You are on page 1of 11

Safety Science 76 (2015) 90–100

Contents lists available at ScienceDirect

Safety Science
journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/ssci

Review

ALARP and CBA all in the same game


B.J.M. Ale a,⇑, D.N.D. Hartford b, D. Slater c
a
Technical University Delft, PO Box 5015, 2600 GA Delft, The Netherlands
b
BC Hydro, Vancouver, Canada
c
University of Cardiff, United Kingdom

a r t i c l e i n f o a b s t r a c t

Article history: The concept of reducing risk As Low As Reasonably Practicable (ALARP) as presented by the UK Health
Received 7 October 2014 and Safety Executive for the purpose of discharging its decision-taking responsibilities and the principle
Received in revised form 1 February 2015 of balancing cost and benefits through monetary Cost Benefit Analysis (CBA) which is used more widely
Accepted 20 February 2015
in health and safety decision-making seem to occupy the extremes of the decision making spectrum.
ALARP seems on the qualitative, holistic, principles based side whereas CBA seems on the quantitative,
limited, precisely defined side. These characteristics expose both principles to criticism. Application of
Keywords:
the ALARP concept may to lead to different decisions in similar contexts resulting in uncertainty and
As Low As Reasonably Practicable
Quantified risk analysis
unpredictability in decision making. CBA leads to decisions in which only money counts and all that can-
Cost Benefit Analysis not be expressed in money or is perceived of no monetary value is neglected. In this paper this issue is
Decision making explored in more depth, and it is concluded that they are part of the general decision making process.
The nature of the relevant safety laws and how they are applied frame the application of these concepts.
If the level of acceptable risk is not explicitly set by law, the risk level resulting from compliance to the
regulations is just as accidental as the Value of a Statistical Life (VOSL) found from ex post evaluations of
decisions. ALARP, QRA and CBA are part of the grander scheme of making decisions. Throughout, the focus
is on the principle rather than the practices of ALARP and CBA in reducing risk.
Ó 2015 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.

Contents

1. Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 90
2. ALARP and SFAIRP . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 91
3. Reasonability . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 92
4. Cost Benefit Analysis . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 92
4.1. The value of life. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 93
4.2. Cost . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 93
4.3. Safety budget. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 94
4.4. Distribution of cost and benefits . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 94
4.5. Societal risk . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 94
4.6. Values used . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 95
4.7. CBA in decision making . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 95
5. Multi criteria analysis . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 95
6. Optimisation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 96
7. Dams and the question ‘‘How safe is safe enough?’’ – A brief overview . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 96
8. Fusing the extremes . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 97
9. The bottom line . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 98
10. Conclusion . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 98

⇑ Corresponding author.
E-mail address: ben.ale@xs4all.nl (B.J.M. Ale).

http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.ssci.2015.02.012
0925-7535/Ó 2015 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.
B.J.M. Ale et al. / Safety Science 76 (2015) 90–100 91

Acknowledgement . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 99
References . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 99

1. Introduction The underpinnings of the term ALARP originates in the UK and


actually predates the term ALAP. The Health and Safety act in the
The principle of As Low As Reasonably Practicable (ALARP) and UK specifies as duty that the risk should be reduced As Far As Is
the principle of balancing cost and benefits through monetary Cost Reasonably Practicable (SFAIRP). The term ALARP appears to have
Benefit Analysis (CBA) have been increasingly used by a diverse emerged between the late 1960s and the late 1980s in relation to
range of industries that cover the spectrum of industrial and public how the UK Health and Safety Executive dealt with how it controls
safety applications ranging from dams and levees, hazardous pro- risk from nuclear power stations. The term ALARP in the context of
cess industries, railways and even steep slopes in urban areas. In the way in which the UK Health and Safety Executive is a reg-
this regard, while the principle of balancing costs and benefits has ulatory interpretation made by the UK Health and Safety
a long history, the range of current applications of the ALARP princi- Executive with respect to how it considers industrial safety over
ple, which may be used in conjunction with CBA, is considerably the spectrum of industries for which it has responsibility.
more diverse than the application for which the ALARP principle According to the HSE document ‘‘ALARP at a glance’’ (HSE,
was originally formulated. These principles seem to occupy the 2014a) these terms mean essentially the same thing. While this
extremes of the safety decision making spectrum. ALARP being on may be the case with respect to how the HSE discharges its
the qualitative, holistic, principles-based side does not necessarily responsibilities; that is ALARP describes the level to which we
lead to uniformly predictable outcomes, whereas CBA is on the (HSE) expect to see workplace risks controlled, it does not mean
quantitative, limited, precisely defined side. These characteristics that the Courts will consider ALARP to be equivalent to ‘‘In So Far
expose both principles to criticism. Application of the ALARP process as is Reasonably Practicable’’ (SFAIRP) (HSE, 2014b). The term ‘‘So
may to lead to different decisions in similar contexts resulting in Far as is Reasonably Practicable’’ (SFAIRP) is used widely in health
uncertainty and unpredictability in decision making. CBA leads to and safety legislation in the UK, whereas the term ALARP is not
decisions in which only money counts and all that cannot be used. However, much of the contemporary commentary on
expressed in money or is perceived of no monetary value is neglected. ALARP suggests that the term has been enshrined in the UK case
This paper explores this issue in more depth and concludes that law since the case of Edwards v. National Coal Board in 1949
ALARP and CBA are part of the general decision making process, even (NN, 1949). In the case the court stated that
if they are identified as separate, individual, explicit steps.
‘‘Reasonably practicable’’ is a narrower term than ‘‘physically pos-
sible’’ and seems to me to imply that a computation must be made
2. ALARP and SFAIRP by the owner in which the quantum of risk is placed on one scale
and the sacrifice involved in the measures necessary for averting
ALAP stands for As Low As Practicable. ALAP originated in the the risk (whether in money, time or trouble) is placed in the other;
field of radiation protection in the US in the 1950s. In 1970 title and if it be shown that there is a gross disproportion between them,
10 of the Code of Federal Regulation Parts 20 and 50 specified that the risk being insignificant in relation to the sacrifice – the [person
exposure to radiation should be kept as far below the limits as was on whom the duty is laid] discharges the onus on them [of proving
reasonably practicable. By 1970 the notion of limits, to be used also that compliance was not reasonably practicable].’’
as reference, was part of the protection construct. In 1979 ALAP
changed in to As Low AS Reasonably Achievable (ALARA) The ruling implied that the risk must be insignificant in relation
(Loewen, 2011). to the sacrifice (in terms of money, time or trouble) required to
In radiation protection the ALARA principle is used as a ratchet avert it: risks must be averted unless there is a gross disproportion
mechanism to update – i.e. lower – the radiation exposure limits as between the costs and benefits of doing so.
a function of the developments in science and technology. When The term SFAIRP was used in the Health and Safety At Work Act
the limit technically can be set lower it will. Interestingly the in 1974 and is used in the regulations. In 2001 Cullen and Uff con-
terminology in the regulation does not require the limits to change cluded that at that time this was still an accurate expression of the
as technology improves. It only requires that one operates as far law (Cullen, 2001).
below the limits as can be achieved. Apparently the updates of Notwithstanding all of the above, duty holders cannot assume
the limits are necessary to make enforcement of the required that if the HSE concludes that a certain risk is ALARP that it means that
behaviour possible or easier. the statutory duty of the dutyholder to reduce the risks SFAIRP is ful-
The principle that measures should be reasonable and practica- filled. It only means that the HSE is satisfied, not that the Courts will be
ble was already used earlier in the United Kingdom in the satisfied that the SFAIRP condition has been achieved. The important
Electricity Regulations 1908 (Evans, 2008), in the Spinning by point here, that is generally not made, is that the two qualifications
Self-acting Mules Regulations of 1905 reg 3 (Rothery, 2008) and are applied to quite different properties. ALARP is applied to the level
in Section 5 of the Salmon Fishery Act 1861. Another early use of ‘risk’ whereas SFAIRP is applied to being ‘safe’. The key question is
was found in the Chaffing Machines Act 1897, the Threshing whether being ‘safe’ is determined solely by the level of ‘risk’. Safety is
Machines Act 1878 (Bagnall, 2008) and the Alkali Act relative and influenced by values whereas risk is quasi-objective and
Amendment Act 1874, but before that appeared in the Leeds Act held to be value-free. The numbers mean the same to everyone, which
of 1848 (NN, 2014a,b,c): ‘‘But no person shall be subject to the fore- of course is why risk became the parameter or property of choice. In
going penalties for any act done in the exercise of any right to which he practice, the difference means that the requirement ‘safe SFAIRP’
is by law entitled, if he prove to the satisfaction of the court, before focuses on reducing the hazard. This is what the law requires and
whom he is tried, that he has used the best practicable means, on which the courts pass judgement.
within a reasonable cost, to render harmless the liquid or solid matter The discussion on the difference between ALARP and ALARA
so permitted to flow or to be put into waters’’. hinges on the definitions of Achievable and Practicable. Munson
92 B.J.M. Ale et al. / Safety Science 76 (2015) 90–100

(1988) state that despite that there may be subtle differences substantially differs from grossly disproportionate in Evens against
between the two terms, they are in practice interchangeable. the Coal Board is difficult to assess.
However it looks like the use of the term ALARP in the UK as
opposed to ALARA seems to imply that achievable includes that
it could be theoretically possible to go lower even if it has not been 3. Reasonability
demonstrated in any way to be feasible in practice. ALARA then
demands to do work, research, engineering to make it work. The use of the term reasonable suggests that – in the UK risk
Practicable seems to indicate that the technical feasibility needs management context – it is not sufficient to just adhere to some
to have been demonstrated. Whether this also means that the tech- limit, if it exists, and that the reasonability of performing or
nical implementation of the possibility should have been realised refraining from an action is not just a matter of money. The term
in practice and that practicable means the same as available tech- expresses that besides aspects that can be expressed in terms of
nology is unclear. money or have a monetary or market value, there are aspects that
In this context the term BAT, Best Available Technology, plays a do not have such a monetary value, or such a value cannot be
role. BAT implies that the costs are not considered. Then BAT established with reasonable accuracy. The aspects may comprise
means the same as ALAP, As Low As Practicable, the term used in such things as equity, sociality and even maybe beauty – even if
radiation protection before it became ALARA. it is only in the eye of the beholder. An area of outstanding beauty
ALARP apparently means that the technology not only should may appeal to one and not to another. And this is certainly true for
be available, but also that the costs should be reasonable. This is buildings, which are conserved for their beauty, the beauty of
confirmed in the verdict on the appeal in the case of Baker against which is an area of contention between architects. In either case
the Quantum Clothing Group (The Supreme Court, 2011a). the monetary value of these areas and buildings in many if not in
most cases is considerably less that the costs associated with keep-
‘‘In considering what is practicable, account must be taken of the ing them that way. In addition areas usually are much more valu-
state of knowledge at the time. A defendant cannot be held liable able in terms of economic production and sales value when they
for failing to use a method which, at the material time, had not can be used as building sites or agricultural areas than when they
been invented: Adsett v K and L Steelfounders and Engineers Ltd are designated as nature conservation areas. Therefore reasonabil-
[1953] 2 All ER 320; nor for failing to take measures against a dan- ity comprises much more than money and it is only loosely
ger which was not known to exist: Richards v Highway defined. It is what those who happen to make a decision consider
Ironfounders (West Bromwich) Ltd [1955] 3 All ER 205.’’ reasonable.
In particular instances, once it is ruled that a certain measure is
In the same verdict the demand of gross disproportionality was reasonable, then it usually does not change, even if circumstances
confirmed: (The Supreme Court, 2011b) change. If a city grows and encroaches on a listed building it has to
construct around this building. At the same time the economic fac-
I agree with Smith LJ in her conclusion (at para 84 of her judgment) tors change. It probably was a building to keep in a rural area, but
that for the defence to succeed, the employer must establish a gross is it also a building to keep now that the area has become a city? It
disproportion between the risk and the measures necessary to seems that once listed means always listed.1 So it looks like reason-
eliminate it. In the words of Asquith LJ in Edwards v National ability depends on the circumstances until the decision has been
Coal Board [1949] 1 KB 704, 712, ‘‘the risk [must be] insignificant made, after which changing circumstances no longer change the rea-
in relation to the sacrifice’’. In the present case, the provision of sonability. Therefore in the UK in many cases the practical meaning
ear defenders at relatively modest cost was entirely practicable. of ALARP can only be inferred and may only be defined definitely
For that reason, and since I have concluded that the employers after a trial in court, which may only take place after an incident.
ought to have been aware of the risk of noise induced hearing loss In the Netherlands legislation follows the Napoleonic principle that
to the respondent, I do not consider that the defence of reasonable it is a citizens right to know in advance what the legislature
practicability was available to them. demands and that governmental decisions need to be predictable
(Ale, 2005).
Another acronym that seems to mean the same is BATNEEC. The advantage of a qualitative somewhat vague concept, and
This term was introduced with the 1984 Air Framework Directive decision-making that depends on a to a large extent subjective
(AFD) and applies to air pollution emissions from large industrial value judgement by a decision maker, lies in that it avoids ques-
installations. BATNEEC stands for Best Available Technology Not tions that are difficult to answer. It also avoids questions that have
Entailing Excessive Costs. In any case the introduction of several ethical connotations. The question of the value of land has already
different acronyms over the years suggests that the authors were been touched above. A much more stinging problem is the mone-
not satisfied that the existing acronyms conveyed had the same tary value of a human life. By demanding substantial dispropor-
meaning of what they tried to express. tionality or gross disproportionality of costs before refraining
Central in the discussion is what is meant by reasonable. A fla- from a risk reducing measure, the problem of precisely setting a
vour for the extremes in these discussions are acronyms also used value on a human need not be addressed. However many decisions
in the debate: CATNIP (Cheapest Available Technology Not imply a value for a human life. Sometimes these values are
Invoking Prosecution) or as David Slater put it (1994): ALARA: As assessed by dividing the costs of the measure by the number of sta-
Large As Regulators Allow, bringing back the notion the only a limit tistical lives saved (or at least not killed by the activity under con-
ultimately can prevent the risks from growing. This also is sideration), such as in Tengs et al. (1995). However it should be
expressed by the drift to danger model as presented by borne in mind that these evaluations implicitly assume that saving
Rasmussen (1997). lives was the only purpose of the measure and the only not mone-
The verdict in the case of Baker against the clothing group states tised issue in the decision. In some of the decisions mentioned by
as elements that the person or institution is aware of the risk or Tengs et al. it seems obvious that the continuation of the political
could reasonably be expected to be aware of it, and that a career of the decision makers was considered an important but not
reasonable person or institution could not use cost or difficulty explicitly monetised factor. So the apparent inconsistency in
as a valid reason for not having such a policy. A valid reason could
be that the costs are substantially disproportionate. Whether this 1
The same applies in the Netherlands.
B.J.M. Ale et al. / Safety Science 76 (2015) 90–100 93

decision making could perhaps be attributed to other factors than at their total portfolio of risks and may compensate an increased
just inconsistency. Nevertheless the question was, is and will be level of risk by risk reducing measures somewhere else. For
raised whether decisions involving risks for human lives and instance, rather than sticking to a moderately healthy diet always
health should be more consistent on the aspect of the implied they may decide to compensate for a heavy meal by a day of
monetary value of a human. Before this issue is addressed first fasting.
the other extreme of the decision making spectrum is considered: If earning power is used (Morall, 1986) the question arises how
CBA. to deal with the unemployed. If the number of life years lost is
used, how can the question of putting the elderly or the young in
specific hazardous situations be dealt with. The notion of Quality
4. Cost Benefit Analysis
Adjusted Life Years (QALY) brings the question of the handicapped
or challenged against the healthy.
In Cost Benefit Analysis and the decision making based on CBA
In terms of expenditure per life-year the numbers range from 0
it is assumed that everything has a value that can be expressed in
to 99 ⁄ 109 US dollar (Tengs et al., 1995). The policy value of a
money. It also assumes that these values can be determined and
human life seemed to gravitate to approximately 7 million US$.
are determined in the market place that the world is considered
This is equivalent to US$200,000 per life-year.
to be.
In more recent literature, the value for a human life to be used
When all aspects to consider are money such as an investment
in cost benefit analyses is called the Value Of Saving a Statistical
decision in stocks or bonds the application is straightforward. But
Life rather than the Value Of a Statistical Life (VOSL). The argument
it gets complicated even for decisions such as constructing a road.
given is that the value of LIFE is unmeasurable. Nevertheless, in any
Is the road value for money? The quantum of what has to be spent
cost benefit decisions the bottom line is that the value used is the
in monetary terms for the design, construction and maintenance
value for letting that life continue in that decision. In decisions
can be calculated. But what is the worth of the time saved by not
where statistical lives are lost, even when that is called tolerable
having tail backs? The value of changing the living environment
(HSE, 2001), the activity and the risk are accepted and decision
for those who have to be rehoused is not only the current market
makers would do better in the public debate if they did not hide
value of their houses (which usually is the item in the CBA), but
this behind words. HSE (2001) uses a value of one million pounds
also the ‘‘imponderable’’ costs of children losing their friends, hav-
in their advice on risky activities. Also this value is based on the
ing to go to another school, which has a value for them and for
amounts spent on road safety (HSE, 2001). HSE remarks that they
which they do not get compensated, which is not considered but
consider a higher value appropriate for risks for which people have
still is a value loss.
a higher aversion, but they do not specify a value for risks such as
Cost Benefit Analysis is attractive because whatever the con-
disasters in a chemical factory or a nuclear power plant.
sideration leading to a decision to implement or refrain from a
In an evaluation that is more recent than the one performed by
measure, one aspect is always that a measure bears some costs.
Tengs et al. (1995) and Viscusi and Aldy (2003) derive a value of 4
The other ubiquitous aspect is that the activity under consideration
million US dollar.
is advantageous to somebody. And in most occasions that advan-
According to Button (1993), the official value of a human life
tage is earning money. There are occasions though where money
varies from €12,000 to €2.35 million (Euro) and the market value
is not the primary objective. Having a race track has ‘‘fun’’ as its
between €97 and €630,000. Blaeij et al. regarding road safety find
main advantage even when money is made by admission fees.
values ranging from US$0.15M to US$30M (Blaeij et al., 2000;
The main disadvantage is noise, which is also difficult to express
Blaeij, 2003). They conclude that the value found depends among
in money terms.
other things on the method used to determine it and on the back-
Using CBA reduces the question of acceptability to the question
ground risk. They also say that to assume that a single (average or
of profitability. Even when it is difficult to answer this question,
mean) VOSL can be attained, as is frequently suggested in the
whether it is ethically acceptable to bother people with noise for
literature as well as among policy-makers, is not sound from a
some people’s fun is a question that is even more difficult. If the
theoretical perspective and that the same conclusion can be drawn
racetrack example is not sufficient to explain the issue, consider
regarding the empirics of VOSL estimations.
fireworks. Does having the fun of fireworks outweigh the suffering
The valuation of injuries is even more difficult as are environ-
of those who are killed and maimed in the accidents associated
mental damages. A comprehensive description is given in the
with the production and the storage of these fireworks?
ExternE (NN, 1995) report, but even there the results remain
The latter raises an even deeper issue. Apparently the people
inconclusive or as Dolan et al. put it ‘‘elusive’’ (Dolan et al., 2008).
involved in the production accept the risk in return for their pay.
So from the point of view of CBA, the market has done its job.
4.2. Cost
There was an offer: money in exchange for a risky job and some-
body accepted it. The more ethical question is: should this offer
There are also great difficulties in assessing the actual value of
be on the table to begin with. This in turn raises the question
the risk reduction costs. A seemingly expensive measure such as
whether human lives can be evaluated in terms of money and if
the desulphurization of residual oil actually brought money.
that is possible whether that value is a universal constant and all
Many of the expenses made in safety result also in increased relia-
people are indeed created equal and finally if that is the case what
bility of the production and less costs of down time and accidents.
that value is.
In fact, in the study performed by Pikaar and Seaman (1995) for the
Dutch ministry of Housing, Physical Planning and Environment it
4.1. The value of life appeared that most industries did not consider it worth their while
to register the costs of these measures. This is consistent with
A continuous stream of efforts has been made to deduce a num- Tengs et al. (1995) finding of the low costs of measures related
ber for the value of a human life. Several attempts have been made to the prevention of accidents.
that all have their specific ethical drawback (NN, 1995). So the methodology for Cost Benefit Analysis itself is well estab-
Recent literature indicates that these estimates can be very mis- lished and works well when only material loss and gain is involved,
leading because people manage their risk much more intelligently such as in finance. Currently there is not yet a clear understanding
then by just looking at the one risk under consideration. They look of how to use Cost Benefit Analysis in an organised way in risk
94 B.J.M. Ale et al. / Safety Science 76 (2015) 90–100

management, when these risks go beyond financial risks. What to initiator has no more money left to invest, improving safety is
put in monetary terms against what otherwise is called ‘‘impon- not considered reasonable. This makes some projects or technolo-
derable’’ is still the subject of considerable debate. gies safer than others. To prevent ‘‘poor’’ projects from being exces-
As described several times previously, especially when human sively unsafe, standards exist that define a maximum level of risk.
life and health are at stake the discussion is more about values These standards can be and are different for different types of
than about costs. But real decisions are often much more cynical activities. There is no law of nature that defines an (un-) acceptable
than that (Evans, 1996). level of risk, nor is there a principle that all risks should be mea-
Illustrative in this respect is the discussion about Automatic sured equally. All of the reasonability principles can only operate
Train Protection systems (ATP) in the United Kingdom. After Lord within the implied or explicit assumption that an ultimate limit
Hidden (1989) in his report of the Clapham Junction accident exists.
advised to introduce ATP on the British Rail network, British rail
issued a report in 1994 (HSC, 1999) in which it showed that, given 4.4. Distribution of cost and benefits
the Value Of a Statistical Life used in the UK, ATP was dispropor-
tionally expensive. This conclusion was endorsed by the Risk acceptability is also a distribution problem. Those who
Department of Transportation (DoT, 1995). After the crash at ‘‘take’’ the risk often are not the same people who ‘‘bear’’ the risks.
Ladbroke Grove Lord Cullen (Cullen, 2001) concludes that that When the rewards of risk taking goes to the risk creators and the
decision was not unreasonable, but that the introduction of ATP costs are carried by the risk bearers a strong incentive is created
was advisable regardless of these costs. This in turn leads Evans for a small group to take large risks at the expense of others. The
(Evans, 2005) to the conclusion that that money could be better banking crisis is a prime example. The management of the banks
spent on road safety, illustrating again that monetary cost benefit took excessive risks and most of them got away with it. The tax
evaluations seldom dominate the final decision. However, the reg- payer had to bail them out. For the moment it looks as if society
ulatory/political decision on ATP has not been the subject of any is curtailing the market freedom of the banks to prevent this beha-
court case. The cost-benefit argument was conducted entirely in viour in the future.
the political domain, much along the lines indicated. To the knowl- The separation between risk takers and risk bearers is in part
edge of the authors, the ALARP argument has never figured in a counteracted by litigation. The victims seek compensation from
court case where the defence would have been that the residual those who created the harm. However, as is illustrated by the case
risk was such as to ensure compliance with the law – in effect, that of the fireworks explosion in the Netherlands in 2000, damages in
the risk was acceptable. The authors are not aware of any such the case of an accident can easily be beyond the financial capabili-
defence and in any case, the hindsight bias available to the court ties of the industry that caused the accident. One could choose for
can be expected to guarantee conviction. the principle that the damage rests where it falls (Helsloot et al.,
Given these experiences the weighting of human lives in an 2010, p83), and leave the victims with the damage, but this invari-
economic framework perhaps has to be left to the decision-makers ably results in public outcry, in which case the tax payer again has
and any analysis that quantifies human losses in terms of money to foot the bill.
has to be explicit about the valuation. Another persistent problem in societal Cost Benefit Analysis is
that even if all the attributes can be expressed in terms of money,
4.3. Safety budget what is considered ‘‘good’’ for society is not necessarily ‘‘good’’ for
everybody. The increase in ‘‘wealth’’ as a total may be maximised,
The remark made by Evans is repeated by Helsloot who com- but some have more profit than others. The sheer fact that econo-
pares various safety measures and states among other things that mists cannot decide on what is best, making society more egalitar-
the costs associated with the signs at emergency exits can better ian, with small difference in income and possessions or less
be spent giving children fruits at school (Helsloot, 2012). egalitarian, with large differences proves the point. Therefore
This reasoning is problematic as it suggests that money spent Cost Benefit Analysis which only considers economic optimisation
on saving or extending human lives can best be spent on food ignores as Tawney (1926), put it:
and medicines in the poorest regions of the world. Thus the ulti-
‘‘A reasonable estimate of economic organization must allow for
mate conclusion of this reasoning would be that it would be better
the fact that, unless industry is to be paralyzed by recurrent revolts
to redistribute the life expectancy over the all the people in the
on the part of outraged human nature, it must satisfy criteria,
world, making the life expectancy in the ‘‘developing’’ world longer
which are not purely economic’’.
at the expense of the life expectancy in the ‘‘western’’ world.
Whether this is ethically better or economically better is unclear.
What is clear is that then there must be a mechanism to deter-
mine where the safety money should go. It is no surprise that 4.5. Societal risk
Helsloot et al. propose an independent commission (Helsloot
et al., 2010, p163), that would decide on purely scientific grounds Societal risk is the term used for risks that involve events with
where the safety money should be spent. The problem that multiple fatalities or victims. Using just the expectation value of a
Helsloot et al. ignore is that there is no such thing as a safety bud- loss implies that the decision maker will attach equal value to risks
get. There is money to spend on safety in a project, but this money for which the R is equal; that it does not matter whether there is a
is part of the project budget. It is difficult to imagine a mechanism 1/100 chance of winning 100 Euros, or a 1/1000 chance of winning
by which such a Commission could decide that that a specific pro- 1000 euros. In normal life betting games this is often the case.
ject can be made more risky, then take money from whoever is However, if the consequences are very high, this might no longer
doing the project and spend it somewhere else. It is easy to imag- be the case. As an example, after 9/11, insurance companies were
ine that should such a procedure exist, whoever has a project no longer prepared to insure losses in excess of 1 billion Euros,
would set the safety budget to zero, budget for more risk and wait regardless of the probability. In such circumstances the conse-
until and if the Commission would do something about it, prefer- quences and the probabilities or frequencies have to be presented
ably by supplying money taken from somebody else. and considered separately.
The current practice of determining reasonability takes the The most widely known expression of these effects in mathe-
spending power of the initiator of a project into account. If the matical terms is the so-called risk-aversion index. Risk aversion
B.J.M. Ale et al. / Safety Science 76 (2015) 90–100 95

means that more severe consequences (with the same frequency) value used was increased (DoT, 1995). According to Cullen and Uff
weigh heavier in the decision making process than more frequent there does not seem to be a scientific reason for this difference. In
events (with the same in total consequence). Large consequence or their report however Cullen and Uff do not give a judgement on
disaster aversion therefore would be a better term (Bedford, 2013). these values, as the issue under their investigation is already settled
There is considerable debate about whether it is ethical to treat by law. It looks as though they are of the opinion that this does not
a single accident with say 10 people killed as worse than 10 acci- by implication set a value on a human life, but they are unclear about
dents with 1 person killed each. Evans and Verlander (1993) state this. From the more recent amended Railways and Other Guided
that having an FN curve as a linear relationship between F (the fre- Transport Systems (Safety) Regulations 2006 (NN, 2014a,b,c) it
quency) and N (the value exceeded) with a slope steeper than 1, appears that this difference no longer is used.
which is the mathematical expression of considering a single mul- The Dutch government uses €5.8M for an average life lost in a
tiple fatality accident as less acceptable than a series of one fatality flood (Deltares, 2011; IENM, 2013). This is based on studies by
accidents with the same total number of victims, violates the eco- Bockarjova et al. (2009a, 2009b, 2009c) who state that the use of
nomic rule of constant utility, and that therefore decisions made on their findings as an estimate for the VOSL is problematic, given
any other criterion than the expectation value of the number of the answers of the respondents in their study, show that people
victims is wrong. Recently however, Bedford (2013) has shown behave more as ‘‘homo politicus’’ than as ‘‘homo economicus’’
that an FN curve with a slope steeper than 1, or valuing a multi- (Bockarjova et al., 2008).
ple fatality accident heavier than a series of single fatality acci- Helsloot et al. (2010) propose to use €3.2MEuro for an average life
dents is not risk averse but consequence averse and can be lost as a uniform amount for all policy decisions in the Netherlands.
shown to be compatible with the economic laws that entities with The ministry of Infrastructure and Environment proposes €2.9M per
the same utility should be valued equally. life lost in the CBA for the introduction of the European Rail Traffic
Multiple fatalities can create more disutility than single fatali- Management System (MuConsult, 2014) which is half the value in
ties, just by the fact that they occur simultaneously, in the same the CBA for the height of the dykes, which underpins the current pro-
event and by the same cause. This finding is a further confirmation posal3 for the new ‘‘Delta’’ works (IENM, 2013).
of the findings in Slovic et al. in 1978. It should be borne in mind In health care the Dutch Health Councils prefers a value of
that expressing the consequences in terms of fatalities is using a €80,000 per Quality Adjusted Life-year (QALY) (RVGZ, 2006).
proxy for all the attributes of a multi-fatality event, sometimes However, when the costs of medicines decreases this may lead to
referred to as social disruption. Slovic at al. called it ‘‘dread’’, which the conclusion that it is worthwhile to treat half of the Dutch pop-
stands for attributes such as disastrousness, inability to cope with- ulation against hypertension even when this risk of adverse conse-
out help, beyond control, man-made. When asked directly people quences is marginal (Smulders and Thijs, 2006). Recent decisions
probably will say that it does not matter whether the number of according the preference of the Health Council regarding the treat-
people killed is one by one, or in a single accident. This does not ment of among other things Pompe’s disease resulted in a parlia-
take away from the fact that 100 people killed in a train crash leads mentary debate and in a revoking of the decision to no longer
to social debate and parliamentary enquiries, while the same num- pay for this treatment under the basic health insurance system in
ber killed on the road does not cause any societal ripple. the Netherlands.
Therefore multiple fatality accidents should not be compared
with multiple accidents with a single fatality by the number of 4.7. CBA in decision making
people killed alone, which strengthens the argument that values
of statistical lives derived from road safety are not transferrable Just as ALARP, CBA based decision making has its merits and its
to other areas of industry. It also strengthens the doubts as to disadvantages. Its primary merit is that it is precisely defined and
whether a value derived from one realm can be transferred to the decision is predictable. Its disadvantage is that it does not take
another realm per se. If indeed there is no law of nature from into account the imponderables that more often than not weigh
which an acceptable risk level can be derived, there is no reason into the decision. Using CBA also suggests that the Value of Life
a priori to assume that the level would be equal for each realm. is a known and universal constant while there is no scientific evi-
This in turn does not prevent any decision maker from deciding dence other than that the VOSL varies over a large range and highly
to adopt a level in one realm which is equal to that in another depends on the circumstances and on the method used to deter-
realm, but this needs separate justification, as for instance was mine it.
done in the Dutch Premises for Risk Management (TK, 1988). What seems to be emerging from the examples in (4.6 above) is
that decisions on statistical human lives and anonymous future
victims are much easier than on real human beings. In the latter
4.6. Values used
example of Pompe’s disease there are only some 10 patients in
the Netherlands. In that case the future victims were no longer sta-
All these publications and the elusiveness of the value of human
tistical but real. This is in line with the findings of Slovic et al.
lives does not prevent authorities from adopting standard values
(1978), that the possibility of identification with the victims makes
for the value of a statistical life. The Australian Government’s
a risk – or a consequence – less acceptable.
Office of Best Practice Regulation adopted a value of 3.5M $US
per life and a value of 151,000$US per statistical life year. It is sta-
ted that these estimates are based on the assumption that the aver- 5. Multi criteria analysis
age person has another 40 years to live, which implies an average
life expectancy of 80 years. There is no indication that they noticed Decisions are made. The processes involved are not always
that these values are completely inconsistent. made explicit. They are the result of a complicated value judge-
The UK Health and Safety Executive stated a value of £1M in ment in which many attributes play a role.
their report R2P2 (HSE, 2001). The UK Department of A possible escape from explicit valuation of human lives is
Environment, Transport and the Regions now uses £1.74M2 for Multi Criteria Analysis (MCA). In MCA criteria are not necessarily
road traffic (2014b). For risks close to the limit of intolerability the expressed in a common metric (such as money), but the relevant

2 3
The value is given in 7 significant digits: 1,742,988. The ministry considers this decision as being taken.
96 B.J.M. Ale et al. / Safety Science 76 (2015) 90–100

attributes are described in their own terms, leaving the weighting reasonably practical. It is meant perhaps to counter the drift to
to the decision maker. MCA appeals to decision makers and others danger under market forces as described by Rasmussen (1997). It
who are uncomfortable with numbers (Vlek, 1996) or are of the should be noted however, that there is a general rule for optimisa-
opinion that the use of numbers implicitly suggests an accuracy tion, which is that the solution is not in the interior of the area of
that these numbers do not have. The latter suggestion is some- feasible solutions, but always on the boundary. This means that if
times reinforced by expressing the VOSL in seven significant digits there are no bounds the solution can be anywhere. It also means
as is done in the CBA for the introduction of ERTMS in the that once a limit is set, the solution will be on this limit, unless
Netherlands.4 The different attributes of risk are expressed in qual- another constraint is more demanding. In the case of a non-
itative form and judged qualitatively. This does not take away from bounded risk problem, the boundary condition for costs is zero
the fact that after the decision, which in this case is a matter of the costs. This means that the risk will rise until the costs are zero. If
willingness to pay, can be evaluated in terms of what the decision there is a risk limit, the risk will be on this limit, unless other
means for the – now implicit – economic valuation of a human life. demands, such as the operability, are more stringent. The resulting
This form of decision making removes another problem that is ‘lower than the limit’ risk then is just a co-incidence. If the risk
created by an explicit valuation; specifically that the numbers used limit puts excessive financial demands on the activity, the activity
are based on studies in which it is stated explicitly that the valuation will be stopped. The remark made in several VOSL studies that the
deduced from willingness to pay investigations or evaluations of VOSL varies widely, may be the result of a process in which other
past decisions have a wide spread and that these values should factors were dominant. In many ex post evaluations of decisions
not be taken as the basis for future decisions without further discus- these factors may not be retrievable, because they are only known
sion. Nevertheless, as described above, the value from the ExternE to the people involved. As an example the fine for not having a
report seem to percolate through CBA based decision making. fence around a swimming-pool in France is €40,000. In terms of
The Safety Case Regime, that applies to certain industries in valuation of a statistical life this may seem an enormous amount,
Australia, New Zealand, and the United Kingdom can be considered unless one knows that the regulation came into force after the
to fall into the multi-attribute category of safety demonstrations. grand child of the responsible minister drowned in a swimming
The United Kingdom Offshore Installations (Safety Case) pool. He judged apparently that it was unreasonable that children
Regulations 2005 are an example. For the purpose of a design noti- drown in swimming pools regardless of the costs of protection.
fication or a relocation notification, the particulars to be provided There are many of these decisions known. They have in common
include among other particulars ‘‘a description of how a chosen lives that were not valued before the decision, and therefor the
design concept is intended to ensure that risks with the potential value was the accidental result, not a pre-set criterion.
to cause a major accident are reduced to the lowest level that is
reasonably practicable’’ (UK Government, 2005). The process for
the Verification of Compliance with UK Shelf Regulations (DNV, 7. Dams and the question ‘‘How safe is safe enough?’’ – A brief
2011) provides an illustration of how the Offshore Safety overview
Regulations are being implemented as follows:
ALARP is particularly important for fixed installations and float- The failure of a large dam or important flood defence dyke,
ing installations located at a fixed location. However, mobile units while perhaps less frightening than a nuclear catastrophe, is com-
coming to the UK will also have to demonstrate an acceptable level parably destructive. The publication of Tolerability of Risk from
of safety including reasonable application of the ALARP principle. Nuclear Power Stations, and in particular the content of
The basic principles for hazard management are: Appendix 4 provided British Columbia Hydro, an owner of large
hydropower and flood control dams, with a basis to propose a
– systematic identification of major hazards on the installation new approach to the assessment of the safety of dams for flood
– taking action to design out, avoid and reduce hazards at source and earthquake hazards (BC Hydro, 1993). The proposed BC
– risk analysis and assessment of major accident hazards, includ- Hydro criteria of life safety were mid-way between the ‘‘local scru-
ing PFEER Regulation 5 assessment tiny line’’ and the ‘‘negligible line’’ for ‘‘major hazards of transport’’
– inclusion of ergonomics and human factors issues within the (Figure D1 of the Tolerability of Risk report). BC Hydro’s objective
risk assessment process was to set ‘‘safety standards’’ for dams in terms of risk to life and
– establishing appropriate prevention, detection, control and mit- economic risk that would be used to determine that a dam would
igation measures, including safety-critical elements and their be deemed to be acceptably safe to the Company and to the Dam
performance standards, to manage remaining hazards Safety Regulatory authority.
– linking to an acceptable verification scheme covering the SCEs At the same time, the Australian National Committee on Large
identified Dams, an industry association, was working towards a similar
– providing suitable evacuation, escape and recovery resources objective as BC Hydro (ANCOLD, 1994, revised 2004). In 1995, a
– demonstration of fulfilment of the ALARP principle. study carried out for State of Victoria office of water reform pub-
lished the Victorian Headworks Review (SMEC, 1995) that repre-
The above work forms the basis for development of the safety sented the first application of a version of risk assessment to a
case(s). portfolio of dams for prioritisation purposes.
In terms of the above, an ALARP demonstration, while an impor- CBA has been used for many years to justify the costs of invest-
tant part of the safety assurance process is not the only part. ments in new water resource infrastructure, including flood
defences where it plays a very significant role. However the idea
of using CBA, which was central to the BC Hydro proposal in the
6. Optimisation determination of the extent to which safety features for dams to
withstand the effects of severe flooding was rejected by the engi-
ALARP is a form of driving the optimal solution of a complicated neering profession, the dams industry and government authorities,
problem in a certain direction: One should make the risk as low as largely on moral and ethical grounds relating to the problem of val-
uation of life. The approach adopted in the Netherlands for flood
4
The value given for a death is €2,877,857, the value for an injured €295,870 Euro; protection dykes was not adopted by the dams industry. The US
(€ 2013), before tax. Bureau of Reclamation (United States Bureau of Reclamation
B.J.M. Ale et al. / Safety Science 76 (2015) 90–100 97

(USBR), 1986) considered the matter with respect to the safety of referred to as harmonised quantitative design targets have been
dams in the mid-1980s but did not pursue it. However, owing to specified in terms of an acceptable rate of failures per hour.
the very high cost and little apparent benefit of traditional safety In response the Rail Safety and Standards Board (RSSB), an
measures for dams the matter remained of interest in a small num- industry organisation has provided guidance to rail operators on
ber of countries, most notably in Australia and in British Columbia, the matter of risk management and demonstrating that risks have
Canada. been reduced So Far As Is Reasonably Practicable (RSSB, 2014).
BC Hydro withdrew its proposal in 1997 because of difficulties
in providing a scientifically robust analysis of the risk, difficulties ‘‘The obligation to ensure safety SFAIRP is sometimes expressed as a
that continue to inhibit the application of risk analysis in determin- requirement to reduce risk to a level that is as low as reasonably
ing the safety of dams, and because of legal and corporate social practicable. Although SFAIRP and ALARP are different in law, they
responsibility concerns. In the same year, the US Bureau of are used interchangeably in the GB rail industry and are regarded
Reclamation (USBR) established a similar criterion to that of BC as representing the same health and safety legal test.’’
Hydro for prioritising its expenditures on dam safety improve-
ments. These criteria have remained in place at the since. Since For the purpose of CBA, the RSSB ‘value of preventing a fatality’
1997, and in recognition that the setting of societal risk control (VPF) was £ 1.826 million in June 2014. In terms of the RSSB
goals is a matter of politics that must be addressed on a jurisdiction Guidance on the use of cost-benefit analysis for ensuring safety,
by jurisdiction basis, BC Hydro has focused its efforts on the matter CBA should only provide an input to the overall decision rather
of improving the industry’s capabilities to perform scientifically than giving a definitive result. Notwithstanding the extensive guid-
robust risk analysis methods. In 2004, the New South Wales Dam ance provided by RSSB to operators, a degree of uncertainty
Safety Committee, the State’s Regulatory Authority for the safety remains with respect to the safety decision because as in other sit-
of dams established a policy of progressive improvement of the uations in the common law system, the adequacy of a duty holder’s
safety of dams based on risk assessment criteria that reflected safety measures will ultimately be determined by the Courts after
the Tolerability of Risk and ALARP philosophy of the UK Health an accident.
and Safety Executive, as re-interpreted by the Australian National While in the case of railways in the United Kingdom, guidance
Committee on Large Dams. This Australian approach to risk assess- on risk-decisions and CBA is provided by the industry, the guidance
ment for dams, the use of which is widespread in Australia for pri- for dams is provided by a Government Agency. However, in both
oritisation of dam safety improvements, adopted societal risk cases, the risk assessment and CBA information inform the safety
criteria that combine the UK HSE’s Tolerability of Risk criteria decision, they do not form the sole basis for the decision.
and the F-N societal risk criteria used in the Netherlands for the However, unlike the railway industry, there is no EU-wide reg-
control of industrial risk, and for flood defences. ulation on the safety of dams and reservoirs.
Subsequent to the publication of Reducing Risks, Protecting Thus, after more than 20 years of activity in the domain or risk
People, the use of the HSE’s Tolerability of Risk Philosophy became assessment in dam safety practice, dam owners in common law
increasingly accepted for prioritisation purposes in the dams jurisdictions are still faced with the problem of comprehensively
industry (e.g. Brown and Godson, 2004). However, this use of the demonstrating that their dams are acceptably safe. In simple
HSE philosophy in the dams industry is not widespread being terms, the uncertainty associated with the safety decision as
restricted to Common Law countries, nor is it fully in accordance described in the Introduction remains a dominant matter for these
with the philosophy as set out in Tolerability of Risk from dam owners with only partial assurance being provided by their
Nuclear Power Stations. Thus far the New South Wales Dam ALARP demonstrations and the Cost-Benefit Analysis regardless
Safety Committee has been the only dam safety regulatory author- of how well grounded these analyses are. This is in marked con-
ity to establish dam safety criteria for dams and only in the context trast to the situation with respect to flood defences in the
of progressive improvement towards established deterministic Netherlands (or other Napoleonic jurisdictions that choose to)
standards. In 2007 the Canadian Dam Association published pro- where the responsible duty holders know how much safety to pro-
posed societal risk criteria for dams in Canada (CDA, 2007), a pro- vide as specified in terms of acceptable risk criteria and CBA.
posal that was revised in 2013. In 2009, the US Army Corps of
Engineers (Munger et al., 2009) prepared its own interpretation 8. Fusing the extremes
of the HSE’s Tolerability of Risk philosophy that serves as an ‘‘inter-
nal regulation’’. In 2013 in the UK, the Department of Environment, As is described above the expression of risk in quantitative
Food and Rural Affairs (DEFRA) published its Guide to risk assess- terms and the valuation of human lives is not going to disappear.
ment for reservoir safety management. However, the DEFRA Guide In a market driven society the bottom line of all decisions is an
does not form part of the reservoir safety legislation in the amount of money to be paid by a company, a victim, a bank,
United Kingdom in the same way as the Offshore Installations society, the consumer or the taxpayer. That does not necessarily
Safety Case Regulations. In 2014, the new policy on the safety of mean that the non-material damages and the non-material bene-
flood protection dykes in the Netherlands which meets BC fits associated with a risk bearing activity need to be valued at
Hydro’s original objective for dykes in the Netherlands was pub- the same price in every situation, in every context and in every
lished (Ministerie van Infrastructuur en Milieu, 2014). However, decision. It should be borne in mind though that the judgement
for the legal and political reasons previously described is not about risk is influenced more heavily by interests than by the abil-
applicable to BC Hydro’s dams or to dams in other jurisdictions ity to influence the decision. Vlek and Stemerding (1984) showed
where the common law system prevails and where the enabling that people judge more favourably on the risks of LPG if they drive
legislation has not been enacted. a car which is fuelled by it and even more favourably if they sell
The situation in the dams industry in common law countries LPG (Vlek and Stallen, 1981; Vlek et al., 1983).
has analogues in other industries such as railways. The existence In many cases the risk bearer is not the risk taker. Many studies
of the Common Safety Method for Risk Evaluation and indicate that a better and more accepted decision can be reached
Assessment for technical risk aspects of railway safety in the by involving the stakeholders (Smulders and Thijs, 2006; Renn,
European Union provides a useful means of examining the matter 2008). Many of these are less familiar with numbers than engi-
of ALARP, SFAIRP and CBA. In the EU regulation, design targets, neers or economists. Discussions in qualitative terms may help to
98 B.J.M. Ale et al. / Safety Science 76 (2015) 90–100

VOSL
emoons
ethics

Societal
CBA demands

QRA
ALARP

Performance
Risk criteria demands

Economy Industry Technical


ALARP
standards prescripons

Legal
Industry requirements

Future
ethics license to
operate
Client
demands reputaon

Fig. 1. The forces around a hazardous activity.

build understanding about what the – unavoidable – numbers What is considered to be reasonable can be evaluated purely
actually mean. qualitatively, but it is usually based on information on the resulting
In this context the use made of ALARP in the UK policy making risk derived from a quantitative risk analysis. Additionally infor-
is not a bad idea at all. First a problem is analysed in quantitative mation can be made available on the costs and the balance
terms as far as possible, including what taking certain measures between costs and benefits. This information also drives the
mean in terms of the implied value given to a human life. Then demands of society in general. However since QRA and CBA are
these numbers are combined with all the qualitative information supposed to be ‘‘factual’’ and ‘‘objective’’ there is not much room
that is available and a decision is made. for ethics in these exercises. Ethics and ‘‘emotions’’ are important
For repetitive decisions such as allowing hazardous activities drivers for human behaviour and thus for society. Although deci-
near populated areas or exposing people to chemical or noise a sion makers sometimes try to objectify their decisions, it cannot
standard or limit can be set. Such a limit prevents the drift to dan- be ignored that politicians lean heavily on emotions during elec-
ger (Rasmussen, 1997) caused by the continuous market pressure tion time. So unless one favours a technocratic dictatorship emo-
to reduce costs. It also prevents malicious exposure of third parties tions will be part of the decision making process, as Slovic and
to risks that only benefit some and finally it prevents exposure to others have shown over decades of research. Also Lord Cullen
risks of a small group ‘‘to the benefit of society’’ without proper and Prof. Uff (2001) conclude in the Southall and Ladbroke Grove
compensation. Joint Inquiry into Train Protection Systems that CBA is a factor to
take into account, but should not be the only factor. It is remarked
9. The bottom line on the side that technocratic dictatorships seem to have a rela-
tively short life span, due to the same emotions and the sometimes
The fusion of this all can best be described using a figure (Fig. 1). violent expression thereof. The resulting societal demands then
An industrial activity is subject to many forces. One of these is the find their way into ALARP, into the regulatory framework and will
legal requirement. In this respect the ‘‘lowest’’ level of safety cul- result at some point in the value attached to a human life in the
ture on the ‘‘Hudson’’ maturity scale can also be seen as the bottom case under consideration.
line of obligations. Indeed making the lawyers happy is a minimum
requirement unless one wants to be a criminal. Showing that what 10. Conclusion
has been done in terms of safety is ALARP can be part of the reg-
ulation, but as long as there is no guidance this remains a matter In all cases QRA and CBA remain information and not overriding
of opinion and therefor a matter of a power struggle between the criteria. The boundary conditions set in law are the only real limits.
regulator and the regulated. As discussed before, this is more rele- The laws could set acceptable risk explicitly, but they do not have
vant to common law than to Roman law. ALARP may be translated to. If the level of acceptable risk is not explicitly set, the risk level
to industry standards, by which the industry complies. This is usu- resulting from compliance to the regulations is just as accidental as
ally by their-own volition, but sometimes also because the law can the VOSL found from ex-post evaluations of decisions.
demand it directly or, and while the authors are not aware of any What remains is that ALARP, QRA and CBA are part of the
precedents, the regulation could define ALARP as the boundary for grander scheme of making decisions. ALARP defines to a certain
reasonability. extent what is done with the information gained by performing a
B.J.M. Ale et al. / Safety Science 76 (2015) 90–100 99

QRA and a CBA, by specifying what is reasonable: whether the Dolan, Paul, Metcalfe, Robert, Munro, Vicki, Christensen, Michael C., 2008. Valuing
lives and life years: anomalies, implications, and an alternative Health
costs should be equal to the benefits or disproportional costs are
Economics. Policy Law 3, 277–300 (ª Cambridge University Press 2008. http://
reasonable until the disproportion is gross? This represents a re- dx.doi.org/10.1017/S1744133108004507).
evaluation of the benefits, including the implied VOSL, making Evans, Andrew W., 1996. The economics of automatic train protection in Britain.
ALARP and CBA the same. Transp. Policy 3 (3), 105–110.
Evans, A.W., 2005. Railway risks, safety values and safety costs. Proc. Inst. Civ. Eng.
How the responsible decisions-makers, be they in industry, in Transp. 158 (TR1), 3–9 (February 2005).
government service, or in government office, utilise the informa- Evans, Ron, 2008. Letter to the Editor HSE Magazine March/April 2008.
tion that can be obtained from ALARP and CBA demonstrations will Evans, A.W., Verlander, N.Q., 1993. What is wrong with criterion FN-lines for
judging the tolerability of risk? Risk Anal. 17 (2), 157–168.
be dependent on the general and specific contexts of each decision. HeLsloot, I., 2012. Veiligheid als (bij)product (Safety as Byproduct). Oratie Radboud
Unlike CBA are no hard and fast rules that define the process as to Universiteit Nijmegen.
how such decisions can be made. The manner in which ALARP and Helsloot, I., Pieterman, R., Hanekamp, J.V., 2010. Risico’s en Redelijkhed (Risk and
reasonability). Boom Juridische Uitgevers, ISBN: 978-90-8974-243-8.
CBA are utilised either individually or together can also be Hidden, Anthony, 1989. Investigation into the Clapham Junction Railway Accident.
expected to be context dependent, with the context being influ- HMSO, London, ISBN: 0101082029.
enced by prevailing political, social, economic and industrial condi- HSC, 1999. <http://www.hse.gov.uk/consult/condocs/cd131.pdf> (as per 14.12.14).
HSE, 2001. Reducing Risk, Protecting People, Her Majesty’s Stationery Office,
tions. However, after an accident, and even if regulatory support Norwich NR3 1BQ, p. 36. ISBN: 0 7176 2151 0.
for the approach to safety has been obtained a-priori, the courts HSE, 2014a. <http://www.hse.gov.uk/risk/theory/alarpglance.htm?goback=%2Egde_
can be expected to judge each case on its merits with each case 2315060_member_187907945#%21> (as per 16.09.14).
HSE, 2014b. Principles and Guidelines to Assist HSE in its Judgements that Duty-
turning on the facts that are unique to that particular case.
holders have Reduced Risk as Low as Reasonably Practicable. <http://www.
hse.gov.uk/risk/theory/alarp1.htm>.
IENM, 2013. Letter of 26 April 2013 to the Parliament, Ministerie van Infrastructuur
Acknowledgement IENM/BSK 2013/19920.
Loewen, Eric P., 2011. Is ALARA Reform Needed? Address to both Eastern
Washington and Trinity Sections of the American Nuclear Society on May 19
The authors are grateful to Dr. James McQuaid, formerly Chief
& 20, 2011. Remarks by Eric P. Loewen, Ph.D. Vice President/President Elect
Scientists and Director of Science and Technology at Her American Nuclear Society.
Majesty’s Health and Safety Executive, for invaluable input, Ministerie van Infrastructuur en Milieu, 2014. Deltaprogramma:
comments and Discussions. Synthesedocument deelprogramma Veiligheid, DG Ruimte en Water, Directie
Algemeen Waterbeleid en Veiligheid.
Morall, J.F., 1986. A review of the record. Regulation 10 (2), 1986.
MuConsult, B.V., 2014. Maatschappelijke Kosten-batenanalyse ERTMS Datum 12
References maart 2014 Kenmerk IM035 (Societal Cost Benefit Analysis ERTMS, date 12
March 2014) Amersfoort.
Ale, B.J.M., 2005. Tolerable or acceptable, a comparison of risk regulation in the UK Munger, D.F., Bowles, D.S., Boyer, D.D., Davis, D.W., Margo, D.A., Moser, D.A., Regan,
and in the Netherlands. Risk Anal. 25 (2). P.J., Snorteland, N., 2009. Interim tolerable risk guidelines for US army corps of
ANCOLD, 1994, 2004. Australian National Committee on Large Dams, Guidelines on engineers dams. In: Proceedings of the Annual Meeting of the US Society on
Risk Assessment. Dams, Nashville.
Bagnall, David, 2008. Letter to the Editor HSE Magazine March/April 2008. Munson, L.H., 1988. (Chairman), Herrington, W.N., Higby, D.P., Kathren, R.L.,
BC Hydro, 1993. Interim Guidelines for Consequence-Based Dam Safety Evaluations Merwin, S.E., Stoetzel, G.A., Vallaria, E.J. DOE Project Manager, Health Physics
and Improvements, HED Report H2528. Manual Of Good Practices For Reducing Radiation, Exposure To Levels That Are
Bedford, T., 2013. Decision making for group risk reduction: dealing with epistemic As Low As Reasonably Achievable (Alara) June 1988, Prepared for the U.S.
uncertainty. Risk Anal. 33 (10), 1884–1898. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/ Department of Energy Assistant Secretary for Environment, Safety, and Health
risa.12047. under Contract DE-AC06-76RLO 1830.
Blaeij, de A., 2003. The value of statistical life in road safety: a meta-analysis. NN, 1949. Edwards vs The National Coal Board (1949) 1 A11 ER 743.
Accident Anal. Prev. 35, 973–986. NN, 1995. Externe, Externalities of Energy, vol. 2, Methodology, European
Blaeij, Arianne de, 2000. In: Florax, Raymond J.G.M., Rietveld, Piet, Verhoef, Erik Commission EUR 16521 EN.
(Eds.), The Value of Statistical Life in Road Safety: A Meta-Analysis, TI 2000-089/ NN, 2014a. <http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Best_available_technology> (20140412).
3 Tinbergen Institute Discussion Paper. NN, 2014b. <https://www.gov.uk/government/uploads/system/uploads/attachment_
Bockarjova, M., Rietveld, P., Verhoef, E.T., 2008. Valuation of Flood Risk in the data/file/244913/rrcgb2012-02.pdf> (as per 13.12.14).
Netherlands: Some Preliminary Results, ESREL 2008 & 17th SRA Conference, NN, 2014c. <http://orr.gov.uk/__data/assets/pdf_file/0018/2547/rogs_2006_
22–25 September, Valencia, Spain. consolidated_with_amendments.pdf> (as per 13.12.14).
Bockarjova, M., Rietveld, P., Verhoef, E., 2009a. First Results Immaterial Damage Pikaar, M.J., Seaman, M.A., 1995. A Review of Risk Control, Report nr SVS 1994/27A.
Valuation: VOSL in Flood Risk Context – A Stated Preference Study (I). Ministry of Housing Physical Planning and Environment, The Netherlands.
Department of Spatial Economics, VU Amsterdam. Rasmussen, J., 1997. Risk management in a dynamic society: a modeling problem.
Bockarjova, M., Rietveld, P., Verhoef, E., 2009b. First Results Immaterial Damage Saf. Sci. 27 (2/3), 183–213.
Valuation: Value of Statistical Life (VOSL) in Flood Risk Context and Value of Renn, O., 2008. Risk Governance. Coping with Uncertainty in a Complex World.
Travel Time Savings (VOT), A Stated Preference Study (II). Department of Spatial Earthscan, London, ISBN: 978010844-7-291-0.
Economics, VU Amsterdam. Rothery, Dave, 2008. Letter to the Editor HSE Magazine March/April 2008.
Bockarjova, M., Rietveld, P., Verhoef, E., 2009c. First Results Immaterial Damage RSSB, 2014a. Taking Safe Decisions, Rail Safety Standards Board.
Valuation: Value of Statistical Life (VOSL), Value of Evacuation (VOE) and Value RSSB, 2014b. Guidance on the Use of Cost-benefit Analysis When Determining
of Injury (VOI) in Flood Risk Context, a Stated Preference Study (III). Department Whether a Measure is Necessary to Ensure Safety so far as is Reasonably
of Spatial Economics, VU Amsterdam. Practicable, Rail Safety Standards Board.
Brown, A., Godson, J., 2004. An Interim Guide to Quantitative Risk Assessment for RVGZ, 2006. Zinnige en duurzame zorg (Sane and Sustainable Care). Raad voor de
UK Reservoirs. Institution of Civil Engineers. Volksgezondheid en Zorg, Den Haag.
Button, K., 1993. Overview of Internalising the Social Costs of Transport, OECD Slater, D., 1994. Private communication.
ECMT Report. Slovic, P., Fischoff, B., Lichtenstein, S., Read, S., Combs, B., 1978. How safe is safe
CDA, 2007. Dam Safety Guidelines. Canadian Dam Association. enough, a psycho-metric study of attitudes towards technological risks and
Cullen, Lord W., 2001. The Ladbroke Grove Rail Inquiry. Her Majesties Stationary benefits. Policy Sci. 8, 127–152.
Office, Norwich, ISBN: 0 7176 2056 5. Smulders, Y.M., Thijs, A., 2006. Kostprijs per gewonnen levensjaar: trends en
Cullen, Lord, Uff, Prof John, 2001. The Southall and Ladbroke Grove Joint Inquiry into tegenstrijdigheden (Value per Lifeyear Gained, Trends and Contradictions) Ned
Train Protection Systems. HMSO, Norwich, UK, ISBN: 0 7176 1998 2. Tijdschr Geneesk. 2006 11 november, 150(45).
DEFRA, 2013. Guide to Risk Assessment for Reservoir Safety Management. Snowy Mountains Engineering Corporation Limited, 1995. Final Report on the
Department of Environment, Food and Rural Affairs. Environment Agency. Review of Headworks. Office of Water Reform (Department of Conservation and
Deltares, 2011. Maatschappelijke kosten-baten analyse Waterveiligheid 21e eeuw Natural Resources), State of Victoria, Australia.
(Societal Cost Benefit Analysis Water Safety 21 Century) Deltares, 1204144- Tawney, R.H., 1926. Religion and the Rise of Capitalism. Penguin Books.
006-ZWS-0012, 31 maart 2011. Tengs, T.O., Adams, M.E., Pliskin, J.S., Safran, D.G., Siegel, J.E., Weinstein, M., Graham,
DoT, 1995. Department of Transport. Mawhinney Endorses HSC View on Future of J.D., 1995. Five hundred life saving interventions and their cost effectiveness.
Automatic Train Protection. DoT Press Notice 98, 30 March 1995. Risk Anal. 15, 369–390.
Det Norsk Veritas (DNV), 2011. Verification for Compliance with UK Shelf Regulations, The Supreme Court, 2011a. UKSC 17 on Appeal from [2009] EWCA Civ 499 dd 13
Offshore Service Specification, DNV-OSS-202Ó. <http://www.dnv.com>. April 2011, nr. 214, p. 96.
100 B.J.M. Ale et al. / Safety Science 76 (2015) 90–100

The Supreme Court, 2011b. UKSC 17 on Appeal from [2009] EWCA Civ 499 dd 13 Vlek, C.A.J., 1996. A multi-stage, multi-level and multi-attribute perspective on risk
April 2011, nr. 184, p. 83. assessment decision making and risk control. Risk Decis. Policy 1 (1996), 9–31.
TK, 1988. Omgaan met Risico’s, Tweede Kamer, vergaderjaar 1988–1989, 21137, nr. Vlek, C., Stallen, P.-J., 1981. Judging risks and benefits in the small and in the large.
5. Under the Same Number the Translation in English is Titled: Premises for Risk Organiz. Behav. Human Perform. 28 (2), 235–271.
Management TK (2001) Records of the Second Chamber of Parliament of the Vlek, C.A.J., Stemerding, S., 1984. Beschrijving en beoordeling van risico’s verbonden
Netherlands, year 2001–2003, 27603 nr. 52. aan het gebruik van gevaarlijke stoffen. Deelrapport I. Probleemstelling,
United Kingdom Government, 2005. The Offshore Installations (Safety Case) projectoverzicht, samenvatting, conclusies en aanbevelingen (Description and
Regulations 2005, Statutory Instrument 2005 No. 3117. The Stationary Office Judgement of Risks Associated with the Use of Hazardous Materials. Part 1,
Limited. Problem-Statement, Project Description, Summary, Conclusions and
United States Bureau of Reclamation, 1986. Guidelines on Decision Analysis, ACER Recommendations) IVEM-rapport nr. 3. Groningen 1984.
Technical Memorandum No. 7, US Department of the Interior. Vlek, C., Kuyper, H., Boer, H., 1983. Large-scale Risk as a Problem of Technological,
United States Bureau of Reclamation, 1997/2003. Guidelines for Achieving Public Psychological and Political Judgement, Environmental Impact Assessment,
Protection in Dam Safety Decision Making. US Department of the Interior. Technology Assessment, and Risk Analysis. roc.
Viscusi, W.K., Aldy, J., 2003. The value of a statistical life: a critical review of market
estimates throughout the world. J. Risk Uncertain. 27, 5–76.

You might also like