You are on page 1of 23

"Not Yet": Adorno and the Utopia of Conscience

Author(s): Max Blechman


Source: Cultural Critique, No. 70 (Fall, 2008), pp. 177-198
Published by: University of Minnesota Press
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/25475492 .
Accessed: 27/12/2014 07:38

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

University of Minnesota Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Cultural
Critique.

http://www.jstor.org

This content downloaded from 139.133.11.3 on Sat, 27 Dec 2014 07:38:54 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
"NOT YET"
AND THEUTOPIAOF CONSCIENCE
ADORNO

Max Blechman

Only the critical idea that unleashes the force stored up in its own object is fruitful;

fruitful both for the object, by helping it to come into its own, and against it,

reminding it that it is not yet itself.


?T. W. Adorno, Hegel: Three Studies

That the subjective conscience will "with good reason" consider objective morality

most hostile to itself?this word ofHegel's looks like a philosophical slip of the pen.

?T. W. Adorno, Negative Dialectics

So it seems necessary at this point to let Kant


burn through Hegel: the self must

remain in everything; at move


though itmay first exteriorize itself everywhere,
reverberantly through everything in order to break the world open, in order above

all to pass through a thousand doorways, but precisely the self that desires and

demands, the not yet implanted postulated world of its a priori is the system's

finest fruit and sole purpose, and therefore Kant ultimately stands above Hegel as
as
surely psyche above pneuma, Self above Pan, ethics above Encyclopedia, and

the moral nominalism of the End above the still half cosmological realism ofHegel's
world-idea.
?Ernst Bloch, The Spirit of Utopia

A flmong the various intellectual gymnastics and surgical oper


ations proposed in the critical reception of Hegel, from "turning Hegel
off his head" (Marx and EngelsfQl}) to "separating the living from the
dead" (CrocefQl}), the strategy suggested by Bloch in The Spirit of

Utopia, "to let Kant burn through Hegel," might best serve to high
light what is at stake in the project of negative dialectics. Indeed,
Adorno may be interpreted as this strategy over for himself
taking
when, in an essay from 1965, he states: "The book, Bloch's first, bear

ing all his later work within it, seemed to me to be one prolonged re
bellion against the renunciation within that extends even into
thought

Cultural Critique 70?Fall 2008?Copyright 2008 Regents of the University of Minnesota

This content downloaded from 139.133.11.3 on Sat, 27 Dec 2014 07:38:54 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
178 | MAXBLECHMAN

its purely formal character. ... I do not believe I have ever written

anything without reference to it, either implicit or explicit."1


A Blochian motif that equally structures Adorno's writings, it
acts as an ongoing reprise or, better still, as the "temporal organizing
principle"2 of his philosophical criticism. But the whole movement?
the spirit of "prolonged rebellion," the imperative re
beyond beyond
sistance to a false reconciliation in relation to which the Hegelian sys
tem is ultimately represents a retrieval of the
judged guilty?itself
fundamental in Hegel's philosophy. Dialectics is true to itself only
insofar as it does justice to the "not yet" of human reconciliation, inas
much as it keeps in view, as Hegel himself had insisted, the "tarrying
with the negative" that alone brings spirit towards "an achieved com

munity of minds."3
This core Hegelian insight, hermetically outlined in the preface
of Phenomenology, is taken up by Adorno as the "system's finest fruit
and sole purpose," to borrow Bloch's phrase. Yet this Hegelian pur
pose, even as it transforms the transcendental basis of the practical in

Kant, expresses in Bloch and Adorno a Kantian qualification of Hegel.


burn while that "Kant can
Letting Kant through Hegel acknowledging
not be done without Hegel,"4 maintaining that "the debate between
Kant and Hegel, in which Hegel's devastating argument had the last
word, is not over"5?these formulations rest on a complex exchange:

1) Against the limits set by Kant, the abstractions of formalism, and with

the experiential, the at once historical and substantial core of Hegelian

dialectics that marks the starting-point of speculation. "It is absurd to

the internal of the very it dwells in, of


prevent subject's cognition thing
the thing in which it has far too much of its own interior."6

2) Against the Hegelian closure, the mapping of the system onto

and with the transcendental Maximum, the normative


objective reality,
ideal of Kantian that unveils the disparity between the rational
practice
and the real. "The ray of that reveals the whole to be untrue in all
light
its moments is none other than the of the whole truth,
Utopia, utopia
which is still to be realized."7

The reciprocal movement carried in the motif, from Kant to Hegel and
from Hegel to Kant, moving "forward and backward at the same time"8
like the thematic articulations of Beethoven's music, reconfigures the

necessary of against the teleological assurance


standpoint speculation
of rational totality. In both Bloch and Adorno, the dialectical Kant/

This content downloaded from 139.133.11.3 on Sat, 27 Dec 2014 07:38:54 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
"NOTYET" | 179

Hegel mechanism structures a permanent melancholic dissonance from


within harmonic expectation. It is as if the triumphant optimism of
the Eroica, the dream-fulfillment of the Grand Symphony, were medi
ated by the harsh counterpoints of a Stravinsky score, written for a
shock-maimed chamber ensemble ... its convulsive dream
"sparse,
like compulsion imparting to music an inkling of negative truth."9
At stake, in short, is thinking our way through the double bind first
one hand,
formulated by Bloch in the Spirit of Utopia. On the Hegel
offers a salient critique of moral individualism and the empty protes
tations of the beautiful soul. That is, he "understands the mediated
that secures against every kind of avoidance or Don Quixote,
thought
against a false, disengaged, unreal radicalism."10 On the other, this
mediation of the real, itself transformed into an absolute, threatens
to become as the
as irrational it only purportedly over
partiality
comes. "One searches in vain in Hegel for that sensibility which alone
directs us upward and is aware of the danger, which manifests itself
in Kant . . . that there must be, beyond the mere repetition of what
is or was, a knowledge grounding the deed, or a vision of that world
that is not but which shall be, which drives us to act."11 Adorno states
matters this way: "Through his critique of Kant, Hegel achieved a

magnificent extension of the practice of critical philosophy beyond the


formal sphere; at the same time, in doing so he evaded the supreme
critical moment, the critique of totality, of something infinite and con

clusively given."12
The Kant-through-Hegel motif may be specified further: inHegel,

subjective spirit has "defected overzealously to the objective one."13

Hegel undermines his own science of the experience of consciousness

by heedlessly dismissing "as an unreconciled evil" the contesting, in


dividual experience of objective universality, and thus lends himself
"to the role of defending power from an
allegedly higher vantage
point."14 Hegel immersed himself in the material, in concrete partic
ularity, only in the last analysis to subsume it to the "self-surveying
whole," the self-returning generality of "higher truth."15 As such, the

passage from subjective to objective idealism is won at the cost of a


"tacit assent to the primacy of the general over the particular, which
constitutes not only the deception of idealism in hypostasizing con

cepts, but also its inhumanity."16 Or again, the Hegelian survey steeps
the Idea in the particular only "to reduce it to a through-station, and

This content downloaded from 139.133.11.3 on Sat, 27 Dec 2014 07:38:54 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
180 | MAXBLECHMAN

finally comes all too quickly to terms with suffering and death for the
sake of a reconciliation occurring merely in reflection."17
It is awinding pathway that Adorno opens through Kant and Hegel.
For he seeks to maintain with Hegel, and against the self-sufficient

autonomy of Kantian practical reason, a dialectically grounded cri

tique of the particular. "The false consciousness of isolated things as

being themselves alone and not moments of the whole" will inevitably
"break down with the power of the whole."18 Yet with Kantian auton

omy, and against the Hegelian


rationalization of objectification, Adorno
wishes simultaneously to maintain a space for an objectivity whose
reality would have to "measure up to the subject's criticism," that is,
a space for "the continuing irreconcilability of subject and object, which
constitutes the theme of dialectical criticism."19
Put differently, the standpoint of totality must be adopted in order
to counteract the delusion of the particular; but without a ground for
the rational independence of the particular, it becomes increasingly
difficult to point to how, in principle, a rational self-consciousness of
the social is to be differentiated from conformity to the delusions of
an irrational totality. Adorno suggests that the standpoint of genuine

totality can be achieved only negatively, as "antagonistic totality,"20


by attending dialectically to the real tensions of the social. But again,
the question remains as to how these tensions may be evaluated crit

ically if the independent, moral voice of criticism is heldto be subjec


tive vanity. Indeed, if it is granted that "morality, autonomy founded
on pure self-certainty, together with conscience, illusion,"21 is mere
then we risk having the pretense to an independence of the particular
a itself caught in the spell of existing social
dispelled only by whole
ity?that of the "insuperable inertia of facts."22

By specifying the problem in this way, we come up against the


contentious knot of the Kant-through-Hegel motif, that is, conscience,
the moral self-certainty charged by Hegel with ambiguity and self

deception. The Phenomenology's suggestion that there is no indepen


dent moral reality is not only a keystone for the self-understanding of
concrete ethical life. It is above all "the recognition that the moral can

by no means be taken for granted, that conscience does not guaran


tee right action, and that pure immersion of the self in the question of
what to do and what not to do entangle one in contradiction and futil

ity."23 InAdorno's view, the Phenomenology pulls the carpet from under

This content downloaded from 139.133.11.3 on Sat, 27 Dec 2014 07:38:54 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
"NOTYET" | 181

the Kantian autonomous subject by linking the inextinguishable ques


tion of the good life "through its own content to the production of a
true totality?to precisely what appears under the name of humanity
in the Critique of Practical Reason/'24 In other words, the primacy of the
individual/universal model, the transcendental matrix of moral imme

diacy and infinite duty, is overturned in favor of attending to the con


crete production of ethical sociality. And it is overturned in such a

way that the abstract, architectonic skeleton of humanity, emancipa


tion's idea, is temporalized
indelible into the real relations that make

up its flesh and blood.


Yet with the emphasis on the social mediation of the rational and
its historical
production?with the displacement of the factum of con
science by the world-idea?negativity, the disparity between the con
ditioned and the unconditioned, goes by the board. The concrete

experience from which Hegel drew is distorted in the dialectic that


claims to disclose the whole with the particular. Adorno's counter
attack against the Hegelian firm grasp of the whole?his specification,
in opposition to Hegel, that the whole is negative, expressive of the

ongoing irreconcilability between subject and object?coheres with


his exigency that philosophy satisfy "the postulate of determinate
which is a is to say, the morally
negation, positing."25 That necessary
negation that brings the untruth of existing totality to the light of day
that reveals the whole as not yet what it should be, itself implies a crit
ical knowledge of the whole?a knowledge that rests on an inkling of
the whole that is yet to he. It is not simply that "consummate negativ
ity, once squarely faced, delineates the mirror image of its opposite."26
Rather, the very facing up to negativity underscores the consciousness
of its opposite as the idea in light of which the untruth of the whole

appears in its saliency.


In this way, we return to the double bind that forms the
guiding
thread of our enquiry. The untruth of conscience consists in its pre

supposed removal from the real, in the moral cognition that would,
as it were, be to the objective to which it is
heterogeneous sociality
inextricably bound. Yet genuine, critical insight into the untruth of

objective sociality requires an independence of moral thought at the


heart of the real, that is, it requires some form of the inner/outer

opposition that Kant had brought to a fever pitch with the notion of
conscience. This is, however, "the utterly impossible thing, because it

This content downloaded from 139.133.11.3 on Sat, 27 Dec 2014 07:38:54 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
182 | MAXBLECHMAN

a even
presupposes standpoint removed, though by a hair's breadth,
from the scope of existence, whereas we well know that any
possible
knowledge must not only be first wrested from what is, if it shall hold

good, but is also marked, for this very reason, by the same distortion
and indigence which it seeks to escape."27
In light of this aporia, the double-edged method of the Phenome

nology?that phenomena would be allowed to appear in a pure "look

ing on," while being reflectively returned to the authentic substance


of the subject?rings false. The extraordinary assumption of this return
to self is expressed succinctly in the Hegelian equation: "the Sub
stance of the individual, the World-Spirit itself."28 Observation is to

provide the content of interpretation, following the formula that the


essential truth-content of moral thought is coextensive with the his
torical self-disclosure of the social world.
Evidently, if the Adornian

critique of Hegel's version of morality in thought is itself informed


historically, it is precisely in the form of a melancholic objection to the

possibility of holding such self-reconciling reality in view: "but how


much more difficult has it become to conform to such morality now
that it is no longer possible to convince oneself of the identity of sub

ject and object, the ultimate assumption of which still enabled Hegel to
conceal the antagonistic demands of observation and interpretation."29
Yet when we consider Adorno's
qualified retrieval of the Hegelian
model?that the morality of thought "should be at every moment both
within things and outside them"30?we are thrown back to the aporia
all over again. How are we to understand this moral consciousness,
this simultaneity of historical inscription and transcendence? How are
we to grasp a
morality of thought that lies "in a procedure that is nei
ther entrenched nor detached, neither blind nor proce
empty"31?a
dure, we may add, that is neither nor recognizably
strictly Hegelian
Kantian?

A unique site is available for examining the tensions of this paradox


ical operation. Ifwe turn back to Bloch, we may put matters this way:
"the real is posited as the Utopian, the Utopian as the real?the Ought
and the Valid have paid the greater price for the Spirit's regrettable
worldliness, itsworld-reality."32 With greater nuance, we find inAdorno
the same accusation of loss, an equal need for qualification: "the real
can be considered rational only insofar as the idea of freedom, that is,

This content downloaded from 139.133.11.3 on Sat, 27 Dec 2014 07:38:54 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
"NOTYET" | 183

human beings' genuine self-determination, shines through it."33 The


rehabilitation, in the mind's comprehension of the real, of a histori

cally heterogeneous utopia?the not yet of the rational in the real?


returns volens nolens to the originary stage of this aporetic tension.
In the Second Division of the Transcendental Logic, Kant construes
the apparent contradiction as follows: "our reason naturally raises itself
to cognitions far too elevated to admit of the possibility of an object
to them?cognitions which are
given by experience corresponding
nevertheless real, and are not mere phantoms of the brain."34 In brief,
the historically real contradicts the Utopian, yet the Utopian?the max
imum inscribed in the idea of reason?is epistemically real, and in this

precise sense, it cannot be alien to the historical and experiential realms


of individual and social existence. What
appear makes the Utopian
unreal is the coercive monopoly of dominant over appearance,
reality
which is not to be confused with the whole of the real itself. The sub
stance of Kant's "far too elevated"
cognitions is a reality that is in the
form of human potentiality. In Adorno's cryptic terms, "utopia is
blocked off by possibility, never by immediate reality; this is why it
seems abstract in the midst of extant things."35 In other words, it is the

socially deformed possibility for Utopia's realization in history, and

nothing inherent to the relation itself, that deepens the chasm between
the historical and the Utopian while endowing the latter with the tenor
of an abstraction, with a likeness to "mere phantoms of the brain."36
The question, however, is not to think within the limits placed on
the Kantian transcendental idea, as ifmorality in thought were to con
sist in ascending to the principles of the unconditioned. Rather, criti
cal theory redirects its gaze, from within extant objectivity, to the as

yet unmonopolized, it "sticks to the concrete, the undisfigured."37 It


takes its cue from a whole that is not yet, but that may be delineated,

negatively, in instances of a still incomplete presence. This implies a


double movement, the maintaining of a tension in the mind:

1) Human reason is retrieved in its that is, in its tie


speculative aspect,
to the Utopian idea of a fulfilled human "Reason as the tran
sociality.
scendental, supraindividual self contains the idea of a free coexistence
in which human themselves to form the universal sub
beings organize
ject and resolve the conflict between pure and empirical
reason in the
conscious solidarity of the whole. The whole represents the idea of true

universality, Utopia."38

This content downloaded from 139.133.11.3 on Sat, 27 Dec 2014 07:38:54 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
184 | MAXBLECHMAN

2) Simultaneously, the materialist immersion in the historically real


is emphasized, while the Hegelian confidence in a truth that would his

torically prevail is inverted. "Critical thought, which does not call a halt

before progress itself, us to take up the cause of the remnants


requires
of freedom, of tendencies toward real humanity, even seem
though they
powerless before the great historical trend."39

The duality of consciousness?as historically immanent and tran


scendent, as both caught in amaterial on the present stage
dependence
of society and tied
inalienably to the truth-content of a Utopian be

yond?is extrapolated and elucidated to form the structural tension


of critical theory's methodology. a
The result is speculative material

ism,40 a negative phenomenology that redefines


the very meaning of
the rational idea: "'A' is to be what it is not yet. Such hope is contradic

torily tied to the breaks in the form of predicative identity. Philosoph


ical tradition had a world for these breaks: 'ideas.' They are neither

X(ogtg nor an empty sound; they are negative signs."41


By redefining the idea in this way, Adorno sets morality in thought
as that which of rea
qualifies both the architectonic identity practical
son (Kant) and the self-reconciling identity of being with its notion

(Hegel). According to this materialism, the idea qua "negative sign"


expresses an implication inscribed in the empirical person, "the sous
entendu that something impossible is ascribed to him because it shows
in him."42 The Adornian redefinition of the rational idea hinges on
this negativity of the sign, on the understanding of this "showing" as
a human ascription confronted by concrete, historical contradiction.
Indeed, it is precisely in the form of nonidentity that the identity of
the idea is made palpable to thought and accessed in its truth. As it
were, likeness shows itself
unlikeness, the presence
through of the
idea's content is experienced as the pang of its absence.
negatively,
The paradox of the idea is that it is only a "given" in the form of an
index to a condition in need of being "taken," yet any positive "tak
is represented under the idea threatens permanently to
ing" of what
belie its truth-content. For the idea is the universal identity, the impos
sible content to which, as concept, it nonetheless demands to be ap

plied. the application


Thus, of the idea to empirical being signifies
ineluctably a
"lagging behind" of the concept, in that any act of appli
cation is simultaneously the indexing of a discrepancy, the unfolding
of a sign that betrays the concept as never being what it says it is.43

This content downloaded from 139.133.11.3 on Sat, 27 Dec 2014 07:38:54 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
"NOTYET" | 185

Because the concept is only a concept insofar at it is equated with what


itmeans to cover, the concept qua form expresses a confrontation with
its own meaning as content. In a word, the duality of the idea as tran
scendence and immanence is caught a priori in the experience of its

ongoing historical contradiction.


Likewise, the truth of the particular, of the individual, of the

subject-content covered under the concept, is to be "both more and less


than his general definition."44 The individual is "more" than his con

cept insofar as the concept as form (the Utopian universal) feigns to


cover an achieved content?a state of affairs that the individual can
as his own "not yet." The
experience only negatively, "lagging behind"
of the concept is the deformity of the idea in its merely operational
as A=A. In other words, the operational concept lags behind
application
in relation to the concept known experientially by the individual in
the form of a lack, of a "not yet." And the "more" of the individual in
relation to the operational concept is the "more" of this lack, the "more"
of the 'A is to he what it is not yet?the "more" of the idea inscribed in
the individual as his own negativity
Which is another way of saying that the individual is "less" than his

general definition, "less" than his idea, inasmuch as the truth-content


of the idea itself points to a "lagging behind" of the individual in rela
tion to himself, inasmuch as it underscores his own damaged condi
tion. The "less" of the individual is his discrepancy as particular-subject
in relation to his idea-form?or, better still, his discrepancy in relation
to himself as
materially bound to the universal of the idea-form. From
the standpoint of Adorno's speculative materialism, the individual, the

particular, the definite, is inextricable from his idea; his "less" than

himself in comparison with the free humanity, the humanitas his idea

implies is also the "less" of the operational concept (the application of


A=A) in relation to what it itself means in the
impossibility of its iden

tity (the negativity inscribed in A=A). Indeed, the individual consid


ered according to his species-being, as being in contradiction with his
own meaning, would only be himself?would only not be "less" than
himself?"by voiding that contradiction?in other words, by achiev

ing an identity of the particular [his individuality as content] with its


as form]."45 It is the experiential
concept [his universality longing for
this "voiding" that characterizes the torn individual, in his negative

identity, as the unresolved of the idea.


exemplifying identity

This content downloaded from 139.133.11.3 on Sat, 27 Dec 2014 07:38:54 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
186 | MAXBLECHMAN

As such, morality in thought?the self-consciousness of the ascrip


tion of the idea?maintains a tension in two essential respects. On the
one hand, itmust affirm its own negativity against the hypostasis of
the concept that would feign a positive identity, that is, that would
pass as the achieved mediation of form and content. In this respect,
the "more" of the individual is the "more" in relation to the "less" of
this operation of mediation, it signifies the necessary protest against
an application of the concept that would knock down the Utopian "not

yet" to the identitarian realism of "what is." It is the imperative dif


ference in identity, the "not yet" coextensive with moral being, that

pushes Adorno to stress that the individual must "hold on to that of


which the general concept robs him."46 But this "holding on" signifies
also a struggle against the formalization of the concept, against the
reification of the material reality?and the historical possibility?con
tained in the idea.
in thought is the expressive pang of this negatively ex
Morality
"more." this means that the melan
perienced Phenomenologically,
cholic experience of the "less" puts the emphasis on the "more" that
the individual is in the form of not yet being it?i.e., on the pledge of
an identity itself prefigured as potential. As such, if the individual
must be wary of trivializing the concept in the self-preservation struc
tures of extant existence?if he must be "concerned with that 'more'
of the concept compared with his need"47?the potential in the idea
calls simultaneously "for criticizing what an inevitable formalization
has made of the potential."48 The tension implicit in the individual's
moral self-understanding expresses the as yet unfulfilled promise of
the real. If the "more" and "less" of morality in thought is the nega
tive condition of the individual's self-knowledge as idea, the idea is
not for all that a pure aperception pointing abstractly to a condition
all experience. Knowledge of the idea is knowledge experi
beyond
enced by the individual as his essential historical destiny. Only, by
contrast to the priority of realism in Hegelian identity-thinking?in
the last instance, the "brutality of coercion that creates the semblance
of reconciliation"49?this knowledge highlights the quintessence of
what is in the form of an ongoing severance.
This severance is not, Adorno emphatically contends, to be un
derstood as primarily ontological. To the contrary, the inner tension
of consciousness has its material grounds; it is at bottom historical,

This content downloaded from 139.133.11.3 on Sat, 27 Dec 2014 07:38:54 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
"NOTYET" | 187

coterminous with
the hegemonic domination of bourgeois civilization.
The point of morality in thought is not to take "its directive, beyond
the real states of affairs, from the highly formal sense of belonging to
oneself."50 chasm in the idea of the individual,
The the alienation of
the happiness and dignity of the species to which the individual be

longs, expresses the powerlessness and nothingness of a social condi


tion to which he equally belongs and not, as itwere, the condition of
his "substance" per se. A certain existentialism, and a certain emphasis
on the existential in Hegel, is antipodal to the speculative material
ism?the negativity of the historical human being qua humanity?that
underscores Adorno's critical conception of morality. The realization
of the nothingness of the human being in present society is trans

posed conveniently by the existential thinker to the pure essence of


the individual, indirectly affirming and eternalizing the very condi
tion that stands in need of critique. The reification of human sociality
is in this way reworked into the sublimity of human nothingness at
the same time that the guiding idea of revolutionary humanism from
Kant toMarx?namely, man's species-being?is plundered in the name
of finitude and authenticity. The individual caught in the conditions
of the present stage of society, Adorno laments, is being robbed of

"precisely those traits which have, as their content, the criticism of


those states of affairs."51 In a striking passage of The Jargon of Authen

ticity that reveals at once the historical debt and the parti pris of his
own moral thinking, Adorno states:

This criticism has been immanent in all as well as in


enlightenment,
early German idealism. The [existential] goes hand in hand with
jargon
a of Man from which all memory of natural law has been erad
concept
icated. ... As it runs in the and death are to be
jargon: suffering, evil,

accepted, not to be The is trained in this tour de


changed. public being
force.... are to understand their nothingness as to
They learning Being,
revere actual, avoidable, or at least need as the most humane
corrigible
element in the of Man. are to respect in
image They learning authority
itself because of their innate human
insufficiency.52

The critical edge of this accusation holds good before Wittgen


stein's maxim "Whereof one cannot speak, thereof one must be silent."53
For at the heart of Adorno's
unequivocal defense of natural law is
a vital human a
goal and Utopian priori which, while it resists clear
and distinct representation, nonetheless coheres in reflection with the

This content downloaded from 139.133.11.3 on Sat, 27 Dec 2014 07:38:54 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
188 | MAXBLECHMAN

material origin integral to critical reason. Here again, the contradiction


is to be understood in relation to the historical present: it expresses
what is "objectively, not just epistemically, unresolved."54 Critical rea
son has as its an end, an fulfillment that
starting-point imperative
contradicts the present reification of consciousness; thus, compliance
with the rules of the game of extant consciousness would be tanta
mount to reason's own negation. Indeed, "to lay contradictions to

incorrigible speculative obstinacy would be to shift the blame."55 The

significance of maintaining in reflection the contradiction coextensive


with speculative materialism is reason's refusal, as the polemos of moral

ity, to be talked out of the cornerstone of its dignity and hope.


Which brings us back to the Utopian truth-content of morality in

thought, its heterogeneity to the identity thinking that seeks to dis


close the particular with the universal. The resistance of morality in

thought to the established state of affairs is the consciousness of the


universal as being universal in the modality of not being the univer
sal it ought to be. Yet this resistance, as the expression of the damaged
is the consciousness of the universal as its own damaged
particular,
identity. In other words, what this understanding of the damaged iden

tity of identity and difference underscores is that the extant identity


of identity and difference is not what it should be. 'A' doesn't equal
'A' in the very precise sense that 'A' is aware that in its identity to 'A'
it is not really itself. In A=A, particular 'A' recognizes itself in uni
versal 'A' as "less" than itself?the equation fails to do justice to the
truth-content of its "more." But because, in another sense, 'A' does

equal 'A'?because the particular is inextricably bound to the whole


of which it is a part?universal 'A' itself is not itself, is itself "less" than
itself radically belying
itself, its universality. On this score, Adorno's

sharp verdict
on Hegel could hardly be more lucid:

He lacks with the Utopian that has been buried


sympathy particular
underneath the universal?with that nonidentity which would not come

into being until realized reason has left the reason of the uni
particular
versal behind. The sense of the wrong by the concept of the uni
implied
versal, a sense which chides, would deserve his respect because
Hegel
of the universality of wrong itself.56

The terms of the particular/universal relation are thereby reversed.


It is not the extant universal, but the Utopian particular that carries

This content downloaded from 139.133.11.3 on Sat, 27 Dec 2014 07:38:54 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
"NOT YET" 189
|

the rational universal. Inversely, the "universal" that feigns to pass as


universal is itself merely particular, which as universal wrong consti
tutes the real object of realized reason's negation. By this reconstruc
tion of the particular/universal relation according to the truth-content
of the "not yet," morality in thought retrieves the critical moment of

Hegelian dialectics?the Utopian substance of the "lingering with the


Adorno's is none other than Bloch's
negative." "utopian particular"
of the conscience"57?in instance, the con
"deepest Utopian part every
sciousness that the purported identity of the universal is "perpetuat

ing nonidentity in suppressed and damaged form.""s

An unresolved are we to understand


question lingers: how conscience
in its link with the "utopian"?what in the last instance is the signifi
cance of this qualifier? I have suggested that for Adorno this self

transcending disposition of human intelligence advances knowledge

only by way of a negative phenomenology, that the material content


of this knowledge is itself negative. Rather than constituting a fully
determined representation of the right, the unhappy consciousness of
conscience is the alarm that signals a wrong. This capacity of the mind
is shrugged off as a form of deluded subjectivism only by neglecting
the material mainspring of moral criticism:

Conscious unhappiness is not a delusion of the mind's vanity but some

thing inherent in the mind, the one authentic dignity it has received in its

separation from the body. This dignity is the mind's negative reminder
of its physical aspect; its capability of that aspect in the only source of
whatever the mind can have.^
hope

The unhappy consciousness of conscience highlights an "authentic

dignity" of the mind's separation from the body in that it is responding


to?and instigating?something beyond individual self-preservation
and need. Yet the alarm of conscience is itself deeply physical, and it
articulates an urge that is no less human and embodied. It is as if a

specific somatic sensitivity of the mind, an upsurge of moral pain,


were in thought as a conscious con
reproduced object of reflection,
an advancement of a
stituting knowledge by way of quasi-corporal
refusal of untruth. In this way, the unhappy consciousness, as the con
sciousness of a universal that is not one, is also the conscious unhap
piness of the universal, its inner principle of unrest. The unassuaged

This content downloaded from 139.133.11.3 on Sat, 27 Dec 2014 07:38:54 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
190 | MAXBLECHMAN

consciousness of conscience is the universal in the form of negativity:


the break in the universal it unveils advances the universal by remind

ing it that it is not yet itself. Which is another way of saying that the

heterogeneous moment of conscience prefigures the universal, brings


the universal to itself negatively, by pointing out that the universal's

identity is reproducing itself as coercive mythology. Conscience in


dexes the universal in the form of the imperative that the unhappiness
incurred by extant "universality" should be undone:

The smallest trace of senseless in the world belies all


suffering empirical
the identitarian philosophy that would talk us out of that suffering: "while

there is a beggar, there is a myth," as


Benjamin put it. This is why the

philosophy of identity is themythological form of thought. The physical


moment tells our that not to be, that things
knowledge suffering ought
should be different. "Woe speaks: 'Go.'" Hence the convergence of spe

cific materialism with criticism, with social change in practice.60

Conscience is therefore not limited to a moral


self-certainty that
would preclude the need of critical reflection. To the contrary, the "spe
cific materialism" implied by conscience is also that which highlights
the need for such reflection. Conscience is the consciousness that the

damage is incurring
the universal is inextricable from the damage it
is itself suffering. The more the objective universal monopolizes the
means for maintaining the myth of its identity, the less moral insight
has any lease on a space that would, as itwere, allow it to manifest its

ingenium independently. As such, conscientious criticism?the "con

vergence of materialism with criticism"?is immanently aware


specific
that "whatever an individual or a group may undertake against the
totality they are part of is infected by the evil of that totality."61 In
other words, the objective conditions of human sociality?according
to Adorno, the real secularization of original sin inmodernity?neces
sitates conscience's reflection on its own grounds lest it reveal itself
as irrational as the "rationality" it is contesting. The very dynamic to
which conscience responds, as well as the conditions for its effective
bar "any single moral decision from being warranted as
possibility,
the right one"62 at the same time that they necessitate recourse to ratio
nal exposition and "the most advanced state of theory."63
Yet formulating matters in this way remains unsatisfying. "Ad
vanced theory" is no more capable of securing itself from the whole of
instituted irrationality than is rational exposition safe from the dealings

This content downloaded from 139.133.11.3 on Sat, 27 Dec 2014 07:38:54 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
"NOTYET" | 191

of rationalized heteronomy At bottom, "without recourse to the mate

rial, no 'ought' could issue from reason."64 This means that at the heart
of the genuinely rational, at the core of morality in thought, there is a
material urge?an experience of an "ought" that breaks out from the
limits of dominant sociality. It is precisely this experience that marks
the starting-point of any genuine critical theory. The "recourse to the
material" Adorno is here emphasizing is incomprehensible simply
in the terms of extant forms of sociality or their latest forms of self

understanding?indeed, such a simplification would render unintel

ligible the ground of possibility for their contradiction. Rather, the


"material" in question is that of the human being as such, that which
constitutes the individual in his humanity, and that of a conscious un
in a state of affairs experienced as dehumanizing. If the "objec
happiness
tivity of conscience vis-a-vis mankind is drawn from the objectivity
of society,"65 it remains that conscience is, in its very dynamic, already
itself as a product of society. Such is the voice of con
transcending
science, the contradiction of the utopian idea: it calls upon thought
"to rise above the individuality that exists as well as above the soci

ety that exists."66 At the end of the day, it is not only as consciousness
of wrong but also as presentiment of a sociality that is not yet and

ought to he, that conscience establishes itself as "the mark of shame of


an unfree society."67 Ripening in conscience "is a potential that would
rid men of coercion"; it is the task of critique to retrieve this potential
"in the objectivity of a reconciled life of the free."68

I am arguing that Adorno's negative dialectics structures a material


ism rooted in the historical negativity of conscience, just as the antin
omies of Kant's philosophy turn on the pivot of practical reason, and
are "resolved" only by a moral-mindedness construed as irreducible.
And I hope to have made it clear that this resumption of Kant?this

solidarity with"metaphysics at the time of its fall"69?ultimately quali


fies Kant as much as it does Hegel. To "let Kant burn
through Hegel"
is to rethink conscience as the consciousness of my own
nonidentity
From this perspective, Kant's unknowable object of rep
metaphysics
resents the alterity of practical reason, the consciousness of reason's

dependence on that which "cannot be wholly translated into its the


oretical determinants without remainder."70 At stake is a reinterpre
tation of freedom in the midst of nature, according towhich the somatic

This content downloaded from 139.133.11.3 on Sat, 27 Dec 2014 07:38:54 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
192 | MAXBLECHMAN

aspect of the mind acts as a self-transcending and self-transforming


interlocutor. Indeed, the "projecting element" of conscientious reflec
tion,this "little piece of our nature that is not nature,"71 is precisely
what makes self-consciousness?that is, the consciousness of my own

alterity?a power that can resist the administered consciousness of


reified, bourgeois society.
The point, therefore, is obviously not to return to the Kantian
moral law as to an ontological ground of rational identity, nor for that
matter to make the practice of deliberative reason the substance of

morality. Rather, Adorno wants to highlight the inexpungible grounds


of subjective freedom, the inexpugnability of a human negativity that
tends towards self-transformation and resistance. This is to say that
awareness of the factum of conscience?however much itmay be medi
ated socially, and not withstanding its having to be justified ratio
nally?represents a rupture of the moral mind, a capacity "to confront

prevailing norms with our own consciousness and to measure each

against the other."72 Whence Adorno's effort to underscore the pre


science of Kant's that "man's nature itself contains some
postulation
thing like a promise that this is not all, that there must be something
further"?or, for that matter, his otherwise startling contention that
"the ontological proof of the existence of God, which Kant himself

subjected to withering criticism, continues to live on."73


For there is no the alternative sequence of trailblazers
overlooking
on the pathway of the "melancholy science." At his most empirical,
Adorno is rescuing that which Kant posits as the
simultaneously
inherent human disposition towards metaphysics (metaphysica natu
ralis),74 that is, a human need strictly analogous to Ernst Bloch's "other
. . . the continual Not-Yet of human possession."75 The onto
hunger
"lives on" in the most sense defined
logical proof, then, elementary
in the innate movement of form inmatter, in the "intrin
by Aristotle:
sic activation" that drives body and mind towards the ethical sub

stance, the perpetually open possibilities of the real.76 And it "lives


on" in the face of an entelechial process that "is tending to become

paler and more desultory," to the point that today it "survives only
It is as if this process were simultaneously caught in the
negatively."77
progressive detachment of form from life?in the estrangement of
form in a power that acts over and against life?only to instill thereby
a negative awareness of its original ends, as well as the resistance that

This content downloaded from 139.133.11.3 on Sat, 27 Dec 2014 07:38:54 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
"NOTYET" | 193

would uphold them. Indeed, if, for Adorno, "the concept of metaphys
ics has been transformed to its innermost core,"78 is it not because today
"the possibility of metaphysical experience is akin to the possibility
of freedom . .
. one that has torn the bonds advertised as salutary"?79
As seen, Adorno does not hesitate to speak of natural law when
he thinks the perseverance of amorality that undermines its own pet
rifaction. m In a the of materialism so as to include
sense, restructuring
metaphysica naturalis already opens this door. Once spiritual need is
recognized
as material need?once moral aversion to injustice is seen
as an extension of the natural aversion to physical pain?the whole
of collective self-transformation is placed on the axis of a
"ought"
self-constituting dignity in human nature, as ifwithout this grounding,
there could be no to be had or to be measured. Awareness of
morality
the factum of conscience?"the awareness that the sphere of right action
does not coincide with mere rationality, that it has an 'addendum'"?
thus underscores a reason that contains within itself the in
practical
of an unyielding, rebellious nature.81
telligence
Clearly, Bloch encouraged Adorno to think the "specific materi
alism" of his morality under the sign of natural law and to revalue
as a of modern
"utopian-conscience-and-knowledge" mainspring
resistance.82Far from indexing extant institutions and ideology, Bloch

staged natural law?in a reinterpretation of the Cynics, the Stoics, and


of Rousseauism?as dissidence in the face of "the idolization of exter
nal correlates."83 For Bloch,
the givenness of natural law is essentially
dialectical. As itwere,
the negativity of natural law permanently tran
scends the positivity of its social codification, sparking an inexhaust
ible responsibility, that of "passing beyond givenness, in the belief that

present existents must be pushed aside in order to liberate and open


the way to a better status."84 Thus, the pain conscience suffers in fact

expresses the material origin of immanent critique: it is at the heart of


the utopian ideals that have informed modern revolutions and institu
tions, and it signals the ongoing capacity to resist historical departures
from what was intended by them.85 In a word, "utopian-conscience
and-knowledge" burns through its own objectifications in view of

rescuing their truth-content.


It is this nonidentity that compels Adorno to tarry with the par
ticular that resists the social norms that have grown extraneous to
it. At stake is pointing?beyond the purported preservation and

This content downloaded from 139.133.11.3 on Sat, 27 Dec 2014 07:38:54 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
194 | MAXBLECHMAN

transcendence of morality inmodern Sittlichkeit?to the imperiled ori

gin of dialectical thinking, to the "utopian thinking, the thinking that


conceives the difference from what exists."86 To take Utopian conscience
as a key to Adorno's dialectics is to take this "difference from what
exists" as the substance that drives his dialectics' negative qualifier.
The dialectic of the universal and the particular is brought over to the
concrete particular for the precise reason that it is here, at the micro

logical level of moral-mindedness, that Adorno finds the Utopian neg


ativity that had always guided his critical theory.

Notes

1. Theodor W. Adorno, "The Handle, the Pot, and Experience," in


Early
Notes to Literature II, trans. S. W. Nicholsen (New York: Columbia Press,
University
1992), 211-12. The importance of Ernst Bloch's for Adorno has received
thought
very little attention in English criticism. We may note, however, Susan Buck

Morss's terse assessment: the of the particular as a


"reading nonidentity promise
of Utopia was an idea that Adorno took from Ernst Bloch." See her The Origin of
Dialectics: Theodor W. Adorno, Walter Benjamin, and the Frankfurt Institute
Negative
(New York: The Free Press, 1977), 76. See also the 1964 discussion between Bloch
and Adorno: IsMissing: On the Contradictions of Utopian Longing/'
"Something
in Ernst Bloch, The Utopian Function of Art and Literature: Selected Essays, trans. Jack

and Frank Mecklenburg Mass.: Massachusetts Institute of Tech


Zipes (Cambridge,
1988). 117. For an overview of the Bloch/Adorno see the spe
nology, relationship,
cial issue of Europe devoted to the subject (Europe 86, no. 949 [May 2008]: 3-253).
2. Theodor W. Adorno, Hegel: Three Studies, trans. S. W. Nicholsen (Cam
Mass.: Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press, 1993), 136.
bridge,
3. G. W. F. Hegel, trans. A. V. Miller (Oxford:
Phenomenology of Spirit,
Oxford University Press, 1977), 19, 43.
4. Ernst Bloch, The Spirit trans. A. Nassar (Stanford: Stanford Uni
of Utopia,

versity Press, 2000), 185.

5. Adorno, Hegel, 86.

6. Theodor W. Adorno, Dialectics, trans. E. B. Ashton (New York:


Negative
Continuum, 1973), 314.

7. Adorno, Hegel, 88.

8. Ibid., 136.
9. Theodor W. Adorno, Minima Moralia, trans. E. Jephcott (London: Verso,

1978), 50.

10. Bloch, Spirit of Utopia, 186.

11. Ibid., 184. It is in this precise that we may describe Bloch as a


respect
Kant" (Paul Ricceur, "La Liber te Selon in Le Conflit
"post-Hegelian l'Esperance,"
des Interpretations: Essais d'Hermeneutique [Paris: Seuil, 1969]), or, more precisely,
as

This content downloaded from 139.133.11.3 on Sat, 27 Dec 2014 07:38:54 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
"NOTYET" | 195

aMarxist (J.Habermas and Ernst Bloch, "Ein Marxistischer Schelling?"


Schelling

Philosophisch-Politische Profile, I [Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1973]). In other words, the


"return to Kant" that is here operative is of an order other the political,
than moral,
and epistemological characteristic of liberal neo-Kantianism. At issue,
agnosticism
as Bloch writes in his 1963 postface to The Spirit of Utopia (279), is a "new, utopian
kind of philosophy"?a of gnosis." "Letting Kant
reawakening "revolutionary
burn therefore a two-way movement: the limits
through Hegel" signals breaking
set on reason in favor of Hegel's
by Kant theoretical historical, speculative reason,
but in terms of the and
rendering speculative knowledge living demanding
of conscience and practical reason.
knowledge
12. Adorno, 86.
Hegel,
13. Adorno, Negative Dialectics, 307.

14. Ibid., 307-8.

15. Hegel, 33.


Phenomenology,
16. Adorno, Minima Moralia, 74.

17. Ibid.

18. Ibid., 246.

19. Ibid. The parallel with Bloch is striking. As Pierre Bouretz puts it, "To
answer the question of human the of the world; to displace
meaning by reality
conscience's thirst for the infinite by the rationality of to assuage
things; finally,
the dissatisfaction of the moral subject in the experience of evil by means of a con

of history: these are the elements of the Hegelian attitude


ciliatory contemplation
that motivate Bloch to turn back on his tracks and to find in Kant more authentic

figures of the human spirit." See his Temoins du Futur: Philosophic et Messianisme

(Paris: Gallimard, 2003), 5S5.


20. Adorno, Hegel, 78.
21. Adorno, Minima Moralia, 245.
22. Ibid., 247. The critique of the untruth of the whole demands the critical

independence of the particular, but if the particular is necessarily mediated by the


whole of which it is a part, it becomes difficult to see how its critique of the whole's

partiality would not be likewise infected. The is internal to immanent


problem
as Adorno admits in his essay, "Cultural Criticism and in Theo
critique, Society,"
dor W. Adorno, Prisms, trans. S. and S. Weber Mass.: Massachusetts
(Cambridge,
Institute of Technology, 1981).
23. Adorno, 48.
Hegel,
24. Ibid.

25. Ibid., 88.

26. Adorno, Minima Moralia, 247.


27. Ibid.
28. The Phenomenology 17.
Hegel, of Spirit,
29. Adorno, Minima Moralia, 74. For Adorno, the "beautiful soul" standpoint
is at once necessary to moral (Kant's metaphysical dualism) and morally
thought
impossible (Hegel's empirical monism), and self-consciousness of this contradic
tion is precisely what defines the modern moralist's melancholia as both
judge

This content downloaded from 139.133.11.3 on Sat, 27 Dec 2014 07:38:54 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
196 MAXBLECHMAN
|

and member of society. The science of the good life is a science, then,
melancholy
because "wrong life cannot be lived (Minima Moralia, s. 18)?or in Bloch's
rightly"
terms, because after what is false has fallen away can what is genuine live"
"only
(Spirit of Utopia, 238). Indeed, the extant social that conditions moral
ontology
as melancholic contradiction to why moral is
thought points directly philosophy
possible only from the of Which leaves untouched the
standpoint redemption.
question: how is such is, what are the conditions of pos
philosophy possible?that

sibility for this standpoint?


30. Adorno, Minima Moralia, 74.

31. Ibid.

32. Bloch, Spirit ofUtopia, 185.


33. Adorno, 44.
Hegel,
34. I. Kant, trans. J.M.
Critique of Pure Reason, D. Meiklejohn (Buffalo: Pro

metheus Books, 1990), 198.

35. Adorno, Negative Dialectics, 57.

36. Adorno insists that the Kantian block on the refers to histor
intelligible
ical as opposed to
ontological conditions. The severance of experience into nou

menal and phenomenal realms reflects the emerging that make


exchange-relations
human increasingly undefined, abstract, and ethereal, while
species-being forcing
the of nature to recede into mere appearance. Kant in
living reality Thinking
materialist terms thus means how the supposed chasm between reason
showing
and nature is coextensive with the historical alienation of human from
beings
each other and from the world. But this also means showing how the Kantian

chasm was meant to preserve in pure the realm of genuine self


possibility?in
determination and freedom?the of an authentic human In
promise universality.
this sense, the transcendent object of the block?the practical content of the tran

scendental to "the overall social rationality in which the utopia of


subject?points
a is already See Theodor W. Adorno, Kant's
rationally organized society implicit."
trans.
Critique of Pure Reason, Rodney Livingstone (Stanford: Stanford University
Press, 2001), 172-73.

37. Ibid.

38. Theodor W. Adorno and Max Horkheimer, Dialectic trans.


of Enlightenment,
E. Jephcott (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2002), 65.
39. Ibid., xi (translation modified).
40. I am borrowing the term "speculative materialism" from Hans-Heinz

Holz [Darmstadt-Neuwied: Luctherhand, 1975], cited in Arno


(Logos Spermatikos
Miinster, Ernst Bloch: Messianisme et [Paris: Presses Universitaires de France,
Utopie
1989], 244). I believe it also Adorno's attempt to transform his
usefully captures
torical materialism into critical theory: that is, to take the Utopian truth-content

of speculative idealism as immanent to materialist method. As such, speculative

materialism a radical of in light of


implies reinterpretation subjective cognition
the mind's or what Adorno calls its "immanent somatic side" (see the
physicality,
to Materialism, Materialism and Immediacy, and Suffering Phys
chapters Passage
In Arno Miinster of Bloch
ical in Negative Dialectics). this respect, what says equally

This content downloaded from 139.133.11.3 on Sat, 27 Dec 2014 07:38:54 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
"NOT YET" 197
|

to Adorno: contrast to Lenin who states that matter and real


applies "By objective

ity exist of human consciousness, Bloch suggests that being and


independently
consciousness are but two of matter." Or more "Man
aspects (products) poetically:
is created from matter, he is its child: in him matter opens its eyes and is reflected"

(Ernst Bloch, Messianisme et Utopie, 249). We may note that this led both Bloch and

Adorno to Schelling's conception of the urge: "And thus, from the bottom stage
on, we see nature follow its inmost, most hidden desire to keep rising and advanc
in its urge, until at last it has attracted the highest essentiality, the pure spiri
ing
tuality itself, and has made it its own" (F.W. Schelling, Die Waltalter, ed. M. Schroter

(Munich: Biederstein, 1946), 136, cited in Adorno, Negative Dialectics, 202).


41. Adorno, Negative Dialectics, 150 (emphasis mine).
42. Ibid., 150-51.

43. Ibid., 151.

44. Ibid.

45. Ibid.

46. Ibid.

47. Ibid.

48. Ibid.
49. Adorno, 20.
Hegel,
50. Theodor W. Adorno, The Jargon of Authenticity, trans. K. Tarnowsky and
F. Will (Evanston, 111.:Northwestern University Press, 1973), 115.
51. Ibid., 65.

52. Ibid., 65-66.

53. Wittgenstein, Tractatus cited in Adorno,


Ludwig Logico-Philosophicus,

Hegel, 101.
54. Adorno, Negative Dialectics, 153.
55. Ibid.

56. Ibid., 318. The conflict thus involves a fundamental of world


opposition
views: for Adorno, to "let Kant burn is to claim against Hegel that
through Hegel"
"evil rules in this world, that this world is the realm of evil." (See T. W. Adorno,
Problems ofMoral Philosophy, trans. R. Livingstone [Stanford: Stanford University
Press, 2001], 149.) In other words, Kantian Moralitat is ultimately more truthful
than Hegelian Sittlichkeit because the modern world is such that norma
precisely
tive must be to individual resistance before circumstances
primacy given given
and existing social institutions.
57. Bloch, The Spirit of Utopia, 186.
58. Adorno, Dialectics, 318.
Negative
59. Ibid., 203.

60. Ibid.

61. Ibid., 243.

62. Ibid.
63. Ibid., 242.
64. Ibid., 243.

65. Ibid., 282.

This content downloaded from 139.133.11.3 on Sat, 27 Dec 2014 07:38:54 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
198 | MAXBLECHMAN

66. Ibid., 283.

67. Ibid., 275.

68. Ibid.
69. Ibid., 408.

70. Problems 9.
Adorno, ofMoral Philosophy,
71. Ibid., 103.
72. Ibid., 123.

73. Ibid., 151. See also Adorno, Negative Dialectics, 385, where Kant's critique
of the ontological is shown to have the "must" of human self-transcendence
proof
as its in the same as Beethoven's Kantian to Joy.
guiding principle, spirit Hymn
74. Kant, "The Universal Problem of Pure Reason," Critique of Pure Reason,
12.

75. Ernst Bloch, Atheism inChristianity: The Religion of theExodus and theKing
dom, trans. J. T. Swann (New York: Herder & Herder, 1972), 264.

76. Aristotle, The Metaphysics, trans. H. Lawson-Tancred (London: Penguin,


1998), Lambda 7: 374.
77. Theodor W. Adorno, Metaphysics: Concept and Problems, trans. E. Jephcott

(Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2001), 143.

78. Ibid., 110.

79. Adorno, Negative Dialectics, 396-97.

80. In addition to the passage in The cited above, see


Jargon of Authenticity
Negative Dialectics, 310: "it is the idea of natural law which critically maintains the
untruth of positive law." Adorno's statement recalls the critical consciousness

behind the English, American, and French traditions of dissent, in which natural

law and conscience, situated Locke to the periphery of a based on


by society
became the banner under which social orders were criticized and trans
property,
formed. For a account of how a new awareness and of con
penetrating language
science informed modern criticism, see
early revolutionary Staughton Lynd,
York:
Intellectual Origins of American Radicalism (New Vintage, 1968).
81. Adorno, Dialectics, 310.
Negative
trans. D. Schmidt
82. Ernst Bloch, A Philosophy of the Future, (Cambridge,
Mass.: Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press, 1981), 91.

83. Ernst Bloch, Natural Law and Human trans. D. Schmidt (Cam
Dignity,
Mass.: Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press, 1986), 192.
bridge,
84. Ibid., 206.

85. Bloch, A Philosophy, 91.


86. Adorno, Dialectics, 313.
Negative

This content downloaded from 139.133.11.3 on Sat, 27 Dec 2014 07:38:54 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

You might also like