, R., Bowles, S., Camerer, C., Cognition, 16(5), 765–772.
Fehr, E., Gintis, H., . . . Tracer, D. (2005). Raihani, N. J., & McAuliffe, K. (2012a). Does
“Economic man” in cross-cultural perspec- inequity aversion motivate punishment?:
tive: Behavioral experiments in 15 small-scale Cleaner fish as a model system. Social Justice
societies. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, Research, 25(2), 213–231.
28(6), 795–815; discussion 815–855. Raihani, N. J., & McAuliffe, K. (2012b). Human
Hopper, L. M., Schapiro, S. J., Lambeth, S. P., & punishment is motivated by inequity aversion,
Brosnan, S. F. (2011). Chimpanzees’ socially not a desire for reciprocity. Biology Letters,
maintained food preferences indicate both 8(5), 802–804.
conservatism and conformity. Animal Behav- Raihani, N. J., McAuliffe, K., Brosnan, S. F., &
iour, 81(6), 1195–1202. Bshary, R. (2012). Are cleaner fish, Labroides
Horowitz, A. (2012). Fair is fine, but more is bet- dimidiatus, inequity averse? Animal Behav-
ter: Limits to inequity aversion in the domestic iour, 84(3), 665–674.
dog. Social Justice Research, 25(2), 195–212. Range, F., Horn, L., Viranyi, Z., & Huber, L.
Jensen, K., Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2007). (2009). The absence of reward induces in-
Chimpanzees are rational maximizers in an ul- equity aversion in dogs. Proceedings of the
timatum game. Science, 318(5847), 107–109. National Academy of Sciences of the USA,
Loewenstein, G. F., Thompson, L., & Bazer- 106(1), 340–345.
man, M. H. (1989). Social utility and decision Range, F., Leitner, K., & Viranyi, Z. (2012). The
making in interpersonal contexts. Journal influence of the relationship and motivation
of Personality and Social Psychology, 57(3), on inequity aversion in dogs. Social Justice
426–441. Research, 25(2), 170–194.
Massen, J. J., van den Berg, L. M., Spruijt, B. Riedl, K., Jensen, K., Call, J., & Tomasello, M.
M., & Sterck, E. H. (2012). Inequity aversion (2012). No third-party punishment in chim-
in relation to effort and relationship quality in panzees. Proceedings of the National Acad-
long-tailed Macaques (Macaca fascicularis). emy of Sciences of the USA, 109(37), 14824–
American Journal of Primatology, 74(2), 145– 14829.
156. Roma, P. G., Silberberg, A., Ruggiero, A. M.,
McAuliffe, K. (under review). Inequity aversion & Suomi, S. J. (2006). Capuchin monkeys,
in dogs (Canis familiaris) and dingoes (Canis inequity aversion, and the frustration effect.
dingo): A test of the domestication hypothesis. Journal of Comparative Psychology, 120(1),
Manuscript submitted for publication. 67–73.
McAuliffe, K., Blake, P. R., Kim, G., Wrangham, Santos, L. R., Sulkowski, G. M., Spaepen, G. M.,
R. W., & Warneken, F. (2013). Social influ- & Hauser, M. D. (2002). Object individuation
ences on inequity aversion in children. PLOS using property/kind information in rhesus ma-
ONE, 8(12), e80966. caques (Macaca mulatta). Cognition, 83(3),
McAuliffe, K., Blake, P. R., & Warneken, 241–264.
F. (2014). Children reject inequity out of Schmidt, M. F. H., & Sommerville, J. A. (2011).
spite. Biology Letters, 10(12). Available at Fairness expectations and altruistic sharing in
http://rsbl.royalsocietypublishing.org/con- 15-month-old human infants. PLOS ONE,
tent/10/12/20140743. 6(10), 1–7.
McAuliffe, K., Chang, L. W., Leimgruber, K. Shaw, A., & Olson, K. R. (2012). Children dis-
L., Spaulding, R., Blake, P. R., & Santos, L. card a resource to avoid inequity. Journal of
R. (2015). Capuchin monkeys, Cebus apella, Experimental Psychology: General, 141(2),
show no evidence for inequity aversion in a 382–395.
costly choice task. Animal Behaviour, 103(C), Sheskin, M., Ashayeri, K., Skerry, A., & Santos,
65–74. L. R. (2014). Capuchin monkeys (Cebus apel-
McAuliffe, K., Shelton, N., & Stone, L. (2014). la) fail to show inequality aversion in a no-cost
Does effort influence inequity aversion in cot- situation. Evolution and Human Behavior,
ton-top tamarins (Saguinus oedipus)? Animal 35(2), 80–88.
Cognition, 17(6), 1289–1301. Silberberg, A., Roma, P. G., Ruggiero, A. M., &
Neiworth, J. J., Johnson, E. T., Whillock, K., Suomi, S. J. (2006). On inequity aversion in
Greenberg, J., & Brown, V. (2009). Is a sense nonhuman primates. Journal of Comparative
of inequity an ancestral primate trait?: Test- Psychology, 120(1), 76.
ing social inequity in cotton top tamarins (Sa- Sloane, S., Baillargeon, R., & Premack, D.
guinus oedipus). Journal of Comparative Psy- (2012). Do infants have a sense of fairness?
chology, 123(1), 10–17. Psychological Science, 23(2), 196–204.
Ostoji, L., & Clayton, N. S. (2013). Inequity Solnick, S. J., & Hemenway, D. (1998). Is more
 Do Animals Have a Sense of Fairness? 401

always better?: A survey on positional con- modified by effort. Proceedings of the Nation-
cerns. Journal of Economic Behavior and Or- al Academy of Sciences of the USA, 104(47),
ganization, 37(3), 373–383. 18854–18859.
Talbot, C. F., Freeman, H. D., Williams, L. E., Wascher, C. A., & Bugnyar, T. (2013). Behavior-
& Brosnan, S. F. (2011). Squirrel monkeys’ al responses to inequity in reward distribution
response to inequitable outcomes indicates a and working effort in crows and ravens. PLOS
behavioural convergence within the primates. ONE, 8(2), e56885.
Biology Letters, 7(5), 680–682. Yamagishi, T., Horita, Y., Takagishi, H., Shina-
Tinklepaugh, E. (1928). An experimental study da, M., Tanida, S., & Cook, K. S. (2009). The
of representative factors in monkeys. Journal private rejection of unfair offers and emotion-
of Comparative Psychology, 13, 207–224. al commitment. Proceedings of the National
van Wolkenten, M., Brosnan, S. F., & de Waal, F. Academy of Sciences of the USA 106(28),
B. M. (2007). Inequity responses of monkeys 11520–11523.
C H A P T E R 41

The Infantile Roots


of Sociomoral Evaluations

Julia W. Van de Vondervoort
J. Kiley Hamlin

How does the capacity to make moral evaluations develop?

The development of morality begins with a sociomoral core, which


evolved to sustain large-scale cooperation.

The tendency to evaluate certain people dren develop a mature moral sense over time
and actions as good, right, and deserving as they become increasingly other-focused,
of praise and others as bad, wrong, and de- experienced, socialized, and cognitively
serving of punishment is present in nearly skilled. Prominent models have focused on
all humans. Although the content of peo- how children actively learn to distinguish
ple’s moral evaluations (e.g., which specific moral concerns from conventional or per-
behaviors are considered morally good and sonal (preference) concerns through parents’,
bad) often varies between individuals within teachers’, and peers’ differential reactions to
and across cultures, all typically developing transgressions within each of these domains
adults agree that some behaviors are right (Turiel, 1983; Smetana, 2006) and on how
and some are wrong (Brown, 1991). But parenting techniques are used to transmit
when and how does this moral sense devel- standards of acceptable behavior and how
op? children internalize these values (Grusec &
Traditional models of human moral de- Goodnow, 1994).
velopment assert that morality is acquired Rather than viewing infants as either
across development (e.g., Kohlberg, 1969; amoral or immoral, we argue that infants
Piaget, 1932; see Killen & Smetana, 2006, possess an innate sociomoral core, which al-
2014, for reviews). In these models, infants lows them to evaluate third parties for their
and young children are believed to be either morally relevant acts. This core is functional
amoral, completely lacking a moral sense, very early in life—as soon as infants are ca-
or immoral, possessing a moral sense that pable of processing the goal-directed actions
opposes that of adults due to selfishness, of agents—and does not require learning or
egocentrism, or cognitive limitations. Chil- specific experiences to become operational.

402
 Infantile Roots of Sociomoral Evaluations 403

Consistent with theories of the evolution of for identifying cooperators and cheaters in
cooperation (see Katz, 2000, for a review), their environment and selectively cooperat-
we hypothesize that this core developed to ing only with those likely to cooperate in re-
sustain the large-scale cooperation found in turn (e.g., Bull & Rice, 1991). Successful co-
human societies, allowing individuals to se- operators are those who positively evaluate
lectively cooperate only with those likely to other cooperators, negatively evaluate non-
cooperate in return. cooperators, and connect these evaluations
with appropriate approach and avoidance
behaviors. By avoiding cheaters and exclud-
The Evolution of Cooperative Systems ing them from the benefits of group living,
the risks associated with noncooperators are
Although the processes underlying the evo- mitigated.
lution of cooperation are often debated Although the inclusion of cooperators and
(Axelrod & Hamilton, 1981; Cosmides & the exclusion of noncooperators reduces the
Tooby, 1992; Henrich & Henrich, 2007; likelihood that costly cooperative acts will
Hrdy, 2009; Trivers, 1971), the ubiquitous not be reciprocated, the complexity of evalu-
presence of cooperative efforts in human ating others’ behaviors entails that mistakes
groups (Brown, 1991) presents a puzzle. are possible: Some cheaters will evade detec-
Specifically, in order to cooperate, one must tion. In addition, the possibility of exclusion
be willing to incur costs to oneself to con- may not always be sufficient to discourage
tribute to the success of others; these costs would-be cheaters. In these cases, the pun-
may or may not be reciprocated in the fu- ishment of antisocial behavior acts as an
ture. Given that reciprocation is uncertain, additional discouragement that can sustain
it is not immediately clear why rational in- cooperative systems, both deterring cheat-
dividuals would habitually take on certain ing beforehand and responding to it after
costs to cooperate. the fact (Boyd & Richerson, 1992; Henrich
One solution to this puzzle is that the et al. 2006; O’Gorman, Henrich, & Van
benefits of belonging to a cooperative group Vugt, 2009). Adults are willing to incur
outweigh the costs of individual cooperative costs to punish others and even find punish-
acts. That is, cooperative groups are better ing wrongdoers rewarding (Fehr & Gächter,
able to meet each individual’s needs (e.g., to 2002; de Quervain et al., 2004).
procure food, fight enemies, raise children) In sum, tendencies to evaluate coopera-
and can achieve successes that an individual tors and noncooperators, to differentially
cannot (e.g., hunt larger game, fight stron- approach or avoid others based on their like-
ger enemies, raise more children). Given the liness to cooperate, and to punish those who
potential benefits of living in cooperative exploit the benefits of a cooperative group
groups, cooperators’ willingness to work may have evolved to sustain large coopera-
with, share with, and help others is not so tive systems. One way to evaluate the valid-
puzzling. ity of this evolutionary claim is to examine
Despite the clear benefits of living in coop- the presence or absence of these tendencies
erative systems, these systems are vulnerable in young humans. Specifically, infants lack
to individuals who “cheat” the system, re- the experiences typically thought necessary
ceiving all the benefits of others’ costly acts to engage in sociomoral evaluation, includ-
but not reciprocating those costs in return. ing experiences of being helped or harmed in
Because cheaters pay no costs, they neces- particular situations, extensive observation
sarily outperform cooperators who do, and of others being helped or harmed, and ex-
thus cooperators should eventually be elimi- plicit teaching about which actions are right
nated from the population. The persistence or wrong. By exploring which (if any) evalu-
of large-scale cooperation in human societ- ative tenancies develop independently of
ies despite this vulnerability to cheaters rais- these experiences, researchers can probe the
es the question: How do cooperators avoid existence of an innate sociomoral core. To
being taken advantage of? One possibility is be consistent with the evolutionary claims
that, along with tendencies toward cooper- described above, humans’ sociomoral core
ating, humans evolved cognitive capacities should be present in infancy, remain intact
404 D E V E L O P M E N TA L A N D E VO L U T I O N A RY R O O T S O F M O R A L I T Y

throughout the lifespan, and constrain how retrieve a dropped ball (Hamlin & Wynn,
experience and maturation in other domains 2011; Hamlin et al., 2007; Kuhlmeier et al.,
influences moral development. The research 2003; see also Buon et al., 2014; Scola, Hol-
reviewed below provides evidence consistent voet, Arciszewski, & Picard, 2015). Follow-
with the existence of such a core. ing each unsuccessful attempt, infants see ei-
ther a Helper facilitate the Protagonist’s goal
(bumps him up the hill, helps him open the
Do Infants Possess a Sociomoral Core? box, returns his ball) or a Hinderer block
the Protagonist’s goal (bumps him down
If cooperation and morality did indeed co- the hill, slams the box closed, steals the ball
evolve, then evolution ought to have en- away).
dowed us with capacities for identifying and After watching alternating helping and
responding to those whose actions would hindering events, infants are presented with
destabilize reciprocal cooperative systems. the Helper and the Hinderer by an experi-
Specifically, these capacities should relate menter who is unaware of the identity of the
to behaviors that are relevant to coopera- agents, and infants’ preference for one or the
tion, such as helping and hindering, giving other is determined by which one they spend
and taking, and fairness and inequity. As more time looking at and/or by which one
predicted by this evolutionary account, in- they reach for. By 3 months of age, infants
fants appear to understand several aspects look longer at individuals who have pushed
of cooperative behaviors. By the end of their a Protagonist up the hill versus those who
first year, infants recognize that intentional pushed him down and look longer at those
agents can work together to achieve a com- who gave a Protagonist his ball back versus
mon goal (Henderson & Woodward, 2011), those who stole it away (Hamlin & Wynn,
that the experience of being helped and hin- 2011; Hamlin, Wynn, & Bloom, 2010).
dered will influence an agent’s social pref- This very early preference for Helpers over
erences (Hamlin, Wynn, & Bloom, 2007; Hinderers seems to be rooted in a negative
Fawcett & Liszkowski, 2012; Kuhlmeier, evaluation of Hinderers rather than a posi-
Wynn, & Bloom, 2003; see also Lee, Yun, tive evaluation of Helpers: 3-month-olds
Kim, & Song, 2015), and that valence- look longer toward Helpers than Hinderers
matched actions are more similar than ac- and toward neutral puppets than Hinderers,
tions that share only physical characteristics but look equally toward neutral puppets and
(e.g., helping and caressing vs. hindering and Helpers (Hamlin et al., 2010). By 4–5 months
hitting; Premack & Premack, 1997). Within of age, infants have acquired the ability to
the second year of life, infants expect that make visually guided reaches toward objects
individuals will treat others fairly, dividing (McDonnell, 1975) and selectively reach for
resources equally between recipients (Ger- Helpers over Hinderers in each of the scenar-
aci & Surian, 2011; Schmidt & Sommer- ios described above (Hamlin, 2015; Hamlin
ville, 2011), as long as those individuals are & Wynn, 2011; Hamlin et al., 2007; but see
equally meritorious (Sloane, Baillargeon, & Salvadori et al., 2015). Furthermore, unlike
Premack, 2012). Together, these results sug- 3-month-olds, 6-month-olds engage in both
gest that infants can interpret the morally positive and negative social evaluations:
relevant behaviors of others. They select Helpers over neutral puppets
and neutral puppets over Hinderers (Ham-
lin et al., 2007).
Infants Evaluate Helpers and Hinderers
One potential concern is that a prefer-
Perhaps the most direct evidence that infants ence for Helpers over Hinderers may not be
make sociomoral evaluations comes from a social evaluation at all; perhaps infants
studies examining infants’ evaluations of are responding based on low-level physical
“Helpers” and “Hinderers.” In these stud- differences between the helping and hinder-
ies, infants are shown one of several distinct ing scenarios (e.g., Scarf, Imuta, Colombo,
puppet shows, in which a Protagonist repeat- & Hayne, 2012). This concern can be ad-
edly struggles to achieve some goal: to climb dressed by demonstrations that infants’
a steep hill, to open the lid on a box, or to preference for Helpers over Hinderers only
 Infantile Roots of Sociomoral Evaluations 405

emerges when the helping and hindering consistent with work suggesting that infants
acts are directed toward a certain type of do not attribute goals to nonagents (e.g.,
target—specifically, a social agent. Consider Hamlin, Newman, & Wynn, 2009; Maha-
that kicking a soccer ball is fundamentally jan & Woodward, 2009; Meltzoff, 1995) and
different from kicking a person; though the with the conclusion that evaluations of Help-
behavior itself is the same in both cases, ball ers and Hinderers are based on their social
kicking is not likely to be considered mor- behaviors rather than on the performance
ally relevant, whereas person kicking is. To of a specific physical act, the causation of a
date, several studies have examined whether specific physical outcome, or a specific per-
infants consider the social status of those ceptual feature of the stimuli (see Scarf et al.,
targeted by “Helpers” and “Hinderers.” 2012, and responses by Hamlin, Wynn, &
First, the studies described above included Bloom, 2012; Hamlin, 2015). That said, the
infants who watched nonsocial versions of evidence provided thus far does not speak to
the helping and hindering events. In these whether infants’ preferences are in any sense
nonsocial scenarios, Helpers and Hinder- moral evaluations: Infants may simply like
ers directed their actions toward an inani- those whose actions facilitate others’ goals
mate object (an eyeless, motionless object and dislike those whose actions block oth-
or moving mechanical claw) rather than ers’ goals, perhaps because they believe those
an animate Protagonist. For example, the who help others are likely to help them. In-
“Helper” bumps an eyeless shape up the hill, deed, a recent study of the neural correlates of
opens the box with a claw, or rolls the ball infants’ processing of Helping and Hindering
back to the claw, and the “Hinderer” pup- events suggests that 6-month-olds’ detection
pet bumps the shape down the hill, slams of prosociality may be supported by the same
the box closed, or takes the ball and runs processes that support social perception more
offstage. If infants only evaluate the physi- generally, including the encoding of goal-di-
cal characteristics of the actions performed rected grasping, pointing, and gaze direction
or the end results of the helping and hinder- (Gredebäck et al., 2015), as opposed to any-
ing events, then infants should continue to thing specifically moral.
prefer the puppet performing helpful ac- To examine whether infants’ prosocial
tions in these nonsocial scenarios. Instead, preferences are consistent with moral eval-
infants do not preferentially look toward or uations, it is critical to determine whether
reach for either the “Helper” or the “Hin- they are sensitive to factors that influence
derer” in any nonsocial condition (Hamlin moral judgments in older children and
& Wynn, 2011; Hamlin et al., 2007, 2010). adults. These factors include (among many
In a second demonstration of the selectivity others) issues such as prosocial and antiso-
of infants’ evaluations to social targets, a cial agents’ intentions, their epistemic states,
recent study directly examined the distinc- and how the targets of their actions have be-
tion as described above, whereby kicking a haved in the past. In what follows, we pro-
person is evaluatively worse than kicking vide evidence that infants’ evaluations are
a soccer ball. Specifically, this study found sensitive to each of these factors.
that 10-month-olds prefer agents who direct
positive behaviors (comforting) toward hu-
Infants Consider Intent
mans and negative actions (pushing) toward
inanimate objects rather than agents who di- When evaluating an individual’s action as
rect negative behaviors toward humans and morally acceptable or unacceptable, adults
positive actions toward inanimate objects consider what the individual meant to do,
(Buon et al., 2014). That is, infants’ evalu- whether or not that individual achieved his
ations distinguish individuals whose actions or her goal (Cushman, 2008; Malle, 1999;
are identical based on which actions were Mikhail, 2007; Young, Cushman, Hauser,
directed toward social others. & Saxe, 2007). Although the outcome of a
Together, these results suggest that cooper- person’s action does influence adults’ moral
ative and noncooperative behaviors must be evaluations (i.e., the case of moral luck;
directed toward a social being for infants to Cushman & Greene, 2012), by considering
form positive or negative evaluations. This is intentions mature evaluators see past failed
406 D E V E L O P M E N TA L A N D E VO L U T I O N A RY R O O T S O F M O R A L I T Y

attempts, accidents, and other situationally 8-month-olds’ evaluations are influenced by


driven outcomes to determine whether an outcomes in contexts in which intent is less
individual possesses an intention to help or salient (e.g., accidents; see Le & Hamlin,
to harm. 2013), and whether infants younger than 8
Although studies using explicit verbal months could successfully focus on intention
measures have reliably demonstrated that in a simpler goal scenario than the one uti-
young children focus on outcome rather than lized in our studies.
intention when making social and moral
judgments (e.g., Baird & Astington, 2004;
Infants Consider Epistemic States
Costanzo, Coie, Grumet, & Farnill, 1973;
Cushman, Sheketoff, Wharton, & Carey, In addition to considering whether an indi-
2013; Piaget, 1932), it is possible that age- vidual facilitated or blocked an agent’s goal,
related changes in responses to verbal tasks and whether this behavior was performed
are confounded with age-related changes in intentionally, adults’ moral evaluations in-
other domains, masking children’s apprecia- clude an appraisal of various other mental
tion of the role of intentions in moral evalua- states. In doing so, sometimes the same
tions. Indeed, previous studies have demon- physical action is appropriately viewed as
strated that by 8–10 months of age infants nice, mean, or neither, depending on what
recognize intentions that go unfulfilled, suc- the actor was thinking while he or she per-
cessfully inferring an agent’s attempted, but formed it. For example, the act of giving a
failed, object-directed goal (e.g., Brandone gift is typically considered prosocial. How-
& Wellman, 2009; Brandone, Horwitz, ever, this evaluation can depend on the gift
Aslin, & Wellman, 2014; Hamlin, Hallinan, givers’ knowledge of both what the gift is
& Woodward, 2008; Hamlin et al., 2009). (e.g., whether the box contains a new watch
Given these results, it seems plausible that or a large spider) and of what the recipient
infants at the same age could incorporate in- desires (e.g., whether she prefers watches or
tention understanding into their sociomoral exotic pets).
evaluations. Although the results remain controver-
To determine whether infants’ evaluations sial (e.g., Heyes, 2014; Perner & Ruffman,
are sensitive to the intentions of third par- 2005), a growing body of research using
ties’ prosocial and antisocial attempts, we various methodologies suggests that infants
showed infants puppet shows featuring suc- and toddlers are able to take actors’ epis-
cessful and unsuccessful Helpers and Hin- temic states, such as knowledge and belief,
derers. Specifically, successful Helpers and into account when interpreting their actions
Hinderers carried out their intentions to (see Baillargeon, Setoh, Sloane, Jin, & Bian,
help or hinder the Protagonist in his efforts 2014, for review). In our laboratory we have
to open a box (as in Hamlin & Wynn, 2011), examined whether infants can also incorpo-
whereas failed Helpers and Hinderers were rate information about an actor’s epistemic
unsuccessful, bringing about outcomes that state into the evaluation of the actor’s so-
opposed their intentions. Across various cial behaviors. In this study, 10-month-olds
combinations of successful and unsuccessful viewed a scene including three characters:
Helpers and Hinderers, 8-month-olds, but a Protagonist who displayed an unfulfilled
not 5-month-olds, reliably preferred charac- goal and two others who observed his failed
ters with positive intentions regardless of the attempts. First, the Protagonist displayed
outcomes they brought about. In contrast, a preference for one of two toys, each of
8-month-olds did not prefer characters that which was accessible through openings in a
brought about better outcomes when ev- high wall. After choosing one toy and not
eryone’s intentions were the same (Hamlin, the other four times, doors were inserted
2013). These results suggest that, in contrast into the wall, blocking the Protagonist from
to a host of findings with preschool-age chil- reaching either toy. The two other puppets,
dren, by 8 months of age infants reliably use who had observed the Protagonist’s toy
intention, rather than outcome, to evaluate choices and so arguably “knew” his prefer-
others’ prosocial and antisocial acts. Several ence, then raised each of the doors in alter-
open questions remain, including whether nation. One Lifter allowed the Protagonist
 Infantile Roots of Sociomoral Evaluations 407

to reach the toy he had previously chosen, we showed infants events in which Helpers
and the other Lifter allowed the Protagonist and Hinderers interacted with previously
to reach the toy he had not previously cho- prosocial or antisocial Protagonists, who,
sen. When given the choice between the two respectively, deserved either reward or pun-
Lifters, 10-month-olds preferred the Lifter ishment. Over several studies, 4.5-, 8-, and
that allowed the Protagonist to reach his 19-month-olds preferred a character who
preferred toy (Hamlin, Ullman, Tenenbaum, helped a previously prosocial puppet but pre-
Goodman, & Baker, 2013). ferred a character who hindered a previously
In a second condition, in which the Lifter antisocial puppet (Hamlin, 2014a; Hamlin,
puppets were offstage during the Protago- Wynn, Bloom, & Mahajan, 2011). Together,
nist’s original object choices and so could these studies suggest that, rather than sim-
not have known which toy he preferred, in- ply preferring individuals who intentionally
fants did not prefer either Lifter, despite the perform prosocial, rather than antisocial,
fact that one Lifter had (unknowingly) al- behaviors, infants consider the recipient of
lowed the Protagonist to reach his preferred the actions and can positively evaluate inten-
toy and the other had not (Hamlin et al., tional antisocial behaviors that are directed
2013). In sum, infants differentially evaluat- toward antisocial individuals.
ed only characters who knew that they were Although positive evaluation of those that
acting to help or hinder the Protagonist; they direct antisocial behavior toward antisocial
did not differentially evaluate those who individuals is consistent with the claim that
happened to help or hinder the Protagonist infants prefer those that punish wrongdo-
without knowing they were doing so. This ers, it is not the only possible interpretation.
pattern of results suggests that infants’ eval- Rather than evaluating an antisocial individ-
uations are sensitive to cues regarding who ual as deserving of punishment, infants may
will cooperate in the future rather than who be attracted to the Hinderer of an antisocial
caused positive outcomes. other because this behavior reflects a shared
(negative) attitude toward that antisocial
other. A shared attitude toward the antiso-
Infants Consider Previous Behavior
cial other may suggest a source of mutual
The studies reviewed above demonstrate liking and affiliation (as illustrated by the
that infants are likely to approach Helpers common phrase “the enemy of my enemy is
and avoid Hinderers and that these tenden- my friend”; e.g., Heider, 1958). In support
cies are sensitive to a number of factors criti- of this affiliative account, infants also pre-
cal to identifying when someone is behav- fer those who hinder individuals that do not
ing prosocially or antisocially, including share the infant’s own food preferences (e.g.,
intention and epistemic states. That said, Hamlin, Mahajan, Liberman, & Wynn,
not all behaviors that are intentionally and 2013). Whereas adults can simultaneously
knowingly performed to block others’ goals dislike an individual’s “enemy” because of
necessarily signal that an individual should shared social preferences and disagree that
be avoided in the future. Indeed, some in- the disliked individual deserves punishment,
tentional antisocial behaviors signal that it is an open question whether infants’ dis-
someone is a good potential cooperative like of an individual is distinct from their
partner; for example, punishment that is desire to see that individual hindered.
directed toward deserving wrongdoers. In-
deed, punishment has been theorized to be
critical to stabilizing cooperative systems What Does a Preference
by reducing the benefits of free riding (e.g., for Helpers Mean?
Boyd & Richerson, 1992; O’Gorman et al.,
2009); successful cooperators must be both We have presented evidence that infants
motivated to punish wrongdoers and able to make relatively sophisticated evaluations,
positively evaluate those who punish appro- preferring those who intentionally and
priately. knowingly act to help deserving third par-
To examine whether infants consider the ties. Although we take this as suggestive that
context in which an action is performed, preverbal infants possess a sociomoral core,
408 D E V E L O P M E N TA L A N D E VO L U T I O N A RY R O O T S O F M O R A L I T Y

some researchers have argued that measure- viduals, suggest that infants’ preferences are
ments of infants’ preferences (via preferential both evaluative and consistent with a socio-
looking or reaching) are ill suited to provide moral core (for further discussion regarding
evidence of infants’ higher-order cognition. how preferential looking and reaching can be
Proponents of this view claim that, although used to explore early competencies in the so-
measures of preference can be used to de- cial and moral domains, see Hamlin, 2014b).
termine infants’ ability to discriminate be-
tween objects and explore perceptual pro-
Preferences for Helpers Are Not Only Evident
cesses, the use of preferential looking and
in Looking and Reaching
reaching paradigms to explore higher-level
domains, such as morality, ascribes too rich In addition, the extent to which preferential
an interpretation to infants’ preferences looking and reaching paradigms are able to
(Haith, 1998). In line with this perspective, distinguish between preferences based on
the conclusion that infants make sociomoral simple discrimination (the traditional use
evaluations has been questioned (e.g., Scarf of the paradigm) and preferences based on
et al., 2012; Tafreshi, Thompson, & Racine, positive evaluations has been questioned
2014). (Tafreshi, et al., 2014). The claim that an in-
nate sociomoral core supports infants’ early
emerging capacities to identify and selective-
Preferences for Helpers Are Not Based
ly approach Helpers necessitates that infants’
on Perceptual Cues
preferences be based on positive evaluations
Specifically, it has been debated whether of cooperative individuals. One way to ex-
infants’ preference for helpful rather than plore whether infants’ preferences are evalu-
unhelpful characters is simply a low-level ative is to examine the continuity between
response to the puppet show stimuli. For ex- the evaluations made in infancy and moral
ample, Scarf and colleagues suggested that judgments and behaviors across the lifespan.
infants’ preference for Helpers over Hin- To the extent that infants positively evaluate
derers in the hill scenario described above Helpers, there should be continuity between
could be due to an association between the early evaluations and later behaviors both
“Helper” and the Protagonist’s bouncing across children (e.g., the same scenarios
after being pushed up the hill (a positive per- should inspire similar judgments and behav-
ceptual event; Scarf et al., 2012). However, iors over development) and on an individual
when the Protagonist’s goal is clear, and his level (e.g., infants who were better at distin-
eyes are fixed in the direction of travel, 6- guishing prosocial from antisocial others in
to 11-month-olds prefer the Helper over the infancy should be better at other aspects of
Hinderer, regardless of whether the Protago- sociomoral development later in life).
nist bounces when he reaches the top of the To explore the first prediction, we have ex-
hill. In contrast, when the Protagonist’s goal plored the continuity between infants’ pref-
is unclear, and his eyes are not fixed in the erences following unfulfilled goal scenarios
direction of travel, infants show no prefer- and toddlers’ more complex behavioral re-
ence for Helpers over Hinderers, even when actions to the same individuals. Previous
the Protagonist bounces at the top of the hill work has shown that 19- to 23-month-olds
(Hamlin, 2015). These results suggest that a will selectively give “treats” to Helpers over
preference for Helpers is not dependent on Hinderers and selectively take “treats” from
low-level perceptual cues but rather due to Hinderers versus Helpers in the box and ball
infants’ sensitivity to whether an individual’s scenarios described above (Hamlin et al.,
goal is being facilitated or blocked. These 2011). Further, when puppets’ toy prefer-
results, combined with infants’ sensitivities ences are known, 20-month-olds are more
to whether a behavior targets a social agent, likely to give preferred toys to Helpers than
whether an action is performed intentionally to Hinderers, and are more likely to with-
and with appropriate mental state informa- hold toys from Hinderers rather than Help-
tion, and whether helping or hindering events ers (Van de Vondervoort, Aknin, Kushnir,
target previously prosocial or antisocial indi- Slevinsky, & Hamlin, in press). We have
 Infantile Roots of Sociomoral Evaluations 409

also explored 3- to 5-year-olds’ responses to core necessitates that infants are concerned
helping and hindering scenarios previously with an objective moral system. That is, in-
shown to infants, and found that preschool- fants’ preference for Helpers over Hinderers
ers preferred the Helper, judged the Helper ought to be due to the increased likelihood
to be “nicer” than the Hinderer, selectively that Helpers will contribute to the coopera-
allocated punishment to the Hinderer, and tive system rather than a preference for those
were able to justify their punishment allo- who infants see as more likely to help them
cations (Van de Vondervoort & Hamlin, specifically. An expectation that Helpers
2017). Continuity between infants’ prefer- will treat the infant well is not equivalent to
ences for Helpers, toddlers’ positive behav- a sense of what is moral, as an infant con-
iors toward Helpers, and children’s positive cerned with morality will prefer those that
verbal evaluations of Helpers suggests that act morally even when this conflicts with the
preferences at each age do in fact reflect pos- infant’s own self-interest.
itive evaluations. To explore whether infants prefer moral
The second prediction is being explored in characters over those that act to benefit the
an ongoing project that looks at individual infant, an ongoing study in our laboratory
differences among infants’ preferences for asks infants to choose between two char-
Helpers versus Hinderers. Although the vast acters: one that provides an equal number
majority of infants prefer helpful characters of resources to the baby and a third char-
over unhelpful characters across numerous acter and one that provides more resources
types of scenarios, there is variation in in- to the infant than to the third character
fants’ responding. We are currently explor- (Tan, Woo, & Hamlin, 2017). The extent to
ing whether differences in infants’ prefer- which infants prefer the fair distributor over
ences for Helpers or for Hinderers relates to the distributor that benefits the infant will
their sociomoral functioning in early child- speak to the likelihood that infants’ prefer-
hood. Parents of now preschool-age children ence for Helpers is related to morality per se,
who participated in several studies during rather than a simple ability to identify those
infancy are being asked to complete assess- likely to help them.
ments used to identify early warning signs One final caveat is that providing evi-
for various social developmental disorders, dence that infants can make some moral
in particular, those involving deficits in evaluations should in no way be taken to un-
understanding, evaluating, and otherwise dermine the roles of development, matura-
behaving appropriately in the sociomoral tion, and experience on moral development.
world (Tan, Mikami, & Hamlin, 2017). Evi- It is not our intention to argue that infants
dence that infants who consistently prefer are sensitive to all or even many of the wide
cooperative characters exhibit greater social variety of factors that adults consider when
and moral competency than infants who making moral judgments. Rather, we ap-
consistently prefer uncooperative characters preciate the role of maturing cognitive abili-
would further support the conclusion that ties (such as executive functioning, problem
infants’ preferences are truly evaluative and solving, counterfactual reasoning), interac-
critical to social developmental functioning. tions with parents and peers, and socializa-
tion within the family and wider community
in the development of a mature moral sys-
Preferences for Helpers Might Reflect
tem (see Killen & Smetana, 2006, 2014, for
Moral Evaluation
reviews). In contrast with these views, how-
In addition to concerns regarding the use of ever, we argue that infants do not start as
preferential looking and reaching paradigms entirely amoral or immoral beings. Rather,
to measure infants’ social evaluations, there infants have been endowed with a socio-
has also been debate regarding whether in- moral sense that supports early evaluations
fants’ preference for helpful actions can be of cooperative and noncooperative others,
interpreted as a preference for moral be- and that (at least somewhat) shapes the in-
havior (Tafreshi et al., 2014). Specifically, fluence of various other developmental pro-
the claim that infants possess a sociomoral cesses on moral development.
410 D E V E L O P M E N TA L A N D E VO L U T I O N A RY R O O T S O F M O R A L I T Y

Conclusion Cosmides, L., & Tooby, J. (1992). Cognitive ad-


aptations for social exchange. In J. Barkow,
In sum, recent developmental research sup- L. Cosmides, & J. Tooby (Eds.), The adapted
ports the claim that infants possess a socio- mind: Evolutionary psychology and the gen-
eration of culture (pp. 163–228). New York:
moral core. From extremely early in life, in- Oxford University Press.
fants make morally relevant evaluations that Costanzo, P. R., Coie, J. D., Grumet, J. F., &
are nuanced, context dependent, and consis- Farnill, D. (1973). A reexamination of the ef-
tent with adults’ reasoned moral judgments. fects of intent and consequence on children’s
This research supports the claim that moral- moral judgments. Child Development, 44(1),
ity and cooperation coevolved and suggests 154–161.
that morality is a core aspect of human na- Cushman, F. (2008). Crime and punishment:
ture. Future research should explore how Distinguishing the roles of causal and inten-
this innate sociomoral core constrains the tional analyses in moral judgment. Cognition,
108, 353–380.
influence of experience and other develop-
Cushman, F., & Greene J. D. (2012). Finding
mental mechanisms across moral develop- faults: How moral dilemmas illuminate cog-
ment and in what ways infants’ evaluations nitive structure. Social Neuroscience, 7(3),
differ from an adult moral sense. 269–279.
Cushman, F., Sheketoff, R., Wharton, S., &
Carey, S. (2013). The development of intent-
REFERENCES based moral judgment. Cognition, 127(1),
6–21.
Axelrod, R., & Hamilton, W. D. (1981). The de Quervain, D. J. F., Fischbacher, U., Treyer, V.,
evolution of cooperation. Science, 211, 1390– Schellhammer, M., Schnyder, U., Buck, A., &
1396. Fehr, E. (2004). The neural basis of altruistic
Baillargeon, R., Setoh, P., Sloane, S., Jin, K., & punishment. Science, 305(5688), 1254–1258.
Bian, L. (2014). Infant social cognition: Psy- Fawcett, C., & Liszkowski, U. (2012). Infants
chological and sociomoral reasoning. In M. S. anticipate others’ social preferences. Infant
Gazzaniga & G. R. Mangun (Eds.), The cog- and Child Development, 21(3), 239–249.
nitive neurosciences (5th ed., pp. 7–14). Cam- Fehr, E., & Gächter, S. (2002). Altruistic punish-
bridge, MA: MIT Press. ment in humans. Nature, 415, 137–140.
Baird, J. A., & Astington, J. W. (2004). The role Geraci, A., & Surian, L. (2011). The develop-
of mental state understanding in the develop- mental roots of fairness: Infants’ reactions to
ment of moral cognition and moral action. equal and unequal distributions of resources.
New Directions for Child and Adolescent De- Developmental Science, 14(5), 1012–1020.
velopment, 103, 37–49. Gredebäck, C., Kaduk, K., Bakker, M.,
Boyd, R., & Richerson, P. J. (1992). Punishment Gottwald, J., Ekberg, T., Elsner, C., . . . Ken-
allows the evolution of cooperation (or any- ward, B. (2015). The neuropsychology of in-
thing else) in sizable groups. Ethology and So- fants’ pro-social preferences. Developmental
ciobiology, 13(3), 171–195. Cognitive Neuroscience, 12, 106–113.
Brandone, A. C., Horwitz, S., Aslin, R. N., & Grusec, J. E., & Goodnow, J. J. (1994). Impact
Wellman, H. M. (2014). Infants’ goal antici- of parental discipline methods on the child’s
pation during failed and successful reaching internalization of values: A reconceptualiza-
actions. Developmental Science, 17(1), 23–34. tion of current points of view. Developmental
Brandone, A. C., & Wellman, H. M. (2009). You Psychology, 30(1), 4–19.
can’t always get what you want: Infants under- Haith, M. M. (1998). Who put the cog in infant
stand failed goal-directed actions. Psychologi- cognition?: Is rich interpretation too costly?
cal Science, 20(1), 85–91. Infant Behavior and Development, 21(2),
Brown, D. E. (1991). Human universals. New 167–179.
York: McGraw-Hill. Hamlin, J. K. (2013). Failed attempts to help and
Bull, J. J., & Rice, W. R. (1991). Distinguishing harm: Intention versus outcome in preverbal
mechanisms for the evolution of co-operation. infants’ social evaluations. Cognition, 128(3),
Journal of Theoretical Biology, 149(1), 63–74. 451–474.
Buon, M., Jacob, P., Margules, S., Brunet, Hamlin, J. K. (2014a). Context-dependent social
I., Dutat, M., Cabrol, D., & Dupoux, E. evaluation in 4.5-month-old human infants:
(2014). Friend or foe?: Early social evalua- The role of domain-general versus domain-
tion of human interactions. PLOS ONE, 9(2), specific processes in the development of evalu-
e88612. ation. Frontiers in Psychology, 5, 614. Avail-
 Infantile Roots of Sociomoral Evaluations 411

able at www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/ mans cooperate: A cultural and evolutionary


PMC4061491. ex­planation. Oxford, UK: Oxford University
Hamlin, J. K. (2014b). The conceptual and em- Press.
pirical case for social evaluation in infancy: Heyes, C. (2014). False belief in infancy: A fresh
Commentary on Tafreshi, Thompson, and look. Developmental Science, 17(5), 647–659.
Racine. Human Development, 57, 250–258. Hrdy, S. B. (2009). Mothers and others: The evo-
Hamlin, J. K. (2015). The case for social evalua- lutionary origins of mutual understanding.
tion in preverbal infants: Gazing toward one’s Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
goal drives infants’ preferences for Helpers Katz, L. D. (Ed.). (2000). Evolutionary origins
over Hinderers in the hill paradigm. Frontiers of morality: Cross-disciplinary perspectives.
in Psychology, 5, 1563. Bowling Green, OH: Imprint Academic.
Hamlin, J. K., Hallinan, E. V., & Woodward, Killen, M., & Smetana, J. (Eds.). (2006). Hand-
A. L. (2008). Do as I do: 7-month-old infants book of moral development. Mahwah, NJ:
selectively reproduce others’ goals. Develop- Erlbaum.
mental Science, 11(4), 487–494. Killen, M., & Smetana, J. (Eds.). (2014). Hand-
Hamlin, J. K., Mahajan, N., Liberman, Z., & book of moral development (2nd ed.). New
Wynn, K. (2013). Not like me = bad: Infants York: Psychology Press.
prefer those who harm dissimilar others. Psy- Kohlberg, L. (1969). Stages in the development
chological Science, 24(4), 589–594. of moral thought and action. New York: Holt,
Hamlin, J. K., Newman, G., & Wynn, K. (2009). Rinehart, & Winston.
8-month-olds infer unfulfilled goals, despite Kuhlmeier, V., Wynn, K., & Bloom, P. (2003).
contrary physical evidence. Infancy, 14(5), Attribution of dispositional states by
579–590. 12-month-olds. Psychological Science, 14(5),
Hamlin, J. K., Ullman, T., Tenenbaum, J., Good- 402–408.
man, N., & Baker, C. (2013). The mentalistic Le, D. T., & Hamlin, J. K. (2013, April). Ten-
basis of core social cognition: Experiments in month-olds’ evaluations of accidental and
preverbal infants and a computational model. intentional actions. Poster presented at the bi-
Developmental Science, 16(2), 209–226. annual meeting for the Society for Research in
Hamlin, J. K., & Wynn, K. (2011). Young infants Child Development, Seattle, WA.
prefer prosocial to antisocial others. Cognitive Lee, Y., Yun, J., Kim, E., & Song, H. (2015). The
Development, 26(1), 30–39. development of infants’ sensitivity to behav-
Hamlin, J. K., Wynn, K., & Bloom, P. (2007). ioral intentions when inferring others’ social
Social evaluation by preverbal infants. Nature, preferences. PLOS ONE, 10(9), e0135588.
450(7169), 557–559. Mahajan, N., & Woodward, A. (2009). Seven-
Hamlin, J. K., Wynn, K., & Bloom, P. (2010). month-old infants selectively reproduce the
Three-month-olds show a negativity bias in goals of animate but not inanimate agents. In-
their social evaluations. Developmental Sci- fancy, 14(6), 667–679.
ence, 13(6), 923–929. Malle, B. F. (1999). How people explain behav-
Hamlin, J. K., Wynn, K., & Bloom, P. (2012). ior: A new theoretical framework. Personality
Reply to Scarf et al.: Nuanced social evalua- and Social Psychology Review, 3(1), 23–48.
tion: Association doesn’t compute. Proceed- McDonnell, P. M. (1975). The development of
ings of the National Academy of Sciences of visually guided reaching. Perception and Psy-
the USA, 109(22), E1427. chophysics, 18(3), 181–185.
Hamlin, J. K., Wynn, K., Bloom, P., & Mahajan, Meltzoff, A. N. (1995). Understanding the inten-
N. (2011). How infants and toddlers react to tions of others: Re-enactment of intended acts
antisocial others. Proceedings of the Nation- by 18-month-old children. Developmental
al Academy of Sciences of the USA, 108(5), Psychology, 31(5), 838–850.
19931–19936. Mikhail, J. (2007). Universal moral grammar:
Heider, F. (1958). The psychologyof interperson- Theory, evidence and the future. Trends in
al relations. New York: Wiley. Cognitive Sciences, 11(4), 143–152.
Henderson, A. M. E., & Woodward, A. L. O’Gorman, R., Henrich, J., & Van Vugt, M.
(2011). “Let’s work together”: What do in- (2009). Constraining free riding in public
fants understand about collaborative goals? goods games: Designated solitary punishers
Cognition, 121, 12–21. can sustain human cooperation. Proceedings
Henrich, J., McElreath, R., Barr, A., Ensminger, of the Royal Society of London: Series B,
J., Barrett, C., Bolyanatz, A., . . . Ziker, J. 276(1655), 323–329.
(2006). Costly punishment across human so- Perner, J., & Ruffman, T. (2005). Infants’ insight
cieties. Science, 312, 1767–1770. into the mind: How deep? Science, 308(5719),
Henrich, N., & Henrich, J. (2007). Why hu- 214–216.
412 D E V E L O P M E N TA L A N D E VO L U T I O N A RY R O O T S O F M O R A L I T Y

Piaget, J. (1932). The moral judgment of the (2014). An analysis of the conceptual founda-
child. London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner. tions of the infant preferential looking para-
Premack, D., & Premack, A. J. (1997). Infants digm. Human Development, 57, 222–240.
attribute value ± to the goal-directed actions Tan, E., Mikami, A. Y., & Hamlin, J. K. (2017).
of self-propelled objects. Journal of Cognitive Performance on infant sociomoral evaluation
Neuroscience, 9(6), 848–856. and action studies predicts preschool social
Salvadori, E., Blazsekova, T., Volein, A., Karap, and behavioural adjustment in males. Unpub-
Z., Tatone, D., Mascaro, O., & Csibra, G. lished manuscript, University of British Co-
(2015). Probing the strength of infants’ pref- lumbia, Vancouver, Canada.
erence for Helpers over Hinderers: Two repli- Tan, E., Woo, B. M., & Hamlin, J. K. (2017).
cation attempts of Hamlin and Wynn (2011). Unfair to whom?: Exploration of infants’ pref-
PLOS ONE, 10(11), e0140570. erences for fair versus self-benefiting others.
Scarf, D., Imuta, K., Colombo, M., & Hayne, Unpublished manuscript.
H. (2012). Social evaluation or simple as- Trivers, R. L. (1971). The evolution of reciprocal
sociation?: Simple associations may explain altruism. Quarterly Review of Biology, 46(1),
moral reasoning in infants. PLOS ONE, 7(8), 35–57.
e42698. Turiel, E. (1983). The development of social
Schmidt, M. F. H., & Sommerville, J. A. (2011). knowledge: Morality and convention. Cam-
Fairness expectation and altruistic sharing in bridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
15-month-old human infants. PLOS ONE, Van de Vondervoort, J. W., Aknin, L. B., Kush-
6(10), e23223. nir, T., Slevinsky, J., & Hamlin, J. K. (in
Scola, C., Holvoet, C., Arciszewski, T., & Picard, press). Selectivity in toddlers’ behavioral and
D. (2015). Further evidence for infants’ prefer- emotional reactions to prosocial and antiso-
ence for prosocial over antisocial behaviors. cial others. Developmental Psychology.
Infancy, 20(6), 684–692. Van de Vondervoort, J. W., & Hamlin, J. K.
Sloane, S., Baillargeon, R., & Premack, D. (2017). Preschoolers’ social and moral judg-
(2012). Do infants have a sense of fairness? ments of third party helpers and hinderers
Psychological Science, 23(2), 196–204. align with infants’ social evaluations. Jour-
Smetana, J. G. (2006). Social-cognitive domain nal of Experimental Child Psychology, 164,
theory: Consistencies and variations in chil- 136–151.
dren’s moral and social judgments. In M. Kil- Young, L., Cushman, F., Hauser, M., & Saxe,
len, & J. G. Smetana (Eds.), Handbook of R. (2007). The neural basis of the interaction
moral development (pp. 119–154). Mahwah, between theory of mind and moral judgment.
NJ: Erlbaum. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sci-
Tafreshi, D., Thompson, J. J., & Racine, T. P. ences of the USA, 104(20), 8235–8240.
CHAPTER 42

Atlas Hugged
The Foundations of Human Altruism

Felix Warneken

What are the origins of human altruism?

Evidence from young children and chimpanzees suggests that human


altruism is based upon psychological processes that have deep roots
in development and evolution, with human-unique social practices
building upon these basic tendencies.

Notwithstanding Ayn Rand’s embrace of alone. Here I propose that one powerful way
self-interested behavior as a virtue, most to illuminate the foundations of human na-
people think they have some obligation ture is to examine the psychology of young
to help others in need; pure egoism is not children.
often celebrated outside such philosophical If we looked only at the mature behaviors
treatises. But what is the foundation of our of adults, we would not be able to ascertain
more altruistic orientations toward others? the critical factors that give rise to our al-
One hypothesis is that altruistic behavior in truistic (and selfish) behaviors. However, if
adults emerges because individuals learn so- we assess the earliest forms of social behav-
cial norms about how to act. This proposal iors in children and trace their development,
would suggest that young children have a we get a better handle on the factors that
fundamentally “Randian” orientation to- are actually foundational and learn how an
ward their interactions with others but over- individual’s tendencies and societal factors
come this inherent selfishness by internal- interact. Therefore, one main goal here is to
izing social standards. An alternative view review recent studies on altruistic behaviors
is that humans actually do possess moral in young children. In addition, I suggest that,
sentiments to act on behalf of others, even to learn something about humans, we also
independent of such social teachings. That have to look at nonhumans. Specifically, by
is, this view suggests that human altruism comparing our behaviors with those of our
does not depend on external social norms closest evolutionary relatives—chimpan-

413
414 D E V E L O P M E N TA L A N D E VO L U T I O N A RY R O O T S O F M O R A L I T Y

zees—we can gain insight into the degree fulfilled goals and finding ways to help. In
to which human society is actually founda- these experiments, situations are created in
tional for our altruistic behaviors or if they which a person needs help and the child has
are rooted in our phylogenetic inheritance. the opportunity to intervene. For example,
Here I argue against the hypothesis that results show that when 18-month-olds wit-
regards the internalization of social norms ness someone unsuccessfully reaching for a
as the condition sine qua non of human al- dropped object, they will get up and pick it
truistic behaviors. In psychology, in several up for the other person. Likewise, when an
variations, it has been proposed that social- adult is awkwardly bumping into the doors
ization practices such as norm internaliza- of a cabinet while carrying a stack of books
tion, social modeling, and rewarding chil- in both hands, the children will hold the
dren for appropriate behaviors are at the door open (Dunfield & Kuhlmeier, 2013;
center of altruism (Bar-Tal, 1982; Chudek Dunfield, Kuhlmeier, O’Connell, & Kel-
& Henrich, 2011; Dahl, 2015; Dovidio, Pil- ley, 2011; Warneken & Tomasello, 2006,
iavin, Schroeder, & Penner, 2006). By con- 2007). Importantly, toddlers help quite flex-
trast, I want to advance the hypothesis that ibly by retrieving out-of-reach objects, open-
the basic altruistic tendencies of humans are ing closed doors, stacking objects, and even
grounded in a biological predisposition that correcting an adult’s path of action: Rather
can be shaped by socialization and other fac- than using the experimenter’s wrong ap-
tors. Thus, although socialization can shape proach to try to squeeze his hand through a
development, the foundation of human al- tiny hole in order to retrieve an object from
truism has deeper roots. a box, children lifted a flap on the side to get
To evaluate these different hypotheses, I to the object. Fourteen-month-olds already
summarize studies on children’s helping be- help with the simpler tasks of handing over
haviors. Briefly put, these studies show that objects (Warneken & Tomasello, 2007),
humans act altruistically from a very early and, by 18 months, children can help in a
age, before specific socialization factors whole array of situations in which they have
such as the internalization of cultural norms to infer the other person’s goal and come up
could have had a major impact on children’s with various ways of how to help (Warneken
development. Moreover, I present evidence & Tomasello, 2006). Thus young children
that chimpanzees also act helpfully toward rapidly develop the ability to help in a vari-
others on occasion—raising the possibility ety of ways.
that humans are perhaps not as special in Eighteen-month-olds show even more
their psychology as one might think. sophistication by assessing a person’s igno-
rance when helping. When an adult did not
see that a toy had moved from one box to
Evidence another box, children disregarded the box
the person was trying to open and fetched
Helping in Children
the object from the correct location (Buttel-
A good test case for the study of early altru- mann, Carpenter, & Tomasello, 2009). This
ism is helping behaviors. To help someone type of response may even be subserved by
with a problem, the helper must be able to a representation of false beliefs. In another
cognitively represent the goal another per- situation, children warned a protagonist
son is trying but failing to achieve and have before she reached into one of two buckets
a motivation to act upon that realization. We when the one she falsely believed contained
regard this helping behavior as altruistically a desired object actually held a yucky ob-
motivated if children act to further the other ject; but they pointed indiscriminately when
person’s goal rather than to gain a concrete she was ignorant (Knudsen & Liszkowski,
benefit for themselves. Recent studies show 2012a, 2012b, 2013). Children seemed to
that children exhibit helping behaviors from infer that when an adult holds a false belief,
early on in life. the adult is likely to take the wrong course
A series of studies have probed children’s of action and has to be warned beforehand.
cognitive sophistication in identifying un- Together, these studies indicate that chil-
 The Foundations of Human Altruism 415

dren actually try to help other people with help and attained the goal (Hepach, Vaish,
the intended goals (and not just blindly join & Tomasello, 2012). Importantly, this relief
into the adult’s activity) and are able to infer occurred whether they helped or some other
these goals based upon the other person’s bystander helped out, indicating that the
state of knowledge. relevant feature was that the other person
With increasing age, toddlers become able achieved the goal, not the child’s own activ-
to make the right inference based upon more ity of helping.
subtle cues. Children at 14–18 months typi- Another possible explanation is that chil-
cally help only after a salient cue, such as dren help to obtain a tangible reward. How-
a person reaching for an object or directly ever, this doesn’t seem to drive children’s
asking the child for help (Svetlova, Nichols, helping, either: In most studies, no concrete
& Brownell, 2009; Warneken & Tomasello, rewards are used, and children still help.
2007). However, 2-year-olds can help even Moreover, children who were offered a re-
when such behavioral cues are absent alto- ward for helping were not more likely to help
gether. For example, they helped by return- than children who helped without a reward
ing cans to a person who had not noticed (Warneken, Hare, Melis, Hanus, & Toma-
that they had rolled off a table and thus did sello, 2007). In fact, material rewards can
not provide any cues that she needed help (as have detrimental effects, as children who re-
compared with a control condition in which ceived a toy for helping were subsequently
no help was necessary; Warneken, 2013). less likely to help spontaneously than chil-
Thus children could help even though con- dren who had never been “paid” (Warneken
current cues to elicit helping were absent, & Tomasello, 2008). This indicates that
demonstrating that they could use situation- external rewards can undermine children’s
al cues to infer what to do. intrinsic motivation for helping.
Young children thus show some level of Finally, this evidence for helping in early
cognitive sophistication. They know when ontogeny makes it implausible that helping
and how to help. But what exactly moti- requires an adult-like moral value system,
vates their helping? One potential explana- as preverbal infants are unlikely to be mo-
tion is that they want to please their parents tivated by normative principles. In fact, it is
or other authority figures (rather than car- only in middle to late childhood that chil-
ing about the person needing help). How- dren begin to reason about social norms as
ever, children help spontaneously in the obligatory. During this period of develop-
parents’ absence, proving that they do not ment, children perceive failures to follow
help just because of obedience to paren- such norms as guilt-evoking (Tomasello &
tal authority or the expectation of praise Vaish, 2013), develop a moral self (Kochan-
(Warneken, 2013; Warneken & Tomasello, ska, 2002), and hold themselves and oth-
2013). Moreover, being watched by oth- ers to the same general standards (Blake,
ers versus acting in private does not seem McAuliffe, & Warneken, 2014; Smith,
to concern children before around 5 years Blake, & Harris, 2013). Therefore, return-
of age, showing that reputational concerns ing to the question about the foundation of
are not foundational for their altruism, ei- human altruism, these studies suggest that
ther (Engelmann, ­Herrmann, & Tomasello, young children may have a predisposition
2012; Leimgruber, Shaw, Santos, & Olson, for altruistic behavior that is not based upon
2012). Thus children seem to be genuinely socialization factors alone, such as reputa-
motivated by the other person’s goal, not by tional concerns about social expectations, a
showing off or demonstrating their mastery long history of being rewarded for helping,
in handling the situation in front of others. or the internalization of a moral value sys-
Further evidence comes from a study that tem. These factors that are known to be rel-
used changes in pupil dilation to measure evant for adults (and have been proposed to
children’s arousal during helping scenarios. underlie the emergence of altruistic behavior
Two-year-olds remained aroused when they in children) do not appear to be necessary
witnessed a person failing to reach an object for the basic altruistic helping behaviors of
but were relieved when the person received young children.
416 D E V E L O P M E N TA L A N D E VO L U T I O N A RY R O O T S O F M O R A L I T Y

Before arriving at the conclusion that so- possess basic capacities for helping. For ex-
cialization alone cannot explain early help- ample, chimpanzees helped a caregiver pick
ing behavior, we have to assess an alternative up dropped objects without a direct request
possibility. Although these particular social- and without receiving a reward (Warneken
ization practices are unlikely to be founda- & Tomasello, 2006). Moreover, chimpan-
tional, toddlers still have several months to zees helped an unfamiliar human without
be socialized into altruism by other means. any prior personal history in a similar con-
Indeed, adults may care so much about turn- text (Warneken et al., 2007). Chimpanzees
ing their (allegedly) selfish children into al- also help other chimpanzees by handing over
truists that children may be on a fast track out-of-reach objects (Yamamoto, Humle,
toward altruism. For example, children grow & Tanaka, 2009; Yamamoto, Humle, &
up in a rich social environment in which Tanaka, 2012). Chimpanzees do not simply
they witness and engage in various coop- hand over any old object but seem to know
erative activities and may be encouraged to how to help. When a conspecific needed a
repeat socially desirable behaviors. Experi- specific tool to retrieve rewards from an ap-
ments show that children’s positive interac- paratus, chimpanzee subjects handed over
tions and affiliative cues prime children to the appropriate tool from a set of potential
be more helpful later (Barragan & Dweck, options (Yamamoto et al., 2012). Chimpan-
2014; Carpenter, Uebel, & Tomasello, 2013; zees, not unlike 18-month-olds, are also ca-
Cirelli, Einarson, & Trainor, 2014; Cirelli, pable of helping others in a variety of dif-
Wan, & Trainor, 2014; Hamann, Warnek- ferent ways, such as opening a door for a
en, & Tomasello, 2012; Kirschner & To- conspecific who is trying to access a piece of
masello, 2010; Over & Carpenter, 2009). food in a neighboring room (Melis, Hare, &
Moreover, the activities children participate Tomasello, 2008; Warneken et al., 2007; for
in at home are correlated with helping in the bonobos, see Tan & Hare, 2013). Moreover,
lab, and parental discourse about other peo- when a conspecific struggled to pull in a bag
ple’s needs and emotions is associated with with treats because the rope was attached to
more helping (Brownell, Svetlova, Anderson, bars with a hook, chimpanzees unhooked
Nichols, & Drummond, 2013; Dahl, 2015; the rope so that the other could pull it in
Hammond & Carpendale, 2015). However, (Melis et al., 2011). Importantly, in all of
the importance of these factors in the ini- these studies, chimpanzees performed these
tial emergence of altruism, as opposed to acts selectively in experimental conditions in
its subsequent refinement, is difficult to as- which help was needed, but they rarely per-
sess from human data alone. Studies with formed these acts in matched control condi-
chimpanzees can help in this case. Although tions in which the behavior would not have
social transmission of some group-typical been helpful. Hence, chimpanzees can make
behavior may occur in some domains, such inferences about the other individual’s goal
as tool use (Whiten, McGuigan, Marshall- and help across various situations much like
Pescini, & Hopper, 2009), there is currently human toddlers. Importantly, some of these
no indication that chimpanzees transmit situations are novel, ruling out that their
cultural norms about appropriate social be- helping was simply shaped by previous ex-
havior or actively reward their offspring for perience.
social behaviors toward others. Thus stud- Concerning apes’ motivation to help, evi-
ies with chimpanzees can inform us about dence suggests that they too are motivated
whether these types of socialization factors by the other individual’s goal, rather than an
are actually necessary for helping behaviors immediate benefit for themselves. Chimpan-
to emerge in the first place. zees offered help without receiving concrete
rewards (Greenberg, Hamann, Warneken,
& Tomasello, 2010; House, Silk, Lambeth,
Helping in Chimpanzees
& Schapiro, 2014; Melis et al., 2008; Melis
Recent experiments have tested chimpan- et al., 2011; Warneken & Tomasello, 2006;
zees in situations similar to the helping Yamamoto et al., 2009, 2012), and chim-
tasks with children described above. These panzees who were rewarded for helping were
experiments reveal that chimpanzees also no more likely to help than those who never
 The Foundations of Human Altruism 417

received a reward (Warneken et al., 2007). are not unique to our species: Chimpanzees
Taken together, the basic cognitive ability as also are motivated and able to help others.
well as the basic altruistic motivation to help This provides strong evidence that altruistic
others appears to be present in chimpanzees behavior can emerge in the absence of norm
as well. internalization or moral teachings. Although
Despite these similarities, there are also there is no doubt that human altruistic be-
several notable differences. One difference havior is shaped by socialization practices
is in the cues that elicit helping. Whereas and adult moral norms as children grow
children help proactively—assisting in the older, these factors appear to build upon a
absence of concurrent cues or solicitation foundation that has deep roots in evolution,
from the recipient (Knudsen & Liszkowski, reaching back to at least the last common an-
2012a, 2012b, 2013; Warneken, 2013)— cestor of humans and chimpanzees.
chimpanzees only seem to help reactively
in response to explicit goal cues. For ex-
ample, chimpanzees are far more likely to ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
help when the recipient is actively trying to
pull in a bag with rewards or communicates I thank Alexandra Rosati for helpful comments
and Randi Vogt for editing. This work was sup-
toward the subject than when the recipient ported by a National Science Foundation CA-
remains passive (Melis et al., 2011). Simi- REER award.
larly, chimpanzees rarely offered a tool to a
conspecific partner unless the recipient was
actively reaching for it (Yamamoto et al., REFERENCES
2009, 2012). More generally, when recipi-
ents are not actively engaged in a task (such Barragan, R. C., & Dweck, C. S. (2014). Re-
as trying to open or retrieve something) but thinking natural altruism: Simple reciprocal
are passively waiting, apes exhibit much interactions trigger children’s benevolence.
lower rates of altruistic behavior (House et Proceedings of the National Academy of Sci-
ences of the USA, 111(48), 17071–17074.
al., 2014). It is unclear whether this apparent Bar-Tal, D. (1982). Sequential development of
species- difference is best explained by a dif- helping behavior: A cognitive-learning ap-
ference in the cognitive capacity to compute proach. Developmental Review, 2, 101–124.
the need for help or whether this reflects a Blake, P. R., McAuliffe, K., & Warneken, F.
difference in motivation. (2014). The developmental origins of fairness:
The knowledge–behavior gap. Trends in Cog-
nitive Sciences, 18(11), 559–561.
Conclusion Brownell, C. A., Svetlova, M., Anderson, R.,
Nichols, S. R., & Drummond, J. (2013). So-
Atlas took it upon himself to carry the sky on cialization of early prosocial behavior: Par-
ents’ talk about emotion is associated with
his shoulders. Human toddlers are not quite
sharing and helping in toddlers. Infancy,
able to make a sacrifice of this scale, but they 18(1), 91–119.
are willing to help others in more down-to- Buttelmann, D., Carpenter, M., & Tomasello,
earth ways that are within their physical M. (2009). Eighteen-month-old infants show
powers—such as by picking up clothespins. false belief understanding in an active helping
Importantly, these fairly basic helping behav- paradigm. Cognition, 112, 337–342.
iors already reflect the core features of altru- Carpenter, M., Uebel, J., & Tomasello, M.
ism seen in adults, and they increase in scope (2013). Being mimicked increases prosocial
and importance over development (Warnek- behavior in 18-month-old infants. Child De-
en, 2015). Yet, in contrast to Atlas, children velopment, 84(5), 1511–1518.
perform these tasks voluntarily. However, Chudek, M., & Henrich, J. (2011). Culture–gene
coevolution, norm-psychology and the emer-
to more fully understand the emergence of gence of human prosociality. Trends in Cogni-
human-like altruism, we have to look be- tive Sciences, 15(5), 218–226.
yond humans (and Titans) to also examine Cirelli, L. K., Einarson, K. M., & Trainor, L. J.
our closest evolutionary relatives. In fact, (2014). Interpersonal synchrony increases pro-
studies that compare children and chimpan- social behavior in infants. Developmental Sci-
zees show that the basic helping tendencies ence, 17(6), 1003–1011.
418 D E V E L O P M E N TA L A N D E VO L U T I O N A RY R O O T S O F M O R A L I T Y

Cirelli, L. K., Wan, S. J., & Trainor, L. J. (2014). Knudsen, B., & Liszkowski, U. (2013). One-
Fourteen-month-old infants use interpersonal year-olds warn others about negative action
synchrony as a cue to direct helpfulness. Philo- outcomes. Journal of Cognition and Develop-
sophical Transactions of the Royal Society of ment, 14(3), 424–436.
London: B. Biological Sciences, 369(1658), Kochanska, G. (2002). Committed compliance,
20130400. moral self, and internalization: A mediational
Dahl, A. (2015). The developing social context of model. Developmental Psychology, 38(3),
infant helping in two US samples. Child De- 339–351.
velopment, 86, 1080–1093. Leimgruber, K. L., Shaw, A., Santos, L. R., &
Dovidio, J. F., Piliavin, J. A., Schroeder, D. A., Olson, K. R. (2012). Young children are more
& Penner, L. A. (2006). The social psychology generous when others are aware of their ac-
of prosocial behavior. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. tions. PLOS ONE, 7(10), e48292.
Dunfield, K. A., & Kuhlmeier, V. A. (2013). Melis, A. P., Hare, B., & Tomasello, M. (2008).
Classifying prosocial behavior: Children’s Do chimpanzees reciprocate received favours?
responses to instrumental need, emotional Animal Behaviour, 76(3), 951–962.
distress, and material desire. Child Develop- Melis, A. P., Warneken, F., Jensen, K., Schnei-
ment, 84(5), 1766–1776. der, A. C., Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2011).
Dunfield, K. A., Kuhlmeier, V. A., O’Connell, Chimpanzees help conspecifics obtain food
L., & Kelley, E. (2011). Examining the diver- and non-food items. Proceedings of the Royal
sity of prosocial behaviour: Helping, sharing, Society of London: Series B, 278(1710),
and comforting in infancy. Infancy, 16(3), 1405–1413.
227–247. Over, H., & Carpenter, M. (2009). Eighteen-
Engelmann, J. M., Herrmann, E., & Tomasello, month-old infants show increased helping fol-
M. (2012). Five-year-olds, but not chimpan- lowing priming with affiliation. Psychological
zees, attempt to manage their reputations. Science, 20(10), 1189–1193.
PLOS ONE, 7(10), e48433. Smith, C. E., Blake, P. R., & Harris, P. L. (2013).
Greenberg, J. R., Hamann, K., Warneken, F., & I should but I won’t: Why young children en-
Tomasello, M. (2010). Chimpanzee helping in dorse norms of fair sharing but do not follow
collaborative and noncollaborative contexts. them. PLOS ONE, 8(3), e59510.
Animal Behaviour, 80(5), 873–880. Svetlova, M., Nichols, S. R., & Brownell, C. A.
Hamann, K., Warneken, F., & Tomasello, M. (2009). Toddlers’ prosocial behavior: From
(2012). Children’s developing commitments instrumental to empathic to altruistic helping.
to joint goals. Child Development, 83(1), Child Development, 81(6), 1814–1827.
137–145. Tan, J., & Hare, B. (2013). Bonobos share with
Hammond, S. I., & Carpendale, J. I. M. (2015). strangers. PLOS ONE, 8(1), e51922.
Helping children help: The relation between Tomasello, M., & Vaish, A. (2013). Origins of
maternal scaffolding and children’s early help. human cooperation and morality. Annual Re-
Social Development, 24, 367–383. view of Psychology, 64, 231–255.
Hepach, R., Vaish, A., & Tomasello, M. (2012). Warneken, F. (2013). Young children proac-
Young children are intrinsically motivated tively remedy unnoticed accidents. Cognition,
to see others helped. Psychological Science, 126(1), 101–108.
23(9), 967–972. Warneken, F. (2015). Precocious prosociality:
House, B. R., Silk, J. B., Lambeth, S. P., & Scha- Why do young children help? Child Develop-
piro, S. J. (2014). Task design influences pro- ment Perspectives, 9, 1–6.
sociality in captive chimpanzees (Pan troglo- Warneken, F., Hare, B., Melis, A. P., Hanus,
dytes). PLOS ONE, 9(9), e103422. D., & Tomasello, M. (2007). Spontaneous
Kirschner, S., & Tomasello, M. (2010). Joint altruism by chimpanzees and young children.
music making promotes prosocial behavior PLOS Biology, 5(7), 1414–1420.
in 4-year-old children. Evolution and Human Warneken, F., & Tomasello, M. (2006). Altruis-
Behavior, 31(5), 354–364. tic helping in human infants and young chim-
Knudsen, B., & Liszkowski, U. (2012a). panzees. Science, 311(5765), 1301–1303.
18-month-olds predict specific action mis- Warneken, F., & Tomasello, M. (2007). Helping
takes through attribution of false belief, not and cooperation at 14 months of age. Infancy,
ignorance, and intervene accordingly. Infancy, 11(3), 271–294.
17(6), 672–691. Warneken, F., & Tomasello, M. (2008). Extrin-
Knudsen, B., & Liszkowski, U. (2012b). Eigh- sic rewards undermine altruistic tendencies in
teen- and 24-month-old infants correct others 20-month-olds. Developmental Psychology,
in anticipation of action mistakes. Develop- 44(6), 1785–1788.
mental Science, 15(1), 113–122. Warneken, F., & Tomasello, M. (2013). Paren-
 The Foundations of Human Altruism 419

tal presence and encouragement do not influ- Yamamoto, S., Humle, T., & Tanaka, M. (2009).
ence helping in young children. Infancy, 18(3), Chimpanzees help each other upon request.
345–368. PLOS ONE, 4(10), 1–7.
Whiten, A., McGuigan, N., Marshall-Pescini, Yamamoto, S., Humle, T., & Tanaka, M. (2012).
S., & Hopper, L. M. (2009). Emulation, imi- Chimpanzees’ flexible targeted helping based
tation, over-imitation and the scope of culture on an understanding of conspecifics’ goals.
for child and chimpanzee. Philosophical Trans- Proceedings of the National Academy of Sci-
actions of the Royal Society, 364, 2417–2428. ences of the USA, 109, 3588–3592.
CHAPTER 43

The Developmental Origins of Infants’


Distributive Fairness Concerns

Jessica A. Sommerville
Talee Ziv

How and when do fairness concerns emerge over the course of


development?

Stemming from infant experience, an intuitive sense of distribu‑


tive fairness emerges within the first 2 years of life, and this sense
encompasses many aspects of mature moral responses.

Debates concerning the origins of moral sen- systems that are general purpose or special-
timents have long occupied the thoughts of ized, and culturally uniform or variable.
scholars and lay people alike. Well before Of course, morality consists of a vari-
modern-day experimental psychologists ety of subdomains that include not only
sought to devise tasks to mine mature and concerns of welfare and fairness (Turiel,
developing moral minds and brains, philos- 1983) but also concerns about loyalty, au-
ophers including Plato, Aristotle, Hobbes, thority, and sanctity (Graham & Haidt,
Locke, and Rousseau (among others) theo- 2010; Haidt, 2007), perhaps extending to
rized about the developmental starting concerns of liberty as well (Haidt, 2012).
points and subsequent unfolding of moral Our own work has primarily focused on
thoughts and behavior. Central to these age- emerging concerns about distributive fair-
old and contemporary debates are questions ness (i.e., concerns about how goods and
regarding the early nature of moral cognition resources should be distributed) as a means
and behavior, as well as how moral cogni- to understanding the nature of early moral
tion and behavior “get off the ground.” An- cognition and behavior. Our goal has been
swering such questions can also contribute to identify the earliest emergence of con-
to our understanding of critical issues in the cerns about distributive fairness and their
field of moral psychology writ large, such as subsequent developmental trajectory, to
whether morality is intuitive or deliberate, provide a precise understanding of the na-
monolithic or multifaceted, composed of ture of infants’ early fairness concerns, and

420
 Origins of Infant’s Distributive Fairness Concerns 421

to identify the role of experience (if any) in regardless of the cause of the disparity in
these concerns. Here, we present evidence need (Lamm & Schwinger, 1980).
that infants possess an intuitive sense of Recent evidence suggests that by at least the
distributive fairness that stems from in- preschool years children are aware of norms
fants’ emerging experience in sharing inter- that govern resource distribution events and
actions and discuss how this evidence can endorse and enact those norms. In third-
inform central questions in moral psychol- party situations, if the number of resources
ogy and moral development. equals the number of potential recipients,
children default to distributing the resources
equally and disregard family relationships or
Distributive Fairness previous friendships (Olson & Spelke, 2008).
as a Case Study for Understanding They will even go as far as deciding to dispose
Early Moral Development of a resource in order to avoid creating an un-
equal distribution (Shaw & Olson, 2012).
Considerations of fairness are central to Children also exhibit negative emotional re-
human morality, affecting interpersonal in- actions when they receive an unequal alloca-
teractions, workplace behaviors, and legal tion (LoBue, Nishida, Chiong, DeLoache, &
judgments alike. Although principles of Haidt, 2011). Furthermore, merit-based dis-
fairness are regularly applied in processes tributions are evident by 3 years of age, as
of decision making and dispute resolution children will keep a larger number of rewards
(procedural fairness) or when considering for themselves if they contributed more work
an appropriate punishment for wrongdo- toward attaining those rewards relative to a
ings (retributive fairness), most important partner (Kanngiesser & Warneken, 2012; see
among adults’ fairness concerns is ensur- also Baumard, Mascaro, & Chevallier, 2012,
ing the just distribution of goods and re- for evidence of preschooler’s merit consider-
sources (distributive fairness). Although ations in third-party situations). Slightly later
adults possess many models for deciding in development, children take material need
how to distribute resources justly, Western into account and share more generously with
adults’ concerns about distributive fairness a poor rather than a rich recipient (Paulus,
are often governed by the principle of equal- 2014).
ity (Deutsch, 1975): All other things being A natural question that extends from this
equal, resources should be distributed evenly work concerns the point at which sensitivity
to recipients. For example, in the context of to fairness first arises in the course of de-
economic games, adults tend to divide re- velopment. At one time it would have been
sources equally between themselves and an anathema to ask whether infants possess
anonymous partner (Fehr & Fischbacher, moral concepts and concerns at all. Moral
2003) and punish individuals who violate cognition and behavior were initially pre-
the norm of equal distribution, even at a per- sumed to be ruled by conscious reasoning
sonal cost (Johnson, Dawes, Fowler, McEl- processes that are constructed gradually
reath, & Smirnov, 2009). Adults also take over a protracted period of development via
into consideration need and merit in allocat- active role taking (Kohlberg, 1969). Sub-
ing resources. Specifically, they allot greater sequent theorists instead suggested that by
monetary rewards to themselves if they are the preschool period children possess dif-
told that the amount of work they contrib- ferent principles for reasoning about moral,
uted to a dyadic task was larger than their conventional, and personal domains, but
partner’s contribution, particularly when nevertheless they have relied on children’s
the partner is a stranger (Austin, 1980; Lev- verbal judgments and justifications to as-
enthal & Michaels, 1969); and, in allocation sess moral sensitivity (Turiel, 1983, 1998;
decisions based on the joint work of a hy- Smetana, 2006). To the extent that moral
pothetical dyad, adults advantage individu- responses require or rely on conscious rea-
als who are described as in need of a larger soning processes that are accessible to verbal
sum of money to achieve a goal, even though report, they would naturally be out of reach
both recipients contributed equal work and of infants. Yet more contemporary research
422 D E V E L O P M E N TA L A N D E VO L U T I O N A RY R O O T S O F M O R A L I T Y

suggests that moral judgments arise at least to other moral subdomains) might in fact
partially from intuitive emotional processes be constituted from a range of processes,
(Greene & Haidt, 2002; Haidt, 2001), rais- some of which are more general purpose,
ing the possibility that even infants may be others of which are specific to the social
capable of moral responses. Thus we asked or moral domain. We also hypothesized
whether infants might possess a sensitivity that these processes may range from more
to distributive fairness. basic to more sophisticated, and, accord-
ingly, some would be in place fairly early in
development, whereas others might have a
Our Approach and Theoretical Stance more delayed developmental onset. Specifi-
cally, we designed tasks to (1) ask whether
Our approach was to first investigate whether infants can detect violations of distributive
infants possess an intuitive sense of fairness fairness, (2) determine whether infants use
in infancy and subsequently to ask questions information about fairness to guide their
concerning the nature of this sensitivity. We affiliative responses, (3) measure whether
began our research with some starting pre- infants view individuals who abide by fair-
dictions. First, we predicted that an intuitive ness norms as praiseworthy and those who
sense of fairness would be present and de- violate fairness norms as blameworthy, and
tectable in infancy. The past several decades (4) determine whether infants act to enforce
have demonstrated that infants possess norms of fairness by rewarding fair behav-
rich social knowledge about the world and ior and punishing unfair behavior. We then
the causal forces that guide others’ behav- systematically tested infants across a range
ior, including simple mental states such as of ages to determine which of these abilities
intentions (Woodward, 2009), more endur- infants’ responses encompass and to deter-
ing dispositional characteristics (Kuhlmeier, mine whether performance across tasks fol-
Wynn, & Bloom, 2003), and extending to lows a common developmental trajectory or
conventions and norms (Graham, Stock, & distinct developmental trajectories.
Henderson, 2006). Moreover, more recent Many of these predictions, and the ensu-
research suggests that infants may possess ing results from this work, speak directly
moral sensitivity in other domains, such as to hotly contested issues in moral psychol-
care/harm (Hamlin, Wynn, & Bloom, 2007; ogy. Because infants are not yet capable of
Hamlin & Wynn, 2011). self-reflective or conscious reasoning, evi-
Second, given the strong role that experi- dence that infants possess a sensitivity to
ence has been found to play in other aspects distributive fairness would support claims
of infants’ social cognitive knowledge, such that at least some aspects of morality are
as their understanding of goals and inten- undergirded by relatively automatic affec-
tions (Gerson & Woodward, 2014; Som- tive reactions rather than conscious reason-
merville, Woodward, & Needham, 2005; ing or deliberation. Gauging the role that
Sommerville, Hildebrand, & Crane, 2008), experience plays in the development of a
we hypothesized that experience would in- sensitivity to distributive fairness (as well
fluence infants’ fairness sensitivity in terms as other moral norms) speaks to issues re-
of both developmental onset and individual garding whether morality is primarily in-
differences. In particular, we hypothesized nate or primarily guided by socialization or
that as agents and observers of sharing be- acculturation. Devising tasks to map onto
havior and resource distributions, gain in- the potential processes underlying moral
fants experiences being both the recipients responses, and then systematically asking
and actors of fair and unfair behavior, which whether infants possess such processes and
might spur infants’ emerging fairness sensi- when they emerge in development, allows
tivity, as well as factors that served to con- us to investigate whether such responses are
strain or enhance these types of experiences. composed of a unitary process or multiple
Third, we hypothesized that infants’ processes, as well as to ask whether such
“moral responses” (to events pertaining to processes are general purpose or specific to
distributive fairness and perhaps extending moral responding.
 Origins of Infant’s Distributive Fairness Concerns 423

As we present in detail below, our claims crackers, 5:5 ounces of milk) or unequal re-
are that: source distribution (3:1 crackers, 8:2 ounc-
es of milk). We found that infants showed
1. Infants possess a sense of distributive significantly longer looking to the unequal
fairness: specifically, all things being outcomes over the equal outcomes; follow-
equal, infants expect resources to be dis- up conditions revealed that infants did not
tributed equally to recipients. differentiate between those same outcomes
2. Infants’ sense of distributive fairness un- when devoid of social context, ruling out
dergoes developmental change that ap- alternative explanations based on a prefer-
pears to be experience dependent. ence for asymmetry. These results suggest
3. There is individual variability in infants’ that 15-month-old infants expect equal out-
distributive fairness sensitivity that ap- comes in resource distribution events.
pears to reflect robust individual differ- To delve deeper into the nature of infants’
ences that are tied, at least in part, to representations, we next asked whether
infants’ everyday experiences and to dis- infants’ sensitivity to fairness norms also
positional attributes that are related to guides their social preferences: Do infants
infants’ altruistic tendencies. prefer to interact with fair individuals over
4. Infants’ reactions to distributive fairness unfair individuals? Fifteen-month-old in-
violations appear to incorporate con- fants watched live distribution displays in
structs that are specifically moral; infants which one actor consistently distributed toys
see those who violate distributive fairness equally among two recipients, whereas the
norms as blameworthy and those who other actor consistently favored one recipi-
abide by such norms as praiseworthy. ent over the other (Burns & Sommerville,
5. The ability to enact punishment to en- 2014). On test trials, infants were presented
force distributive fairness norms is likely with both actors and given the opportunity
a (relatively) late development. to pick who to affiliate with; on some tri-
als, the distributors simultaneously offered
Below, we discuss the evidence as it per- identical toys, on other trials the distributors
tains to each of these claims, as well as the both invited the infant to come play with
implications that this evidence has for the them on opposing sides of the room. Infants
questions raised above. showed a systematic preference for actors
who had previously acted fairly over those
who acted unfairly, despite the fact that at
Evidence the moment of choice, both actors behaved
identically. These findings provide some ini-
Infants Possess a Sense
tial information that infants evaluate fair
of Distributive Fairness
and unfair individuals: Infants’ affiliative
In our first foray into investigating infants’ preferences presumably indicate that they
fairness concerns, we reasoned that one view fair individuals more favorably, or at
of the most basic components of a mature least less unfavorably, than unfair individu-
sense of distributive fairness likely con- als.
sists of an ability to detect when fairness Together, these findings and related re-
norms have been either violated or adhered sults (Sloane, Baillargeon, & Premack,
to. To address whether infants hold expec- 2012; Geraci & Surian, 2011; Meristo &
tations of equality in the context of third- Surian, 2013, 2014) show that infants pos-
party resource distribution events, we tested sess expectations regarding how goods
15-month-old infants on a resource distri- should be distributed and, more specifically,
bution task (Schmidt & Sommerville, 2011). are aware of at least one distributive fairness
Infants watched distribution events in which norm and use it to guide their social prefer-
an individual distributed crackers or milk to ences, suggesting that by at least 15 months
two recipients; on test, infants’ visual atten- of age infants’ sensitivity to distributive fair-
tion was timed to static outcomes that de- ness shares some key attributes with older
picted either equal resource distribution (2:2 children and adults.
424 D E V E L O P M E N TA L A N D E VO L U T I O N A RY R O O T S O F M O R A L I T Y

Infants’ Sense of Distributive Fairness there is considerable variability in natural-


Undergoes Experience‑Related istic sharing, infants’ detection of fairness
Developmental Change norms was related to whether or not they
had begun to engage in naturalistic sharing
The next question we sought to answer
as measured by parental report. Together,
concerned the developmental trajectory of
these findings suggest that infants’ fairness
infants’ fairness expectations. On the one
expectations are developmentally acquired
hand, a sensitivity to fairness could be evo-
and may depend on their experience in shar-
lutionarily derived and thus should be ob- ing interactions.
served early and continuously over develop-
ment, independently of experience. On the
other hand, the emergence of fairness expec- Individual Differences in Infants’
tations or concerns might rely on experience Fairness Expectations
and thus arise in a more piecemeal fashion For adults, there are individual variabil-
across development. In support of this latter ity and cross-cultural differences in how
possibility, research has shown cross-cultur- strongly individuals subscribe to and adhere
al variability in the degree of adherence to to these equality norms, as well as other
fairness norms in both adults and children fairness norms. These findings suggest that
(Henrich et al., 2005; Schäfer, Haun, & To- experience may shape the extent to which
masello, 2015). individuals subscribe to and adhere to fair-
We (Ziv & Sommerville, 2016) recently ness norms.
investigated the developmental trajectory of Our research has revealed that beyond the
infants’ fairness expectations: Infants at 6, period of developmental transitions in in-
9, 12, and 15 months of age took part in a fants’ fairness expectations, stable individ-
resource distribution task that was very sim- ual differences in infants’ fairness concerns
ilar to the task used by Schmidt and Som- likely emerge and consolidate, and that such
merville (2011). Our first goal was to test individual differences are predicted, at least
the hypothesis that infants’ fairness expec- in part, by experiential factors. One fac-
tations would be developmentally emergent, tor that appears to predict individual dif-
meaning that there would be a period of ferences in infants’ fairness expectations is
developmental transition in infants’ fairness the presence or absence of a sibling. Infants
expectations. Our results confirmed this hy- 12 and 15 months old with siblings show
pothesis: Whereas both 12- and 15-month- enhanced distributive fairness expectations
old infants showed enhanced visual atten- (as assessed by the violation of expecta-
tion to the unequal outcomes, 6-month-old tion [VOE] task) in comparison with in-
infants did not, suggesting a developmental fants without siblings (Ziv & Sommerville,
transition between 6 and 12 months of age. 2016). Frequent interactions with siblings
Our second goal was to test the hypothesis might afford infants more opportunities to
that the developmental transition in infants’ directly experience fair and unfair outcomes
fairness expectations would be tied to the through regular observation and participa-
onset of infants’ naturalistic sharing behav- tion in sharing and resource distribution.
ior. Sharing interactions may contribute to Indeed, sibling disputes regularly occur in
the development of a sense of fairness since early childhood (Dunn, 1987), often per-
they emphasize equality and reciprocity. In taining to issues of rights and possession
particular, through the turn-taking nature (Dunn & Mann, 1987), and provide one of
of sharing interactions infants experience as the earliest contexts for applying concepts
both recipients and agents of fair and unfair of morality (Smetana, 1997).
outcomes. Through this process, infants can Recent work in our lab has also revealed
learn about the impact that fair or unfair be- that parental dispositional tendencies are
havior has on others, perhaps via their emo- related to infants’ fairness expectations at
tional reactions, and subsequently link that 12–15 months of age. Specifically, parental
feedback to their own feelings as recipients empathy, as captured by self-report ques-
of similar behavior. Consistent with this hy- tionnaires such as the Davis Interpersonal
pothesis at 9 months of age, an age at which Reactivity Index (IRI; Davis, 1983) is corre-
 Origins of Infant’s Distributive Fairness Concerns 425

lated with the extent to which infants show same factors that predict individual differ-
enhanced attention to unfair outcomes. Par- ences beyond this period of development
ents who score higher in affective empathy transition (such as the presence or absence
(i.e., empathic concern) and cognitive em- of siblings, parental empathy, and the way in
pathy (i.e., perspective taking) have infants which infants share toys).
that show greater attention to unfair over
fair outcomes. One possible read of these
Infants’ Reactions to Distributive Fairness
findings is that they may reflect a shared ge-
Violations Appear to Incorporate Specifically
netic tendency toward prosociality. Another
Moral Constructs
possibility, which we prefer, is that parents
who are more empathic may differ in how The aforementioned findings suggest that
frequently they introduce events related to infants can detect violations to distributive
fairness to infants (such as sharing interac- fairness norms and use them to guide their
tions) and the nature of these interactions. social behavior. However, from these results
Finally, our work suggests that individual alone it is not clear that there is anything
differences in infants’ sensitivity to fairness specifically “moral” about these responses.
at 12–15 months are predicted by how in- Infants’ ability to detect violations to fair-
fants choose to share toys with others. Al- ness norms could come about from a ten-
though the vast majority of infants at 12 dency to attend to social events paired with
months and older are capable of sharing domain-general statistical learning mecha-
toys, according to parental report and lab nisms (although it is unlikely that this is the
studies, infants differ in the extent of their case, because there is no reason to believe
underlying altruistic motivation to share. that more altruistic infants would be better
Across several studies, infants were allowed at detecting statistical regularities than less
to select one of two toys and then given the altruistic infants). Similarly, infants’ selec-
opportunity to share one of these toys with tions of previously fair individuals could be
a stranger. Infants who generously share a driven not by an appreciation that one actor
preferred toy more strongly detect viola- behaved morally and the other immorally,
tions to distributive fairness than do infants but by strategic inferences about how the in-
who share nonpreferred toys with strangers dividual might distribute goods to the infant
(Schmidt & Sommerville, 2011; Sommer- him- or herself.
ville, Schmidt, Yun, & Burns, 2013; Ziv In adults and older children, moral con-
& Sommerville, 2016). These findings may siderations include notions of right and
suggest that infants’ degree of altruism pre- wrong, as well as praise and blame. To de-
dicts the extent of infants’ awareness of dis- termine whether infants’ representations of
tributive fairness norms. Again, these results fair and unfair behavior include these con-
may stem from genetically influenced vari- structs, after showing infants video clips of
ability in the degree of prosociality different one individual distributing goods equally to
infants possess. Alternately, these relations recipients and another individual distribut-
may capture the fact that parents differ in ing goods unequally to recipients, infants
their tendency to emphasize prosocial or al- saw just the faces of the fair and unfair actor
truistic tendencies in infants that manifest in on flanking monitors (DesChamps, Eason,
increased or decreased awareness of distrib- & Sommerville, 2016). After an initial trial
utive fairness norms and altruistic behavior. in which infants’ baseline attention to both
Intriguingly, whereas each of these factors faces was measured, infants heard either
predict variability in infants’ fairness ex- praise (“Good job! She’s a good girl”) or ad-
pectations at 12–15 months of age, they do monishment (“Bad job! She’s a bad girl”).
not predict variability at younger ages (i.e., The results indicated that infants as young
9 and 6 months of age). Coupled with prior as 13 months of age systematically shifted
results, these findings suggest that factors their visual attention as a function of the ac-
associated with group-level developmental companying vocal stimuli. Infants looked
transitions in infants’ fairness expectations significantly longer to the unfair distributor
(such as whether or not an infant has experi- on admonishment trials than at the fair dis-
ence sharing or not) are not necessarily the tributor; on the praise trials, infants looked
426 D E V E L O P M E N TA L A N D E VO L U T I O N A RY R O O T S O F M O R A L I T Y

numerically (but not significantly) longer at that infants uniquely reward fair behaviors
the fair distributor than the unfair distribu- and, perhaps, other acts of prosocial behav-
tor. These findings suggest that by at least 13 ior (we are currently testing this possibility).
months of age infants associate praise with Intriguingly, these results dovetail with
fair behavior and admonishment with unfair those of Jensen and colleagues (Riedl, Jen-
behavior and also that there is an asymme- sen, Call, & Tomasello, 2015), who demon-
try in the extent of these associations (i.e., strated that, although 3-year-old children
they see unfair behavior as more blamewor- will intervene to correct an injustice (e.g., re-
thy than fair behavior is praiseworthy). An turning a stolen item to its rightful owner),
open question for future work is whether these same children appear to be reluctant
younger infants also possess this ability. to engage in punishment. Together, these
findings suggest that the tendency to act to
enforce moral norms via punishment may
The Ability to Enact Punishment to Enforce
occur significantly later than an awareness
Distributive Norms Is Likely a (Relatively)
of moral norms and use of these norms to
Late Development
guide behavior, as well as the ability to rec-
Finally, adults and older children also act in ognize particular actions as blameworthy
various ways to enforce moral norms. Spe- and praiseworthy.
cifically, they engage in reward and punish-
ment behaviors to encourage moral actions
and discourage immoral actions. We were Summary and Implications
interested in whether infants are similarly
motivated to enforce fairness norms. Infants The findings herein suggest that infants
were presented with a touch screen, and we develop an intuitive sense of distributive
taught them that touching a colored bar on fairness over the first year of life, between
one side of the screen elicited reward, where- roughly 6 and 12 months of age, that may
as touching a colored bar on the other side be facilitated by their experience engaging
of the screen elicited punishment. We op- in sharing interactions. Furthermore, indi-
erationalized punishment and reward across vidual differences beyond this period of de-
studies both in terms of verbal reward and velopmental acquisition exist and are linked
punishment and material reward and pun- to factors that influence infants’ everyday
ishment—the actor either received a cookie experiences. Our findings also suggest that
or had a cookie taken away from her (Ziv & by 13 months of age infants apply notions
Sommerville, in preparation). Then infants of praise and blame to those that adhere
saw videos of one actor distributing goods to rather than violate distributive fairness
equally to recipients and another actor dis- norms. Interestingly, however, even slightly
tributing goods unequally to recipients. On older infants cannot fully translate these no-
test trials, a picture of one of the actor’s tions into actions to enforce distributive fair-
faces appeared in the middle of the screen, ness norms.
flanked by the two colored bars, and we re- Our findings impinge on several questions
corded infants’ spontaneous bar presses. that are central to classic and contemporary
We found that, on trials in which the fair debates. First, the fact that even infants pos-
actor’s face appeared, infants pressed the sess a basic sense of distributive fairness sug-
reward bar more frequently than the pun- gests that moral responses are driven, at least
ishment bar. On trials in which the unfair in part, by relatively automatic affective re-
actor’s face appeared, infants pressed the sponses given that infants lack self-reflective
colored bars equally. These findings sug- conscious reasoning abilities. Second, our
gested that infants rewarded the fair actor findings are relevant to the debate regarding
but neither rewarded nor punished the un- whether morality is innate versus learned,
fair actor. A follow-up control condition re- although they do not definitively settle this
vealed that infants did not show this same debate. Of course, the term innate has been
pattern of responses to positively and nega- used in many different ways. As Prinz (2008)
tively valenced stimuli more broadly (liked points out, some definitions of innateness
and disliked foods). These findings suggest portray traits or abilities as fixed and imper-
 Origins of Infant’s Distributive Fairness Concerns 427

vious to change; in other definitions, traits development in other subdomains may have
or abilities are innate if they have a highly other sources (such as harm/care; see Ham-
circumscribed range of potential manifesta- lin, 2013).
tions; finally, other definitions attribute in- Our results also speak to issues of the num-
nateness to traits or abilities with a greater ber and types of processes that contribute to
flexibility in their expressions provided that morality. Our findings suggest that infants’
there is a specialized system evolved solely to ability to recognize moral transgressors as
produce a given trait or ability. Many con- blameworthy and moral abiders as praise-
temporary authors follow Marcus’s (2004) worthy is likely distinct from their ability to
definition in defining innateness as “orga- enact reward and punishment, as the former
nized in advance of experience.” is in place by at least 13 months of age and
Our results, suggesting that (1) there is the latter is still developing at 16 months of
a developmental onset of awareness of dis- age. Thus these findings suggest that more
tributive fairness norms and (2) this devel- implicit moral reactions are distinct from
opmental onset may be a product of expe- explicit moral reactions, at least in infancy.
rience, raise the possibility that infants’ An important question for future research
sensitivity to fairness is mostly acquired is whether the earliest manifestations of in-
through acculturation. Moreover, they fants’ sensitivity to distributive fairness are
allow us to rule out some versions of innate- driven by a single process that is specific to
ness, such as the possibility that infants’ sen- morality or by multiple processes, a subset
sitivity to fairness is fixed and impervious to of which may not be specific to morality. In
change. However, there are some important order to make traction on this issue, it will
caveats to this claim. First, our data so far be important to test infants between 9 and
tell us that there is an association between 12 months of age (ages at which an aware-
the onset of participation in sharing interac- ness of distributive fairness norms is onset-
tions and infants’ awareness of distributive ting) on tasks that investigate their tendency
fairness norms, but this does not necessar- to associate praise and blame with fair and
ily mean that infants’ sharing experience unfair behavior, respectively.
drives their fairness concerns (as opposed to
the other way around or to a third variable
accounting for both tendencies). Interven- Conclusions
tion studies aimed at enhancing the onset of
sharing behavior in younger infants are nec- In this chapter, we provided evidence that
essary to determine whether there are down- infants possess an intuitive sense of fairness
stream consequences for infants’ awareness that likely emerges as a result of experience,
of distributive fairness norms; our initial particularly with interactions that enable
work in this vein suggests that presharing infants to observe and participate in ex-
infants can learn to share through regular changes allowing them to be both the agents
practice with reciprocal object exchanges and recipients of fair and unfair behavior.
(Xu, Saether, & Sommerville, 2016). An- Together, our results suggest that a sensi-
other technique for addressing questions tivity to distributive fairness both emerges
related to innate and learned contributions early and is reliant on experience for both
would be to test infants across cultures using its emergence and subsequent nature. Criti-
similar paradigms to determine whether the cally, and perhaps on a hopeful note, these
starting point of a given moral construct is findings suggest that concerns about fair-
shared across cultures or varies from the ness may be relatively malleable and thus
get-go. If the starting point of distributive can be enhanced perhaps even earlier in de-
fairness norms is consistent across cultures, velopment.
this would suggest a strong innate basis; if These findings pave the way for future
distributive fairness norms differ by culture directions. In terms of infants’ fairness
from the start, this would suggest a strong sensitivity most directly, it is important to
influence of acculturation. Finally, it is im- understand when and whether infants and/
portant to point out that, regardless of the or young children develop other models or
developmental origins of a sense of fairness, principles for resource distributions; some
428 D E V E L O P M E N TA L A N D E VO L U T I O N A RY R O O T S O F M O R A L I T Y

existing work suggests that toward the end of standing: Development in the second year. In
the second year of life infants begin to con- J. Kagan & S. Lamb (Eds.), The emergence of
sider merit in their expectations regarding morality in young children (pp. 91–112). Chi-
how goods are typically distributed (Sloane cago: University of Chicago Press.
Dunn, J., & Munn, P. (1987). Development of
et al., 2012), and recent ongoing work from justification in disputes with mother and sib-
our lab suggests that infants may incorpo- ling. Developmental Psychology, 23(6), 791–
rate information about recipients’ social 798.
status in their expectations about resource Fehr, E., & Fischbacher, U. (2003). The nature of
distributions. Another, broader future direc- human altruism. Nature, 425(6960), 785–791.
tion is to determine when infants recognize Geraci, A., & Surian, L. (2011). The develop-
both commonalities across different moral mental roots of fairness: Infants’ reactions to
subdomains and differences between moral equal and unequal distributions of resources.
violations and other types of violations, such Developmental Science, 14(5), 1012–1020.
Gerson, S. A., & Woodward, A. L. (2014).
as social conventions or rules. Finally, it will Learning from their own actions: The unique
be interesting to learn how and when infants effect of producing actions on infants’ action
rank or weigh concerns about the welfare of understanding. Child Development, 85(1),
others against concerns that are more self- 264–277.
or group-serving; emerging work from our Graham, J., & Haidt, J. (2010). Beyond beliefs:
lab suggests that infants are more tolerant Religions bind individuals into moral commu-
of violations to fairness norms when there nities. Personality and Social Psychology Re-
is reason to believe that inequality may ben- view, 14(1), 140–150.
efit same-group members (Burns & Som- Graham, S. A., Stock, H., & Henderson, A. M.
(2006). Nineteen-month-olds’ understanding
merville, 2014). Together, the results from
of the conventionality of object labels versus
this work will continue to inform classic and desires. Infancy, 9(3), 341–350.
contemporary debates in moral psychology Greene, J., & Haidt, J. (2002). How (and where)
and development. does moral judgment work? Trends in Cogni-
tive Sciences, 6(12), 517–523.
Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional dog and its ra-
REFERENCES tional tail: A social intuitionist approach
to moral judgment. Psychological Review,
Austin, W. (1980). Friendship and fairness: Ef- 108(4), 814–834.
fects of type of relationship and task perfor- Haidt, J. (2007). The new synthesis in moral psy-
mance on choice of distribution rules. Per- chology. Science, 316(5827), 998–1002.
sonality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 6(3), Haidt, J. (2012). The righteous mind: Why good
402–408. people are divided by politics and religion.
Baumard, N., Mascaro, O., & Chevallier, C. New York: Pantheon.
(2012). Preschoolers are able to take merit into Hamlin, J. K. (2013). Moral judgment and action
account when distributing goods. Develop- in preverbal infants and toddlers: Evidence for
mental Psychology, 48(2), 492–498. an innate moral core. Current Directions in
Burns, M. P., & Sommerville, J. A. (2014). “I Psychological Science, 22(3), 186–193.
pick you”: The impact of fairness and race on Hamlin, J. K., & Wynn, K. (2011). Young infants
infants’ selection of social partners. Frontiers prefer prosocial to antisocial others. Cognitive
in Psychology, 5. Available at www.ncbi.nlm. Development, 26(1), 30–39.
nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC3921677. Hamlin, J. K., Wynn, K., & Bloom, P. (2007).
Davis, M. H. (1983). Measuring individual dif- Social evaluation by preverbal infants. Nature,
ferences in empathy: Evidence for a multidi- 450(7169), 557–559.
mensional approach. Journal of Personality Henrich, J., Boyd, R., Bowles, S., Camerer, C.,
and Social Psychology, 44(1), 113–126. Fehr, E., Gintis, H., . . . Henrich, N. S. (2005).
DesChamps, T. D., Eason, A. E., & Sommerville, “Economic man” in cross-cultural perspec-
J. A. (2016). Infants associate praise and ad- tive: Behavioral experiments in 15 small-scale
monishment with fair and unfair individuals. societies. Behavioral and Brain Sciences,
Infancy, 21, 478–504. 28(6), 795–815.
Deutsch, M. (1975). Equity, equality, and need: Johnson, T., Dawes, C. T., Fowler, J. H., McEl-
What determines which value will be used as reath, R., & Smirnov, O. (2009). The role of
the basis of distributive justice? Journal of So- egalitarian motives in altruistic punishment.
cial Issues, 31(3), 137–149. Economics Letters, 102(3), 192–194.
Dunn, J. (1987). The beginnings of moral under- Kanngiesser, P., & Warneken, F. (2012). Young
 Origins of Infant’s Distributive Fairness Concerns 429

children consider merit when sharing resourc- Experimental Psychology: General, 141(2),
es with others. PLOS ONE, 7(8), e43979. 382.
Kohlberg, L. (1969). Stage and sequence: The Sloane, S., Baillargeon, R., & Premack, D.
cognitive-developmental approach to social- (2012). Do infants have a sense of fairness?
ization. In D. A. Goslin (Ed.), Handbook of Psychological Science, 23, 196–204.
socialization theory and research (pp. 347– Smetana, J. G. (1997). Parenting and the devel-
480). Chicago: Rand McNally. opment of social knowledge reconceptualized:
Kuhlmeier, V., Wynn, K., & Bloom, P. (2003). At- A social domain analysis. In J. E. Grusec &
tribution of dispositional states by 12-month- L. Kuczynski (Eds.), Parenting and children’s
olds. Psychological Science, 14(5), 402–408. internalization of values: A handbook of con-
Lamm, H., & Schwinger, T. (1980). Norms con- temporary theory (pp. 162–192). New York:
cerning distributive justice: Are needs taken Wiley.
into consideration in allocation decisions? So- Smetana, J. G. (2006). Social-cognitive domain
cial Psychology Quarterly, 43(4), 425–429. theory: Consistencies and variations in chil-
Leventhal, G. S., & Michaels, J. W. (1969). Ex- dren’s moral and social judgments. In M.
tending the equity model: Perception of inputs Killen & J. G. Smetana (Eds.), Handbook of
and allocation of reward as a function of du- moral development (pp. 119–153). Mahwah,
ration and quantity of performance. Journal NJ: Erlbaum.
of Personality and Social Psychology, 12(4), Sommerville, J. A., Hildebrand, E. A., & Crane,
303–309. C. C. (2008). Experience matters: The impact
LoBue, V., Nishida, T., Chiong, C., DeLoache, of doing versus watching on infants’ subse-
J. S., & Haidt, J. (2011). When getting some- quent perception of tool-use events. Develop-
thing good is bad: Even three-year-olds react mental Psychology, 44(5), 1249–1256.
to inequality. Social Development, 20(1), Sommerville, J. A., Schmidt, M. F., Yun, J. E.,
154–170. & Burns, M. (2013). The development of fair-
Marcus, G. (2004). The birth of the mind: How a ness expectations and prosocial behavior in
tiny number of genes creates the complexities the second year of life. Infancy, 18(1), 40–66.
of human thought. New York: Basic Books. Sommerville, J. A., Woodward, A. L., & Need-
Meristo, M., & Surian, L. (2013). Do infants ham, A. (2005). Action experience alters
detect indirect reciprocity? Cognition, 129(1), 3-month-old infants’ perception of others’ ac-
102–113. tions. Cognition, 96(1), B1–B11.
Meristo, M., & Surian, L. (2014). Infants dis- Turiel, E. (1983). The development of social
tinguish antisocial actions directed towards knowledge: Morality and convention. Cam-
fair and unfair agents. PLOS ONE, 9(10), bridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
e110553. Turiel, E. (1998). The development of morality.
Olson, K. R., & Spelke, E. S. (2008). Founda- In W. Damon & R. M. Lerner (Series Eds.) &
tions of cooperation in young children. Cogni- N. Eisenberg (Vol. Ed.), Handbook of child
tion, 108(1), 222–231. psychology: Vol. 3. Social, emotional, and
Paulus, M. (2014). The early origins of human personality development (pp. 863–932). New
charity: Developmental changes in preschool- York: Wiley.
er’s sharing with poor and wealthy individu- Woodward, A. L. (2009). Infants’ grasp of oth-
als. Frontiers in Psychology, 5, 344. Avail- ers’ intentions. Current Directions in Psycho-
able at www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/ logical Science, 18(1), 53–57.
PMC4071819. Xu, J., Saether, L. & Sommerville, J. A. (2016).
Prinz, J. (2008). Is morality innate? Moral Psy- Experience facilitates the emergence of shar-
chology, 1, 367–406. ing behavior among 7.5-month-old infants.
Riedl, K., Jensen, K., Call, J., & Tomasello, M. ­Developmental Psychology, 52(11), 1732–
(2015). Restorative justice in children. Current 1743.
Biology, 25, 1731–1735. Ziv, T., & Sommerville, J. A. (2016). Develop-
Schäfer, M., Haun, D. B., & Tomasello, M. mental differences in infants’ fairness expec-
(2015). Fair is not fair everywhere. Psycho- tations from 6 to 15 months of age. Child
logical Science, 26, 1252–1260. ­Development. Available at http://onlineli-
Schmidt, M. F., & Sommerville, J. A. (2011). brary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/cdev.12674/ab-
Fairness expectations and altruistic sharing stract.
in 15-month-old human infants. PLOS ONE, Ziv, T., & Sommerville, J. A. (in preparation).
6(10), e23223. Infants reward individuals who act fairly in
Shaw, A., & Olson, K. R. (2012). Children dis- third-party resource distributions. Unpub-
card a resource to avoid inequity. Journal of lished manuscript.
CHAPTER 44

Vulnerability‑Based Morality

Anton J. M. Dijker

What is the most essential innate psychological mechanism


underlying morality?

A hypothetical care mechanism—triggered by perceptions of vul‑


nerability—can explain many aspects of both moral judgment and
behavior.

Research on the psychological and philo- of human warfare shows many instances of
sophical aspects of morality has strongly fo- victimization of women and children (Davie,
cused on how people judge the permissibil- 1929). Yet the contradiction may only be ap-
ity or moral wrongness of certain acts given parent as the slaughtering of women and
their particular consequences. Yet intuitive- children during warfare can be interpreted
ly, certain properties of the persons affected as intentional demoralization of the enemy
by those acts must also play a significant role (Davie, 1929).
in moral judgment. This is especially evident Children in particular tend to be used in
from the strong feelings that are aroused order to inhibit aggression in situations of
when children, women, or elderly persons potential conflict. For example, when heads
are harmed or benefitted. In particular, not of state or military leaders visit each other,
only in everyday life (e.g., Cialdini, Brown, displays of military strength often are ac-
Lewis, Luce, & Neuberg, 1997; Dijker, companied with the presence of children of-
2001; Eagly & Crowley, 1986) but also in fering flowers (Eibl-Eibesfeldt, 1989). More
situations of warfare (e.g., Carpenter, 2003; generally, humans employ a rich variety of
Hoijer, 2004; McKeogh, 2002), people feel infantile behaviors (e.g., begging, crying,
a strong moral obligation to help and protect playing) to ensure aggression reduction,
these categories of individuals, and they re- tolerance, and prosocial behavior under ev-
spond with moral outrage to the harm doers. eryday conditions (cf. Eibl-Eibesfeldt, 1989;
Sometimes, the idea that women and Keltner, Young, & Buswell, 1997).
children are more deserving of help and What properties do children, women, and
protection than men (also referred to as the elderly persons have in common that have
“women-and-children-first” norm) seems to these moral implications? The goal of this
be contradicted. For example, the history chapter is to show that the central physical

430
 Vulnerability‑Based Morality 431

property at stake here is vulnerability and For example, if the perceived events sim-
that its perception reliably activates a moti- ply indicate a desirable state of well-being
vational mechanism that is responsible for a of the vulnerable object, tenderness may
wide variety of moral emotions, judgments, be felt, associated with appraising the ob-
and behaviors. Importantly, I will argue that ject as “cute” and a desire to stay close to
the perception of vulnerability and its asso- it, keeping a watchful eye on its behavior
ciated motivational mechanism also deter- and the environment. If a threat to, or ac-
mine moral judgment and behavior in situa- tual decrease in, the object’s well-being is
tions in which one is not visually exposed to perceived that can be attributed to another
individuals of flesh and blood, such as in the agent or the self, moral anger or guilt may be
trolley problem and the Prisoner’s Dilem- felt, respectively, resulting in protective and
ma—two widely employed research para- aggressive tendencies to prevent (further)
digms for investigating moral judgment and harm. Perception of a decrease in well-being
behavior. But first I outline the hypothetical in the absence of responsible agents may pri-
psychological mechanism responsible for the marily result in pity or sympathy and a de-
moral implications of vulnerability percep- sire to comfort and heal the individual (for
tion. a detailed explanation of these and other
moral emotions in terms of an activated care
mechanism and an attributional process, see
A Theory of Vulnerability‑Based Morality Dijker, 2014b).
A care mechanism may be present not
With respect to living things, vulnerability only in parents but, in different degrees, in
refers to the property or disposition of ob- all members of a group of cooperative breed-
jects to change into a state of damage (i.e., ers, and especially in humans (Hrdy, 2009).
a state of lowered fitness that is inconsistent In humans, an exceptionally strong care sys-
with genetic “design specifications”) when tem may have evolved, easily activated by the
exposed to certain conditions. For those slightest evidence of vulnerability and imma-
concerned with the fitness and well-being of turity, even making vulnerability perception
others, an assessment of vulnerability would more important than kin recognition and its
be crucial, as information about this prop- attitudinal consequences (although kinship
erty can help perceivers to predict and thus remains influential; see Park, Schaller, &
prevent actual harm. After all, especially in Van Vugt, 2008). Complementarily, humans
ancestral environments, it would have been may have evolved a rich variety of ways to
much better to prevent injury than to try to intentionally signal vulnerability and im-
relieve harm already inflicted and likely re- maturity in order to trigger a care system in
sulting in death (Dijker, 2011). others (e.g., they may behave in an infantile
Evolutionary theory predicts the evolu- manner), thereby ensuring aggression reduc-
tion of a behavioral mechanism (best termed tion, diverse prosocial behaviors, and a rich
a care mechanism; Dijker & Koomen, 2007) variety of functional moral emotions (Di-
that would motivate especially parents to jker, 2014b). Note that the influence of the
respond adaptively to this fitness-relevant care mechanism on social behavior may be
property of their young offspring. Crucial less visible when there is strong competition
features of such a mechanism would be that with motivational mechanisms associated
it can be quickly and unconditionally acti- with self-preservation, resulting in primarily
vated by simple perceptual cues that are cor- fearful, aggressive, or stigmatizing respons-
related with vulnerability (e.g., certain phys- es (Dijker & Koomen, 2007).
ical or behavioral features indicating young How does this theory help explain re-
age or lack of physical strength; cf. Alley, sponses to moral dilemmas in which persons
1983; Berry & McArthur, 1986; Lorenz, of flesh and blood with visible vulnerability
1943) and that its activation causes differ- cues are absent? To answer that question, it
ent moral emotions or adaptive behavioral is important to realize that vulnerability can
goals, dependent on the perceived relevance also be inferred from knowledge or beliefs
of the current situation for the well-being of about the situational causes of harm and suf-
the vulnerable object. fering. For example, if information about age
432 D E V E L O P M E N TA L A N D E VO L U T I O N A RY R O O T S O F M O R A L I T Y

and gender of the persons affected is absent train and save the five other persons. Typi-
and an illness or injury can be entirely attrib- cally, no background information is supplied
uted to strong situational and uncontrollable about the individuals that can be sacrificed
factors (e.g., another’s careless behavior, a and saved in this way. It is generally found
natural disaster, or a genetic defect), people that very few people consider it permissible
tend to feel sympathy for the affected per- to personally kill another person to save five
sons, apparently seeing them as “innocent” others in the footbridge version, whereas
or “defenseless.” In contrast, these same per- many more people find it acceptable to sac-
sons tend to arouse anger and less sympathy rifice an individual in the bystander version
when their agency and personal responsibil- (for reviews see, e.g., Christensen & Gomi-
ity for their condition are emphasized (e.g., la, 2012; Mikhail, 2007).
Dijker & Koomen, 2003; Weiner, Perry, & Researchers have explained these judg-
Magnusson, 1988). More recently, Gray and ments primarily in terms of degree of in-
Wegner (2009) introduced a conceptual con- tentionality and the causal relationships be-
trast between “moral patients” and “moral tween the events leading to the harm. For
agents” to describe a similar process of sym- example, it has been shown that the permis-
pathy and anger arousal. Asking people to sibility of sacrificing a person to save five
take another’s perspective seems to arouse others in the bystander version depends on
sympathy and reduce aggression in a similar the opportunity to interpret the sacrifice as a
way, as this, too, may stimulate attention to side rather than an intended effect (Mikhail,
situational causes for the person’s condition 2007) and the extent to which the killing
or behavior (Batson et al., 1997). would require close physical contact with
The traditional attributional description the victim (e.g., Greene et al., 2009). This
of these relationships is insufficient to ex- focus has led some to argue that moral judg-
plain why we care about strangers lacking in ment can be sufficiently explained in terms
responsibility for their own illness or suffer- of an innate “grammar” underlying people’s
ing (Dijker & Koomen, 2003) and why we understanding of the causal structure of the
would want to improve their condition—an trolley problem (Mikhail, 2007).
essential motivational aspect of sympathy Researchers often relate the differential
(Wispé, 1991). However, a truly causal ex- responses to the footbridge and bystander
planation for sympathy arousal is possible versions of the trolley problem to Kant’s
by assuming that situational attribution emphasis on the moral wrongness or good-
makes victims appear more vulnerable and ness of acts in general and Bentham’s focus
hence helps to activate a care mechanism. on the role of perceived consequences and
The next section examines how a theory of utilities of acts (e.g., the mere number of
vulnerability-based morality can be used to people that can be saved), respectively. Inter-
improve understanding of responses to the estingly, the relatively few studies in which
trolley problem and the Prisoner’s Dilemma. background information has been provided
about the persons to be saved and sacrificed
are more in line with Hume’s emphasis on
The Trolley Problem the role of preexisting attitudes toward the
objects of moral judgments (e.g., positive at-
In one of the most frequently used dilemmas titudes toward one’s own children, husband
in psychological research on moral decision or wife, or a benefactor). For example, it has
making—the trolley problem—a runaway been demonstrated that people are less will-
trolley is about to run over and kill five peo- ing to sacrifice a brother or sister (Petrinov-
ple, but a bystander can throw a switch that ich, O’Neill, & Jorgensen, 1993) or to save
will turn the trolley on a side track, where it a group of Nazis (Petrinovich et al., 1993),
will kill one person. Research participants homeless people (Cikara, Farnsworth, Har-
are asked if it is permissible to throw the ris, & Fiske, 2010), or foreigners (Swann,
switch. Responses to this bystander version Gómez, Dovidio, Hart, & Jetten, 2010).
are often compared with those to a version Especially in light of Kant’s position, these
in which a person needs to be pushed from a causal influences are incongruent with uni-
footbridge onto the track in order to stop the versal principles of morality, as they intro-
 Vulnerability‑Based Morality 433

duce partiality, bias, and unfairness (see The present hypotheses about responses to
Wiggins, 2006, on Hume’s and Kant’s at- the trolley problem may be tested by adding
tempts to deal with the conflict between to the traditional presentation of the trolley
object-based attitudes and impartiality in problem real persons who differ in vulner-
morality). ability (e.g., by means of photographs); mea-
Responses to the different versions of the suring perceived vulnerability, permissibility
trolley problem have not yet been explained of saving or sacrificing individuals, and dif-
in terms of a psychological mechanism that ferent moral emotions; and establishing me-
connects, in a causal and law-like manner, diation of permissibility and emotion ratings
the perception of physical events and prop- by perceived vulnerability.
erties with particular motivational states, A final note on Kant’s categorical impera-
emotions, and judgments (see also Krebs, tive in light of the trolley problem. That Kant
2007)—a mechanism that would also un- proposes that one should never treat human
derlie our moral responses to perceivable beings as instruments but only as ends in
individuals of flesh and blood. Additional themselves (Wiggins, 2006) may be partially
assumptions about the perception of certain due to the strong emotional force of imag-
properties of the persons involved in the ining harming objects that appear especially
trolley problem may help to reveal such a vulnerable and care-arousing when under
mechanism. our own mental and behavioral control and
In particular, the bystander version of hence at our mercy. This would imply that re-
the trolley problem presents people with a sponses to the footbridge version do not sim-
salient situational cause for the imminent ply involve a focus on the wrongness of acts
and simultaneous deaths of a group of five in general (deontology) but are motivated by
individuals (a potentially devastating event), a mechanism that responds to a particular
making that group appear vulnerable or “in- property of the objects of moral judgments.
nocent,” and likely activating the hypothe-
sized care mechanism. The perceiver is in-
vited to consider whether the side track, on The Prisoner’s Dilemma
which a single person happens to be stand-
ing, can be used as an instrument to prevent At first sight, there is little resemblance be-
the harmful event from happening. In this tween studies in which research participants
particular variant of the bystander version, are asked to make life-or-death decisions in
care and protection are focused on the per- a hypothetical situation such as the trolley
sons on the main track, with the person on problem and studies requiring participants
the side track apparently seen as a minor de- to play a Prisoner’s Dilemma game in which
tail of an effective action to protect the most they can harm or benefit each other in a
vulnerable. However, it has been found that modest way (e.g., in terms of money earned
when the side track loops back onto the main or lost). Yet, in both types of studies, par-
track and the person standing on it can be ticipants are typically asked to make moral
used as an obstacle or instrument to stop the decisions about another individual’s well-
train, the act of turning the switch becomes being in the absence of visual or background
somewhat less permissible (Mikhail, 2007). information about that individual.
Yet it is especially the footbridge version The main properties of the Prisoner’s Di-
that may completely change the perception lemma are usually illustrated with a 2 × 2
of vulnerability. Now, perceivers are forced matrix representing the four different com-
to consider whether they should harm a vic- binations (cells of the matrix) of the two
tim apparently completely under their con- players’ decisions to cooperate or defect and
trol and “at their mercy” and perhaps imag- their associated payoffs. Often, the players
ined as standing with his or her back turned are first supplied with a particular amount
toward them; an innocent and vulnerable of money or tokens that is either decreased
victim who has automatically activated their or increased, dependent on the particular
care mechanism and perhaps arousing a combinations of decisions obtained. It is the
high level of guilt when imagined to be sac- particular ranking of the payoffs associated
rificed and killed. with the four combinations of choices that
434 D E V E L O P M E N TA L A N D E VO L U T I O N A RY R O O T S O F M O R A L I T Y

defines the dilemma in this game. Thus, if pressive cues (e.g., a touch or smile) of the
one player defects and the other cooperates, other player that apparently signal kindness
the former will receive the largest benefit or trustworthiness (e.g., Mehu, Grammer,
possible in the game (this outcome is called & Dunbar, 2007) or to facial features that
the temptation to defect, T), but the latter, resemble positive attitude objects such as kin
the worst possible outcome (sucker’s payoff, (Krupp, Debruine, & Barclay, 2008). Al-
S). If both players cooperate, they receive less though these studies contribute to our under-
than could have been obtained in the T cell standing of mechanisms responsible for pro-
but will still benefit substantially (reward for social behavior in general, game-­theoretical
cooperation, R). The fourth combination of experiments do not seem necessary to reveal
choices represents the outcome that both them. More importantly, these additions pro-
players defect, and it is associated with some vide little information about the psychologi-
costs to both (punishment for defection, or cal mechanism at work when the Prisoner’s
P). If the payoffs can be ranked as T > R > Dilemma is presented in its usual form. As
P > S and each player expects the game to may be true for the trolley problem, a more
be played only once, the only rational choice general psychological mechanism involved in
for a player would be to defect, but because responding to bodily features of target per-
this is also true for the other player, both sons may be involved here as well.
will inevitably be punished for defection and In particular, for players with consider-
receive less than what might have been pos- able mental capabilities such as humans, the
sible if both would have chosen to cooper- paradigm may reveal an important aspect
ate (for reviews of behavioral outcomes, see of cooperation and morality. In particular,
Dawes, 1980; Kollock, 1998). The moral mentally representing the payoff matrix of
dilemma involved can be described as a con- the Prisoner’s Dilemma implies that players
flict between making an attractive, safe, and are aware that both of them are dependent
relatively selfish choice that can harm the on each other (and find themselves in a vul-
other player and a cooperative one that at nerable position), especially in the sense that
first sight seems less beneficial to oneself. both may be tempted to defect because this is
Like the trolley problem, the Prisoner’s associated with the greatest individual bene-
Dilemma as such offers no clues about the fit. Especially in making the first move in the
physical properties that players respond to Prisoner’s Dilemma game, one may more or
when making choices between the rows and less trust that the other will care about one’s
columns of a payoff matrix (Dijker, 2011). vulnerable position (for an interpretation of
(For this reason, cooperation in the Prison- trust in terms of vulnerability, see Rousseau,
er’s Dilemma and similar “social dilemmas” Sitkin, Burt, & Camerer, 1998).
is dominantly explained in terms of “choice Now, according to the present theory,
strategies,” personal dispositions, or value causing or imagining causing harm to vul-
orientations.) Indeed, it is a fundamental nerable beings (which are likely to activate
assumption underlying game theory in gen- the care system) is responsible for a variety of
eral that players cannot influence each other moral emotions. Thus, when trust is broken,
except by means of (independently) making the other player’s defection and its result-
choices given the presented payoff matrix ing unequal distribution of valuable goods
(Binmore, 2007). Thus players should not, may arouse moral anger, whereas his or her
for example, point guns at each other to en- unexpected cooperation may result in grati-
force a particular choice, beg for a particular tude. One’s own defection may induce guilt
outcome, or let each other win for reasons (Nelissen, Dijker, & de Vries, 2007; Trivers,
unrelated to the game itself. It is therefore re- 1971). In case of the other’s defection, pity or
markable that behavioral scientists increas- forgiveness may also be aroused, especially
ingly add external influences to games to if the defection can be attributed to external
demonstrate that these influences are very causes beyond the individual’s control, such
important to explain the choices made. For as illness (Batson & Ahmad, 2001) or noise
example, making cooperative choices in the (Van Lange, Ouwekerk, & Tazelaar, 2002).
Prisoner’s Dilemma is especially likely when Note that this analysis of the Prisoner’s
participants have first been exposed to ex- Dilemma also calls for a particular inter-
 Vulnerability‑Based Morality 435

pretation of the terms fairness and justice, emotional correlate of parental care, has
closely linking these terms to the concepts not played any significant role in the major
of vulnerability and care. That is, we tend 20th-century theories of emotion. A plau-
to use the term fairness not only to indicate sible reason for this state of affairs seems to
that goods or services are evenly or unself- be that it is rather difficult to imagine how
ishly distributed but also to refer to situa- a mechanism that is saliently at work dur-
tions in which vulnerable individuals should ing parenting can also play a causal role in
be protected from physical harm. Thus we children’s social behavior (i.e., well before
find it unfair to attack a defenseless and reproductive age) or during everyday social
unarmed person (e.g., stab a person in the interactions between adult strangers. The
back, kick a person lying on the ground or at present theory solves the problem of gener-
sleep) or to aggress against and not forgive alization of parental care by assuming that
a person who strongly shows remorse and it derives from a more general care mecha-
cries in an infantile manner. Even when oth- nism that originally evolved from the need
ers deserve our aggression and punishment, to inhibit aggression among vulnerable kin
we would like to give them “a fair chance” in general (Hamilton, 1964), necessitating
and to let them defend themselves or make a fast and automatic change from an ag-
themselves less vulnerable. gressive to a softer mode of conduct, as evi-
To conclude, the impartiality of moral denced, for example, in children’s play, for-
judgment sought for by philosophers such giveness, reconciliation, benevolent humor,
as Hume and Kant, and so typical for ideas and politeness rituals (Dijker, 2014b).
about fairness, may unexpectedly depend on
a motivational mechanism that is responsible
for reacting with sympathy to, and preferen- Theoretical Stance and Distinctions
tial treatment of, a specific individual. Yet
an activated care mechanism can be applied The most distinctive feature of the present
to different individuals sharing the same theory of moral judgment is its hypothesized
level of perceived vulnerability, resulting in care mechanism. By proposing a law-like
attempts to prevent one of them from ending mechanism, it comes much closer than other
up, unfairly, as relatively more deprived and theories to a real causal and integrative ex-
vulnerable than the others. planation of many phenomena that are re-
lated to morality—both responses that are
based on concrete sensory input and those
Historical Context that rely more on symbolic mental represen-
tations of complex situations.
Many 18th- (e.g., Hume, Rousseau, Smith), In contrast, moral emotions such as sym-
19th- (e.g., Bain, Darwin, Ribot, Shand), pathy or guilt are often explained by merely
and 20th- (e.g., Eibl-Eibesfeldt, de Waal, treating them as words correlated with other
MacLean, McDougall) century thinkers on words (e.g., responsibility) without referring
morality have recognized parental care as to mediating mechanisms. Yet, a mechanis-
the prototypical example of altruism and tic description is required to combine the dif-
context for the development of moral capa- ferent variables in a truly explanatory fash-
bilities—some of them (e.g., Bain, Hume, ion (Bechtel & Abrahamsen, 2005). Such a
McDougall) also paying considerable atten- description becomes especially urgent if we
tion to tenderness or the “softer passion” want to be able to interpret in a functional
as a central moral emotion. Although these manner the rapidly increasing data on the
scholars tend to assume that some of its psy- many brain areas that are involved in moral
chological elements must also play a role judgment and emotion (Young & Dungan,
outside parent–child and family relation- 2012).
ships, the mechanism underlying parenting At present, the theory of vulnerability-
has not yet been taken seriously enough as based morality is most in agreement with
a more general mechanism underlying many Gray and Wegner’s (2009) proposal to ana-
different kinds of prosocial and moral re- lyze morality in terms of a contrast between
sponses. Relatedly, tenderness, the typical (intentional) “agents” and (suffering) “pa-
436 D E V E L O P M E N TA L A N D E VO L U T I O N A RY R O O T S O F M O R A L I T Y

tients.” For example, where Gray and Weg- Extending the Theory:


ner argue that perceivers have a tendency to Relationships between Moral Goodness,
think in a complementary way about agents Truth, and Beauty
and patients (which they refer to as “dyadic
completion”), the present theory argues that An exciting implication of the present ac-
perceptions of vulnerable individuals and count of morality is that it allows us to ad-
their intentional, manipulating, and control- dress in a new way the century-old philo-
ling environments are reciprocally related. sophical puzzle of the relationships between
Yet the present theory additionally offers a the concepts of moral goodness, truth, and
distinct psychological mechanism that ex- beauty (Scruton, 2011). First, consider that
plains why we feel a special moral obliga- all three concepts may refer to different con-
tion (together with multiple moral emotions; sequences of the same behavior that is moti-
Dijker, 2014b) in relation to vulnerable ob- vated by the perception of a vulnerable ob-
jects. In addition, the present theory does ject. In particular, when a care mechanism
not assume that to experience this obliga- is activated, a vulnerable object motivates
tion, perceivers need to associate vulnerable behavior aimed at protecting and improving
objects or “patients” with a mental capacity the object’s condition, whether the object is
to experience pleasure or pain; age and sex- a living or nonliving thing. This behavior is
related bodily vulnerability cues are often seen as morally good. The careful manipula-
sufficient to activate the care mechanism. tion of the object, which may involve clean-
ing, reparation, restoration, and different
kinds of maintenance activities, may result
Evidence in an object that is vulnerable but in good
condition and considered beautiful (see also
Perhaps the strongest evidence to date for the Burke’s [1759/1990] suggestion that beauti-
validity of the present theory comes from the ful things tend to be relatively fragile and
rapidly increasing number of studies show- delicate). Finally, the careful, slow, and
ing that oxytocin, a hormone so characteris- thoughtful manipulation of the vulnerable
tic for mammalian parental care, appears to object may result in internal representations
influence social decision making and moral that accurately and objectively represent the
judgment in many other contexts than par- different properties of the object in terms of
ent–child relationships (for a review, see a large set of sensorimotor expectancies. On
Bartz, Zaki, Bolger, & Ochsner, 2011). The the basis of these representations, proposi-
general effect of this hormone can be de- tions about the object can be derived that
scribed as the softening of behavior directed tend to be true (Dijker, 2014a).
at vulnerable targets, sometimes combined These consequences of careful behavior, in
with harsh responses to those who threaten turn, may positively feed back on the moti-
their well-being. Moreover, brain areas orig- vation to improve the object’s condition. For
inally thought to be exclusively involved in example, its increased beauty makes it more
parental care are increasingly shown to have attractive and attention-grabbing, thereby
a more general function in controlling non- increasing the motivation to manipulate it in
parents’ responses to both infants and moral gentle and protective ways, resulting in rep-
dilemmas (Moll, Zahn, de Oliveira-Souza, resentations that are still richer in detail and
Krueger, & Grafman, 2005; Numan, 2012). more objective. Importantly, in the course
More indirect evidence for the pervasive of this process, keeping the object in mind
influence of a care mechanism comes from and looking at it from multiple perspectives
studies showing people’s sensitivity to baby is as important as ensuring that the object
features of adult faces (Zebrowitz, Fellous, actually remains present and in good condi-
Mignault, & Andreoletti, 2003) and of bod- tion. This process may explain not only why
ies differing in fatness (Dijker, DeLuster, human craft is judged in terms of the same
Peeters, & De Vries, 2017) and studies dem- moral values and norms that are applied to
onstrating that different moral emotions are social behavior in general (e.g., honesty, re-
related to perceived vulnerability (Dijker, liability, precision, patience) but also why
2001, 2010). the pervasive beautification of early human
 Vulnerability‑Based Morality 437

tools (Dobres, 2001) probably was as impor- partly on fearful and aggressive responses to
tant for their invention and development as protect vulnerable beings in effective ways
their functional properties. (Dijker, 2014b) competes with other types
It is interesting to note that several other of morality that primarily depend on fear or
psychological concepts share certain of aggression. For example, a morality of obe-
the above-mentioned elements of a care- dience seems to be strongly related to a ten-
ful mode of thinking. For example, both dency to fearfully submit to powerful others
the concepts of wisdom (e.g., Sternberg, and to aggress or show contempt to those
1998) and mindfulness (e.g., Brown, Ryan, who are disobedient and violate norms. Fur-
& ­ Creswell, 2007) assume relationships thermore, although a morality of reciproc-
between thought, sympathy, prosocial ten- ity can be partly explained by assuming a
dencies, and aesthetic experience. However, general tendency to care for vulnerable or
these proposals fail to mention a mecha- needy others, it strongly relies on people’s
nism responsible for linking general aspects desire to consistently apply a norm of reci-
of cognition to prosocial tendencies. From procity (Gouldner, 1960), requiring a rela-
the present perspective, the capacity of wise tively stronger role for distrust, anger, desire
and mindful persons to acquire a thorough to punish nonreciprocators, and a morality
and perhaps objective understanding of how of justice. An important issue for future re-
people’s lives are affected by the environ- search, therefore, would be to examine the
ment (Brown et al., 2007; Sternberg, 1998) relative importance of different types of mo-
and how they are thus made vulnerable in- rality in different persons, situations, and
creases the likelihood of activation of the cultures (see also Haidt, 2007).
care mechanism, enabling these persons to
frequently feel tenderness and sympathy in
their thinking. Complementarily, frequent REFERENCES
activation of the care mechanism in wise
Alley, T. R. (1983). Growth-produced changes in
and mindful persons helps them to look for, body shape and size as determinants of per-
and enhance their knowledge about, envi- ceived age and adult caregiving. Child Devel-
ronmental threats and opportunities that opment, 54, 241–248.
are relevant to vulnerable beings. Bartz, J. A., Zaki, J., Bolger, N., & Ochsner, K.
N. (2011). Social effects of oxytocin in hu-
mans: Context and person matter. Trends in
Conclusions Cognitive Sciences, 15, 301–309.
Batson, C. D., & Ahmad, N. (2001). Empathy-
This chapter has attempted to show that, induced altruism in a prisoner’s dilemma: II.
although vulnerability is a property of indi- What if the target of empathy has defected?
European Journal of Social Psychology, 31,
viduals of flesh and blood, such as children, 25–36.
women, and elderly persons, it can also be Batson, C. D., Polycarpou, M. P., Harmon-Jones,
inferred from frequently used experimen- E., Imhoff, H. J., Mitchener, E. C., Bednar,
tal dilemmas in which concrete individuals L. L., . . . Highberger, L. (1997). Empathy
are absent or invisible, such as in the trol- and attitudes: Can feeling for a member of a
ley problem or the Prisoner’s Dilemma. As stigmatized group improve feelings toward the
mentioned, the involvement of vulnerability group? Journal of Personality and Social Psy-
perception in responding to these dilemmas chology, 72, 105–118.
awaits empirical testing. Bechtel, W., & Abrahamsen, A. (2005). Expla-
The present focus on the perception of nation: A mechanistic alternative. Studies in
the History and Philosophy of Biological and
vulnerability not only provides new insights Biomedical Sciences, 36, 421–441.
into the nature of morality but also encour- Berry, D. S., & McArthur, L. Z. (1986). Perceiv-
ages us to think about mental states, perhaps ing character in faces: The impact of age-relat-
unique to humans, in which morality, true ed craniofacial changes on social perception.
understanding, and aesthetic experience are Psychological Bulletin, 100, 3–18.
fused. However, it seems likely that a vul- Binmore, K. (2007). Game theory: A very short
nerability-based morality that depends on introduction. Oxford, UK: Oxford University
the activation of a care mechanism and also Press.
438 D E V E L O P M E N TA L A N D E VO L U T I O N A RY R O O T S O F M O R A L I T Y

Brown, K. W., Ryan, R. M., & Creswell, J. D. ance. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University
(2007). Mindfulness: Theoretical foundations Press.
and evidence for its salutary effects. Psycho- Dobres, M. A. (2001). Meaning in the making:
logical Inquiry, 18, 211–237. Agency and the social embodiment of technol-
Burke, E. (1759/1990). A philosophical enquiry ogy and art. In M. B. Schiffer (Ed.), Anthro-
into the origin of our ideas of the sublime and pological perspectives on technology (pp. 47–
beautiful. Oxford, UK: Oxford University 76). Albuquerque: University of New Mexico
Press. Press.
Carpenter, R. C. (2003). “Women and children Eagly, A. H., & Crowley, M. (1986). Gender and
first”: Gender, norms, and humanitarian evac- helping behavior: A meta-analytic review of
uation in the Balkans 1991–95. International the social psychological literature. Psychologi-
Organization, 57, 661–694. cal Bulletin, 100, 283–308.
Christensen, J. F., & Gomila, A. (2012). Moral Eibl-Eibesfeldt, I. (1989). Human ethology. New
dilemmas in cognitive neuroscience of moral York: Aldine de Gruyter.
decision-making: A principled review. Neu- Gouldner, A. W. (1960). The norm of reciprocity:
roscience and Biobehavioral Reviews, 36, A preliminary statement. American Sociologi-
1249–1264. cal Review, 25, 161–178.
Cialdini, R. B., Brown, S. L., Lewis, B. P., Luce, Gray, K., & Wegner, D. M. (2009). Moral type-
C., & Neuberg, S. L. (1997). Reinterpreting casting: Divergent perceptions of moral agents
the empathy–altruism relationship: When one and moral patients. Journal of Personality and
into one equals oneness. Journal of Personal- Social Psychology, 96, 505–520.
ity and Social Psychology, 73, 481–494. Greene, J. D., Cushman, F. A., Stewart, L. A.,
Cikara, M., Farnsworth, R. A., Harris, L. T., & Lowenberg, K., Nystrom, L. E., & Cohen, J.
Fiske, S. T. (2010). On the wrong side of the D. (2009). Pushing moral buttons: The inter-
trolley track: Neural correlates of relative so- action between personal force and intention
cial valuation. Social Cognitive and Affective in moral judgment. Cognition, 111, 364–371.
Neuroscience, 5, 404–413. Haidt, J. (2007). The new synthesis in moral psy-
Davie, M. R. (1929). The evolution of war: A chology. Science, 316, 998–1002.
study of its role in early societies. New Haven, Hamilton, W. D. (1964). The genetical evolution
CT: Yale University Press. of social behaviour: I and II. Journal of Theo-
Dawes, R. M. (1980). Social dilemmas. Annual retical Biology, 7, 1–52.
Review of Psychology, 31, 169–193. Hoijer, B. (2004). The discourse of global com-
Dijker, A. J. M. (2001). The influence of per- passion: The audience and media reporting of
ceived suffering and vulnerability on the ex- human suffering. Media, Culture, and Soci-
perience of pity. European Journal of Social ety, 26, 513–531.
Psychology, 31, 659–676. Hrdy, S. B. (2009). Mothers and others: The evo-
Dijker, A. J. M. (2010). Perceived vulnerability lutionary origins of mutual understanding.
as a common basis of moral emotions. British Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Journal of Social Psychology, 49, 415–423. Keltner, D., Young, R. C., & Buswell, B. N.
Dijker, A. J. M. (2011). Physical constraints on (1997). Appeasement in human emotion, so-
the evolution of cooperation. Evolutionary Bi- cial practice, and personality. Aggressive Be-
ology, 38, 124–143. havior, 23, 359–374.
Dijker, A. J. M. (2014a). Consciousness: A neural Kollock, P. (1998). Social dilemmas: The anato-
capacity for objectivity, especially pronounced my of cooperation. Annual Review of Sociol-
in humans. Frontiers in Psychology, 5(223). ogy, 24, 183–214.
Dijker, A. J. M. (2014b). A theory of vulnera- Krebs, D. L. (2007). Deciphering the structure
bility-based morality. Emotion Review, 6, of the moral sense: A review of Marc Haus-
175–183. er’s Moral minds: How nature designed our
Dijker, A. J. M., Deluster, R., Peeters, N., & De universal sense of right and wrong. Evolution
Vries, N. K. (2017). Seeing overweight adults and Human Behavior, 28, 294–298.
as babies: Physical cues and implications for Krupp, D. B., Debruine, L. M., & Barclay, P.
stigmatization. British Journal of Psychology. (2008). A cue to kinship promotes cooperation
[Epub ahead of print] for the public good. Evolution and Human
Dijker, A. J. M., & Koomen, W. (2003). Extend- Behavior, 29, 49–55.
ing Weiner’s attribution–emotion model of Lorenz, K. (1943). Die angeborenen Formen
stigmatization of ill persons. Basic and Ap- möglicher Erfahrung [The innate forms of
plied Social Psychology, 25, 51–68. potential experience]. Zeitschrift fur Tierpsy-
Dijker, A. J. M., & Koomen, W. (2007). Stigma- chologie, 5, 235–409.
tization, tolerance, and repair: An integrative McKeogh, C. (2002). Innocent civilians: The
psychological analysis of responses to devi- morality of killing in war. New York: Palgrave.
 Vulnerability‑Based Morality 439

Mehu, M., Grammer, K., & Dunbar, R. I. M. Scruton, R. (2011). Beauty: A very short in-
(2007). Smiles when sharing. Evolution and troduction. Oxford, UK: Oxford University
Human Behavior, 28, 415–422. Press.
Mikhail, J. (2007). Universal moral grammar: Sternberg, R. J. (1998). A balance theory of wis-
Theory, evidence and the future. Trends in dom. Review of General Psychology, 2, 347–
Cognitive Sciences, 11, 143–152. 365.
Moll, J., Zahn, R., de Oliveira-Souza, R., Swann, W. B., Gómez, A., Dovidio, J. F., Hart, S.,
Krueger, F., & Grafman, J. (2005). The neural & Jetten, J. (2010). Dying and killing for one’s
basis of human moral cognition. Nature Re- group: Identity fusion moderates responses
views/Neuroscience, 6, 799–809. to intergroup versions of the trolley problem.
Nelissen, R. M. A., Dijker, A. J. M., & de Vries, Psychological Science, 21, 1176–1183.
N. K. (2007). How to turn a hawk into a dove Trivers, R. L. (1971). The evolution of reciprocal
and vice versa: Interactions between emotions altruism. Quarterly Review of Biology, 46,
and goals in a give-some dilemma game. Jour- 35–57.
nal of Experimental Social Psychology, 43, Van Lange, P. A. M., Ouwekerk, J. W., & Taz-
280–286. elaar, M. J. A. (2002). How to overcome the
Numan, M. (2012). Neural circuits regulating detrimental effects of noise in social interac-
maternal behavior: Implications for under- tion: The benefits of generosity. Journal of
standing the neural basis of social coopera- Personality and Social Psychology, 82, 768–
tion and competition. In S. L. Brown, R. M. 780.
Brown, & L. A. Penner (Eds.), Moving beyond Weiner, B., Perry, R. P., & Magnusson, J. (1988).
self-interest: Perspectives from evolutionary An attributional analysis of reactions to stig-
biology, neuroscience, and the social sciences mas. Journal of Personality and Social Psy-
(pp. 89–108). Oxford, UK: Oxford University chology, 55(5), 738–748.
Press. Wiggins, D. (2006). Ethics: Twelve lectures on
Park, J. T., Schaller, M., & Van Vugt, M. (2008). the philosophy of morality. London: Penguin
Psychology of human kin recognition: Heuris- Books.
tic cues, erroneous inferences, and their impli- Wispé, L. (1991). The psychology of sympathy.
cations. Review of General Psychology, 12, New York: Plenum Press.
215–235. Young, L., & Dungan, J. (2012). Where in the
Petrinovich, L., O’Neill, P., & Jorgensen, M. brain is morality?: Everywhere and maybe no-
(1993). An empirical study of moral intuitions: where. Social Neuroscience, 7, 1–10.
Toward an evolutionary ethics. Journal of Per- Zebrowitz, L. A., Fellous, J.-M., Mignault, A.,
sonality and Social Psychology, 64, 467–478. & Andreoletti, C. (2003). Trait impressions
Rousseau, D. M., Sitkin, S. B., Burt, R. S., & as overgeneralized responses to adaptively
Camerer, C. (1998). Not so different after all: significant facial qualities: Evidence from con-
A cross-discipline view of trust. Academy of nectionist modeling. Personality and Social
Management Review, 23, 393–404. Psychology Review, 7, 194–215.
CHAPTER 45

The Attachment Approach


to Moral Judgment

Aner Govrin

What are the rules and patterns guiding the rapid, automatic, and
unconscious processes of moral judgment?

The attachment approach suggests that early interactions with care‑


givers give rise to a dyadic representation of morality—adult acting
upon a child—that determines how moral judgments are construed,
used, and understood.

When looking at moral situations, one can 2006; Mikhail, 2000; Shweder & Haidt,
discern that despite the variety and differ- 1994). There is, however, considerable dis-
ences in content of moral situations, people agreement and confusion as to what moral
recognize them immediately, intuitively, and intuitions are and how they work.
effortlessly. Just think of how situations The attachment approach to moral judg-
such as medical negligence, the death pen- ment suggests that the patterns of people’s
alty, rape, theft, and torture methods used moral decisions actually follow fairly
against terrorists are crucially different. And straightforwardly from internally represent-
yet people easily categorize all of these situ- ed principles or rules acquired in infancy.
ations as requiring right–wrong judgments. My assumption is that moral judgment is
What cognitive processes unite different a complex cognitive achievement that may
moral situations in one category? How are depend on a set of building block systems
moral situations represented in our minds? that appear early on in human ontogeny and
How do people recognize moral situations phylogeny. This claim comes in the wake
and notice their patterns? of 20 years of infant research showing that
Recent research in moral psychology the knowledge accumulated during the first
has produced strong evidence to suggest year of life is the foundation on which later
that moral judgment is intuitive and ac- learning, including language acquisition,
complished by a rapid, automatic, and un- numeracy, object categorization, social re-
conscious psychological process (Dama- lations, and other complex cognitive skills,
sio, 1994; Greene & Haidt, 2002; Hauser, rests (Ensink & Mayes, 2010; Mandler &

440
 The Attachment Approach to Moral Judgment 441

McDonough, 1998; Spelke, 2000; Starkey involve harming others because they repre-
& Cooper, 1980; Wynn, 1990). sent an essential component of moral judg-
Research in the moral domain has shown ment. This seems to be true across cultures
that infants have an inherent moral foun- (Nichols, 2004).
dation—the capacity and preparedness to The fundamental unit of moral situa-
judge the actions of others, a certain sense tions is the dyad. I term this phenomenon
of justice, and an intuitive response to mean- the dyad-superiority effect of moral situ-
ness. In a number of studies (Hamlin, Wynn, ations. Essentially, this means that moral
Bloom, & Mahajan, 2011; Hamlin, Wynn, situations are mentally represented as two
& Bloom, 2007, 2010; Hamlin, 2013a), ba- parties in conflict. Strong evidence exists for
bies showed a clear preference for an indi- the dyadic nature of moral situations. A se-
vidual who was being helpful as opposed to ries of studies by Gray and colleagues (Gray,
someone who obstructed another’s path in Waytz, & Young, 2012) showed that the es-
life. Moreover, the studies show that infants sence of moral judgment is the perception
preferred a helpful individual to one who of two complementary minds—a dyad con-
stood on the sidelines and the latter to one sisting of an intentional moral agent and a
who was deliberately unhelpful. suffering moral patient. As the dyad is being
However, the experiments tell us very lit- perceived by an observer, there are three
tle about the procedures or moral principles parties to a basic moral judgment situation:
that infants learn, how they encode a moral two conflicting parties—the perceived adult
situation, and what representations they (A) and the perceived child (C)— and an ob-
compare it with. My supposition is that, server (O). O makes a judgment on the dyad
in the same way as an infant born with in- A → C.
herent linguistic faculties will only learn to
speak if he or she grows up in the presence of O: Observer.
people who talk to him or her, infant–care- A: Perceived adult (wrongdoer).
giver interactions enable us to construe and C: Perceived child (victim).
give meaning to moral situations. → Behavior, harm done, overall attitude
In order to establish the link between early of A toward C.
infancy and the acquisition of basic moral
faculties, we have to be able to define (1) the Given the huge amount of data that exists
appropriate stimulus that is likely to lead to in relation to any given moral dyad, how do
the learning of the actual processes by which we organize the information for a particular
moral judgment is exercised and (2) the deep perceived dyad? How do we extract a judg-
structures that are common to the entire ment from the basic features of A, →, and C?
range of moral situations, including the link It is probably the case that, in the process
between those structures and the initial im- of reaching a moral judgment, the moral
petus that made moral learning possible. dyad that appears in our minds is weighed
up against some prior knowledge we have
about dyads. My premise is that we can reach
How Can These Assertions Be Tested? a moral judgment only if, in our minds, we
hold some reliable form of prior knowledge
There is no direct evidence of the way in of the moral situation, a mental representa-
which infants acquire moral knowledge, just tion of what we know about conflicts in our
as there is no direct evidence of the way in social environment.
which infants learn the deep structures of Thus I am assuming that we deal with
language. Therefore, we must discover what moral situations in the same way that we
the deep structures of moral situations are deal with other concepts. Moral knowl-
and then look into the way in which these edge, just as other human knowledge, is or-
are linked to the first year of a child’s life. ganized around encodings of prototypical
The aim is to advance the most basic set of cases, rather than via the use and storage of
assumptions that can still account for vari- rules and definitions. In the case of moral
ous moral judgments and situations. My ac- judgment, we classify the situation as moral
count is mainly about moral situations that and then judge it according to the preexist-
442 D E V E L O P M E N TA L A N D E VO L U T I O N A RY R O O T S O F M O R A L I T Y

ing representation it most closely resembles popping out of nowhere, without much con-
(Hahn & Ramscar, 2001). scious awareness of their origins or of the
My assertion is that the various compo- manner of their formation.
nents of a moral situation—such as inten- The schemas are fixed around defining
tionality, controllability, personal respon- features of adults and children, such as big–
sibility, and free will—have an additional small, weak–strong, vulnerable–resistant,
layer of representational content that has helpless–powerful, dependent–independent,
not been noticed by social psychologists. knowingly–unknowingly, responsible–irre-
They are secondary features. They represent sponsible. The schemas are broad enough to
something more primary, more basic. handle endless variations of these themes. I
The central underlying thesis that I ad- suggest that when facing a moral situation
vance is that the most informative features the mind uses these schemas to select and
of moral judgments—intent, free will, and organize the information that will most ef-
controllability—are supported by a more fectively aid us in the judgment process.
deeply seated feature—our knowledge about In generating a nonconscious moral judg-
infants (or children) and adults. We possess ment, we perform two mental operations:
an affective and cognitive mechanism that is We impose a dyadic structure of child–adult
highly sensitive to the distinctions between (or agent–patient; Gray et al., 2012) upon
child-like and adult-like traits. As I dis- two parties in conflict, and we compare the
cuss, these traits are very instructive when behavior of A toward C with our prior ex-
it comes to an understanding of others. The pectations of what adults should and should
same parameters that are crucial to the at- not do to children. Acts that violate our ex-
tribution of responsibility for a wrongdoing pectations are judged as morally wrong. Al-
(intentionality, controllability, and free will) though the decision as to which party is C
are pivotal to the distinction between chil- or A is highly subjective, the general traits
dren and adults. that are associated with children and those
The evaluation of the moral situation is a associated with adults are constant and uni-
derivative of our inner schemas of children versal.
(dependents) and adults (independents). In As Figure 45.1 demonstrates, in generat-
our minds, different expectations, feelings, ing a nonconscious moral judgment, we per-
cognitions, and mental images are associ- form two mental operations:
ated with children and adults. For example,
we are emotionally much more responsive 1. Evaluating the child-like and the adult-
to the suffering of children than to that of like characteristics of each party and de-
adults (Dijker, 2001). ciding, if we are able to, which of the par-
Strong emotional reactivity to the suffer- ties matches an adult schema and which a
ing of children and infants is not the only child schema.
thing that distinguishes the way in which 2. Evaluating the relationship between the
we relate to children and adults. Apparently, adult-like and child-like parties in terms
children and adults are identified by separate of (→), where → is the symbol for the
schemas that also involve cognitions and at- harm done, as well as the overall relation
tributions. Children are perceived as weak, of the independent vis-à-vis the depen-
needy, helpless, lacking control, vulnerable, dent in a particular dyad. That is, we do
dependent, and unable to take care of oth- not have schemas only for children and
ers. These traits have profound implications adults. We also possess a schema for the
for our attributions and moral judgments. dyadic relation, centered on prior expec-
I suggest that we represent each of the par- tations of how adults should treat chil-
ties (A and C) in ways that are comparable to dren.
our representations of children and adults.
All our efforts are geared to construct the The evaluation of child-like and adult-like
reality of the moral situation in terms of an characteristics in a particular moral situa-
adult–child dyad. Judgments placing the tion is observer relative. The same individ-
parties on the child–adult spectrum come ual in a particular dyad might be construed
to mind quickly and effortlessly, seemingly as A by one person and as C by another. In
 The Attachment Approach to Moral Judgment 443

we all understand without having been con-


Dyadic sciously instructed in it.
Relations Contrary to what the accounts of senti-
Child-/adult- Child-/adult- mentalists or intuitionists may argue (Haidt,
like like 2010; Prinz, 2007), our moral judgments,
unlike our aesthetic tastes, are not arbitrary.
X Y Even when they lead to contradictory conclu-
Moral sions, they are not entirely flexible. Though
judgment it can be said that the construing of moral
judgment is “tolerant” and allows diverse
A C cultural and personal projections, it is not
the case that each and every projection will
be perceived as sensible and/or acceptable.
FIGURE 45.1.  The attachment model of moral A dyad will allow certain projections and
judgment. In generating a nonconscious moral block others if, and only if, it is construed
judgment, we perform two mental operations: as A → C. Moral judgments are therefore
We impose a dyadic structure of child–adult/ constrained by rules that are guided by the
agent–patient (Gray et al., 2012) on two parties knowledge we have as to how dyads should
in conflict, and we compare the behavior of A function and work. Our expectations of per-
toward C with our prior expectations of what ceived independents in the presence of de-
adults should and should not do to children. Acts pendents impose extrinsic requirements on
that violate our expectations are judged as mor- our moral judgments.
ally wrong. Although the decision as to which
party is child-like or adult-like is highly subjec-
tive, the general traits that are associated with Historical Context
children and those associated with adults are
constant and universal. The idea that our moral sense is essentially
connected to early ties of dependency be-
tween the child and his or her caregiver is
not new. It was suggested by John Bowlby’s
fact, construing the parties as C or A is the attachment theory and Carol Gilligan’s eth-
principal act of moral judgment. If party X ics of care (Bowlby, 1944, 1953, 1958, 1980;
matches an adult schema (A), and party Y Gilligan, 1982; Gilligan & Wiggins, 1987).
matches a child schema (C), it means that However, the ideas of attachment theory
we think X has done harm to Y and that we and ethics of care have not been accorded
sympathize with C and condemn A. But this the centrality in moral psychology appropri-
is only true for an observer who perceives X ate to their importance.
as adult-like and Y as child-like. So child-like Darwin (1874), theorized that social in-
and adult-like schemas are not just cognitive stincts originated in “parental and filial af-
assessments of traits. They incorporate our fections” (p. 95). Lakoff and Johnson (1999)
emotions, judgments, and actions toward write: “Brains tend to optimize on the basis
the parties. of what they already have, to add only what
The general idea is that moral judgment is necessary. Over the course of evolution,
involves computing child-like and adult-like newer parts of the brain have built on, taken
characteristics and comparing the adult-like input from, and used older parts of the
party’s behavior toward the child-like party brain” (p. 43). Is it really plausible to suggest
with our prior expectations. This process is that if the infant–caregiver system can be put
almost like a reflex: It operates quickly and to work in the service of a parent protecting
automatically so that, for instance, one can- his or her child, the brain would build a new
not help taking into account the child-like system to duplicate what it could already do
face of an adult, the young age of a thief, or in other social relations?
the unintended harm of an accidental kill- Dyadic morality (Gray & Wegner, 2008,
ing. This is a natural language of relations 2009; Gray et al., 2012) has significantly in-
between dependents and independents that formed the current theory. Gray and his col-
444 D E V E L O P M E N TA L A N D E VO L U T I O N A RY R O O T S O F M O R A L I T Y

leagues suggest that mind perception is the in a moral situation, positive and negative
essence of moral judgment. Gray’s argument excitation cycles will circulate in the net-
is that a prototypical immoral act should in- work, and a steady state will be achieved,
clude a moral agent who intentionally causes resulting in a full gestalt of the moral situa-
harm and a moral patient who suffers as a tion as A → C.
result. I see my theory as completing and en- Because a node’s activation is a function
riching this perspective, recognizing the deep of all the positive and negative connections
roots of the agent–patient dyad in the repre- to other nodes that are activated in paral-
sentations of dependents and caregivers. lel, the final activation of a node (i.e., at the
The attachment approach to moral judg- point at which the system stabilizes) can be
ment draws heavily on the theory of sche- thought of as the satisfaction of multiple
matic representation (Rumelhart & Ortony, constraints. In a connectionist model, each
1977) as a simple model for understand- connection between nodes is a constraint
ing moral judgments. These judgments are (Freeman & Ambady, 2011). For instance, a
based on child and adult schemas. I have node representing the category “baby face”
chosen schemas because they are often more might excite and be excited by another node
task-oriented than are exemplars or proto- representing the cognition “wrongdoing was
types and less concerned with recognition unintentional.” When these two nodes are
and classification. Rather, a schema is a incorporated in a larger recurrent network,
mental framework for organizing important the “baby face” node serves as a constraint
knowledge, creating a meaningful structure on the network. That is, for the network to
of related concepts based on prior experi- ever achieve stability, activation must flow
ences. Therefore, schemas seem more appro- through that connection and incorporate it
priate to the moral domain, which involves into an overall stable pattern that includes
not merely recognition and classification but all other nodal connections.
also the organization of material in a par- Thus nodes in a recurrent network con-
ticular way. strain each other in finding the best overall
pattern that is consistent with the input.
Such a model of a connectionist network can
Connectionism
explain how one single component of a dyad
What model of the brain can describe such influences the other components.
a hypothesis? Some researchers (Freeman Serious moral dilemmas can also be ex-
& Ambady, 2011; Harman, Mason, & plained by a connectionist model. These
Sinnott-Armstrong, 2010; Hopfield, 1982; dilemmas require relatively high levels of
Rumelhart & McClelland, 1986; Thagard, cognitive processing, because each party is
1989, 2000) argued that a connectionist net- simultaneously associated with “bad” and
work model possibly provides us with a way “good” aspects. Thus each side sort of blocks
of explaining how people reach judgments the conflicting characteristics attributed to
about others. Dynamical systems, such as each party. The process involves a dynamic
a recurrent connectionist network of the competition between victim–­ perpetrator
human brain, are powerful in their ability representations (“they are victims but at the
to integrate multiple simultaneous sources same time perpetrators”) that continuously
of information. In a recurrent connectionist compete. The bombing of civilians in Dres-
network, there are a number of nodes with den in World War II, the use of harsh inter-
connections that can be positive (excitatory) rogation methods against terrorists, and the
or negative (inhibitory). Positive links con- bullying of cruel criminals by the police are
nect one set of nodes to other nodes so that, some of the cases in which moral judgment
as one of the nodes becomes more excited, is effortful and requires a great deal of pro-
its excitation increases the excitation of the cessing.
other nodes (Freeman & Ambady, 2011). For the system to settle into a stable state
Conversely, as the excitation of one such (e.g., reach a final moral judgment), the
node lessens or is in receipt of negative lev- parallel and partially active victim-versus-­
els of excitation, the excitation of the other perpetrator category nodes of each party
nodes is lessened. When applied to elements must engage in a dynamic competition, with
 The Attachment Approach to Moral Judgment 445

one gradually gaining activation and the set of theories in psychology that claim that
other gradually dying off, as they suppress moral judgment takes the form of intuition,
each other’s activation through inhibition. accomplished by a rapid, automatic, and
Note that the model of a holistic dyad rep- unconscious psychological process (Haidt,
resentation does not mean that the compet- 2001; Hauser, 2006; Mikhail, 2000; Shwed-
ing traits of the two parties (actor–patient) er & Haidt, 1994). But it differs from these
must give way to a winner-take-all mecha- theories in many important respects.
nism. Rather, it would seem more plausible First, it posits that moral judgment could
that in serious moral dilemmas there are a arise through the influence of either affect or
multitude of representations also at the level reason. Emotions and gut feelings are essen-
of the dyad and that the competition takes tial parts of moral judgment, but cool rea-
place at that level as well. This is naturally son and consequentialist principles can also
accommodated by a connectionist approach. influence the dyad construal and add to the
“Dyad units” represent this domain on vari- computing process. Second, the added value
ous levels of abstraction. of the attachment approach is that it specifies
in detail what exactly goes on “in our heads”
when we follow our moral intuitions and the
Theoretical Stance way in which the entire procedure relates to
cognitive processes. The intuitions and emo-
The child–caregiver dyad is perhaps the tions behind moral judgments are rule based.
most undertheorized domain in moral psy- By rules, I mean inferential devices for
chology. Though there is an enormous body categorization, estimation, paired compari-
of literature showing the link between pat- sons, and other judgmental tasks that go
terns of early attachment and moral behav- beyond the information given. The rule con-
ior (Mikulincer & Florian, 2000; Shaver & cept denotes an if–then relation of the type if
Mikulincer, 2012; van IJzendoorn, 1997), (cues), then (judgment; Kruglanski & Giger-
the subject of parenthood in infancy remains enzer, 2011). One of the rules we use in judg-
in the margins, exiled by moral psychology’s ing moral situations is: If a party is perceived
long-standing cultural bias against it and ig- to be child-like (cues) then we judge that
norance of the subject’s importance. party as less accountable, less reprehensible,
In most of the studies, infants were still less responsible, less wrathful, and so on.
being perceived apart from their surround- Third, the important thing is that the
ings, as if they possessed an isolated mind rules apply to whole relations, not to spe-
that was developing separately from the en- cific harmful acts. We do not judge an act
vironment in which they were growing up. as wrongdoing; we judge an entire relation-
For example, Hamlin et al. (2007, 2010) ship, a dyad. Wrongdoings are violations of
posit that the capacity of infants to evaluate our expectations of independents. Acts are
individuals on the basis of their social inter- judged as transgressions when an observer
actions is unlearned (Hamlin, 2013b). evaluates or senses that a dyad went wrong,
This lacuna has a long history in moral violated an expected contingency.
psychology that stretches from Piaget and One of the main merits of the proposed
Kohlberg to contemporary moral psychol- model is that it has an explanatory power
ogy. And yet, infant research conducted for understanding one of the most haunting
outside of moral psychology (Beebe & Lach- questions in moral psychology: Are moral
man, 2002; Emde, 1988; Fonagy & Tar- rules absolute and universal, or are they cul-
get, 2007; Mayes, Fonagy, & Target, 2007) turally dependent?
shows that out of all the influences around
him or her, the one that affects the newborn
Is Morality Universal and Absolute
the most is the maternal care that he or she
or Culturally Driven?
receives. Despite this consistent finding,
theories in moral development have failed to How can moral knowledge based on dyadic
integrate it in any meaningful way. principles claim to be universal when moral
From another perspective, the attachment systems and values differ so much from one
approach to moral judgment belongs to a another?
446 D E V E L O P M E N TA L A N D E VO L U T I O N A RY R O O T S O F M O R A L I T Y

The dyadic principles, it has to be remem- another. In other words, it is conceivable


bered, are not intended to be common to that in the deep structures of moral situa-
all moral systems. These are principles that tions there is a basic identification of the two
are intended to serve as a “toolkit” that a sides along the dependent–independent axis
child acquires in order to learn how right– and an assessment of whether the adult side
wrong judgments of all kinds are reached. had behaved in line with our expectations.
It is the platform on which moral judgments But this process can be formed in different
are carried, thought about, and understood. ways (e.g., through education or cultural in-
It’s somewhat like a car: When we turn on fluences) and not necessarily in the first year
the ignition, the car operates like a car—not of life. And yet there are many reasons for
a boat—simply because it’s built like a car. the belief that the first year of life is critical
However, if we don’t turn the key, nothing to the development of moral faculties.
happens. The interactions between infant There is a great deal of evidence to sup-
and caregiver are required in order to feed port the view that expectations of social
moral principle acquisition into the system. relations emerge in the first months of life
However, these infant–caregiver interac- through infant–caregiver interactions (see
tions do not determine the content, form, Beebe & Stern, 1977; Beebe & Lachmann,
or nature of the specific morality. But they 1988; Sander, 1977, 1983, 1985; Stern,
contain all the principles necessary for most 1985, 1998). A principle called ongoing reg-
moral judgments to be reached in different ulations between mother and infant (Beebe
cultures and among a variety of agents. The & Lachmann, 2002) provides the most basic
cultural and personal differences among rule for organizing representations. An in-
agents are encoded as assigning different fant develops an ability to anticipate when
weight to the various components of the something is likely to happen and an expec-
dyad. Hence, the dyadic rules must be rich tation that what he or she does has conse-
and specific enough to enable each child quences. In addition, we know that infants
to acquire basic moral knowledge but flex- have specific capacities that are related to
ible enough to enable him or her to acquire moral judgment: Young infants understand
different moral preferences in different cul- intentional action as goal-directed and ra-
tures. tional (Gergely, 2002, 2011; Meltzoff &
Moore, 1995; Schwier, Van Maanen, Car-
penter, & Tomasello, 2006).
Evidence The second hypothesis according to
which observers look at both sides for signs
The attachment approach to moral judg- of “child” and “adult” is based on indirect
ment is supported by numerous studies in evidence. For example, as already noted,
various disciplines, including moral psy- the key elements in moral judgment—such
chology, infant research, and cognitive neu- as internal and controllable causality and
roscience. Though none of this evidence is intentionality—are significant because they
unequivocal, when put together, it offers, at include a wealth of information about the
the very least, an acceptable level of support characteristics of child–adult that the ob-
for the proposed theory. The theory includes server is looking for.
two hypotheses. The first claims that moral Another line of evidence comes from a
principles are determined during the first number of experiments (Berry & Zebrow-
year of life through parent–child interac- itz-McArthur, 1985) that indicate that a
tion. The second hypothesis deals with the baby-faced defendant will be considered less
way in which people break moral situations likely to have committed an offense inten-
down to their defining components: Who re- tionally and more likely to have committed
sembles a child, who resembles an adult, and it through negligence. Beyond the model’s
what is the nature of the relations between ability to explain a wide range of phenom-
them? ena, it also gives rise to a number of new
It has to be noted that the first and sec- and distinctive predictions that future work
ond hypotheses are not dependent on one could directly examine.
 The Attachment Approach to Moral Judgment 447

The model predicts that any given change The theory’s big challenge will be to show
in one node of the dyad component (A, C, and the way in which the sensorimotor experi-
→) will lead to changes in all other nodes, as ences in the first year of life are translated
the system works over time to maximally into knowledge about dyadic relations and
satisfy all of its constraints in parallel. For how they form a set of expectations that is
example, when there are conflicting consid- no longer linked to the direct relations be-
erations (such as malice without harm; harm tween child and caregiver.
mild but intended; baby face and intended In brain research, the challenge will be to
harm; harm planned to affect one individual prove that moral situations are resolved as
but intended to save several other potential a result of “moral computations”: Whenever
victims), there is considerable tension be- a moral problem arises, the observer com-
tween the nodes. This might reduce the sys- putes the “child” and “adult” components
tem’s efficiency and slow down the process, of each side of the dyad. The observer then
because it will take the system more time to calculates the extent to which the conduct
reach a full gestalt of the dyad. toward the child by the side perceived as the
adult deviates from the observer’s expecta-
tions. Of course, one has to add a subjective
component, which is linked to the emotional
Extension and Expansion connection and the way the observer feels
toward each party.
Apart from its contribution to moral psy-
chology, the attachment approach to moral
The Challenge in the Philosophical Domain
judgment is likely to augment and enrich two
other centrally important fields of study: in- If we unconsciously and intuitively engage in
fant and brain research. computing each party’s child-like and adult-
From the knowledge acquired by an infant like features and compare the adult-like par-
in the first year of life, one can see what the ty’s behavior to our former expectations, we
psychologist Susan Carey (2011) termed core are not employing moral principles. Moral
cognition. Carey argues that explaining the principles (such as Kant’s categorical impera-
human capacity for conceptual understand- tive or the utilitarian principle) make no ref-
ing begins with the observation that evolu- erence to particular people, places, or times.
tion offers developmental primitives that are Yet moral computation is greatly influenced
much richer than the sensorimotor represen- by these considerations. How, then, do we
tations that many assume are the input to determine what is right and what is wrong?
all learning. Some of these developmental According to the proposed theory, our only
primitives are embedded in systems of what guide to moral right and moral wrong is our
Carey calls core cognition. innate detection system for child-like and
Core cognitions differ from other concep- adult-like features and our prior expecta-
tual representations because they include in- tions of adults. So, even if there indeed are
nate perceptual input analyzers that identify moral principles, they are not part of the
the entities in core domains, a long evolu- knowledge on which we based our moral
tionary history, continuity throughout de- judgment.
velopment, and iconic (or analog) formats. One way to tackle this problem is to posit
Core cognition carves the mind into signifi- that general moral principles such as those
cant subsystems. It is one very distinctive suggested by Rawls and Kant enable us to
part of the human mind: No other systems rise above the construal of subjective dyad.
of conceptual representations share its suite Turning the moral mechanism into a univer-
of characteristics. Thus one could say that sal law enables us, for example, to protect
if the evolutionary process of natural se- the weak and prevent moral injustices inde-
lection has endowed our minds with input pendently of the emotional mechanism that
analyzers, then one would think that such links an individual to a particular party.
processes would be of use to adults, as well In other words, moral principles apply the
as to children. same parameters to moral judgment as does
448 D E V E L O P M E N TA L A N D E VO L U T I O N A RY R O O T S O F M O R A L I T Y

the dyadic construal. They merely introduce lection in relation to sex. New York: Rand
additional cognitions that had not previ- McNally.
ously been taken into account. Whereas the Dijker, A. J. (2001). The influence of perceived
suffering and vulnerability on the experience
“natural” psychological mechanism often
of pity. European Journal of Social Psychol-
identifies people as child-like on the basis ogy, 31(6), 659–676.
of resemblance to and membership in that Emde, R. N. (1988). Reflections on mothering
same group, the moral principles compel us and on reexperiencing the early relationship
to ignore this component and relate to all experience. Infant Mental Health Journal,
suffering people as child-like. They might 9(1), 4–9.
be used as constraints that inhibit personal Ensink, K., & Mayes, L. C. (2010). The devel-
preference, cultural bias, or any other kind opment of mentalisation in children from a
of subjective factors besides the parameters theory of mind perspective. Psychoanalytic
Inquiry, 30(4), 301–337.
of the general dyadic rules. Fonagy, P., & Target, M. (2007). The rooting of
In conclusion, given the limited research the mind in the body: New links between at-
base, this model—although reflecting avail- tachment theory and psychoanalytic thought.
able research evidence—primarily serves a Journal of the American Psychoanalytic As-
heuristic function. I hope, nonetheless, that sociation, 55(2), 411–456.
the model will inspire researchers to gain Freeman, J. B., & Ambady, N. (2011). A dynamic
more empirical data on the mechanisms interactive theory of person construal. Psycho-
through which early attachment relations logical Review, 118(2), 247–279.
modulate moral judgments. Gergely, G. (2002). The development of under-
standing self and agency. In U. Goswami (Ed.),
Blackwell handbook of childhood cogni-
tive development (pp. 26–46). Malden, MA:
REFERENCES
Blackwell.
Gergely, G. (2011). Kinds of agents: The origins
Beebe, B., & Lachmann, F. (Eds.). (1988). Moth-
of understanding instrumental and commu-
er–infant mutual influence and precursors of
nicative agency. In U. Goswami (Ed.), The
psychic structure. Hillsdale, NJ: Analytic Press.
Wiley-Blackwell handbook of childhood
Beebe, B., & Lachmann, F. (2002). Infant re-
cognitive development (2nd ed., pp. 76–105).
search and adult treatment: Co-constructing
Hoboken, NJ: Wiley-Blackwell.
interactions. Hillsdale, NJ: Analytic Press. Gilligan, C. (1982). In a different voice: Women’s
Beebe, B., & Stern, D. (1977). Engagement–dis- conception of self and morality. Cambridge,
engagement and early object experiences. In MA: Harvard University Press.
N. Freedman & S. Grand (Ed.), Communica- Gilligan, C., & Wiggins, G. (1987). The origins
tive structures and psychic structures (pp. 35– of morality in early childhood relationships. In
55). New York: Plenum Press. J. Kagan & S. Lamb (Eds.), The emergence of
Berry, D. S., & Zebrowitz-McArthur, L. Z. morality in young children (pp. 277–305) Chi-
(1985). Some components and consequences cago: University of Chicago Press.
of a babyface. Journal of Personality and So- Gray, K., Waytz, A., & Young, L. (2012). The
cial Psychology, 48(2), 312–323. moral dyad: A fundamental template unifying
Bowlby, J. (1944). Forty-four juvenile thieves: moral judgment. Psychological Inquiry, 23(2),
Their characters and home-life: II. Inter­ 206–215.
national Journal of Psychoanalysis, 25, 107– Gray, K., & Wegner, D. M. (2008). The sting
128. of intentional pain. Psychological Science,
Bowlby, J. (1953). Child care and the growth of 19(12), 1260–1262.
love. London: Penguin Books. Gray, K., & Wegner, D. M. (2009). Moral type-
Bowlby, J. (1958). The nature of the child’s tie to casting: Divergent perceptions of moral agents
his mother. International Journal of Psycho- and moral patients. Journal of Personality and
analysis, 39, 350–373. Social Psychology, 96(3), 505–520.
Bowlby, J. (1980). Attachment and loss. New Greene, J., & Haidt, J. (2002). How (and where)
York: Basic Books. does moral judgment work? Trends in Cogni-
Carey, S. (2011). Précis of the origin of concepts. tive Sciences, 6(12), 517–523.
Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 34(3), 113– Hahn, U., & Ramscar, M. (Eds.). (2001). Simi-
167. larity and categorization. New York: Oxford
Damasio, A. (1994). Descartes’ error. Boston: University Press.
Norton. Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional dog and its ra-
Darwin, C. (1874). The descent of man and se- tional tail: A social intuitionist approach to
 The Attachment Approach to Moral Judgment 449

moral judgment. Psychological Review, 108, L. Bermúdez, N. Eilan, & A. Marcel (Eds.),
814–834. The body and the self (pp. 43–69). Cambridge,
Haidt, J. (2010). Moral psychology must not MA: MIT Press.
be based on faith and hope: Commentary on Mikhail, J. (2000). Rawls’ linguistic analogy:
Narvaez (2010). Perspectives on Psychological A study of the “generative grammar” model
Science, 5(2), 182–184. of moral theory described by John Rawls in
Hamlin, J. K. (2013a). Failed attempts to help “A Theory of Justice.” Available at https://
and harm: Intention versus outcome in pre- papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_
verbal infants’ social evaluations. Cognition, id=766464.
128(3), 451–474. Mikhail, J. (2011). Elements of moral cognition:
Hamlin, J. K. (2013b). Moral judgment and ac- Rawls’ linguistic analogy and the cognitive
tion in preverbal infants and toddlers: Evidence science of moral and legal judgment. New
for an innate moral core. Current Directions York: Cambridge University Press.
in Psychological Science, 22(3), 186–193. Mikulincer, M., & Florian, V. (2000). Exploring
Hamlin, J. K., Wynn, K., & Bloom, P. (2007). individual differences in reactions to mortality
Social evaluation in preverbal infants. Nature, salience: Does attachment style regulate terror
450(7169), 557–559. management mechanisms? Journal of Person-
Hamlin, J. K., Wynn, K., & Bloom, P. (2010). ality and Social Psychology, 79(2), 260–273.
Three-month-olds show a negativity bias in Nichols, S. (2004). Sentimental rules: On the
their social evaluations. Developmental Sci- natural foundations of moral judgment. Ox-
ence, 13(6), 923–929. ford, UK: Oxford University Press.
Hamlin, J. K., Wynn, K., Bloom, P., & Mahajan, Prinz, J. J. (2007). The emotional construction of
N. (2011). How infants and toddlers react to morals. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
antisocial others. Proceedings of the National Rumelhart, D. E., & McClelland, J. L. (1986).
Academy of Sciences of the USA, 108(50), Parallel distributed processing: Explorations
19931–19936. in the microstructure of cognition: Vol. 1.
Harman. G., Mason, K., & Sinnott-Armstrong, Foundations. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
W. (2010). Moral reasoning. In J. M. Doris Rumelhart, D. E., & Ortony, A. (1977). The
(Ed.), The moral psychology handbook representation of knowledge in memory. In R.
(pp. 206–245). Oxford, UK: Oxford Univer- C. Anderson, R. J. Spiro, & W. E. Montague
sity Press. (Eds.), Schooling and the acquisition of knowl-
Hauser, M. D. (2006). Moral minds: How na- edge (pp. 99–135). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
ture designed our universal sense of right and Sander, L. (1977). The regulation of exchange
wrong. London: HarperCollins. in the infant–caretaker system and some as-
Hauser, M. D. (2007). Moral minds: The nature pects of the context–content relationship. In
of right and wrong. New York: HarperCollins. M. Lewis & L. Rosenblum (Eds.), Interaction,
Hopfield, J. J. (1982). Neural networks and phys- conversation, and the development of lan-
ical systems with emergent collective compu- guage (pp. 133–156). New York: Wiley.
tational abilities. Proceedings of the National Sander, L. (1983). Polarity paradox and the or-
Academy of Sciences of the USA, 79, 2554– ganizing process in development. In J. D. Call,
2558. E. Galenson, & R. Tyson (Eds.), Frontiers of
Kruglanski, A. W., & Gigerenzer, G. (2011). In- infant psychiatry (pp. 315–327). New York:
tuitive and deliberate judgments are based on Basic Books.
common principles: Correction to Kruglanski Sander, L. (1985). Toward a logic of organization
and Gigerenzer. Psychology Reviews, 118, in psycho-biological development. In K. Klar
522. & L. Siever (Eds.), Biological response styles:
Lakoff, G., & Johnson, M. (1999). Philosophy Clinical implications (pp. 20–36). Washing-
in the flesh: The embodied mind and its chal- ton DC: American Psychiatric Press.
lenge to Western thought. New York: Basic Schwier, C., Van Maanen, C., Carpenter, M., &
Books. Tomasello, M. (2006). Rational imitation in
Mandler, J. M., & McDonough, L. (1998). On 12-month-old infants. Infancy, 10(3), 303–311.
developing a knowledge base in infancy. De- Shaver, P. R., & Mikulincer, M. (2012). An at-
velopmental Psychology, 34(6), 1274–1288. tachment perspective on morality: Strengthen-
Mayes, L., Fonagy, P., & Target, M. (Eds.). ing authentic forms of moral decision making.
(2007). Developmental science and psycho- In M. Mikulincer & P. R. Shaver (Eds.), The
analysis: Integration and innovation. London, social psychology of morality: Exploring the
UK: Karnac Books. causes of good and evil (pp. 257–274). Wash-
Meltzoff, A. N., & Moore, M. K. (1995). In- ington, DC: American Psychological Associa-
fants’ understanding of people and things: tion.
From body imitation to folk psychology. In J. Shweder, R. A., & Haidt, J. (1994). The future
450 D E V E L O P M E N TA L A N D E VO L U T I O N A RY R O O T S O F M O R A L I T Y

of moral psychology: Truth, intuition, and developmental psychology. London, UK: Kar-
the pluralist way. In B. Puka (Ed.), Reaching nac.
out: Caring, altruism, and prosocial behavior. Thagard, P. (1989). Explanatory coherence. Be-
(pp. 336–341) New York: Garland. havioral and Brain Sciences, 12(3), 435–502.
Spelke, E. S. (2000). Core knowledge. American Thagard, P. (2000). Coherence in thought and
Psychologist, 55(11), 1233–1243. action Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Starkey, P., & Cooper, R. G. (1980). Percep- van IJzendoorn, M. H. (1997). Attachment,
tion of numbers by human infants. Science, emergent morality, and aggression: Toward a
210(4473), 1033–1035. developmental socioemotional model of anti-
Stern, D. N. (1985). The interpersonal world of social behavior. International Journal of Be-
the infant. New York: Basic Books. havioral Development, 21(4), 703–727.
Stern, D. N. (1998). The interpersonal world of Wynn, K. (1990). Children’s understanding of
the infant: A view from psychoanalysis and counting. Cognition, 36(2), 155–193.
CHAPTER 46

Ethogenesis
Evolution, Early Experience, and Moral Becoming

Darcia Narvaez

What is the best comprehensive theory for understanding moral


development?

Taking an evolutionary developmental systems standpoint that


includes multiple ecological levels and extragenetic inheritances
(e.g., developmental niche, self-organization), ethogenesis describes
species-typical moral development, which includes relational attun‑
ement and communal imagination—orientations and capacities that
emerge from the biopsychosocial development of the brain/mind in
early life within a species-typical niche.

What is the best comprehensive theory for Narvaez, 2008, 2014a, 2016) was developed
understanding moral development? Etho- to bring the embodied perspective into moral
genesis takes an evolutionary developmental psychological research (Narvaez, 2010b).
systems perspective to describe how moral TEM is part of the trend toward studying
dispositions are biosocially shaped by ex- the effects of embodied experience on bio-
perience, especially in early life when basic psychosocial functioning. It provides a way
foundations for biopsychosocial function- to integrate findings across neuroscience,
ing are laid. It describes how development developmental, personality, and clinical
mismatched with the evolved development psychology. TEM identifies several neuro-
niche creates a different human nature, one biologically based moral mindsets and pro-
that does not match up with 99% of human- poses, for example, that self-regulatory ca-
ity’s history nor displays the characteristics pacities are critical for moral functioning. As
of what Darwin called humanity’s “moral illustration, when the stress response is acti-
sense.” vated, blood flows away from the prefron-
Ethogenesis directs attention to evolved tal cortex, impairing higher order thought
global mindsets that can guide human per- processes (Arnsten, 2009); with the mobili-
ception, interpretation, cognition, and be- zation of muscles and survival systems for
havior. Triune ethics meta-theory (TEM; personal safety, attention is drawn to issues

451
452 D E V E L O P M E N TA L A N D E VO L U T I O N A RY R O O T S O F M O R A L I T Y

of self-concern. TEM also points out how from experience, learned from experiencing
neurobiological functions critical for moral intersubjectivity, emotional presence, rever-
functioning are significantly shaped by early ence, play, and empathy (Emde, Biringen,
experience (Schore, 1994, 1996, 1997, 2000, Clyman, & Oppenheim, 1991; Trevarthen,
2001, 2003a, 2003b, 2005, 2013). Notably, 2005).
the parameters and threshold for the hypo- The imagination orientation emerges from
thalamic–pituitary–adrenal gland axis are executive functions such as planning, fore-
established in early life, so that when early sight, and abstraction (which take decades
experience is highly stressful, an individual to fully develop), allowing for an imagina-
can develop a hyper- or hypo­reactive stress tive perspective in social relations beyond
response, undermining capacities for social face-to-face interaction. The imagination
attunement (Lupien, McEwen, Gunnar, & orientation can build on either protectionism
Heim, 2009). The vagus nerve, critically or attunement. When imagination builds on
formed by early caregiving, is fundamen- relational attunement, as in a species-typical
tal to social approach and social closeness brain, it coordinates cortical and subcortical
(Porges, 2011), capacities necessary for systems for cooperative and compassionate
compassionate moral behavior. When basic behavior. When imagination builds on self-
neurobiological structures are poorly devel- protectionism, due to the (misdeveloped)
oped, humanity’s highest moral capacities power of survival systems that then hijack
are undermined, and self-concern emerges cortical systems, it results in an aggressive
as “normal” and morally justifiable. type (vicious) that seeks control over others
The TEM framework for understanding or a withdrawing type (detached) in which
moral development and behavior focuses abstraction capabilities are used without a
on three orientations rooted in global brain sense of relational consequence.
states identified by MacLean (1990): protec-
tionism, engagement, and imagination. When
action is taken from an orientation, trumping Dispositional or Situational?
other values and actions, it becomes an ethic.
The protectionist orientation focuses on self- In any given situation, an orientation can be-
preservation through general distrust or, come the mindset that dominates perception
more specifically, through social opposition and action. For most people, moral mindsets
or withdrawal. Protectionist orientations are shift frequently, depending on the context—
based in clinical notions of internalizing and who is present and the task at hand. Moral
externalizing and the power of social stress to mindsets can be tonic, slowly aroused, for
direct perception, thought, and action in self- example, from a physical irritation that goes
protective ways, guided by primitive survival on too long and surpasses tolerance. Or they
systems (fight–flight–freeze–faint; Sapolsky, can be phasic, suddenly appearing, such as
2004). The individual’s social homeostasis is flying off the handle when driving. Some-
thrown off, and he or she reacts cacostatical- times there is a struggle between mindsets,
ly, too strongly (aggressively) or too weakly and an oscillation between states can occur.
(withdrawing) in a one-up–one-down hier- Arpaly (2003) provides two useful examples
archical manner. Protectionism can become of how the shifting can occur. The Nazi min-
dispositional if early experience is inadequate ister of propaganda, Joseph Goebbels, who
or other trauma occurs later in life that im- organized attacks on Jews during Hitler’s re-
pairs neurobiological flexibility. gime, occasionally behaved compassionately
The engagement orientation draws on no- toward Jews he met, suggesting an engage-
tions of emotional presence, relational at- ment mindset. But afterward, because the
tunement, and unconditional positive regard Jews were members of a group he was trying
(Rogers, 1961), which rely on flexible devel- to help exterminate, he would interpret his
opmental neurobiological capacities such as kindness as weakness of the will and harden
vagal tone (Porges, 2011) and socially sup- his resolve to not lapse again, increasing his
portive systems such as the oxytocin system cruelty. In this case, Goebbels appears to
(Carter, 2003). When the evolved develop- have exhibited engagement in the presence
mental niche is provided in childhood, an of Jews and shifted into vicious imagination
engagement orientation develops naturally outside their presence. The storybook char-
 Evolution, Early Experience, and Moral Becoming 453

acter Huckleberry Finn (Twain, 2001), like to develop. Developmental systems theory
Goebbels, also interpreted as weakness of provides a useful framework for expanding
the will his reluctance to remit to the author- understanding of human heritages and how
ities his friend, Jim, a runaway slave. The they develop (Oyama, Griffiths, & Gray,
morals he had been taught included obeying 2001). Organismic adaptation involves re-
the law. But he could not bring himself to sources that are available to subsequent gen-
follow the law to turn in runaway slaves. In erations—not only genes but culture, ecol-
this case, an engagement mindset trumped ogy, microbiome, and the developmental
rule learning (detached imagination). In manifold or system in which an offspring is
these cases you can see mindsets shifting raised. The latter we call the evolved devel-
or in conflict, with explicit versus implicit opmental niche (EDN).
understanding at battle. In the case of Goe-
bbels, the context primed particular states,
The Evolved Development Niche
shifting perception and action, and so he
flipped into different mind- and action sets. Like all animals, over the course of evolu-
In the case of Huck, experience and practice tion humans developed an early-life niche
changed his perceptions and understanding. for their offspring that matches up with the
Huck’s deeper intuitions and tacit knowl- maturational schedule of the young. Hu-
edge of Jim and his humanity trumped the mans are highly immature at birth, born
explicit rules he had been taught. 9–18 months early compared with other
Moral mindsets can be primed by situa- animals (Trevathan, 2011), with the most
tion or experience. With attachment prim- intense and longest lasting niche for off-
ing, caring behavior increases (Mikulincer spring development (over 20 years). Early
& Shaver, 2005), whereas with fear prim- care evolved to be intense and to follow the
ing, self-protectionism ensues (withdrawal, EDN, which emerged more than 30 million
detached or vicious imagination), as seen years ago among social mammals and in-
in terror management theory research (e.g., tensified through human evolution (Konner,
Mikulincer & Shaver, 2001). A similar with- 2005, 2010). The EDN for young children
drawal from engaged relationship is visible includes soothing perinatal experiences,
in moral disengagement, when emotional lengthy breastfeeding, responsive caregivers,
detachment and decoupling of relational re- extensive positive and no negative touch,
sponsibility lead to lack of caring behavior extensive free play with multiage playmates
or worse (Bandura, 1999). in nature, and emotional and social support
Mindsets can also be deliberately fostered, (Konner, 2005; Narvaez, 2013).
as in the Rwanda massacre, when radio pro- Neurobiological and developmental stud-
grams denigrated the Tutsi and later encour- ies show the importance of each of the EDN
aged the massacre against them (Dallaire, components in fostering health and social
2003). Suspicion and hate can be fostered well-being (Narvaez, Panksepp, Schore &
through education as well, encouraging vi- Gleason, 2013a, 2013b; Narvaez, Valen-
ciousness toward an outgroup, as before and tino, Fuentes, McKenna & Gray, 2014). An
during the Nazi Germany era toward the individual’s neurobiology is co-constructed
Jews (Staub, 1989). On the other hand, com- by caregivers during early life, when many
passion training can foster a “broaden and brain and body systems establish their pa-
build orientation,” with decreased threat rameters and thresholds. EDN-consistent
vigilance and increased openness (Fredrick- care forms biological underpinnings that
son, 2001, 2013; Neff, 2011). follow a person the rest of his or her life,
barring therapy or other modifying experi-
ences.
Historical Context: Understanding In our laboratory, we have examined
Moral Developmental Systems whether these early experiences influence
and Human Baselines moral capacities, and they do. For example,
preschoolers whose mothers report greater
The humans we see today do not necessarily EDN-consistent care show greater empa-
embody the inherited human moral capaci- thy, self-control, and conscience (Narvaez,
ties that need species-typical experiences Wang, et al., 2013). A longitudinal sample
454 D E V E L O P M E N TA L A N D E VO L U T I O N A RY R O O T S O F M O R A L I T Y

studying touch found that over the first sic sense. Instead, it is deeply embodied in
3 years of life mothers who used corporal the early “wiring” of the brain, biosocially
punishment had children who were less constructed from embodied social experi-
self-regulated, less socially engaged, less co- ence. Darwin’s moral sense develops under
operative, and less socially competent and particular conditions, conditions that used
had more externalizing problems (Narvaez, to be universal in childhood. How do we
Wang, Cheng, Gleason, & Lefever, 2015). know? Because of converging evidence: 99%
Mothers providing more positive touch at of human history was spent in small-band
4 months had children with greater self- hunter–gatherer societies (SBHG; Lee &
regulation and verbal cognitive intelligence Daly, 1999); and in these societies, the EDN
at 36 months, even after controlling for is provided to children, with slight variation;
responsive care (Narvaez, Gleason, Wang, and members of these societies, from all re-
Brooks, Lefever, Cheng, & Centers for the ports, show the characteristics of Darwin’s
Prevention of Child Neglect, 2013). We also moral sense. SBHG become a useful baseline
find that adult retrospective reports of EDN to use for human moral development and
experience were related to adult attachment, flourishing (Narvaez, 2013).
psychopathology, moral capacities (perspec-
tive taking, empathy) and moral orientation:
Is Morality Innate or Learned?
Less EDN-consistent childhoods followed
a suboptimal pathway to protectionist eth- Some forms of morality are innate and oth-
ics through psychopathology and low per- ers are co-constructed by social experience,
spective taking or high personal distress, especially in early life when brain systems,
whereas EDN-consistent childhoods formed their parameters and thresholds, are estab-
a chain to secure attachment, low pathology, lished. Lower forms of morality (i.e., protec-
perspective taking or empathy, and an en- tionism) are rooted in more primitive brain
gagement ethic (Narvaez, Wang & Cheng, functions, the innate survival systems (e.g.,
2016). fear, anger, panic circuits), with which hu-
mans are born. These survival systems are
available from birth and can take over a
Darwin’s Moral Sense
mind when the stress response is activated. If
Is morality innate? Darwin seemed to think a child is not properly cared for as designed
so. Darwin (1981) described the moral sense by evolution with the EDN, these primitive
as a set of capacities inherited through the survival systems are more likely to dominate
tree of life (from earlier species). The ca- personality and morality.
pacities he identified include social pleasure, The higher forms of morality (i.e., engage-
memory of past behavior, empathy, concern ment and communal imagination) are not
for the opinion of others, and habit control. innate but rely on circuitries that are ini-
What we are finding out today from research tially co-constructed in early life when brain
and social developments is that these capaci- systems are highly immature and malleable.
ties are not innate but biosocially construct- These circuits require appropriate early care
ed. To develop social pleasure and empathy when systems that facilitate prosociality are
requires experience of each through em- in rapid development (e.g., vagus nerve, en-
pathic care and experiences of social enjoy- docrine systems). The EDN fosters the devel-
ment with caregivers (Emde et al., 1991; Ko- opment of higher forms of moral function,
chanska, 1994, 2002; Kochanska & Aksan, those that are other-regarding, includ-
2004, 2006; Kochanska, Aksan & Koenig, ing relational attunement and communal
1995; Kochanska & Coy, 1997; Trevarthen, imagination (Narvaez, 2014a). Thereafter,
2005). Concern for the opinion of others they are maintained by supportive environ-
and self-control also require responsive care ments, although extreme stress, such as war
in childhood (Kochanska, 2002). Memory experience, can lead to a coup by survival
systems too are influenced by the quality of systems which take over during stress in so-
childhood relationships (Grosjean & Tsai, cial relationships, as in posttraumatic stress
2007). disorder. Thus, although humans are born
Thus it appears that Darwin’s moral sense with survival systems that are conditioned
is not innate. Neither is it learned in the clas- up or down from early experience, the high-
 Evolution, Early Experience, and Moral Becoming 455

er forms of morality require appropriate virtuous person will spend most time in the
evolved care. Early experience sets the foun- relational mode, responding to the individu-
dation for these characteristics. For the vast ality of the situation, using focused attention
majority of human genus’s existence, a com- relatively rarely.
mon early childhood was provided to young It is important to understand that auto-
children. The adult personalities that emerge matic processes can be well educated, poor-
from this common experience are similar all ly educated, or uneducated and impulsive.
over the world (Ingold, 1999). Well-educated automatic moral processes
are found in the virtuous person, whose
sensibilities, perceptions, interpretations,
Is Morality Intuitive or Deliberative?
and explanations are coordinated toward
One or Two or Many Processes?
openness and prosociality. Poorly educated
Morality involves one’s manner of being in automatic processes are developed in “wick-
the moment, which, of course, involves a ed” environments, ones that “train up” the
shifting combination of intuitive and delib- wrong intuitions (Hogarth, 2001). So, for
erative processes. Implicit moral processes example, a child growing up in a violent
emerge from social experience throughout home learns intuitions to be distrustful and
life, with foundations established in early violent and generalizes these reactions even
life, when all sorts of implicit understand- to contexts that are not in themselves threat-
ings of the social world are shaped. As Jean ening. Or one can have no trained intuitions
Piaget documented thoroughly throughout about something but react according to envi-
his studies of cognitive development, implic- ronmental press or based on what comes to
it understandings and intuitions (schemas) mind (availability heuristic), what has been
develop first in a domain, guiding behavior; frequently recalled (accessibility heuristic),
with enough experience and encouragement, or a meme in the culture. With poor execu-
explicit understanding emerges and expla- tive function from early undercare, one can
nations become possible, which he thought be morally mindless and dominated by fast
were evidence of thorough understanding but dumb automatic processes, shifting from
(Piaget, 1963, 1954). Like any other cogni- reaction to reaction. Moral mindfulness,
tive development, moral understanding too however, combines explicit and implicit ca-
is initially implicitly held unless it too is en- pacities for moral agility, based on experi-
couraged to become explicit (Piaget, 1965). ence, working at appropriate levels of detail
Specific implicit schemas and deliberate or abstraction as needed.
processes are influenced by multiple factors. Deliberate moral processes include fol-
For example, one’s decisions are influenced lowing explicit decision trees, reasoning
implicitly by what is chronically accessible aloud about a case, and deliberating with
(e.g., moral identity; Narvaez, Lapsley, others about possible joint actions. How-
Hagele, & Lasky, 2006), which is influenced ever, deliberate processes are always influ-
by the places where one habitually places enced by one’s history, mood, expertise, re-
one’s attention (Murdoch, 1989). It also activity, aims, immediate prior experience,
matters which form of attention is adopted and so forth. A virtuous person is aware of
at the time: focused or relational. Focused potential biases and takes the time to sort
processing is left-hemisphere directed and through them, to check reactions with wise
narrowly attentive to decontextualized, stat- others, to reflect on their behavior, and to
ic pieces of reality (McGilchrist, 2009). An move toward openness rather than bracing
emotionally detached concentrated attention (Bourgeault, 2003).
is useful in rare moments when details are A well-constructed brain is agile, work-
needed, but it otherwise misses out on a lot ing at appropriate levels of abstraction, with
of what is really happening in the moment. control or automaticity as needed (Kout-
In contrast, relational attention, reliant on staal, 2013). In a poorly functioning brain,
right-hemisphere capacities (which are un- processing can get mired in abstractions,
derdeveloped when the EDN is missing; which can lead to depression, or in specifics,
Schore, 1994), is alert to the uniqueness of which leads to obsession. Or, a brain/mind
the moment, with a sense of living connec- that relies too much on controlled processes
tion to whatever exists in the moment. A emphasizes rigid rule following, whereas too
456 D E V E L O P M E N TA L A N D E VO L U T I O N A RY R O O T S O F M O R A L I T Y

much reliance on automatic processes can The difference likely has to do with early
lead to stereotyping. A morally virtuous ex- formation when the foundations of social-
pert is able to shift attention and processes ity are co-constructed. Human evolution
as needed for particular situations. Deep prepared a uniform early nest for children,
empathy (built from a species-typical niche) the EDN. In societies conforming with our
fuels communal imagination and action. 99%, children are provided this nest, a “cul-
tural commons” for human personality and
virtue development, resulting in adults who
Is Morality Generic or Special?
are calm, self-regulated, and content. They
Moral virtue is a set of capstone capacities show patience, generosity, kindness, social
that are founded on layers of other capaci- fitness, and openness. Cultures in the last
ties (e.g., various forms of physiological or 1% of human history have violated the nest,
psychological self-regulation). Although with concomitant alterations in moral ca-
morality includes judgment, it relies on self- pacities, moral intelligence, and moral ori-
regulation processes and well-trained emo- entations.
tion systems. It also involves perceptual
sensitivities, conceptual structures, social
sensibilities, self-regulation, and effectivi- Theoretical Stance:
ties (effective action capacities; Narvaez, Similarities and Uniqueness
2010a). Morality builds on general func- of Ethogenesis Theory
tions, including receptive intelligence. It
builds on what the individual has experi- Similar to other theories, ethogenesis looks
enced as pleasurable, how trustworthy oth- to implicit processes as the power base for
ers are perceived to be, how well emotions moral functioning. Implicit processes in-
work to guide actions (how trustworthy clude neurobiological foundations for socio-
the individual’s emotions are based on their moral intelligence built in early life when the
shaping in early life), how self-aware the in- right hemisphere is developing rapidly. But
dividual is, and how socially fit he or she is implicit processes must be well educated to
(Narvaez, 2014b). be worthwhile. Top-down processes are also
Morality is about skilled action or vir- emphasized, as moral expertise is guided
tue—applying the right capabilities in the by mindfulness, self-authorship, and delib-
right manner for the moment. Quick judg- erately-built cultural institutions (Narvaez,
ments can be closed-minded and self-protec- 2010).
tive, representative of lower forms of moral Ethogenesis theory is different from other
functioning, or be based on experience and theories in several ways, including being
expertise, representative of extensive prac- more interdisciplinary; building on evolu-
tice and know-how. For a moral virtue ex- tionary relational developmental systems
pert, the moral landscape for action is wide, theory and taking a lifespan developmen-
with full intelligence (both receptive and tal perspective; integrating neurobiological
focused) available rather than conditioned roots of emotional and cognitive develop-
self-protective responses that impair flexible ment; and understanding the importance of
response. biosociocultural co-construction of human
beingness. Ethogenesis used to be virtually
the same for all humans, but now in the last
Is Morality Culturally Uniform or Variable?
1%, culture has trumped evolutionary pro-
Evolution provided a cultural commons for cesses. Baselines for what is normal child
ethogenesis. Human moral development raising, normal personality and well-being
used to be fairly uniform; in environments in childhood and adulthood, have deterio-
representative of humanity’s 99%, SBHG rated relative to our 99% so much so that
societies, one can see the same type of per- culture supports the undermining of child
sonality and moral personality around the well-being through intentional undercare
world. Adults are gentle, generous, calm, (lack of EDN-consistent care), such as, for
and happy (Ingold, 1999; review in Nar- example, letting babies cry or forcing them
vaez, 2013). to sleep alone.
 Evolution, Early Experience, and Moral Becoming 457

Evidence • From emphasizing Western cognitive, left-


hemisphere-directed thinking to a fuller
Ethogenesis is an integrative theory drawing set of intelligences (McGilchrist, 2009)
from multiple disciplines. Evidence in sup- better represented in SBHG societies
port of moral developmental systems theory (Narvaez, 2013)
is interdisciplinary. It includes biological • Realizing that only certain cultures dam-
anthropology (e.g., McKenna & McDade, age human nature and the biosphere,
2005; McKenna, Ball, & Gettler, 2007); af- whereas others are oriented to preserving
fective neuroscience (Panksepp, 1998); clini- it (Berkes, 1999)
cal science (Schore, 1994, 2003a, 2003b); • From viewing humans as unique to un-
developmental moral science (Kochanska, derstanding their continuity in tree of life
2002); relational developmental systems (Berkes, 1999; Margulis, 1998)
theory (Overton, 2013, 2015; Overton & • Expanding virtue and morality beyond
Molenaar, 2015), and, more recently, studies humanity to include other-than-human
of moral relational developmental systems well-being (Narvaez, 2014a, 2015)
theory (Narvaez, Wang & Cheng, 2016).
Ethogenesis theory is a meta-theory that
addresses multiple levels: neurobiology, so- Extension and Expansion: Implications
cial context, and culture. Scholarship in and Future Directions
multiple domains is currently undergoing
Implications for Practice
paradigm shifts relevant to ethogenetic the-
ory: To return to our evolved moral inheritanc-
es, relational attunement (engagement),
• From an emphasis on genetics to epi- and communal imagination, adults need to
genetics in developmental psychology restore EDN—species-typical care of the
(Leckman & March, 2011) young. Instead of focusing on genes and
• From genecentrist theory to relational washing our hands of child-to-adult out-
developmental systems theory (Overton, comes, we should be focused on epigenetics,
2013) taking greater intergenerational responsibil-
• Attending to epigenetic inheritance ity for the well-being of the young and fu-
(Gluckman & Hanson, 2004, 2005) ture generations.
• Understanding our inheritances through
evolution as much more than genes
Implications for Policy
(Jablonka & Lamb, 2006; Oyama, 1985,
2000) In the United States currently, many policies
• From an emphasis on genetic competi- and institutions work against species-typical
tion to an emphasis on cooperation in care (e.g., traumatic medicalized birth, in-
every natural system (Weiss & Buchanan, fant formula feeding, sleep training for isola-
2009). tion). Instead, we should ensure that policies
• From dualism to biosocial co-construc- and practices ensure that every child receives
tion of human development (Ingold, 2013) care consistent with the EDN. This means
• From static either–or thinking to dynamic that societies need to integrate child raising
interactionisms: biology and social expe- into adult activities and recenter workplaces
rience, intuition and deliberation, culture around the needs of children.
and child rearing (Narvaez, 2014a, 2014b)
• From a focus on resilience to one on
Implications for Research
human potential (Gleason & Narvaez,
2014) We have to be careful about which base-
• Noting lasting effects of early trauma and lines we use for measuring human normal-
toxic stress at critical times (Shonkoff & ity. We should not be drawing conclusions
Phillips, 2000) about human capacities from people raised
• From thinking that Westerners reflect outside the species-typical niche. Current
human nature to studying our 99% research focuses primarily on human beings
(SBHG) for a baseline (Ingold, 1999, 2011) who typically have missed the EDN, mak-
458 D E V E L O P M E N TA L A N D E VO L U T I O N A RY R O O T S O F M O R A L I T Y

ing them more stress reactive and necessarily and virtuous action that encompasses the
self-centered. They miss developing fully the globe, the human species, along with many
receptive and perceptive intelligences appar- others, will disappear. An ethical theory
ent in SBHGs. Just like Western, educated, must address this reality.
industrialized, rich, democratic nations do
not represent humanity, neither do their
brains. They are the wrong populations for REFERENCES
drawing generalizations about human na-
Arnsten, A. F. T. (2009). Stress signaling path-
ture or human potential. ways that impair prefrontal cortex structure
and function. Nature Reviews Neuroscience,
Future Directions 10(6), 410–422.
Arpaly, N. (2003). Unprincipled virtue: An in-
It is only in the last 1% of human existence quiry into moral agency. New York: Oxford
that humans have adopted a domineering University Press.
attitude toward other-than-humans, “en- Bandura, A. (1999). Moral disengagement in the
slaving” both animals and plants (Martin, perpetration of inhumanities. Personality and
1992, 1999). Humans have become an in- Social Psychology Review, 3(3), 269–275.
vasive pioneer species, which are typically Berkes, F. (1999). Sacred ecology (2nd ed.). New
York: Routledge.
“individualistic, aggressive, and hustling” Bourgeault, C. (2003). The wisdom way of
and “attempt to exterminate or suppress knowing: Reclaiming an ancient tradition to
other species” (Naess & Rothenberg, 1989, awaken the heart. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass.
p. 182). Although invasive species learn to Carter, C. S. (2003). Developmental consequenc-
live in unfavorable circumstances, “they es of oxytocin. Physiology and Behavior,
are ultimately self-destructive” and are ulti- 79(3), 383–397.
mately “replaced by other species which are Dallaire, R. (2003). Shake hands with the devil:
better suited to restabilize and mature the The failure of humanity in Rwanda. New
ecosystem” (pp. 182–183). York: Carroll & Graf.
As a result of an invasive, domineering at- Darwin, C. (1981). The descent of man. Princ-
eton, NJ: Princeton University Press. (Original
titude, every ecosystem is under duress from work published 1871)
human activity, which continues to accel- Emde, R. N., Biringen, Z., Clyman, R., & Op-
erate (Millennium Ecosystem Assessment, penheim, D. (1991). The moral self of infancy:
2005). Half the species on the planet have Affective core and procedural knowledge. De-
disappeared since 1970. The oceans are full velopmental Review, 11, 251–270.
of plastic instead of fish. The globe is warm- Fredrickson, B. L. (2001). The role of positive
ing. To discuss morality without discussing emotions in positive psychology. American
responsibilities to other-than-humans is in- Psychologist, 56(3), 218–226.
adequate. Other-than-human entities (e.g., Fredrickson, B. L. (2013). Love 2.0: How our
plants, animals, mountains, streams) need supreme emotion affects everything we feel,
think, do, and become. London: Hudson
to be included in the circle of concern. Street Press.
In the 99%, individuals grew up in part- Gleason, T., & Narvaez, D. (2014). Child en-
nership with other-than-humans, not kill- vironments and flourishing. In D. Narvaez,
ing off predators or dictating which species K. Valentino, A. Fuentes, J., McKenna, & P.
should live or die. Again, the restoration Gray (Eds.), Ancestral landscapes in human
of the EDN, especially with childhood em- evolution: Culture, childrearing and social
bedded in outdoor natural systems, may well-being (pp. 335–348). New York: Oxford
be needed to restore receptive intelligence University Press.
capacities—the awareness and openness to Gluckman, P. D., & Hanson, M. A. (2004). Liv-
other-than-humans. As in traditional Native ing with the past: Evolution, development,
and patterns of disease. Science, 305(5691),
American/American Indian communities, 1733–1736.
the embedded EDN nurtures a sense of eco- Gluckman, P. D., & Hanson, M. (2005). Fetal
logical attachment to the well-being of the matrix: Evolution, development and disease.
local landscape, leading to sustainable life- New York: Cambridge University Press.
styles and deep ecological wisdom (Berkes, Grosjean, B., & Tsai, G. E. (2007). NMDA neu-
1999). Without greater ecological wisdom rotransmission as a critical mediator of bor-
 Evolution, Early Experience, and Moral Becoming 459

derline personality disorder. Journal of Psy- Lee, R. B., & Daly, R. (Eds.). (1999). The Cam-
chiatry and Neuroscience, 32(2), 103–115. bridge encyclopedia of hunters and gatherers.
Hogarth, R. M. (2001). Educating intuition. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Lupien, S. J., McEwen, B. S., Gunnar, M. R., &
Ingold, T. (1999). On the social relations of the Heim, C. (2009). Effects of stress throughout
hunter–gatherer band. In R. B. Lee & R. Daly the lifespan on the brain, behaviour and cog-
(Eds.), The Cambridge encyclopedia of hunt- nition, Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 10(6),
ers and gatherers (pp. 399–410). New York: 434–445.
Cambridge University Press. MacLean, P. D. (1990). The triune brain in evo-
Ingold, T. (2011). The perception of the environ- lution: Role in paleocerebral functions. New
ment: Essay on livelihood, dwelling and skill. York: Plenum Press.
London: Routledge. Margulis, L. (1998). Symbiotic planet: A new look
Ingold, T. (2013) Prospect. In T. Ingold & G. Pal- at evolution. Amherst, MA: Sciencewriters.
sson (Eds.), Biosocial becomings: Integrating Martin, C. L. (1992). In the spirit. Baltimore:
social and biological anthropology (pp. 1–21). Johns Hopkins University Press.
Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Martin, C. L. (1999). The way of the human
Jablonka, E., & Lamb, M. J. (2006). The evolu- being. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
tion of information in the major transitions. McGilchrist, I. (2009). The master and his emis-
Journal of Theoretical Biology, 239(2), 236– sary: The divided brain and the making of the
246. Western world. New Haven, CT: Yale Univer-
Kochanska, G. (1994). Beyond cognition: Ex- sity Press.
panding the search for the early roots of in- McKenna, J., Ball, H., & Gettler, L. (2007).
ternalization and conscience. Developmental Mother–infant cosleeping, breastfeeding and
Psychology, 30(1), 20–22. sudden infant death syndrome: What biologi-
Kochanska, G. (2002). Mutually responsive ori- cal anthropology has discovered about nor-
entation between mothers and their young mal infant sleep and pediatric sleep medicine.
children: A context for the early development Yearbook of Physiological Anthropology, 50,
of conscience. Current Directions in Psycho- 133–161.
logical Science, 11(6), 191–195. McKenna, J., & McDade, T. (2005). Why babies
Kochanska, G., & Aksan, N. (2004). Conscience should never sleep alone: A review of the co-
in childhood: Past, present, and future. Mer- sleeping controversy in relation to SIDS, bed-
rill–Palmer Quarterly: Journal of Develop- sharing and breast feeding. Paediatric Respi-
mental Psychology, 50(3), 299–310. ratory Reviews, 6(2), 134–152.
Kochanska, G., & Aksan, N. (2006). Children’s Mikulincer, M., & Shaver, P. R. (2001). Attach-
conscience and self-regulation. Journal of Per- ment theory and intergroup bias: Evidence
sonality, 74(6), 1587–1617. that priming the secure base schema attenu-
Kochanska, G., Aksan, N., & Koenig, A. L. ates negative reactions to out-groups. Jour-
(1995). A longitudinal study of the roots of nal of Personality and Social Psychology, 81,
preschoolers’ conscience: Committed compli- 97–115.
ance and emerging internalization. Child De- Mikulincer, M., & Shaver, P. R. (2005). At-
velopment, 66, 1752–1769. tachment security, compassion, and altruism.
Kochanska, G., & Coy, K. C. (1997). Inhibitory Current Directions in Psychological Science,
control as a contributor to conscience in child- 14(1), 34–38.
hood: From toddler to early school age. Child Millennium Ecosystem Assessment. (2005). Eco-
Development, 68, 263–277. systems and human well-being: Synthesis.
Konner, M. (2005). Hunter–gatherer infancy Washington, DC: Island Press.
and childhood: The !Kung and others. In B. Murdoch, I. (1989). The sovereignty of good.
Hewlett & M. Lamb (Eds.), Hunter–gatherer London: Routledge. (Original work published
childhoods: Evolutionary, developmental and 1970)
cultural perspectives (pp. 19–64). New Bruns- Naess, A., & Rothenberg, D. (1989). Ecology,
wick, NJ: Transaction. community and lifestyle. Cambridge, UK:
Konner, M. (2010). The evolution of childhood. Cambridge University Press.
Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press. Narvaez, D. (2008). Triune ethics: The neurobio-
Koutstaal, W. (2013). The agile mind. New York: logical roots of our multiple moralities. New
Oxford University Press. Ideas in Psychology, 26, 95–119.
Leckman, J. F., & March, J. S. (2011). Editorial: Narvaez, D. (2010a). Moral complexity: The
Developmental neuroscience comes of age. fatal attraction of truthiness and the impor-
Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, tance of mature moral functioning. Perspec-
52, 333–338. tives on Psychological Science, 5(2), 163–181.
460 D E V E L O P M E N TA L A N D E VO L U T I O N A RY R O O T S O F M O R A L I T Y

Narvaez, D. (2010b). The embodied dynamism Narvaez, D., Wang, L., Cheng, A., Gleason,
of moral becoming. Perspectives on Psycho- T., Woodbury, R., Kurth, A., & Lefever, J.
logical Science, 5(2), 185–186. B. (2017, April). The importance of early life
Narvaez, D. (2013). The 99 percent—Develop- touch for psychosocial and moral develop-
ment and socialization within an evolutionary ment. Symposium on Empathy, Prosociality
context: Growing up to become “A good and and Morality: Neurobiological and Relational
useful human being.” In D. Fry (Ed.), War, Contributions to Development, Society for
peace and human nature: The convergence Research in Child Development, Philadelphia,
of evolutionary and cultural views (pp. 643– PA.
672). New York: Oxford University Press. Narvaez, D., Wang, L., Gleason, T., Cheng, A.,
Narvaez, D. (2014a). Neurobiology and the de- Lefever, J., & Deng, L. (2013). The evolved de-
velopment of human morality: Evolution, cul- velopmental niche and sociomoral outcomes in
ture and wisdom. New York: Norton. Chinese three-year-olds. European Journal of
Narvaez, D. (2014b). The co-construction of Developmental Psychology, 10(2), 106–127.
virtue: Epigenetics, neurobiology and develop- Narvaez, D., Valentino, K., Fuentes, A., McK-
ment. In N. E. Snow (Ed.), Cultivating virtue enna, J., & Gray, P. (Eds.). (2014). Ancestral
(pp. 251–277). New York: Oxford University landscapes in human evolution: Culture, chil-
Press. drearing and social wellbeing. New York: Ox-
Narvaez, D. (2015). Understanding flourishing: ford University Press.
Evolutionary baselines and morality. Journal Neff, K. (2011). Self-compassion: Stop beating
of Moral Education, 44(3), 253–262. yourself up and leave insecurity behind. New
Narvaez, D. (2016). Embodied morality: Protec- York: Morrow.
tionism, engagement and imagination. New Overton, W. F. (2013). A new paradigm for de-
York: Palgrave-Macmillan. velopmental science: Relationism and relation-
Narvaez, D., & Gleason, T. (2013). Developmen- al-developmental systems. Applied Develop-
tal optimization. In D. Narvaez, J. Panksepp, mental Science, 17(2), 94–107.
A. Schore, & T. Gleason (Eds.), Evolution, Overton, W. F. (2015). Process and relational-de-
early experience and human development: velopmental systems. In R. M. Lerner (Series
From research to practice and policy (pp. 307– Ed.) & W. F. Overton & P. C. M. Molenaar
325). New York: Oxford University Press. (Vol. Eds.), Handbook of child psychology
Narvaez, D., Gleason, T., Wang, L., Brooks, J., and developmental science: Vol. 1. Theory
Lefever, J., Cheng, A., & Centers for the Pre- and method (7th ed., pp. 9–62). Hoboken, NJ:
vention of Child Neglect. (2013). The evolved Wiley.
development niche: Longitudinal effects of Overton, W. F., & Molenaar, P. C. (2015). Con-
caregiving practices on early childhood psy- cepts, theory, and method in developmental
chosocial development. Early Childhood Re- science: A view of the issues. In R. M. Lerner
search Quarterly, 28(4), 759–773. (Series Ed.) & W. F. Overton & P. C. M. Mo-
Narvaez, D., Lapsley, D. K., Hagele, S., & Lasky, lenaar (Vol. Eds.), Handbook of child psy-
B. (2006). Moral chronicity and social infor- chology and developmental science: Vol. 1.
mation processing: Tests of a social cognitive Theory and method (7th ed., pp. 2–8). New
approach to the moral personality. Journal of York: Wiley.
Research in Personality, 40, 966–985. Oyama, S. (1985). The ontogeny of information:
Narvaez, D., Panksepp, J., Schore, A., & Glea- Developmental systems and evolution. New
son, T. (Eds.). (2013a). Evolution, early ex- York: Cambridge University Press.
perience and human development: From Oyama, S. (2000). Evolution’s eye: A systems
research to practice and policy. New York: view of the biology–culture divide. Durham,
Oxford University Press. NC: Duke University Press.
Narvaez, D., Panksepp, J., Schore, A., & Glea- Oyama, S., Griffiths, P. E., & Gray, R. D. (2001).
son, T. (2013b). The value of using an evo- Cycles of contingency: Developmental sys-
lutionary framework for gauging children’s tems and evolution. Cambridge, MA: MIT
well-being. In D. Narvaez, J. Panksepp, A. Press.
Schore, & T. Gleason (Eds.), Evolution, early Panksepp, J. (1998). Affective neuroscience: The
experience and human development: From re- foundations of human and animal emotions.
search to practice and policy (pp. 3–30). New New York: Oxford University Press.
York: Oxford University Press. Piaget, J. (1954). The construction of reality in
Narvaez, D., Wang, L., & Cheng, A. (2016). the child. New York: Basic Books.
Evolved developmental niche history: Relation Piaget, J. (1963). The origins of intelligence in
to adult psychopathology and morality. Ap- children. New York: Norton. (Original work
plied Developmental Science, 20, 294–309. published 1936)
 Evolution, Early Experience, and Moral Becoming 461

Piaget, J. (1965). The moral judgment of the Schore, A. N. (2013). Bowlby’s “environment of
child (M. Gabain, Trans.). New York: Free evolutionary adaptedness”: Recent studies on
Press. (Original work published 1932) the interpersonal neurobiology of attachment
Porges, S. W. (2011). The polyvagal theory: Neu- and emotional development. In D. Narvaez, J.
rophysiologial foundations of emotions, at- Panksepp, A. N. Shore, & T. Gleason (Eds.),
tachment, communication, self-regulation. Human nature, early experience and human
New York: Norton. development (pp. 31–67). Oxford, UK: Ox-
Rogers, C. (1961). On becoming a person: A ford University Press.
therapist’s view of psychotherapy. London: Shonkoff, J. P., Garner, A. S., Siegel, B. S., Dob-
Constable. bins, M. I., Earls, M. F., McGuinn, L., . . .
Sapolsky, R. (2004). Why zebras don’t get ulcers Wood, D. L. (2012). The lifelong effects of
(3rd ed.). New York: Holt. early childhood adversity and toxic stress. Pe-
Schore, A. (1994). Affect regulation. Hillsdale, diatrics, 129(1), 232–246.
NJ: Erlbaum. Shonkoff, J. P., & Phillips, D. A. (2000). From
Schore, A. (1996). The experience-dependent neurons to neighborhoods: The science of
maturation of a regulatory system in the or- early childhood development. Washington,
bital prefrontal cortex and the origin of devel- DC: National Academies Press.
opment psychopathology. Development and Staub, E. (1989). The roots of evil: The origins
Psychopathology, 8, 59–87. of genocide and other group violence. Cam-
Schore, A. N. (1997). Early organization of bridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
the nonlinear right brain and development Trevarthen, C. (2005). Stepping away from the
of a predisposition to psychiatric disorders. mirror: Pride and shame in adventures of com-
­Development and Psychopathology, 9, 595– panionship: Reflections on the nature and
631. emotional needs of infant intersubjectivity.
Schore, A. N. (2000). Attachment and the reg- In C. S. Carter, L. Ahnert, K. E. Grossmann,
ulation of the right brain. Attachment and S. B. Hrdy, M. E. Lamb, S. W. Porges, & N.
Human Development, 2, 23–47. Sachser (Eds.), Attachment and bonding: A
Schore, A. N. (2001). The effects of early rela- new synthesis (pp. 55–84). Cambridge, MA:
tional trauma on right brain development, MIT Press.
affect regulation, and infant mental health. Trevathan, W. R. (2011). Human birth: An evo-
Infant Mental Health Journal, 22, 201–269. lutionary perspective (2nd ed.). New York: Al-
Schore, A. N. (2003a). Affect regulation and the dine de Gruyter.
origin of the self. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Twain, M. (2001). The adventures of Huckle-
Schore, A. N. (2003b). Affect regulation and the berry Finn. New York: Collector’s Library.
repair of the self. New York: Norton. (Original work published 1884)
Schore, A. N. (2005). Attachment, affect regula- Weiss, K. M., & Buchanan, A. V. (2009). The
tion, and the developing right brain: Linking mermaid’s tale: Four billion years of coop-
developmental neuroscience to pediatrics. Pe- eration in the making of living things. Cam-
diatrics in Review, 26, 204–211. bridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
PART X
MORAL BEHAVIOR

Q U E S T I O N S A N S W E R E D I N PA R T X

CHAPTER 47  Is unethical behavior always selfish, and is selfish behavior


always unethical?

CHAPTER 48  To what extent is our unethical behavior a product


of dispositional or situational forces?

CHAPTER 49  Is moral behavior conflicted or unconflicted


for a virtuous agent?

CHAPTER 50  How do people come to possess different levels


of moral clarity, which denotes the degree of ambiguity people perceive
when judging whether behaviors are right or wrong?
CHAPTER 47

On the Distinction between Unethical
and Selfish Behavior

Jackson G. Lu
Ting Zhang
Derek D. Rucker
Adam D. Galinsky

Is unethical behavior always selfish, and is selfish behavior always


unethical?

We conceptually distinguish between unethicality and selfishness by


analyzing the four distinct categories of behavior that these two con‑
structs combine to produce: selfish/unethical, selfish/ethical, unself‑
ish/ethical, and unselfish/unethical behavior.

Does unethical behavior always represent Swartz downloaded 4.8 million articles from
selfish behavior? Consider the seminal di- the journal database JSTOR and made them
lemma that serves as the foundation for publicly available. Although his action clear-
modern moral psychology: The wife of a ly violated computer and copyright laws, his
man named Heinz was near death and des- alleged intention was “to place the material
perate for a medicine that he could not afford on the Internet so that it could be freely dis-
(Kohlberg, 1963). To save her life, Heinz tributed around the entire globe” (Abelson,
broke into a drugstore to steal the medicine. Diamond, Grosso, & Pfeiffer, 2013, p. 31).
Kohlberg asked his subjects, “Should Heinz Oftentimes, to act unethically is to act
have stolen for his dying wife? Why or why selfishly. Indeed, the bulk of ancient Greek
not?” Whereas Kohlberg was interested in philosophy and modern moral psychology
how people reasoned through this moral di- has studied how individuals resolve moral
lemma, we were instead struck by the fact dilemmas in which “doing the right thing”
that Heinz stole not to help himself, but to and acting in one’s self-interest are in con-
assist another person. Heinz might have flict (Bazerman & Gino, 2012). In fact,
acted unethically, but did he act selfishly? Plato (trans. 1997) himself believed that self-
Or consider the contemporary case of interest lies at the root of all unethical be-
Aaron Swartz. As a computer programmer, haviors: “the cause of each and every crime

465
466 M O R A L B E H AV I O R

we commit is precisely this excessive love of need not arise out of selfishness. As we saw
ourselves . . . ” (p. 1414). in the examples of Heinz and Swartz, uneth-
Because unethical behaviors often coin- ical behaviors can originate from the desire
cide with selfish intentions, most empiri- to help others. In a similar vein, selfishness
cal studies focus on the antecedents and can promote ethical behaviors, particularly
consequences of unethical behaviors that in contexts in which others’ interests are
benefit the perpetrators at the expense of aligned with one’s own.
other individuals, groups, and organizations In the following sections, we decouple un-
(e.g., Cohn, Fehr, & Maréchal, 2014; Gino, ethical and selfish behaviors by illustrating
Ayal, & Ariely, 2009; Lu, Brockner, Vardi, how unethical behaviors can be either self-
& Weitz, 2017; Lu, Lee, Gino, & Galinsky, ish or unselfish and how selfish behaviors
in press; Lu et al., 2017). To examine how can be either ethical or unethical. For each
frequently unethical behavior overlaps with category of behavior, we offer real-world ex-
selfish behavior in empirical studies, we con- amples that distinguish between these two
ducted a bibliometric analysis of morality- constructs (see Table 47.1 for an overview).
related articles published in elite psychology Thereafter, we discuss cases in which differ-
and management journals between 2000 entiating unethicality from selfishness offers
and 2015. We found that 83% of the articles a more comprehensive understanding of the
(72 articles out of a total of 87 published) antecedents of unethical behavior. Finally,
studied selfish unethical behavior without we close the chapter by proposing future
any consideration of unselfish unethical directions in the study of unethicality and
behavior.1 In other words, the majority of selfishness.
studies in behavioral ethics appear to have
confounded unethical behavior with selfish
behavior. Selfish and Unethical Behavior
Despite their frequent co-occurrence,
unethical behavior and selfish behavior Numerous studies have found that individu-
are conceptually orthogonal. In the social als resort to unethical behaviors out of self-
sciences, unethical behavior is commonly interest. Researchers studying selfish unethi-
defined as behavior that is “illegal or mor- cal behaviors have examined conditions that
ally unacceptable to the large community” trigger individuals to cheat, lie, and steal for
(Jones, 1991, p. 367). By contrast, selfish be- themselves. For instance, competitive envi-
havior is defined as behavior that prioritizes ronments often promote a “whatever it takes
one’s own interests and benefits over those to win” mindset (Hegarty & Sims, 1978;
of others. Critically, these definitions reveal Kilduff, Galinsky, Gallo, & Reade, 2016),
that, on the one hand, selfish intentions are thereby increasing selfish behaviors that are
not a prerequisite for unethical behaviors unethical. In firms, employees who compete
and, on the other hand, unethical behaviors for status are more likely to fabricate their

TABLE 47.1.  Distinguishing between Ethical/Unethical and Selfish/Unselfish Behaviors


Behavior
Motive Ethical Unethical
Selfish Definition: Behaviors driven by self- Definition: Behaviors driven by self-
beneficial motives that do not violate legal beneficial motives that violate legal laws or
laws or moral codes of conduct. moral codes of conduct.
Example: Charitable donations to receive tax Example: Cheating on an exam
deductions

Unselfish Definition: Behaviors driven by other- Definition: Behaviors driven by other-


beneficial motives that do not violate legal beneficial motives that violate legal laws or
laws or moral codes of conduct. moral codes of conduct.
Example: Community service Example: Stealing to help the poor
 Unethical and Selfish Behavior 467

performance and sabotage competitors’ than others for the same unethical behavior
work (Charness, Masclet, & Villeval, 2014). (Valdesolo & DeSteno, 2007, 2008).
In sports, players adopt unsportsmanlike
behaviors in order to get ahead of their ri-
vals (Kilduff et al., 2016). In academia, to Selfish and Ethical Behavior
compete with their peers, scholars inflate
their papers’ download counts from leading Although self-interest often breeds unethical
working paper repositories such as the So- behaviors, it can also foster ethical behav-
cial Science Research Network (SSRN; Edel- iors, particularly in situations in which self-
man & Larkin, 2015). interest is aligned with the interest of others.
Similarly, goals can “go wild” (Ordóñez, In what follows, we highlight how self-inter-
Schweitzer, Galinsky, & Bazerman, 2009): est can lead individuals to avoid temptations
By narrowing individuals’ focus on the to cheat, to rectify others’ unethical acts,
outcome, goals may motivate them to take and to engage in prosocial behaviors.
selfish actions, including unethical ones In society, the presence of legal punish-
(Schweitzer, Ordóñez, & Douma, 2004). ment speaks directly to how self-interest dis-
Barsky (2008) formulated two psychologi- courages unethical behaviors. Selfishly, peo-
cal mechanisms through which goal set- ple often refrain from behaving unethically
ting can facilitate unethical behavior: moral when the risk and cost of being caught are
disengagement and lack of ethical recogni- high (Brass, Butterfield, & Skaggs, 1998).
tion. When individuals are highly focused Even in the absence of formal punishment,
on their goals, they may disengage their individuals are still driven to protect their
internal moral controls to rationalize their moral identity as a “good person” (Bryan,
unethical behaviors (i.e., moral disengage- Adams, & Monin, 2013). As a result, they
ment) or even fail to recognize the unethi- often adopt behaviors that serve to present
cality of such behaviors (i.e., lack of ethical themselves as “moral” in their own eyes
recognition; Barsky, 2008). In workplace and the eyes of others (Frimer, Schaefer,
settings, the use of production or sales goals & Oakes, 2014). For example, individuals
can encourage employees to cheat and lie were less likely to cheat when told “don’t be
(Jensen, 2003). For example, Sears’s goal- a cheater” than when told “don’t cheat,” be-
oriented commission system has been iden- cause being labeled a cheater is threatening
tified as the culprit for its employees’ sys- to one’s self-image (Bryan et al., 2013).
tematic defrauding of customers (Paine & Self-interest can also guide individuals
Santoro, 1993). Moreover, individuals are to take action against others’ unethical be-
likely to resort to unethical means when haviors. For instance, whistle-blowing, de-
they are about to fall short of their goals fined as the disclosure of “illegal, immoral
(Schweitzer et al., 2004). For example, au- or illegitimate practices . . . to persons or
thors are particularly apt to inflate their pa- organizations who may be able to effect ac-
pers’ download counts in order to prevent tion” (Near & Miceli, 1985, p. 4), is often
their papers from falling off the “top-10” motivated by self-interest. In reporting on a
list of the SSRN (Edelman & Larkin, 2015). cheater in an academic competition, a stu-
The influence of selfish motives on un- dent not only upholds the academic honor
ethicality also extends to the dimension of code but also gains an edge over the compe-
moral judgment. Instead of adhering to a tition by eliminating a contender. Similarly,
stable set of moral codes, individuals apply when whistle-blowers reveal fraudulent be-
their beliefs and judgments strategically to havior, they may be entitled to a percentage
maximize their personal outcomes (DeScio- of the financial recovery. For example, “the
li, Massenkoff, Shaw, Petersen, & Kurzban, IRS Whistleblower Office pays money to
2014). For example, people judge the unethi- people who blow the whistle on persons who
cal behavior of others more leniently when fail to pay the tax that they owe” (U.S. De-
that behavior serves their own interests (Bo- partment of the Treasury, Internal Revenue
cian & Wojciszke, 2014). Likewise, self-in- Service, 2017). Socially, the larger commu-
terest motivates “moral hypocrisy,” where- nity may even hail whistle-blowers as heroes
by people evaluate themselves less harshly (Johnson, 2003).
468 M O R A L B E H AV I O R

Selfish motives can also foster prosocial 2005). People help others (e.g., anonymous
behaviors, or voluntary, intentional behav- donations, community service) even when
iors that result in benefits for others (Eisen- there is no clear or direct benefit to them-
berg & Miller, 1987). In the United States, selves other than the “warm glow” of giving
many individuals donate to charitable or- (Harbaugh, Mayr, & Burghart, 2007; Pilia-
ganizations, both to receive tax deductions vin, 2003).
(Feldstein, 1975) and to publicly signal their Individuals also engage in risky and self-
wealth, status, or moral character (Ari- sacrificing behaviors in order to benefit oth-
ely, Bracha, & Meier, 2009; Rege & Telle, ers. Raising sensitive issues within an orga-
2004). Similarly, parents make substantial nization (e.g., telling a manager that his new
donations to universities to increase their policy is unpopular among employees) has
children’s chances of admission (Golden, the potential to benefit others (e.g., the man-
2003). In China, many citizens donate “just ager enacts favorable changes) but may also
enough” blood (i.e., 800 milliliters) to qual- pose risks for the actor (e.g., dismissal from
ify as recipients in future blood transfusions job; Burris, Detert, & Romney, 2013).
(Shi et al., 2014). Likewise, in countries such Two other areas that highlight the role of
as Israel and Singapore, individuals register unselfish ethical behavior are whistle-blow-
as organ donors so that they are prioritized ing and altruistic punishment. Although
if they should be in need of organs in the whistle-blowing can be motivated by selfish
future (Lavee, Ashkenazi, Gurman, & Stein- reasons (as highlighted earlier), it can also
berg, 2010). be driven by moral principles. For example,
Prominent philosophers and economists Waytz, Dungan, and Young (2013) provide
have argued that selfishness and ethicality evidence that whistle-blowing is especially
are closely linked. Adam Smith, the found- likely to occur when people are focused
ing father of economics, famously wrote, “it on justice and fairness. Sometimes whistle-
is not from the benevolence of the butcher, blowers are not only unselfish but also vul-
the brewer, or the baker, that we expect our nerable to both psychological distress (e.g.,
dinner, but from their regard to their own anxiety, nightmares, flashbacks; Peters et
self-interest” (Smith, 1937, p. 16). In essence, al., 2011) and social backlash from members
the study of free-market economics—which of their own community (Dyck, Morse, &
Smith viewed as a branch of moral philoso- Zingales, 2010).
phy (Griswold, 1999)—rests on the premise Altruistic punishment, in which “indi-
that human beings are self-interested (Smith, viduals punish, although the punishment is
1937) and that, when each individual seeks costly for them and yields no material gain”
to maximize his or her own utility, the col- (Fehr & Gächter, 2002, p. 137), is another
lective will prosper. Milton Friedman, a case of unselfish ethical behavior. People
Nobel Prize laureate in economics, called often go out of their way (incurring effort
this Invisible Hand (of selfishness) “the pos- and time cost) to punish perpetrators (e.g.,
sibility of cooperation without coercion” individuals who cut into lines or who sneak
(Friedman, 1999). into music festivals) because “it is the right
thing to do.” Altruistic punishment facili-
tates cooperation in groups, organizations,
Unselfish and Ethical Behavior and societies; without it, cooperation would
often break down (Fehr & Gächter, 2002).
Just as selfishness can foster both unethical
and ethical behaviors, unselfishness—the
willingness to put the needs of others before Unselfish and Unethical Behavior
one’s own—can also lead to both ethical
and unethical behaviors. Although unselfishness can lead to ethical
Much research has explored conditions behaviors, it can also result in unethical
under which altruistic intentions produce behaviors. Unselfish yet unethical behav-
ethical outcomes (Batson & Shaw, 1991; iors typically arise when there is a conflict
Penner, Dovidio, Piliavin, & Schroeder, between two competing moral principles
 Unethical and Selfish Behavior 469

(Levine & Schweitzer, 2014). For example, behaviors—can also lead individuals to
many moral dilemmas that lead individuals violate moral rules by according “favored”
toward unselfish and unethical actions often status and preferential treatment to the tar-
feature a contention between two founda- get of empathy (Batson, Klein, Highberger,
tional pillars of moral psychology: justice & Shaw, 1995). Individuals induced to feel
and care (Levine & Schweitzer, 2014, 2015). empathy for a particular individual are more
Whereas justice reflects deontological moral likely to violate the principle of justice by al-
imperatives (e.g., thou shalt not lie; Kant, locating resources preferentially to that per-
1959), care prioritizes the utilitarian con- son (Batson, Klein, et al., 1995), even at the
sideration of helping and protecting others cost of reducing the collective good (Batson,
(Bentham, 1948; Walker & Hennig, 2004). Batson, et al., 1995).
Heinz’s dilemma (Kohlberg, 1963) epitomiz-
es this moral tension: Stealing would breach
the law of justice, whereas watching one’s Antecedents of Selfish versus Unselfish
wife die without intervening would violate Unethical Behavior
the principle of caring for others.
When individuals are faced with this ten- As illustrated in the previous sections, draw-
sion in moral judgment, care can supersede ing a distinction between unethical behavior
justice and lead individuals to take unselfish and selfish behavior is critical to the study
yet unethical actions. Many of us engage in of moral psychology. Given that both ethical
altruistic lying, defined as “false statements and unethical behaviors can result from both
that are costly for the liar and are made with selfish and unselfish intentions, merely focus-
the intention of misleading and benefitting a ing on situations in which unethicality and
target’’ (Levine & Schweitzer, 2014, p. 108). selfishness co-occur creates an incomplete
Since early childhood, we are taught that it is and inaccurate representation of the drivers
polite to tell prosocial lies (Broomfield, Rob- of unethical behavior. We next discuss three
inson, & Robinson, 2002; Talwar, Murphy, specific cases (social class, organizational
& Lee, 2007), particularly when these lies identification, and loyalty) that demonstrate
provide others with interpersonal support the need to parse unethical behaviors driven
(Brown & Levinson, 1987) and psychologi- by selfish versus unselfish motives.
cal protection (DePaulo & Kashy, 1998). For
example, parents may lie about their divorce
Social Class
to protect their child. Similarly, with no ap-
parent self-serving motive, doctors may lie Prior research has found a positive rela-
to patients about bleak prognoses to provide tionship between social class and unethi-
them hope and comfort (Iezzoni, Rao, Des- cal behavior (Piff, Stancato, Côté, Mendo-
Roches, Vogeli, & Campbell, 2012). za-Denton, & Keltner, 2012). Upper-class
Like Aaron Swartz, some individuals are individuals have more favorable attitudes
willing to engage in unethical behaviors toward greed, which partially account for
that have the potential to benefit a larger their higher tendency to engage in unethical
community—even at the cost of sacrificing behaviors such as lying and cheating (Piff et
themselves. Members of WikiLeaks, for ex- al., 2012). However, a closer examination
ample, exposed classified information to the of this effect reveals that the identity of the
public—an illegal activity that antagonized beneficiary of an unethical behavior is a crit-
the U.S government—in order to serve its ical moderator of the relationship between
altruistic mission of “defense of freedom of social class and unethical behavior (Dubois,
speech and media publishing” and ultimate- Rucker, & Galinsky, 2015). Upper-class in-
ly “to create a better society for all people” dividuals, relative to lower-class individuals,
(https://wikileaks.org/About.html, 2011). 2 are more prone to commit unethical acts
Finally, motives that are linked to altru- that benefit themselves; in contrast, lower-
ism can produce behaviors that violate moral class individuals, relative to upper-class indi-
rules. For example, empathy—a psychologi- viduals, are more prone to commit unethical
cal process that generally leads to prosocial acts that benefit others. In explaining these
470 M O R A L B E H AV I O R

findings, Dubois and colleagues (2015) con- Future Directions


tend that higher social class tends to foster
an agentic, self-serving orientation, whereas In light of the distinction between unethical-
lower social class tends to nurture a com- ity and selfishness, we re-­examine some of
munal, altruistic orientation. As a result, the previously documented antecedents of
although both upper- and lower-class indi- unethical behavior, and offer several nuanced
viduals can behave unethically, upper-class predictions that could be tested in the future.
individuals are more likely to do so for their
own sake, whereas lower-class individuals
Money versus Time
are more likely to do so for others’ sake.
These findings demonstrate that disentan- Empirical studies have found that activat-
gling selfishness and unethicality serves to ing the concept of money increases unethical
provide a more complete understanding of intentions and behaviors (Cohn et al., 2014;
the antecedents of unethical behavior. Gino & Mogilner, 2014; Kouchaki, Smith-
Crowe, Brief, & Sousa, 2013), whereas shift-
ing the focus onto time may offset these ef-
Organizational Identification
fects (Gino & Mogilner, 2014). However, in
The distinction between unethicality and these experiments the beneficiary of the un-
selfishness also helps unpack the relation- ethical behavior was always the participant
ship between organizational identification him- or herself. If the unethical behavior
and ethicality. Organizational identification were instead to benefit others rather than the
refers to an individual’s feeling of “oneness” agent of the behavior, we might see a reversal
with his or her organization (Ashforth & of the “money versus time effect.” That is, al-
Mael, 1989). Individuals’ organizational though money might increase selfish unethi-
identification significantly affects the ex- cal behavior, money may actually decrease
tent to which they engage in selfish versus unselfish unethical behavior. Consistent with
unselfish unethical behaviors (Vadera & this proposition, across nine studies Vohs,
Pratt, 2013). Individuals who strongly iden- Mead, and Goode (2006) found that money
tify with their organizations are more apt to produces a self-sufficient orientation. Hence,
behave unethically to benefit their organi- activating the concept of money might lower
zations at a cost to themselves (Umphress, an individual’s willingness to behave unethi-
Bingham, & Mitchell, 2010). To take an cally to benefit others. Conversely, although
extreme example, tragic stories of terror- activating time can curb selfish unethical
ism reveal that suicide bombers are often behavior (Gino & Mogilner, 2014), it may
overidentified members emboldened to “do actually increase unselfish unethical behav-
justice” on behalf of their groups (Sageman, ior by making people more other-focused. In
2004). Similarly, although less violently, a support of this possibility, Mogilner (2010)
strong organizational identification can lead found that priming time motivates individu-
employees to turn a blind eye to illegal ac- als to invest more effort in social relation-
tivities in order to serve the interests of their ships (i.e., friends and family) and less time
organization (Dukerich et al., 1998). in their own instrumental work.
In contrast, individuals who do not iden-
tify with their organizations are more likely
Social Learning Strategy
to engage in selfish unethical acts. They tend
to ignore organizational rules and feel free Prior research shows that individuals differ
to act selfishly (e.g., arriving late to work systematically in their social learning strate-
and leaving early; Vadera & Pratt, 2013). In gies (van den Berg, Molleman, & Weissing,
more extreme cases, individuals who have 2015): Whereas some individuals attempt
disengaged from their organization may to imitate the most successful members of
even purposefully harm their organization the group, others attend to the most norma-
to serve their self-interest, such as stealing tive members. Importantly, success-oriented
office supplies and fabricating receipts for learners both cooperate less and behave
reimbursement (Vadera & Pratt, 2013). more selfishly as compared with norm-ori-
 Unethical and Selfish Behavior 471

ented learners (van den Berg et al., 2015). ogy and set a promising research agenda for
These findings suggest that success-oriented the future.
individuals may be prone to engage in selfish
unethical behavior, whereas norm-oriented
individuals may be prone to engage in un- NOTES
selfish unethical behavior. This possibility
1. Results are based on a bibliometric analysis
awaits further research.
of articles published between 2000 and 2015
in Academy of Management Journal, Admin-
Individualism versus Collectivism istrative Science Quarterly, Journal of Ap-
plied Psychology, Journal of Personality and
Culture may also influence whether unethi- Social Psychology, Organizational Behavior
cal behaviors are selfish or unselfish. For ex- and Human Decision Processes, and Psycho-
ample, cultural values appear to serve as one logical Science that contain one or more of
predictor of bribery. Based on cross-national the following terms as keywords: ethics, ethic,
and laboratory data, Mazar and Aggarwal ethical, unethical, ethically, moral, morality,
(2011) argued that collectivist cultures are morals, immoral, amoral, dishonest, honest,
deception, dishonesty, honesty, dishonestly,
the breeding ground for bribery. In light
honestly, misconduct, wrongdoing. Details of
of the distinction between unethicality and procedure and analyses can be requested from
selfishness, we predict a more nuanced rela- the authors.
tionship between individualism–collectivism 2. We describe the behaviors of WikiLeaks and
and the type of unethical behavior enacted: Aaron Swartz as prosocial based on the as-
Individualistic cultures may be more con- sumption that they intended to serve the larg-
ducive to selfish unethical behaviors (e.g., er community. However, it remains possible
bribing for one’s personal gain), whereas that they were motivated by selfish motives
collectivistic culture may be more conducive of fame and notoriety. As with whistle-blow-
to unselfish unethical behaviors (e.g., brib- ing, the key factor for ultimately determining
whether a behavior is selfish or altruistic is the
ing for one’s organization, as in Mazar &
intention underlying the behavior.
Aggarwal, 2011). The logic for this predic-
tion is consistent with the established no-
tion that individualistic cultures foster more REFERENCES
self-focused behaviors, whereas collectivistic
cultures nurture more other-focused behav- Abelson, H., Diamond, P. A., Grosso, A., & Pfei-
iors (Markus & Kitayama, 1991). Future ffer, D. W. (2013). MIT and the prosecution of
research could investigate how cultural ori- Aaron Swartz. Retrieved from http://swartz-
entations affect unethical behavior enacted report.mit.edu/docs/report-to-the-president.
for oneself versus others. pdf.
Ariely, D., Bracha, A., & Meier, S. (2009). Doing
good or doing well?: Image motivation and
monetary incentives in behaving prosocially.
Conclusion American Economic Review, 99(1), 544–555.
Ashforth, B. E., & Mael, F. (1989). Social iden-
At first glance, unethical behavior and self- tity theory and the organization. Academy of
ish intention are logical companions. Indeed, Management Review, 14(1), 20–39.
unethical behavior and selfish behavior typi- Barsky, A. (2008). Understanding the ethical
cally co-occur in the behavioral ethics liter- cost of organizational goal-setting: A review
ature. However, such a perspective fails to and theory development. Journal of Business
reckon with their conceptual distinctions Ethics, 81(1), 63–81.
and unnecessarily limits our understand- Batson, C. D., Batson, J. G., Todd, R. M., Brum-
mett, B. H., Shaw, L. L., & Aldeguer, C. M. R.
ing of social behavior. Human beings can (1995). Empathy and the collective good: Car-
behave ethically or unethically, and behind ing for one of the others in a social dilemma.
those behaviors can lurk selfish or unselfish Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
intentions. By teasing apart the constructs of 68(4), 619–631.
ethicality and selfishness, we acquire a more Batson, C. D., Klein, T. R., Highberger, L., &
complete understanding of moral psychol- Shaw, L. L. (1995). Immorality from empathy-
472 M O R A L B E H AV I O R

induced altruism: When compassion and jus- (Eds.), Identity in organizations: Building
tice conflict. Journal of Personality and Social theory through conversations (pp. 245–256).
Psychology, 68(6), 1042–1054. Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE.
Batson, C. D., & Shaw, L. L. (1991). Evidence for Dyck, A., Morse, A., & Zingales, L. (2010). Who
altruism: Toward a pluralism of prosocial mo- blows the whistle on corporate fraud? Journal
tives. Psychological Inquiry, 2(2), 107–122. of Finance, 65(6), 2213–2253.
Bazerman, M. H., & Gino, F. (2012). Behavior- Edelman, B., & Larkin, I. (2015). Social com-
al ethics: Toward a deeper understanding of parisons and deception across workplace hi-
moral judgment and dishonesty. Annual Re- erarchies: Field and experimental evidence.
view of Law and Social Science, 8, 85–104. Organization Science, 26(1), 78–98.
Bentham, J. (1948). An introduction to the prin- Eisenberg, N., & Miller, P. A. (1987). The rela-
ciples of morals and legislation. Oxford, UK: tion of empathy to prosocial and related behav-
Blackwell. (Original work published 1789) iors. Psychological Bulletin, 101(1), 91–119.
Bocian, K., & Wojciszke, B. (2014). Self-interest Fehr, E., & Gächter, S. (2002). Altruistic punish-
bias in moral judgments of others’ actions. ment in humans. Nature, 415(6868), 137–140.
Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, Feldstein, M. (1975). The income tax and chari-
40(7), 898–909. table contributions: Part I. Aggregate and
Brass, D. J., Butterfield, K. D., & Skaggs, B. C. distributional effects. National Tax Journal,
(1998). Relationships and unethical behavior: 28(1), 81–100.
A social network perspective. Academy of Friedman, M. (1999). Introduction. In L. E.
Management Review, 23(1), 14–31. Read, I, pencil: My family tree as told to
Broomfield, K. A., Robinson, E. J., & Robinson, Leonard E. Read. Irvington-on-Hudson, NY:
W. P. (2002). Children’s understanding about Foundation for Economic Education.
white lies. British Journal of Developmental Frimer, J. A., Schaefer, N. K., & Oakes, H.
Psychology, 20(1), 47–65. (2014). Moral actor, selfish agent. Journal of
Brown, P., & Levinson, S. (1987). Politeness: Personality and Social Psychology, 106(5),
Some universals in language usage. Cam- 790–802.
bridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Gino, F., Ayal, S., & Ariely, D. (2009). Conta-
Bryan, C. J., Adams, G. S., & Monin, B. (2013). gion and differentiation in unethical behavior:
When cheating would make you a cheater: Im- The effect of one bad apple on the barrel. Psy-
plicating the self prevents unethical behavior. chological Science, 20(3), 393–398.
Journal of Experimental Psychology: Gener- Gino, F., & Mogilner, C. (2014). Time, money,
al, 142(4), 1001–1005. and morality. Psychological Science, 25(2),
Burris, E. R., Detert, J. R., & Romney, A. C. 414–421.
(2013). Speaking up vs. being heard: The dis- Golden, D. (2003, March 12). How much does
agreement around and outcomes of employee it cost to buy your child in? Wall Street Jour-
voice. Organization Science, 24(1), 22–38. nal. Retrieved from www.wsj.com/articles/
Charness, G., Masclet, D., & Villeval, M. C. SB1047409881995483800.
(2014). The dark side of competition for sta- Griswold, C. L. (1999). Adam Smith and the vir-
tus. Management Science, 60(1), 38–55. tues of enlightenment. Cambridge, UK: Cam-
Cohn, A., Fehr, E., & Maréchal, M. A. (2014). bridge University Press.
Business culture and dishonesty in the bank- Harbaugh, W. T., Mayr, U., & Burghart, D. R.
ing industry. Nature, 516(7529), 86–89. (2007). Neural responses to taxation and vol-
DePaulo, B. M., & Kashy, D. A. (1998). Everyday untary giving reveal motives for charitable do-
lies in close and casual relationships. Journal nations. Science, 316(5831), 1622–1625.
of Personality and Social Psychology, 74(1), Hegarty, W. H., & Sims, H. P. (1978). Some de-
63–79. terminants of unethical decision behavior: An
DeScioli, P., Massenkoff, M., Shaw, A., Petersen, experiment. Journal of Applied Psychology,
M. B., & Kurzban, R. (2014). Equity or equal- 63(4), 451–457.
ity?: Moral judgments follow the money. Pro- Iezzoni, L. I., Rao, S. R., DesRoches, C. M.,
ceedings of the Royal Society of London: B. Vogeli, C., & Campbell, E. G. (2012). Survey
Biological Sciences, 281(1797), 20142112. shows that at least some physicians are not al-
Dubois, D., Rucker, D. D., & Galinsky, A. D. ways open or honest with patients. Health Af-
(2015). Social class, power, and selfishness: fairs, 31(2), 383–391.
When and why upper and lower class individu- Jensen, M. C. (2003). Paying people to lie: The
als behave unethically. Journal of Personality truth about the budgeting process. European
and Social Psychology, 108(3), 436–449. Financial Management, 9(3), 379–406.
Dukerich, J. M., Kramer, R., & Parks, J. M. Johnson, R. A. (2003). Whistleblowing: When it
(1998). The dark side of organizational iden- works and why. Boulder, CO: Lynne Riener.
tification. In D. A. Whetten & P. C. Godfrey Jones, T. M. (1991). Ethical decision making by
 Unethical and Selfish Behavior 473

individuals in organizations: An issue-con- tional dissidence: The case of whistle-blowing.


tingent model. Academy of Management Re- Journal of Business Ethics, 4(1), 1–16.
view, 16(2), 366–395. Ordóñez, L. D., Schweitzer, M. E., Galinsky, A.
Kant, I. (1959). Foundation of the metaphysics D., & Bazerman, M. H. (2009). Goals gone
of morals (L. W. Beck, Trans.). Indianapolis, wild: The systematic side effects of overpre-
IN: Bobbs-Merrill. (Original work published scribing goal setting. Academy of Manage-
1785) ment Perspectives, 23(1), 6–16.
Kern, M. C., & Chugh, D. (2009). Bounded ethi- Paine, L. S., & Santoro, M. A. (1993). Sears
cality: The perils of loss framing. Psychologi- auto centers (A) (Harvard Business School
cal Science, 20(3), 378–384. case 9-394-009). Boston: Harvard Business
Kilduff, G., Galinksy, A., Gallo, E., & Reade, J. School.
(2016). Whatever it takes to win: Rivalry in- Penner, L. A., Dovidio, J. F., Piliavin, J. A., &
creases unethical behavior. Academy of Man- Schroeder, D. A. (2005). Prosocial behavior:
agement Journal, 59, 1508–1534. Multilevel perspectives. Annual Review of
Kohlberg, L. (1963). The development of chil- Psychology, 56, 365–392.
dren’s orientations toward a moral order. Peters, K., Luck, L., Hutchinson, M., Wilkes, L.,
Human Development, 6(1–2), 11–33. Andrew, S., & Jackson, D. (2011). The emo-
Kouchaki, M., Smith-Crowe, K., Brief, A. P., tional sequelae of whistleblowing: Findings
& Sousa, C. (2013). Seeing green: Mere ex- from a qualitative study. Journal of Clinical
posure to money triggers a business decision Nursing, 20(19–20), 2907–2914.
frame and unethical outcomes. Organization- Piff, P. K., Stancato, D. M., Côté, S., Mendoza-
al Behavior and Human Decision Processes, Denton, R., & Keltner, D. (2012). Higher so-
121(1), 53–61. cial class predicts increased unethical behav-
Lavee, J., Ashkenazi, T., Gurman, G., & Stein- ior. Proceedings of the National Academy of
berg, D. (2010). A new law for allocation of Sciences of the USA, 109(11), 4086–4091.
donor organs in Israel. The Lancet, 375(9720), Piliavin, J. A. (2003). Doing well by doing good:
1131–1133. Benefits for the benefactor. In M. Keyes & J.
Levine, E. E., & Schweitzer, M. E. (2014). Are Haidt (Eds.), Flourishing: Positive psychology
liars ethical?: On the tension between benevo- and the life well lived (pp. 227–247). Washing-
lence and honesty. Journal of Experimental ton, DC: American Psychological Association.
Social Psychology, 53, 107–117. Plato. (1997). Laws (T. J. Saunders, Trans.). In
Levine, E. E., & Schweitzer, M. E. (2015). Pro- J. Cooper & D. Hutchinson (Eds.), Complete
social lies: When deception breeds trust. Or- works. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett. (Original
ganizational Behavior and Human Decision work published 360 B.C.)
Processes, 126, 88–106. Rege, M., & Telle, K. (2004). The impact of so-
Lu, J. G., Brockner, J., Vardi, Y., & Weitz, E. cial approval and framing on cooperation in
(2017). The dark side of experiencing job au- public good situations. Journal of Public Eco-
tonomy: Unethical behavior. Journal of Ex- nomics, 88(7), 1625–1644.
perimental Social Psychology, 73, 222–234. Sageman, M. (2004). Understanding terror net-
Lu, J. G., Lee, J. J., Gino, F., & Galinsky, A. D. works. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylva-
(in press). Polluted morality: Air pollution pre- nia Press.
dicts criminal activity and unethical behavior. Schweitzer, M. E., Ordóñez, L., & Douma, B.
Psychological Science. (2004). Goal setting as a motivator of unethi-
Lu, J. G., Quoidbach, J., Gino, F., Chakroff, A., cal behavior. Academy of Management Jour-
Maddux, W. W., & Galinsky, A. D. (2017). nal, 47(3), 422–432.
The dark side of going abroad: How broad for- Shi, L., Wang, J., Liu, Z., Stevens, L., Sadler,
eign experiences increase immoral behavior. A., Ness, P., & Shan, H. (2014). Blood donor
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, management in China. Transfusion Medicine
112(1), 1–16. and Hemotherapy, 41(4), 273–282.
Markus, H. R., & Kitayama, S. (1991). Culture Smith, A. (1937). An inquiry into the nature and
and the self: Implications for cognition, emo- causes of the wealth of nations. New York:
tion, and motivation. Psychological Review, Modern Library. (Original work published
98(2), 224–253. 1776)
Mazar, N., & Aggarwal, P. (2011). Greasing the Talwar, V., Murphy, S. M., & Lee, K. (2007).
palm: Can collectivism promote bribery? Psy- White lie-telling in children for politeness pur-
chological Science, 22(7), 843–848. poses. International Journal of Behavioral
Mogilner, C. (2010). The pursuit of happiness: Development, 31(1), 1–11.
Time, money, and social connection. Psycho- Umphress, E. E., Bingham, J. B., & Mitchell, M.
logical Science, 21(9), 1348–1354. S. (2010). Unethical behavior in the name of
Near, J. P., & Miceli, M. P. (1985). Organiza- the company: The moderating effect of orga-
474 M O R A L B E H AV I O R

nizational identification and positive reciproc- Journal of Experimental Social Psychology,


ity beliefs on unethical pro-organizational be- 44(5), 1334–1338.
havior. Journal of Applied Psychology, 95(4), van den Berg, P., Molleman, L., & Weissing, F.
769–780. J. (2015). Focus on the success of others leads
U.S. Department of the Treasury, Internal Reve- to selfish behavior. Proceedings of the Nation-
nue Service. (2017). Whistleblower-Informant al Academy of Sciences of the USA, 112(9),
Award. Retrieved from www.irs.gov/uac/ 2912–2917.
Whistleblower-Informant-Award. Vohs, K. D., Mead, N. L., & Goode, M. R.
Vadera, A. K., & Pratt, M. G. (2013). Love, hate, (2006). The psychological consequences of
ambivalence, or indifference?: A conceptual money. Science, 314(5802), 1154–1156.
examination of workplace crimes and organi- Walker, L. J., & Hennig, K. H. (2004). Differing
zational identification. Organization Science, conceptions of moral exemplarity: Just, brave,
24(1), 172–188. and caring. Journal of Personality and Social
Valdesolo, P., & DeSteno, D. (2007). Moral Psychology, 86(4), 629–647.
­hypocrisy social groups and the flexibility of Waytz, A., Dungan, J., & Young, L. (2013). The
virtue. Psychological Science, 18(8), 689–690. whistleblower’s dilemma and the fairness–loy-
Valdesolo, P., & DeSteno, D. (2008). The duality alty tradeoff. Journal of Experimental Social
of virtue: Deconstructing the moral hypocrite. Psychology, 49(6), 1027–1033.
CHAPTER 48

In Search of Moral Equilibrium


Person, Situation, and Their Interplay
in Behavioral Ethics

Julia J. Lee
Francesca Gino

To what extent is our unethical behavior a product of dispositional


or situational forces?

We argue that unethical behavior should be understood in terms of


the dynamic interplay between dispositional factors—such as (1) one’s
ability and willpower, (2) personality traits, and (3) motivations and
identity—and trait-relevant situational factors.

Despite the ever-increasing number of empir- the interplay of dispositional and situational
ical studies in behavioral ethics, our knowl- factors in depth.
edge of how dispositional forces interact A review of the literature on unethical be-
with situational forces to influence unethi- havior indicates that researchers generally
cal behavior is largely absent. We posit that maintain that two main sets of factors influ-
individuals may have a different equilibrium ence employees’ decisions to act unethically:
point at which they are willing to sacrifice a (1) situational forces (related to the context
positive self-concept for their own benefit, the person is operating in) and (2) disposi-
and such equilibrium may well be deter- tional forces (related to the person’s person-
mined as a result of both dispositional and ality). Recent advances in behavioral ethics
situational factors. We thus propose a model unveiled the psychological tendencies that
of unethical behavior that incorporates both would lead even good people to cross ethi-
situational and dispositional forces (see Fig- cal boundaries (Bazerman & Gino, 2012).
ure 48.1). In this chapter, we first provide One of the notable assumptions in the field
a nuanced definition of unethical behavior of behavioral ethics is that morality is rather
and then review the literature supporting dynamic and malleable, instead of being a
the view that individual differences may be stable individual difference (Bazerman &
a key determinant of our moral equilibrium. Gino, 2012; Monin & Jordan, 2009). Em-
We then call for future studies that examine pirical studies that support this view are

475
476 M O R A L B E H AV I O R

FIGURE 48.1.  An interactionist model of unethical behavior.

abundant; when individuals are placed in a person’s environment can have a significant
situations in which they have the opportu- impact on his or her behavior (Asch, 1955;
nity to behave unethically, they are moti- Milgram, 1974; Zimbardo, 2007). Consis-
vated to strike a balance between pursuing tent with these theoretical bases, scholars
self-interest and maintaining a positive self- have largely focused on environmental fac-
view (Gino, Schweitzer, Mead, & Ariely, tors that could sway one’s moral compass.
2011; Mazar, Amir, & Ariely, 2008; Mead, Examples of such studies include ethics
Baumeister, & Gino, 2009). Research has training (Delaney & Sockell, 1992); ethical
since demonstrated that human behavior is climate, leadership, and culture (Treviño,
malleable rather than fixed across different 1986; Victor & Cullen, 1988); accountabil-
situations and can change, depending on a ity (Pitesa & Thau, 2013); codes of conduct
wide range of factors, from momentary dips (Brief, Dukerich, Brown, & Brett, 1996;
in our ability to resist temptation (Mead Helin & Sandström, 2007; Mayer, Kuenzi,
et al., 2009) to how tired we are (Killgore, Greenbaum, Bardes, & Salvador, 2009; Mc-
Killgore, Day, & Li, 2007) to the time of day Cabe, Treviño, & Butterfield, 2002); reward
(Kouchaki & Smith, 2013). This body of re- systems and incentives (Flannery & May,
search propelled a development of a model 2000; Hegarty & Sims, 1978; Schweitzer &
of ethical decision making by accounting for Croson, 1999; Tenbrunsel, 1998; Treviño &
the capricious nature of human behavior. Youngblood, 1990); the nature of the goals
The relationship between situational in- driving one’s actions (Schweitzer, Ordóñez,
fluences and unethical behavior is rooted in & Douma, 2004); and wealth present in
social psychological research suggesting that one’s environment (Gino & Pierce, 2009).
 In Search of Moral Equilibrium 477

Defining Unethical Behavior Bringing the Person Back In1


Ethical Behavior as a Matter of Ability
Unethical behavior refers to an action that
and Willpower
has harmful effects on others and that is “ei-
ther illegal or morally unacceptable to the The study of the relationship between dis-
larger community” (Jones, 1991, p. 367). position and unethical behavior is rooted
This definition has been widely endorsed by in models of individuals’ cognitive moral
behavioral ethics scholars, and researchers development (Treviño, 1986; Treviño &
in this area have largely focused on unethical Youngblood, 1990), which determines how
behaviors such as lying, cheating, and steal- an individual thinks about ethical dilemmas
ing (Treviño, Weaver, & Reynolds, 2006). and decides what is right or wrong in any
By definition, unethical behaviors are given situation. According to Rest’s (1986)
not necessarily selfish acts and not always four-component model, ethical behavior is
committed within the agent’s conscious a result of four processes—awareness, judg-
awareness. Still, by and large, researchers ment, motivation/intention, and action. This
have focused on motives that emphasize a model is intuitive and compelling and easily
self-serving or self-oriented motivation for adaptable to different theoretical needs.
unethical behavior. For example, Gneezy Rest’s model provides a largely context-
(2005) noted that people tell lies whenever independent view of moral behavior. Es-
it is beneficial for them, regardless of the sentially, it understands moral behavior as
lies’ effect on the other party. Similarly, a learnable skill that will be manifested so
Tenbrunsel (1998) showed that monetary in- long as one has the knowledge about what
centives increase individuals’ willingness to the correct action is and has developed the
misrepresent information to another party appropriate behavioral priorities through
in a social exchange, consistent with Le- one’s childhood and education. Though Rest
wicki’s (1983) argument that individuals lie makes some acknowledgment that our so-
to the extent that lying benefits them. This cial context may affect whether we become
view is consistent with prior work concep- aware of the moral import of a given deci-
tualizing the decision to behave unethically sion (Rest, 1986), the role of social context
as a product of economic incentives (Alling- is essentially tangential in his model. In ad-
ham & Sandmo, 1972; Holmstrom, 1979). dition, Rest offers a highly agentic model of
However, researchers have also identified moral behavior, by which we mean that the
unethical behaviors that are motivated by individual actor is credited with the lion’s
interpersonal emotions (such as envy and share of control and accountability over his
compassion) and that thus do not necessarily or her ultimate moral choices. This agentic
benefit the self; for example, individuals may model makes the assumption that failures to
inflict intentional harm to others or bend behave ethically are due to flaws in an in-
the rule to help others (see Gino & Pierce, dividual’s moral awareness, judgment, mo-
2010a, 2010b; Lee & Gino, 2017). In addi- tivation, or follow-through. Based as it is in
tion, Bazerman and Gino (2012) argued that Kohlberg’s cognitive moral development the-
even those individuals who want to be seen ory (Kohlberg, 1969, 1984), a fundamental
as moral might fail to recognize that there assumption of Rest’s framework is that the
is a moral issue at stake in the decision that key to improving moral behavior is moral
they are making. For instance, people failed education (Kohlberg, 1984; Rest, 1986).
to recognize their own conflicts of interest This assumption about how moral behavior
that led to unethical behavior (Moore, Tet- happens puts a large onus on the individual
lock, Tanlu, & Bazerman, 2006) and were both to be perfectly aware of the “correct”
unable to notice others’ unethical behav- moral outcome and to have the courage and
ior when ethical degradation occurs slowly authority to be able to enact that outcome.
(Gino & Bazerman, 2009). We therefore use Importantly, Rest’s model emphasizes the
the term unethical behavior throughout this agent’s cognitive ability to do the right thing.
chapter to reflect this nuanced understand- Another set of research on self-control
ing of what such behaviors entail. highlights the role of an agent’s willpower
478 M O R A L B E H AV I O R

as an antecedent of unethical behavior (Bau- 2014). On the other hand, moral disengage-
meister, Vohs, & Tice, 2007; Gino et al., ment describes an individual’s propensity
2011; Tangney, Baumeister, & Boone, 2004). to cognitively disengage to allow him- or
This view starts with an assumption that herself to behave unethically without feel-
people behave unethically when they face a ing distress (Bandura, 2002; Moore et al.,
dilemma between actions that offer short- 2012). Moral disengagement has been found
term benefits (e.g., monetary payoff) versus to predict self-reported unethical behavior,
long-term benefits (e.g., ethical reputation decisions to commit fraud, self-serving deci-
and social acceptance; see Monin, Pizarro, sions in the workplace, and other-reported
& Beer, 2007; Sheldon & Fishbach, 2015). unethical work behaviors (Moore et al.,
Empirical evidence supports this view by 2012).
showing that one’s exertion of self-­control Second, we identify two affect-based per-
depletes one’s self-regulation resources, thus sonality traits that have significant influence
increasing unethical behavior in an unrelat- on ethical behavior—trait empathy (Eisen-
ed domain (Barnes, Schaubroeck, Huth, & berg & Miller, 1987; Tangney, 1991) and
Ghumman, 2011; Gino et al., 2011; Mead guilt proneness (Cohen, Panter, & Turan,
et al., 2009). At a trait level, low self-control 2012). Trait empathy has shown to contrib-
is found to be associated with a set of crimi- ute to ethical behavior and to reduce un-
nal and antisocial behaviors (Gottfredson ethical behavior in various studies (Cohen et
& Hirschi, 1990). Similar to Rest’s theory, al., 2014; Eisenberg & Miller, 1987; Hoff-
research on self-control puts much empha- man, 2000; Tangney, 1991). Similarly, guilt
sis on an individual’s ability to resist ethical proneness has predicted making fewer un-
temptations. ethical business decisions, committing fewer
delinquent behaviors, and behaving more
honestly at work (Cohen et al., 2012; Cohen
Ethical Behavior as a Matter
et al., 2014).
of Personality Traits
Lastly, two traits have been shown to give
Whereas the above-mentioned research fo- rise to unethical behavior: Machiavellianism
cuses on one’s ability to do the right thing, (Christie & Geis, 2013; O’Boyle, Forsyth,
another stream of research points to how & Banks, 2012) and psychopathy (Hare &
one’s personality traits may influence ethi- Neumann, 2009; O’Boyle et al., 2012). Both
cal behavior. traits predicted the likelihood of making
First, past research on personality traits unethical decisions at work (Kish-Gephart,
has found various traits that may predispose Harrison, & Treviño, 2010), as well as pay-
a person to unethical behavior. Some per- ing kickbacks in a marketing simulation
sonality traits are more directly related to (Hegarty & Sims, 1978, 1979). Similarly,
morality than others (Cohen, Panter, Turan, psychopathic personality predicted coun-
Morse, & Kim, 2014). We identify two mor- terproductive behavior at work (O’Boyle et
ally relevant traits: the self-importance of al., 2012), as well as academic cheating (Na-
moral identity (Aquino & Reed, 2002) and thanson, Paulhus, & Williams, 2006).
moral disengagement (Moore, Detert, Trev-
iño, Baker, & Mayer, 2012). Moral identity
Ethical Behavior as a Matter of Identity
is defined as a self-conception organized
and Motivation
around a set of moral traits and is known
to be a relatively stable individual difference Previous research has thus far focused on
over time (Aquino & Reed, 2002). Moral either ability-based or personality-based ac-
identity has been shown to be positively cor- counts of morality. We argue that there are
related with prosocial behavior and reduced motivational factors that should be taken
unethical behavior (Aquino & Reed, 2002; into account when examining the individual
Shao, Aquino, & Freeman, 2008). As part differences that give a rise to unethical be-
of moral character, moral identity (internal- havior. Further, we propose that these moti-
izing the importance of possessing moral vational differences are relatively malleable
traits, in particular) also predicted ethical as compared with the factors that we have
behavior in the workplace (Cohen et al., summarized so far, such that these factors
 In Search of Moral Equilibrium 479

are likely to interact with situational factors. This finding is consistent with the view that
Here we identify attachment and perfor- anxiety evoked by performance-related un-
mance anxiety as such motivational factors. certainty encourages cheating as a means
First, attachment can be a powerful social of reducing such aversive states (Anderman,
motivation that could result in interpersonal Griesinger, & Westerfield, 1998). In line
unethical behaviors. The theory of attach- with this research, Wakeman and Moore
ment is built around the idea that security- (2015) found that individuals are more likely
enhancing caregivers (“attachment figures”) to cheat after their self-views on competence
help a child develop positive self-views and are threatened by performing poorly on the
relationships (Bowlby, 1982; Cassidy & task.
Shaver, 2008; Mikulincer & Shaver, 2007).
Attachment security is theorized to direct
individuals to be less anxious and defensive The Interplay between Person
and more open and prosocial, which might and Situation
contribute to a sense of authenticity and
honesty. Indeed, dispositional attachment Following the interactionist views that were
insecurity was correlated with unethical put forth by Treviño (1986) and Bandura
behavior (lying and cheating), and experi- (1990), we argue that unethical behavior
mentally manipulated attachment security is a function of individual differences, situ-
has been shown to reduce the tendency to ational factors, and their interactions. Here
lie or cheat (Gillath, Sesko, Shaver, & Chun, we draw on the interactionist principle of
2010). In particular, attachment avoidance trait activation (Kenrick & Funder, 1988;
(i.e., the degree to which people are com- Tett & Guterman, 2000) to identify the situ-
fortable with physical and emotional inti- ational forces that are relevant to disposi-
macy) predicted more unethical workplace tional forces. That is, the behavioral expres-
decisions in hypothetical scenarios (Chopik, sion of a trait requires arousal of that trait
2015). This relationship between attach- by trait-relevant situational cues. This view
ment avoidance and unethical decisions was allows the possibility that individuals can
mediated by emotional exhaustion, which behave consistently across different situa-
suggests the importance of interpersonal tions through strong dispositions, but strong
and emotional motivations that underlie un- situations can also cause different people
ethical behavior. to behave similarly (Beaty, Cleveland, &
Second, performance anxiety can be an- Murphy, 2001; Mischel, 1973, 1977). We
other source of motivation that could pro- use this situation–trait relevance as a guide
pel one’s unethical behavior. Performance- to identify a few thematically relevant situ-
related anxiety has shown to increase the ational factors that are likely to interact with
likelihood of cheating among college stu- one’s disposition.
dents (Berger, Levin, Jacobson, & Millham, The first model of unethical behavior
1977), and experimentally manipulated focuses on how an individual’s ability and
anxiety also increased unethical behavior willpower can interact with situations that
(Kouchaki & Desai, 2014). In our own re- are cognitively depleting. Consider a team
search, we measured participants’ pre- and of consultants who had to travel long hours
postperformance hormone levels (testoster- and are severely jet-lagged. Research has
one as a marker for reward and risk seek- shown that sleep deprivation can lead to
ing and cortisol as a marker for anxiety and unethical behavior (Barnes et al., 2011)
stress) and gave them an opportunity to and that individuals are more ethical in the
cheat. We found that elevated concentrations morning than later in the day (Kouchaki &
of testosterone and cortisol predicted more Smith, 2013). When the team faces a deci-
cheating on a performance test (Lee, Gino, sion of ethical import to be made, would
Jin, Rice, & Josephs, 2015). More impor- everyone on the team prefer to make an un-
tantly, we found that the more participants ethical decision? Despite the strength of situ-
cheated, the greater were the hormonal and ation (Baumeister, Bratslavsky, Finkenauer,
emotional rewards of cheating, as indicated & Vohs, 2001), the team members’ decision
by reductions in cortisol and negative affect. may depend on individuals’ cognitive aware-
480 M O R A L B E H AV I O R

ness and construal of the situation as carry- employee’s performance anxiety. Indeed,
ing moral weights, as well as the ability to individuals’ thinking about their identity
resist the temptation. A good example of the as bank employees led to more cheating,
Person × Situation interaction in this context which suggests that business culture may
demonstrated that the fit between a person’s play a significant role in shaping one’s moral
chronotype (i.e., whether one’s circadian compass. Similarly, work stressors, such as
rhythms are optimized for morning or for interpersonal conflicts and organizational
evening) and the time of day predicted ethi- constraints, have shown to increase coun-
cal behavior (Barnes et al., 2011). Similarly, terproductive work behaviors (Kim, Cohen,
future studies could examine the situations & Panter, 2015; Meier & Spector, 2013).
that could render individuals cognitively de- Consistent with the view that those individ-
pleted, such as excessive workload and time uals who experience high levels of anxiety
constraints, and examine how these relevant and attachment avoidance might find their
situations can lead to more unethical behav- situation particularly stressful (Hazan &
ior for those who have high or low moral Shaver, 1990), a high-stress environment
awareness or self-control at the trait level. may amplify the workers’ need to reduce the
The second model focused on various per- performance-related stress by crossing ethi-
sonality traits that are relatively stable, such cal boundaries, particularly for those who
as moral identity, moral disengagement, already have elevated levels of performance
trait empathy, guilt proneness, Machiavel- anxiety. Thus future studies could identify
lianism, and psychopathy. One can imagine the environmental stressors (e.g., pay for
various situational factors that are relevant performance) that could interact with one’s
to each of these personality traits. But as an motivational differences.
example, an ethical norm that allows indi-
viduals to easily rationalize their unethical
behavior can reinforce the unethical behav- Conclusion
ior committed by those who have high moral
disengagement. Consider an employee– On a daily basis, we are faced with choices
s­upervisor dyad in which the employee ob- that could advance our own self-interest or
serves the supervisor inflating the expense demonstrate consistency with our moral
report and telling the employee that every- compass. Across contexts, from politics and
one in the company does the same. This in- sport to education and business, these choic-
cident is likely to increase the employee’s es are often tempting, leading even people
tendency to behave unethically (Shu, Gino, who care about morality and being ethical
& Bazerman, 2011), but this may depend to act unethically. Given the economic and
on a person’s own propensity to engage in social costs of unethical behavior, it is im-
moral disengagement. For example, Bonner, portant to understand the antecedents of
Greenbaum, and Mayer (2016) have shown these behaviors. In this chapter, we built on
that the negative relationship between su- insightful research in behavioral ethics and
pervisors’ moral disengagement and em- moral psychology to propose an interactive
ployees’ perceptions of ethical leadership is model of person- and situation-based un-
stronger when employees’ moral disengage- ethical behavior. We first placed morality in
ment is low versus high. Future research the realm of the behavioral ethics literature
could thus examine the ethical norms (e.g., to define unethical behavior in broad terms.
norms of accountability, the extent to which We then provided a review of three different
performance goals are aligned with ethical models of individual difference that predict
goals, or incentives that reinforce the idea of unethical behavior. Finally, we suggested
a zero-sum game) could trigger relevant per- that unethical behavior should be under-
sonality traits. stood in terms of the dynamic interplay be-
The last model viewed unethical behavior tween dispositional factors and situational
as a function of motivational forces, such factors and called for more research on this
as attachment and performance anxiety. interplay. We hope that by responding to
For instance, a high-stress work environ- this call, scholars from various fields will
ment (think Wall Street) can reinforce an identify important insights as to why even
 In Search of Moral Equilibrium 481

good people do bad things and how they can moral judgment and dishonesty. Annual Re-
best ensure that they will follow their moral view of Law and Social Science, 8(1), 85–104.
compass in both challenging and more ordi- Beaty, J. C., Jr., Cleveland, J. N., & Murphy, K.
nary ethical situations. R. (2001). The relation between personality
and contextual performance in “strong” ver-
sus “weak” situations. Human Performance,
NOTE 14(2), 125–148.
Berger, S. E., Levin, P., Jacobson, L. I., & Mill-
1. We did not include a host of demographic ham, J. (1977). Gain approval or avoid dis-
antecedents of unethical behavior for two approval: Comparison of motive strengths in
reasons. First, we focus on the individual dif- high need for approval scorers. Journal of Per-
ferences that can be changed or made salient sonality, 45(3), 458–468.
and that are thus relatively malleable. Second, Bonner, J. M., Greenbaum, R. L., & Mayer, D.
despite some evidence showing that demo- M. (2016). My boss is morally disengaged:
graphic variables influence ethical decisions The role of ethical leadership in explaining the
(O’Fallon & Butterfield, 2005; Piff, Stancato, interactive effect of supervisor and employee
Côté, Mendoza-Denton, & Keltner, 2012), moral disengagement on employee behaviors.
studies have found that the effect size tends Journal of Business Ethics, 137, 731–742.
to be relatively small or not significant as Bowlby, J. (1982). Attachment and loss: Retro-
compared with other morally relevant traits spect and prospect. American Journal of Or-
(Cohen, Panter, Turan, Morse, & Kim, 2014; thopsychiatry, 52(4), 664–678.
Kish-Gephart, Harrison, & Treviño, 2010). Brief, A. P., Dukerich, J. M., Brown, P. R., &
Brett, J. F. (1996). What’s wrong with the
Treadway Commission report?: Experimen-
REFERENCES tal analyses of the effects of personal values
and codes of conduct on fraudulent financial
Allingham, M. G., & Sandmo, A. (1972). Income reporting. Journal of Business Ethics, 15(2),
tax evasion: A theoretical analysis. Journal of 183–198.
Public Economics, 1(3–4), 323–338. Cassidy, J., & Shaver, P. R. (Eds.). (2008). Hand-
Anderman, E. M., Griesinger, T., & Westerfield, book of attachment (2nd ed.). New York:
G. (1998). Motivation and cheating during Guilford Press.
early adolescence. Journal of Educational Psy- Chopik, W. J. (2015). Relational attachment and
chology, 90, 84–93. ethical workplace decisions: The mediating
Aquino, K., & Reed, A., II. (2002). The self- role of emotional burnout. Journal of Experi-
importance of moral identity. Journal of Per- mental Psychology: General, 75, 160–164.
sonality and Social Psychology, 83(6), 1423– Christie, R., & Geis, F. L. (2013). Studies in Ma-
1440. chiavellianism. New York: Academic Press.
Asch, S. E. (1955). Opinions and social pressure. Cohen, T. R., Panter, A. T., & Turan, N. (2012).
Scientific American, 193(5), 31–35. Guilt proneness and moral character. Current
Bandura, A. (1990). Selective activation and dis- Directions in Psychological Science, 21(5),
engagement of moral control. Journal of So- 355–359.
cial Issues, 46(1), 27–46. Cohen, T. R., Panter, A. T., Turan, N., Morse,
Bandura, A. (2002). Selective moral disengage- L., & Kim, Y. (2014). Moral character in the
ment in the exercise of moral agency. Journal workplace. Journal of Personality and Social
of Moral Education, 31(2), 101–119. Psychology, 107(5), 943–963.
Barnes, C. M., Schaubroeck, J., Huth, M., & Delaney, J. T., & Sockell, D. (1992). Do company
Ghumman, S. (2011). Lack of sleep and un- ethics training programs make a difference?:
ethical conduct. Organizational Behavior and An empirical analysis. Journal of Business
Human Decision Processes, 115(2), 169–180. Ethics, 11(9), 719–727.
Baumeister, R. F., Bratslavsky, E., Finkenauer, Eisenberg, N., & Miller, P. A. (1987). The rela-
C., & Vohs, K. D. (2001). Bad is stronger than tion of empathy to prosocial and related behav-
good. Review of General Psychology, 5(4), iors. Psychological Bulletin, 101(1), 91–119.
323–370. Flannery, B. L., & May, D. R. (2000). Environ-
Baumeister, R. F., Vohs, K. D., & Tice, D. M. mental ethical decision making in the U.S.
(2007). The strength model of self-control. metal-finishing industry. Academy of Man-
Current Directions in Psychological Science, agement Journal, 43(4), 642–662.
16(6), 351–355. Gillath, O., Sesko, A. K., Shaver, P. R., & Chun,
Bazerman, M. H., & Gino, F. (2012). Behavior- D. S. (2010). Attachment, authenticity, and
al ethics: Toward a deeper understanding of honesty: Dispositional and experimentally
482 M O R A L B E H AV I O R

induced security can reduce self- and other- servability. Bell Journal of Economics, 10(1),
deception. Journal of Personality and Social 74–91.
Psychology, 98(5), 841–855. Jones, T. M. (1991). Ethical decision making by
Gino, F., & Bazerman, M. H. (2009). When mis- individuals in organizations: An issue-con-
conduct goes unnoticed: The acceptability of tingent model. Academy of Management Re-
gradual erosion in others’ unethical behavior. view, 16(2), 366–395.
Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, Kenrick, D. T., & Funder, D. C. (1988). Profit-
45(4), 708–719. ing from controversy: Lessons from the per-
Gino, F., & Pierce, L. (2009). The abundance son–situation debate. American Psychologist,
effect: Unethical behavior in the presence of 43(1), 23–34.
wealth. Organizational Behavior and Human Killgore, W., Killgore, D. B., Day, L. M., & Li,
Decision Processes, 109(2), 142–155. C. (2007). The effects of 53 hours of sleep
Gino, F., & Pierce, L. (2010a). Lying to level the deprivation on moral judgment. Sleep, 30(3),
playing field: Why people may dishonestly 345–352.
help or hurt others to create equity. Journal of Kim, Y., Cohen, T. R., & Panter, A. T. (2016).
Business Ethics, 95(S1), 89–103. Cause or consequence?: The reciprocal
Gino, F., & Pierce, L. (2010b). Robin Hood model of counterproductive work behavior
under the hood: Wealth-based discrimination and mistreatment. Academy of Management
in illicit customer help. Organization Science, Annual Meeting Best Paper Proceedings.
21(6), 1176–1194. Available at http://proceedings.aom.org/con-
Gino, F., Schweitzer, M. E., Mead, N. L., & tent/2016/1/18071.
Ariely, D. (2011). Unable to resist temptation: Kish-Gephart, J. J., Harrison, D. A., & Treviño,
How self-control depletion promotes unethi- L. K. (2010). Bad apples, bad cases, and bad
cal behavior. Organizational Behavior and barrels: Meta-analytic evidence about sources
Human Decision Processes, 115(2), 191–203. of unethical decisions at work. Journal of Ap-
Gneezy, U. (2005). Deception: The role of conse- plied Psychology, 95(1), 1–31.
quences. American Economic Review, 95(1), Kohlberg, L. (1969). Stage and sequence: The
384–394. cognitive development approach to social-
Gottfredson, M. R., & Hirschi, T. (1990). Low ization. In D. A. Goslin (Ed.), Handbook of
self-control and crime. Available at www.self- socialization theory (pp. 347–480). Chicago:
teachingresources.com/yahoo_ site_ admin/ Rand McNally.
assets/docs/Low_ Self_Control_ and_Crime_ Kohlberg, L. (1984). The psychology of moral
Gottfredson_Hirschi.23144447.pdf. development: The nature and validity of
Hare, R. D., & Neumann, C. S. (2009). Psychop- moral stages (2nd ed.). San Francisco: Harp-
athy and its measurement. In P. J. Corr & G. erCollins.
Matthews (Eds.), The Cambridge handbook Kouchaki, M., & Desai, S. D. (2014). Anxious,
of personality psychology (pp. 660–686). threatened, and also unethical: How anxiety
Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. makes individuals feel threatened and commit
Hazan, C., & Shaver, P. R. (1990). Love and unethical acts. Journal of Applied Psychology,
work: An attachment-theoretical perspective. 100(2), 360–375.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, Kouchaki, M., & Smith, I. H. (2013). The morn-
59(2), 270–280. ing morality effect: The influence of time of
Hegarty, W. H., & Sims, H. P. (1978). Some de- day on unethical behavior. Psychological Sci-
terminants of unethical decision behavior: An ence, 25(1), 95–102.
experiment. Journal of Applied Psychology, Lee, J. J., & Gino, F. (2017). Envy and interper-
63(4), 451–457. sonal corruption: Social comparison processes
Hegarty, W. H., & Sims, H. P. (1979). Organi- and unethical behavior in organizations. In R.
zational philosophy, policies, and objectives Smith, U. Merlone, & M. Duffy (Eds.), Envy
related to unethical decision behavior: A labo- at work and in organizations: Research, theo-
ratory experiment. Journal of Applied Psy- ry, and applications (pp. 347–371). New York:
chology, 64(3), 331–338. Oxford University Press.
Helin, S., & Sandström, J. (2007). An inquiry Lee, J. J., Gino, F., Jin, E. S., Rice, L. K., & Jo-
into the study of corporate codes of ethics. sephs, B. (2015). Hormones and ethics: Under-
Journal of Business Ethics, 75(3), 253–271. standing the biological basis of unethical con-
Hoffman, M. L. (2000). Development of em- duct. Journal of Experimental Psychology:
pathic distress. In Empathy and moral devel- General, 144(5), 891–897.
opment. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge Univer- Lewicki, P. (1983). Self-image bias in person per-
sity Press. ception. Journal of Personality and Social Psy-
Holmstrom, B. (1979). Moral hazard and ob- chology, 45(2), 384–393.
 In Search of Moral Equilibrium 483

Mayer, D. M., Kuenzi, M., Greenbaum, R., Nathanson, C., Paulhus, D. L., & Williams, K.
Bardes, M., & Salvador, R. B. (2009). How M. (2006). Personality and misconduct corre-
low does ethical leadership flow?: Test of a lates of body modification and other cultural
trickle-down model. Organizational Behavior deviance markers. Journal of Research in Per-
and Human Decision Processes, 108(1), 1–13. sonality, 40(5), 779–802.
Mazar, N., Amir, O., & Ariely, D. (2008). The O’Boyle, E. H., Jr., Forsyth, D. R., & Banks,
dishonesty of honest people: A theory of self- G. C. (2012). A meta-analysis of the dark
concept maintenance. Journal of Marketing triad and work behavior: A social exchange
Research, 45(6), 633–644. perspective. Journal of Applied Psychology,
McCabe, D. L., Treviño, L. K., & Butterfield, K. 97(3), 557–579.
D. (2002). Honor codes and other contextual O’Fallon, M. J., & Butterfield, K. D. (2005). A
influences on academic integrity: A replication review of the empirical ethical decision-mak-
and extension to modified honor code set- ing literature: 1996–2003. Journal of Business
tings. Research in Higher Education, 43(3), Ethics, 59(4), 375–413.
357–378. Piff, P. K., Stancato, D. M., Côté, S., Mendoza-
Mead, N. L., Baumeister, R. F., & Gino, F. Denton, R., & Keltner, D. (2012). Higher so-
(2009). Too tired to tell the truth: Self-control cial class predicts increased unethical behav-
resource depletion and dishonesty. Journal of ior. Proceedings of the National Academy of
Experimental Social Psychology, 45(3), 594– Sciences of the USA, 109(11), 4086–4091.
597. Pitesa, M., & Thau, S. (2013). Compliant sin-
Meier, L. L., & Spector, P. E. (2013). Reciprocal ners, obstinate saints: How power and self-fo-
effects of work stressors and counterproduc- cus determine the effectiveness of social influ-
tive work behavior: A five-wave longitudinal ences in ethical decision making. Academy of
study. Journal of Applied Psychology, 98(3), Management Journal, 56(3), 635–658.
529–539. Rest, J. (1986). Moral development: Advances in
Mikulincer, M., & Shaver, P. R. (2007). Boost- research and theory. New York: Praeger.
ing attachment security to promote mental Schweitzer, M. E., & Croson, R. (1999). Curtail-
health, prosocial values, and inter-group toler- ing deception: The impact of direct questions
ance. Psychological Inquiry, 18(3), 139–156. on lies and omissions. International Journal
Milgram, S. (1974). Obedience to authority. of Conflict Management, 10(3), 225–248.
London: Tavistock. Schweitzer, M. E., Ordóñez, L., & Douma, B.
Mischel, W. (1973). Toward a cognitive social (2004). Goal setting as a motivator of unethi-
learning reconceptualization of personality. cal behavior. Academy of Management Jour-
Psychological Review, 80(4), 252–283. nal, 47(3), 422–432.
Mischel, W. (1977). The interaction of per- Shao, R., Aquino, K., & Freeman, D. (2008).
son and situation. In D. Magnusson & N. S. Beyond moral reasoning: A review of moral
Endler (Eds.), Personality at the crossroads: identity research and its implications for busi-
Current issues in interactional psychology ness ethics. Business Ethics Quarterly, 18(4),
(pp. 333–352). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. 513–540.
Monin, B., & Jordan, A. H. (2009). The dynam- Sheldon, O. J., & Fishbach, A. (2015). Anticipat-
ic moral self: A social psychological perspec- ing and resisting the temptation to behave un-
tive. In D. Narvaez & D. K. Lapsley (Eds.), ethically. Personality and Social Psychology
Personality, identity, and character (pp. 341– Bulletin, 41(7), 962–975.
354). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Shu, L. L., Gino, F., & Bazerman, M. H. (2011).
Press. Dishonest deed, clear conscience: When cheat-
Monin, B., Pizarro, D. A., & Beer, J. S. (2007). ing leads to moral disengagement and motivat-
Deciding versus reacting: Conceptions of ed forgetting. Personality and Social Psychol-
moral judgment and the reason–affect debate. ogy Bulletin, 37(3), 330–349.
Review of General Psychology, 11(2), 99–111. Tangney, J. P. (1991). Moral affect: The good, the
Moore, C., Detert, J. R., Treviño, L. K., Baker, bad, and the ugly. Journal of Personality and
V. L., & Mayer, D. M. (2012). Why employ- Social Psychology, 61(4), 598–607.
ees do bad things: Moral disengagement and Tangney, J. P., Baumeister, R. F., & Boone, A.
unethical organizational behavior. Personnel L. (2004). High self-control predicts good ad-
Psychology, 65(1), 1–48. justment, less pathology, better grades, and
Moore, D. A., Tetlock, P. E., Tanlu, L., & Bazer- interpersonal success. Journal of Personality,
man, M. H. (2006). Conflicts of interest and 72(2), 271–324.
the case of auditor independence: Moral se- Tenbrunsel, A. E. (1998). Misrepresentation and
duction and strategic issue cycling. Academy expectations of misrepresentation in an ethical
of Management Review, 31(1), 10–29. dilemma: The role of incentives and tempta-
484 M O R A L B E H AV I O R

tion. Academy of Management Journal, 41(3), Treviño, L. K., & Youngblood, S. A. (1990). Bad
330–339. apples in bad barrels: A causal analysis of ethi-
Tett, R. P., & Guterman, H. A. (2000). Situation cal decision-making behavior. Journal of Ap-
trait relevance, trait expression, and cross- plied Psychology, 75(4), 378–385.
situational consistency: Testing a principle of Victor, B., & Cullen, J. B. (1988). The organiza-
trait activation. Journal of Research in Per- tional bases of ethical work climates. Admin-
sonality, 34(4), 397–423. istrative Science Quarterly, 33(1), 101–125.
Treviño, L. K. (1986). Ethical decision making in Wakeman, S. W., & Moore, C. (2015). A coun-
organizations: A person–situation interaction- terfeit competence: After threat, cheating
ist model. Academy of Management Review, boosts one’s self-image. Working paper.
11(3), 601–617. Zimbardo, P. (2007). The Lucifer effect: Un-
Treviño, L. K., Weaver, G. R., & Reynolds, S. J. derstanding how good people turn evil. New
(2006). Behavioral ethics in organizations: A re- York: Random House.
view. Journal of Management, 32(6), 951–990.
CHAPTER 49

Unconflicted Virtue

Kate C. S. Schmidt

Is moral behavior conflicted or unconflicted for a virtuous agent?

Moral behavior can be understood according to the psychological


models of other skilled behavior; although results are mixed, expert
behavior often lacks conflict.

A virtuous agent might be best understood scenario, the agent acts without any conflict,
as one who is able to act correctly despite fluidly doing as virtue requires.
competing inclinations. Imagine a firefighter Although both scenarios describe a fire-
who is about to run into a burning building. fighter who acts morally, the first seems
He recognizes that the flames represent a intuitively to be more admirable. Courage
risk to his life and may feel fear at the pros- is often understood as the ability to over-
pect of entering the building. Nevertheless, come fear, and in the second description it is
by focusing on the importance of saving tempting to say the firefighter is just not as
lives, he overcomes that fear and pushes for- brave. It seems as though it is a nervous fire-
ward into the fire. This account of the agent man, not an oblivious one, who deserves the
suggests that moral behavior is conflicted most praise for entering the building. This
and is in part characterized by overcoming is consistent with intuitions that virtue in-
a sort of internal motivational conflict. Re- volves overcoming conflict, rather than act-
gardless of the effort needed to complete the ing in an unconflicted way.
action, there is an internal process of adjudi- Consider a different example of virtu-
cating between tempting options. The virtu- ous behavior. While out having drinks, a
ous firefighter runs into the building, over- woman is offered the opportunity to cheat
coming the competing inclination toward on her partner. She’s tempted, but because
self-preservation. of her good character is able to overcome
An alternative understanding of virtue the temptation and remains loyal. If virtue is
characterizes the firefighter as less conflict- conflicted, then when she acts correctly she
ed. Perhaps after much practice he no longer does so because her sense of loyalty is strong
hesitates at the doorway to a building. He enough to overcome the inclination to cheat.
focuses completely on his goals, undisturbed On the other hand, if virtue is unconflict-
by the risks surrounding his actions. In this ed, she maintains fidelity without even the

485
486 M O R A L B E H AV I O R

temptation to act contrary to virtue. The op- because it requires overcoming an internal
portunity doesn’t strike her as a temptation, conflict; not everyone would be able to take
and she rejects it without internal struggle. such an action. True moral behavior comes
In this case, it intuitively seems like the un- at a cost, and only the virtuous are able to
conflicted agent is the one who possesses persevere despite the difficulty.
virtue. Loyalty seems to entail more than Virtuous agents are often portrayed as
successfully resisting temptation. struggling with internal conflict, sometimes
mirroring situations of external conflict.
Descriptions of bravery during war include
Conflicted Virtue the circumstances that individuals must
overcome, and agents are praised for their
The position that virtue involves overcoming actions based in part on the effort it seems
conflict can be understood through Philip- to take. Captain Henry Comey fought in
pa Foot’s notion of virtue as “corrective” the U.S. Civil War, enlisting with a volun-
(Foot, 2002). On her account, virtues exist teer regiment. He describes leaving for war
to correct natural human frailties: “They after a dramatic send-off, wondering if he
are corrective, each one standing at a point would ever see his family again: “I tried hard
at which there is some temptation to be re- to assume the role of a brave soldier, but I
sisted or deficiency of motivation to be made knew my eyes were wet with tears” (Comey
good” (Foot, 2002, p. 8). The chance to act & Comey, 2004, p. 11). It is understandable
morally emerges out of these human liabili- that such a sacrifice would have been pain-
ties. Virtues are good precisely because of ful regardless of the level of commitment to
their corrective nature; if humans had dif- one’s country. It would be counterintuitive to
ferent temptations, then virtues would be suggest that these sorts of actions are in any
different. Foot says: “One may say that it is way unconflicted for the agent. Yet, these
only because fear and the desire for pleasure actions also seem intuitively virtuous. In the
often operate as temptations that courage words of Nelson Mandela, “The brave man
and temperance exist as virtues at all” (p. 9). is not he who does not feel afraid, but he who
This model is aligned with the idea that a conquers that fear” (Mandela, 1994, p. 542).
virtuous agent acts well by overcoming frail- Moral behavior sometimes involves con-
ties in his or her character. Conflict emerges flict because it requires choosing between
between the requirements of virtue and the two significant values or giving up some-
common temptation to act wrongly. Foot ar- thing that might otherwise be considered
gues: “The temperate man who must on oc- valuable. In situations in which there are
casion refuse pleasures need not desire them multiple moral values, it seems virtuous to
any less than the intemperate man” (2002, feel conflicted about an action. Karen Stohr
p. 8). Virtuous agents feel temptations to- (2003) argues that an agent who must do
ward vice just as keenly as those who act im- something harmful in order to avoid a great-
morally, but because of their virtue they can er harm ought to feel torn and upset—to feel
overcome their own desires. otherwise would be a failure to register the
This account of conflicted action is con- harmful consequences of her or his actions.
sistent with some central intuitions about An agent who feels unconflicted may be act-
virtue. In the case of our firefighter, it seems ing without truly thinking or understanding
surprising to suggest that the firefighter the nature of the scenario. Anne Margaret
must feel no fear. It is natural for an agent to Baxley (2007) explains, “Virtue can have a
recognize the danger to his or her own life, cost, and a mark of the wise person is that
and it is courageous to take action despite she recognizes it” (p. 403). A model of vir-
this danger. The urge to avoid suffering and tue as unconflicted fails to recognize the fact
to worry about one’s own welfare is a com- that virtuous agents face real risks and real
mon human tendency. Despite this aversion harms (Baxley, 2007). This helps explain
to suffering, some agents are able to choose the intuition that a virtuous agent must act
costly actions when they know it is the right through overcoming internal conflict.
thing to do. The intuition might even be that This model of virtue as conflicted also has
the action demonstrates courage precisely historic support from Aristotle. He empha-
 Unconflicted Virtue 487

sized that those who are brave are not brave say), but as silencing them. (McDowell, 1979,
because they are insensitive to the reasons p. 335)
for fear. Aristotle says, “He would be a sort
of madman or insensible person if he feared Because competing reasons are silenced,
nothing” (Barnes, 1984, pp. 1117a25– the virtuous agent has no temptation to act
1117a26). One who acts bravely can clearly wrongly and so acts without conflict.
see the reasons for fear but is still able to McDowell emphasizes that once an agent
act. “It is for facing what is painful, then, sees what virtue requires, it is easy to act.
as has been said, that men are called brave” This ease of action is accomplished by stay-
(Barnes 1984, pp. 1117a32–1117a33). Aris- ing focused on what is truly important:
totle suggests that the virtuous agent may “The lack of struggle is ensured by keeping
feel the cost of virtue even more keenly than the attention firmly fixed on what Aristotle
others: calls ‘the noble’; not by a weighing of at-
tractions” (McDowell & McFetridge, 1978,
The more he is possessed of excellence in its p. 27). This attentional focus and expertise
entirety and the happier he is, the more he will are what allow the agent to act in an uncon-
be pained at the thought of death; for life is flicted manner without attending to irrel-
best worth living for such a man, and he is evant temptations. Moral behavior involves
knowingly losing the greatest goods, and this “a renunciation, without struggle, of some-
is painful. But he is none the less brave, and thing which in the abstract one would value
perhaps all the more so, because he chooses highly (physical pleasure, security of life
noble deeds of war at that cost. (Barnes 1984, and limb)” (McDowell & McFetridge 1978,
1117b10–1117b15)
p. 27). While these things are valuable in the
abstract, when they conflict with virtue the
The virtuous agent is aware of the conflict
moral agent is no longer tempted by them.
created by the high cost of virtue, feels such
This view is also consistent with intuitions
conflict more intensely because of his virtue, about moral behavior. It is difficult to imag-
and yet is able to ultimately persevere. ine a moral agent who must overcome con-
trary inclinations before acting with loyalty,
compassion, or honesty. It seems that feeling
Unconflicted Virtue the temptation to cheat is enough to indicate
a lack of loyalty. A truly loyal partner would
On the opposing view, that of unconflicted not need to overcome such internal conflict.
virtue, a moral agent has the ability to focus The idea that virtuous behavior happens
solely on the requirements of virtue without without conflict is reflected in first-person
experiencing conflicting inclinations. John reports of people who have acted quickly
McDowell (1979) argues that a virtuous in dangerous situations. Deborah Hughes
agent is able to quickly recognize moral rea- placed herself in the middle of a mob at-
sons for action and to respond to them with- tack to defend a stranger, suddenly finding
out ever being tempted by alternatives. It is an urge to protect someone she didn’t even
not that a virtuous agent must compare or know (Baldas, 2015). Afterward, she de-
weigh competing courses of action; rather, scribed how the fear didn’t seem to reach
any reasons to act other than according to her in the moment: “I don’t know. Some-
virtue are silenced. Virtuous agents are espe- thing happened. I had courage. I just didn’t
cially sensitive to the requirements of virtue want them to hurt him. . . . Sometimes, I’ll
in his or her moral situation: sit here and I’ll cry. And I’ll say, ‘Did I actu-
ally do that?’ ” Brady Olson, a high school
The view of a situation which he arrives at by
teacher who disarmed a student gunman in
exercising his sensitivity is one in which some
aspect of the situation is seen as constituting a his school, describes a similar fixation on a
reason for acting in some way; this reason is specific course of action (Piccoli, 2015): “I
apprehended, not as outweighing or overrid- don’t know if it was a rational thought at the
ing any reasons for acting in other ways which time, but I thought, ‘I have to get the gun
would otherwise be constituted by other as- away from him to prevent him from harm-
pects of the situation (the present danger, ing students.’ ”
488 M O R A L B E H AV I O R

These stories describe people who acted (2011) defends a close comparison between
quickly and effectively when faced with dan- virtues and skills, saying, “Exercising a vir-
gerous situations. Olson doesn’t describe tue involves practical reasoning of a kind
indecision or temptation toward safely— that can illuminatingly be compared to the
instead, his focus was on the need to take kind of reasoning we find in someone exer-
action. Similarly, Hughes doesn’t question cising a practical skill” (p. 1). Virtues (like
her actions until afterward. When an agent skills) require time and practice to master
has a virtuous disposition, the proper action and involve continuously striving for bet-
occurs without resistance. These examples ter performance. The psychology literature
suggest the experience of moral behavior is on skilled behavior can be applied to help
unconflicted, and agents seem to fully and understand the nature of a virtuous agent.
quickly commit to the moral course of ac- Annas (2011) argues that virtue becomes
tion. easier for the more practiced moral agent.
This model of virtue can also draw sup- The virtuous agent has obtained a skill and
port from Aristotle. Aristotle draws a dis- so no longer needs to focus on overcoming
tinction between an agent who is continent any internal conflict.
and one who is fully virtuous. Difficulty According to Annas (2011), moral behav-
doing the right thing indicates mere conti- ior will also feel distinctively conflict-free
nence rather than virtue, because the agent for the agent because of his or her expertise.
is still tempted to do wrong. Discussing the Experts can at times become completely
virtue of temperance, Aristotle clarifies: consumed in the performance of a task, a
state known as “flow” (Csikszentmihalyi
Both the continent man and the temperate & LeFevre, 1989). This complete immer-
man are such as to do nothing contrary to sion seems to involve a match between per-
reason for the sake of the bodily pleasures,
ceptions of the skill required to complete a
but the former has and the latter has not bad
appetites, and the latter is such as not to feel task and the ability to rise to the challenge;
pleasure contrary to reason, while the former agents describe the experience as one that
is such as to feel pleasure but not to be led by is enjoyable, valuable, and unselfconscious.
it. (Barnes 1984, pp. 1151b34–1152a3). This sense of flow has been studied across
different fields of skilled expertise, in popu-
Although in both cases the agent acts cor- lations such as dancers and musicians (Hef-
rectly, it is a sign of virtue that the agent has feron & Ollis, 2006; Wrigley & Emmerson,
no contrary temptations. Moral behavior in- 2013). There is a moment when everything
volves a lack of temptation, consistent with “just clicks,” and there is complete absorp-
the model that virtue is unconflicted. tion in the task (Hefferon & Ollis, 2006,
p. 148). Annas (2011) argues that this sense
of flow is also attainable for agents engaged
Virtue as Skilled Expertise in moral behavior: “The activity is experi-
enced as unhindered, unselfconscious, and
Psychology research can help to adjudicate effortless” (p. 72). Conflicted virtue is not
between these two models of virtue as con- consistent with this sort of flow experience;
flicted or unconflicted for the moral agent. internal conflict requires attention to be fo-
If virtue is conflicted, moral behavior char- cused on resolving the disagreement, rather
acteristically involves overcoming compet- than allowing attention to become com-
ing inclinations and resisting temptations. pletely immersed in the goals of the activity.
The contrary view, that virtue is uncon- Annas (2011) says, “The merely continent
flicted, suggests that moral behavior comes person does the right thing, and is even guid-
easily and perhaps fluidly to those who are ed to doing the right thing by developing vir-
virtuous. tue, but has other commitments and values
An unconflicted view of virtue has been that conflict with the exercise of virtue”
defended by Julia Annas (2011), drawing (p. 75). Fully virtuous individuals will lack
on psychology research to support classical these conflicting commitments and values,
Aristotelian conceptions of virtue. Annas allowing them to act in an unconflicted way.
 Unconflicted Virtue 489

The notion of an unconflicted moral agent expert doctors or police officers might still
is consistent with psychology literature on be expected to experience conflict given the
other forms of expertise. The most virtuous nature of their goals. It seems that treating
agents, like other experts, have cultivated a a medical problem would require consider-
skill that allows them to perform complex ing competing options.1 It is also more dif-
behavior more effectively. Experts may not ficult to identify the criteria for skilled per-
experience conflict because their skill allows formance in some domains than others; it’s
them to interact with the environment in a easier to define expertise in chess than in
different way than novices do. For example, medicine (Ericsson, 2015). If moral skill is
when the problem-solving behavior of ex- more similar to medical skill, it might seem
pert and novice pilots in a simulated situa- similarly implausible to suggest that a vir-
tion was studied, experts spent more of their tuous agent will regularly act in an uncon-
attention (as measured through eye-tracking flicted way. Some types of skilled expertise
software) on the details that were essential appear to rely more closely on cognitive
to the problem at hand (Schriver, Morrow, monitoring and competing inclinations that
Wickens, & Talleur, 2008). An agent with would generate conflict for the agent. Even
expertise in a skill might have better devel- if moral behavior gets easier with practice, it
oped mental models, sharper perceptions, might not seem like a virtuous agent will act
and efficient patterns of attention, all of in the fluid way that Annas (2011) suggests.
which contribute to an unconflicted task
performance. This is consistent with Mc-
Dowell’s (1979) description of the virtuous Testing Moral Behavior
agent’s perceptual skill. Virtue is “an abil-
ity to recognize requirements which situa- Researchers can study moral decision mak-
tions impose on one’s behavior. It is a single ing by putting participants into a position in
complex sensitivity of this sort which we are which they have the opportunity to act in
aiming to instill when we aim to inculcate an honest or a dishonest manner. Analyz-
a moral outlook” (p. 333). This perception ing the actions of participants can reveal
allows experts to respond to a problem ef- factors that influence moral behavior. One
fectively and without experiencing conflict. hypothesis is that agents who have more
Although research suggests that expert self-control are better able to behave mor-
behavior may often happen fluently, it need ally and that agents who lose these self-
not be considered merely automatic. Even control reserves are more likely to act badly.
behavior that appears highly automated may To test this idea, psychologists gave partici-
rely on elements of cognitive control (Chris- pants opportunities for deception after hav-
tensen, Sutton, & McIlwain, 2016). Agents ing them perform tasks designed to deplete
acquire skills through a process of practice, self-control resources (Mead, Baumeister,
which involves monitoring and reflecting on Gino, Schweitzer, & Ariely, 2009). 2 The re-
performance. Ericsson (2015) has empha- sults showed that cheating was much more
sized the importance of deliberative prac- frequent when participants had depleted
tice in obtaining expertise. It is important self-control, and researchers concluded that
to have access to feedback and to practice “self-control resource depletion led to dis-
in a goal-oriented way in order to acquire honest behavior” (Mead et al., 2009). Simi-
superior skills. This practice may involve re- lar results have been found by other psychol-
peatedly overcoming conflict until an agent ogists (Gino, Schweitzer, Mead, & Ariely,
reaches a point where the action becomes 2011).
unconflicted. This fits closely with a conflicted notion
However, in some domains, it seems odd of virtue, and Foot’s (2002) notion of virtue
to suggest that skilled experts will react in as a corrective. Perhaps moral behavior re-
such unconflicted ways. Imagining an ex- quires some sort of effort, lending plausibil-
pert athlete, it’s possible to picture how the ity to the idea that moral agents act through
behavior may start to come quickly and ef- overcoming conflict. However, moral behav-
fortlessly with expertise. On the other hand, ior might require effort for different reasons,
490 M O R A L B E H AV I O R

and this might not indicate the presence of tion, comparable to the controlled cognitive
conflict. Additionally, these studies are vul- processes that enable the delay of reward. Ac-
nerable to participant expectancy effects. cording to the “Grace” hypothesis, honesty
Participants may expect that self-control is a results from the absence of temptation, consis-
tent with research emphasizing the determina-
resource to be depleted and turn the experi- tion of behavior by the presence or absence of
ment into a self-fulfilling prophecy (Mar- automatic processes. (Greene & Paxton, 2009,
tijn, Tenbült, Merckelbach, Dreezens, & p. 12506)
de Vries, 2002). Other studies have shown
that participants who had their expectations The researchers looked at reaction-time
challenged improved their behavior, show- differences, as well as comparative fMRI
ing less fatigue than other participants and differences, across individuals who either
outperforming other groups (Martijn et al., did or did not cheat. The study examined
2002, p. 449). This work calls into question differences in brain activity when partici-
whether previous research does in fact show pants lost money without the opportunity
that there is a sort of motivational depletion to cheat, compared with losing money by
that influences moral behavior.3 ignoring an available opportunity to cheat
This literature may not directly rule out (choosing to be honest). Reaction-time mea-
the possibility of unconflicted virtuous be- sures were also used to see whether there
havior. The studies above primarily focus on were significant reaction-time differences
individuals behaving badly (cheating) rather when participants had to make a decision
than on individuals behaving well. Even if about whether or not to cheat.
compelling empirical evidence emerges that The results of the study supported the
moral behavior involves effortfully over- “grace” hypothesis—that, for honest indi-
coming conflict, it may be because most of viduals, choosing honesty was an unconflict-
the study participants are merely continent ed decision. Participants who were dishonest
and not yet virtuous. showed differences in reaction times when
Greene and Paxton (2009) performed an there was an opportunity to avoid loss, tak-
fMRI study rewarding participants for cor- ing longer to react when they had the chance
rectly predicting the outcome of a coin flip. to lie. The honest participants did not show
This gave them the opportunity to study this difference in reaction time across condi-
honest behavior in an fMRI. On some of tions, suggesting that, whereas the dishonest
the trials, participants were required to re- participants had to hesitate or consider the
cord their predictions prior to the coin flip, option to lie, honest participants acted just
but other trials were not monitored, so par- as quickly as usual. Importantly, all of the
ticipants had an opportunity to cheat (by honest participants confirmed after the end
recording their “prediction” after the coin of the study that they were aware that there
flip). Participants were told the study was in- was an opportunity to cheat (Greene & Pax-
vestigating paranormal predictive abilities. ton, 2009). The fMRI data showed no dif-
Cheating was determined by statistically ferences in activation within the control net-
analyzing the outcomes to determine which work areas of the brain for the honest group
results were highly unlikely due to chance. between situations with the opportunity to
Based upon the participants’ responses, cheat or without the opportunity to cheat.
some were categorized into the “honest” In contrast, dishonest participants did show
group. The study was designed to examine differences in activation. This reinforces the
the nature of honest behavior. Two hypoth- idea that honest behavior did not require any
eses were tested: Either honest participants additional cognitive resources than usual
were able to behave that way through over- for the honest participants.4 Further studies
coming conflicting inclinations (called the have revealed that for dishonest participants
“Will” hypothesis), or honest participants (compared with honest ones), there was ad-
experienced no conflict and acted easily ditional activation in the reward centers of
(“Grace”). the brain (Abe & Greene, 2014). This also
suggests that dishonest participants may ex-
According to the “Will” hypothesis, honesty perience more temptation than honest par-
results from the active resistance of tempta- ticipants.
 Unconflicted Virtue 491

An Expert Moral Agent this when studying honesty: They isolate a


specific outcome and then examine behav-
The empirical results described above sup- ior relevant to that outcome. Their research
port the notion that moral behavior can focuses on only one subset of moral behav-
occur without conflict for the virtuous agent. ior (honesty), while there may be variation
Virtue can be understood as a complex skill, among different types of virtue. Although
psychologically similar to other forms of ex- unconflicted virtue seems the appropriate
pertise. Greene and Paxton (2009) show that model for honesty, future inquiry may still
for honest participants there do not seem to locate a role for conflict in other moral skills.
be additional cognitive processes at work As with nonmoral skills, the overall re-
when choosing to be honest. This paints a sults seem to be mixed, with some moral
picture of an honest individual for whom behaviors that seem clearly unconflicted
moral behavior comes without conflict. and others that might involve overcoming
This model is consistent with McDowell’s conflict. Both unconflicted and conflicted
(1979) claims that virtue comes without the models of virtue have some intuitive and
agent experiencing competing temptations. philosophic support. The existing psychol-
This model of unconflicted virtue shows ogy literature lends support to the model of
that while practice is important for gaining virtue as an unconflicted skill. Understand-
moral expertise, ultimately the behavior is ing virtue as a skill requires careful thinking
unconflicted and fluid. about the exact nature of the skill, in order
A worry remains that unconflicted moral to better understand the nature of virtuous
behavior seems implausible in some cases. expertise. Current literature focuses primar-
Perhaps this is because it is so rare: many ily on one type of moral expertise, but there
people will be merely continent, as Aristo- might be variations. Future inquiry may be
tle points out. A virtuous agent has become more successful in understanding virtue by
familiar with how to properly attend to the separating out specific types of moral behav-
various requirements of a given moral situa- ior, rather than treating virtue as unitary. If
tion, and this is what explains the ease and virtue is a skill like honesty, then the truly
unconflicted nature of his or her action. virtuous agent will be unconflicted.
When an agent is fully immersed in moral
action, competing inclinations are silenced. ACKNOWLEDGMENT
Full immersion in an activity still seems
more plausible for some moral skills than Thanks to John Doris for his assistance with this
others. It might seem strange to think of chapter.
a moral agent acting in a state of flow, es-
pecially in particularly complex situations.
Intuitions about non-moral skilled expertise NOTES
can vary according to the nature of the skill:
Although a musician might act without con- 1. Ericsson (2015) has pointed out the impor-
tance of cognitive monitoring in the medical
flict, the same might not be said for a doc- field.
tor. The moral domain might similarly be 2. Participants were instructed to score them-
composed of a variety of skills, only some of selves and pay themselves (using quarters in
which seem unconflicted. an envelope in front of them) based upon the
Annas (2011) argues that virtues can all number of successes in the task. Participants
be understood similarly according to the in the study completed a puzzle task, and half
model of fluid skilled expertise. However, of them were given an opportunity to cheat
skilled expertise often looks different in dif- on the task by scoring their own performance
ferent domains. This means that it may be without the experimenter. Half of the partici-
pants were exposed to a self-control depletion
important to examine moral virtues sepa-
task prior to being given the opportunity to
rately, clarifying what type of skill is being cheat.
examined in each case. Specifying the crite- 3. The authors argue that “the occurrence of the
ria for the successful performance of a skill ego depletion phenomenon is strongly influ-
is necessary for studying expertise (Erics- enced by expectancies or schemata about self-
son, 2015). Green and Paxton (2009) do control” (Martijn et al., 2002, p. 441).
492 M O R A L B E H AV I O R

4. The authors conclude that the honest partici- Ariely, D. (2011). Unable to resist temptation:
pants “showed no sign of engaging additional How self-control depletion promotes unethi-
control processes (or other processes) when cal behavior. Organizational Behavior and
choosing to forgo opportunities for dishonest Human Decision Processes, 115(2), 191–203.
gain” (Greene & Paxton, 2009, p. 12508). Greene, J. D., & Paxton, J. M. (2009). Patterns
of neural activity associated with honest and
dishonest moral decisions. Proceedings of the
REFERENCES National Academy of Sciences of the USA,
106(30), 12506–12511.
Abe, N., & Greene, J. D. (2014). Response to Hefferon, K. M., & Ollis, S. (2006). “Just clicks”:
anticipated reward in the nucleus accumbens An interpretive phenomenological analysis of
predicts behavior in an independent test of professional dancers’ experience of flow. Re-
honesty. Journal of Neuroscience, 34(32), search in Dance Education, 7(2), 141–159.
10564–10572. Mandela, N. (1994). Long walk to freedom: The
Annas, J. (2011). Intelligent virtue. Oxford, UK: autobiography of Nelson Mandela. Boston:
Oxford University Press. Little, Brown and Company.
Baldas, T. (2015, February 26). Acts of cour- Martijn, C., Tenbült, P., Merckelbach, H.,
age: The ordinary doing the extraordinary. Dreezens, E., & de Vries, N. K. (2002). Get-
USA Today. Available at www.usatoday. ting a grip on ourselves: Challenging expec-
com/story/news/nation/2015/02/26/acts-of- tancies about loss of energy after self-control.
courage-the-ordinary-doing-the-extraordi- Social Cognition, 20(6), 441–460.
nary/24029119. McDowell, J. (1979). Virtue and reason. The
Barnes, J. (Ed.). (1984). The complete works of Monist, 62(3), 331–350.
Aristotle: Nichomachean ethics. Princeton, McDowell, J., & McFetridge, I. G. (1978). Are
NJ: Princeton University Press. moral requirements hypothetical imperatives?
Baxley, A. (2007). The price of virtue. Pacific (Suppl. Vol.). Proceedings of the Aristotelian
Philosophical Quarterly, 88(4), 403–423. Society, 52, 13–42. Available at www.jstor.
Christensen, W., Sutton, J., & McIlwain, D. J. org/stable/4106788.
F. (2016). Cognition in skilled action: Meshed Mead, N. L., Baumeister, R. F., Gino, F., Sch-
control and the varieties of skill experience. weitzer, M. E., & Ariely, D. (2009). Too tired
Mind and Language, 31(1), 37–66. to tell the truth: Self-control resource deple-
Comey, H. N., & Comey, L. R. (2004). A legacy tion and dishonesty. Journal of Experimental
of valor: The memoirs and letters of Captain Social Psychology, 45(3), 594–597.
Henry Newton Comey, 2nd Massachusetts Piccoli, S. (2015). Teacher who disarmed student
Infantry. Knoxville: University of Tennessee gunman: I’m no hero. Available at www.news-
Press. max.com/Newsmax-Tv/high-school-teacher-
Csikszentmihalyi, M., & LeFevre, J. (1989). Op- washington-disarmed/2015/05/11/id/643939.
timal experience in work and leisure. Journal Schriver, A. T., Morrow, D. G., Wickens, C.
of Personality and Social Psychology, 56(5), D., & Talleur, D. A. (2008). Expertise differ-
815–822. ences in attentional strategies related to pilot
Ericsson, K. A. (2015). Acquisition and mainte- decision making. Human Factors: Journal of
nance of medical expertise: A perspective from the Human Factors and Ergonomics Society,
the expert-performance approach with delib- 50(6), 864–878.
erate practice. Academic Medicine, 90(11), Stohr, K. E. (2003). Moral cacophony: When
1471–1486. continence is a virtue. Journal of Ethics, 7(4),
Foot, P. (2002). Virtues and vices. In Virtues 339–363.
and vices and other essays in moral philoso- Wrigley, W. J., & Emmerson, S. B. (2013). The
phy (pp. 1–18). New York: Oxford University experience of the flow state in live music per-
Press. formance. Psychology of Music, 41(3), 292–
Gino, F., Schweitzer, M. E., Mead, N. L., & 305.
CHAPTER 50

Moral Clarity

Scott S. Wiltermuth
David T. Newman

How do people come to possess different levels of moral clarity,


which denotes the degree of ambiguity people perceive when
judging whether behaviors are right or wrong?

We argue that the experience of moral clarity depends on both


cognitive processing and affective appraisals of certainty; addition‑
ally, we describe how moral clarity has innate origins but can be
heightened or repressed by the influence of parents, teachers, peers,
and culture.

Some people are baffled that others seem to clarity and why individuals differ in how
see behavior in such clear terms of right and much ambiguity they perceive in moral judg-
wrong, good and bad, and black and white. ments. We first examine whether a sense of
They struggle to understand how those oth- moral clarity is more likely to develop from
ers miss so much nuance that they do not rec- intuitive or deliberative forms of processing.
ognize that it is not always clear whether be- We then examine which cognitive processes
haviors are morally right or morally wrong. are likely to give rise to a heightened sense
Those who do see clear distinctions between of moral clarity. We investigate specifically
right and wrong are equally baffled by the whether the processes are general in that
inability of those who see shades of gray they also give rise to certainty in nonmoral
everywhere to diagnose right from wrong, judgments or whether they are specific to
good from bad, and black from white. moral judgments. We also examine how the
These differences in moral clarity—the consequences of moral clarity differ from
degree of ambiguity people perceive when the consequences of certainty on nonmoral
judging whether behaviors are right or issues. Next, we address whether people
wrong (Wiltermuth & Flynn, 2013)—may have a fixed, innate sense of moral clarity or
be socially determined. In this chapter, we whether moral clarity is a learned attitude
explore how people develop a sense of moral that is, at times, cultivated and, at other

493
494 M O R A L B E H AV I O R

times, suppressed through education. Final- evaluations tend to promote certainty when
ly, we discuss whether cultural values, such people express opinions or evaluate familiar
as individualism–collectivism and power objects, whereas slow evaluations generally
distance, influence the degree to which peo- promote certainty when people form new
ple see ambiguity in the judgment of moral opinions or evaluate unfamiliar objects.
behaviors. Morality is familiar to most adults, or even
organized by evolutionary mechanisms in
advance of individual experience (Haidt,
Intuitive versus Deliberative 2007); it is reasonable to suppose that moral
judgment is more like expressing than form-
Moral Clarity May Be Greater with Intuition
ing an opinion. Thus moral judgment is most
than with Deliberation
likely to demonstrate clarity when proceed-
Intuition, contrasted with reasoning, is a ing directly from intuition.
kind of cognition that occurs quickly, ef- Tetlock’s (2003) work on taboo trade-offs
fortlessly, and automatically, such that the indicates that we expect people to distinguish
outcome but not the process is accessible to right from wrong quickly and easily, and ex-
consciousness (Haidt, 2001). Haidt’s model cessive deliberation on the relative worth of
of intuitive ethics proposes that moral intu- sacred values (e.g., justice) may signal a lack
itions are activated immediately in response of moral clarity and thereby cast doubt on
to morally relevant facts, with effortful, de- an individual’s moral character. Some ex-
liberative moral reasoning occurring only changes (e.g., money for human dignity) are
after a judgment has already been made. considered unthinkable, and people respond
Empirical studies have tended to confirm the to the contemplation of such trade-offs with
view that affective intuition plays a larger moral outrage, cleansing, and value reaffir-
role than deliberate reasoning in the process mation (Tetlock, Kristel, Elson, Green, &
of moral judgment (Greene & Haidt, 2002). Lerner, 2000). Moral clarity displayed via
People often claim to know with certainty intuitive judgment may, therefore, serve as
that an action is morally wrong even when a yardstick by which to measure ethical up-
they cannot marshal reasoning to support rightness in ourselves and others.
their intuition (Haidt, 2007). Hence we
might expect that judgments driven by intu-
Information Processing and Clarity
ition evince greater moral clarity than those
reached through careful deliberation. In contrast to the foregoing, research on in-
Research on the amount of time allowed formation processing has at times implied
to make decisions supports this expecta- that cognitive elaboration, or the thought-
tion. Inhibiting deliberation through ma- fulness with which one considers informa-
nipulations of time alters moral judgments tion relevant to an evaluation, enhances
in response to dilemmas involving the kill- attitude certainty (Smith, Fabrigar, Mac-
ing of one person to save many (Suter & Dougall, & Wiesenthal, 2008). However,
Hertwig, 2011). Time pressure yields fast recent evidence suggests that this effect is
deontological gut reactions (e.g., killing is driven primarily by people’s perceptions of
wrong), whereas time availability enables their own elaboration and naïve theories
consequentialist deliberations (e.g., the lives that elaboration produces better judgments
of many outweigh the life of one) to override (Barden & Tormala, 2014). Because of the
the initial response. Furthermore, direct ma- fluency with which people can generate post
nipulations of deliberative decision making hoc reasoning to justify their intuitive judg-
have been shown to increase deception and ments (Haidt, 2001), a quick, clear, intuitive
decrease altruism (Zhong, 2011), suggesting moral judgment may often give rise to an im-
that deliberation obscures our intuitive un- pression of thoughtful processing.
derstanding of moral behavior by permitting Attitude accessibility is associated with
rationalization of unethical conduct. greater attitude strength (Holland, Verplan-
These findings comport with work on the ken, & Van Knippenberg, 2003), entail-
effect of the perceived time taken to generate ing that intuitive judgments come stamped
an evaluation on attitude certainty (Torma- with the imprimatur of certainty by virtue
la, Clarkson, & Henderson, 2011). Quick of their ease of retrieval. Over a lifetime of
 Moral Clarity 495

experience and repetition, moral intuition One, Two, or Many Processes


is elevated to moral conviction. Clarity in
Degrees of Clarity across Moral Domains
moral judgment is also enhanced by the
certainty appraisals imbued in morally rel- Individuals are predisposed to different trait
evant emotions, such as anger, disgust, hap- levels of clarity in the moral domain (Wilter-
piness, and contentment (Tiedens & Linton, muth & Flynn, 2013). However, the moral
2001). These emotions occur with a sense domain is not a monolith; moral founda-
of certainty and promote heuristic (intui- tions theory proposes the existence of plural
tive) processing, whereas emotions such as moral domains whose values are sometimes
hope, surprise, worry, and sadness occur in conflict (Graham et al., 2013). Morality
with a sense of uncertainty and promote is an adaptive characteristic of our species,
systematic (deliberative) processing. If intui- born out of several clusters of innate intu-
tive processes heighten perceptions of moral itions naturally selected over countless gen-
clarity, we would therefore expect people to erations of human development. In a similar
perceive themselves to have greater moral vein, moral clarity may be an adaptation for
clarity when experiencing emotions associ- successfully converting our moral intuitions
ated with certainty. into concordant behavior. We may therefore
We may also expect cognitive depletion to expect that, just as endorsement of each
result in greater moral clarity. Information moral foundation (e.g., care, fairness, loyal-
processing is often inhibited by ego deple- ty, authority, sanctity) varies from person to
tion, leading people to rely heavily on auto- person, so, too, does the clarity with which
matic processes such as intuition when they individuals form judgments in each domain.
are ego-depleted (Baumeister, Muraven, People who strongly endorse a particular
& Tice, 2000). Research on consumer re- moral foundation may experience greater
sponses to advertising has found that atti- certainty within that domain than would
tudes formed under conditions of depletion people for whom the same foundation is of
exhibit greater certainty and influence on lesser concern.
purchase behavior (Wan, Rucker, Tormala, This view is substantiated by work show-
& Clarkson, 2010). Feeling depleted may ing the effect of moral foundations framing
increase certainty through the perception on political attitudes. Feinberg and Willer
that substantial information processing has (2013) found that most environmental dis-
taken place. Consequently, we may expect course centers on concerns of harm and care,
that ego-depleted individuals will form with liberals but not conservatives viewing
moral judgments based on intuition and the environment in moral terms. Reframing
with a high degree of clarity. environmental rhetoric in terms of purity re-
duces the gap between liberals and conserva-
tives, suggesting a change in conservatives’
Epiphanies and Inspiration
moral judgments even on an issue for which
Epiphanies and prophetic experiences, inso- they may have previously perceived little am-
far as they impel individuals to adopt a par- biguity. Framing issues using moral founda-
ticular course of conduct deemed virtuous tions may shift political attitudes through
or obligatory, may represent extreme ver- either entrenchment or persuasion (Day,
sions of moral clarity. Those who experience Fiske, Downing, & Trail, 2014). Relevant
divine communication frequently report it moral foundation frames entrench political
as thoughts or feelings simply appearing in attitudes for both liberals and conservatives,
their minds, accompanied by a sense of ab- presumably by enhancing the moral clarity
solute clarity and authority (Dein & Cook, with which the issues are judged. Persuasion,
2015). Epiphanic experiences are usually on the other hand, has been found only for
accompanied by awe, an emotion character- conservative-relevant moral frames of liberal
ized primarily by a sense of vastness and a issues. This is not to say that other instances
need for accommodation (Keltner & Haidt, of persuasion are impossible—clearly they
2003). It seems likely that the emotion of occur all the time—but some framings may
awe includes a certainty appraisal, which be more persuasive than others for specific
may drive the intense clarity associated with types of people. Graham, Haidt, and Nosek
inspiration. (2009) observed that conservatives endorse
496 M O R A L B E H AV I O R

all five foundations about equally, whereas to rationalize preferred moral conclusions
liberals assign preeminence to care and fair- (Uhlmann, Pizarro, Tannenbaum, & Ditto,
ness. Conservatives may accordingly experi- 2009). Rather than acting as intuitive sci-
ence moral clarity in more varied contexts entists seeking the truth, people behave like
than do liberals. intuitive politicians, theologians, and pros-
ecutors who advocate, protect, and enforce
the values to which they are already commit-
Manichaeism and Dogmatism
ted (Tetlock, 2002). This implies that moral
Manichaeism, originally a religion founded clarity may be greatest when individuals are
by the Iranian prophet Mani, now refers in a persuasive or combative mode.
to any dualistic worldview that pits good This view is supported by evidence that
against evil or us against them. Manichaean attitude certainty increases when individu-
thinking may be an expression of high trait- als resist attempts at persuasion (Tormala
level moral clarity, which leads people to & Petty, 2002). Conversely, increasing at-
experience the moral universe in black and titude certainty tends to amplify the domi-
white. Alternatively, individuals who are nant effects of attitude on judgment, such
taught Manichaean thinking as dogma may that univalent attitudes become more resis-
resultantly develop greater clarity in judg- tant to persuasion and ambivalent attitudes
ing relevant moral issues. Although power- less resistant (Clarkson, Tormala, & Ruck-
ful convictions about right and wrong may er, 2008). Thus certainty enables people to
sometimes encourage prosocial behaviors, see clearly whether their judgments support
they also underlie acts of ideologically driv- one or multiple perspectives in a persuasive
en violence and terrorism (Skitka & Mullen, context. Because explanatory reasoning
2002). has a way of reinforcing existing positions,
Extreme views on both ends of the lib- morally oriented conversation promotes
­
eral–conservative spectrum are associated honest behavior by clarifying ethical val-
with dogmatic beliefs about the correct- ues (Gunia, Wang, Huang, Wang, & Mur-
ness of one’s position (Toner, Leary, Asher, nighan, 2012).
& Jongman-Sereno, 2013), yielding politi-
cal intolerance that cuts both left and right
Time and Distance
(Crawford & Pilanski, 2014). Political par-
tisans are likely to support discrimination If folk wisdom is to be believed, people per-
against those who violate their moral values ceive events more clearly with the benefit
(Wetherell, Brandt, & Reyna, 2013), and of time and distance. This view of clarity is
conversation across the aisle may make the supported by evidence from construal level
situation worse, not better: In developing theory demonstrating that people judge im-
their Manichaeism scale, Johnson, Motyl, moral actions more harshly, and moral ac-
and Graham (2015) found that individu- tions more approvingly, when the actions
als who discussed abortion or gun control are psychologically distant (Eyal, Liberman,
with someone who held an opposing stance & Trope, 2008). Distal objects and behav-
showed increases in Manichaeism compared iors are construed more abstractly, such that
with those who talked with someone who individuals’ evaluations are less susceptible
agreed with them. Like visual acuity, moral to contextual influence and more reflective
clarity may be facilitated by the presence of of ideological commitments (Ledgerwood,
contrast. Trope, & Chaiken, 2010). Hence we form
moral judgments most clearly when consid-
ering events far in the past or future or when
Persuasion
judging people across the divide of conti-
There is increasing acknowledgment that nents or social class. Moreover, we apply
the primary function of human reasoning the moral clarity of distance to our own
may be not epistemic but argumentative self-concept, strongly rejecting the represen-
(Mercier & Sperber, 2011). Motivated rea- tativeness of distant-future behaviors that
soning is particularly evident in the selec- violate our acknowledged values (Wakslak,
tive application of general moral principles Nussbaum, Liberman, & Trope, 2008).
 Moral Clarity 497

General or Specific Processes clarity with which people make moral judg-


ments.
The preceding discussion illustrates that Given that the same factors seem to con-
numerous processes influence the sense of tribute to clarity in moral and nonmoral
clarity people have when making moral beliefs, one might legitimately ask whether
judgments. Numerous factors also increase it is possible to be highly certain in moral
the sense of certainty that people feel when domains and less certain in other domains.
making decisions outside of the domain of The proposition is entirely untested, but we
morality. This raises the question of whether can imagine people who are not especially
the process of developing moral clarity dif- confident in their own bases of knowledge,
fers from the process of developing non- or in their tastes, possessing a strong sense
moral forms of clarity or certainty, such as of right and wrong if they see that sense
overconfidence in forecasting. It also raises of right and wrong as something that was
the question of whether the downstream handed down to them by God or by their
consequences of moral clarity differ from parents. Such people would have a high level
the consequences generated by other forms of moral clarity but relatively little clarity in
of clarity. other judgments.

Antecedents Consequences
Little research has examined the anteced- Moral clarity may produce different con-
ents of moral clarity. Wiltermuth and Flynn sequences than does certainty or clarity on
(2012), however, found that people who nonmoral issues. Evidence for this comes
possess power also develop a heightened from a study by Skitka, Bauman, and Sar-
sense of moral clarity and consequently gis (2005) on moral convictions and the at-
punish others more severely for perceived titudes (i.e., moral mandates) that stem from
transgressions than do people who lack those convictions. Skitka and colleagues
power. Moreover, Lammers and Stapel (2005) found that convictions on moral is-
(2009) found that power increases people’s sues, on which people would possess high
reliance on deontological or formalist forms levels of moral clarity, led people to feel
of moral reasoning over teleological or utili- greater antipathy toward individuals who
tarian approaches. To the extent that relying held dissimilar views on those issues than
on one principle of action increases moral did similar differences in attitudes that were
clarity relative to relying on a calculation of not based on moral issues. To the extent that
situationally dependent costs and benefits, disagreements based on moral convictions
power may increase moral clarity by chang- are more deleterious toward cooperativeness
ing people’s approaches to ethical decision and tolerance of others than are disagree-
making. ments based on nonmoral attitudes, it be-
The effects of power on nonmoral atti- comes especially important to understand
tudes parallel the effects of power on moral why people come to develop such strong
clarity. Power similarly makes people over- moral attitudes and see moral issues with
confident of their knowledge of factual mat- such (justified or unjustified) clarity.
ters (Fast, Sivanathan, Mayer, & Galinsky,
2012) and leads people to engage in con-
firmatory information processing (Fischer, Innate, Learned, or Both?
Fischer, Englich, Aydin, & Frey, 2011),
which could cause them to be more certain A growing body of research suggests that
in all their attitudes, moral and nonmoral people have an innate sense of right and
alike. Factors that strengthen people’s atti- wrong. Some of the strongest evidence for
tude certainty, such as perceived consensus, this claim comes, perhaps oddly, from non-
the number of times they have voiced that humans. Capuchin monkeys will reject re-
attitude, and the ease with which they can wards for tasks when their rewards seem
defend the attitude (for review, see Tormala inequitable in comparison with the rewards
& Rucker, 2007) are also likely to affect the received by other capuchins (Brosnan & de
498 M O R A L B E H AV I O R

Waal, 2003). Thus species sharing a com- view. Additionally, they may be motivated to
mon ancestry with humans further share a construe any information about an issue as
sense of fairness. Human babies as young as supportive of their initial position. If these
15 months can also detect unfairness when processes occur, moral clarity may be self-
it occurs, as evidenced by the longer gaze reinforcing.
they give to experimenters when those ex- Such processes are particularly likely to
perimenters administer unequal portions of occur if people feel that their self-views or
food to people than when those experiment- core beliefs are threatened (Munro & Ditto,
ers administer equal portions (Schmidt & 2007; Munro & Stansbury, 2009). In such
Sommerville, 2011). Infants as young as 6 instances, people dig in their heels and seek
months show preferences for prosocial indi- to discredit any information that under-
viduals over antisocial individuals (Hamlin, mines the views they hold dear (Greenwald,
Wynn, & Boom, 2007). Moreover, cross- 1980). As such, moral clarity may be partic-
cultural research has demonstrated that ularly self-reinforcing when people’s values
some moral precepts, such as “do not harm collide and those who already perceive little
others,” are common across cultures. ambiguity in the moral matters at hand feel
The strong evidence that people possess that their views are under threat.
innate moral compasses suggests that some
level of moral clarity is probably innate.
However, it does not necessarily suggest that Cultural Influences
moral clarity is entirely innate. A large lit-
erature has shown that parents heavily influ- The culture surrounding an individual may
ence the values held by their children (e.g., influence how much of a sense of moral clar-
Lapsley & Power, 2005). By placing high ity that individual possesses. One way that
importance on some values and less impor- culture may influence how much ambigu-
tance on others, parents likely also influence ity people perceive is through norms about
the degree of ambiguity children see in vari- which behaviors are morally appropriate,
ous situations regarding those values. They which behaviors are morally tolerable, and
may do so through their direct conversations which behaviors are grounds for moral cen-
with their children and through their choic- sure. For example, in some cultures there
es about the environments (e.g., schools, re- may be a strong norm against nepotism,
ligious institutions) in which their children whereas in other cultures the practice may
spend their time. Peers no doubt have effects be seen as a natural and acceptable exten-
as well on which values individuals come sion of loyalty to one’s ingroup. In cultures
to hold with a great sense of clarity. Moral in which there is strong social consensus
clarity on specific issues may therefore have that a behavior is either immoral or moral,
a learned component. people may possess a high sense of moral
It is similarly possible that parents, teach- clarity on the issue (Jones, 1991). When the
ers, and others could influence moral clarity prevailing societal view is less clear, people
in individuals across a range of domains and may possess less clarity.
issues by instilling a questioning attitude, Culture may also influence behavior more
such that they train children to question the systematically. Hofstede (1979, 1983) estab-
stances that people take on issues and see lished four dimensions on which cultures
the nuances in ethically charged situations. can vary: individualism/collectivism, power
By the same token, parents may encourage distance, masculinity/femininity, and uncer-
moral clarity by encouraging steadfast ad- tainty avoidance. Uncertainty avoidance is
herence to some principles. the dimension most relevant to moral clarity
Once an individual develops a sense of and is defined as “the extent to which indi-
clarity about an issue, that person may be- viduals within a culture are made nervous
come highly unlikely to change his or her by situations that are unstructured, unclear,
opinion about the issue, because, consistent or unpredictable, and the extent to which
with the confirmation bias (for a review, these individuals attempt to avoid such situ-
see Nickerson, 1998), they may selectively ations by adopting strict codes of behavior
attend to information that supports their and a belief in absolute truth” (Vitell, Nwa-
 Moral Clarity 499

chukwu, & Barnes, 1993, p. 754). People Future research could and should deter-
may possess heightened levels of moral clar- mine whether moral clarity differs depend-
ity in countries such as Germany and Japan, ing upon the level of uncertainty avoidance
which are characterized by high levels of in a culture and the degree to which people
uncertainty avoidance, relative to people in in that culture espouse dualistic philoso-
Singapore and the United Kingdom, which phies. We hope that it also further examines
are characterized by low levels of uncertain- what moral clarity looks like when people
ty avoidance. strongly adhere to using relativistic or cul-
The philosophies or religions foundational turally specific standards of behavior. Some
to a culture may also influence the strength people worry that certainty of any kind has
of moral clarity an individual from that cul- become the casualty of a postmodern age
ture will possess. In Chinese culture, the in which all beliefs and judgments are con-
religions of Taoism and (to a lesser extent) sidered socially constructed and situation-
Confucianism feature the yin and the yang, ally dependent, but it is equally possible that
suggesting that two opposite forces (such as such firmly relativistic contentions evince
light and dark) are present and necessary for their own form of moral clarity.
each to exist. These two opposite forces are
seen as working not against each other but
rather with each other to achieve a perfect Conclusion
balance (e.g., Garrett, 1993). In the graphi-
cal representation of yin and yang, there is a Throughout our lives we expect and are
drop of yin in the yang and a drop of yang expected to know right from wrong. Ordi-
in the yin. Viewed through this lens, actions nary citizens, prominent figures, and even
may be seen as not purely moral or purely entire governments are routinely criticized
immoral but rather some mix of these. We for showing an absence of moral clarity. On
might, therefore, expect people to exhibit the other hand, some people may find over-
lower levels of moral clarity in cultures in confidence about moral issues to be narrow-
which Taoist and related philosophies are minded or oppressive. Hence moral clarity
followed. Indeed, scholars have suggested occupies a unique position in our social en-
that following such philosophies encourages vironment compared with certainty about
people to adopt multiple perspectives when factual knowledge or personal preferences.
analyzing behavior (Johnson, 2000). Moral clarity acts as both a motive for indi-
Adopting multiple perspectives when ana- vidual conduct and a signal in interpersonal
lyzing behavior may correlate with people relations. Paradoxically, clarity enables us to
taking a relativistic rather than an absolu- direct our will yet simultaneously constrains
tistic approach to ethics. People who take our decisions. Without any clarity whatsoev-
a relativistic view would argue that society er, we would be helpless to choose between
defines what is moral and immoral and, as all available options, but extreme clarity can
societies differ, so too might the meanings restrict the many possibilities for action to a
of moral and immoral, right and wrong, dif- single unequivocal path. Moral clarity may
fer across cultures (Forsyth & Berger, 1982). be seen in this light as a valve controlling the
One could legitimately ask whether it is pos- flow of judgment and behavior. Investigat-
sible to have a strong sense of moral clar- ing the forces that turn this mechanism, and
ity when using relativistic forms of moral the downstream consequences that follow,
judgment. We would posit that one could will open a new channel to understanding
have a sense of moral clarity using relativ- the dynamics of morality.
istic judgments, but that the moral clarity of
such judgments would likely stem from one’s
REFERENCES
confidence in the prevailing views of soci-
ety. Moral clarity using absolute (i.e., invari- Barden, J., & Tormala, Z. L. (2014). Elaboration
ant) standards of moral judgment is easier to and attitude strength: The new meta-cognitive
understand, as it would correspond to how perspective. Social and Personality Psychol-
sure an individual is that a behavior violates ogy Compass, 8(1), 17–29.
an absolute principle. Baumeister, R. F., Muraven, M., & Tice, D. M.
500 M O R A L B E H AV I O R

(2000). Ego depletion: A resource model of vo- rication and revision of personal histories.
lition, self-regulation, and controlled process- American Psychologist, 35, 603–618.
ing. Social Cognition, 18(2), 130–150. Gunia, B. C., Wang, L., Huang, L., Wang, J., &
Brosnan, S., & de Waal, F. B. M. (2003). Mon- Murnighan, J. K. (2012). Contemplation and
keys reject unequal pay. Nature, 425, 297– conversation: Subtle influences on moral deci-
299. sion making. Academy of Management Jour-
Clarkson, J. J., Tormala, Z. L., & Rucker, D. D. nal, 55(1), 13–33.
(2008). A new look at the consequences of at- Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional dog and its ra-
titude certainty: The amplification hypothesis. tional tail: A social intuitionist approach
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, to moral judgment. Psychological Review,
95(4), 810–825. 108(4), 814–834.
Crawford, J. T. & Pilanski, J. M. (2014). Political Haidt, J. (2007). The new synthesis in moral psy-
intolerance, Right and Left. Political Psychol- chology. Science, 316(5827), 998–1002.
ogy, 35(6), 841–851. Hamlin J. K., Wynn, K., & Bloom P. (2007). So-
Day, M. V., Fiske, S. T., Downing, E. L., & Trail, cial evaluation by preverbal infants. Nature,
T. E. (2014). Shifting liberal and conserva- 450, 557–559.
tive attitudes using moral foundations theory. Hofstede, G. (1979). Value systems in forty
Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, countries: Interpretation, validation, and con-
40(12), 1559–1573. sequences for theory. In L. H. Eckensberger,
Dein, S., & Cook, C. C. H. (2015). God put a W. J. Lonner, & Y. H. Poortinga (Eds.),
thought into my mind: The charismatic Chris- Cross-cultural contributions to psychology
tian experience of receiving communications (pp. 398–407). Lisse, The Netherlands: Swets
from God. Mental Health, Religion and Cul- & Zeitlinger.
ture, 18(2), 97–113. Hofstede, G. (1983). Dimensions of national cul-
Eyal, T., Liberman, N., & Trope, Y. (2008). ture in fifty countries and three regions. In J.
Judging near and distant virtue and vice. Jour- B. Deregowski, S. Dziurawiec, & R. C. Annios
nal of Experimental Social Psychology, 44(4), (Eds.), Expiscations in cross-cultural psychol-
1204–1209. ogy (pp. 335–355). Lisse, The Netherlands:
Fast, N. J., Sivanathan, N., Mayer, N. D., & Ga- Swets & Zeitlinger.
linsky, A. D. (2012). Power and overconfident Holland, R. W., Verplanken, B., & Van Knippen-
decision-making. Organizational Behavior berg, A. (2003). From repetition to conviction:
and Human Decision Processes, 117(2), 249– Attitude accessibility as a determinant of atti-
260. tude certainty. Journal of Experimental Social
Feinberg, M., & Willer, R. (2013). The moral Psychology, 39(6), 594–601.
roots of environmental attitudes. Psychologi- Johnson, C. (2000). Taoist leadership ethics.
cal Science, 24(1), 56–62. Journal of Leadership and Organizational
Fischer, J., Fischer, P., Englich, B., Aydin, N., & Studies, 7(1), 82–91.
Frey, D. (2011). Empower my decisions: The Johnson, K., Motyl, M., & Graham, J. (2015).
effects of power gestures on confirmatory in- Measuring Manichaeism: Moral intuitions
formation processing. Journal of Experimen- and political extremism. Unpublished manu-
tal Social Psychology, 47(6), 1146–1154. script.
Forsyth, D. R., & Berger, R. E. (1982). The ef- Jones, T. M. (1991). Ethical decision making by
fects of ethical ideology on moral behavior. individuals in organizations: An issue-con-
Journal of Social Psychology, 117(1), 53–56. tingent model. Academy of Management Re-
Garrett, M. (1993). Pathos reconsidered from the view, 16(2), 366–395.
perspective of classical Chinese rhetorical the- Keltner, D., & Haidt, J. (2003). Approaching
ories. Quarterly Journal of Speech, 79, 19–39. awe, a moral, spiritual, and aesthetic emotion.
Graham, J., Haidt, J., Koleva, S., Motyl, M., Iyer, Cognition and Emotion, 17(2), 297–314.
R., Wojcik, S., & Ditto, P. H. (2013). Moral Lammers, J., & Stapel, D. A. (2009). How power
foundations theory: The pragmatic validity of influences moral thinking. Journal of Person-
moral pluralism. Advances in Experimental ality and Social Psychology, 97, 279–289.
Social Psychology, 47, 55–130. Lapsley, D. K., & Power, F. C. (Eds.). (2005).
Graham, J., Haidt, J., & Nosek, B. A. (2009). Character psychology and character educa-
Liberals and conservatives rely on different tion (pp. 140–165). Notre Dame, IN: Univer-
sets of moral foundations. Journal of Personal- sity of Notre Dame Press.
ity and Social Psychology, 96(5), 1029–1046. Ledgerwood, A., Trope, Y., & Chaiken, S.
Greene, J., & Haidt, J. (2002). How (and where) (2010). Flexibility now, consistency later: Psy-
does moral judgment work? Trends in Cogni- chological distance and construal shape evalu-
tive Sciences, 6(12), 517–523. ative responding. Journal of Personality and
Greenwald, G. (1980). The totalitarian ego: Fab- Social Psychology, 99(1), 32–51.
 Moral Clarity 501

Mercier, H., & Sperber, D. (2011). Why do hu- The effects of specific emotions on informa-
mans reason?: Arguments for an argumenta- tion processing. Journal of Personality and
tive theory. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, Social Psychology, 81(6), 973–988.
34(2), 57–111. Toner, K., Leary, M. R., Asher, M. W., & Jong-
Munro, G. D., & Ditto, P. H. (1997). Biased as- man-Sereno, K. P. (2013). Feeling superior is a
similation, attitude polarization, and affect in bipartisan issue: Extremity (not direction) of
reactions to stereotyped-relevant scientific in- political views predicts perceived belief supe-
formation. Personality and Social Psychology riority. Psychological Science, 24(12), 2454–
Bulletin, 23, 636–653. 2462.
Munro, G. D., & Stansbury, J. A. (2009). The Tormala, Z. L., Clarkson, J. J., & Henderson,
dark side of self-affirmation: Confirmation M. D. (2011). Does fast or slow evaluation fos-
bias and illusory correlation in response to ter greater certainty? Personality and Social
threatening information. Personality and So- Psychology Bulletin, 37(3), 422–434.
cial Psychology Bulletin, 35, 1143–1153. Tormala, Z. L., & Petty, R. E. (2002). What
Nickerson, R. S. (1998). Confirmation bias: A doesn’t kill me makes me stronger: The effects
ubiquitous phenomenon in many guises. Re- of resisting persuasion on attitude certainty.
view of General Psychology, 2(2), 175. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
Schmidt, M. F. H. & Sommerville, J. A. (2011). 83(6), 1298–1313.
Fairness expectations and altruistic sharing in Tormala, Z. L., & Rucker, D. D. (2007). Atti-
15-month-old human infants. PLOS ONE, tude certainty: A review of past findings and
6(10), e23223. emerging perspectives. Social and Personality
Skitka, L. J., Bauman, C. W., & Sargis, E. G. Psychology Compass, 1(1), 469–492.
(2005). Moral conviction: Another contribu- Uhlmann, E. L., Pizarro, D. A., Tannenbaum,
tor to attitude strength or something more? D., & Ditto, P. H. (2009). The motivated use
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, of moral principles. Judgment and Decision
88(6), 895–917. Making, 4(6), 476–491.
Skitka, L. J., & Mullen, E. (2002). The dark side Vitell, S. J., Nwachukwu, S. L., & Barnes, J.
of moral conviction. Analyses of Social Issues H. (1993). The effects of culture on ethical
and Public Policy, 2(1), 35–41. decision-making: An application of Hofstede’s
Smith, S. M., Fabrigar, L. R., MacDougall, B. typology. Journal of Business Ethics, 12(10),
L., & Wiesenthal, N. L. (2008). The role of 753–760.
amount, cognitive elaboration, and structural Wakslak, C. J., Nussbaum, S., Liberman, N., &
consistency of attitude-relevant knowledge in Trope, Y. (2008). Representations of the self in
the formation of attitude certainty. European the near and distant future. Journal of Person-
Journal of Social Psychology, 38(2), 280–295. ality and Social Psychology, 95(4), 757–773.
Suter, R. S., & Hertwig, R. (2011). Time and Wan, E. W., Rucker, D. D., Tormala, Z. L., &
moral judgment. Cognition, 119(3), 454–458. Clarkson, J. J. (2010). The effect of regula-
Tetlock, P. E. (2002). Social functionalist frame- tory depletion on attitude certainty. Journal of
works for judgment and choice: Intuitive poli- Marketing Research, 47(3), 531–541.
ticians, theologians, and prosecutors. Psycho- Wetherell, G. A., Brandt, M. J., & Reyna, C.
logical Review, 109(3), 451–471. (2013). Discrimination across the ideological
Tetlock, P. E. (2003). Thinking the unthinkable: divide: The role of value violations and ab-
Sacred values and taboo cognitions. Trends in stract values in discrimination by liberals and
Cognitive Sciences, 7(7), 320–324. conservatives. Social Psychological and Per-
Tetlock, P. E., Kristel, O. V., Elson, S. B., Green, sonality Science, 4(6), 658–667.
M. C., & Lerner, J. S. (2000). The psychology Wiltermuth, S. S., & Flynn, F. J. (2013). Power,
of the unthinkable: Taboo trade-offs, forbid- moral clarity, and punishment in the work-
den base rates, and heretical counterfactuals. place. Academy of Management Journal,
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 56(4), 1002–1023.
78(5), 853–870. Zhong, C. (2011). The ethical dangers of deliber-
Tiedens, L. Z., & Linton, S. (2001). Judgment ative decision making. Administrative Science
under emotional certainty and uncertainty: Quarterly, 56(1), 1–25.
PART XI
STUDYING MORALITY

Q U E S T I O N S A N S W E R E D I N PA R T X I

CHAPTER 51  How is moral sensitivity constructed


and what are its precursors in early development?

CHAPTER 52  What is the best method for understanding moral judgment?

CHAPTER 53  How can we investigate moral values in the real world?

CHAPTER 54  Is moral psychology overly focused on theory?


CH A P TER 51

Why Developmental Neuroscience


Is Critical for the Study of Morality

Jean Decety
Jason M. Cowell

How is moral sensitivity constructed and what are its precursors in


early development?

Developmental neuroscience is critical for clarifying what computa‑


tional systems mediate morality, and promising evidence suggests
that early social evaluations are relatively basic in nature, rooted in
domain-general approach–withdrawal tendencies and the allocation
of attention to relevant stimuli.

Morality is a fundamental aspect of all developing individuals across cultures have


human societies and regulates large facets of the basic notion that some things are right
social interactions. It is centrally concerned and others are wrong. Certain behaviors
with how individuals ought to interact and are viewed as good, right, and deserving
get along with others and has been an en- of praise and reward. Other behaviors are
during topic of interest to psychologists and viewed as bad, wrong, and worthy of blame
philosophers (Smetana, 2013). Work across and punishment (Hamlin, 2014). Human
various academic disciplines has converged social existence is characterized by an in-
on the view that morality arises from the tuitive sense of fairness, concern for others,
integration of both innate general abilities and enactment of cultural norms (Toma-
shaped by natural selection and delibera- sello, 2009) to an extent that is unseen in
tive processes that interact with the social other species. Early signs of moral sensitiv-
environment and cultural exposure (Decety ity are considered as the foundation for adult
& Howard, 2013; Hamlin, 2015; Killen & morality, emanating from the sophisticated
Smetana, 2013). Moral cognition can there- integration of emotional, motivational, and
fore be seen as a genetic–cultural coevolu- cognitive mechanisms across development
tionary product, representing an important (Wynn, 2007).
adaptive element for social cohesion and Although most theoretical perspectives
cooperation in group living. All normally concur that morality is multifaceted and in-

505
506 S T U DY I N G M O R A L I T Y

cludes affective, cognitive, and motivational & Svetlova, 2012). This capacity to reso-
components, different approaches have var- nate with the general positive and negative
ied as to which of these components are pri- emotional states of others has great adaptive
oritized and how they come into play during value in serving as a bond between individu-
ontogeny. In order to more accurately under- als, facilitating cooperation and caregiving
stand the foundations and development of a for offspring and kin.
mature moral self, an increased focus on a Although empathetic abilities are often
neurobiological perspective is informative. associated with morality, research in so-
Establishing neurological methods within a cial psychology and social neuroscience
developmental framework provides a more suggests that empathic concern does not
complete account of the computations un- necessarily produce moral behavior. In
derlying moral cognition, bridging the gap fact, empathy may lead one to act in a way
between behaviors and their underlying that violates the moral principles of justice
cognitive mechanisms. Thus neuroscience and fairness, when, for instance, allocat-
research is critical to clarify what computa- ing resources preferentially to the person
tional systems mediate early social evalua- for whom empathy was felt (Batson, Klein,
tions, moral judgment, and behaviors. For Highberger, & Shaw, 1995; Decety &
example, examining neural activation and Cowell, 2015a, 2015b). On the other hand,
functional connectivity (Decety, Michalska, a lack of empathic concern for the well-
& Kinzler, 2012), as well as the spatiotempo- being of others is considered a risk factor
ral dynamics of the neural processing when for amoral behavior and is the hallmark of
young children view social interactions and individuals with psychopathy (Hawes &
morally laden situations (Cowell & Decety, Dadds, 2012; Sobhani & Bechara, 2011).
2015a, 2015b), helps to better characterize This illustrates the complex nature of the
the contributions of affect, cognition, and relationships between empathy and moral-
deliberation to early morality. Although ity. Basic emotional processes such as em-
there is clear, accumulating evidence for an pathic arousal may be necessary to develop
“innate” ability for third-party sociomoral some aspects of moral reasoning, such as
evaluation, particularly when perceiving care-base morality. Overall, empathy pro-
helping and hindering agents, as young as 8 vides the impulse to care for a conspecific
months of age (e.g., Hamlin, 2015; Schmidt but is powerless in the face of rationaliza-
& Sommerville, 2011), the social, cognitive, tion and denial. Indeed, empathy is rela-
and affective processes and their interaction tively more predictive of prosocial behavior
behind these early evaluations are only be- when the victim is an individual. However,
ginning to be identified, and there is still an empathy alone is insufficient for producing
intense debate on the ontogenetic origins of a mature moral cognition (Decety & Cow-
human morality. ell, 2015a). Indeed, cognitive and reasoning
abilities play a crucial role in guiding moral
decision making and in the integration of
Theoretical Debates social context into deliberations. This con-
ception fundamentally alters “gut” reac-
Most theorists agree that the issue of harm tions to the perception of intentional harm,
is one of the foundations or the core founda- allowing more flexible and nuanced moral
tion of morality, particularly that any inten- evaluations and more effective translation
tional harm (given specific social context) to adaptive behavior.
is immoral (Gray, Young, & Waytz, 2012).
Some argue that empathy-related respond-
ing, including caring and sympathetic con- Current Knowledge of the Moral Brain
cern, motivates prosocial behavior, inhib-
its aggression, and paves the way to moral Our understanding of the brain mecha-
conduct (Zahn-Waxler & Radke-Yarrow, nisms involved in moral cognition is primar-
1990). A rudimentary component of empa- ily based on converging results from lesion
thy, affective sharing/arousal, can be ob- studies (Gleichgerrcht, Torralva, Roca, Pose,
served very early in development (Decety & Manes, 2011; Taber-Thomas, 2014), clin-
 Developmental Neuroscience 507

ical neuroscience with forensic psychopaths necessary to analyze the intentions behind
(Aharoni, Sinnott-Armstrong, & Kiehl, the surface of behavior, emotional circuitry
2012), and functional neuroimaging studies responsible for social emotions, and moral
conducted with adult participants (Moll et decisions. Specifically, moral cognition is
al., 2002; Moll et al., 2007). These studies the process of integrating reasoning and
point to specific regions underlying moral judgment based on one’s understanding of
sensitivity, judgment, and decision making. social norms, with the attribution of inten-
These regions include the posterior superior tions, beliefs, and emotions to oneself and
temporal sulcus, also known at the temporo- other people. In addition, regions of the
parietal junction (pSTS/TPJ), the amygdala, brain such as the vmPFC, amygdala and the
ventral striatum, insula, ventromedial pre- pSTS/TPJ have been implicated in aversive
frontal cortex (vmPFC), medial prefrontal social learning, interpretation of social cues
cortex (mPFC) and dorsolateral prefrontal such as intention, and assigning social and
cortex (DLPFC). Importantly, none of these emotional value to environmental stimuli to
regions can be singled out as a uniquely guide decisions. Thus most of neuroscience
moral center, and all of them are implicated research supports the claim that morality
in other mental functions, such as mental relies on multiple domain-general processes,
states representations, emotional saliency, which are distributed in circuits involved in
empathic concern, and decision making the social brain (Figure 51.1). It is thus not
(Decety & Cowell, 2014; Young & Dungan, clear whether there are computations that
2012). Moral cognition thus involves many are specific to morality, at least in the adult
parallel affective and cognitive processes moral brain.

FIGURE 51.1.  Neuroscience demonstrates that the brain regions underpinning moral reasoning share
computational resources with circuits controlling other capacities, such as emotional saliency, mental
state understanding, valuation of rewards from various modalities, and decision making and involve
the posterior superior temporal sulcus (pSTS) near the temporoparietal junction, the amygdala, the
insula, the ventromedial prefrontal cortex (vmPFC), the dorsolateral prefrontal cortex (dlPFC), and the
medial prefrontal cortex (mPFC). These systems are not domain-specific. Rather, they support more
domain-general processing. Importantly, both empathic concern and moral decision making require
involvement of the vmPFC, which bridges conceptual and affective processes necessary to guide moral
behavior and decision making. Early damage to this region leads to severe impairment of both moral
behavior and empathic concern.
508 S T U DY I N G M O R A L I T Y

Due to the methodological constraints will receive a shock (Lamm, Decety, & Sing-
of most neuroimaging methods, only a few er, 2011). It is worth noting that these vicari-
studies have examined children’s moral de- ously instigated activations are not specific
velopment. Such studies, in conjunction with to the sensory qualities of pain. Rather, they
neurological observations of brain-damaged reflect more general survival mechanisms
patients—which are obviously unexpected such as aversion and withdrawal when ex-
and unfortunate natural experiments—offer posed to danger and threat (Decety, 2010).
empirical and theoretical clarity on the bio- Activity of this cortical network, in adult
logical basis of and brain–behavior process- participants, thus indexes a system involved
es involved in morality. Developmental neu- in detecting, processing, and reacting to the
roscience provides a unique opportunity to occurrence of salient sensory events regard-
see how the components of morality interact less of the sensory channel through which
in ways that are not possible in adults—in these events are conveyed.
whom all the components are fully mature To examine developmental changes in
and operational. Integrating this neurode- the network involved in the perception of
velopmental perspective with behavioral pain, one fMRI study included participants
work shed light into the neurobiological from 7 to 40 years of age, who were pre-
and cognitive mechanisms underpinning the sented with video clips depicting individuals
basic building blocks of morality and their being accidentally or intentionally injured
age-related functional changes. Such an inte- (Decety & Michalska, 2010). The subjective
gration also contributes to our understand- evaluations of the scenarios, collected after
ing of the neural processes that underpin scanning, showed an age-related decrease
prosocial behavior. in ratings of pain intensity for both painful
conditions (accidental vs. intentional), with
younger participants rating the scenarios as
Developmental Neuroscience of Empathy significantly more painful than older par-
and Morality ticipants. The younger the participants, the
more strongly the amygdala, posterior in-
Developmental neuroscience can inform two sula, and vmPFC were recruited when they
large debates in our understanding of mo- watched others in painful situations. A sig-
rality. Specifically, functional neuroimaging nificant negative correlation between age
allows the charting out of neural networks and degree of neurohemodynamic response
involved in affective and cognitive processes was found in the posterior insula. In con-
when perceiving other people in distress, as trast, a positive correlation was found in the
well as the developmental changes in the re- anterior portion of the insula. A posterior-
spective contribution of each. Electrophysi- to-anterior progression of increasingly com-
ological methods, given their precise tem- plex re-representations in the human insula
poral resolution, afford the disentangling of is thought of as providing a foundation for
relatively automatic versus controlled mech- the sequential integration of the individual
anisms underlying empathy and morality. homeostatic condition with one’s sensory
When perceiving another individual in environment and motivational condition
pain or distress, numerous functional neu- (Craig, 2003). The posterior insula receives
roimaging (fMRI) studies have documented inputs from the ventromedial nucleus of the
the recruitment of a network involved in the thalamus, an area that is highly specialized
processing of physical pain and aversion. to convey emotional and homeostatic infor-
This neural network is composed of the an- mation and serves as a primary sensory cor-
terior insula, supplementary motor area, an- tex for both of these distinct interoceptive
terior midcingulate cortex (aMCC), somato- feelings from the body. The fact that, in re-
sensory cortex, and the periaqueductal gray sponse to others’ physical distress, younger
area. Reliable activation in this network has participants recruited the posterior portion
been shown when participants imagine the of the insula in conjunction with the amyg-
pain of others, view facial expressions of dala and vmPFC more than adults did indi-
pain or the injuring of body parts, or even cates that children were more aroused by the
observe a signal denoting that a conspecific perception of others’ distress. This, in turn,
 Developmental Neuroscience 509

may lead to a heightened experience of dis- and fMRI measures elicited by scenarios
comfort associated with a visceral response depicting intentional or accidental harm to
to a potential threat, whereas adult partici- people. After scanning, participants were
pants tend to use more abstract secondary presented with the same scenarios that they
representations of pain when perceiving oth- saw in the scanner and were asked to judge
ers in distress. The early engagement of the whether the action performed by the perpe-
amygdala, periaqueductal gray (PAG), insu- trator in the video clip was intentional or
la, and vmPFC during the perception of oth- not. Participants were also asked to respond
ers’ distress is consistent with the timing of to a set of questions probing moral judgment
their structural maturation. These recipro- (wrongness and punishment), empathic con-
cally interconnected regions, which underlie cern for the victim, personal distress, and
rapid and prioritized processing of emotion understanding of the perpetrator’s mental
signals and are involved in affective arousal state. In all participants, perceived inten-
and somatovisceral resonance, come online tional harm to people (as opposed to acci-
much earlier in ontogeny than other neural dental harm) was associated with increased
structures. In contrast, the dorsal and later- activation in brain regions sensitive to the
al vmPFC undergo considerable maturation perception, prediction, and interpretation of
during the childhood years and become pro- others’ mental states, such as the right pSTS/
gressively specialized for the evaluation of TPJ (Pelphrey & Carter, 2008), as well as re-
social stimuli (Paus, 2011). These regions of gions processing the affective consequences
the prefrontal cortex are crucial for empath- of these actions, namely the temporal poles,
ic concern and mentalizing, both of which insula, vmPFC, and amygdala. The more
are necessary for mature moral reasoning. participants reported being personally dis-
Indeed, one study examined the impact tressed about harmful actions, the higher
of early-onset (before 5 years) versus late- the activity in the amygdala.
onset lesions to the vmPFC on moral judg- Age was negatively related to empathic sad-
ment (Taber-Thomas et al., 2014). Patients ness for the victim of harm in the video clips,
with developmental-onset lesions endorsed with the youngest participants exhibiting the
significantly more self-serving judgments greatest personal sadness, and the degree of
that broke moral rules or inflicted harm on sadness was predictive of the response in the
others, suggesting that the vmPFC is a criti- insula, thalamus, and subgenual prefrontal
cal neural substrate for the acquisition and cortex. This latter region has extensive con-
maturation of moral competency that goes nections with circuits implicated in emotion-
beyond self-interest to consider the welfare al behavior and autonomic/neuroendocrine
of others. Disruption to this affective neural response to stressors, including the amyg-
system early in life interrupts moral develop- dala, lateral hypothalamus, and brain stem
ment. serotonergic, noradrenergic, and dopami-
A decisive aspect in third-party moral nergic nuclei (Drevets et al., 1997). Damage
judgment relies heavily on the detection of to the subgenual prefrontal cortex is asso-
intentionality. It is the critical cue in deter- ciated with abnormal autonomic responses
mining whether an action was malicious or to emotional experiences and impaired
not (Malle & Guglielmo, 2012). How in- comprehension of the adverse consequenc-
formation about intentionality is used for es of pernicious social behaviors (Bechara,
judging the wrongness of an action may Tranel, Damasio, & Damasio, 1996). The
be age-dependent (Zelazo, Helwig, & Lau, response in the amygdala followed a curvi-
1996) and, in turn, will influence recom- linear function, such that the hemodynamic
mendations of deserved punishment. These signal was highest at the youngest ages, de-
determinations of punishment require a creased rapidly through childhood and early
complex integration between the analysis adolescence, and reached an asymptote in
of mental states (desires, beliefs, intentions) late adolescence through adulthood. This
of the perpetrator and the consequences of developmental change in amygdala recruit-
his or her actions. A neurodevelopmental ment, coupled with its relation to ratings of
study of participants ages 4–37 years com- empathic distress, supports the role of this
bined sociomoral appraisals, eye tracking, region in the normal development of em-
510 S T U DY I N G M O R A L I T Y

pathic understanding (Decety & Michalska, who damaged an object than an agent who
2010). Conversely, the neurohemodynamic harmed a person. Though even young chil-
signal in older participants increased in the dren attend to both intentionality and tar-
mPFC and vmPFC, regions that are associ- get in guiding their own empathic responses
ated with metacognitive representations, and judgments of wrongness, an increased
valuation, and social decision making. discrimination of intentionality and target
Patterns of functional connectivity dur- in determining moral culpability with age
ing the perception of intentional, relative is consistent with the developmental shift
to accidental, harm showed complementary in moral judgment dominated by an early
evidence for an increased developmental in- focus on outcomes and the later integration
tegration of the prefrontal cortex and amyg- of both intent and consequences.
dala. The older participants showed signifi- Finally, another fMRI study with par-
cant coactivation in these regions during ticipants ages 13–53 examined the neural
the perception of intentional harm relative response to International Affective Picture
to accidental harm, whereas the youngest System (IAPS) pictures that did or did not
children only exhibited a significant covari- depict moral violations (Harenski, Haren-
ation between the vmPFC and PAG in the ski, Shane, & Kiehl, 2012). Making deci-
brain stem. Furthermore, adult participants sions about the severity of pictures was as-
showed the strongest connectivity between sociated with increased amygdala, pSTS/
vmPFC and pSTS/TPJ while viewing moral- TPJ, and posterior cingulate cortex activity
ly laden actions suggestive of developmental in adolescents and adults. Moreover, the
changes in functional integration within the magnitude of activity in the pSTS increased
mentalizing system. across development. These findings suggest
Neurodevelopmental variations during that across development, individuals pro-
the perception of morally laden scenarios gressively integrate knowledge of the men-
are clearly seen in neural regions that are tal states of others, especially intentionality,
implicated in emotional saliency (amygdala into moral evaluations.
and insula), with a gradual decrease in ac- Taken together, findings from these neu-
tivation with age. Conversely, activity in rodevelopmental investigations document
regions of the medial and vmPFC that are the importance of and changes in several
reciprocally connected with the amygdala interconnected networks implicated in pro-
and that are involved in decision making cessing the distress of others, intentionality
and evaluation increased with age and be- of the agents, consequences for the victims,
came functionally coupled. This pattern of and cognitive decision making.
developmental change was also reflected in Although fMRI yields important insights
the moral evaluations, which require the into the mechanisms that guide moral cogni-
capacity to integrate a representation of tion, two limitations hinder its utility. The
the mental states and intentions of others, hemodynamic signal has a poor temporal
together with the consequences of their ac- resolution (around 5 seconds) and thus can-
tions (Leslie, Knobe, & Cohen, 2006). Al- not inform arguments about the timing and
though third-party judgments of wrongness automaticity of the processes investigated.
did not change across age—all participants Furthermore, from a practical sense, the
rated intentional harm as more wrong than fMRI environment is not well suited to in-
accidental harm—when asked about the ma- fants and young children. Electroencepha-
levolence of the agent, subjective evaluations lography (EEG) and event-related potentials
indicated a more differentiated appraisal (ERPs), on the other hand, do not have such
with age. Whereas young children consid- limitations. The temporal resolution is ex-
ered all agents malicious, irrespective of in- cellent (at the millisecond level), and these
tention and targets (i.e., people and objects), methods are frequently used in toddlers and
older participants perceived the perpetrator young children.
as clearly less mean when carrying out an ac- To examine the neurodevelopment of em-
cidental action, and even more so when the pathy, one study used EEGs and ERPs in
target was an object. As age increased, par- children ages 3–9 years who were shown
ticipants also less severely punished an agent stimuli depicting physical injuries to people.
 Developmental Neuroscience 511

Results demonstrated both an early auto- influence is likely based on a dynamic bidi-
matic component (N200), which reflects rectional interaction between biology and
attention to salient stimuli, and a late-­ socioenvironmental context, rather than
positive potential (LPP), indexing cognitive simply the product of one or the other.
reappraisal or more complex processing of Another neurodevelopmental study (Cow-
emotional stimuli. The LPP showed an age- ell & Decety, 2015b) assessed the implicit
related differentiation between painful and moral evaluations of antisocial (harming)
neutral scenes (Cheng et al., 2014). Another and prosocial (helping) behaviors in young
study used high-density EEG to examine children (3–5 years) and further investigat-
the spatiotemporal neurodynamic responses ed whether early automatic (early posterior
when viewing people in physical distress negativity [EPN]) or later cognitive con-
under two subjective contexts: one evoking trolled (LPP) processes were predictive of
affect sharing, the other, empathic concern children’s own generosity. Significant differ-
(Decety, Lewis, & Cowell, 2015). Results ences were found in early automatic as well
indicate that early automatic (175–275 milli- as later controlled temporal periods when
seconds) and later controlled responses (LPP children viewed the morally laden scenarios.
400–1000 milliseconds) were differentially Importantly, only controlled processes pre-
modulated by engagement in affect sharing dicted actual prosocial behavior (i.e., the
or empathic concern. Importantly, the late number of stickers given to another anony-
ERP component was significantly affected mous child). This study demonstrates how
by dispositional empathy, but the early com- young children exhibit automatic responses
ponent was not. to morally laden stimuli and reappraise
There is accumulative evidence that pre- these stimuli in a controlled manner. Thus
verbal infants have the ability to morally children’s moral judgments are the result of
evaluate the actions of others (Hamlin, an integration of both early and automatic
2015). To examine the neural underpin- processing of helping and harming scenarios
nings of moral sensitivity in infants and and later cognitively controlled reappraisal
toddlers ages 12–24 months, Cowell and of these scenes. Importantly, the latter and
Decety (2015a) employed a series of inter- not the former predicts actual sharing be-
woven measures combining multiple levels havior.
of analysis, including resting state and time- In other research on moral reasoning,
locked electrophysiology, eye-tracking, be- consistently early and late differences in the
havioral, and socioenvironmental measures. spatiotemporal processing of dilemmas have
Continuous EEG and time-locked ERPs and been identified. For instance, larger N2 am-
gaze fixation were recorded while children plitudes for moral versus conventional viola-
watched characters engaging in prosocial tions were found in children ages 9–10 years
and antisocial actions. All children dem- (Lahat, Helwig, & Zelazo, 2013). In another
onstrated a neural differentiation in both study, P300 differences in response to moral
spectral EEG power density modulations judgment were observed, and individual dif-
and time-locked ERPs when perceiving ferences in this ERP component predicted
prosocial compared with antisocial agents. dispositional attitudes toward prosociality
Time-locked neural differences also predict- (Chiu Loke, Evans, & Lee, 2011). Moreover,
ed children’s preferential reaching for proso- in a study with emerging adult participants,
cial over antisocial characters. This neural high-density ERPs, combined with source
and behavioral differentiation of prosocial localization analyses, revealed that differ-
and antisocial others is relatively basic in ences due to the perception of intentional
nature, rooted in approach–withdrawal ten- harm compared with accidental harm were
dencies and rudimentary resource allocation first detected in the right pSTS/TPJ, as fast
to relevant stimuli. Interestingly, the values as 62 milliseconds poststimulus, and later
of parents regarding justice and their own responses were found in the amygdala (122
cognitive empathic dispositions significantly milliseconds) and vmPFC (182 milliseconds;
influenced toddlers’ neural processing of the Decety & Cacioppo, 2012).
morally laden scenarios and their propensity Overall, EEGs and ERPs provide a valu-
to share, respectively. Such an early social able method for characterizing the roles of
512 S T U DY I N G M O R A L I T Y

automatic and controlled processes involved dala) with the vmPFC (Motzkin, Newman,
in moral judgment and social decision mak- Kiehl, & Koenigs, 2011). They also exhibit
ing. Importantly, EEGs and ERPs allow for an atypical pattern of brain activation and
neurodevelopmental investigations, docu- effective connectivity seeded in the anterior
menting the relative importance of both insula and amygdala with the vmPFC when
of these processes across development, the perceiving interpersonal harm and signals of
modulations in each, and their respective distress (Decety, Chen, Harenski, & Kiehl,
contributions to moral behavior in infancy, 2013).
childhood, adolescence, and emerging adult- Children with psychopathic tendencies
hood. and callous-unemotional traits show con-
sistent deficits in affective sharing and em-
pathic concern across childhood and ado-
The Lack of Affect Sharing Hinders lescence. These abnormal responses to the
Moral Behavior distress of others may be evident as early as
childhood. For example, children with psy-
To further clarify the importance of emo- chopathic tendencies exhibit reduced elec-
tion and affect sharing in moral cognition trodermal responses to distress cues (e.g.,
and behavior, individuals who lack empathy a crying face) and threatening stimuli (e.g.,
provide a natural experiment. Individuals a pointed gun) relative to controls (Blair,
who are indifferent to the fear, distress, and 1995). Another study using EEG examined
sadness of others are those who are difficult this phenomenon by assessing how callous-
to socialize (Blair, 1995). A paradigmatic unemotional traits in juvenile psychopaths
case is psychopathy, a neurodevelopmental were related to deficits in affective sharing
personality disorder believed to affect ap- (Cheng, Hung, & Decety, 2012). Results
proximately 1% of the general population demonstrated that youth with high callous-
and 20–30% of the male and female prison unemotional traits exhibit atypical neural
population. Relative to nonpsychopathic dynamics in response to stimuli depicting
criminals, psychopaths are responsible for a other individuals in physical distress. This
disproportionate amount of repetitive crime abnormality was exemplified by a lack of
and violence in society (Kiehl, 2014). These the early EPR response (120 milliseconds),
individuals often possess specific traits that thought to reflect an automatic aversive re-
point to stunted emotional development, a action to negative stimuli, and was coupled
general lack of attachment to others, and with relative insensitivity to actual pain (as
difficulties experiencing empathic concern measured with the pressure pain threshold).
and remorse (Maibom, 2009). Individuals Nevertheless, their capacity to understand
with psychopathy are often callous, shallow, the agent’s intentionality was not impaired.
and superficial. They lack fear of punish- In support of this finding, fMRI studies have
ment, have difficulty regulating their emo- also reported that children and adolescents
tions, and do not experience insight into the with disruptive psychopathic traits show re-
consequences of their harmful actions for duced activity to the pain of others within the
others (Hare & Neumann, 2008). neural structures (anterior cingulate cortex,
Structural neuroimaging studies associate insula, and amygdala) typically implicated in
psychopathy with a host of morphological affective responses to others’ pain and dis-
brain abnormalities, including reduced vol- tress (Marsh et al., 2013; Lockwood et al.,
umes of the amygdala; reduced gray matter 2013). This uncoupling between affective
volumes in the frontal and temporal cor- sharing and cognitive understanding likely
tex, especially in the right pSTS/TPJ; and contributes to psychopaths’ callous disre-
increased volume of the striatum (Koenigs, gard for the rights and feelings of others. Fi-
Baskin-Sommers, Zeier, & Newman, 2011). nally, similar to adult psychopaths (Wolf et
Furthermore, psychopaths often exhibit al., 2015), children with conduct problems
signs of reduced structural integrity of the and psychopathic tendencies exhibit white-
uncinate fasciculus—a connecting path- matter microstructural abnormalities in the
way of the limbic system in the temporal anatomical tract that connects the amygdala
lobe (such as the hippocampus and amyg- and vmPFC (Passamonti et al., 2012). Ab-
 Developmental Neuroscience 513

normal connectivity in the amygdala–orbital of social and contextual information in in-


frontal cortex/vmPFC limbic network con- fluencing the neural networks involved in
tributes to the neurobiological mechanisms moral judgment and subsequent behaviors.
underpinning the antisocial behavior, lack Preliminary developmental investigations of
of empathic concern, and emotional detach- the neural underpinnings of moral cognition
ment associated with psychopathy. have largely focused on the simplest forms
of morality, such as the perception of dis-
tress cues and evaluations of interpersonal
Directions for Developmental harm. However, with age, due to increases
Moral Neuroscience in the cognitive capacities to balance, coor-
dinate, and integrate multiple elements of
Overall, developmental neuroscience inves- a situation, contextual information plays a
tigations inform the fundamental nature of fundamental role in moral reasoning. For
moral cognition, including its underpinnings instance, while at all ages children negative-
in relatively general processes, providing ly evaluate prototypical harm, behavioral
plausible mechanisms of early change, and studies suggest that judgments of necessary
a foundation for forward movement in the harm become increasingly more forgiving
field. Some basic elements that are critical with age as justifications pertaining to the
to building morality are in place very early actor’s harm decrease (Jambon & Smetana,
in childhood, comprising both automatic 2014). Such contextual aspects are certainly
and controlled processing, as well as affec- a fascinating topic worthy of being empiri-
tive and cognitive representations. Neurosci- cally studied.
ence methods in the study of morality and
prosocial behavior across age allow us to
advocate for the best practices in capturing REFERENCES
the modulation of affective, cognitive, and
social processes, by dispositional character- Aharoni, E., Sinnott-Armstrong, W., & Kiehl, K.
A. (2012). Can psychopathic offenders discern
istics, and individual differences, that are moral wrongs?: A new look at the moral/con-
possibly unique to human nature. This new ventional distinction. Journal of Abnormal
information sheds important light on the Psychology, 121, 484–497.
theoretical understanding and appropriate Batson, C. D., Klein, T. R., Highberger, L., &
methods for exploring the ontogeny of so- Shaw, L. L. (1995). Immorality from empathy-
cial cognition, empathy, and moral reason- induced altruism: When compassion and jus-
ing. This demonstrates the potential of de- tice conflict. Journal of Personality and Social
velopmental social neuroscience to provide Psychology, 68, 1042–1054.
productive, new, and exciting directions for Bechara, A., Tranel, D., Damasio, H., & Dama-
the study of moral development when stem- sio, A. R. (1996). Failure to respond autonomi-
cally to anticipated future outcomes following
ming from an integration of neurobiology,
damage to the prefrontal cortex. Cerebral
behavior, and social environment (Killen & Cortex, 6, 215–225.
Smetana, 2008). Yet many challenges exist Blair, R. J. R. (1995). A cognitive developmental
in implementing neuroscience methods with approach to morality: Investigating the psy-
dilemmas and scenarios that are ecologically chopath. Cognition, 57, 1–29.
valid and developmentally sensitive. In par- Cheng, Y., Chen, C., & Decety, J. (2014). An
ticular, it is difficult to operationalize such EEG/ERP investigation of the development
paradigms in a neuroscience laboratory en- of empathy during early childhood. Develop-
vironment, where an excessive repetition of mental Cognitive Neuroscience, 10, 160–169.
trials is necessary in both fMRI and EEG Cheng, Y., Hung, A., & Decety, J. (2012). Disso-
to obtain sufficient signal-to-noise ratio. By ciation between affective sharing and emotion
understanding in juvenile psychopaths. Devel-
nature, such experimental manipulations opment and Psychopathology, 24, 623–636.
cannot be similar to ecologically valid situ- Chiu Loke, I., Evans, A. D., & Lee, K. (2011).
ations that one may encounter when having The neural correlates of reasoning about
to judge a particular decision or action. prosocial-helping decisions: An event-related
Further developmental neuroscience re- brain potentials study. Brain Research, 1369,
search should specifically examine the role 140–148.
514 S T U DY I N G M O R A L I T Y

Cowell, J. M., & Decety, J. (2015a). Precursors R. D., Reich, T., Vannier, M., . . . Raichle, M.
to morality in development as a complex in- E. (1997). Subgenual prefrontal cortex ab-
terplay between neural, socio-environmental, normalities in mood disorders. Nature, 386,
and behavioral facets. Proceedings of the 824–827.
National Academy of Sciences of the USA, Gleichgerrcht, E., Torralva, T., Roca, M., Pose,
112(41), 12657–12662. M., & Manes, F. (2011). The role of social
Cowell, J. M., & Decety, J. (2015b). The neu- cognition in moral judgment in frontotempo-
roscience of implicit moral evaluation and its ral dementia. Social Neuroscience, 6, 113–
relation to generosity in early childhood. Cur- 122.
rent Biology, 25, 1–5. Gray, K., Young, L., & Waytz, A. (2012). Mind
Craig, A. D. (2003). Interoception: The sense of perception is the essence of morality. Psycho-
the physiological condition of the body. Cur- logical Inquiry, 23, 101–124.
rent Opinion in Neurobiology, 13, 500–505. Hamlin, J. K. (2014). The origins of human mo-
Decety, J. (2010). To what extent is the experi- rality: Complex socio-moral evaluations in
ence of empathy mediated by shared neural preverbal infants. In J. Decety & Y. Christen
circuits? Emotion Review, 2, 204–207. (Eds.), New frontiers in social neuroscience
Decety, J., & Cacioppo, S. (2012). The speed (pp. 165–188). Berlin: Springer Verlag.
of morality: A high-density electrical neuro- Hamlin, J. K. (2015). The infantile origins of
imaging study. Journal of Neurophysiology, our moral brains. In J. Decety & T. Wheat-
108(11), 3068–3072. ley (Eds.), The moral brain: Multidisciplinary
Decety, J., Chen, C., Harenski, C. L., & Kiehl, perspectives (pp. 105–122). Cambridge, MA:
K. A. (2013). An fMRI study of affective per- MIT Press.
spective taking in individuals with psychopa- Hare, R. D., & Neumann, C. S. (2008). Psy-
thy: Imagining another in pain does not evoke chopathy as a clinical and empirical construct.
empathy. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, Annual Review of Clinical Psychology, 4,
7, 489. 217–246.
Decety, J., & Cowell, J. M. (2014). Friends or Harenski, C. L., Harenski, K. A., Shane, M. S.,
foes: Is empathy necessary for moral behavior? & Kiehl, K. A. (2012). Neural development of
Perspectives on Psychological Science, 9(5), mentalizing in moral judgment from adoles-
525–537. cence to adulthood. Developmental Cognitive
Decety, J., & Cowell, J. M. (2015a). The equivo- Neuroscience, 2, 162–173.
cal relationships between morality and empa- Hawes, D. J., & Dadds, M. R. (2012). Revisit-
thy. In J. Decety & T. Wheatley (Eds.), The ing the role of empathy in childhood pathways
moral brain: A multidisciplinary perspective to antisocial behavior. In R. Langdon & C.
(pp. 279–302). Cambridge, MA: MIT press. Mackenzie (Eds.), Emotions, imagination,
Decety, J., & Cowell, J. M. (2015b). Empathy, and moral reasoning (pp. 45–70). New York:
justice and moral behavior. American Journal Psychology Press.
of Bioethics—Neuroscience, 6(3), 3–14. Jambon, M., & Smetana, J. G. (2014). Moral
Decety, J., & Howard, L. (2013). The role of complexity in middle childhood: Children’s
affect in the neurodevelopment of morality. evaluations of necessary harm. Developmen-
Child Development Perspectives, 7, 49–54. tal Psychology, 50, 22–33.
Decety, J., Lewis, K., & Cowell, J. M. (2015). Kiehl, K. A. (2014). The psychopath whisperer:
Specific electrophysiological components dis- Inside the minds of those without a con-
entangle affective sharing and empathic con- science. New York: Crown.
cern in psychopathy. Journal of Neurophysiol- Killen, M., & Smetana, J. (2008). Moral judg-
ogy, 114, 493–504. ment and moral neuroscience: Intersections,
Decety, J., & Michalska, K. J. (2010). Neuro- definitions, and issues. Child Development
developmental changes in the circuits under- Perspectives, 2, 1–6.
lying empathy and sympathy from childhood Killen, M., & Smetana, J. G. (2013). Handbook
to adulthood. Developmental Science, 13, of moral development. New York: Psychology
886–899. Press.
Decety, J., Michalska, K. J., & Kinzler, K. D. Koenigs, M., Baskin-Sommers, A., Zeier, J., &
(2012). The contribution of emotion and cog- Newman, J. P. (2011). Investigating the neural
nition to moral sensitivity: A neurodevelop- correlates of psychopathy: A critical review.
mental study. Cerebral Cortex, 22, 209–220. Molecular Psychiatry, 16, 792–799.
Decety, J., & Svetlova, M. (2012). Putting to- Lahat, A., Helwig, C. C., & Zelazo, P. D. (2013).
gether phylogenetic and ontogenetic perspec- An event-related potential study of adoles-
tives on empathy. Developmental Cognitive cents’ and young adults’ judgments of moral
Neuroscience, 2, 1–24. and social conventional violations. Child De-
Drevets, W. C., Price, J. L., Simpson, J. R., Todd, velopment, 84(3), 955–969.
 Developmental Neuroscience 515

Lamm, C., Decety, J., & Singer, T. (2011). Me- and orbitofrontal cortex in conduct disorder.
ta-analytic evidence for common and distinct PLOS ONE, 7(11), e48789.
neural networks associated with directly expe- Paus, T. (2011). Brain development during child-
rienced pain and empathy for pain. NeuroIm- hood and adolescence. In J. Decety & J. T.
age, 54(3), 2492–2502. Cacioppo (Eds.), Oxford handbook of social
Leslie, A., Knobe, J., & Cohen, A. (2006). Acting neuroscience (pp. 293–313). New York: Ox-
intentionally and the side-effect effect: Theory ford University Press.
of mind and moral judgment. Psychological Pelphrey, K. E., & Carter, E. J. (2008). Chart-
Science, 17, 421–427. ing the typical and atypical development of the
Lockwood, P. L., Sebastian, C. L., McCrory, E. social brain. Development and Psychopathol-
J., Hyde, Z. H., Gu, X., De Brito, S. A., & ogy, 20, 1081–1102.
Viding, E. (2013). Association of callous traits Schmidt, M., & Sommerville, J. A. (2011). Fair-
with reduced neural response to others’ pain ness expectations and altruistic sharing in
in children with conduct disorder. Current Bi- 15-month-old human infants. PLOS ONE, 6,
ology, 23, 1–5. e23223.
Maibom, H. L. (2009). Feeling for others: Em- Smetana, J. G. (2013). Moral development: The
pathy, sympathy, and morality. Inquiry, 52, social domain theory view. In P. Zelazo (Ed.),
483–499. Oxford handbook of developmental psychol-
Malle, B. F., & Guglielmo, S. (2012). Are inten- ogy (pp. 832–865). New York: Oxford Univer-
tionality judgments fundamentally moral? In sity Press.
R. Langdon & C. Mackenzie (Eds.), Emo- Sobhani, M., & Bechara, A. (2011). A somatic
tions, imagination, and moral reasoning marker perspective of immoral and corrupt
(pp. 275–293). Hove, UK: Psychology Press. behavior. Social Neuroscience, 6, 640–652.
Marsh, A. A., Finger, E. C., Fowler, K. A., Taber-Thomas, B. C., Asp, E. W., Koenigs, M.,
Adalio, C. J., Jurkowitz, I. N., Schechter, J. Sutterer, M., Anderson, S. W., & Tranel, D.
C., . . . Blair, R. J. R. (2013). Empathic re- (2014). Arrested development: Early prefron-
sponsiveness in amygdala and anterior cingu- tal lesions impair the maturation of moral
late cortex in youths with psychopathic traits. judgment. Brain, 137, 1254–1261.
Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, Tomasello, M. (2009). Why we cooperate. Cam-
54, 900–910. bridge, MA: MIT Press.
Moll, J., de Oliveira-Souza, R., Eslinger, P. J., Wolf, R. C., Pujara, M. S., Motzkin, J. C., New-
Bramati, I. E., Mourao-Miranda, J., An- man, J. P., Kiehl, K. A., Decety, J., . . . Koe-
dreiuolo, P. A., . . . Pessoa, L. (2002). The neu- nigs, M. (2015). Interpersonal traits of psy-
ral correlates of moral sensitivity: A functional chopathy linked to reduced integrity of the
magnetic resonance imaging investigation of uncinate fasciculus. Human Brain Mapping,
basic moral emotions. Journal of Neurosci- 36(10), 4202–4209.
ence, 22, 2730–2736. Wynn, K. (2007). Some innate foundations of so-
Moll, J., de Oliveira-Souza, R., Garrido, G. J., cial and moral cognition. In P. Carruthers, S.
Bramati, I. E., Caparelli, E. M. A., Paiva, M. Laurence, & S. Stich (Eds.), The innate mind:
L. M. F., . . . Grafman, J. (2007). The self as a Vol. 3. Foundations and the future (pp. 330–
moral agent: Linking the neural bases of social 347). New York: Oxford University Press.
agency and moral sensitivity. Social Neurosci- Young, L., & Dungan, J. (2012). Where in the
ence, 2, 336–352. brain is morality?: Everywhere and maybe no-
Motzkin, J. C., Newman, J. P., Kiehl, K. A., & where. Social Neuroscience, 7, 1–10.
Koenigs, M. (2011). Reduced prefrontal con- Zahn-Waxler, C., & Radke-Yarrow, M. (1990).
nectivity in psychopathy. Journal of Neurosci- The origins of empathic concern. Motivation
ence, 31, 17348–17357. and Emotion, 14, 107–130.
Passamonti, L., Fairchild, G., Fornito, A., Zelazo, P. D., Helwig, C. C., & Lau, A. (1996).
Goodyer, I. M., Nimmo-Smith, I., Hagan, Intention, act and outcome in behavioral pre-
C. C., & Calder, A. J. (2012). Abnormal ana- diction and moral judgment. Child Develop-
tomical connectivity between the amygdala ment, 67, 2478–2492.
CHAPTER 52

Implicit Moral Cognition

C. Daryl Cameron
Julian A. Scheffer
Victoria L. Spring

What is the best method for understanding moral judgment?

We use implicit measurement and mathematical modeling to capture


implicit moral evaluations, because this method can address debates
over the role of intuition and reason in moral judgment and over
domain-general versus domain-specific views of moral psychology.

A man kicks a puppy as hard as he can. A son What Is an Implicit Moral Attitude?


slaps his mother across the face. A soldier
betrays his unit. A terrorist defiles a temple. Within moral psychology, one of the most
These actions all seem like moral transgres- influential accounts of moral judgment is
sions. And before you deliberate about why social intuitionism (Haidt, 2001). Social in-
they are wrong—that is, what principles do tuitionism claims that the heart of human
they violate—you probably have an imme- morality is intuition, not reason: When we
diate gut reaction: “That is wrong!” If you consider the actions or character of others,
don’t have that reaction, that is important we have automatic moral intuitions that are
for us and everyone else to know, because the main cause of our moral judgments. As
it might mean you have fewer inhibitions defined by this approach, a moral intuition
about engaging in such behaviors. And you is “the sudden appearance in conscious-
might know what the “appropriate” reaction ness or at the fringe of consciousness, of an
is supposed to look like, so it’s important to evaluative feeling (like–dislike, good–bad)
find a way to reliably assess your gut reac- about the character or actions of a person,
tions before you can edit your responses. In without any conscious awareness of having
this chapter, we discuss a new approach to gone through steps of search, weighing evi-
measuring moral intuitions that draws upon dence, or inferring a conclusion” (Haidt &
advances in implicit social cognition and Bjorklund, 2008, p. 188). Moral intuitions
mathematical modeling. are thought to be quick, spontaneous, and

516
 Implicit Moral Cognition 517

unintentional (Haidt, 2001; Sinnott-Arm- ing to a recent review of moral psychology,


strong, Young, & Cushman, 2010), like “the precise roles played by intuition and
many of the implicit cognitive processes that reasoning in moral judgment cannot yet be
have been documented in social psychology established based on the existing empirical
(for a review, see Gawronski & Payne, 2010). evidence” (Haidt & Kesebir, 2010, p. 807).
Because psychologists and philosophers dif- One reason for this stalemate may be that
fer in how they define moral intuition— previous dual-process theories only verbally
many psychologists would simply take it to describe relationships between intuition and
mean an automatic process, whereas many deliberation. However, the stalemate can be
philosophers would add claims about infer- broken if we turn to formalized dual-process
ence and epistemic justification (e.g., Hue- approaches that mathematically specify re-
mer, 2005)—we opt for the term implicit lationships between intuition and delibera-
moral attitude. Like other implicit attitudes, tion (Gawronski, Sherman, & Trope, 2014).
an implicit moral attitude is an association We discuss one such approach: multinomial
between a person or action and a moral va- modeling.
lence (right–wrong), activated immediately
in reaction to a social event.
We do not claim that moral cognition A Modeling Approach to Morality
is a natural kind, separate from nonmoral
cognition; rather, as suggested by work in Implicit moral attitudes are the central con-
social neuroscience, moral evaluations re- struct for intuitionist theories of morality,
cruit domain-general processes such as af- yet they have received surprisingly little at-
fect, conceptual knowledge, attention, and tention in moral psychology (for an initial
others (for a review of a domain-general ap- discussion, see Payne & Cameron, 2010).
proach to morality, see Cameron, Lindquist, Early work in support of social intuition-
& Gray, 2015). On our approach, implicit ism manipulated affective states to change
moral attitudes are evaluations that typical- moral judgments (e.g., Valdesolo & DeSte-
ly involve an affective response and concep- no, 2006), whereas other research examined
tual knowledge about morality. These need emotions and moral judgments in response
not reflect “online” moral decisions about to different classes of transgressions (for
a transgression and could instead reflect reviews, see Cameron et al., 2015; Monin,
stored moral associations with previously Pizarro, & Beer, 2007). Yet these responses
encountered transgressions. Of course, may reflect more than just implicit moral at-
people also have implicit negative attitudes titudes—self-reports may reflect a complex
about social events and social groups that blend of intuitive and deliberative processes
are not moralized, and we believe that the as people consider the appropriate response.
difference between these and implicit moral More recently, researchers have used im-
attitudes is a matter of degree, not of kind. plicit evaluation measures from social cogni-
Historically, our approach is grounded tion to understand implicit moral attitudes.
in a classic debate in moral philosophy and Unlike self-report measures, implicit mea-
moral psychology: Is moral judgment based sures do not directly request the response of
on intuition or on reason? We think that, as interest (for a review, see Wentura & Degner,
with many debates, both sides are right: Intu- 2010). For instance, the Implicit Association
itive and deliberative processes interact with Test (IAT) examines the strength of associa-
each other to shape moral judgment. Many tions between concepts based upon reaction
current theories of moral judgment propose times (Greenwald, McGhee, & Schwarz,
dual processes of intuition and deliberation 1998), and the affect misattribution proce-
that work together to produce moral judg- dure (AMP) measures automatic affective
ment (Greene, 2013; Haidt, 2012), with the reactions toward prime stimuli based upon
major point of contention being the relative how these reactions influence judgments of
influence of each (Paxton & Greene, 2010). ambiguous target stimuli (Payne, Cheng,
Is reason, as put by Hume, “the slave to the Govorun, & Stewart, 2005). Such mea-
passions,” or is it a process that can inter- sures have been used frequently to capture
cede to shape moral judgments? Accord- implicit racial attitudes (e.g., Payne, 2001),
518 S T U DY I N G M O R A L I T Y

and meta-analyses reveal that they predict interact to produce behavior within a given
explicit attitudes and behaviors (Cameron, context (Riefer & Batchelder, 1988). One
Brown-Iannuzzi, & Payne, 2012; Green- well-known subset of multinomial models
wald, Uhlmann, Poehlman, & Banaji, 2009; is process dissociation (Jacoby, 1991; Payne,
Hofmann, Gawronski, Gschwendner, Le, 2008; Payne & Cameron, 2014), which has
& Schmitt, 2005). Some have used the IAT been used to separate automatic and con-
to examine associations between morality trolled processes in the context of racial
and the self-concept (Aquino & Reed, 2002; stereotyping (Payne, 2001), heuristics and
Perugini & Leone, 2009) and between mo- biases (Ferreira, Garcia-Marques, Sherman,
rality and pleasantness judgments (Cima, & Sherman, 2006), and deontological and
Tonnaer, & Lobbestael, 2007; Gray, Mac- utilitarian moral decisions (Conway & Gaw-
Culloch, Smith, Morris, & Snowden, 2003; ronski, 2013). More broadly, multinomial
Luo et al., 2006), whereas others have used models have been used to quantify multiple
the AMP to examine affective reactions to- processes that underpin social evaluation
ward moral and nonmoral actions (Graham and social cognition (e.g., Conrey, Sherman,
et al., 2015; Hofmann & Baumert, 2010). Gawronski, Hugenberg, & Groom, 2005;
These studies have shown that implicit moral Krieglmeyer & Sherman, 2012; Payne, Hall,
attitudes predict moral personality (Cima et Cameron, & Bishara, 2010; for reviews, see
al., 2007; Gray et al., 2003) and moral be- Payne & Bishara, 2009; Bishara & Payne,
havior (Hofmann & Baumert, 2010). 2009; Sherman, Klauer, & Allen, 2011).
But do these measures really capture im- Multinomial modeling is different from
plicit moral attitudes? First, although the many previous approaches because it carries
tasks involve moral content (words or pic- very few assumptions about the underlying
tures related to morality), they do not spe- processes involved. As noted above, multi-
cifically involve moral judgment. To capture nomial modeling does not assume that an
implicit moral attitudes about transgres- implicit measure only captures a single pro-
sions, it may be optimal to set up a task cess (e.g., that the IAT only captures implicit
that can show how immediate reactions to attitudes). Instead, the modeling approach
moral stimuli bias wrongness judgments assumes that performance on any task is the
about different stimuli. Second, past uses of net result of multiple underlying processes
implicit measurement to assess moral judg- that interact with each other. Our approach
ment adopt the task dissociation approach: does not assume that these processes arise
that a single task corresponds to a single from the operation of dual systems (e.g.,
process. This assumption is common in “System I” and “System II”) or from differ-
much research in implicit social cognition, ent processing “modes” that cannot oper-
which presumes that an implicit measure ate at the same time (e.g., “autopilot” and
such as the IAT only captures implicit atti- “manual”; Greene, 2013). The model does
tudes, whereas an explicit self-report mea- not equate process with content—that is,
sure only captures explicit attitudes. Yet it the model does not assume that automatic
is likely that multiple processes—such as processes correspond to deontological prin-
implicit attitudes, executive control, and ciples and that controlled processes corre-
guessing—contribute to how people com- spond to utilitarian principles. Rather, peo-
plete both implicit and explicit measures. To ple are likely to have implicit moral attitudes
more precisely measure the construct of in- that correspond to a wide variety of moral
terest (implicit moral attitudes), we need to philosophies. In light of numerous theoreti-
decompose task performance into these un- cal and methodological debates about sacri-
derlying processes. This increased precision ficial dilemmas in moral psychology (Bartels
in measurement may allow us to better pre- & Pizarro, 2011; Bauman, McGraw, Bar-
dict moral personality and moral behavior. tels, & Warren, 2014; Greene, 2013; Kah-
In this chapter, we present a multinomial ane, 2015; Kahane, Everett, Earp, Farias, &
model of moral judgment, which allows us Savulescu, 2015; Gray & Schein, 2012), we
to quantify individual differences in implicit move beyond using these dilemmas and we
moral attitudes. Multinomial models for- do not equate these processes or their oper-
malize the latent cognitive processes that ating conditions with specific moral philos-
 Implicit Moral Cognition 519

ophies. Through dissociating these intuitive Across multiple experiments, we repli-


and deliberative processes, we may further cate a within-subjects priming effect on
understand when and why individuals differ moral judgment in the moral categorization
in their moral judgments and moral behav- task. Overall, people tend to make more er-
iors. rors when there is a mismatch between the
Our approach is unique in adapting im- moral content of the prime and target ac-
plicit measurement and multinomial model- tions. When people are judging morally
ing to understand implicit moral attitudes. neutral targets such as poetry and leisure,
The work presented in this chapter builds on they make more errors after morally wrong
intuitionist theories of morality, while taking primes than after morally neutral primes.
a formal modeling approach to differentiate Similarly, when people are judging morally
the component processes that contribute wrong targets such as genocide and killing,
to moral judgments. Multinomial model- they make more errors after morally neutral
ing proposes processes a priori as media- primes than after morally wrong primes.
tors between situational inputs (i.e., moral This behavioral pattern suggests that people
transgressions) and behavior (i.e., moral are having an unintentional response to the
judgments), rather than inferring processes prime actions that is causing changes in their
from task performance (Gawronski et al., judgments of the target actions.
2014). This makes multinomial modeling To understand the underlying processes
a novel and fundamentally social cognitive that are causing this effect, we apply mul-
approach to measuring implicit moral atti- tinomial modeling. The multinomial model
tudes (Gawronski & Bodenhausen, 2014). formally posits three underlying processes
that give rise to performance on the moral
categorization task. The first process is in-
What’s the Evidence? tentional moral judgment: the ability to
make accurate moral judgments about target
Across many experiments, we have provided actions, consistent with task instructions.
evidence that supports our approach to im- This parameter can be thought to capture
plicit moral attitudes (Cameron, Payne, Sin- executive control as deployed to achieve the
nott-Armstrong, Scheffer, & Inzlicht, 2017). task goal of morally judging target actions.
The first step develops an implicit measure The second process is the one of primary
that captures moral judgments. The second interest: unintentional moral judgment.
step validates a multinomial model that al- Unintentional moral judgment, or implicit
lows us to quantify individual differences in moral evaluations, is the tendency to moral-
implicit moral attitudes. ly judge target actions in a prime-consistent
First, we created the moral categorization way. If the prime is morally wrong, then it
task, a sequential priming task that assesses should inspire an implicit moral evaluation
moral judgment. In this task, people com- “wrong” that biases judgments of target ac-
plete a series of trials. On each trial, they see tions in that direction. If the prime is moral-
two stimuli in sequence: a prime word for ly neutral, then it should inspire an implicit
100 milliseconds, followed by a target word. moral evaluation “not wrong” that biases
The prime and target words are actions that judgments of target actions in that direction
are either noncontroversially morally wrong instead. Put another way, implicit moral at-
(e.g., murder, rape) or morally neutral (e.g., titudes toward the prime actions are being
baking, golf). People are instructed to judge measured via how they incidentally influ-
whether the target action is morally wrong ence moral judgments about the target ac-
or not, while avoiding being influenced by tions. Finally, the third process is response
the prime actions. Because we utilize ac- bias: a tendency to always judge target ac-
tions that are noncontroversially wrong or tions in a certain direction (e.g., always
not wrong, we can code target judgments guess “wrong”).
for accuracy. To ensure sufficient errors for Multinomial modeling formalizes how
analysis and to reduce response correction, these processes interact to produce moral
we impose a fast response deadline (from judgments on the moral categorization
400–600 milliseconds). task. If intentional judgment operates, then
520 S T U DY I N G M O R A L I T Y

people will always be correct regardless of primes is stronger for participants with in-
prime–target combination. If unintentional creased moral identity and guilt proneness
judgment operates, then people will be cor- and weaker for participants with increased
rect on trials in which prime and target have self-reported psychopathic tendencies. In
the same moral valence and incorrect on tri- other words, people who care more about
als in which prime and target have differ- morality have stronger implicit moral atti-
ent moral valence. For instance, if the prime tudes, and people who care less about mo-
murder precedes the target poetry, then the rality have weaker implicit moral attitudes.
implicit moral attitude toward the prime These effects tend to be specific to implicit
should be activated and lead people to inac- moral attitudes about moral transgressions,
curately judge the target poetry as morally as unintentional judgment after nonmoral
wrong. If response bias operates, then cor- negative primes does not consistently predict
rect responses will be determined by the di- these moral personality traits.
rection of the bias: If the bias is to guess that The multinomial model does not make
target actions are wrong, this will lead to strong assumptions about the operating con-
correct responses on wrong-target trials but ditions of the underlying processes of inten-
incorrect responses on neutral-target trials. tional judgment, unintentional judgment,
The model also posits conditional relation- and response bias. Although it would be
ships between these processes: Unintention- easy to assume that discrimination has char-
al judgment only operates when intentional acteristics of controlled processes—such
judgment fails, and response bias only op- as requiring cognitive resources—this as-
erates when unintentional judgment fails. sumption needs to be tested experimentally.
These relationships are logical and do not Imposing faster response deadlines during
specify the timing of when these processes the moral categorization task (e.g., 400 vs.
operate. 800 milliseconds) reduces intentional judg-
Because the multinomial model speci- ment, suggesting that this process is inhib-
fies expected accuracy rates based upon a ited under cognitive strain. On the other
priori assumptions, the observed accuracy hand, unintentional judgment is not affected
rates can be used to estimate model fit and by the deadline manipulation, suggesting it
to solve for the probabilities of each process may be a resource-efficient process. In relat-
operating. Model fit is obtained if the ex- ed work, we find that intentional judgment
pected and observed accuracy rates on the associates with the error-related negativ-
moral categorization task do not differ sig- ity, a neurophysiological signal of conflict
nificantly. If the multinomial model did not monitoring and behavioral control (Amodio
fit the behavioral data, that would suggest et al., 2004; Amodio, Devine, & Harmon-
that the model is not specified correctly and Jones, 2008; Inzlicht & Al-Khindi, 2012).
that alternative model structures should be Thus intentional judgment appears to ex-
considered. hibit characteristics of a controlled process.
Across experiments, we find that the Another question that may arise: Is this
multinomial model fits the data, suggesting task just about affect and not morality?
that the multinomial model is appropriate- Maybe what we are seeing on the moral cat-
ly specified. Testing additional hypotheses egorization task is negative affective prim-
about the underlying processes involves con- ing, and not anything about morality in
straining parameter estimates and examin- particular. As noted earlier, we think that
ing whether doing so significantly reduces the difference between implicit moral and
model fit. To examine individual-difference nonmoral attitudes is one of degree, not
correlations between process parameters of kind. Both are likely to involve negative
and other constructs, the multinomial model affect. However, implicit moral attitudes
has to be estimated for each individual par- should also involve conceptual content re-
ticipant in order to get parameter estimates lated to morality. To address this question,
for each participant. we adapted the moral categorization task to
Upon doing so, we find that the model include negative affective primes and targets
estimates converge with other morality that are not typically associated with moral-
constructs. In our work, we tend to find ity (e.g., cancer, rabies). We find that nega-
that unintentional judgment after wrong tive nonmoral primes influence judgments in
 Implicit Moral Cognition 521

the same direction as morally wrong primes titudes may exhibit similar variability. Does
(i.e., they lead people to make mistaken committing a moral transgression lead to a
moral judgments about neutral actions), but temporary weakening of implicit moral at-
not to the same extent. Similarly, uninten- titudes? Do certain kinds of cultures and en-
tional judgment after wrong primes is stron- vironments—such as those involving wide-
ger than unintentional judgment after nega- spread violence or corruption—lead to the
tive primes, suggesting that implicit moral long-term deterioration of implicit moral
attitudes are strongest when there is both attitudes?
negative affect and moral content involved. Another clear extension of this approach
For these reasons, we believe that although is to clinical populations. Our work has al-
negative affect is involved in implicit moral ready shown that moral personality associ-
attitudes, it is not the whole story: Concep- ates with implicit moral attitudes: People
tual content about morality is also needed to who care more about morality have stronger
produce implicit moral attitudes. implicit moral attitudes, and people with
Finally, we have demonstrated that our psychopathic tendencies have weaker implic-
approach can be adapted to moral issues on it moral attitudes. It stands to reason that
which opinions differ, such as gay marriage. clinical psychopaths should exhibit a simi-
We find that for people who explicitly believe lar effect. Our approach is especially useful
that gay marriage is morally wrong, gay mar- for this population, because incarcerated
riage primes act similarly to morally wrong psychopaths are typically highly motivated
primes on the moral categorization task— to appear morally normal (Schaich Borg &
they lead people to make mistaken moral Sinnott-Armstrong, 2013; Kiehl, 2008). It
judgments about target actions. Moreover, is thus imperative to bypass self-report and
unintentional judgment that gay marriage find a measure of morality that psychopaths
is wrong is modestly stronger among people cannot “beat.” Such an approach could be
who voted in favor of a North Carolina con- usefully complemented by recent work that
stitutional amendment against gay marriage. has applied implicit measurement and for-
Future research should consider other con- mal modeling to capture empathy for pain
troversial moral issues—such as abortion, (Cameron, Spring, & Todd, 2017).
capital punishment, and euthanasia—to This task can also be used to examine
extend the versatility of the approach. Aside moral judgments in clinical populations
from voting, it will also be important to fur- that have lesions to brain areas previously
ther establish the predictive validity of the associated with moral judgment. For in-
model parameters by examining relation- stance, patients with lesions to the ventro-
ships between implicit moral evaluations and medial prefrontal cortex (vmPFC) make
more prototypical moral behavior measures more utilitarian judgments in high-conflict
such as cheating, hypocrisy, and aggression. moral dilemmas that pit deontological rules
against a greater good, possibly because of
their difficulties integrating affect into deci-
Extensions and Expansions sion making (Koenigs et al., 2007; Thomas,
Croft, & Tranel, 2011). In recent work, we
We believe that this approach to implicit have administered the moral categorization
moral attitudes will prove useful in answer- task to vmPFC lesion patients (Cameron,
ing ongoing debates in moral psychology Reber, Spring, & Tranel, 2017). Compared
and sparking new ones. In other words, this with control participants, these patients
novel method may spur new moral psycho- exhibit reduced unintentional judgment in
logical theory (Greenwald, 2012). One of the response to moral transgressions—but not
most pressing initial extensions is to apply in response to nonmoral negative affective
our approach to understanding the stability primes—as well as reduced intentional judg-
of implicit moral attitudes. To what extent ment. Thus our task and modeling approach
do implicit moral attitudes fluctuate across captures a dual deficit in vmPFC patients.
different situations and contexts? Research Our approach also speaks to the debate
on moral self-regulation suggests that moral over distinct domains of morality. One of
behavior varies depending on prior moral or the most well-known domain theories,
immoral behavior, and so implicit moral at- moral foundations theory, separates mo-
522 S T U DY I N G M O R A L I T Y

rality into categories of harm, fairness, REFERENCES


loyalty, authority, purity, and liberty (Gra-
ham et al., 2013). Previous studies find that Amodio, D. M., Devine, P. G., & Harmon-Jones,
whereas conservatives tend to endorse all E. (2008). Individual differences in the regu-
lation of intergroup bias: The role of conflict
foundations as relevant to morality, liber- monitoring and neural signals for control.
als tend to endorse only harm and fairness Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
(Graham, Haidt, & Nosek, 2009). This 94, 60–74.
difference disappears when participants are Amodio, D. M., Harmon-Jones, E., Devine, P.
under cognitive strain or self-control deple- G., Curtin, J. J., Hartley, S. L., & Covert, A.
tion, suggesting that conservatives may be E. (2004). Neural signals for the detection of
engaging in motivated reasoning to ratio- unintentional race bias. Psychological Science,
nalize the binding foundations (Wright & 15, 88–93.
Baril, 2011). Yet other research finds that, Aquino, K., & Reed, A., II. (2002). The self-im-
portance of moral identity. Journal of Person-
using implicit measures, liberals and con- ality and Social Psychology, 83, 1423–1440.
servatives have similar affective reactions Bartels, D. M., & Pizarro, D. A. (2011). The
to violations across different moral founda- mismeasure of morals: Antisocial personality
tions (Graham et al., 2015). Our approach traits predict utilitarian responses to moral di-
could be adapted to test this question. The lemmas. Cognition, 121, 154–161.
moral categorization task can include prime Bauman, C. W., McGraw, A. P., Bartels, D. M.,
stimuli corresponding to different moral & Warren, C. (2014). Revisiting external va-
foundations, and an unintentional judg- lidity: Concerns about trolley problems and
other sacrificial dilemmas in moral psychol-
ment parameter can be estimated for each
ogy. Social and Personality Psychology Com-
foundation. If liberals and conservatives pass, 8(9), 536–554.
differ in terms of moral foundation endorse- Bishara, A. J., & Payne, B. K. (2009). Multino-
ment, then they should differ in their im- mial process tree models of control and auto-
plicit moral attitudes about different moral maticity in weapon misidentification. Journal
foundations. Our approach can also ad- of Experimental Social Psychology, 45, 524–
dress whether the single dimension of harm 534.
unites different moral foundations (Gray, Cameron, C. D., Brown-Iannuzzi, J. L., & Payne,
Young, & Waytz, 2012). If intuition after B. K. (2012). Sequential priming measures of
implicit social cognition: A meta-analysis of
harm primes predicts explicit endorsement
associations with behavior and explicit atti-
of all moral foundations, but intuition after tudes. Personality and Social Psychology Re-
purity primes does not, that would suggest view, 16, 330–350.
that harm has primacy in moral evaluation Cameron, C. D., Lindquist, K. A., & Gray, K.
(for more discussion of domain-general vs. (2015). A constructionist review of morality
domain-specific theories of morality, see and emotions: No evidence for specific links
Cameron, Lindquist, & Gray, 2015). between moral content and discrete emotions.
Personality and Social Psychology Review,
19, 371–394.
Conclusion Cameron, C. D., Payne, B. K., Sinnott-Arm-
strong, W., Scheffer, J., & Inzlicht, M. (2017).
Implicit moral cognition: A multinomial mod-
Implicit moral evaluations are pivotal to eling approach. Cognition, 158, 224–241.
many prominent theories of morality, and Cameron, C. D., Reber, J., Spring, V., & Tranel,
they matter a great deal for social life. We D. (2017). vmPFC lesions impair intentional
want to know that others share our moral and unintentional moral judgments. Manu-
reactions and are inhibited from transgress- script in preparation.
ing against us. Using implicit measurement Cameron, C. D., Spring, U. L., & Todd, A.
and multinomial modeling, we quantify in- (2017). The empathy impulse: A multinomial
dividual differences in these implicit moral model of intentional and unintentional empa-
thy for pain. Emotion, 17, 395–411.
attitudes and find that they vary as a func- Cima, M., Tonnaer, F., & Lobbestael, J. (2007).
tion of moral personality and predict moral Moral emotions in predatory and impulsive
behavior. We believe that our work will offenders using implicit measures. Nether-
motivate increased focus on the component lands Journal of Psychology, 63, 133–142.
processes that underpin everyday morality. Conrey, F. R., Sherman, J. W., Gawronski, B.,
 Implicit Moral Cognition 523

Hugenberg, K., & Groom, C. J. (2005). Sepa- theoretical as a good method. Perspectives on
rating multiple processes in implicit social cog- Psychological Science, 7, 99–108.
nition: The quad model of implicit task per- Greenwald, A. G., McGhee, D., & Schwartz, J.
formance. Journal of Personality and Social (1998). Measuring individual differences in
Psychology, 89, 469–487. implicit cognition: The Implicit Association
Conway, P., & Gawronski, B. (2013). Deontolog- Test. Journal of Personality and Social Psy-
ical and utilitarian inclinations in moral deci- chology, 74, 1464–1480.
sion making: A process dissociation approach. Greenwald, A. G., Uhlmann, E. L., Poehlman,
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, T. A., & Banaji, M. R. (2009). Understanding
104, 216–235. and using the Implicit Association Test: III.
Ferreira, M. B., Garcia-Marques, L., Sherman, Meta-analysis of predictive validity. Journal of
S. J., & Sherman, J. W. (2006). Automatic and Personality and Social Psychology, 97, 17–41.
controlled components of judgment and deci- Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional dog and its ra-
sion making. Journal of Personality and So- tional tail: A social intuitionist approach to
cial Psychology, 91, 797–813. moral judgment. Psychological Review, 108,
Gawronski, B., & Bodenhausen, G. V. (2014). 814–834.
Social-cognitive theories. In B. Gawronski & Haidt, J. (2012). The righteous mind: Why good
G. V. Bodenhausen (Eds.), Theory and expla- people are divided by politics and religion.
nation in social psychology (pp. 63–83). New New York: Pantheon.
York: Guilford Press. Haidt, J., & Bjorklund, F. (2008). Social intu-
Gawronski, B., & Payne, B. K. (Eds.). (2010). itionists answer six questions about moral
Handbook of implicit social cognition: Mea- psychology. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.),
surement, theory, and applications. New Moral psychology: Vol. 2. The cognitive sci-
York: Guilford Press. ence of morality: Intuition and diversity
Gawronski, B., Sherman, J. W., & Trope, Y. (pp. 181–217). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
(2014). Two of what?: A conceptual analysis Haidt, J., & Kesebir, S. (2010). Morality. In S.
of dual-process theories. In J. W. Sherman, B. Fiske, D. Gilbert, & G. Lindzey (Eds.), Hand-
Gawronski, & Y. Trope (Eds.), Dual-process book of social psychology (5th ed., pp. 797–
theories of the social mind (pp. 3–19). New 832). Hoboken, NJ: Wiley.
York: Guilford Press. Hofmann, W., & Baumert, A. (2010). Immedi-
Graham, J., Englander, Z., Morris, J. P., ate affect as a basis for intuitive moral judge-
Hawkins, C. B., Haidt, J., & Nosek, B. A. ment: An adaptation of the affect misattribu-
(2015). Warning bell: Liberals implicitly re- tion procedure. Cognition and Emotion, 24,
spond to group morality before rejecting it 522–535.
explicitly. Unpublished manuscript. Hofmann, W., Gawronski, B., Gschwendner, T.,
Graham, J., Haidt, J., Koleva, S., Motyl, M., Iyer, Le, H., & Schmitt, M. (2005). A meta-analysis
R., Wojcik, S., . . . Ditto, P. H. (2013). Moral on the correlation between the Implicit Asso-
foundations theory: The pragmatic validity of ciation Test and explicit self-report measures.
moral pluralism. Advances in Experimental Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin,
Social Psychology, 47, 55–130. 31, 1369–1385.
Graham, J., Haidt, J., & Nosek, B. A. (2009). Huemer, M. (2005). Ethical intuitionism. New
Liberals and conservatives rely on different York: Palgrave Macmillan.
sets of moral foundations. Journal of Person- Inzlicht, M., & Al-Khindi, T. (2012). ERN and
ality and Social Psychology, 96, 1029–1046. the placebo: A misattribution approach to
Gray, K., & Schein, C. (2012). Two minds vs. two studying the arousal properties of the error-
philosophies: Mind perception defines moral- related negativity. Journal of Experimental
ity and dissolves the debate between deontol- Psychology: General, 141, 799–807.
ogy and utilitarianism. Review of Philosophy Jacoby, L. L. (1991). A process dissociation
and Psychology, 3, 405–423. framework: Separating automatic from inten-
Gray, K., Young, L., & Waytz, A. (2012). Mind tional uses of memory. Journal of Memory
perception is the essence of morality. Psycho- and Language, 30, 513–541.
logical Inquiry, 23, 101–124. Kahane, G. (2015). Sidetracked by trolleys: Why
Gray, N. S., MacCulloch, M. J., Smith, J., Mor- sacrificial moral dilemmas tell us little (or
ris, M., & Snowden, R. J. (2003). Forensic nothing) about moral judgment. Social Neu-
psychology: Violence viewed by psychopathic roscience, 10(5), 551–560.
murderers. Nature, 423, 497–498. Kahane, G., Everett, J. A., Earp, B. D., Farias,
Greene, J. D. (2013). Moral tribes: Emotion, rea- M., & Savulescu, J. (2015). “Utilitarian” judg-
son, and the gap between us and them. New ments in sacrificial moral dilemmas do not re-
York: Penguin. flect impartial concern for the greater good.
Greenwald, A. G. (2012). There is nothing so Cognition, 134, 193–209.
524 S T U DY I N G M O R A L I T Y

Kiehl, K. (2008). Without morals: The cognitive Payne, B. K., Cheng, C. M., Govorun, O., &
neuroscience of criminal psychopaths. In W. Stewart, B. D. (2005). An inkblot for attitudes:
Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral psychology: Affect misattribution as implicit measurement.
Vol. 3. The neuroscience of morality (pp. 119– Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
149). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. 89, 277–293.
Koenigs, M., Young, L., Adolphs, R., Tranel, Payne, B. K., Hall, D. L., Cameron, C. D., & Bis-
D., Cushman, F., Hauser, M., . . . Damasio, hara, A. J. (2010). A process model of affect
A. (2007). Damage to the prefrontal cortex in- misattribution. Personality and Social Psy-
creases utilitarian moral judgements. Nature, chology Bulletin, 36, 1397–1408.
446, 908–911. Perugini, M., & Leone, L. (2009). Implicit self-
Krieglmeyer, R., & Sherman, J. W. (2012). Dis- concept and moral action. Journal of Research
entangling stereotype activation and stereo- in Personality, 43, 747–754.
type application in the stereotype mispercep- Riefer, D., & Batchelder, W. (1988). Multinomial
tion task. Journal of Personality and Social modeling and the measurement of cognitive
Psychology, 103, 205–224. processes. Psychological Review, 95, 318–339.
Luo, Q., Nakic, M., Wheatley, T., Richell, R., Schaich Borg, J., & Sinnott-Armstrong, W.
Martin, A., & Blair, R. J. R. (2006). The neu- (2013). Do psychopaths make moral judg-
ral basis of implicit moral attitude: An IAT ments? In K. Kiehl & W. Sinnott-Armstrong
study using event-related fMRI. NeuroImage, (Eds.), Handbook on psychopathy and law
30, 1449–1457. (pp. 107–128). New York: Oxford University
Monin, B., Pizarro, D. A., & Beer, J. S. (2007). Press.
Deciding versus reacting: Conceptions of Sherman, J. W., Klauer, K. C., & Allen, T. J.
moral judgment and the reason–affect debate. (2011). Mathematical modeling of implicit so-
Review of General Psychology, 11, 99–111. cial cognition. In B. Gawronski & B. K. Payne
Paxton, J. M., & Greene, J. D. (2010). Moral rea- (Eds.), Handbook of implicit social cogni-
soning: Hints and allegations. Topics in Cog- tion: Measurement, theory, and applications
nitive Science, 2, 511–527. (pp. 156–175). New York: Guilford Press.
Payne, B. K. (2001). Prejudice and perception: Sinnott-Armstrong, W., Young, L., & Cushman,
The role of automatic and controlled processes F. (2010). Moral intuitions. In J. Doris & the
in misperceiving a weapon. Journal of Person- Moral Psychology Research Group (Eds.), The
ality and Social Psychology, 81, 181–192. moral psychology handbook (pp. 246–272).
Payne, B. K. (2008). What mistakes disclose: A Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
process dissociation approach to automatic Thomas, B. C., Croft, K. E., & Tranel, D. (2011).
and controlled processes in social psychology. Harming kin to save strangers: Further evi-
Social and Personality Psychology Compass, dence for abnormally utilitarian moral judg-
2, 1073–1092. ments after ventromedial prefrontal damage.
Payne, B. K., & Bishara, A. J. (2009). An integra- Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 23, 2186–
tive review of process dissociation and related 2196.
models in social cognition. European Review Valdesolo, P., & DeSteno, D. (2006). Manip­
of Social Psychology, 20, 272–314. ulations of emotional context shape moral
Payne, B. K., & Cameron, C. D. (2010). Divided judgment. Psychological Science, 17, 476–
minds, divided morals: How implicit social 477.
cognition underpins and undermines our sense Wentura, D., & Degner, J. (2010). A practical
of social justice. In B. Gawronski & B. K. Payne guide to sequential priming and related tasks.
(Eds.), Handbook of implicit social cogni- In B. Gawronski & B. K. Payne (Eds.), Hand-
tion: Measurement, theory, and applications book of implicit social cognition: Measure-
(pp. 445–462). New York: Guilford Press. ment, theory, and applications (pp. 95–116).
Payne, B. K., & Cameron, C. D. (2014). Dual- New York: Guilford Press.
process theory from a process dissociation Wright, J. C., & Baril, G. (2011). The role of
perspective. In J. Sherman, B. Gawronski, & cognitive resources in determining our moral
Y. Trope (Eds.), Dual-process theories of the intuitions: Are we all liberals at heart? Jour-
social mind (pp. 107–120). New York: Guil- nal of Experimental Social Psychology, 47,
ford Press. 1007–1012.
CHAPTER 53

Into the Wild


Big Data Analytics in Moral Psychology

Joseph Hoover
Morteza Dehghani
Kate Johnson
Rumen Iliev
Jesse Graham

How can we investigate moral values in the real world?

We propose that naturally generated linguistic data, such as social


media content, can be used to study morality outside of the labora‑
tory.

Moral values are culturally variable entities as a number of notable disagreements (e.g.,
that emerge from dynamic, hierarchical in- see Graham & Iyer, 2012; Gray, Schein,
teractions between individual- and group- & Ward, 2014; Janoff-Bulman & Carnes,
level phenomena. Human-generated un- 2013; Rai & Fiske, 2011, on moral values;
structured data from sources such as social Cushman & Greene, 2012, and Kahane,
media offer an unprecedented opportunity 2015, on moral decision making). None-
to observe these phenomena in a natural theless, several points of convergence have
habitat, which is an essential vantage point emerged within the field. It is generally ac-
for understanding moral values and their cepted that morality is a fundamentally
role in moral judgment and behavior. social evolutionary adaptation and that it
The interdisciplinary science of moral- arises dynamically through interactions be-
ity has blossomed in the last decade, with tween native, interindividual mechanisms
insights from social psychology, neurosci- and sociocultural factors (e.g., Graham et
ence, behavioral economics, experimental al., 2013; Haidt, 2012; Mikhail, 2007; Rai
philosophy, developmental science, sociol- & Fiske, 2011; Fiske & Rai, 2015). How-
ogy, consumer behavior, and anthropology ever, although many contemporary ap-
informing one another and inspiring fur- proaches to morality are premised on some
ther interdisciplinary collaborations (Haidt, iteration of the social–functional evolution-
2007). This proliferation of research has led ary model, we believe that the majority of
to substantive theoretical advances, as well the research methodologies used to substan-

525
526 S T U DY I N G M O R A L I T Y

tiate these theories are, ironically, not able choose one or the other. Indeed, our view is
to adequately account for the dynamic social that researchers will benefit the most by de-
functioning of morality that they prioritize. veloping rigorous multimethod approaches
Most research on morality is conducted with that counterbalance the weaknesses of tra-
undergraduates in decontextualized labora- ditional methods with the strengths of big
tory settings, and, much more often than data analytics, and vice versa (Dehghani et
not, morally relevant variables are measured al., 2016).
using self-reports. Although there is nothing We believe big data analytics offer suf-
immediately wrong with these methods, we ficient advantages for basic psychological
doubt they can fully capture, for example, research to warrant their inclusion in social
the highly variable and subjective nature scientists’ toolkits. However, the behaviors
of individual moral values (Graham, 2014; responsible for generating morality-relevant
Meindl & Graham, 2014) or group-level big data—such as participation in online
moral processes (Ginges, Atran, Sachdeva, social networks—have become increasingly
& Medin, 2011). prominent across social groups and cultures,
Accordingly, we believe it is vital that re- which marks them as targets of study in
searchers supplement traditional methodol- their own right. As of January 2015, more
ogies with alternative approaches that have than 25% of the global population was
greater ecological and external validity and using social media (Kemp, 2015), and these
that are better able to capture the full social– platforms are increasingly being used as
functional range of morality. In this chapter, loudspeakers when morally relevant events
we argue that a range of computationally take place. Four of many possible examples
intensive methods, drawn predominantly are the hashtags (“#”) #blacklivesmatter and
from computer science and computational #baltimore, which have been used widely in
linguistics, can help researchers do just this. protests against recent incidents involving
By mining psychologically relevant informa- police brutality across the United States;
tion from large-scale, human-generated, on- #governmentshutdown, which was promi-
line data such as blog posts, news articles, nent in discussions of the 2013 U.S. Govern-
tweets, Facebook status updates, and social- ment shutdown; and #AllEyesOnISIS, which
network structures—collectively referred has been used by ISIS in disseminations of
to as “big data”—researchers can use these propaganda and by individuals to show sup-
methods to investigate morally relevant phe- port for the extremist organization.
nomena in the real world. These methods Clearly, this level of global connectivity is
enable researchers to investigate large-scale, unprecedented, and it likely has important
diachronic moral phenomena such as the effects on processes related to morality. As
diffusion of moral values through popula- social media communications become more
tions and the moralization of specific topics deeply woven into the fabric of society, un-
(Graham, Haidt, & Nosek, 2009; Sagi & derstanding trends in dynamic morally rel-
Dehghani, 2014). They also offer research- evant phenomena may increasingly require
ers new opportunities to investigate the re- understanding the psychological role that
lationship between moral values and moral social media play in contemporary societ-
behavior (Dehghani et al., 2016; Boyd et al., ies. By incorporating big data analytics into
2015), which is both notoriously difficult to the study of morality, researchers will gain
study in the laboratory and deeply important a new way to gather information in natu-
for understanding how morality functions ral settings about the structure of moral vi-
(Graham, Meindl, & Beall, 2012; Graham sions (Graham & Haidt, 2012), large-scale
et al., 2013). Of course, we are not suggest- moral behavioral patterns, and the relation
ing that these methods—which we refer to between the two. However, they will also be
as “big data analytics”—can or should re- able to explore the specific effects that to-
place traditional approaches. Big data ana- day’s communication technologies have on
lytics have their own weaknesses (Ruths & relevant phenomena. This methodological
Pfeffer, 2014), and they cannot match all of development could potentially transform the
the strengths of conventional methodolo- study of morality, improving the ecological
gies. Fortunately, researchers do not have to and external validity of a field that has re-
 Big Data Analytics 527

lied almost exclusively on self-reports sam- the relationship between natural language
pled from predominantly WEIRD (Western, and psychology at an unprecedented scale.
Educated, Industrialized, Rich, Democratic; How NLP is accomplished ranges consid-
Henrich, Heine, & Norenzayan, 2010) pop- erably between methodologies. For concep-
ulations. tual clarity, Iliev and colleagues (2014) sepa-
rate NLP methods into three broad groups,
which is the approach we take here. In the
Historical Context first group of methods, user-defined dic-
tionaries (UDD), researchers rely on expert-
Mining massive sets of extant data for psy- generated dictionaries, which specify words
chological information is a relatively new that are relevant to dimensions of interest.
practice, and it has become possible only Popularized in psychology by James Pen-
through constant increases in computa- nebaker and colleagues (Pennebaker, 2011;
tional power, availability of new methods, Tausczik & Pennebaker, 2010), these meth-
and greater accessibility of human-generat- ods aim to classify the semantic content of
ed data. Recently, two methods of analy- texts along a given dimension by summing
sis—natural language processing and social the within-text occurrences of words speci-
network analysis—have emerged as valuable fied by the UDD as related to the dimension.
tools for gleaning psychologically relevant For example, sums of positive- and negative-
information from online data. However, affect word occurrences can be used to infer
while these methods are gradually being in- the overall sentiment of a text (Kahn, Tobin,
corporated into psychological research, psy- Massey, & Anderson, 2007) and, further,
chologists still primarily rely on rudimentary such sentiment analyses can be used to make
and increasingly dated techniques. Further, predictions about individual differences,
until recently, these methods have remained such as depression (Rude, Gortner, & Pen-
almost completely neglected in moral psy- nebaker, 2004).
chology. Therefore, although a comprehen- The methods in the second class, feature
sive review of these methodologies is beyond extraction methods, forgo UDDs and rely
the scope of this chapter, a brief introduc- on machine learning algorithms to extract
tion to their aims and approaches is provid- features from texts that are predictive of
ed below, followed by a discussion of how variables of interest. In this case, a subset
they fit into contemporary models of mor- of texts preclassified on a variable of inter-
ally relevant phenomena. est (e.g., gender or religious affiliation) are
Natural language processing (NLP) used to “train” an algorithm to detect the
dates back to the 1950s (Nadkarni, Ohno- features that predict the target variable.
Machado, & Chapman, 2011; Jones, 1994; After training, the algorithm is tested on
Dostert, 1955/1976) and relies on a range of an independent preclassified set of texts,
approaches to parse semantic information which allows researchers to obtain relatively
from unstructured text (Iliev, Dehghani, & stable estimates of the classifier’s error rate.
Sagi, 2014). Initially developed in linguis- The algorithm can then be used to classify
tics and computer science, NLP has only unlabeled texts on the variable of interest
recently been incorporated into psychologi- through probabilistic estimation (though it
cal research. However, the notion that psy- should be noted that, as target texts increase
chological information can be gleaned from in difference between the training and test
language is hardly a new idea; for over a texts, accuracy has been shown to decrease,
century, researchers have relied on language sometimes dramatically).
to make inferences about human psychology One shortcoming of both UDD and fea-
(Freud, 1901; Kintsch & Van Dijk, 1978; ture extraction methods, however, is that
Braun & Clarke, 2006). The availability of they rely on individual word occurrences
digitized natural language corpora—drawn and are not able to account for the context
from sources such as blogs, Congressional in which a word occurs. Because words do
transcripts, news publications, and social not occur in isolation, this leads to substan-
networking platforms such as Facebook and tial information loss. The methods in the
Twitter—has allowed researchers to explore third class, word co-occurrence methods,
528 S T U DY I N G M O R A L I T Y

attempt to minimize this information loss works as exogenous factors that determine
by capturing the relations between words. In social behavior, recent research suggests
general, this is accomplished through several that non-network factors can also affect net-
steps, though these steps vary between spe- work formation. For example, Clifton, Tur-
cific methods. For example, latent semantic kheimer, and Oltmanns (2009) identified
analysis (LSA; Deerwester, Dumais, Furnas, reliable relationships between psychopatho-
Landauer, & Harshman, 1990; Landauer logical characteristics of military personnel
& Dumais, 1997; Dumais, 2004) involves and their social network positions. Further,
first representing words and documents— Vaisey and Lizardo (2010) found that moral
any discrete set of texts, such as tweets, blog disposition is a better predictor of network
posts, or entire novels—as vectors in high- composition than network composition is of
dimensional space. In this space, words that moral disposition, suggesting that networks
tend to appear in the same documents are might be better conceptualized as endog-
closer to each other, and documents that use enous factors with reciprocal, hierarchical
similar words are closer to each other. This relations to their nodes.
then permits analysts to assess the seman- In tandem, NLP and SNA allow research-
tic similarity between words and between ers to quantify individual-level natural
documents by measuring the “distance” language expressions and model complex
between these entities. Other word co-­ group-level network dynamics. These meth-
occurrence methods include, for example, ods have only recently begun to be applied
latent Dirichlet analysis (Blei, Ng, & Jordan, to research on morally relevant phenomena
2003; Blei, 2012), new vector-based meth- (e.g., Dehghani, Sagae, Sachdeva, & Gratch,
ods (e.g., Mikolov, Sutskever, Chen, Corra- 2014; Vaisey & Miles, 2014; Graham et al.,
do, & Dean, 2013; Sagi & Dehghani, 2014), 2009); however, we believe that they offer
and TopicMapping (Lancichinetti et al., a valuable complement to the methods tra-
2015). Although these methods are consid- ditionally used to investigate moral phe-
erably more complex than UDD and feature nomena, which rely almost exclusively on
extraction methods, they constitute much of self-report measures and highly controlled
the cutting edge in NLP. Accordingly, as mo- experimental paradigms. By incorporating
rality researchers begin testing increasingly these methods into their research programs,
sophisticated hypotheses using large-scale scientists—regardless of their theoretical
text corpora, it will be essential that they in- framework—can begin to provide stronger
corporate these methods into their analyses. tests for hypotheses by making predictions
Whereas NLP focuses on quantifying about real-world phenomena. Although
natural language generated by individuals, these methods are relatively new, they offer
social network analysis (SNA; Marin & possibilities that have been sought for de-
Wellman, 2011) aims to understand human cades by psychologists—access to relevant
behavior in terms of group-level systems of phenomena untainted by the biases that ac-
relational patterns. SNA represents social company laboratory-based research (Gib-
groups as relationships (“edges”) between son, 1977).
individuals (“nodes”) in order to quantify
complex group-level phenomena. As SNA
was originally developed by sociologists, so- Methodological Stance
cial network research tends to prioritize net-
work-based explanations of phenomena and, Over time, researchers have come to recog-
in some instances, rejects outright the notion nize that morality is constituted by a net-
that social norms and individual-level psy- work of components, including values, judg-
chological characteristics play an important ment, intuition, reasoning, and behavior.
causal role in network outcomes (Marin & Although exactly how these phenomena fit
Wellman, 2011). However, network analysts together is not fully agreed upon, this gen-
are increasingly recognizing the role of indi- eral view has been supported by research
vidual differences—particularly individual employing a wide range of methodologies,
moral differences—in network composition including laboratory experiments, cross-cul-
(Vaisey & Lizardo 2010; Hitlin & Vaisey, tural surveys, online questionnaires, implicit
2013). While traditional SNA treats net- social cognition measures, and neurophysi-
 Big Data Analytics 529

ological measurements, among others. De- methods cannot reach at scale. For example,
spite this methodological diversity, however, despite many notable differences, many con-
the vast majority of studies have relied on temporary psychological theories of mo-
artificial paradigms and self-reports to ap- rality converge on the view that morality
proximate access to real-world morally rel- emerges from a complex, recursive network
evant phenomena. Although these methods of individual- and group-level influences
have proven immensely useful, widespread (Haidt, 2007; Graham et al., 2013; Rai &
reliance on them has motivated concern Fiske, 2011; Fiske & Rai, 2015). Although
about the external validity of morality re- individual-level moral phenomena are gener-
search. For example, Bauman, McGraw, ated from the moral components mentioned
Bartels, and Warren (2014) question the de- above, these phenomena are also influenced
gree to which responses to moral judgment by social and cultural factors (Lakoff, 2002;
measures that use extreme scenarios actual- Marietta, 2008; Dehghani et al., 2009; Kol-
ly correspond to real-world moral function- eva, Graham, Haidt, Iyer, & Ditto, 2012;
ing, and other research suggests that conven- Baumard, André, & Sperber, 2013), which,
tional measures of moral utilitarianism (e.g., in turn, are influenced by individual-level
Greene, Sommerville, Nystrom, Darley, & factors. However, the extent to which tradi-
Cohen, 2001; Greene, Morelli, Lowenberg, tional research methods can capture cross-
Nystrom, & Cohen, 2008) might actually level interactions of moral phenomena is
be measuring nonmoral or even immoral limited. These interactions tend to occur
dimensions, rather than genuine utilitarian at scales larger than can be accommodated
moral concerns (Bartels & Pizarro, 2011; by laboratory methods, and their temporal
Kahane et al., 2015). dynamism further complicates conventional
Despite these criticisms, we believe that psychological investigation. However, mo-
artificial paradigms and self-reports have rality research employing computational
been and will continue to be valuable tools methods such as NLP and SNA suggests that
for probing moral phenomena. However, we these obstacles for laboratory research can
also believe that their value should not ob- be at least partially circumnavigated via big
scure their shortcomings. As has been wide- data analytics. For example, Sagi and Deh-
ly observed, theories based on self-report ghani (2014) were able to measure dynamic
measures—particularly those characterized changes in group-level moral concerns re-
by low ecological validity—need to be care- garding the World Trade Center attacks,
fully vetted for external validity (Cronbach, the Ground Zero mosque, and abortion
1949; Cronbach & Meehl, 1955; Messick, by analyzing text collected from the New
1995; Allen & Yen, 2001). Unfortunately, York Times, the blogosphere, and transcrip-
rigorous external validity tests of moral the- tions of U.S. Senate speeches, respectively.
ories have been infrequent, likely due to the Additionally, combining NLP and SNA,
considerable difficulty of accessing moral Dehghani et al. (2016) demonstrated how
phenomena through alternative methods individual moral concerns can influence
(Graham, 2014; Ginges et al., 2011; Hof- group-level phenomena such as social net-
mann, Wisneski, Brandt, & Skitka, 2014). work structures.
Thus, although we are not advocating for re- Although the application of big data ana-
searchers to stop using traditional measure- lytics to morality research is in its infancy, it
ment methods to study morality, we believe already seems clear that these methods can
the general absence of alternative methods make a substantial contribution to the field.
that can counterbalance the weaknesses of Researchers can use these methods to test
traditional measures is problematic. Such a established theories on data that are gener-
counterbalance can be at least partially pro- ated by messy, uncontrolled human behav-
vided by big data analytics, which we believe ior, which is a valuable opportunity given
can help validate traditional measures and the historical inaccessibility of real-world
theories. morality phenomena. By providing alterna-
However, big data analytics are useful for tive measurement methods, big data ana-
much more than validation. They can also lytics can also help researchers improve the
provide researchers ways to access dimen- external validity of their measures. Perhaps
sions of moral phenomena that traditional even more importantly, however, big data
530 S T U DY I N G M O R A L I T Y

analytics can help researchers study other- that provide powerful insights into the links
wise inaccessible dimensions of morality, between personality and language use (e.g.,
such as changes in moral values associated Schwartz et al., 2013; Back et al., 2010) and
with environmental and socioecological fac- that possess impressive psychometric quali-
tors, group-level moral phenomena, and the ties (e.g., Park et al., 2015).
relationship between real-world moral val- Similarly, morality researchers have suc-
ues and behavior. Although most theories of cessfully used techniques from machine
morality at least recognize the importance learning, NLP, and SNA to investigate
of these dimensions, there has been little re- morally relevant phenomena. In one of the
search that has been able to directly target earliest applications of NLP to morality re-
them. This has left considerable gaps in our search, Graham et al. (2009) developed a
understanding of human morality. If, as we UDD of words and word stems associated
believe, the goal of moral psychology is to with the constructs of moral foundations
understand moral functioning in the real theory (MFT). This Moral Foundations
world, then researchers must begin to fill Dictionary (MFD) was then used with an
these gaps. NLP program called Linguistics Inquiry and
Word Count (LIWC; Tausczik & Pennebak-
er, 2010) to explore variations in moral
Evidence concerns between liberal and conservative
congregations as expressed in a corpus of
For big data analytics to be useful for mo- sermons. Notably, their results converged
rality research, at least two conditions must with previous MFT findings. Sermons de-
be satisfied. Big data must contain reliable livered in liberal churches were more associ-
traces of moral phenomena left by human ated with harm and fairness concerns, com-
behavior, and these moral traces must have pared with those delivered in conservative
sufficient informational richness to offer churches, and sermons delivered in conser-
genuine insights into moral phenomena. vative churches were more associated with
Big data analytics have only recently begun purity and authority concerns, compared
being incorporated into morality research, with those delivered in liberal churches. In
yet there is already a growing body of evi- another investigation of moral value differ-
dence that these conditions are amply met. ences between liberals and conservatives,
Additionally, the increasing use of big data Dehghani and colleagues (2013) used an
analytics on nonmoral psychological phe- unsupervised hierarchical generative topic
nomena corroborates the value of these modeling technique based on latent Dirich-
methods for psychological research (Tausc- let allocation (LDA: Blei et al., 2003), which
zik & Pennebaker, 2010; Park et al., 2015). enabled them to extract topics from a corpus
For example, various NLP methods have of liberal and conservative blogs. Notably,
uncovered word usage patterns that predict though conventional LDA techniques have
depression (Rude et al., 2004), status (Kace- no control over what topics are extracted,
wicz, Pennebaker, Davis, Jeon, & Graesser, the method (Andrzejewski & Zhu, 2009)
2014), motivation (Gill, Nowson, & Ober- employed by Dehghani et al. (2013) used
lander, 2009), cultural epistemological ori- small sets of words from the MFD as seeds to
entations (Dehghani et al., 2009; Dehghani, favor the detection of topics associated with
Bang, Medin, Marin, Leddon, & Wax- moral concerns. Using subsequent statistical
man, 2013), academic success (Pennebaker, analyses to compare differences between the
Chung, Frazee, Lavergne, & Beaver, 2014), moral topics extracted from the liberal and
political affiliation (Diermeier, Godbout, conservative blogs, they found that their re-
Yu, & Kaufmann, 2012; Dehghani et al., sults were consistent with previous research
2014), personality (Oberlander & Nowson, on moral psychology and political ideology.
2006), and mental disorders. Further, per- Recent research has also demonstrated
sonality researchers—who were among the that NLP can be used to test sophisticated
first psychologists to begin rigorously incor- hypotheses about individual- and group-
porating big data analytics into their work— level moral phenomena. For example, in a
have developed measurement approaches series of three studies, Sagi and Dehghani
 Big Data Analytics 531

(2014) showed that the “moral loading” of five MFD dimensions. Notably, their results
specific topics can be estimated by calcu- converged with perceptions of both parties’
lating the semantic similarity between the stances on abortion: Democrats were most
contexts of keywords representing topics concerned about fairness, whereas Republi-
of interest and different moral concerns. In cans were most concerned about purity. Un-
essence, this method allows researchers to expectedly, Sagi and Dehghani (2014) also
measure the moralization of specific topics found that harm concerns—which seem
throughout an entire corpus and thereby deeply incorporated into conservative stanc-
produce group-level estimations of topic- es on abortion—were only the third-highest-
specific moral concerns. Using these estima- loading moral dimension. However, noting
tions, researchers can test hypotheses about that the purity dimension is represented by
longitudinal changes and between-group keywords such as abstinence, celibacy, and
differences in the moral loadings of topics of prostitution, Sagi and Dehghani (2014)
interest. For instance, across three studies, propose that these results indicate that, al-
Sagi and Dehghani (2014) used this method though Republicans endorse sanctity-of-life
to test hypotheses about the moral loadings arguments when debating abortion, they are
of three different topics: the World Trade more often concerned with the relationship
Center attack, the Ground Zero mosque, between abortion and sexual purity. In sum,
and abortion. In their first study, they used a these studies demonstrate that NLP can be
corpus of 1.8 million New York Times arti- used to test precise hypotheses about group-
cles dating from January 1987 to June 2007 level moral phenomena, as well as to uncover
to test the hypothesis that major events can potentially counterintuitive patterns in mor-
precipitate lasting changes in moral rhetoric. alization, such as the apparent primacy of
More specifically, they predicted that the purity concerns within Republican stances
9/11 attack on the World Trade Center led on abortion.
to significant increases in journalists’ use of In addition to detecting patterns in group-
moral harm and ingroup rhetoric associated level moral phenomena, big data analytics
with the World Trade Center but not with have been used to conduct novel explorations
the Empire State Building, which was used into the relationship between moral values
as a control topic. Consistent with their hy- and behavior. For example, Boyd et al. (2015)
pothesis, they found that harm and loyalty used a topic modeling technique called the
concerns associated with the World Trade meaning extraction method (MEM; Chung
Center increased dramatically following & Pennebaker, 2008) to investigate values
9/11, but that similar concerns associated and behaviors that emerge from natural lan-
with the Empire State Building remained rel- guage texts. Across two studies, Boyd et al.
atively low. In their second study, Sagi and (2015) compared estimates of participants’
Dehghani (2014) predicted that moral con- values generated from the Schwartz Value
cerns about the Cordoba Muslim Commu- Survey (SVS; Schwartz, 1992) and from
nity Center in New York City—popularly MEM analyses of open-ended text produced
referred to as the “Ground-Zero mosque”— during an online survey (Study 1) and of
would increase sharply during the highly more than 130,000 Facebook status updates
politicized debates that swept through the culled from myPersonality (an app that so-
blogosphere in 2010, but that this moraliza- licits Facebook data from users) data (Study
tion would decrease as the debates dwin- 2; Kosinski, Stillwell, & Graepel, 2013).
dled. Their results supported both predic- Although the results from the MEM analy-
tions, indicating that NLP methods can be sis converged somewhat with the SVS mea-
used to measure dynamic longitudinal pat- sures, the correlations between values-rele-
terns in moral rhetoric. In their final study, vant topics extracted by the MEM and the
they explored differences between Democrat SVS dimensions were generally low, which
and Republican moralization of abortion Boyd et al. (2015) interpreted as suggesting
by analyzing transcripts of nearly 230,000 that people’s natural language expressions of
U.S. Senate speeches. As predicted, they their core values do not necessarily conform
found that Republicans exhibited higher to the theory-driven set of values measured
moral loadings than Democrats across all by the SVS. Finally, after comparing the SVS
532 S T U DY I N G M O R A L I T Y

and MEM values measurements, Boyd et al. although we believe these methods can be
(2015) investigated the degree to which they immensely useful for researchers, we also
could predict everyday behaviors. Notably, recognize that the full extent of this useful-
in both studies, they found that the MEM ness remains an open question; there is still
measurements showed greater predictive va- much left to discover about both the value
lidity for participants’ reported behaviors and the limitations of big data. Accordingly,
than did the SVS measurements, suggesting in addition to revealing and exploiting the
that the expressions of values contained in insights available through big data analytics,
people’s everyday language might actually future research must also focus on uncover-
provide more information about their be- ing the boundaries of this insight. Some
havior than traditional self-report methods. specific goals should be to develop a better
Dehghani and colleagues (2016) also used understanding of how sampling biases affect
NLP measurements of moral values to pre- big data and how social media platforms af-
dict behavior. Specifically, they investigated fect user behavior (Ruths & Pfeffer, 2014). It
the idea that moral homophily (love of the will also be vital for researchers to critically
same) plays a prominent role in the forma- test assumptions about correspondences be-
tion of network structures. Their hypothesis tween social media behavior and real-world
was that the distance between two people in behavior. For example, Lewis, Gray, and
a social network could be predicted by the Meierhenrich (2014) note that, although
differences in the moral purity loadings of there has been much speculation about the
their messages. To test this hypothesis, they relationship between social media and civic
used the same adapted LSA method applied engagement, there has been little empirical
by Sagi and Dehghani (2014) to estimate investigation of this relation. Further, they
the moral loading of tweets collected from found that although social media is a pow-
188,467 Twitter users. They then generated erful tool for forming groups around civic
a model of the network structure connecting causes, group affiliation does not necessar-
these users and calculated the distance be- ily predict more meaningful civic behav-
tween them. Finally, using a series of statisti- iors, such as making financial donations
cal tests, they explored the degree to which to causes. Big data offer an unprecedented
differences in moral foundation–related window into human behavior; yet they are
concerns predict social network distance. nonetheless vulnerable to many of the issues
Supporting their hypothesis, they found a that distort the relation between other forms
strong association between purity difference of data and the phenomena they purport to
and network distance, and, importantly, measure. This does not negate our conten-
they also found that purity loading differ- tion that big data contain reliable and infor-
ence was the most accurate predictor of net- mationally rich traces of moral phenomena;
work distance, compared with the loadings however, it does highlight the importance of
of other moral concerns. Dehghani et al. testing inferences drawn from big data, as
(2016) then replicated this finding experi- well as the necessity of developing analytical
mentally by manipulating participants’ per- protocols that can account for issues such as
ceptions of moral similarity and measuring population and selection biases.
the effect that this manipulation had on so-
cial distancing. As in their first study, moral
purity difference predicted social distance Extension and Expansion
preferences above and beyond all other
moral foundation concerns. Although the Moral psychology holds that morality is a
importance of moral homophily has been fundamental component of human psychol-
previously recognized by social scientists, ogy and that the social sphere is both per-
these studies were, to our knowledge, the meated and partially structured by moral
first to investigate which moral similarities phenomena. However, there has been very
drive this phenomenon. little opportunity and, relatedly, very few at-
So far, this chapter has focused primar- tempts to investigate this directly. We know
ily on the advantages of big data analytics at least a little, and perhaps quite a lot, about
for moral psychology research. However, moral functioning in the laboratory and po-
 Big Data Analytics 533

tentially much less about moral functioning come “devoted actors” (Atran, 2006). This
in the world (Graham, 2014; Hofmann et kind of real-world predictive modeling will
al., 2014). Of course, the problem of inves- be doubly valuable for morality research-
tigating psychological phenomena in natural ers. Not only can it help illuminate current
environments has been the Achilles’ heel of events, but it also enables researchers to
psychology since its inception. In part, this evaluate moral psychology theories based on
problem has been driven by a simple lack of the degree to which they can predict human
data. The availability of big data and the ad- behavior in the wild—the gold standard for
vent of big data analytics definitely does not psychological science.
resolve the problem, but it does offer a par-
tial solution. By complementing traditional
methodologies with theoretically driven big REFERENCES
data analyses, researchers can dramatically
increase the verisimilitude of theories about Allen, M. J., & Yen, W. M. (2001). Introduc-
tion to measurement theory. Long Grove, IL:
real-world moral functioning.
Waveland Press.
In addition to advancing basic research, Andrzejewski, D., & Zhu, X. (2009). Latent
coupling big data analytics with theories Dirichlet allocation with topic-in-set knowl-
about the moral-psychological factors that edge. In Proceedings of the NAACL 2009
influence social behavior will enable moral- Workshop on Semi-Supervised Learning for
ity researchers to contribute substantive in- Natural Language Processing (pp. 43–48).
sights into real-world events. Social media Stroudsburg, PA: Association for Computa-
analysis is already widely incorporated in tional Linguistics.
predictive social and political forecasting Aquino, K., Freeman, D., Reed, A., II, Lim, V.
models. These models have shown promis- K., & Felps, W. (2009). Testing a social-cog-
ing potential to predict crime (e.g., Wang, nitive model of moral behavior: The interac-
tive influence of situations and moral identity
Gerber, & Brown, 2012; Gerber, 2014), elec-
centrality.  Journal of Personality and Social
toral outcomes (e.g., Unankard, Li, Sharaf, Psychology, 97(1), 123.
Zhong, & Li, 2014; Franks & Scherr, 2015), Atran, S. (2006). The moral logic and growth
and stock market trends (e.g., Bollen, Mao, of suicide terrorism. Washington Quarter-
& Zeng, 2011), for example. However, con- ly, 29(2), 127–147.
temporary forecasting models generally do Atran, S., & Ginges, J. (2012). Religious and sa-
not attempt to account for the role of moral cred imperatives in human conflict. Science,
phenomena in human behavior. As moral- 336(6083), 855–857.
ity researchers, we believe this is a grievous Back, M. D., Stopfer, J. M., Vazire, S., Gaddis,
oversight. For instance, recent work in social S., Schmukle, S. C., Egloff, B., & Gosling,
and cognitive psychology suggests that sa- S. D. (2010). Facebook profiles reflect actual
personality, not self-idealization. Psychologi-
cred moral values are important motivators
cal Science, 21, 372–374.
of political, social, and religious extrem- Bartels, D. M., & Pizarro, D. A. (2011). The
ism and violence (Atran & Ginges, 2012; mismeasure of morals: Antisocial personality
Dehghani, Atran, Iliev, Sachdeva, Medin,
­ traits predict utilitarian responses to moral di-
& Ginges, 2010), voting behavior (Caprara, lemmas. Cognition, 121, 154–161.
Schwartz, Capanna, & Vecchione, 2006; Bauman, C. W., McGraw, A. P., Bartels, D. M.,
Franks & Scherr, 2015; Johnson et al., & Warren, C. (2014). Revisiting external va-
2014), and charitable giving (Aquino, Free- lidity: Concerns about trolley problems and
man, Reed, Lim, & Felps, 2009) and that other sacrificial dilemmas in moral psychol-
they can emerge from the use of moral rheto- ogy. Social and Personality Psychology Com-
ric (Dehghani et al., 2010; Frimer, Aquino, pass, 8(9), 536–554.
Baumard, N., André, J. B., & Sperber, D. (2013)
Gebauer, Zhu, & Oakes, 2015). As Deh-
A mutualistic theory of morality: The evolu-
ghani and colleagues (2014) point out, re- tion of fairness by partner choice. Behavioral
searchers can use theoretically informed big and Brain Sciences, 36, 59–122.
data analytics to examine dynamic morality Blei, D. (2012). Probabilistic topic models. Com-
phenomena and thereby derive insights into munications of the Association for Comput-
the moralization of specific issues, as well as ing Machinery, 55(4), 77–84.
to help predict when “rational actors” be- Blei, D. M., Ng, A. Y., & Jordan, M. I. (2003).
534 S T U DY I N G M O R A L I T Y

Latent Dirichlet allocation. Journal of Ma- Dehghani, M., Iliev, R., Sachdeva, S., Atran, S.,
chine Learning Research, 3, 993–1022. Ginges, J., & Medin, D. (2009). Emerging sa-
Bollen, J., Mao, H., & Zeng, X. (2011). Twit- cred values: Iran’s nuclear program. Judgment
ter mood predicts the stock market. Journal of and Decision Making, 4, 930–933.
Computational Science, 2(1), 1–8. Dehghani, M., Sagae, K., Sachdeva, S., & Gratch,
Boyd, R. L., Wilson, S. R., Pennebaker, J. W., J. (2014). Analyzing political rhetoric in con-
Kosinski, M., Stillwell, D. J., & Mihalcea, servative and liberal weblogs related to the
R. (2015). Values in words: Using language construction of the “Ground Zero Mosque.”
to evaluate and understand personal values. Journal of Information Technology and Poli-
Proceedings of the Ninth International AAAI tics, 11(1), 1–14.
Conference on Web and Social Media. Re- Diermeier, D., Godbout, J. F., Yu, B., &
trieved from www.aaai.org/ocs/index.php/ Kaufmann, S. (2012). Language and ideology
ICWSM/ICWSM15/paper/view/10482. in Congress. British Journal of Political Sci-
Braun, V., & Clarke, V. (2006). Using thematic ence, 42(1), 31–55.
analysis in psychology. Qualitative Research Dostert, L. E. (1976). The Georgetown–IBM
in Psychology, 3(2), 77–101. experiment. In W. N. Locke & A. D. Booth
Caprara, G. V., Schwartz, S., Capanna, C., Vec- (Eds.), Machine translation of languages:
chione, M., & Barbaranelli, C. (2006). Per- Fourteen essays (pp. 124–135). New York:
sonality and politics: Values, traits, and politi- Wiley. (Original work published 1955)
cal choice. Political Psychology, 27(1), 1–28. Dumais, S. T. (2004). Latent semantic analysis.
Chung, C. K., & Pennebaker, J. W. (2008). Re- Annual Review of Information Science and
vealing dimensions of thinking in open-ended Technology, 38, 188–230.
self-descriptions: An automated meaning ex- Fiske, A. P., & Rai, T. S. (2015). Virtuous vio-
traction method for natural language. Journal lence: Hurting and killing to create, sustain,
of Research in Personality, 42, 96–132. end and honor social relationships. Cam-
Clifton, A., Turkheimer, E., & Oltmanns, T. bridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
F. (2009). Personality disorder in social net- Franks, A. S., & Scherr, K. C. (2015). Using
works: Network position as a marker of inter- moral foundations to predict voting behavior:
personal dysfunction. Social Networks, 31(1), Regression models from the 2012 US presi-
26–32. dential election. Analyses of Social Issues and
Cronbach, L. J. (1949). Essentials of psychologi- Public Policy, 15(1), 213–232.
cal testing. New York: Harper & Brothers. Freud, S. (1901). Zur Psychopathologie des All-
Cronbach, L. J., & Meehl, P. E. (1955). Con- tagslebens (Vergessen, Versprechen, Vergrei-
struct validity in psychological tests. Psycho- fen) nebst Bemerkungen über eine Wurzel des
logical Bulletin, 52(4), 281. Aberglaubens.  European Neurology, 10(1),
Cushman, F., & Greene, J. D. (2012). Finding 1–16.
faults: How moral dilemmas illuminate cog- Frimer, J. A., Aquino, K., Gebauer, J. E., Zhu, L.
nitive structure. Social Neuroscience, 7(3), L., & Oakes, H. (2015). A decline in prosocial
269–279. language helps explain public disapproval of
Deerwester, S., Dumais, S. T., Furnas, G. W., the US Congress. Proceedings of the National
Landauer, T. K., & Harshman, R. (1990). Academy of Sciences, 112(21), 6591–6594.
Indexing by latent semantic analysis. Journal Gerber, M. S. (2014). Predicting crime using
of the American Society for Information Sci- Twitter and kernel density estimation. Deci-
ence, 41, 391–407. sion Support Systems, 61, 115–125.
Dehghani, M., Atran, S., Iliev, R., Sachdeva, S., Gibson, J. J. (1977). The theory of affordances.
Medin, D., & Ginges, J. (2010). Sacred val- Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
ues and conflict over Iran’s nuclear program. Gill, A. J., Nowson, S., & Oberlander, J. (2009,
Judgment and Decision Making, 5(7), 540. May). What are they blogging about?: Person-
Dehghani, M., Bang, M., Medin, D., Marin, A., ality, topic and motivation in blogs. Proceed-
Leddon, E., & Waxman, S. (2013). Epistemol- ings of the Third International ICWSM Con-
ogies in the text of children’s books: Native- ference, Menlo Park, CA.
and non-Native-authored books. Interna- Ginges, J., Atran, S., Sachdeva, S., & Medin, D.
tional Journal of Science Education, 35(13), (2011). Psychology out of the laboratory: The
2133–2151. challenge of violent extremism. American Psy-
Dehghani, M., Johnson, K. M., Sagi, E., Garten, chologist, 66(6), 507–519.
J., Parmar, N. J., Vaisey, S., . . . Graham, J. Graham, J. (2014). Morality beyond the lab. Sci-
(2016). Purity homophily in social networks. ence, 345(6202), 1242–1242.
Journal of Experimental Psychology: Gen- Graham, J., Haidt, J., Koleva, S., Motyl, M., Iyer,
eral, 145, 366–375. R., Wojcik, S., & Ditto, P. H. (2013). Moral
 Big Data Analytics 535

foundations theory: The pragmatic validity of Jones, K. S. (1994). Natural language processing: A
moral pluralism. Advances in Experimental historical review. In A. Zampolli, N. Calzolari,
Social Psychology, 47, 55–130. & M. Palmer (Eds.), Current issues in compu-
Graham, J., Haidt, J., & Nosek, B. A. (2009). tational linguistics: In honour of Don Walker
Liberals and conservatives rely on different (pp. 3–16). Houten, The Netherlands: Springer.
sets of moral foundations. Journal of Person- Kacewicz, E., Pennebaker, J. W., Davis, M.,
ality and Social Psychology, 96, 1029–1046. Jeon, M., & Graesser, A. C. (2014). Pronoun
Graham, J., & Iyer, R. (2012). The unbearable use reflects standings in social hierarchies.
vagueness of “essence”: Forty-four clarifica- Journal of Language and Social Psychology,
tion questions for Gray, Young, & Waytz. Psy- 33(2), 125–143.
chological Inquiry, 23, 162–165. Kahane, G. (2015). Sidetracked by trolleys: Why
Graham, J., Meindl, P., & Beall, E. (2012). Inte- sacrificial moral dilemmas tell us little (or
grating the streams of morality research: The nothing) about utilitarian judgment. Social
case of political ideology. Current Directions Neuroscience, 10(5), 551–560.
in Psychological Science, 21, 373–377. Kahane, G., Everett, J. A., Earp, B. D., Farias,
Gray, K., Schein, C., & Ward. A. F. (2014). The M., & Savulescu, J. (2015). “Utilitarian” judg-
myth of harmless wrongs in moral cognition: ments in sacrificial moral dilemmas do not re-
Automatic dyadic completion from sin to suf- flect impartial concern for the greater good.
fering. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Cognition, 134, 193–209.
General, 143, 1600–1615. Kahn, J. H., Tobin, R. M., Massey, A. E., & An-
Greene, J. D., Morelli, S. A., Lowenberg, K., derson, J. A. (2007). Measuring emotional ex-
Nystrom, L. E., & Cohen, J. D. (2008). Cogni- pression with the Linguistic Inquiry and Word
tive load selectively interferes with utilitarian Count. The American Journal of Psychology,
moral judgment. Cognition, 107, 1144–1154. 120, 263–286.
Greene, J. D., Sommerville, R. B., Nystrom, L. Kemp, S. (2015, January 21). Digital, social and
E., Darley, J. M., & Cohen, J. D. (2001). An mobile worldwide in 2015. [Blog post]. Re-
fMRI investigation of emotional engagement trieved from http://wearesocial.net/tag/sdmw.
in moral judgment. Science, 293(5537), 2105– Kintsch, W., & Van Dijk, T. A. (1978). Toward
2108. a model of text comprehension and produc-
Haidt, J. (2007). The new synthesis in moral psy- tion. Psychological Review, 85(5), 363.
chology. Science, 316(5827), 998–1002. Koleva, S., Graham, J., Haidt, J., Iyer, R., &
Haidt, J. (2012). The righteous mind: Why good Ditto, P. H. (2012). Tracing the threads: How
people are divided by politics and religion. five moral concerns (especially Purity) help
New York: Vintage. explain culture war attitudes. Journal of Re-
Henrich, J., Heine, S. J., & Norenzayan, A. search in Personality, 46, 184–194.
(2010). The weirdest people in the world? Be- Kosinski, M., Stillwell, D., & Graepel, T. (2013).
havioral and Brain Sciences, 33, 61–83. Private traits and attributes are predictable
Hitlin, S., & Vaisey, S. (2013). The new sociol- from digital records of human behavior. Pro-
ogy of morality. Annual Review of Sociol- ceedings of the National Academy of Scienc-
ogy, 39, 51–68. es, 110(15), 5802–5805.
Hofmann, W., Wisneski, D. C., Brandt, M. J., & Lakoff, G. (2002). Moral politics: How liberals
Skitka, L. J. (2014). Morality in everyday life. and conservatives think. Chicago: University
Science, 345(6202), 1340–1343. of Chicago Press.
Iliev, R., Dehghani, M., & Sagi, E. (2014). Au- Lancichinetti, A., Sirer, M. I., Wang, J. X.,
tomated text analysis in psychology: Meth- Acuna, D., Körding, K., & Amaral, L. A. N.
ods, applications, and future developments. (2015). High-reproducibility and high-accura-
Language and Cognition, 1–26. Available at cy method for automated topic classification.
http://morteza-dehghani.net/wp-content/up- Physical Review X, 5(1), 011007.
loads/Iliev-Dehghani-Sagi-2014.pdf. Landauer, T. K., & Dumais, S. T. (1997). A so-
Janoff-Bulman, R., & Carnes, N. C. (2013). Sur- lution to Plato’s problem: The latent semantic
veying the moral landscape: Moral motives analysis theory of acquisition, induction, and
and group-based moralities. Personality and representation of knowledge. Psychological
Social Psychology Review, 17, 219–236. Review, 104(2), 211–240.
Johnson, K. M., Iyer, R., Wojcik, S. P., Vaisey, Lewis, K., Gray, K., & Meierhenrich, J. (2014,
S., Miles, A., Chu, V., . . . Graham, J. (2014). February). The structure of online activism.
Ideology-specific patterns of moral indiffer- Sociological Science, 1, 1–19.
ence predict intentions not to vote. Analyses Marietta, M. (2008). From my cold, dead hands:
of Social Issues and Public Policy, 14(Suppl.), Democratic consequences of sacred rhetoric.
61–77. Journal of Politics, 70, 767–779.
536 S T U DY I N G M O R A L I T Y

Marin, A., & Wellman, B. (2011). Social net- for unity, hierarchy, equality, and proportion-
work analysis: An introduction. In J. Scott & ality. Psychological Review, 118(1), 57–75.
P. J. Carrington (Eds.), SAGE handbook of Rude, S., Gortner, E. M., & Pennebaker, J.
social network analysis (pp. 11–25). London: (2004). Language use of depressed and depres-
SAGE. sion-vulnerable college students. Cognition
Meindl, P., & Graham, J. (2014). Know thy par- and Emotion, 18(8), 1121–1133.
ticipant: The trouble with nomothetic assump- Ruths, D., & Pfeffer, J. (2014). Social media for
tions in moral psychology. In H. Sarkissian & large studies of behavior. Science, 346(6213),
J. C. Wright (Eds.), Advances in experimen- 1063–1064.
tal moral psychology (pp. 233–252). London: Sagi, E., & Dehghani, M. (2014). Measuring
Bloomsbury. moral rhetoric in text. Social Science Com-
Messick, S. (1995). Validity of psychological as- puter Review, 32(2), 132–144.
sessment: Validation of inferences from per- Schwartz, H. A., Eichstaedt, J. C., Kern, M. L.,
sons’ responses and performances as scientific Dziurzynski, L., Ramones, S. M., Agrawal,
inquiry into score meaning. American Psy- M., . . . Ungar, L. H. (2013). Personality, gen-
chologist, 50(9), 741–749. der, and age in the language of social media:
Mikhail, J. (2007). Universal moral grammar: The open-vocabulary approach. PLOS ONE,
Theory, evidence and the future. Trends in 8(9), e73791.
Cognitive Sciences, 11(4), 143–152. Schwartz, H. A., Eichstaedt, J. C., Kern, M. L.,
Mikolov, T., Sutskever, I., Chen, K., Corrado, G. Park, G., Sap, M., Stillwell, D., . . . Ungar,
S., & Dean, J. (2013). Distributed representa- L. H. (2014). Towards assessing changes in
tions of words and phrases and their compo- degree of depression through Facebook. Pro-
sitionality. In C. J. C. Burges, L. Bottou, M. ceedings of the ACL 2014 Workshop on Com-
Welling, Z. Ghahramani, & K. Q. Weinberger putational Linguistics and Clinical Psychol-
(Eds.), Advances in neural information pro- ogy: From linguistic signal to clinical reality
cessing systems (Vol. 26, pp. 3111–3119). Red (pp. 118–125). Stroudsburg, PA: Association
Hook, NY: Curran Associates. for Computational Linguistics.
Nadkarni, P. M., Ohno-Machado, L., & Chap- Schwartz, S. H. (1992). Universals in the content
man, W. W. (2011). Natural language process- and structure of values: Theory and empiri-
ing: An introduction. Journal of the Ameri- cal tests in 20 countries. In M. Zanna (Ed.),
can Medical Informatics Association, 18(5), Advances in experimental social psychology
544–551. (pp. 1–65). New York: Academic Press.
Oberlander, J., & Nowson, S. (2006, July). Whose Tausczik, Y. R., & Pennebaker, J. W. (2010). The
thumb is it anyway?: Classifying author per- psychological meaning of words: LIWC and
sonality from weblog text. In Proceedings of computerized text analysis methods. Journal
the COLING/ACL on Main conference poster of Language and Social Psychology, 29, 24–
sessions (pp. 627–634). Stroudsburg, PA: As- 54.
sociation for Computational Linguistics. Unankard, S., Li, X., Sharaf, M., Zhong, J., &
Park, G., Schwartz, H. A., Eichstaedt, J. C., Li, X. (2014). Predicting elections from so-
Kern, M. L., Kosinski, M., Stillwell, D. J., cial networks based on sub-event detection
. . . . Seligman, M. E. P. (2015). Automatic and sentiment analysis. In B. Benatallah, A.
personality assessment through social media Bestavros, Y. Manolopoulos, A. Vakali, & Y.
language. Journal of Personality and Social Zhang (Eds.), Web Information Systems En-
Psychology, 108(6), 934–952. gineering–WISE 2014 (pp. 1–16). New York:
Pennebaker, J. W. (2011). The secret life of pro- Springer International.
nouns: What our words say about us. New Vaisey, S., & Lizardo, O. (2010). Can cultural
York: Bloomsbury Press. worldviews influence network composition?
Pennebaker, J. W., Chung, C. K., Frazee, J., Social Forces, 88, 1595–1618.
Lavergne, G. M., & Beaver, D. I. (2014) Vaisey, S., & Miles, A. (2014). Tools from moral
When small words foretell academic success: psychology for measuring personal moral cul-
The case of college admissions essays. PLOS ture. Theory and Society, 43, 311–332.
ONE, 9(12), e115844. Wang, X., Gerber, M. S., & Brown, D. E. (2012).
Pennebaker, J. W., Francis, M. E., & Booth, R. Automatic crime prediction using events ex-
J. (2003). Linguistic inquiry and word count: tracted from Twitter posts. In S. J. Yang, A.
LIWC 2001 manual. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. M. Greenberg, & M. Endsley (Eds.), Social
Rai, T. S., & Fiske, A. P. (2011). Moral psychol- computing, behavioral-cultural modeling and
ogy is relationship regulation: Moral motives prediction (pp. 231–238). Berlin: Springer.
CHAPTER 54

Applied Moral Psychology

Yoel Inbar

Is moral psychology overly focused on theory?

I argue that it is and that we need more descriptive research and


more application of what moral psychologists have learned to real-
world problems.

Is morality innate or learned through cul- that question is beside the point—as are the
tural experience? Is it intuitive or the re- theoretical disputes named above. Namely, I
sult of effortful, deliberative reasoning? Is argue that we needn’t wait for many of these
it best described as a single mental process, disputes to be resolved in order to apply
two processes, or more? Does moral cogni- moral psychology to important social ques-
tion rely more on domain-specific modules tions. Notwithstanding deep theoretical
or general-purpose mental equipment? The disagreement about process, the descriptive
diverse theoretical perspectives described empirical regularities that researchers have
in this volume take strong and often-con- uncovered can help us solve problems and
flicting positions on these questions, and answer questions in the real world today.
resolving them empirically is a laudable This is true because an understanding of
goal. However, history suggests that these what moral thinking looks like, and of how
fundamental theoretical differences will not moral beliefs motivate behavior, can help us
be resolved in the near future. Psychologists understand much real-world behavior that
have been investigating moral reasoning seems perplexing, irrational, or self-defeat-
empirically for somewhere between 60 and ing.
85 years, depending on whether the clock Of course, even what qualifies as “moral
starts with Kohlberg (1958) or with Piaget thinking” is controversial. However, as I dis-
(1932). Over this time, we have surely made cuss (1) there is much less controversy about
progress in the understanding of moral cog- descriptive claims than process claims, and
nition, but nonetheless there is still disagree- (2) even when there is controversy, there is
ment over many theoretical questions—as usually also enough common ground on de-
this volume shows. It is not obvious wheth- scriptive facts that can be useful in explain-
er this progress rate is encouraging or dis- ing everyday behavior. In the following, I
couraging, but for my current argument, describe two examples of what I mean.

537
538 S T U DY I N G M O R A L I T Y

Example 1: Why Do People Dislike attitudes at all (Frewer, Howard, Hedderly,


Genetically Modified Food? & Shepherd, 1999); polarized attitudes such
that there was no net attitude change (Frew-
Opposition to genetically modified (GM) er, Howard, & Shepherd, 1998); or even
food is widespread (Frewer et al., 2013; made attitudes more negative (Scholderer &
Priest, 2000), even for crops with great po- Frewer, 2003). So, giving people more infor-
tential to benefit the world’s least well off. mation doesn’t make things better and may
For example, “golden rice,” genetically even make things worse.
modified to combat vitamin A deficiency in In a recent paper (Scott, Inbar, & Rozin,
Asia and Africa, has been strongly opposed 2016), my colleagues and I hypothesized
(Harmon, 2013). Many people in the United that, for many people, attitudes about GM
States and elsewhere are worried about GM food are the result of absolute (i.e., deontic)
food safety—for example, in a recent survey moral values rather than consequence-based
of the American public, only 37% thought calculations. This would explain why people
genetically modified food was safe to eat have strong beliefs about the acceptability of
(Pew Research Center, 2015). This stands GM food despite knowing little about GM
in sharp contrast to the scientific consensus, technology and why providing more in-
which is that genetically modified crops are formation does not change beliefs (at least
no more dangerous to human health than not on average). To make our argument,
conventionally bred ones (American As- we drew from the literature on “sacred” or
sociation for the Advancement of Science “protected” values (Baron & Spranca, 1997;
[AAAS], 2012). Indeed, the same Pew survey Tetlock, 2003). Despite some superficial dis-
found that 88% of AAAS members thought tinctions, these literatures both describe the
GM food was safe. This 51-point gap be- cognitive and emotional consequences of
tween scientists and the public was the larg- holding deontic prohibitions (e.g., “Do not
est of any issue tested, including anthropo- cause the extinction of a species” or “Do
genic climate change and human evolution. not kill another human being”). Again, de-
Why should this be the case? For other is- spite some differences in the details, both lit-
sues on which the public and scientists dis- eratures agree on the important features of
agree, attitudes have become aligned with sacred/protected values: They entail the un-
broader political ideology. This is the case, conditional proscriptions of certain actions;
for example, with attitudes in the United they are protected from trade-offs with sec-
States on human evolution and especially ular values (especially money); and their vio-
climate change. Those on the right are much lation evokes strong emotions, such as anger
less likely than those on the left to say they and disgust (Tetlock, Kristel, Elson, Lerner,
“believe in” climate change, even though & Green, 2000). For example, many people
they are equally well informed about what believe that buying and selling human or-
scientists believe (Kahan, 2015). This is not gans is intrinsically morally wrong; that
the true, though, of attitudes toward GM organ markets should be prohibited regard-
food, which do not correlate consistently less of whether they might make people bet-
with political ideology (Khan, 2013; Kahan, ter off on average; and that organ traffick-
2015). ers are reprehensible and repugnant (Roth,
Scientific literacy is a strong predictor of 2007).
GM acceptance (Frewer, Scholderer, & Bre- We also drew on the literature linking dis-
dahl, 2003), so one very reasonable possibil- gust, in particular, to certain kinds of moral
ity is that people are simply misinformed. If violations. Although here there is more theo-
this were the case, dispelling people’s mis- retical disagreement, nonetheless most moral
conceptions about GM food should make judgment researchers agree that some moral
them more positively disposed toward it. violations evoke disgust and that disgust can
However, multiple studies in which people be distinguished from other moral emotions,
were given information explaining the ben- such as anger (Chapman & Anderson, 2013;
efits and casting doubt on the risks of GM Royzman, Leeman, & Sabini, 2008; Russell
food found no evidence of this. Exposure to & Giner-Sorolla, 2011, 2013). Furthermore,
these kinds of messages either did not affect at least some moral violations—those per-
 Applied Moral Psychology 539

taining to sex, food, and the body, or those DS-R) and regarding the consumption of
evoking notions of unnaturalness, impurity, genetically modified foods specifically; and
or contamination—seem to be condemned (3) disgust predicted support for legal re-
at least in part because they are disgusting strictions on GM (such as labeling, extensive
(Haidt, Koller, & Dias, 1993; Rozin, Haidt, safety testing, or outright bans), even when
& McCauley, 2008). Many people say dis- controlling for people’s ratings of GM risks
gusting but “harmless” behaviors (i.e., those and benefits.
in which there is not an obvious direct tar- Drawing on moral psychology helped
get of harm) are morally wrong; some well- us explain (1) why GM food opposition is
known examples include siblings who decide so widespread despite minimal knowledge
to have sex, a family who eats its (deceased) about GM technology; (2) why GM food
pet dog, and a man who masturbates into a attitudes resist disconfirmation by evidence
chicken carcass and then eats it for dinner about risks and benefits (e.g., Scholderer &
(Haidt et al., 1993). Certainly, some theo- Frewer, 2003); and (3) why the popular rhet-
rists would say that people don’t actually see oric about GM so often invokes metaphors
these kinds of behaviors as harmless (see, of pollution, contamination, and unnatu-
e.g., Gray, Young, & Waytz, 2012). They ralness (e.g., “Frankenfoods”; McWilliams,
might be seen, for example, as harming the 2015). It also provides a new lens through
protagonists’ social relationships (Royz- which we can understand attitudes toward
man, Kim, & Leeman, 2015), the commu- other novel food technologies, including in-
nity, or public decency. For our purposes, sect consumption (Rozin, Ruby, & Chan,
however, these theoretical disputes were 2015) and recycled water (Rozin, Haddad,
not important. Most researchers agree on Nemeroff, & Slovic, 2015). In both these
the (for us) necessary facts: Certain disgust- cases, there are convincible opponents and
ing behaviors are seen by many as immoral evidence-insensitive absolutist opponents,
notwithstanding the absence of an obvious just as there are for GM food. As in the
victim (Haidt et al., 1993); and many people present case, opponents of recycled water
explicitly agree that “whether someone did are also more disgust sensitive (Rozin et al.,
something disgusting” is morally relevant 2015).
(Graham, Haidt, & Nosek, 2009). By building on the foundations of moral
We drew on this research to help explain psychology, we were able to ask questions
GM food attitudes in a representative sample that had been missed in previous research
of about 850 Americans. We asked respon- on GM food attitudes. Most of this re-
dents for their views of the acceptability of search has proceeded from the explicit or
GM using a set of questions that have previ- implicit premise that consumers logically
ously been used to measure protected values reason about costs and benefits to arrive at
(Baron & Spranca, 1997). For our purposes, their attitudes, and thus it has focused on
the key question was whether participants rational or quasi-rational factors such as be-
agreed that GM should be prohibited “no liefs about GM risks and benefits (Siegrist,
matter how small the risks and how great 2000), trust in GM-related institutions, and
the benefits” (i.e., absolute opposition). We scientific literacy (Frewer et al., 2003). By
also asked people to rate how disgusted they employing an approach informed by moral
were when imagining people eating differ- psychology, we were able to add to this ra-
ent GM foods and measured their domain- tionalist approach, which—productive as it
general disgust sensitivity (using the Disgust has been—at the same time has significant
Scale—Revised (DS-R); Haidt, McCauley, limitations.
& Rozin, 1994, modified by Olatunji, Wil- We were able to do this despite the sub-
liams, Tolin, & Abramowitz, 2007). stantial theoretical debates in moral psy-
We found that (1) 46% of respondents chology; for our purposes we could remain
said they opposed GM and would maintain agnostic, for example, as to whether moral
their opposition for any balance of risks and judgment is primarily intuitive or reasoned.
benefits; (2) GM opponents, especially ab- All that we needed to assume was that for
solutist opponents, tended to feel heightened some judgments emotional intuitions play at
disgust, both generally (as measured by the least some role—a proposition that we think
540 S T U DY I N G M O R A L I T Y

most moral psychologists would be willing regarding global warming as are liberals and
to accept. Likewise, we were able to sidestep score just as highly on a quiz assessing sci-
the robust debate regarding when people are entific literacy and general reasoning ability
more likely to make consequentialist versus (Kahan, 2015).
deontological judgments; how these judg- Instead, it seems more likely that the liber-
ments are best measured; and whether they al–conservative divergence on global warm-
are the result of a single process, two pro- ing and the environment is the result not of
cesses, or more. We only needed to assume intrinsic differences in scientific openness,
that under some circumstances some people but rather of other features of the rhetoric
are willing to endorse absolute (i.e., deontic) surrounding environmental issues. The “five
prohibitions. Of course, we needed to know foundations” model of morality proposed
what expressions of deontic prohibition usu- by Graham, Haidt, and colleagues is a use-
ally look like, what questions best measure ful lens through which to view this rhetoric.
them, and what their consequences generally According to this model, secular Western
are. But note that all of these questions are liberals see morality as exclusively concern-
simply descriptive—they simply ask “what.” ing questions of harm and fairness, whereas
No doubt “why” and “how” questions— conservatives (and most people outside the
questions of process—will continue to com- West) have a broader conception of morality
mand the attention of most moral judg- that includes questions of purity, deference
ment researchers. But I think it is important to legitimate authority, and loyalty to one’s
to consider how much can be achieved by ingroup (Haidt & Graham, 2007; Graham
drawing on largely descriptive research. et al., 2009; Graham et al., 2011). It is im-
portant to note that this model can be ap-
plied purely descriptively, as a summary and
Example 2. What Environmental Appeals classification of the kinds of things people
Are Most Effective? find morally relevant. On these terms, it is
perfectly compatible with, for example, a
Unlike GM food attitudes, attitudes to- dyadic view of morality (Gray et al., 2012),
ward the environment in general and global on which perceiving a moral action entails
warming in particular are strongly associ- the perception of an agent (who deserves
ated with political ideology, particularly in blame or praise) and a patient (who is helped
the United States. Political liberals tend to or harmed). On such an account a “violation
endorse both the scientific conventional wis- of authority” might be seen to harm an au-
dom on climate change (i.e., that it is hap- thority figure or structure, the social order,
pening and that humans are at least partly and so on. The point is that the descriptive
responsible) and more restrictive environ- facts (a taxonomy of the things that people
mental regulations. Political conservatives describe as “moral”) can be separated from
tend to be more skeptical of environmen- an underlying theoretical claim about the
tal regulation and of the consensus opinion deep structure of morality.
among scientists regarding climate change Applying the five-foundations model to
(DeSilver, 2013; Dunlap, Xiao, & Mc- the rhetoric surrounding environmental is-
Cright, 2001; McCright & Dunlap, 2011). sues in the United States yields some useful
Some have argued that this shows liberals to insights. When people attempt to persuade
be inherently more open to science than con- others to care about the environment—such
servatives, perhaps due to fundamental per- as in online videos or newspaper op-eds—
sonality differences associated with political they are substantially more likely to do so
ideology (Mooney, 2012). But the absence using moral language of harm and care
of any differences between liberals and con- than of, say, authority or purity (Feinberg
servatives in GM food acceptance—which is & Willer, 2013, Study 1). This may well be
strongly associated with science knowledge because pro-environment messages are more
and education (Frewer et al., 2003)—makes likely to be created by liberals, who use lan-
this interpretation less plausible. So does re- guage that naturally seems most morally
search showing that conservatives are just as persuasive to them (a moral version of the
well-informed about the scientific consensus “curse of knowledge”). Research showing
 Applied Moral Psychology 541

that conservatives are more responsive to fore we have spent time documenting what,
moral messages emphasizing purity suggests exactly, it is we are trying to explain. The
a straightforward hypothesis: Conservatives same argument is made by Rozin (2001),
should be more influenced by environmental who points out that researchers in the physi-
messages employing rhetoric of purity (and cal sciences made a great deal of progress
its opposite, degradation). And indeed, this simply by making careful observations. Al-
is the case. When people were exposed to though these observations were, of course,
a purity-themed pro-environment message informed by expertise, they were not intend-
that emphasized environmental pollution ed to test a process model, but only to docu-
and contamination, conservatives supported ment empirical facts. These facts could then
environmental protection legislation just as be used to build theory, but even if the theo-
much as liberals did (Feinberg & Willer, ries devised to explain those observations
2013, Study 3). And although conserva- were wrong, the data themselves were still
tives in all conditions were more skeptical useful, both in future theory-building and
of global warming than were liberals, this in practice. Even if you erroneously believe
difference was significantly smaller in the that the Earth is the center of the universe,
“purity message” condition. carefully recording the motions of celestial
These results may seem surprising, but bodies helps you navigate more accurately—
they are consistent with how one prominent and one day, it can lead to the realization
conservative has recently discussed environ- that the Earth revolves around the sun. Even
mental issues. In the recent draft Encyclical today, researchers in the physical sciences
Letter “On Care for our Common Home,” are much more likely to publish purely de-
Pope Francis introduced a section on “Pollu- scriptive papers than are social psychologists
tion and Climate Change” by writing, “The (Rozin, 2001).
earth, our home, is beginning to look more The hyper-focus on process and experi-
and more like an immense pile of filth. In ment (and consequent neglect of description)
many parts of the planet, the elderly lament that characterizes much of psychology seems
that once beautiful landscapes are now cov- especially acute in moral psychology. Focus-
ered with rubbish.” (Francis, 2015). ing on process above all else tends to encour-
Again, employing the five-foundations age researchers to construct highly unrealis-
model to understand people’s real-world at- tic abstractions to isolate and manipulate the
titudes does not depend on a commitment important variables. Trolley problems, for
to one process account of moral reasoning example, have been called the “fruit fly” of
over another. It may well be that when con- moral psychology—by their simplicity, they
servatives say that disgusting behaviors are are supposed to allow us to understand more
immoral, they have in mind some actual or complicated processes of moral reasoning in
symbolic victims that they think are being real-life situations. There is no question that
harmed. But whether or not this is true, the abstract and unusual scenarios can be infor-
observation that liberals and conservatives mative, but a research program that focuses
(or Westerners and non-Westerners) respond exclusively on highly abstract scenarios with
differently to messages emphasizing purity little resemblance to everyday moral think-
and degradation can be usefully applied. ing runs serious risks. If the theory mo-
tivating the studies is wrong, there can be
little left to salvage, because the data have
More Description, Less Process little value outside a very specific theoretical
paradigm. Or if it turns out that the para-
Most social psychologists would probably digm doesn’t really tap the processes it was
agree that the field’s primary aim is the un- believed to—if, for example, endorsement of
derstanding of mental processes by means of pushing people off bridges taps antisocial-
experiments. There is no question that un- ity rather than consequentialism (Bartels
derstanding process is important, but good & Pizarro, 2011)—all the careful experi-
description (i.e., the what rather than the mentation within that paradigm can turn
how) is just as important. Indeed, it may be out to be uninterpretable. This is not true
premature to focus so heavily on process be- of research programs that focus on describ-
542 S T U DY I N G M O R A L I T Y

ing real-world phenomena. Here, the theory (2001). Politics and environment in America:
may very well be wrong, but this does not Partisan and ideological cleavages in public
render the descriptions valueless. Process- support for environmentalism. Environmental
focused research can certainly yield valuable Politics, 10, 23–48.
Feinberg, M., & Willer, R. (2013). The moral
insights, but it is prudent to hedge our bets roots of environmental attitudes. Psychologi-
by investing in descriptive research as well. cal Science, 24, 56–62.
Francis. (2015, May 24). Laudato si’: On care
for our common home [Encyclical letter]. The
Conclusion Vatican: Libreria Editrice Vaticana.
Frewer, L. J., Howard, C., Hedderley, D., &
Current moral psychology offers an all-you- Shepherd, R. (1997). Consumer attitudes to-
can-eat buffet of theories, perspectives, and wards different food-processing technologies
approaches. In many ways this is a good used in cheese production: The influence of
thing; robust theoretical disagreement re- consumer benefit. Food Quality and Prefer-
ence, 8, 271–280.
flects scientific progress. Notwithstanding, Frewer, L. J., Howard, C., & Shepherd, R.
in all the theoretical debate it is possible to (1998). The influence of initial attitudes on
lose sight of the useful descriptive facts we responses to communication about genetic en-
have accumulated. Applying these obser- gineering in food production. Agriculture and
vations to domains outside moral psychol- Human Values, 15, 15–30.
ogy—for example, to people’s attitudes on Frewer, L. J., Scholderer, J., & Bredahl, L.
contentious social and political issues—can (2003). Communicating about the risks and
lead to real insights, even while there is still benefits of genetically modified foods: The
substantial theoretical debate within moral mediating role of trust. Risk Analysis, 23,
psychology. Especially if moral psycholo- 1117–1133.
Frewer, L. J., van der Lans, I. A., Fischer, A. R.
gists spend more of their time describing H., Reinders, M. J., Menozzi, D., Zhang, X.,
real-world moral phenomena, rather than . . . Zimmermann, K. L. (2013). Public per-
testing competing hypotheses in abstract, ceptions of agri-food applications of genetic
simplified stimuli, researchers in the rest modification: A systematic review and meta-
of psychology and beyond can learn much analysis. Trends in Food Science and Technol-
from our research. ogy, 30, 142–152.
Graham, J., Haidt, J., & Nosek, B. A. (2009).
Liberal and conservatives rely on different set
REFERENCES of moral foundations. Journal of Personality
and Social Psychology, 96, 1029–1046.
American Association for the Advancement Graham, J., Nosek, B. A., Haidt, J., Iyer, R., Kol-
of Science. (2012, October 20). Labeling of eva, S., & Ditto, P. H. (2011). Mapping the
genetically modified foods. Retrieved from moral domain. Journal of Personality and So-
http://archives.aaas.org/docs/resolutions. cial Psychology, 101, 366–385.
php?doc_id=464. Gray, K., Young, L., & Waytz, A. (2012). Mind
Baron, J., & Spranca, M. (1997). Protected val- perception is the essence of morality. Psycho-
ues. Organizational Behavior and Human logical Inquiry, 23, 101–124.
Decision Processes, 70, 1–16. Haidt, J., & Graham, J. (2007). When morality
Bartels, D. M., & Pizarro, D. A. (2011). The opposes justice: Conservatives have moral in-
mismeasure of morals: Antisocial personality tuitions that liberals may not recognize. Social
traits predict utilitarian responses to moral di- Justice Research, 20, 98–116.
lemmas. Cognition, 121, 154–161. Haidt, J., Koller, S. H., & Dias, M. G. (1993).
Chapman, H. A., & Anderson, A. K. (2013). Affect, culture, and morality, or is it wrong to
Things rank and gross in nature: A review and eat your dog? Journal of Personality and So-
synthesis of moral disgust. Psychological Bul- cial Psychology, 65, 613–628.
letin, 139, 300–327. Haidt, J., McCauley, C., & Rozin, P. (1994). In-
DeSilver, D. (2013). Most Americans say global dividual differences in sensitivity to disgust: A
warming is real, but opinions split on why. scale sampling seven domains of disgust elici-
Retrieved from www.pewresearch.org/fact- tors. Personality and Individual Differences,
tank/2013/06/06/most-americans-say-glob- 16, 701–713.
al-warming-is-real-but-opinions-split-on- Harmon, A. (2013, August 24). Golden rice:
why. Lifesaver? New York Times. Retrieved from
Dunlap, R. E., Xiao, C., & McCright, A. M. www.nytimes.com.
 Applied Moral Psychology 543

Kahan, D. M. (2015). Climate-science commu- (2008). “You make me sick”: Moral dyspepsia
nication and the measurement problem. Ad- as a reaction to third-party sibling incest. Mo-
vances in Political Psychology, 36, 1–43. tivation and Emotion, 32, 100–108.
Khan, R. (2013, June 11). Do liberals oppose Rozin, P. (2001). Social psychology and science:
genetically modified organisms more than Some lessons from Solomon Asch. Personality
conservatives? Retrieved from http://blogs. and Social Psychology Review, 5, 2–14.
discovermagazine.com/gnxp/2013/06/do- Rozin, P., Haddad, B., Nemeroff, C., & Slovic,
liberals-oppose-genetically-modified-organ- P. (2015). Psychological aspects of the rejec-
isms-more-than-conservatives. tion of recycled water: Contamination, puri-
Kohlberg, L. (1958). The development of modes fication and disgust. Judgment and Decision
of thinking and choices in years 10 to 16. Un- Making, 10, 50–63.
published doctoral dissertation, University of Rozin, P., Haidt, J., & McCauley, C. R. (2008).
Chicago, Chicago, IL. Disgust. In M. Lewis, J. M. Haviland-Jones,
McCright, A. M., & Dunlap, R. E. (2011). The & L. F. Barrett (Eds.), Handbook of emotions
politicization of climate change and polariza- (3rd ed., pp. 757–776). New York: Guilford
tion in the American public’s views of global Press.
warming, 2001–2010. Sociological Quarterly, Rozin, P., Ruby, M., & Chan, C. (2015). Deter-
52, 155–194. minants of willingness to eat insects in the
McWilliams, J. (2015). Ban GMOs: That shit U.S.A. and India. Journal of Insects as Food
ain’t food. Pacific Standard. Retrieved from and Feed, 1(3), 215–225.
www.psmag.com/nature-and-technology/ Russell, P. S., & Giner-Sorolla, R. (2011). Moral
ban-gmos-that-shit-aint-food. anger, but not moral disgust, responds to in-
Mooney, C. (2012). The Republican brain: The tentionality. Emotion, 11, 233–240.
science of why they deny science—and reality. Russell, P. S., & Giner-Sorolla, R. (2013). Bodily
Hoboken, NJ: Wiley. moral disgust: What it is, how it is different
Olatunji, B. O., Williams, N. L., Tolin, D. F., & from anger, and why it is an unreasoned emo-
Abramowitz, J. S. (2007). The Disgust Scale: tion. Psychological Bulletin, 139, 328–351.
Item analysis, factor structure, and sugges- Scholderer, J., & Frewer, L. J. (2003). The bio-
tions for refinement. Psychological Assess- technology communication paradox: Experi-
ment, 19, 281–297. mental evidence and the need for a new strate-
Pew Research Center. (2015, January 28). Pub- gy. Journal of Consumer Policy, 26, 125–157.
lic and scientists views on science and so- Scott, S. S., Inbar, Y., & Rozin, P. (2016). Evi-
ciety. Retrieved from www.pewinternet. dence for absolute moral opposition to ge-
org/2015/01/29/public-and-scientists-views- netically modified food in the United States.
on-science-and-society/pi_ 2015– 01–29_sci- Perspectives on Psychological Science, 11(3),
ence-and-society-00–01. 315–324.
Piaget, J. (1932). The moral judgment of the Siegrist, M. (2000). The influence of trust and
child. London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner. perceptions of risks and benefits on the ac-
Priest, S. H. (2000). US public opinion divided ceptance of gene technology. Risk Analysis,
over biotechnology? Nature Biotechnology, 20(2), 195–203.
18, 939–942. Tetlock, P. E. (2003). Thinking the unthinkable:
Roth, A. E. (2007). Repugnance as a constraint Sacred values and taboo cognition. Trends in
on markets. Journal of Economic Perspec- Cognitive Sciences, 7, 320–324.
tives, 21, 37–58. Tetlock, P. E., Kristel, O. V., Elson, S. B., Lerner,
Royzman, E. B., Kim, K., & Leeman, R. F. J., & Green, M. C. (2000). The psychology
(2015). The curious tale of Julie and Mark: of the unthinkable: Taboo trade-offs, forbid-
Unraveling the moral dumbfounding effect. den base rates, and heretical counterfactuals.
Judgment and Decision Making, 10, 296–313. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
Royzman, E. B., Leeman, R. F., & Sabini, J. 78(5), 853–870.
PART XII
CLARIFYING MORALITY

Q U E S T I O N S A N S W E R E D I N PA R T X I I

CHAPTER 55  How can we specify the boundaries


of the moral domain?

CHAPTER 56  Can human cognition be divided neatly into moral


and nonmoral elements?

CHAPTER 57  Are moral judgments as a whole innate, culturally variable,


intuitive, or based on multiple or special processes?
CHAP TER 55

The Moral Domain

Stephen Stich

How can we specify the boundaries of the moral domain?

We can’t, because the moral domain does not exist.

The central task to which contemporary moral The Project of Defining Morality:


philosophers have addressed themselves is that What It Is and What It Isn’t
of listing the distinctive characteristics of moral
utterances.
—Alasdair MacIntyre (1957, p. 325) The project begins with a pair of intuitive
distinctions that most WEIRD philosophers
During much of the 20th century and on into take to be obvious.1 The first distinction
the 21st, philosophers have devoted a great separates claims like those in Group 1 from
deal of effort to the project of constructing claims like those in Group 2.
and defending a definition of morality (Wal-
lace & Walker 1970; Gert, 2005, Chapter Group 1 Group 2
1; Gert, 2012). More recently, psychologists, 1. People should 1. More people were
anthropologists, and other social scientists not murder other murdered in New
have joined the debate and introduced a new people. York in 1994 than
name for an old problem. In this literature, in 2014.
the term “the moral domain” is often used,
2. It is wrong for 2. Father–daughter
and the goal is to offer and defend a defini- fathers to have sex is more
tion of the moral domain. In this chapter I sex with their common than
argue that this project should be abandoned. daughters. mother–son sex.
I maintain that there is no correct definition
of morality and that the moral domain does 3. Wealthy people 3. In the U.S.A., the
not exist! Before setting out the case for this ought to help those richest 1% control
rather provocative view, I’ll need to provide who are less well 40% of the wealth.
off.
an account of the project that I’ll be criticiz-
ing. I’ll start by explaining what those who 4. People should not 4. Starfish are the
seek to define the moral domain are—and eat raw oysters in main predators for
are not—trying to do. July. oysters.

547
548 CLARIF YING MOR ALIT Y

5. It is wrong to eat 5. On average, many nonphilosophers, think is of funda-


pasta with your Italians eat over mental importance. This divides the moral
fingers 30 kgs. of pasta a
year.
claims that are true (or correct, or valid, or
justified) from those that are false (or incor-
6. Jews ought to go 6. Most orthodox rect, or invalid, or unjustified). Figure 55.1
to synagogue on Jews go to provides a useful reminder of the spate of
Yom Kippur. synagogue on Yom distinctions I have drawn thus far.
Kippur. Not all philosophers think that there is
a distinction between true and false moral
The claims in Group 1 are normative claims. Emotivists and other noncognitiv-
claims; those in Group 2 are factual claims. ists argue that moral claims are neither true
The second distinction focuses on the nor- nor false—they are not “truth apt.” Moral
mative claims. It divides them into two cat- skeptics and moral nihilists agree. But most
egories. Claims like the first three in Group historically important philosophers, and all
1 are moral claims; claims like the following contemporary “moral realists,” maintain
three are nonmoral claims. The nonmoral that some moral claims are true and that dis-
claims can be further divided into catego- covering and defending moral truths about
ries like prudential claims, etiquette claims, important matters is a central goal of moral
and religious claims, some of which may be philosophy. Many nonphilosophers are also
categorized as conventional. But for the mo- profoundly interested in which moral claims
ment I ignore those further divisions. The are true, though most of these folks have lit-
goal of the project of providing a definition tle or no interest in what distinguishes moral
of morality is to characterize the set of moral claims from nonmoral normative claims. All
claims in a way that makes it clear what dis- of this is important for our purposes, be-
tinguishes those claims from nonmoral nor- cause far too many people working in this
mative claims. 2 area fail to keep the distinction between
Within the moral domain, there is anoth- these two projects in mind. The project that
er distinction that many philosophers, and we are concerned with is characterizing the

The “moral domain”—the class of claims


that the project is trying to characterize

Moral Claims

True Moral
Claims Nonmoral
Claims

False Moral Claims

Normative Claims Non-Normative Claims


All Claims

FIGURE 55.1. The class of claims that the project is trying to characterize.
 The Moral Domain 549

difference between moral claims and non- altruism, and altruism is neither necessary
moral normative claims. Specifying which nor sufficient for morality. The researchers
moral claims (if any) are true and explaining Joyce is criticizing could, of course, simply
how it is possible for a moral claim to be stipulate that they will use the term moral-
true are completely irrelevant to this project. ity to mean altruism. But to do so would be
It is easy to understand why people find to miss the point of Joyce’s criticism. What
the project of discovering moral truths to Joyce is claiming is that on the correct defi-
be interesting and important. But why is nition of morality, altruism is neither neces-
the project of defining or characterizing sary nor sufficient for morality. Joyce’s cri-
the moral domain interesting or important? tique makes no sense unless we assume that
That’s a much harder question. In the quote there is a correct definition.
from Alasdair MacIntyre that serves as my
epigraph, the focus is on moral utterances.
This focus reflects the “linguistic turn” in How Can We Test a Proposed Definition
philosophy in the middle of the last century of Morality?: The Philosophers’ Strategy
that was spearheaded by logical positivism
and ordinary language philosophy. In the Now that I have explained what I take the
wake of these two influential movements, project of defining morality to be, and why
many philosophers were convinced that the those who undertake the project think it is
only legitimate philosophical claims are an- important, I want to turn to a methodologi-
alytic, and thus that the only legitimate phil- cal issue. How can we determine whether
osophical activity is linguistic or conceptual a proposed definition is correct? There are
analysis. But many of the philosophers that two very different answers to this question,
MacIntyre had in mind were also convinced one typically assumed by philosophers, the
that by analyzing the concept of moral ut- other typically assumed by psychologists. I’ll
terance (or moral judgment), we would learn start with the philosophers’ answer.
something important about the phenom- The main tool used by the philosophers
enon of morality. Indeed, though they might that MacIntyre (1957) had in mind—those
not have endorsed this way of putting the who seek to specify “the distinctive charac-
point, many of these philosophers believed teristics of moral utterances”—is one that
that the concept of moral utterance or moral philosophers have used since antiquity. It
judgment specifies some (or perhaps all) of is often called the “method of cases.” To
the essential properties of morality and, use this method, a philosopher describes a
thus, that a definition that made this con- (usually imaginary) situation—in this case it
cept explicit would tell us what the essential would be a situation in which a protagonist
features of morality are. As we’ll see on page makes a normative claim. The philosopher
552, psychologists who offer a definition of then offers his own judgment about wheth-
morality are also trying to discover essential er the protagonist’s claim is a moral claim
properties of morality. and checks to see whether his philosophical
It is important to note that if our goal friends and colleagues make the same judg-
is to use a definition of moral utterance or ment. In the years after Chomsky’s work
moral judgment to learn something impor- became influential in philosophy, these
tant about morality, then we have to get the judgments have become known as “philo-
correct definition. A stipulative definition sophical intuitions.” Like the linguistic intu-
won’t do! This point is nicely illustrated itions that play a central role in Chomsky’s
by an argument offered in Richard Joyce’s work, they are typically made quite quickly,
(2006) widely discussed book, The Evolu- with little or no conscious reasoning. Hav-
tion of Morality. Joyce notes that one can’t ing assembled a number of cases that he and
address the evolution of morality seriously his friends agree are moral claims, and a
unless one has an account of what morality number of others that they judge are clearly
is. He then argues that much of the litera- not moral claims, the philosopher tries to
ture on the evolution of morality is simply construct a theory (a definition of morality)
irrelevant, because it is aimed at explaining that will provide necessary and sufficient
the evolution of biological or psychological conditions for a claim being a moral claim.
550 CL ARIF YING MOR ALIT Y

The theory is then tested against new hypo- Many people in Honduras believe that people
thetical cases and modified as necessary. should not kill others for no reason.
By 1957, when MacIntyre’s paper was Do you agree that people in your community
published, it was already clear that this should not kill others for no reason?
project was not going well. A definition of
morality of the sort that philosophers using 3 Strongly agree
††
the method of cases were seeking turned out 2
††
1
††
to be very difficult to construct. Whenever
0 Neither agree nor disagree
††
a philosopher offered a promising proposal,
–1
††
some other philosopher produced a counter-
–2
††
example. One problem that beset the philos- –3 Strongly disagree
††
ophers’ project is now widely acknowledged.
Philosophers were trying to find necessary Now consider the judgment you just made. Is
and sufficient conditions for the concept of that a moral judgement or some other kind of
a moral utterance. They were committed judgment?
to what has become known as the classical 3 Clearly IS a moral judgment
††
theory of concepts. And as empirical and 2
††
philosophical work on concepts progressed, 1
††
it became increasingly clear that the classical 0 Not a clear case
††
theory of concepts is false for most ordinary –1
††
concepts (Smith & Medin 1981; Laurence –2
††
& Margolis, 1999). Though there are ways –3 Clearly NOT a moral judgment
††
around this problem, another, less trac-
table, problem has begun to emerge from
Many people in Italy believe that adults should
recent work in experimental philosophy.
not eat pasta with their fingers.
Inspired by the work of cultural psycholo-
gists, experimental philosophers have been Do you agree that adults in your community
exploring the possibility that philosophi- should not eat pasta with their fingers?
cal intuitions—the data for the method of 3 Strongly agree
††
cases—may vary in different demographic 2
††
groups. If this is true—and there is a grow- 1
††
ing body of evidence that it is—then philo- 0 Neither agree nor disagree
††
sophically important concepts also vary in –1
††
different demographic groups. –2
††
Several years ago, Edouard Machery and –3 Strongly disagree
††
I joined forces with a group of psychologists Now consider the judgment you just made. Is
and philosophers in a project aimed at deter- that a moral judgment or some other kind of
mining if people’s intuitions about whether judgment?
a judgment is a moral judgment, rather than
some other kind of judgment, varied across 3 Clearly IS a moral judgment
††
different religious groups (Levine, Rottman, 2
††
Davis, Stich, & Machery, 2017). Each par- 1
††
ticipant in the study was asked a series of 0 Not a clear case
††
–1
††
50 paired questions. The first question in
–2
††
the pair described a normative belief in a
–3 Clearly NOT a moral judgment
††
specific community and asked whether the
participant believed that people in their own
community should adhere to the norm.3 The Though this work is ongoing, the prelimi-
second question asked participants whether nary results are very suggestive indeed. They
the judgment they had just made was a moral indicate that the pattern of responses to the
judgment or some other sort of judgment. second question in each pair is notably dif-
The following are examples of the questions ferent in Christians, Mormons, and non-
that participants were asked. religious participants. But the responses of
 The Moral Domain 551

religious Jewish participants are not signifi- forth. Without some reason to think that one
cantly different from the responses of nonre- of these cultural variants succeeds in picking
ligious participants. out what really are the essential properties
In a study using a quite different method- of morality while the others miss the mark,
ology, Emma Buchtel and colleagues (2015) it looks like this traditional philosophical
presented participants with a list of 26 prob- approach to characterizing the moral do-
lematic behaviors and asked whether the main should be abandoned. For if there is
behaviors were (1) “immoral,” (2) “wrong, a correct characterization of the moral do-
but immoral isn’t the best word,” or (3) “not main—a correct definition of morality—this
immoral at all.” They found dramatic dif- approach will not tell us what it is.4
ferences between the responses of Western
(Canadian and Australian) participants and
participants in Beijing. “In general,” they How Can We Test a Proposed Definition
report, “seemingly mild misbehaviors such of Morality?: The Psychologists’ Strategy
as spitting, cursing, and littering were much
more likely to be called immoral by Beijing The philosopher’s strategy assumes that the
than Western participants, while serious be- correct definition of “moral judgment” can
haviors such as killing, stealing, and hurting be found in the heads of ordinary speakers.
others were much more likely to be called More specifically, it assumes that the correct
immoral by Western participants” (Buchtel definition is implicit in the mentally stored
et al., 2015). information that guides people’s intuitions
Much more work is needed before we about the application of the term “moral
can confidently conclude that intuitions judgment.” But in a seminal paper published
about whether a judgment is a moral judg- 40 years ago, Hilary Putnam famously ar-
ment vary in different demographic groups. gued that, in many cases, “meanings just
But for present purposes, I will assume ain’t in the head” (Putnam, 1975, p. 227).
that these results are on the right track and When the term in question is a natural kind
that different demographic groups do in- term, Putnam urged, it is empirical science,
deed have different intuitions about which not people’s ordinary concept, that deter-
normative judgments are moral judgments. mines the essential features of the natural
Let’s explore the implications of this as- kind, and these essential features constitute
sumption for the project of providing a defi- the correct definition of the kind. Building
nition of morality. Suppose it is the case that on Putnam’s argument, Hilary Kornblith
secular liberal Americans, orthodox Jews in (1998) and Michael Devitt (1996) have de-
the United States, American Mormons, and veloped detailed accounts of how empirical
Beijing Chinese all have different intuitions science can discover the essential features of
about which judgments are moral judg- a natural kind.
ments and thus that they have somewhat The first step in the Kornblith–Devitt
different concepts of moral judgment. Sup- method exploits intuitive judgments of or-
pose further that the intuitions of some or dinary speakers to locate intuitively clear
all of these groups differ from the intuitions cases of the kind in question. Once a sub-
of early-21st-century English-speaking ana- stantial number of intuitively clear cases
lytic philosophers. The goal of the project have been found, the appropriate scientific
of defining morality is to distinguish moral methods are used to discover what nomo-
claims from nonmoral normative claims and logical cluster of properties these intuitively
to do it correctly, not stipulatively. But if our clear cases have in common. The properties
assumption is correct, it looks as though in that cluster are the essential features of
the best that the method of cases can give the kind in question. So an intuitively clear
us is a characterization of the secular liberal case that lacks some or all of the cluster of
concept of moral judgment, the orthodox properties exhibited by most other intui-
Jewish concept of moral judgment, the Mor- tively clear cases will not count as a mem-
mon concept of moral judgment, the Beijing ber of the kind, and a case that intuition
Chinese concept of moral judgment, and so does not recognize as a member of the kind
552 CL ARIF YING MOR ALIT Y

will be counted as a member of the kind if 1. The action described involves harm (or
it has the nomological cluster of properties injustice or a violation of rights)
that many other intuitively clear cases have. 2. The wrongness of the action is author-
Thus, while intuitions do play a role in the ity independent. It does not stop being
first stage of this method, they are the lad- wrong if an authority figure says it is OK.
der that can be kicked away after we have 3. The wrongness of the action is not geo-
climbed it. There is, of course, no guarantee graphically local; it is also judged to be
that the method will always work smoothly. wrong if it takes place in other places
Sometimes there will be no nomological around the world.
cluster of properties in the vicinity of the 4. The wrongness of the action is not tem-
intuitively clear cases, and sometimes there porally local; it is also judged to be wrong
will be several (or many) different nomolog- if it takes place at different times in his-
ical clusters in the vicinity of the intuitive tory.6
category. But when things work well, the
method enables us to offer an empirically In an impressive body of subsequent
supported account of the essential features work, Turiel and his associates found that
of a kind. It may also enable us to discover these four properties cluster in the judg-
that some cases that we thought were in- ments about cases made by a wide range of
tuitively clear members of the kind are not participants of different ages, religions, and
members of the kind at all, while some cases nationalities. The conclusion suggested by
that intuition decrees are not members of the Kornblith–Devitt account is that moral
the kind actually are.5 judgements are a psychological natural kind
The Kornblith–Devitt strategy is a quite and that these four properties are the essen-
general one that can be used to explore the tial features of that kind. If that’s right, then
essential properties of substances like water the conjunction of these four features consti-
and gold, or animal species (echidnas are tute an empirically supported definition of
Devitt’s favorite example), or philosophi- the moral domain.
cally interesting phenomena like knowledge During the last 25 years, a growing body
or reference. What makes it important for of research has been critical of Turiel’s ac-
our purposes is that, on one very plausible count of the moral domain. The core criti-
reading, the influential work of Elliott Turiel cism focuses on Turiel’s putative nomologi-
can be viewed as using the Kornblith–Devitt cal cluster, properties (1), (2), (3) and (4).
method to discover the correct definition of According to the critics, this is not a no-
morality (Turiel, 1978, 1983; Turiel, Killen, mological cluster at all, because in lots of
& Helwig, 1987). Turiel is treating the moral cases the cluster comes apart. Perhaps the
domain as a psychological natural kind and most famous examples are to be found in
using the methods of experimental psychol- the work of Jonathan Haidt and colleagues
ogy to discover its essential features. (Haidt, Koller, & Dias, 1993), who reported
On this interpretation, Turiel starts with that most of his participants of low socio-
two intuitive subsets of the class of norma- economic status (SES) judged actions that
tive judgments—those that many people are not harmful (like having sex with a dead
judge to be moral judgments and those that chicken) to be wrong, and also maintained
many people judge to be conventional judg- that the wrongness of these actions is au-
ments. He then uses the techniques of ex- thority independent and generalizes to other
perimental psychology to explore whether places and times). In earlier work, Nisan
there is a nomological cluster of properties (1987) asked children in Israeli Arab villages
that are shared by most of the judgments about a range of other transgressions that
that intuition classifies as moral and that are did not involve harm. They, too, judged that
not exhibited by most of the judgments that the wrongness of these actions was author-
intuition classifies as conventional. Turiel’s ity independent and that the actions would
early studies reported that moral claims be wrong in other places and times. More
typically exhibit four properties that are not recently, in a widely discussed study, Kelly,
exhibited by conventional claims. Stich, Haley, Eng, and Fessler (2007) looked
 The Moral Domain 553

at cases involving more serious harms than 1. How good or bad is what Nantu did?
the schoolyard cases that predominate in Please show me on this line.
the Turiel literature (Kelly et al., 2007). The
cases they considered included slavery and
the use of whipping as punishment. They
found that, for many participants, judg-
ments about these clearly harmful cases
were not authority independent and did not 2. Suppose that X [an appropriate local au-
generalize to other times and places. thority figure, e.g., the head of the village]
One major limitation of existing studies said that it is not bad to take things from
aimed at testing Turiel’s characterization strangers who do not live nearby and do
of the moral domain is that almost all of not speak Shuar. If X said that, how good
them—even those done in non-WEIRD cul- or bad would it be to do what Nantu did?
tures—use participants who are members of Please show me on this line.
large-scale societies. These individuals are 3. What if this happened a long, long time
likely to be similar to WEIRD people on a ago, before your grandparents were born,
number of dimensions, including school- even before their grandparents were born.
How good or bad would it be to do what
based education and familiarity with formal
Nantu did a very long time ago? Please
legal systems. However, if Turiel’s cluster show me on this line.
really does pick out a psychological natu- 4. What if this happened in a place very far
ral kind, it should be pan-cultural. Indeed, from here, a place that no one in this vil-
some researchers (though not Turiel himself) lage has ever visited, and I (the experiment-
have argued that it is innate (Dwyer, 1999). er) have never visited either. How good or
To address the question of whether the bad would it be to do what Nantu did if it
Turiel cluster can be found outside large- happened very far from here? Please show
scale societies, Fessler et al. (2015) con- me on this line.
ducted a study that compared seven quite
disparate societies, including five small- Fessler et al. found that participants in all
scale societies.7 Participants were present- seven societies viewed the described actions
ed with vignettes describing seven “grown as less bad when they occurred long ago and
up” transgressions: stealing, wife battery, when they occurred far away. Endorsement
violence following accidental harm, market- by an authority figure had this effect in four
place cheating, defamation, unjust perjury, of the seven societies; the remaining three
and rape. The version of the stealing vi- showed nonsignificant trends in the direc-
gnette used with the Shuar participants was tion of reduced severity. So we now have
a translation of the following: evidence that Turiel’s putative nomologi-
cal cluster shatters in a number of societies
Nantu is a man from another Shuar commu- (including small-scale societies) around the
nity. On a road near the village, Nantu en-
counters a stranger from Iceland, a country world.
that is very far away from here. The stranger The lesson that I think we should take
does not speak Shuar. After the stranger pass- away from the growing collection of studies
es Nantu, the stranger puts his sack down and in which (1)–(4) come unglued is that these
walks down a small hill to wash in a stream. four properties are not a nomological cluster
When the stranger is out of sight, Nantu opens at all. If that is correct, then they are not the
his sack and looks at the contents. He finds essential features of a natural kind, and they
$X [roughly a week’s wages locally], takes the cannot be used to construct an empirically
money and walks away quickly. The stranger
does not realize his money has been taken supported definition of the moral domain.
until he is back home in his country, and he Perhaps there is some other cluster of prop-
is then too far away to do anything about it. erties that overlaps substantially with the
(Fessler et al., 2015, p. 53). intuitive cases of moral judgments and that
really is a genuine nomological cluster. But
Participants were asked a series of ques- at this point, I don’t think there are any plau-
tions including: sible candidates. If that’s right, then the Ko-
554 CL ARIF YING MOR ALIT Y

rnblith–Devitt strategy will not lead us to an think, an illusion fostered by Christian the-
empirically supported definition of morality. ology and Western moral philosophy. Mak-
ing the case for this suspicion is a job for
another paper.
There Is No Moral Domain

Both the philosophers’ strategy for discover- NOTES


ing the correct definition of morality and the
1. “WEIRD” is the acronym introduced by Hen-
psychologists’ strategy appear to have failed. rich, Heine, and Norenzayan (2010) for cul-
Neither method has enabled us to give a tures that are Western, Educated, Industrial-
nonstipulative empirically supported defini- ized, Rich, and Democratic.
tion of the moral domain. Nor, to the best 2. Though I have been focusing on the distinc-
of my knowledge, is there any other method tion between moral and nonmoral claims,
that promises to yield the sort of definition some discussions of the moral domain focus
that both philosophers and psychologists instead on moral and nonmoral utterances,
have been seeking. So the quest for a defini- or judgments, or rules, or transgressions.
tion of the moral domain has reached an im- Though in many contexts the distinctions be-
tween claims, utterances, judgments, rules,
passe. The conclusion that I am inclined to
and transgressions are very important, I think
draw at this point that the quest is doomed we can safely ignore them here.
to failure. There is no correct definition of 3. Another version of this first question asked
morality. There is no moral domain. whether all people should adhere to the norm.
Sometimes when I set out the arguments The results from these two versions of the first
I have sketched in this chapter and propose question were very similar.
my admittedly radical conclusion, my inter- 4. Some philosophers might suggest that the cor-
locutors will challenge one or another move rect definition of morality is the one picked out
in the arguments. And certainly there is by the intuitions of professional moral philos-
plenty of room for further debate. However, ophers, because they are the experts about the
moral domain. But in light of the growing lit-
the most common response to my conclusion
erature exploring the alleged moral expertise
is not a counterargument but rather what of philosophers, it is hard to take this sugges-
David Lewis famously called “the incredu- tion seriously. See, for example, Schwitzgebel
lous stare,” a reaction that is often provoked and Cushman (2012); Tobia, Buckwalter, and
by claims that seem to conflict with deeply Stich (2013), and Tobia, Chapman, and Stich
entrenched common sense (Lewis, 1986, (2013); Schwitzgebel and Rust (2016).
p. 33). “How is that possible?” my interlocu- 5. It is worth noting that the Kornblith–Devitt
tors ask with astonishment. “How could it method can be used successfully even when
be that there is no moral domain?” different groups of speakers have different
My answer begins be making it clear that intuitions about specific cases. If there are a
substantial number of cases on which most or
I am not denying that there is a class of nor- all speakers agree, then the appropriate sci-
mative judgments (or utterances or claims). ence can attempt to discover the nomological
Quite the opposite. I think that normative cluster of properties that most of these cases
judgments are a psychological natural kind have in common.
with an interesting and important evolution- 6. In some of Turiel’s early papers, the serious-
ary history (Sripada & Stich, 2006). More- ness of the transgression was an additional
over, I suspect that there are number of sub- feature that characterized moral judgments,
classes of normative judgments that are also but in later work seriousness was dropped
natural kinds. Normative judgments about from the moral cluster.
7. The five small-scale societies were Tsimane’
purity, reciprocity, authority, and kinship
(Bolivia), Shuar (Ecuador), Yasawa (Fiji), Karo
may well be examples of distinct natural Batak (Indonesia), and Sursurunga (New Ire-
kinds. But the conviction that there must land—Papua New Guinea). The other sites
be a natural or well-motivated way of di- where data were collected were Storozhnitsa
viding normative judgments into those that (Ukraine) and Santa Monica and San Jose
are moral and those that are nonmoral is, I (California).
 The Moral Domain 555

REFERENCES Lewis, D. (1986). On the plurality of worlds.


Oxford, UK: Blackwell.
Buchtel, E., Guan, Y., Peng, Q., Su Y., Sang, B., MacIntyre, A. (1957). What morality is not. Phi-
Chen, S., & Bond, M. (2015). Immorality East losophy, 32, 325–335.
and West: Are prototypically immoral behav- Nisan, M. (1987). Moral norms and social con-
iors especially harmful, or especially uncul- ventions: A cross-cultural comparison. Devel-
tured? Personality and Social Psychology Bul- opmental Psychology, 23, 719–725.
letin, 41(10), 1382–1394. Putnam, H. (1975). The meaning of “meaning.”
Devitt, M. (1996). Coming to our senses. Cam- In K. Gunderson (Ed.), Minnesota studies in
bridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. the philosophy of science: Vol. 7. Language,
Dwyer, S. (1999). Moral competence. In K. Mu- mind and knowledge. Minneapolis: University
rasugi & R. Stainton (Eds.), Philosophy and of Minnesota Press.
linguistics (pp. 169–190). Boulder, CO: West- Schwitzgebel, E., & Cushman, F. (2012). Ex-
view Press. pertise in moral reasoning?: Order effects on
Fessler, D. M. T., Barrett, H. C., Kanovsky, moral judgment in professional philosophers
M., Stich, S., Holbrook, C., Henrich, J., . . . and non-philosophers. Mind and Language,
Laurence, S. (2015). Moral parochialism and 27(2), 135–153.
contextual contingency across seven disparate Schwitzgebel, E., & Rust, J. (2016). The moral
societies. Proceedings of the Royal Society B, behavior of ethicists. In J. Sytsma & W. Buck-
282, 1813. walter (Eds.), A companion to experimental
Gert, B. (2005). Morality: Its nature and justifi- philosophy. Oxford, UK: Blackwell.
cation (rev. ed.). New York: Oxford University Smith, E., & Medin, D. (1981). Categories and
Press. concepts. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Univer-
Gert, B. (2012). The definition of morality. In E. sity Press.
N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of Sripada, C., & Stich, S. (2006). A framework for
philosophy. Available at http://plato.stanford. the psychology of norms. In P. Carruthers, S.
edu/archives/fall2012/entries/morality-defini- Laurence, & S. Stich (Eds.), The innate mind:
tion. Culture and cognition (pp. 133–158). New
Haidt, J., Koller, S., & Dias, M. (1993). Affect, York: Oxford University Press.
culture and morality, or is it wrong to eat your Tobia, K., Buckwalter, W., & Stich, S. (2013).
dog? Journal of Personality and Social Psy- Moral intuitions: Are philosophers ex-
chology, 65, 613–628. perts?  Philosophical Psychology, 26(5), 629–
Henrich, J., Heine, S. & Norenzayan, A. (2010). 638.
The weirdest people in the world? Behavioral Tobia, K., Chapman, G., & Stich, S. (2013).
and Brain Sciences, 33, 61–83. Cleanliness is next to morality, even for phi-
Joyce, R. (2006). The evolution of morality. losophers. Journal of Consciousness Studies,
Cambridge, MA: Bradford/MIT Press. 20, 195–204.
Kelly, D., Stich, S. P., Haley, K., Eng, S., & Fes- Turiel, E. (1978). Distinct conceptual and de-
sler, D. (2007). Harm, affect and the moral/ velopmental domains: Social convention and
conventional distinction. Mind and Language, morality. In H. Howe & C. Keasey (Eds.), Ne-
22, 117–131. braska Symposium on Motivation, 1977: Vol.
Kornblith, H. (1998). The role of intuition in 25. Social cognitive development. Lincoln:
philosophical inquiry: An account with no University of Nebraska Press.
unnatural ingredients. In M. DePaul & W. Turiel, E. (1983). The development of social
Ramsey (Eds.), Rethinking intuition (pp. 129– knowledge. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge Uni-
142). Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield. versity Press.
Laurence, S., & Margolis, E. (1999). Concepts Turiel, E., Killen, M., & Helwig, C. (1987). Mo-
and cognitive science. In E. Margolis & S. rality: Its structure, functions, and vagaries.
Laurence (Eds.), Concepts: Core readings. In J. Kagan & S. Lamb (Eds.), The emergence
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. of morality in young children (pp. 155–243).
Levine, S., Rottman, J., Davis, T., Stich, S., & Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Machery, E. (2017). Religion and the scope of Wallace, G., & Walker, A. (1970). The definition
the moral domain. Manuscript in preparation. of morality. London: Methuen.
CHAPTER 56

There Is No Important Distinction


between Moral and Nonmoral Cognition

Joshua Knobe

Can human cognition be divided neatly into moral and nonmoral


elements?

No; rather, the moral and the nonmoral are jumbled together in such
a way that a single process or representation can often be sensitive
to an undifferentiated mixture of moral and nonmoral consider-
ations.

Research over the past 15 years or so has not On this interpretation, people’s cognition
tended to suggest that moral judgments are can be divided fairly neatly into moral and
the product of some distinctively moral form nonmoral parts. It’s just that people’s moral
of cognition. Instead, most of the important judgments are primarily the product of the
work has involved explaining moral judg- nonmoral parts.
ments in terms of the very same psychologi- It should be noted, however, that this in-
cal processes people use to make nonmoral terpretation does not follow immediately
judgments. For example, moral judgments from the empirical findings themselves. The
have been shown to be influenced by per- findings simply suggest that people’s moral
fectly general processes of emotion, causal judgments and nonmoral judgments are gen-
cognition, agency detection, and reinforce- erated by the very same processes. In itself,
ment learning (Crockett, 2013; Cushman, this claim is completely symmetric. As a
2013; Cushman & Young, 2011; Gray & number of researchers have already noted,
Wegner, 2009; Young & Saxe, 2008). it can be used to say something surprising
The question now is how to understand about people’s moral judgments. Specifical-
what this finding is telling us about the ly, it implies that people’s moral judgments
human mind. One natural interpretation are not the product of some special process
would be that it is teaching us something that applies only to moral judgments; they
like this: are generated by the very same processes
that generate the nonmoral judgments (see,
People’s moral judgments are generated primarily by e.g., Cushman & Young, 2011). But, in just
purely nonmoral representations and processes. the same way, it can also be used to say

556
 Moral and Nonmoral Cognition 557

something surprising about people’s non- trying to identify the cause of the fire, they
moral judgments. In particular, it shows that tend not to treat these two factors equally.
people’s nonmoral judgments are not the There is a tendency to specifically pick out
product of some special process that applies the act of lighting a match and say that it
only to nonmoral judgments; they are gener- was the cause of the fire, while treating the
ated by the very same processes that people oxygen as merely a “background condi-
use to make moral judgments. tion,” rather than a full-blown cause (Hart
Drawing on this symmetric character of & Honoré, 1985). A question now arises as
existing findings, I will be arguing for a new to how people make these judgments. Given
and very different interpretation of what the that any given outcome will depend on a
results are teaching us. This interpretation huge variety of different factors, how do
is: people decide which of these factors to count
as full-blown causes of the outcome itself?
There is no important distinction between moral and One obvious consideration here is a statis-
nonmoral cognition. tical one, namely, people’s tendency to pick
out factors that are especially infrequent. In
On this interpretation, what the results show the case described above, one notes imme-
is that it is not helpful to categorize people’s diately that there is an important difference
cognitive processes and representations as between lit matches and oxygen: Lit match-
either moral or nonmoral. The human mind es are highly infrequent, whereas oxygen is
is simply not divided up neatly in that way. present almost all of the time. Existing re-
Rather, any given process or representation search suggests that this is one of the main
can involve an undifferentiated jumble of considerations we use in determining which
moral and nonmoral considerations. factors to regard as causes. Of all the fac-
Before moving onward, just a quick word tors on which an outcome depends, we tend
to avoid creating unduly inflated expecta- to pick out specifically those factors that are
tions. I will not be arguing that existing data statistically infrequent (see, e.g., Hilton &
provide overwhelming and decisive support Slugoski, 1986).
for this interpretation. Instead, the claim But this appears not to be the only rele-
will be a weaker one. If one starts out with vant consideration. People also seem to be
the idea that there is a clear divide between influenced by a kind of consideration that is
moral and nonmoral cognition, one would moral or evaluative, namely, the degree to
not naturally predict the kinds of effects we which a given factor is in some way wrong.
actually observe in existing studies, and one For example, consider the following vig­
would have to add in a whole web of com- nette:
plex, bidirectional relationships between
moral and nonmoral processes to explain The receptionist in the philosophy depart-
these effects. By contrast, if one starts out ment keeps her desk stocked with pens. The
with the idea that there is no important dis- administrative assistants are allowed to take
tinction here, one can construct models on the pens, but faculty members are supposed to
which the effects we actually observe are buy their own.
precisely what one would most naturally The administrative assistants typically do
predict. Thus, existing results give us at least take the pens. Unfortunately, so do the fac-
some reason to prefer this latter interpreta- ulty members. The receptionist has repeatedly
emailed them reminders that only administra-
tion over the former.
tive assistants are allowed to take the pens.
On Monday morning, one of the adminis-
trative assistants encounters Professor Smith
First Example: Norms walking past the receptionist’s desk. Both take
pens. Later that day, the receptionist needs to
Consider an ordinary case of a person start- take an important message . . . but she has a
ing a fire. The fire would not have started problem. There are no pens left on her desk.
if the person had not lit a match, but it also
would not have started if there had been no In this case, the actions of the professor and
oxygen in the room. Yet, when people are of the administrative assistant are similar
558 CL ARIF YING MOR ALIT Y

from a purely statistical point of view, but ought to occur). One possible view would
they differ from a more evaluative stand- be that people have two completely separate
point. The professor is doing something representations for these two distinct kinds
wrong, whereas the administrative assistant of norms: a purely nonmoral representa-
is simply doing exactly what he or she is sup- tion for the statistical norms and a partially
posed to do. This evaluative judgment also moral representation for the prescriptive
appears to impact people’s causal intuitions. norms. But suppose we abandon this view.
People consistently say that the professor, We can then posit a single unified represen-
rather than the administrative assistant, was tation that captures both kinds of norms.
the cause of the problem (Knobe & Fraser, This representation would not be dedicated
2008). just to statistical norms, or just to prescrip-
How are we to explain this pattern of re- tive norms; it would be a unified representa-
sponses? One option would be to suppose tion of the overall degree to which an event
that these two effects are the products of violates norms.
two completely separate processes (see Fig- One piece of evidence for this hypothesis
ure 56.1). On this picture, people have a comes from people’s use of the English word
purely nonmoral judgment of statistical fre- normal. Studies show that people’s use of
quency that influences their causal intuitions this word actually reflects a complex mix
and then, separately, they have a moral judg- of statistical and prescriptive considerations
ment of wrongness that also influences their (Wysocki, n.d.; see also Bear & Knobe,
causal intuitions. 2017). People tend to say that a given event
However, researchers have increasingly is not normal to the extent that they think
turned to a quite different picture. The sug- it is statistically infrequent, but also to the
gestion has been that we do not need to extent that they think it is prescriptively
posit separate representations for statistical wrong. Thus, people’s use of this term seems
infrequency and wrongness. Instead, we can to be tapping into precisely the sort of hybrid
posit a single representation that keeps track notion posited by this hypothesis.
of both of these properties. Specifically, the With all this in the background, we can
claim is that people’s causal intuitions are now offer a new and far simpler explana-
affected by the degree to which they regard tion of the results obtained in the causation
certain events as norm violations (Halpern studies. It is not that people have a statistical
& Hitchcock, 2015; Hitchcock & Knobe, representation and a separate moral repre-
2009; Kominsky, Phillips, Gerstenberg, sentation and then these two representations
Lagnado, & Knobe, 2015). both end up affecting their causal intuitions.
Intuitively, it seems that people need to Rather, they have a single hybrid represen-
represent two different kinds of norms. tation of norm violation. This one repre-
First, there are statistical norms (which sentation then ends up influencing causal
things generally tend to occur). Second, judgments (see Figure 56.2), and the result is
there are prescriptive norms (which things that people’s causal judgments are sensitive
to both statistical and prescriptive consider-
ations.
Statistical We can now emphasize the more general
Frequency idea of which this first example was just one
(nonmoral) illustration. In the domain of causal judg-
Causation

Wrongness Normality
Causation
(moral) (hybrid)

FIGURE 56.1. Hypothesis positing separate ef- FIGURE 56.2.  Hypothesis positing a single hy-
fects of moral and non-moral representations on brid representation of normality that impacts
causal judgment. causal judgment.
 Moral and Nonmoral Cognition 559

ment, existing results indicate that nonmor- Second, it seems that some entities have a
al and moral considerations have the same kind of moral status such that we think it is
sort of impact. One way to explain this phe- morally good to help them and morally bad
nomenon would be to start by positing a dis- to harm them. We can refer to this status
tinction between nonmoral and moral repre- as moral patiency. People are more inclined
sentations. Then we could say that there are to ascribe this latter moral status to an en-
two completely separate representations—a tity when they see it as having a capacity for
nonmoral representation and a moral rep- psychological experience. In other words, if
resentation—which just happen to end up people see an entity as being capable of plea-
having the same sort of impact. I have sug- sure and pain, they will be more inclined to
gested, however, that there might be reason say that it would be good to help this entity
to prefer a simpler model. We can abandon and wrong to harm it.
the assumption that there is a distinction be- So far, all of this should be fairly intuitive,
tween nonmoral and moral representations. but subsequent studies have shown some-
Then we can posit just a single representa- thing further and quite surprising. It turns
tion, involving a hybrid of nonmoral and out that the connection between psychologi-
moral considerations, and we can explain cal status and moral status can also go in the
the entire phenomenon in terms of this one opposite direction, with people’s tendency to
representation. see an entity as having a particular kind of
moral status actually affecting their attribu-
tions to that entity of certain psychological
Second Example: Mind Perception capacities. In particular, these studies have
revealed two striking patterns:
People attribute to each other a whole vari-
ety of different kinds of psychological states, 1. Attributions to an entity of moral agency
but recent research suggests that these states can lead to attributions to that entity of
can be divided into two basic types. On the psychological agency (Clark et al., 2014;
one hand, there are capacities for reasoning, Hamlin & Baron, 2014; Ullman, Leite,
planning, thinking, and self-control. These Phillips, Kim-Cohen, & Scassellati,
capacities are known collectively as psycho- 2014).
logical agency. On the other hand, there are 2. Attributions to an entity of moral pa-
capacities for pain, joy, fear, and pleasure. tiency can lead to attributions to that en-
These capacities are known as psychological tity of psychological experience (Bastian,
experience. This claim receives its clearest Loughnan, Haslam, & Radke, 2012;
and most powerful articulation in an im- Ward, Olsen, & Wegner, 2013).
portant paper by Gray, Gray, and Wegner
(2007), but numerous other researchers have These latter effects are far less obvious and
arrived at similar conclusions (e.g., Haslam, intuitive than the ones discussed above. The
2006; Knobe & Prinz, 2008). basic idea is that making a certain moral
Perhaps unsurprisingly, people’s attribu- judgment (e.g., that an entity is blamewor-
tions of a capacity for these different kinds thy) can actually lead you to make a corre-
of states has been shown to affect their moral sponding psychological judgment (e.g., that
judgments (Gray et al., 2007). First, it seems the entity is capable of reasoning and plan-
that some entities have a special kind of ning).
moral status such that we praise them for the How are we to understand these phenom-
good they do and blame them for the bad. ena? One obvious approach would be in
Let us refer to that status as moral agency. terms of a structure like the one depicted in
People are more inclined to ascribe this sort Figure 56.3. On this view, we have distinct
of moral status to an entity when they see representations for psychological properties
that entity as capable of psychological agen- and moral properties, and there is then a
cy. In other words, if people see an entity complex web of causal relationships between
as being capable of reasoning and planning, the two. In particular, this account posits
they will be more inclined to think that this four separate causal relationships, depicted
entity is deserving of praise and blame. by the four separate arrows in the figure.
560 CL ARIF YING MOR ALIT Y

Psychological soning, planning, self-control, etc.). Why


Moral Agency
Agency couldn’t this very same representation also
(moral)
(nonmoral) be at the root of people’s attributions of
moral properties (praise, blame, etc.)? The
Psychological
answer does not seem to lie in any specific
Moral Patiency empirical results. Rather, it just seemed in-
Experience
(moral) tuitive somehow that the representations un-
(nonmoral)
derlying our psychological judgments should
be coming from the representations underly-
FIGURE 56.3.  Hypothesis positing bidirectional ing our moral judgments.
causal influence of psychological and moral at- Let us now sketch an account that aban-
tributions. dons these assumptions (Figure 56.4). We
will posit a single, unified representation of
agency. This representation would involve
To make sense of this account, one would certain psychological capacities (reasoning,
have to provide an explanation for all four planning) and also a certain moral status
of these relationships. Moreover, one would (deserving blame and praise). Then, similar-
have to provide an account for the striking ly, we will posit a single, unified representa-
symmetry we observe between them. That tion of patiency. This representation again
is, one would have to explain why it is that involves both psychological capacities (pain,
whenever attributions of a psychological joy) and moral status (moral patiency).
capacity affect attributions of a particular On this view, when people encounter a
moral status, we also find a corresponding new entity, it is not as though they have to
impact in the opposite direction. separately ask themselves, “Does this entity
But before we seek an explanation along have the capacity for psychological agency?”
these lines, perhaps we should pause for a and also “Is this is entity the sort of thing
moment to question one of our assump- that can be deserving of praise and blame?”
tions. We started out with the assumption Rather, they only have to ask themselves a
that there is a distinction between the rep- single question: “Is this entity an agent?”
resentation of psychological agency and the Judgments about both psychological and
representation of moral agency. Similarly, moral properties will affect their answers to
we assumed that there was a distinction this question, and their answers will in turn
between the representation of psychologi- affect both their psychological and moral
cal experience and the representation of judgments.
moral patiency. Then we immediately faced This one type of representation can ex-
a question as to why these different repre- plain the effects we find going in both causal
sentations had such a strong impact on each directions. If people conclude that an entity
other. has certain psychological capacities, they
A question now arises as to whether there will be more likely to see it as an agent and
is any actual justification for this assump- hence to regard it as deserving of praise and
tion. We have been assuming that there is a blame. The same basic logic then applies in
single underlying representation at the root the opposite direction. If people conclude
of people’s attributions of a whole variety that an entity is deserving of praise or blame,
of different psychological capacities (rea- they will be more likely to see it as an agent

Agency Patiency
(hybrid) (hybrid)

Reasoning Planning Blame Praise Pain Joy Moral Significance

FIGURE 56.4.  Hypothesis positing hybrid representations of agency and patiency.


 Moral and Nonmoral Cognition 561

and hence to regard it as having certain psy- iar from scientific research begins to seem
chological capacities. completely natural. This capacity does not
Note that although this second example seem to require any special explanation; it
involved a quite different domain from the just appears to be a basic part of people’s or-
first, the overall structure of the argument dinary cognition. Then, when one finds that
is exactly the same. Existing results show people’s moral judgments can affect their
a certain pattern of interrelations among intuitions about what appear to be strictly
nonmoral and moral judgments. One way scientific questions, one assumes that this
to explain those results would be to posit a phenomenon must be due to some special
distinction between nonmoral representa- additional process that is getting in the way
tions and moral representations and then to of people’s more basic cognitive capacities.
posit a complex web of causal connections My suggestion is that we try to turn this
between the two. I have been suggesting that whole question around and look at it from
we have reason to prefer a simpler model. the opposite perspective. Suppose we start
One can abandon the distinction between out with the idea that people have some way
the nonmoral and moral representations and of representing these things that involves an
then posit a single hybrid sort of representa- undifferentiated jumble of nonmoral and
tion that explains all of these effects. moral elements. Then the puzzling thing, the
thing that calls out for explanation, would
be that we are sometimes able to engage in a
Ordinary Cognition, Scientific Cognition more purely scientific mode of cognition in
which we focus purely on the nonmoral con-
Thus far, we have considered two examples. siderations and leave the moral ones aside.
In each case, we found that existing results Perhaps the best way to get a sense for the
can be explained on a simple and elegant proposal here would be to go through one
model in which there is no clear distinc- example in a bit more detail. Consider again
tion between moral and nonmoral cogni- people’s capacity for thinking about norms
tion. However, in both cases, we also found and normality. Now contrast two different
that it would also be possible to explain kinds of questions you might ask yourself:
these results on a more complex model in
which moral and nonmoral cognition are 1. First try asking yourself a perfectly or-
fundamentally distinct. The question now dinary question: What would be a nor-
is whether we have any reason to prefer the mal amount of television for a person to
more complex model. watch in a day?
One salient fact here is that many existing 2. Now try to put away out of your mind
theories, both about causal judgment and any prescriptive considerations and an-
about mind perception, have been explicitly swer a purely statistical question: What
designed on analogy with the kind of think- is the average amount of television that
ing used in science (e.g., Gopnik, 1996). people watch per day?
When people are doing systematic scientific
research, it does seem that they make use Participants tend to give quite high answers
of purely nonmoral representations that are in response to this second question, but
importantly distinct from their moral repre- somewhat lower answers in the response to
sentations. Thus, if people’s ordinary way the first (Bear & Knobe, 2017; extending
of making sense of the world is similar to work by Wysocki, n.d.).
scientific research, we would have reason to What we seem to be finding here is that
suppose that people’s ordinary way of mak- these two kinds of judgments rely on differ-
ing sense of the world involves a rigorous ent kinds of considerations. As noted above,
distinction between the nonmoral and the people’s judgments of the normal seem to
moral. involve a messy combination of statistical
If one starts out from this perspective, and prescriptive considerations. However, it
it is easy to find oneself adopting a certain seems that people are also capable, at least
picture. People’s capacity to develop purely to some degree, of arriving at judgments of
nonmoral representations of the sort famil- the average that are more purely statistical.
562 CL ARIF YING MOR ALIT Y

Putting these two results together, we arrive study explored the ways in which trained
at the striking finding that people think that scientists make judgments about whether a
the average amount of television is not a nor- trait is “innate” (Knobe & Samuels, 2013).
mal amount but rather an abnormally high When scientists were assigned in a between-
one. subjects design to receive either a vignette in-
The question now is how to understand volving something morally good or a vignette
the relationship between these two kinds involving something morally bad, their judg-
of judgment. One hypothesis would be that ments were affected by the moral status of
the second, purely statistical judgment is re- the events in the vignette. However, when
vealing some basic fact about how human scientists received both vignettes together in
beings make sense of the world. It might be a within-subjects design, they tended to say
that this purely statistical judgment comes that the two did not differ with regard to
naturally to people and informs numerous their innateness (Knobe & Samuels, 2013).
aspects of their cognition. Then, if we want These results indicate that even trained sci-
to explain why people give lower numbers entists can only avoid the impact of moral
when they are asked about the “normal,” we considerations to the extent that they are
could posit some special additional process able to engage in some additional process
that somehow intervenes and allows their that suppresses their initial intuitions.
judgments about what is normal to be af- To sum up, it does appear that scientific
fected by prescriptive considerations. cognition involves, at least to some degree,
This hypothesis might turn out to be cor- a distinction between moral and nonmoral
rect, but I have been trying to suggest that representations. However, it also seems
we have reason to consider an alternative that it might be a mistake to see this kind
view. On this alternative view, it is the first of cognition as reflecting our ordinary way
judgment, with its complex mixture of the of making sense of the world. Rather, part
statistical and the prescriptive, that reflects of what makes the study of scientific cogni-
our most basic way of making sense of the tion so fascinating is precisely the fact that it
world. This first sort of judgment comes involves such a radical departure from our
naturally to people and informs numerous more ordinary mode of understanding.
other aspects of their cognition. Then, when
we want to explain how people can make
more purely scientific judgments about the Conclusion
“average,” we will have to do so by positing
a special additional process that intervenes The distinction between the moral and the
in certain cases and make it possible for nonmoral has proven enormously impor-
people to arrive at judgments using purely tant in numerous activities, and it is natural
statistical considerations. enough to suppose that it might also prove
One reason to prefer this alternative view important in understanding human cogni-
is that it accords so well with existing work tion. In particular, one obvious view would
on scientific cognition. Such work indicates be that cognitive processes can be divided
that a purely scientific way of making sense fairly neatly into the moral and the nonmor-
of the world never really comes naturally to al, with moral judgments being generated by
people (e.g., McCauley, 2000). Rather, even some distinctively moral form of cognition
after extensive scientific education, people and nonmoral judgments being generated by
still find it more intuitive to apply non-scien- a distinctively nonmoral form of cognition.
tific concepts and have to suppress that ini- We now have a substantial amount of evi-
tial intuition using cognitive control (Gold- dence against this view. First, as numerous
berg & Thompson-Schill, 2009; Shtulman authors have already noted, people’s moral
& Valcarcel, 2012). judgments appear to be generated by the
At this point, there has been relatively lit- very same sort of cognition that one finds
tle work about the ways in which scientific at work in generating nonmoral judgments.
cognition avoids the use of moral consider- Second, as we have been emphasizing here,
ations, but what research there is suggests there is also a striking effect in the opposite
a similar process. For example, one recent direction. Judgments about what might ap-
 Moral and Nonmoral Cognition 563

pear to be entirely nonmoral matters (causa- sumption. Personality and Social Psychology
tion, psychological capacities) can actually Bulletin, 38, 247–256.
be influenced by moral judgments. Bear, A., & Knobe, J. (2017). Normality: Part
Of course, one possible hypothesis would descriptive, part prescriptive. Cognition, 167,
25–37.
be that human cognition is indeed best un- Clark, C. J., Luguri, J. B., Ditto, P. H., Knobe,
derstood using a distinction between the J., Shariff, A. F., & Baumeister, R. F. (2014).
nonmoral and the moral but that the con- Free to punish: A motivated account of free
nections between these two types of cogni- will belief. Journal of Personality and Social
tion are far more complex than we had origi- Psychology, 106, 501–513.
nally anticipated. For example, it might be Crockett, M. J. (2013). Models of morali-
that people’s cognition involves a relatively ty. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 17, 363–366.
clear distinction between moral cognition Cushman, F. (2013). Action, outcome, and value
and nonmoral cognition but that moral a dual-system framework for morality. Per-
sonality and Social Psychology Review, 17,
judgments are due in large part to nonmoral
273–292.
cognition and nonmoral judgments are due Cushman, F., & Young, L. (2011). Patterns of
in part to moral cognition. Perhaps this hy- moral judgment derive from nonmoral psy-
pothesis will ultimately turn out to be cor- chological representations. Cognitive Science,
rect. 35, 1052–1075.
Still, at this point, it seems that there is Goldberg, R. F., & Thompson-Schill, S. L.
something to be said for beginning to ex- (2009). Developmental “roots” in mature bio-
plore a very different alternative. Suppose logical knowledge. Psychological Science, 20,
that we simply ignore the whole moral–non- 480–487.
moral distinction. We will still presumably Gopnik, A. (1996). The scientist as child. Phi-
losophy of Science, 63, 485–514.
want to develop theoretical frameworks that
Gray, H. M., Gray, K., & Wegner, D. M. (2007).
distinguish different kinds of processes and Dimensions of mind perception. Science, 315,
representations, but we can do so in a way 619.
that is driven more directly by the actual em- Gray, K., & Wegner, D. M. (2009). Moral type-
pirical data. casting: divergent perceptions of moral agents
Judging from the two examples discussed and moral patients. Journal of Personality and
here, this latter approach may lead to a very Social Psychology, 96, 505–520.
different relationship between our theoreti- Halpern, J. Y., & Hitchcock, C. (2015). Graded
cal frameworks and the empirical results. causation and defaults. British Journal for the
To the extent that we insist on a distinction Philosophy of Science, 66, 413–457.
Hamlin, J. K., & Baron, A. S. (2014). Agency at-
between moral and nonmoral cognition, we tribution in infancy: Evidence for a negativity
typically end up creating theoretical frame- bias. PLOS ONE, 9, e96112.
works that, taken in themselves, do not Hart, H. L. A., & Honoré, T. (1985). Causation
seem to predict many of the effects we ac- in the law. Oxford, UK: Oxford University
tually observe. Then, to make these frame- Press.
works compatible with the data, we have to Haslam, N. (2006). Dehumanization: An inte-
add in a whole bunch of causal connections grative review. Personality and Social Psychol-
between distinct representations that don’t ogy Review, 10, 252–264.
seem to follow in any natural way from the Hilton, D. J., & Slugoski, B. R. (1986). Knowl-
edge-based causal attribution: The abnormal
frameworks themselves. By contrast, if we
conditions focus model. Psychological Re-
get rid of this distinction, we can construct view, 93, 75–88.
frameworks that seem immediately to pre- Hitchcock, C., & Knobe, J. (2009). Cause and
dict the observed effects and which would norm. Journal of Philosophy, 106, 587–612.
have difficulty explaining how these effects Knobe, J., & Fraser, B. (2008). Causal judgment
could possibly fail to arise. and moral judgment: Two experiments. In W.
Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral psychology
(pp.441–448). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
REFERENCES Knobe, J., & Prinz, J. (2008). Intuitions about
consciousness: Experimental studies. Phe­
Bastian, B., Loughnan, S., Haslam, N., & nomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 7,
Radke, H. R. (2012). Don’t mind meat?: The 67–83.
denial of mind to animals used for human con- Knobe, J., & Samuels, R. (2013). Thinking like
564 CL ARIF YING MOR ALIT Y

a scientist: Innateness as a case study. Cogni- social agency. In P. Bello, M. Guarini, M. Mc-
tion, 126,– 72–86. Shane, & B. Scassellati (Chairs), Proceedings
Kominsky, J. F., Phillips, J., Gerstenberg, T., of the 36th annual conference of the Cognitive
Lagnado, D., & Knobe, J. (2015). Causal su- Science Society (pp. 2996–3001). Red Hook,
perseding. Cognition, 137, 196–209. NY: Curran Associates.
McCauley, R. (2000). The naturalness of religion Ward, A. F., Olsen, A. S., & Wegner, D. M.
and the unnaturalness of science. In F. Keil & (2013). The harm-made mind observing vic-
R. Wilson (Eds.), Explanation and cognition timization augments attribution of minds to
(pp. 61–86). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. vegetative patients, robots, and the dead. Psy-
Shtulman, A., & Valcarcel, J. (2012). Scien- chological Science, 24, 1437–1445.
tific knowledge suppresses but does not sup- Wysocki, T. (n.d.). Normality: A two-faced con-
plant earlier intuitions. Cognition, 124, 209– cept. Unpublished manuscript, University of
215. Washington in St. Louis, St. Louis, MO.
Ullman, D., Leite, I., Phillips, J., Kim-Cohen, J., Young, L., & Saxe, R. (2008). The neural basis
& Scassellati, B. (2014). Smart human, smart- of belief encoding and integration in moral
er robot: How cheating affects perceptions of judgment. NeuroImage, 40, 1912–1920.
CHAPTER 57

Asking the Right Questions


in Moral Psychology

Walter Sinnott‑Armstrong

Are moral judgments as a whole innate, culturally variable,


intuitive, or based on multiple or special processes?

This question is too general to answer, because we need to distin‑


guish verdicts from deliberation, explicit answers from implicit atti‑
tudes, and areas of morality that have nothing in common that could
support any general theory of all moral judgments.

Moral psychologists and philosophers often to be precise or accurate. Bad input yields
ask questions about morality as a whole: Is bad output. If someone asks how heavy jade
morality innate or learned? Is morality cul- is, we could not answer well without distin-
turally variable or uniform? Is morality in- guishing kinds of jade (jadeite or nephrite?),
tuitive or deliberative? Is morality based on meanings of “heavy” (mass or weight?), and
a single process or many? Is that process or size of pieces (an earring or a statue?).
processes special to morality or generic? This point is especially important to sci-
These questions grab readers partly be- ence. Ronald DeSousa (in personal conver-
cause they are simple. It feels nice to be able sation) once proposed that the progress of
to give a one-word answer: “yes” or “no.” In science can be measured in how many ques-
contrast, audiences grow impatient when a tions one can ask without being able to an-
scholar says that there are 17 aspects of mo- swer them. New discoveries and new theories
rality, each of which is innate (or variable or do lead to new knowledge, but they also en-
intuitive) in only some of the 42 meanings of able us to ask more questions that we could
innate. Replies such as “It depends on what not even formulate before. When psycholo-
‘morality’ is” make scholars seem too much gists distinguished remembering how to ride
like Bill Clinton saying, “It depends on what a bike (procedural memory) from remem-
the meaning of the word ‘is’ is.” Nobody bering that Raleigh is the capital of North
likes evasion. We want a straightforward Carolina (semantic memory) from remem-
answer to the question that is posed. bering visiting Raleigh last week (episodic
The problem, of course, is that a vague memory), we become able to ask which of
question makes it impossible for any answer these kinds of memory have propositions as

565
566 CL ARIF YING MOR ALIT Y

contents, which kinds of memory are affect- in its box while listening to evidence during
ed in which ways by which emotions, which the trial. Then it goes into another room to
brain areas are involved in which kinds of deliberate. At the end of deliberation, it votes
memory, and so on. The ability to ask such on a verdict. Then it comes back into the
detailed questions is real progress, because courtroom to deliver its verdict. Legal judg-
we could not answer similar questions about ment thus involves many parts. Analogously,
memory in general: Do memories have prop- moral judgment might include (1) gathering
ositions as contents? Some do, but others do relevant information, (2) deliberating about
not. Are memories reduced by disgust? Some that evidence, (3) endorsing a conclusion,
are, but others are not. Where are memories and (4) expressing that conclusion. When
lodged in the brain? Different places. In someone asks about moral judgment, do they
order to be able to answer questions about mean (1), (2), (3), (4), or all of the above?
memory, we need to ask the right questions The most common way to study moral
at the right level of generality. judgment is to contrast answers to questions
Similarly, we cannot make progress in about different kinds of moral dilemmas.
moral psychology until we ask the right Greene and colleagues (2001, 2004), for
questions. This simple point has been the example, contrast brain activations when
focus of much of my own work on moral participants report moral judgments about
judgments in both philosophy and psychol- difficult versus easy personal versus imper-
ogy. sonal moral dilemmas (except Analysis 2 in
In philosophy, consider moral dilemmas Greene et al. 2004, which contrasts different
(Sinnott-Armstrong, 1988, 2008). Should judgments about a single kind of dilemma).
Sophie give her son to the Nazis to be killed This method is groundbreaking and illumi-
when the concentration camp guard tells her nating, but it conflates (1)–(4), because the
that he will kill them all if she does not hand differences in brain activation could occur
over one of her two children? The answer during any part of the overall process.
depends on what “should” means. Sophie In order to dig a little deeper, Jana Schai-
has reason to hand over (1) one child instead ch Borg, Kent Kiehl, Vince Calhoun, and I
of none, even if she has no reason to hand had to deploy a novel design and analysis
over (2) her son instead of her daughter. (Schaich Borg, Sinnott-Armstrong, Cal-
We cannot say what she should do until we houn, & Kiehl, 2011). The first change was
know whether the question is about contrast to contrast judgments instead of kinds of
(1) or contrast (2). Even if we focus on (2), dilemmas. To do so, we included acts that
we still need to know whether she should do were clearly wrong, clearly not wrong, and
an act when nothing else is better (as when controversial. The second issue was statisti-
it is equal to the top) or only when this act cal. Moral dilemmas need to be described in
is better than every other option. Semantic detail in order to include all relevant infor-
distinctions such as these are the stock-in- mation, but lengthy stimuli limit the number
trade of traditional philosophy, so it should of trials per participant. To increase statisti-
come as no surprise that they aid progress in cal power, we developed a form of stimulus
that field. that could be judged within a few seconds.
This point is less widely acknowledged in Finally, we analyzed the earliest and latest
moral psychology, but it is no less impor- periods for each stimulus separately in order
tant. I give three examples in order to show to distinguish earlier deliberation from later
how important and useful it is. verdict.
The results showed that brain areas that
previous studies had associated with moral
Verdict versus Deliberation judgment—the ventromedial prefrontal cor-
tex, posterior cingulate, and temporopari-
Which parts of the brain are involved in etal junction—were related to deliberation
moral judgment? A large literature addresses but not verdict. In contrast, verdict but not
this question, but the answer obviously de- deliberation was associated with a distinct
pends on what counts as moral judgment. set of brain areas—bilateral anterior insula,
Compare juries in a legal trial. The jury sits basal ganglia, and amygdala.
 Asking the Right Questions 567

Because moral deliberation and verdict (or affecting as much) the inputs or process-
activate different brain areas, it makes no es of deliberation. Again, we do not know.
sense for moral psychologists to ask which Still, we clearly should not assume that ver-
brain areas are related to moral judgment if dict must be innate and uniform if delibera-
judgment includes both deliberation and ver- tion is—or vice versa. Yet that assumption
dict. Too much information is lost by con- is built into research that claims to address
flating deliberation and verdict under the moral judgment in general without distin-
umbrella term judgment. guishing deliberation from verdict.
These results also affect the question of
whether moral judgment is intuitive or de-
liberative. Deliberation is deliberative (of Explicit Beliefs versus Implicit Attitudes
course!), but verdict still might be intuitive.
Accordingly, any study of whether moral Now let’s focus on verdicts as a kind of judg-
judgment is intuitive needs to be careful to ment. We still need another distinction. Sup-
focus on verdicts instead of deliberation. pose someone thinks about his neighbors
Another lesson is for the question of having gay sex. Does he judge (or reach the
whether morality is based on a single pro- verdict) that their act is immoral? The an-
cess or many processes. Compare law. Is the swer varies between individuals, of course,
jury process a single process when it includes but it also depends on precisely what we
the jury listening during the trial, deliberat- mean by verdict. The question might be
ing elsewhere, and then reporting its verdict? about explicit beliefs or it might be about
Whether this set of events is one process or implicit attitudes.
three depends on how we count processes, The difference is well known from studies
which seems arbitrary. The same applies to of attitudes toward race and gender. Implicit
morality. We could count deliberation and association tests (IATs) reveal that many
verdict as two processes or as two parts of a people who sincerely claim that they have
single process (called judgment). There is no nothing against people with African ances-
clear basis for favoring either way of count- try still associate black faces with being bad
ing, so each answer seems arbitrary. (Greenwald, McGhee, & Schwartz, 1998).
This distinction between deliberation and Their implicit racial attitudes conflict with
verdict might also affect whether the pro- their explicit racial beliefs.
cesses underlying moral judgment are special Similar conflicts arise in morality, when
to morality or generic. Perhaps deliberation explicit moral beliefs come apart from im-
is generic in combining inputs, but verdicts plicit moral attitudes. Someone who sin-
in morality are special, because they are dis- cerely claims to believe that there is nothing
tinct from other kinds of verdicts. After all, morally wrong with gay sex still might have
we can judge that one candidate for a job implicit moral attitudes that oppose or con-
is morally superior but another candidate is demn gay sex. These implicit moral attitudes
still better for this job. We might use many can be revealed by moral versions of the IAT
of the same inputs and bring together these and other tests, including the affect misat-
considerations in deliberation but still reach tribution procedure and Stroop tests. Here
different verdicts about morality versus de- I focus on a powerful measure of implicit
serving the job, and that difference might moral attitudes that Daryl Cameron devel-
be due to special moral processes underly- oped and tested in collaboration with Keith
ing the verdicts. We do not know. The point Payne, Julian Scheffer, Michael Inzlicht, and
here is only that we cannot even ask this me (Cameron, Payne, Sinnott-Armstrong,
question until we distinguish deliberation Scheffer, & Inzlicht, 2017).
from verdict. Our test starts with a sequential priming
Finally, if someone asks whether moral task that uses three sets of words: neutral
judgment is innate or learned or whether it (e.g., baking), moral (e.g., murder), and emo-
is culturally variable or uniform, then one tional but nonmoral (e.g., cancer). A prime
answer might be correct for deliberation and word is presented for 100 milliseconds, fol-
another for verdict. Culture might affect lowed by a target word for 400–800 mil-
which verdicts we reach without affecting liseconds. Participants are instructed to ig-
568 CL ARIF YING MOR ALIT Y

nore the prime and report whether the target to questions in experiments. The process of
word describes an act that is morally wrong. deciding whether and how to answer a moral
Those with an implicit moral attitude are question (or even whether to endorse one’s
supposed to be more likely to mistakenly moral attitudes) might require weighing the
judge neutral targets as morally wrong when pros and cons of making certain public state-
they just saw a morally wrong prime. By cal- ments, in which case it might be deliberative
culations on error rates, we can decompose in a way that our implicit moral attitudes are
task performance into multiple processes of not. We do not know yet. The point here is
moral judgment, including implicit moral at- only that we cannot formulate—much less
titude and control (ability to follow the in- answer—that question until we distinguish
structions despite misleading primes). This implicit moral attitudes from explicit moral
multinomial model enables us not just to beliefs and develop tools to measure implicit
identify implicit moral attitudes but also to moral attitudes.
measure their strength in each individual. This distinction might affect other ques-
This method has been replicated often tions as well. Is moral judgment innate or
and extended to morally controversial cases. learned? It seems possible and perhaps plau-
When we add controversial moral words sible that implicit moral attitudes are innate
(e.g., gay marriage) as primes, only partici- in ways that explicit beliefs and answers are
pants who have an implicit moral attitude not. We might have to learn which implicit
against that act are more likely to judge the moral attitudes to endorse and express, just
following target to be wrong. The test pre- as we need to learn which visual appear-
dicts both charitable giving (to controver- ances to endorse and which to dismiss. If so,
sial charities) and also voting behavior (in a then maybe implicit moral attitudes are less
referendum on gay marriage). We also have culturally variable and more uniform than
found neural correlates of some revealed fac- explicit moral beliefs.
tors and have shown that implicit moral at- Of course, we do not know any of this.
titudes are not reducible to negative affect Our tests of implicit moral attitudes have
(suggesting that this moral process might not yet been used cross-culturally or in chil-
be special rather than generic). Finally, our dren. The point here is only that we cannot
measured factors correlate with nonclinical investigate these issues properly if we keep
scores on a self-report psychopathy scale, asking about moral judgment in ways that
suggesting that psychopaths are deficient conflate implicit moral attitudes with explic-
in implicit moral attitudes even if they give it moral beliefs. We need to ask more specific
normal answers to explicit moral questions questions in order to make progress.
(Schaich Borg & Sinnott-Armstrong, 2013).
Why does this matter here? The most ob-
vious lesson is for the question of whether Areas of Morality
moral judgment (even if restricted to verdict
rather than deliberation) is a single pro- Even if we focus on implicit verdicts, it is
cess or many. The psychological and neural still useful to draw further distinctions. Jon
processes that constitute implicit moral at- Haidt distinguished four foundations (Haidt
titudes are distinct from the processes that & Joseph, 2004), then five (Haidt & Gra-
constitute explicit belief (what we reflec- ham, 2007), and now six (Haidt, 2012):
tively endorse and commit ourselves to). The harm/care, fairness/reciprocity, ingroup/
process of forming explicit beliefs is also dis- loyalty, authority/respect, purity/sanctity,
tinct from the process of deciding whether and liberty. Scott Clifford, Vijeth Iyengar,
and how to express those beliefs. If experi- Roberto Cabeza, and I developed stimuli
menters measure only explicit answers to among which factor analyses also distin-
questions, then they conflate these distinct guished physical versus emotional harm and
processes. harm to humans versus animals (Clifford,
The next question is whether moral judg- Iyengar, Cabeza, & Sinnott-Armstrong,
ment is intuitive or deliberative. Here it 2015). In addition, I suspect that fairness
again matters whether the question is about needs to be subdivided into distributive, re-
implicit attitudes, explicit beliefs, or answers tributive, and procedural justice, as well as
 Asking the Right Questions 569

fair prices and exchanges, and honesty needs who tees off first and suppresses self-interest
to fit somewhere (Parkinson et al., 2011). of those who are impatient to tee off, but it
Some critics doubt that all of these distinc- is still not seen as immoral to tee off out of
tions make a difference, and some fit them turn. Similarly, linguistic rules of pronuncia-
into two superordinate groups, such as in- tion (as well as semantics and syntax) enable
dividualizing versus binding foundations or cooperation by enabling communication,
foundations based on anger versus disgust. and they suppress self-interest in creative
I do not engage in those debates here except expression, but it is not seen as immoral to
to say that both sides might be right. Super- mispronounce words, even intentionally.
ordinate classifications are compatible with Although morality is not unified by func-
subdivisions. tion, it still might be unified at some other
What matters here is whether these areas level, such as content. Kurt Gray and col-
of morality—however many there are— leagues (Gray, Young, & Waytz, 2012) have
share anything important in common that suggested that every moral judgment shares
makes them all moral as opposed to con- a “cognitive template” insofar as it “conjures
ventional, religious, legal, aesthetic, or some to mind” intentional harm to other people:
other kind of norm. Of course, moral norms “On our account, perceived suffering is not
might be unified in any number of ways, but a distinct moral domain, but a core feature
several candidates are prominent. of all immoral acts” (p. 16). Really? Many
The first potential unifier of moral norms people throughout history have believed,
is function. Haidt (2012) writes, “Moral sys- and some still believe, that masturbation is
tems are interlocking sets of values, virtues, immoral, but this judgment is often based
norms, practices, identities, institutions, on the claim that masturbation is unnatural
technologies, and evolved psychological and not always on any perception that mas-
mechanisms that work together to suppress turbators suffer or cause suffering to others.
or regulate self-interest and make coopera- Indeed, critics of masturbation seem to think
tive societies possible” (p. 270). Josh Greene that masturbators have too much fun. Gray
(2013) proposes a similar definition: “Mo- and colleagues (2012) reply that people who
rality is a set of psychological adaptations think of masturbation as immoral believe
that allow otherwise selfish individuals to in some kind of “spiritual destruction,” but
reap the benefits of cooperation” (p. 23). such spiritual destruction is not suffering in
Many others agree openly or by assumption any literal sense, it is not causing suffering of
that all and only moral norms function to other people, and it is not caused intention-
enable cooperation by suppressing selfish- ally (Sinnott-Armstrong, 2012).
ness. Even if moral judgments are not unified by
I disagree. Many moral norms do not aim function or content (or cognitive template),
at cooperation. Just think of retributivist they still might be unified by a shared brain
norms of criminal punishment, such as “a process. To test this hypothesis, Carolyn
life for a life.” That norm might have aided Parkinson and a group of us (Parkinson et
cooperation in times when tribes would oth- al., 2011) used fMRI to examine the neural
erwise take two lives for each tribe member correlates of moral judgments about dishon-
who was killed. However, the desire to take esty, sexual disgust, and physical harm. We
more than one life as payback for killing is found that distinct neural systems became
not selfish (indeed, it is costly), and their his- active during moral judgments about these
tory does not show that retributivist norms areas. Dishonest, disgusting, and harmful
function to aid cooperation today. Indeed, moral transgressions activated brain re-
retributivist norms undermine cooperation gions associated with mentalizing, affective
when they insist on punishment in cases processing, and action understanding, re-
in which punishment leads only to dishar- spectively. Dorsal medial prefrontal cortex
mony. Conversely, many norms that aim at was recruited by all scenarios judged to be
cooperation and suppress self-interest are morally wrong, but this region was also re-
not moral in nature. The rule in golf that the cruited by dishonest and harmful scenarios
most recent winner of a hole tees off first en- judged not to be morally wrong. Overall, no
ables cooperation by avoiding disputes about brain area or network was common and pe-
570 CL ARIF YING MOR ALIT Y

culiar to moral judgments of wrongness in distinctions between verdict and delibera-


all three areas. tion, explicit belief and implicit attitude,
Morality still might be unified in many and areas of morality? We need to become
other ways. We consider several more else- splitters rather than lumpers. Each experi-
where (Sinnott-Armstrong & Wheatley, ment should focus on one specific kind of
2014) and conclude provisionally that noth- moral judgment: verdict or deliberation, ex-
ing unifies moral judgments. I will not re- plicit belief or implicit attitude, within one
peat those arguments here. Instead, I want area of morality, and also uniform in other
to explore the implications of our view for ways (such as first person or third person,
the questions that frame this volume. concrete or abstract, and so on). After we
The most obvious lesson is for the ques- investigate several specific subcategories
tion of whether morality is based on a single of “moral judgment” in a series of sepa-
process or many. Our factor analyses plus rate experiments, then we can compare the
our brain data suggest that different moral psychological and neural processes behind
judgments involve different processes with those different subcategories. In the end, we
nothing important in common (though it is might find that many or all moral judgments
admittedly not clear whether some results share something distinctive and important.
concern verdicts or deliberation). Of course, Indeed, data-driven analyses of large moral
these different processes need to be com- datasets might even unearth unifying char-
bined at some point in order to make a single acteristics in different moral processes that
decision in a conflict, but that need is not we never hypothesized in advance. In any
distinctive of morality. case, such uniformity should be an empiri-
The next question is whether morality is cal discovery, not an assumption.
intuitive or deliberative. It seems simplistic to I admit that my own research rarely lives
ask this question about morality as a whole up to this ideal. Nonetheless, splitting seems
when different answers might be needed for to be the best way to make progress in moral
different areas of morality. We might have to psychology. We need to ask the right ques-
reason or deliberate more about procedural tions in order to become able to find an-
justice (Should past misbehavior be allowed swers, and the right questions will have to
as evidence when someone is accused of cur- focus, focus, focus.
rent misbehavior?) than about intentional
harm (Was it misbehavior when he hit his
children?). Again, if humans have an intu- REFERENCES
ition that it is immoral to eat humans but
not immoral to eat other animals, then they Cameron, C. D., Payne, B. K., Sinnott-Arm-
need to deliberate or reason more in order to strong, W., Scheffer, J., & Inzlicht, M. (2017).
reach the moral judgment that eating other Measuring moral intuitions: A multinomial
modeling approach. Cognition, 158, 224–241.
animals is immoral. Clifford, S., Iyengar, V., Cabeza, R. E., & Sin-
The same point applies to other questions. nott-Armstrong, W. (2015). Moral founda-
Is morality innate or learned? Is morality tions vignettes: A standardized stimulus data-
culturally variable or uniform? Maybe ex- base of scenarios based on moral foundations
perience and culture affect some areas more theory. Behavior Research Methods, 47(4),
than others. Because of variations among 1178–1198.
(and within) areas of morality, information Gray, K., Young, L., & Waytz, A. (2012). Mind
and precision will be lost if we ask only gen- perception is the essence of morality. Psycho-
eral questions about whether morality as a logical Inquiry, 23(2), 101–124.
whole is intuitive or deliberative, innate or Greene, J. (2013). Moral tribes: Emotion, rea-
learned, variable or uniform. son, and the gap between us and them. New
York: Penguin.
Greene, J. D., Nystrom, L. E., Engell, A. D., Dar-
ley, J. M., & Cohen, J. D. (2004). The neu-
How to Make Progress ral bases of cognitive conflict and control in
moral judgment. Neuron, 44, 389–400.
It is easy to criticize and hard to improve. Greene, J. D., Sommerville, R. B., Nystrom, L.
How should we proceed in light of these E., Darley, J. M., & Cohen, J. D. (2001). An
 Asking the Right Questions 571

fMRI investigation of emotional engagement of harm, dishonesty, and disgust. Journal of


in moral judgment. Science, 293(5537), 2105– Cognitive Neuroscience, 23(10), 3162–3180.
2108. Schaich Borg, J., & Sinnott-Armstrong, W.
Greenwald, A. G., McGhee, D. E., & Schwartz, (2013). Do psychopaths make moral judg-
J. L. K. (1998). Measuring individual differ- ments? In K. A. Kiehl & W. Sinnott-Arm-
ences in implicit cognition: The Implicit Asso- strong (Eds.), Handbook on psychopathy and
ciation Test. Journal of Personality and Social law (pp. 107–128). New York: Oxford Univer-
Psychology, 74, 1464–1480. sity Press.
Haidt, J. (2012). The righteous mind: Why good Schaich Borg, J., Sinnott-Armstrong, W., Cal-
people are divided by politics and religion. houn, V. D., & Kiehl, K. A. (2011). The neural
New York: Pantheon. basis of moral verdict and moral deliberation.
Haidt, J., & Graham, J. (2007). When morality Social Neuroscience, 6(4), 398–413.
opposes justice: Conservatives have moral in- Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (1988). Moral dilemmas.
tuitions that liberals may not recognize. Social Oxford, UK: Basil Blackwell.
Justice Research, 20, 98–116. Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2008). A contrastivist
Haidt, J., & Joseph, C. (2004). Intuitive ethics: manifesto. Social Epistemology, 22(3), 257–
How innately prepared intuitions generate 270.
culturally variable virtues. Daedalus, 133(4), Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2012). Does morality
55–66. have an essence? Psychological Inquiry, 23(2),
Parkinson, C., Sinnott-Armstrong, W., Koralus, 194–197.
P. E., Mendelovici, A., McGeer, V., & Wheat- Sinnott-Armstrong, W., & Wheatley, T. (2014).
ley, T. (2011). Is morality unified?: Evidence Are moral judgments unified? Philosophical
that distinct neural systems underlie judgments Psychology, 27(4), 451–474.
Index

Note. f, n, or t following a page number indicates a figure, a note, or a table.

Abortion, 326, 327, 521, 531 research findings and, 414–417 Animals, thinking morally about
Action value, 61–63, 65. See also side-taking strategies and, cognition and, 167–168
Moral values 181–183 emotions and, 168–170
Adolescents, 13–15, 21, 23–25, 28, unselfish behavior and, 468 fairness and, 393–399
54. See also Developmental Altruistic lying, 469 free will and, 333, 334–335
processes Alzheimer’s disease, 141, 144 historical context of, 166
Affect, 84, 116–117 Ambiguity, 493–494 identity and, 170–171
Affect misattribution procedure Amygdala inequity aversion in, 394–399
(AMP), 517–518 empathy and, 508, 509 moralization and, 366
Affective neuroscience, 457. See folk moral theories and, 322 overview, 165–166, 166f,
also Neuroscience moral judgment and, 566–567 171–172
Affective processes, 4, 295, moral values and, 63 side-taking strategies and, 180
512–513 overview, 507, 507f theory and, 166–171
Afterlife beliefs, 241–249. See also Analysis of data. See Big data Anterior cingulate cortex (ACC),
Religious traditions analysis; Data analysis 60, 63, 64
Age, 204–205, 313–314, 430–431, Anger Anterior insula (AI), 60, 64, 508
509 avoidance- and approach-related Anterior midcingulate cortex
Agency, 333, 376, 559–561, 560f behavioral responses and, 78 (aMCC), 508
Agency-based mental states, 189. compared to disgust, 75 Anthropic principle, 357
See also Mental states component process model Anthropocentric perspective,
Aggression (CPM) and, 72, 72f 353–354, 354t, 355–356
intergroup aggression and, historical moral change and, 271 Anthropological approaches
193–198 moral foundations theory (MFT) historical moral change and,
relationship regulation theory and, 90 260, 268
(RRT) and, 235 moralization of the body and, moral foundations theory (MFT)
side-taking strategies and, 179 280 and, 213, 214, 218
vulnerability and, 430–431, 431 vulnerability-based morality, religions and, 340
Allocation hypothesis, 182 432 Anti-essentialist assumptions,
Altruism. See also Helping Animal inequity aversion. See also 92–93
behaviors Animals, thinking morally Antisocial behavior, 195–196, 249
in animals, 416–417 about Anxiety, 242, 245–246, 479
choosing sides and, 177 compared to human inequity Anxiety buffer disruption theory
historical moral change and, aversion, 398 (ABDT), 249
260, 270 moral clarity and, 497–498 Apathy, 194, 195
overview, 413–417 overview, 394–399 Appearance, 169–170

573
574 Index

Appraisals, 82–83 B Biases


Attachment blame and, 387
ethical behavior and, 479 Badness empathy and, 49–50
ethogenesis and, 453 blame and, 387 intelligent design and, 352–358
historical context of, 443–445 compared to wrongness, 40–44 moral character and, 104
overview, 440–441, 441–443, moral cognition and, 113–114, moral clarity and, 498
443f, 447–448 115 moral cognition and, 112
research findings and, 446–447 overview, 40–41 moral coherence and, 376–377
terror management theory theory and, 41 relationship regulation theory
(TMT) and, 244 Banality of evil perspective, (RRT) and, 232
theory and, 445–446 195–196 religions and, 340
Attitudes Basal ganglia, 566–567 Big data analysis. See also Data
grounded approaches and, 296 Basic emotion theory (BET), 89, analysis
Implicit processes and, 516–517, 90, 91–93 historical context of, 527–528
520, 567–568 Behavior. See also Ethical methodology and, 528–530
modeling approach and, behavior; Goal-directed overview, 525–527, 532–533
517–518 behavior; Helping behaviors; research findings and, 530–532
moral clarity and, 494–495, 496 Selfish behavior; Unethical Bilateral anterior insula, 566–567
vulnerability-based morality, behavior; Unselfish behavior Biocentrism, 354t, 357–358
431 choosing sides and, 177–184 Bioethical issues, 326–328, 327t
Attribution death awareness and, 247–248 Biological factors
ambiguity and, 76 development of sociomoral altruism in children and, 414
moral cognition and, 559–560, evaluations in infants and, ethogenesis, 451–452
560f 404–405 folk moral theories and, 325
moral standing of animals and, developmental neuroscience and, historical moral change and,
166f, 167–168 512–513 270, 273–274
vulnerability-based morality, 432 distributive fairness and, intelligent design and, 353
Authority 421–422 moral vitalism and, 304, 305,
constructive origins of morality ethogenesis and, 453 308
and, 25 evaluating moral character and, stereotype content model (SCM)
development of morality and, 100–102 and, 204
11, 16n, 21 historicist view of morality and, terror management theory
geographies of morality and, 341 260 (TMT) and, 242–243
historicist view of morality and, infants’ evaluation of, 407 Biopsychosocial functioning,
261 intergroup aggression and, 451–452
implicit moral processes and, 522 193–198 Blame
intergroup aggression and, moral beliefs and, 315–317 acceptance versus condemnation
195–196 moral clarity and, 494 of, 387–388
moral foundations theory (MFT) moral cognition and, 111 evolutionary heritage of,
and, 213 moral identity and, 137, 145 383–384
overview, 568–569 moral self-theory and, 154–156, hypotheses about, 384
relationship regulation theory 157 inclinations towards, 384–385
(RRT) and, 233, 236–237 moral vitalism and, 305–306 moral cognition and, 112,
social and moral decision moralization and, 367–368 113–114, 114f, 115–116
making and, 12–13 perceived control and, 385–386 moral coherence and, 374
Automatic mechanisms preference for helpers by infants overview, 382–383, 388–389
blame and, 384–385 and, 408–409 perceived control and, 385–387
empathy and, 51–52, 53 relationship regulation theory research evidence regarding
ethogenesis and, 455–456 (RRT) and, 233, 237–238 infants’ fairness concerns and,
folk moral theories and, religions and, 340–341 425
321–322, 322t side-taking strategies and, 180 social interactions and, 191
moral cognition and, 109–110 testing moral behavior, 489–490 stereotypes and, 202
moral foundations theory (MFT) unconflicted virtue and, Body, moralization of
and, 213 485–492 boundaries of the self, 279–287
moral judgment and, 3, 25 vulnerability-based morality grounded approaches and,
Autonomous decision making, 21. and, 436–437 296–297
See also Decision making Belief systems, 241–249, historical context of, 280
Aversion, 41–42. See also Disgust 303–308. See also Moral overview, 286–287
Avoidance processes, 78, 223–224, belief; Religious traditions; research findings and, 280–286
224f, 479 Spirituality theory and, 280
 Index 575

Boundaries of the self moral self-theory and, 154 moral vitalism and, 304–305
expansion of, 284–286 moral vitalism and, 306–307 overview, 556–557, 561–563
grounded approaches and, 296 overview, 99–100, 106 parallel morality hypothesis
historical context of, 280 person-centered morality and, and, 33
overview, 279–280, 286–287 122–127 terror management theory
research findings and, 280–286 Charitable acts, 154–155, (TMT) and, 243
theory and, 280 339–340. See also Behavior; Coherence processes. See Moral
Brain regions. See also Prosocial acts coherence processes
Neuroscience Cheating, 212, 479, 489–490 Collectivism, 273, 471, 498–499
attachment and, 444 Child marriage, 269 Communication, 82, 83, 254–255
folk moral theories and, 321–322 Children. See also Developmental Comparisons, 105–106
implicit moral processes and, processes Compassion, 90, 213
521 altruism and, 413–417 Competition, 62–63, 188–189,
intergroup aggression and, 197 constructive origins of morality 194–195, 196–197
moral judgment and, 566–567 and, 23–25 Complexity, moral. See Moral
moral values and, 60–61, 64–65 ethogenesis and, 452 complexity
overview, 4, 506–508, 507f moral clarity and, 498 Compliance, 24–25, 285
parallel morality hypothesis and, moral judgment and, 21, 28 Component process model (CPM).
35–36 prejudice and, 26 See also Disgust
stereotypes and, 202 psychopathy, 512 historical context of, 72–74
social and moral decision overview, 72, 72f, 77–78
making and, 13–15 research findings and, 75–77
C social inequalities and, 27–28 theory and, 74–75
vulnerability and, 430–431 Condemnation, 177–184
CAD (Contempt/Anger/Disgust) wrongness compared to badness Condom education, 374–375
triad hypothesis, 73, 74–75, and, 40–44 Confirmation bias, 104, 498
84–85, 260 Choice, 11–13, 15, 332–336 Conflicted virtue, 486–487,
Capital punishment, 374–375, 379, Choosing sides. See Side-taking 489–490, 491
521 strategies Conformity, 11, 270
Care Clarity, moral. See Moral clarity Conscientiousness, 226, 453–454
caring behavior, 453 Cleanliness, 284–286 Constructivist approach
moral foundations theory (MFT) Climate change, 379, 540–541 emotions and, 88–89
and, 212, 213, 214, 215 Cognition-affect interactions, 52 intergroup relationships and,
overview, 568–569 Cognitive control, 4 25–26
unselfish behavior and, 469 Cognitive depletion, 495 overview, 11, 23–25
Causation Cognitive development, 150–151, whole-number approach and,
folk moral theories and, 324 455–456, 477–478 90–91, 92–93
free will and, 333 Cognitive dissonance theory, 372 Contextual effects, 297–298, 306
intelligent design and, 353 Cognitive load, 52–53 Control, perceived, 385–387
norms and, 558f Cognitive neuroscience, 197, 198. Controlled mechanisms, 109–110,
perceived control and, 385–386, See also Neuroscience 321–322, 322t, 374
385–387 Cognitive processes. See also Cooperation
Certainty, 494, 496 Moral cognition altruism in children and, 416
Change, moral. See Historical altruism in children and, 415 development of sociomoral
moral change complexity and, 27–28 evaluations in infants and,
Character evaluation. See also component process model 403–404, 405
Character judgments; Moral (CPM) and, 76–77 evolved developmental niche
character distributive fairness and, (EDN) and, 454
defining moral character and, 421–422 free will and, 335
102–104 ethical behavior and, 479–480 inequity aversion in animals
overview, 99–100 folk moral theories and, and, 395–398
social cognition and, 100–102, 323–324 mental states and, 188–189
125 grounded approaches and, 293 model of moral motives (MMM)
social interactions and, 187 historical moral change and, and, 226–227, 228–229
Character judgments. See also 266, 274 moral coherence and, 378–379
Character evaluation; Moral historicist view of morality and, moral heroes as puppets and, 254
character 260 moral values and, 62–63
component process model moral clarity and, 493, 495 moralization of the body and, 283
(CPM) and, 72, 76–77 moral standing of animals and, religions and, 340
diagnosticity and, 124 167–168 side-taking strategies and, 179
576 Index

Coordination, 227, 228–229 Deception, 13–14. See also Developmental processes


Core disgust evaluation, 76–77, Honesty altruism and, 413–417
271. See also Disgust Decision making constructive origins of morality
Culpability, 373, 374, 376 brain mechanisms, 507 and, 23–25
Culpable control model of blame cultural practices and, 14–16, distributive fairness and,
(CCM), 383, 384, 385–387, 16f 421–422
388–389. See also Blame development of morality and, ethogenesis and, 453–456
Cultural anthropology of morality, 13–14 evolved developmental niche
213, 218, 243 grounded approaches and, 297, (EDN) and, 453–456
Cultural factors 298 fairness and, 420–428
anthropocentrism and, 355 moral clarity and, 494 folk moral theories and,
attachment and, 445–446, 448 moral cognition and, 111 323–324
blame and, 387–388 moral judgment and, 21 honesty and deception and,
disgust and, 74 nonmoral considerations and, 13–14
ethogenesis and, 456 22–23 moral beliefs and, 312
fairness and, 394 parallel morality hypothesis moral clarity and, 498
free will and, 333–334 and, 36 moral foundations theory (MFT)
grounded approaches and, 293 perceived control and, 386–387 and, 215
historical moral change and, processes of, 11–14 moral judgment and, 21
260–261, 262–263, 269, 270 relationship regulation theory nonmoral considerations and,
identity and, 143–144 (RRT) and, 232–233, 236 22–23
model of moral motives (MMM) testing moral behavior, 489–490 overview, 10–11, 28
and, 224–225, 227 the trolley problem, 432–433 prejudice and, 26
moral beliefs and, 312 Defining morality research evidence regarding
moral clarity and, 498–499 inability to, 554 infants’ fairness concerns and,
moral foundations theory (MFT) moral psychology and, 565–570 423–426
and, 212, 213, 216 overview, 547–549, 548f social and moral decision
moral judgment and, 569 testing a definition of morality, making and, 13–14
moral self-theory and, 152 549–554 social cognitive development
moral vitalism and, 305 Dehumanization, 202, 238, 356 and, 23
moralization of the body and, Deities, belief in, 241–249, social inequalities and, 27–28
282 352–358, 384–385 sociomoral evaluations and,
overview, 14–16, 16f Deliberative processes 402–410
relationship regulation theory disgust and, 73–74 terror management theory
(RRT) and, 234, 235–236, ethogenesis and, 455–456 (TMT) and, 243
238–239 folk moral theories and, wrongness compared to badness
religions and, 340 321–324, 322t and, 40–44
side-taking strategies and, 180 grounded approaches and, Diachronic identity, 141, 145–146.
stereotype content model (SCM) 294–295 See also Identity
and, 204–205 historical context of, 32–33 Diagnostic and Statistical Manual
terror management theory (TMT) moral clarity and, 494–495 of Mental Disorders (DSM),
and, 242, 243–246, 249 moral cognition and, 110 388
testing a definition of morality, moral judgment and, 567, 569 Disease, 280–286, 305
552–553 overview, 31–32, 36–37 Disgust. See also Component
theory of dyadic morality research findings and, 34–36 process model (CPM)
(TDM) and, 366–367 theory and, 33–34 avoidance- and approach-related
unethical behavior and, 471 Demoralization, 365–366, 365f behavioral responses and, 78
worldviews, 243–246 Descriptive processes, 234, 379 functional conflict theory of
Determinism, 326–328, 327t moral emotions and, 83
Developmental neuroscience. See historical context of, 72–74
D also Neuroscience historical moral change and,
affective sharing and, 512–513 271
Data analysis, 525–527, 532–533. brain mechanisms, 506–508, intergroup aggression and,
See also Big data analysis 507f 194–195
Davis Interpersonal Reactivity empathy and morality and, moral foundations theory (MFT)
Index (IRI), 424–425 508–512 and, 90
Death, 241–249 future directions and, 513 moral standing of animals and,
Death-thought accessibility (DTA), overview, 505–506 168–169
246, 248 theory and, 506 moral vitalism and, 307
 Index 577

moralization of the body and, E research findings and, 53–54


280, 281, 282–283, 284 theory and, 51–53
opposition to genetically Economic factors, 272–273, 283 unselfish behavior and, 469
modified (GM) food, 538–540 Ego depletion, 491n Environmental appeals, 540–541
overview, 70–71, 77–78 Egocentrism, 352–358, 354t Environmental factors
relationship regulation theory Elderly persons, 430–431 constructive origins of morality
(RRT) and, 234 Embedded morality, 294, 297–298. and, 24–25
research findings and, 75–77 See also Grounded approaches evolved developmental niche
stereotypes and, 201–202 to morality (EDN) and, 454–455
theory and, 74–75 Embodied morality approach. See grounded approaches and,
Disgust Scale—Revised (DS-R), also Grounded approaches to 297–298
539 morality moral clarity and, 495
Dispositional orientation, historical context of, 280 moral self-theory and, 152
452–453, 475 overview, 279–280, 286–287 moral values and, 62–63
Distributive fairness. See also research findings and, 280–286 overview, 338–339
Fairness theory and, 280 skills expertise and, 489
early moral development and, Embryonic stem cell research, 326, Envy, 201–202
421–422 327, 374–375 Epiphanies, 495
overview, 420–421, 426–428 Emotions Epistemic states, 406–407
research evidence regarding attachment and, 445 Equality, 232–233, 236, 297. See
infants’ fairness concerns and, blame and, 384, 387 also Fairness; Inequity aversion
423–426 developmental neuroscience and, Essentialism, 92–93, 143
theory and, 422–423 506 Ethical behavior. See also Behavior
Divinity, 70–71, 294. See also emotion regulation, 170 ability and willpower and,
Component process model empathy and, 51–53 477–478
(CPM); Disgust functional conflict theory of, identity and motivation and,
Dogmatism, 496 81–86 478–479
Domain specificity effects, 91 grounded approaches and, 296 overview, 465–466, 466t
Domain theory, 234–235 historical moral change and, personality traits and, 478
Dopaminergic nuclei, 509 267–268, 271–272, 274 selfish behavior and, 467–468
Dorsolateral prefrontal cortex intergroup aggression and, unselfish behavior and, 468
(DLPFC) 194–195 Ethics, 231
folk moral theories and, 321, 322 moral judgment and, 88–89 Ethnicity, 15–16, 16f
moral thinking and, 4 moral standing of animals and, Ethogenesis
overview, 507, 507f 166f, 168–170 dispositional and situational
parallel morality hypothesis and, moralization of the body and, orientations, 452–453
34–35 280 historical context of, 453–456
Dualism+ Scale, 326–328, 327t overview, 4, 54 overview, 451–452, 457–458
Dual-process model research findings and, 85 research findings and, 457
egocentrism and, 354 role of, 89–90 theory and, 456
folk moral theories and, 321– as a social–moral signal, Euthanasia. See Physician-assisted
324, 322t, 326–328, 327t 116–117 suicide
grounded approaches and, 295 stereotypes and, 201–202 Evaluation, 27–28. See also Moral
model of moral motives (MMM) unethical behavior and, 477 judgment
and, 225 Empathy Event-related potentials (ERPs),
moral self-theory and, 153 developmental neuroscience and, 510–512
moral vitalism and, 306 506, 508–512 Evolutionary factors
overview, 89, 122 ethical behavior and, 478, 480 anthropocentrism and, 355
Dual-systems approach, 321 evolved developmental niche attachment and, 443–444
Dyadic comparison, 364 (EDN) and, 453–454 blame and, 383–384, 388
Dyadic completion, 306, 364, 377 functional conflict theory of cooperation and, 403–404
Dyadic loop, 365–366, 365f moral emotions and, 83 development of sociomoral
Dyadic model, 73, 441–443, 443f historical context of, 50–51 evaluations in infants and,
Dyadic morality, 366–367, 367, identity and, 146 403–404
443–444, 446 intergroup aggression and, ethogenesis, 451–458
Dyadic morality theory (DMT), 193–198 evolved developmental niche
215–216. See also Theory of moral standing of animals and, (EDN) and, 453–456
dyadic morality (TDM) 170 historical moral change and,
Dyad-superiority effect, 441–442 overview, 49–50, 53, 54, 194 266, 267–268, 270
578 Index

Evolutionary factors (cont.) research evidence regarding stereotype content model (SCM)
historicist view of morality and, infants’ fairness concerns and, and, 204–205
260 423–426 transformations over time,
moral clarity and, 494 social interactions and, 190 15–16, 16f
moral foundations theory (MFT) Fear vulnerability and, 430–431
and, 211 ethogenesis and, 453 Generosity, 340. See also Sharing
moral heroes as puppets and, historical moral change and, 271 Genetic factors, 267, 268,
254 intergroup aggression and, 338–339, 456, 505
moral identity and, 145–146 194–195 Genetically modified organisms
moral self-theory and, 151 moral standing of animals and, (GMOs)
moralization of the body and, 168–169 dyadic loop and, 365
282 moralization of the body and, moral psychology and, 538–540
overview, 338–339 280–281 moralization and, 367, 368
side-taking strategies and, 180 Femininity, 498–499 Genetic–cultural coevolutionary
stereotype content model (SCM) Firm views of moral identity, 135, products, 505
and, 204–205 136–137. See also Moral Geocentricism, 354t, 356–357
terror management theory identity Geographies of morality
(TMT) and, 242–243 Five-foundations model, 540–541 continents, comparison among,
theory of dyadic morality Flexible views of moral identity, 345–347
(TDM) and, 364 135–137, 138–139. See also overview, 338–339, 347
vulnerability-based morality, Moral identity religions and, 339–341
431 Folk moral theories secularia and, 341–345, 342f,
Evolutionary psychology, 213–214 dual-process perspective, 344f
Evolved developmental niche 321–324, 322t Glückschmerz, 194. See also
(EDN), 453–456, 457–458 future directions and, 328–329 Outgroup pain
Executive control, 519 intuitive dualism and, 326–328, Goal-directed behavior, 52–53, 194–
Expertise, 487–488 327t 195, 422. See also Behavior
Explicit beliefs, 567–568 overview, 320–321 God(s), belief in
Expressivism, 311 research findings and, 324–326 blame and, 384–385
Foot binding, 271 intelligent design and, 352–358
Forgiveness, 336, 387–388 terror management theory
F Free will, 326–328, 327t, 332–336 (TMT) and, 241–249
Friendliness, 205–206 Goodness, 436–437
Facial expressions, 75, 85, 296 Functional conflict theory Ground Zero mosque, 531
Fairness. See also Distributive historical context of, 82–84 Grounded approaches to morality.
fairness; Equality; Inequity overview, 81–82, 85–86 See also Embodied morality
aversion; Justice research findings and, 85 approach
animals and, 393–399 theory and, 84–85 historical context of, 292–293
comparing animals to humans Functionalist approach, 102, overview, 292, 297–298
and, 398 123–124, 151–152, 323, 510 research findings and, 295–297
cultural practices and, 15 Fundamentalist view, 104, theory and, 293–295
development of sociomoral 259–264 Grounded cognition, 292, 293, 294
evaluations in infants and, Group membership. See also
404 Ingroup identity; Intergroup
developmental origins of, G relationships
420–428 historical moral change and, 270
implicit moral processes and, Game-theoretic tools intergroup relationships and,
521–522 historical moral change and, 25–26
model of moral motives (MMM) 267–268 moral heroes as puppets and, 254
and, 224 Prisoner’s Dilemma game, 61, moral identity and, 137
moral clarity and, 497–498 433–435 moral self-theory and, 152
moral foundations theory (MFT) side-taking strategies and, 180 religion and, 247
and, 212, 214 Gay marriage. See Same-sex Guilt
moral judgment and, 27, 32 marriage ethical behavior and, 478, 480
moral values and, 61 Gender functional conflict theory of
moralization of the body and, blame and, 387 moral emotions and, 83
281, 283–284 cultural practices and, 15 moral self-theory and, 155–156
overview, 568–569 historical moral change and, 269 relationship regulation theory
Prisoner’s Dilemma game, 435 intergroup relationships and, 26 (RRT) and, 237
 Index 579

H moral coherence and, 375 Impurity judgments, 216–217,


moral judgment and, 367, 368, 281–284
Happiness, 280 568 Incidental disgust, 71, 73–74. See
Harm theory of dyadic morality also Disgust
developmental neuroscience and, (TDM) and, 364 Individual differences
506 Honesty distributive fairness and, 426
dyadic loop and, 365, 365f development of morality and, moral beliefs and, 313–314
harm hypothesis, 234–235 13–14 moral identity and, 136–137
implicit moral processes and, geographies of morality and, moral vitalism and, 307
521–522 340 research evidence regarding
moral coherence and, 376, 377 overview, 569 infants’ fairness concerns and,
moral foundations theory (MFT) social and moral decision 424–425
and, 212, 213, 215, 216–217 making and, 13–14 Individualism
moralization of the body and, testing moral behavior, 490 historical moral change and, 273
281 Honor killings, 269 moral clarity and, 498–499
opposition to genetically Human inequity aversion, 393– moral foundations theory (MFT)
modified (GM) food, 539–540 394, 398. See also Fairness and, 213
overview, 194, 568–569 Humility, 105–106 unethical behavior and, 471
pluralism and, 215–216 Hypocrisy, 340 Industriousness, 223–224, 224f,
relationship regulation theory 225–226
(RRT) and, 234–235 Inequity aversion. See also Fairness
theory of dyadic morality I in animals, 394–399
(TDM) and, 366–367 comparing animals to humans
wrongness compared to badness Identity. See also Moral identity; and, 398
and, 42 Self-identity in humans, 393–394
Hatred, 194–195 essentialism and, 143 overview, 398–399
Health, 280–286, 305 ethical behavior and, 478–479 Infants
Helpers, 404–406, 407–409. See folk moral theories and, altruism and, 414
also Helping behaviors 326–328, 327t attachment and, 441–443, 443f
Helping behaviors. See also historical context of, 142–143 constructive origins of morality
Altruism; Behavior; Helpers moral standing of animals and, and, 23–25
in animals, 416–417 166f, 170–171 distributive fairness and,
in children, 414–416 moral values and, 59 420–428
empathy and, 51 overview, 141–142, 145–146, infant–caregiver interactions,
moralization of the body and, 153–154 446
285 research evidence and, 143–144 moral clarity and, 498
unselfish behavior and, 468 social cognitive model of, possession of a sociomoral core
Hero Pose, 255–256 133–139 by, 404–407
Heroes, moral. See Moral heroes uncertainties and, 144–145 preference for helpers by,
Hero’s Speech, 254–255 Image-focused moral self, 152 407–409
Hierarchy, 124–125, 233, Imagination orientation, 452 research evidence regarding
236–237, 297 Immoral behavior, 155–156, infants’ fairness concerns and,
Hinderers, 404–406, 407–409 367–368. See also Behavior 423–426
Historical moral change Immortality, 241–249 sociomoral evaluations and,
historical context of, 266–267 Impartiality, 183 402–410
moralization and, 363–368 Imperialism, 269–270 Inferences, 353, 415, 445
overview, 266, 273–274 Implicit Association Test (IAT), Information processing, 385,
research findings and, 268–273 202–203, 517–518, 494–495
theory and, 267–268 567–568 Ingroup identity. See also Group
Historicist view of morality Implicit attitudes, 567–568 membership
historical context of, 260–261 Implicit moral processes empathy and, 53
overview, 259–260, 263–264 ethogenesis and, 455–456 intergroup aggression and,
research findings and, 262–263 implicit moral attitude, 194–195
theory and, 261–262 516–517 moral judgment and, 27
Homosexuality. See also Same-sex modeling approach and, overview, 26, 137, 568–569
marriage 517–519 Inhibition, 35–37, 444
dyadic loop and, 366 overview, 516–517, 521–522 Insula, 507, 507f, 508–509
implicit moral processes and, research findings and, 519–521 Integrative approach, 152–153,
521 Impression management, 254 243, 457
580 Index

Intelligent design disgust and, 73–74 Laws, 28, 343, 345


anthropocentrism and, 354t, distributive fairness and, 422 Lay meta-ethics, 312–314
355–356 ethogenesis and, 455–456 Leadership, 252–256
biocentrism and, 354t, 357–358 fairness and, 422 Learning
egocentrism and, 354–355, 354t folk moral theories and, evolved developmental niche
geocentricism and, 354t, 321–324, 322t, 324, 326–328, (EDN) and, 454–455
356–357 327t functional conflict theory of
historical context of, 352–353, grounded approaches and, moral emotions and, 82
354t 294–295 historical moral change and, 274
overview, 352, 358 historical context of, 32–33 learning theory, 24–25
Intentionality moral clarity and, 494–495, 496 moral clarity and, 497–498
blame and, 384–385 moral cognition and, 110 moral cognition and, 110–111
development of sociomoral moral coherence and, 373–374 moral judgment and, 569
evaluations in infants and, moral foundations theory (MFT) moral values and, 63–64, 65
404 and, 212 unethical behavior and, 471
developmental neuroscience and, moral intuition and, 517 LGBT rights, 269
510 moral judgment and, 127–128, Liberty, 522, 568–569
disgust and, 76 567, 569 Life bioethical issues, 326, 327.
distributive fairness and, 422 moral vitalism and, 305 See also Abortion; Physician-
infants’ evaluation of, 405–406 overview, 31–32, 36–37 assisted suicide
moral coherence and, 374, 377 research findings and, 34–36 Love, 271
moral self-theory and, 154 theory and, 33–34 Loyalty, 212–213, 470, 522,
moralization of the body and, vulnerability and, 430 568–569
281, 285
relationship regulation theory
(RRT) and, 234–235 J M
wrongness compared to badness
and, 44 Judgments. See also Moral Macbeth effect, 285
Interactionist model of unethical judgment Machiavellianism, 478, 480
behavior, 475–477, 476f, cultural practices and, 15 Manichaeism, 496
479–480. See also Unethical development of morality and, Market pricing, 232, 236
behavior 10–11 Marriage. See also Same-sex
Interdependence structures, 205 empathy and, 51–52 marriage
Interference paradigms, 296 evaluating moral character and, dyadic loop and, 366
Intergroup aggression. See also 100–102 historical moral change and,
Aggression moral self-theory and, 155–156 271, 273
debates regarding, 194–196 moral values and, 64–65 implicit moral processes and,
overview, 193, 197–198 social and moral decision 521
Schadenfreude as a motivator of, making and, 11–13 moral judgment and, 367, 568
196–197 Justice, 10–11, 213, 435, 469. See Masculinity, 498–499
Intergroup relationships. See also Fairness Masturbation
also Group membership; Justification, 195–196 dyadic loop and, 366
Relationships Just-world theory, 35 moral judgment and, 569
constructing morality and, moralization and, 363–364, 368
25–26 theory of dyadic morality
moral judgment and, 26–27 K (TDM) and, 364
overview, 194 Materialist tradition, 272–273
Schadenfreude and, 194–198 Kindness, 237, 239 Meaning extraction method
social inequalities and, 27–28 Kornblith–Devitt strategy, 551–554 (MEM), 531–532
stereotype content model (SCM) Medial orbitofrontal cortex
and, 203 (mOFC), 60–61, 63, 64–65
International Affective Picture L Medial prefrontal cortex (mPFC),
System (IAPS), 510 507, 507f, 510
Interrogation, 374–375 Latent Dirichlet allocation (LDA), Mental representations, 296. See
Intuitive dualism, 326–328, 327t 530–531 also Representations
Intuitive processes. See also Moral Latent semantic analysis (LSA), Mental states, 186–190
intuition 528, 532 Meritocracy, 205
attachment and, 440–441 Late-positive potential (LPP), 511 Meta-ethical beliefs, 312–314,
behavior and, 487 Lateral hypothalamus, 509 315–317. See also Moral belief
 Index 581

Metaphors, 295–296 Moral decision making. See also Moral identity. See also Identity
Mind attribution, 167–168 Decision making ethical behavior and, 478, 480
Mind perception, 559–561, 560f cultural practices and, 14–16, historical context of, 142–143
Mind–brain identity, 326–328, 16f overview, 145–146, 150
327t empathy and, 49–50 social cognitive model of,
Model of moral motives (MMM). historical context of, 122 133–139
See also Motivation moral cognition and, 111 Moral intuition, 89, 152–153,
historical context of, 225 processes of, 11–14 373–374. See also Intuitive
overview, 223–225, 224f, 229 Moral dilemmas, 565–570 processes
research findings and, 227–229 Moral disagreements, 233, 238 Moral judgment. See also
theory and, 225–227 Moral discourse theory, 213 Judgments; Sociomoral
Modeling approach, 517–519 Moral disengagement, 37, 478, 480 evaluations
Moderation, 223–224, 224f, Moral diversity, 268–270 attachment approach to,
225–226 Moral domain 440–448
Money, 470–471 lack of support for, 554 blame as, 382–389
Moral agency, 559. See also overview, 547 brain mechanisms, 507
Agency project of defining morality, choosing sides and, 177–184
Moral belief. See also Belief 547–554, 548f death awareness and, 247–248
systems testing a definition of morality, disgust and, 70–71, 76–77
behavior and, 315–317 549–554 emotions and, 88–93
lay meta-ethics, 312–314 Moral domain theory, 261, 262 ethogenesis and, 456
overview, 310–312, 314–315, Moral Dyad Theory, 216–217 folk moral theories and, 320–
317 Moral emotions, 81–86, 201–202. 321, 322–323, 324, 328
psychological research and, See also Emotions free will and, 333, 335–336
311–312 Moral foundations theory (MFT) grounded approaches and, 297
Moral change. See Historical moral big data analysis and, 530, 532 historical context of, 122
change constructionism and, 90–91 historicist view of morality and,
Moral character, 99–106, emotions and, 89–90 260
122–125. See also Character grounded approaches and, 297 how people form, 31–32
evaluation; Character historical context of, 213–214, implicit moral processes and,
judgments 260 516–522
Moral clarity, 493–495, 497–498, implicit moral processes and, intergroup relationships and,
499 521–522 25–26, 26–27
Moral cognition. See also model of moral motives (MMM) intuitive and rational processes
Cognitive processes and, 225–227, 228–229 and, 127–128
character and, 124 moral clarity and, 495–496 moral beliefs and, 312
grounded approaches and, 294, moral vitalism and, 305 moral clarity and, 493–499
296, 297–298 moralization and, 366 moral cognition and, 111
historical context of, 109–110, overview, 93, 211–213, 218 moral coherence and, 372–379
109f relationship regulation theory moral foundations theory (MFT)
mind perception and, 559–561, (RRT) and, 234 and, 214, 216–217
560f research findings and, 216–217 moral vitalism and, 306
norms and, 557–559, 558f side-taking strategies and, 180 moralization of the body and,
overview, 108–109, 109f, social interactions and, 280, 281–284, 285
116–117, 186–187, 556–557, 189–190 nonmoral considerations and,
562–563 terror management theory 22–23
research findings and, 113–116 (TMT) and, 242, 247 overview, 20–22, 25, 28,
scientific cognition, 561–562 theory and, 214–217 121–122, 565–570
theory and, 110–113, 111f, 113f theory of dyadic morality parallel morality hypothesis and,
Moral coherence processes (TDM) and, 367 31–37
historical context of, 372 whole-number approach and, preference for helpers by infants
overview, 371–372, 378–379 90, 91–93 and, 409
research findings and, 374–378 Moral grammar hypothesis, 43, relationship regulation theory
theory and, 372–374 234–235 (RRT) and, 231–233, 234
Moral complexity Moral heroes social cognitive development
historical context of, 372 historical context of, 253 and, 23
moral coherence and, 371–379 overview, 252–253, 256 social inequalities and, 27–28
overview, 371–372, 378–379 research findings and, 254–256 social interactions and, 189–191
theory and, 372–374 theory and, 253–254 social regulation and, 116
582 Index

Moral judgment (cont.) research findings and, 153–156 Neuroscience. See also Brain
terror management theory theoretical stance of, 151–153 regions; Developmental
(TMT) and, 245–246 Moral standing of animals. See neuroscience
theory and, 41 Animal inequity aversion; ethogenesis and, 452, 457
theory of dyadic morality Animals, thinking morally folk moral theories and,
(TDM) and, 363–368 about 321–322
wrongness compared to badness Moral transformation, 268–270 intergroup aggression and, 197,
and, 40–44 Moral values 198
Moral monism, 215–217 action value, 61–63 moral values and, 60, 64–65
Moral objectivism, 314–316, 317 feedback and learning, 63–64 testing moral behavior, 490
Moral psychology. See also grounded approaches and, 297 Nonconsequentialism, 181–182
Psychological foundations judgment and, 64–65 Nonhuman sense of fairness,
attachment and, 440–441, 445 outcome value, 60–61 393–399. See also Animals,
big data analysis and, 532–533 overview, 59–60, 65–66 thinking morally about;
description and process and, Moral vitalism Fairness
541–542 historical moral change and, Nonmoral cognition, 561–563. See
environmental appeals and, 304–305 also Cognitive processes
540–541 overview, 303–304, 307–308 Nonpurity transgressions, 70–71,
fairness and, 420–421 research findings and, 306–307 74–77. See also Component
folk moral theories and, theory and, 305–306 process model (CPM); Disgust
323–324 Morality, 20–22, 149 Nonsocial hypothesis, 395–398
free will and, 332–336 Moralization Noradrenergic system, 509
grounded approaches and, 294, dyadic loop and, 365–366, 365f Normative cognition, 260
297, 298 historical context of, 366–367 Normative judgments, 260
historical moral change and, overview, 363–364, 368 Norms
267–268, 273–274 research findings and, 367–368 altruism and, 414
moral foundations theory (MFT) theory and, 367 development of morality and,
and, 213–214, 218 Mortality, 241–249 11
moralization and, 368 Mortality salience (MS), 246, 248 free will and, 333–334
opposition to genetically Motivation. See also Model of historical moral change and,
modified (GM) food, 538–540 moral motives (MMM) 271, 273
overview, 537, 542, 565–570 disgust and, 75–76 historicist view of morality and,
Prisoner’s Dilemma game, empathy and, 53 260, 261, 262–263
433–435 ethical behavior and, 478–479 learning and, 110–111
relationship regulation theory functional conflict theory of moral cognition and, 110–111
(RRT) and, 233, 234–235, moral emotions and, 84 moral judgment and, 27
238 historicist view of morality and, moral values and, 64
terror management theory 260 moralization and, 363–368
(TMT) and, 241–242 mental states and, 189 overview, 557–559, 558f, 569
testing a definition of morality, moral heroes as puppets and, relationship regulation theory
551–554 254 (RRT) and, 231–232
the trolley problem, 432–433 moral values and, 62 research evidence regarding
Moral reasoning. See also overview, 168, 223–225, 224f infants’ fairness concerns and,
Reasoning relationship regulation theory 426
developmental neuroscience and, (RRT) and, 232–233, 232t social interactions and, 191
511 social interactions and, 188 theory of dyadic morality
folk moral theories and, Multinomial model, 518–521 (TDM) and, 364
322–323 Multivoxel pattern analysis vulnerability and, 430–431
moral coherence and, 373 (MVPA), 65 wrongness compared to badness
moral self-theory and, 150–151, and, 41–43
153
moral vitalism and, 304–308 N
Moral self-perception theory, 149– O
150. See also Self-perceptions Nativism, 211–212, 216
Moral self-theory. See also Self- Natural kind models, 92–93 Objectivity, 310, 314–316, 317
identity Natural language processing Outcome bias, 376–377
historical context of, 150–151 (NLP), 527–528, 529, Outcome control, 385–386, 387
overview, 149–150, 156–157 530–531, 532 Outgroup bias, 26, 27, 53
 Index 583

Outgroup hate, 194–195 Philosophy empathy and, 52–54


Outgroup pain, 194–198. See also attachment and, 447–448 ethogenesis and, 455
Schadenfreude blame and, 387–388 geographies of morality and, 339
folk moral theories and, 326 moral clarity and, 496, 498
grounded approaches and, 293 moral identity and, 137
P historicist view of morality and, moral self-theory and, 154–155,
260 157
Parallel morality hypothesis moral beliefs and, 310–311 moralization of the body and, 284
historical context of, 32–33 moral dilemmas and, 566 religions and, 340–341
overview, 31–32, 36–37 moralization and, 366 selfish behavior and, 468
research findings and, 34–36 selfish behavior and, 468 vulnerability-based morality
theory and, 33–34 testing a definition of morality, and, 437
Parent–child interaction, 446 549–551 Psychological agency, 559. See also
Parenting factors theory of dyadic morality Agency
altruism in children and, 415 (TDM) and, 366–367 Psychological essentialism, 143
constructive origins of morality Physician-assisted suicide, Psychological foundations. See also
and, 24–25 320–321, 326, 327, 521 Moral psychology
decision making and, 14 Pity, 201–202 blame and, 388
historical moral change and, 273 Pluralism folk moral theories and,
moralization of the body and, harm pluralism, 215–216 323–324
285 moral beliefs and, 313 historicist view of morality and,
parental behavior, 181–183 moral foundations theory (MFT) 260
relationship regulation theory and, 213–217 intelligent design and, 353
(RRT) and, 236–237 theory of dyadic morality model of moral motives (MMM)
research evidence regarding (TDM) and, 366–367 and, 224–225
infants’ fairness concerns and, Political factors moral beliefs and, 311–312
424–425 big data analysis and, 530 moral foundations theory (MFT)
terror management theory climate change and, 540–541 and, 212, 213–214, 218
(TMT) and, 244 historical moral change and, moralization of the body and,
Perceptions. See also Self- 269, 271 283–284, 285
perceptions moral clarity and, 496 overview, 51
moral standing of animals and, moral coherence and, 378–379 terror management theory
167–168 moral psychology and, 540–541 (TMT) and, 243
preference for helpers by infants political psychology, 215 theory of dyadic morality
and, 408 Porn consumption, 340, 365, 365f (TDM) and, 366–367
research findings and, 153–154 Posterior insula, 508–509 Psychopathy, 478, 480, 512–513
social and moral decision Posterior superior temporal sulcus Punishments
making and, 11 (pSTS), 507, 507f, 509, 510 blame and, 387
social interactions and, 187–188 Posttraumatic stress disorder component process model
theory of dyadic morality (PTSD), 249, 454–455 (CPM) and, 78
(TDM) and, 364 Posture, 255–256, 293 geographies of morality and, 343
Performance anxiety, 479 Power historical moral change and, 270
Periaqueductal gray area (PAG), historical moral change and, 273 moral values and, 62
508, 509, 510 moral clarity and, 497, 498–499 relationship regulation theory
Person perception, 153–154. See Prejudice, 26, 83, 206–207. See (RRT) and, 236–237
also Perceptions also Stereotyping research evidence regarding
Person X Situation interaction, Prescriptive processes, 223–224, infants’ fairness concerns and,
479–480 224f, 234, 379, 558 426
Personal identity. See Identity Prisoner’s Dilemma game, 61, selfish behavior and, 467
Personality characteristics, 103, 154 433–435, 437 side-taking strategies and, 179
Personality disorders, 388, Property rights, 343, 345 terror management theory
512–513 Proportionality, 232, 236, 297 (TMT) and, 248
Personality psychology, 243, 253 Proscriptive regulation, 223–224, unselfish behavior and, 468
Personality traits, 478, 479–480, 224f Puppet theory
521 Prosocial acts. See also Behavior historical context of, 253
Person-centered morality (PCM), altruistic lying and, 469 overview, 252–253, 256
122–128, 129n developmental neuroscience and, research findings and, 254–256
Persuasion, 495–496 506 theory and, 253–254
584 Index

Purity. See also Component process overview, 231–233, 232t, fairness and, 393–394
model (CPM); Disgust 238–239 moral clarity and, 497–498
big data analysis and, 531 research findings and, 235–238 moral thinking and, 3
implicit moral processes and, theory and, 234–235 moral values and, 62, 65
522 Relationships. See also Intergroup Rights, 10–11, 28, 213, 269–270
moral foundations theory (MFT) relationships Rivalry, 196–197
and, 213, 216–217 constructing morality and, Rules. See also Wrongness
moral judgment and, 189–190 25–26 development of morality and, 11
moral vitalism and, 303–308 distributive fairness and, 421 folk moral theories and, 324
moralization of the body and, free will and, 336 free will and, 334
281–284 grounded approaches and, 297 geographies of morality and,
overview, 70–71, 568–569 moral character and, 102, 343, 345
research findings and, 75–77 104–105 historical moral change and,
theory and, 74–75 moral clarity and, 498 267
moralization of the body and, model of moral motives (MMM)
285 and, 228–229
R relationship regulation theory overview, 43–44
(RRT) and, 231–232, 233 relationship regulation theory
Race, 15–16, 16f, 204–205, vulnerability-based morality (RRT) and, 239
517–518 and, 437
Rational processes, 127–128, Relativism, 311, 314–315, 499
233–234 religions, 339–341, 345–347 S
Reactive attitudes, 384, 425–426 Religious traditions
Reasoning. See also Moral blame and, 384–385, 387–388 Same-sex marriage. See also
reasoning continents, comparison among, Homosexuality; Marriage
development of morality and, 345–347 implicit moral processes and,
10–11 folk moral theories and, 521
folk moral theories and, 326–328, 327t moral coherence and, 375
322–323 free will and, 333–334 moral judgment and, 568
intelligent design and, 352–353 geographies of morality and, moralization and, 366, 367
moral clarity and, 494–495, 496 339–345, 342f, 344f Schadenfreude, 193–198, 202. See
moral judgment and, 25 historical moral change and, also Outgroup pain
moral self-theory and, 150–151, 263, 267, 268 Schema, 235, 444, 455–456
153 identity and, 142–143 Schwartz Value Survey (SVS),
moral vitalism and, 304–308 intelligent design and, 352–358 531–532
nonmoral considerations and, moral clarity and, 499 Science, scope of, 326–328, 327t,
22–23 moral vitalism and, 303–308 356
overview, 6, 9–10 moralization and, 363–364 Scientific cognition, 561–562. See
parallel morality hypothesis terror management theory also Cognitive processes
and, 36 (TMT) and, 241–249 Secularia, 341–347, 342f, 344f
role of in morality, 9 testing a definition of morality, Self-control, 453–454, 477–478,
social and moral decision 550–551 480, 489–490
making and, 11–14 Representations, 293, 294–295, Self-enhancement, 105–106
social interactions and, 187, 188 296, 441–443 Self-esteem, 243–246, 249
Reciprocity Resource allocation, 283–284, Self-identity, 145. See also Identity;
altruism and, 177 285, 396, 421, 423 Moral self-theory
cooperation and, 403–404 Respect, 568–569 Selfish behavior. See also Behavior
development of sociomoral Response bias, 519–520 antecedents of, 469–470
evaluations in infants and, Response inhibition, 35–36 ethical behavior and, 467–468
403 Response patterns, 558 future directions and, 470–471
overview, 338–339, 568–569 Responsibilities, 165–172, overview, 465–466, 466t,
Reinforcement learning, 41, 42–43, 195–196, 376 471–472
65 Retrospective gambler’s fallacy, unethical behavior and,
Relationship regulation theory 357 466–467
(RRT) Rewards Selflessness, 285
historical context of, 233–234 altruism in children and, 415 Self-perceptions, 149–150,
moral foundations theory (MFT) distributive fairness and, 421, 153–154, 155–157. See also
and, 214–215 422 Perceptions
 Index 585

Self-regulation Social identification, 194 Social–moral signals, 116–117


evolved developmental niche Social identity, 25–26, 253 Social-psychological research, 384
(EDN) and, 454 Social inequalities, 27–28 Social–relational cognition, 232
free will and, 335 Social interactions, 187–190 Social–relational context, 235
functional conflict theory of Social intuitionist model (SIM) Sociomoral evaluations. See also
moral emotions and, 83 disgust and, 71, 73–74 Moral judgment
implicit moral processes and, grounded approaches and, cooperative systems and,
521 294–295 403–404
relationship regulation theory moral coherence and, 372 development of in infants,
(RRT) and, 235 moral foundations theory (MFT) 404–407
terror management theory and, 212, 213 overview, 402–403, 410
(TMT) and, 249 moral intuition and, 89–90 preference for helpers by infants
Serotonergic system, 509 moralization of the body and, and, 407–409
Sexual activity, 284 280 Somatosensory cortex, 508
Sexual behavior, 367–368, 531 Social justice Spirituality
Sexuality, 269 cultural practices and, 15–16 blame and, 384–385
Sharing, 233, 285, 286, 506, development of morality and, folk moral theories and,
512–513 10–11 326–328, 327t
Side-taking strategies. See also how people form, 31–32 grounded approaches and, 294
Moral judgment model of moral motives (MMM) identity and, 142–143
historical context of, 179–180 and, 224, 226–227 moral judgment and, 569
overview, 177–179, 183–184 moral foundations theory (MFT) moral vitalism and, 303–308
research findings and, 181–183 and, 214 terror management theory
theory and, 180–181 parallel morality hypothesis (TMT) and, 241–249
Sin, 363–364. See also Religious and, 33 Spontaneous evaluations, 384–385.
traditions; Wrongness Social learning strategy, 471 See also Moral judgment
Situational orientation, 452–453, Social network analysis (SNA), Stage model of moral reasoning,
475, 476 528, 529, 530 150–151. See also Reasoning
Situation-trait relevance, 479–480 Social neuroscience, 506. See also Statistical norms, 558. See also
Skepticism, 310–311, 317n Neuroscience Norms
Skilled expertise, 487–488, 491 Social opposition, 14–15 Stem cell research. See Embryonic
Slavery, 271–273 Social order, 224, 226–227, stem cell research
Smoking, 271, 365, 366, 367, 368 228–229 Stereotype content model (SCM)
Sociability, 205–206 Social organization, 15 intergroup aggression and,
Social biases, 232 Social perceptions, 149–150 194–195
Social class, 15–16, 16f, 204–205, Social perspectives, 103–104 overview, 203, 206–207
469–470 Social psychology research findings and, 205–206
Social cognition. See also Cognitive developmental neuroscience and, theory and, 203–205
processes 506 Stereotyping
character and, 124 grounded approaches and, 293 debates regarding, 202–203
character evaluation and, 125 moral foundations theory (MFT) intergroup relationships and, 26
moral character and, 100–102 and, 213 overview, 201–202, 206–207
moral cognition and, 108–118, moral heroes as puppets and, Stress, 454–455
109f, 111f, 113f, 114f 253 Strong view of moral identity,
moral foundations and, 189–190 unethical behavior and, 476 136–137. See also Moral
overview, 23, 108–109, 109f, Social regulation, 108–118, 109f, identity
186, 187 111f, 113f, 114f Subgenual prefrontal cortex, 509
Social cognitive theory (SCT), Social Science Research Network Supplementary motor area, 508
133–139 (SSRN), 467 Sympathy
Social cohesion, 267–268, 270–271 Social systems, 334 functional conflict theory of
Social context, 186–189, 190–191 Social–functional emotions theory, moral emotions and, 83
Social exclusion, 26 85 historical moral change and,
Social expressions, 114, 114f Social–functional evolutionary 271, 272
Social factors, 231–232, 341–345, model, 525–527 moral standing of animals and,
342f, 344f Sociality, effectance, and elicited 168–169
Social grooming, 285 agent knowledge (SEEK) vulnerability-based morality
Social hierarchies, 15–16, 16f model, 168 and, 437
Social hypothesis, 395–398 Socialization, 244–245, 414, 416 Synchronicity, 354–355
586 Index

T U moral thinking and, 4


overview, 507, 507f
Teleological bias, 352–358 Ultimatum Game, 61 Violation of expectations, 424–425
Temporoparietal junction (TPJ), Uncertainty avoidance, 498–499 Violent actions
507, 507f, 509, 510 Unconflicted virtue historical moral change and,
Terror management theory (TMT) overview, 485–486, 491 269, 273
biological roots of morality and, skills expertise and, 487–488 intergroup aggression and,
242–243 testing moral behavior, 489–490 193–198
death awareness in moral Unethical behavior. See also moral values and, 63
behavior and judgment and, Behavior relationship regulation theory
247–248 antecedents of, 469–470 (RRT) and, 233, 235–238
ethogenesis and, 453 attachment and, 479 terror management theory
future directions and, 248–249 disposition and, 477–479 (TMT) and, 249
human morality and, 246–247 equilibrium and, 475–481, 476f Virtue, 485–492, 487–488
overview, 241–242, 243–247 future directions and, 470–471 Virtue ethics, 122–125, 456
Thalamus, 509 overview, 465–466, 466t, Virtuous violence, 195–196, 235–238
Theory of dyadic morality (TDM). 471–472, 475–477, 476f Vitalistic thinking, 304. See also
See also Dyadic morality selfish behavior and, 466–467 Moral vitalism
theory (DMT) unselfish behavior and, 468–469 Vulnerability
dyadic loop and, 365–366, Unfairness, 283–284. See also free will and, 335
365f Fairness historical context of, 435
historical context of, 366–367 Unintentional moral judgment, overview, 430–431, 437
overview, 363–365, 368 519–520. See also Moral Prisoner’s Dilemma game,
research findings and, 367–368 judgment 433–435
theory and, 367 Unity, 233, 237, 297 research findings and, 436
Theory of mind (ToM), 186, 187, Universal moral grammar (UMG), theory and, 431–432, 435–437
202 234–235, 295 the trolley problem, 432–433
Trait egocentrism, 354. See also Unselfish behavior. See also
Egocentrism Behavior
Trait empathy, 478, 480 antecedents of, 469–470 W
Trait perception, 168 ethical behavior and, 468
Trait theory, 253 overview, 465–466, 466t War, 236, 341, 342f
Trauma, 249, 454–455 unethical behavior and, 468–469 Well-being, 53, 431, 453–454, 506
Triune ethics meta-theory (TEM), User-defined dictionaries (NDD), Whistle blowers, 467–468
451–452 527–528 Whole-number approach, 89–90,
Trolley problem, 432–433, 434, 91–93
437 Willpower, 477–478, 479–480
Trustworthiness V Withdrawal motivations, 75–76.
moral character and, 104 See also Motivation
person-centered morality and, Values, moral. See Moral values Women’s suffrage, 269
128n–129n Vaping, 366 Work ethics, 226
social and moral decision Vegans, 170–171 World Trade Center attack, 531
making and, 13–14 Vegetarians, 170–171, 271, 325, Worldviews, 243–246, 249
stereotype content model (SCM) 327–328 Wrongness. See also Rules
and, 205–206 Ventral striatum (VS), 60–61, 64, compared to badness, 40–44
stereotypes and, 202 65, 507 disgust and, 71, 76–77
Truth, 436–437. See also Ventromedial prefrontal cortex moral beliefs and, 313
Honesty (vmPFC) moral cognition and, 113–114
Two-dimensional model of moral empathy and, 508–509, 509, 510 norms and, 557–558, 558f
identity, 135–136. See also folk moral theories and, 321, 322 overview, 40–41, 363–364
Moral identity implicit moral processes and, 521 theory and, 41

You might also like