You are on page 1of 78

See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.

net/publication/31439318

Rethinking Mammalian Brain Evolution

Article  in  Integrative and Comparative Biology · July 1990


DOI: 10.1093/icb/30.3.629 · Source: OAI

CITATIONS READS

252 3,088

1 author:

Terrence W Deacon
University of California, Berkeley
141 PUBLICATIONS   11,242 CITATIONS   

SEE PROFILE

Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:

Emergent Dynamics View project

All content following this page was uploaded by Terrence W Deacon on 25 July 2014.

The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file.


Rethinking Mammalian Brain Evolution1

Harvard University, Peabody Museum, Cambridge, Massachusetts 02138

SYNOPSIS. A critical review of past and current theories of mammalian brain evolution
is presented in order to discuss conceptual problems that persist in the field. Problems
with the concept of homology arise because of the interaction of cell lineages and axonal
connectivity in the determination of structural features of the brain. Focusing on the
continuity of information represented by ontogenetic mechanisms as opposed to mor-
phological features avoids many of these problems and suggests homological relationships
that otherwise have gone unnoticed. Many apparently progressive trends and parallelisms
in mammalian brain evolution turn out to result from the influence of underlying devel-
opmental homologies. Confusions about evolutionary advancement, increasing architec-
tonic differentiation, and the evolution of new brain structures result from a failure to
appreciate how increasing brain size can bias developmental processes with respect to
axonal competition, increased cellular metabolic demands and decreased information
processing efficiency. Explanations of the evolution of novel structures and new connec-
tional patterns are criticized for their failure to consider the constraints of neural devel-
opmental processes. T h e correlations between structural neogenesis, functional special-
ization and size changes in brain evolution are explained by a theory of competitive
displacement of neural connections by others during development under the biasing
influences of differential allometry, cell death or axon-target affinity changes. T h e "dis-
placement hypothesis" is used to propose speculative accounts for the differential enlarge-
ment and multiplication of cortical areas, the origins of mammalian isocortex, the unusual
features of dolphin cortex and the dramatic structural and functional reorganizations that
characterize human brain evolution.

I NTRODUCTION required to even begin to grapple with the


Intrinsic difficulties questions in a meaningful way. T h e dis-
turbing correlate of this is that speculative
Despite the fact that the evolution of the
theories concerning brain evolutionó
brain-particularly the human brain-is
especially human brain evolution-are
of intrinsic interest to anyone curious about
widespread and often contain relatively lit-
the human mind and the origins of human
tle neuroanatomical or neurophysiological
nature, the scientific study of brain evo-
information. But even theories conceived
lution is not a major subdiscipline within
by neuroanatomists and neurophysiolo-
biology, psychology, anthropology or even
gists often reflect numerous unsupported
the neurosciences. T h e apparently poor
assumptions about the direction of evolu-
representation of this area of study in the
tionary trends, the nature of natural selec-
sciences can in part be attributed to the
tion affecting brain processes, the ways that
paucity of direct paleontological evidence
brains can vary from one species to another,
regarding brain evolution and the long-
the relationship between structure and
time inaccessibility of crucial comparative
function within the brain and even the
neuroanatomic details. T h e poor repre-
nature of intelligence itself. Although
sentation of information about brain evo-
paleoneurology is unlikely to experience
lution in disciplines outside the neurosci-
sudden advances in the years to come, many
ences is additionally limited by the
of the barriers to relevant neuroanatomi-
considerable sophistication in comparative
cal evidence have dissolved in the wake of
neuroanatomy and physiology that is
the introduction of many new experimen-
tal techniques in recent decades. Now that
many of the technical impediments stand-
' From the Symposium on Science as a Way of Know- i n g in the way of detailed knowledge about
ing-Neurobiology and Behavior organized by Edward
S. Hodgson and presented at the Centennial Meeting brain structure and function have been
of the American Society of Zoologists, 27-30 Decem- removed, many of these hitherto unques-
ber 1989, at Boston, Massachusetts. tioned assumptions are now open to test.
Among colleagues in the neurosciences of most species. This level of analysis is
one sometimes hears the criticism that, made possible by the immensity and com-
unlike most other areas of neuroscience, plexity of the existing genomes. In many
the study of brain evolution is limited to cases even direct fossil evidence of appar-
theory because it is essentially beyond the ent phylogenetic relationships has been
reach of experimental approaches. abandoned in the face of contrary molec-
Although brains of extinct species are not ular information. As nearly limitless sources
available for direct inspection and analysis, of correlative molecular evidence are fed
this does not necessarily mean that theories into phylogenetic analyses in the near
of brain evolution are empirically untest- future they will become immensely more
able. Indeed they are every bit as suscep- reliable for the determination of phylog-
tible to experimental investigation and eny than the best of all possible fossil finds.
testing as are other theories of brain orga- Living organisms are incredibly complex
nization and function. T h e approach must systems at all levels of scale. Each molec-
necessarily be indirect, but it need be no ular and organ system within an organism
less effectual nor any less scientific o r embodies within its design the ubiquitous
experimental. We should remember that mark of its particular evolutionary history.
the vast majority of scientific data in any In addition, the processes of embryogen-
field is indirect, irrespective of whether the esis that direct the construction of these
object under study is directly observable. systems are themselves products and symp-
From tracks left by subatomic particles in toms of an evolutionary past that a t various
nuclear accelerators to the measurements levels intersects with the ancestries of other
of minute amounts of unseen biochemicals species. Comparisons of the differences and
registered in scintillation counters, nearly similarities among molecular systems,
all of the "hard data" generated in the organ systems and developmental pro-
laboratories of any field of the natural sci- cesses in different species provide an almost
ences are indirect and circumstantial. It is limitless source of information for inves-
not the directness o r indirectness of the tigating the evolution of biological struc-
data that is important, rather it is the tures. This is ultimately the final arbiter of
repeatability of the findings and the coher- any analysis of evolutionary relation-
ence of many lines of evidence that are ships-even for paleontological data—
crucial to scientific knowledge. since the interpretation of fossils is only as
A good analogy t o the study of brain accurate and complete as the information
evolution is provided by the study of gene we have about living counterparts.
evolution. Modern techniques for analyz- T h e complexity of the vertebrate brain
ing and comparing base sequences of DNA rivals or exceeds the complexity of all the
molecules from living organisms are begin- other organ systems of the body consid-
ning to provide a truly astronomical fund ered together. Because of this we should
of information concerning both molecular expect that information derived from the
and organismal evolution. Without analyz- brains of living species will be more than
ing a single fossil specimen of DNA we are adequate to the task of investigating brain
nonetheless capable of reconstructing large evolution, so long as we are willing and able
fractions of the genomes of extinct species, to approach the task with the level of
characterizing major gene duplication and sophistication demanded by it. Given this
reorganization events of the distant past, complexity and our still primitive under-
and predicting the ancestral lineages of liv- standing of brain organizati'on and func-
ing species and the approximate dates of tion, we must be prepared to integrate
their divergences. Al this is available today information from a variety of subfields of
despite the fact that only miniscule por- neuroscience and evolutionary biology in
tions of the DNA in even the best studied order to begin to approach the problems
species are actually known and virtually of brain evolution with any clarity.
nothing is directly known about the DNA Although numerous researchers since the
nineteenth century have pursued the study ing techniques were developed that took
of brain evolution, most have focused on advantage of the in vivo uptake and axonal
a single source of evidence to support their transport. of amino acids, macromolecules
theories, including: relative brain size (e.g., and certain fluorescent dyes. These tech-
apparent trends in brain size increase); fea- niques have now made it possible to inves-
tures of cortical surface morphology (e.g., tigate the organization of axonal circuitry
the appearance or reorganization of sulci); in full microscopic detail. In this regard
relative sizes of macroscopic brain struc- the most basic functional anatomy of the
tures with respect to one another (e.g., the brain has at last become available for study.
apparent enlargement of isocortex with We are still far from possessing a complete
respect t o limbic cortex in presumed connectional characterization for even the
"advanced" brains); or cyto- and myelo- best studied of mammalian brains, yet
architectonic features (e.g., the apparent already the scattered details from compar-
enlargement of association cortex in the ative studies have begun to provide a
cerebral cortices of "advanced" species). remarkable array of new insights into the
But uni-dimensional approaches are almost patterns of brain diversity.
certain to lead into one misleading cul-de- Now that tracer techniques have filled
sac after another. This has been the fate this crucial gap in information about basic
of many past theories, just as it will surely neural functional anatomy, these data can
also be the fate of the corresponding uni- be integrated with data from physiological
dimensional theories of the present. T h e and quantitative studies to provide all the
only hopeful approach is to integrate rel- pieces of evidence necessary for investi-
evant information from many lines of neu- gating the principles underlying brain evo-
robiological research that bear on the lution. However, it is insufficient to apply
questions of the patterns of variation and the analysis to adult brains only. Probably
constraint exhibited by the brains of dif- the most crucial information for evolu-
ferent species. tionary purposes is how connection pat-
terns and structural differentiation are ini-
Experimental approaches tially established in a developing brain. New
A number of recent technical advances techniques for labeling mitotic cells, mark-
have significantly augmented the infor- ing cell lineages, and experimentally alter-
mation previously available to comparative ing development in neonatal animals o r in
neuroanatomists. Unlike many other organ utero by removing o r transplanting embry-
systems, the functionally relevant features onic tissues are also beginning to provide
of brain anatomy are entirely microscopic detailed information about the develop-
and for many decades were nearly impos- mental processes that shape neural circuits.
sible to distinguish even under the micro- Developmental information can play a cru-
scope. T h e axonal connections linking cial role in settling questions of homology.
neuron to neuron, though visible for short More generally, it can provide evidence for
distances in Golgi-stained material (avail- the range of possible mechanisms available
able since the turn of the century), have for natural selection to modify and dem-
only become amenable to study in recent onstrates the constraints that limit possible
decades. In the 1950s techniques were per- variation. Many scenarios of brain evolu-
fected for visualizing degenerating axons. tion conceived in the absence of critical
With these techniques it was possible to information about the development of the
identify the general patterns of long axonal structures in question turn out to be incom-
connections in the brains of experimental patible with these constraints.
animals. However, the resolution and sen- This rapidly growing body of neuro-
sitivity of these techniques were insuffi- biological information is providing an
cient t o resolve many of the finer details unprecedented opportunity to discover new
of axonal connection patterns. Beginning patterns of similarity and variation in brain
in the mid 1970s a number of axonal trac- evolution, and to test old and new hypoth-
eses about neural evolutionary processes. influence they exert over contemporary
It also provides impetus for a critical reex- ideas about brain function in general. T h e
amination of the dogmas and unanalyzed first of these is the concept of homology-
assumptions that currently dominate the relationship shared by structures by
thinking about brain evolution. virtue of sharing a common ancestry. T h e
second is the notion of evolutionary progress
Conceptual problems o r orthogenesis-the idea that evolution
Most of the theories concerning brain proceeds in a particular direction of
evolution in the early part of the 20th cen- improvement or development. T h e third
tury focused on its most studiable features, is the significance of brain size-both in
size, gross morphology, and cytoarchitec- absolute terms and relative to the body or
ture. Crude connectional information was to component brain structures. T h e fourth
available only from careful dissections and is the problem of identifying and explain-
what little could be discerned with Golgi- ing neogenesis-the evolution of new struc-
staining. Despite the unavailability of cru- tures and functions.
cial categories of information, theories of All four conceptual issues were familiar
brain evolution have flourished. As a result to the 19th century pioneers in this field
modern students entering this field will find whose major assumptions in all these areas
the literature replete with numerous well remain dominant in many contemporary
accepted dogmas about the general char- treatments of the subject. Contemporary
acter of brain evolution espoused by some versions of these ideas are in the back-
of the century's most brilliant comparative ground of every theory of brain function
neuroanatomists. Even more daunting is as well as every attempt to articulate a the-
the fact that many of these dogmas have ory of brain evolution. Despite a century
become seamlessly woven into the anatom- of advances in evolutionary thinking in
ical and functional terminology of the rest other fields of biology these ideas within
of the neurosciences as well. Terms like the neurosciences still carry the distinct
paleocortex, neocortex, primary areas, imprint of late 19th century evolutionism.
secondary areas, projection cortex and And despite a century of experimental
association cortex all bear the stamp of an investigation of brain function these ideas
evolutionary vision that appears beyond still reflect one or the other side of the 19th
question, a part of the unspoken common century debates over associationistic and
knowledge of the neurosciences. But with holistic theories of mental function. Exor-
the recent advent of new tools and a flood cising these influences is one of the central
of new information concerning neural con- purposes of this presentation.
nections, functions and ontogenetic pro- The other major purpose is to present
cesses, there has been a growing disso- an alternative approach to the study of
nance between the new data and some of brain evolution that avoids many of'these
the well-established principles of brain evo- a priori assumptions. Many of these
lution. My purpose here is to play devil's assumptions have been derive'd f r o m
advocate; to question even the most well attempts to arrange the adult nervous sys-
founded of these dogmas and adopt the tems of contemporary species in some sort
heretical stance that many-if not most- of evolutionary sequence o r cladistic den-
of the traditional assumptions concerning drogram so that any two may be linked via
neural evolutionary processes are without some intermediate adult forms. While this
foundation. Hopefully, the introduction of is a powerful heuristic it tends to imply the
a healthy dose of skepticism will allow us misleading conclusion that the mecha-
to look at the problem of brain evolution nisms for evolutionary change can be accu-
with fresh eyes. rately described in terms of the modifica-
Four major conceptual problem areas will tion of adult forms. This, of course, misses
be reexamined most carefully because of a crucial intervening level of analysis. Ulti-
their potential for misdirecting the study mately, the mechanisms of evolutionary
of brain evolution and also because of the change must be explained in terms of the
ontogenetic processes and developmental CLADlSTlC COMPARISON CLADlSTlC HOMOLOGV

constraints that build brains. Explanations C


of evolutionary change that are not cast in
developmental terms are merely disguised
comparative morphological descriptions.
Consequently, the reviews and criticisms
presented will constantly appeal to devel-
opmental data to test the plausibility and
PARALLEL HOMOPLASY CONVERGENT HOMOPLASY
consistency of some of the dominant the-
ories of brain evolution. Finally, in the last
two sections many of these developmental
insights will be utilized to outline an alter-
native ontogenetically based interpreta-
tion of the processes underlying brain evo-
lution in mammals. This interpretation of
brain reorganization events-called the FIG. 1. Homology relationships. T h e basic homol-
ogy relationships as outlined by Northcutt (1984). T h e
"displacement hypothesis"-suggests that arrows represent descent relationships. T h e vertical
there is an interdependent relationship axis represents comparison over time o r descent in
bdtween differential growth of particular evolution and the horizontal dimension represents
neural cell groups and competitive-regres- comparison of contemporaneous species. T h e geo-
sive processes in brain development that metric shapes represent similar o r different, ancestral
o r derived traits. In the case of parallel homoplasy it
constrain patterns of brain evolution, often is unclear whether the parallel divergence from the
resulting in parallel or converging trends. ancestral condition is a consequence of internal (ho-
Two particularly enigmatic cases are exam- mological) o r external (selectional) commonalities.
ined in t h e last section- dolphin a n d These same relationships can be applied equally t o
comparisons between lineages o r to homologous rep-
human brain evolution-and are inter- etition of parts within an organism. (Redrawn from
preted in terms of displacement processes. Northcutt, 1984.)
Features of these brains that previously
have been difficult to explain o r seemed
beyond study become understandable in applied to traits that exhibit structural o r
terms of the displacement hypothesis. functional similarities but which are not
derived from common ancestry. In other
H OMOLOGY words, their similarity is the result of influ-
ences extrinsic to the organism. T h e other,
The concepts of homology and homoplasy parallel homoplasy, has traditionally been
T h e concept of homology in some form termed parallelism and refers to cases where
is essential to any study of evolutionary there is similarity in both form and com-
morphology. It defines the warp of evo- mon ancestry but where the formal simi-
lutionary continuity with respect to which larity between traits is not shared in the
the weft of diverse adaptations can be common ancestral condition. I n o t h e r
understood. I n a useful summary of the words, the formal similarity of the (patris-
problems of homology in comparative neu- tically) homologous parts is presumed t o
roscience Northcutt (1984) distinguishes have arisen independently in the two lin-
patristic homologies (the actual descent rela- eages after divergence from the common
tionship between an ancestral form and a ancestor. In this case there is both a patris-
present form) from cladistic homologies (the tic homological relationship and a cladistic
comparison of extant forms with respect convergent homoplaseous relationship
to their possible common ancestral rela- involved. T h e parallel divergence of the
tionships) and then contrasts these with two two descendent traits from the common
forms of dishornology that may be con- ancestral condition is presumably the result
fused with homology. One of these, con- of common extrinsic selection pressures.
vergent homoplasy, corresponds to what has These relationships are schematized in Fig-
traditionally been termed analogy and is ure 1 (redrawn from Northcutt, 1984).
Where the ancestral condition is the nuity of function. Although the particular
unknown feature to be inferred from cla- features of the individual components of
distic comparisons it can be quite difficult the organism may change over evolution-
t o distinguish homology from these two ary time the systemic relationships among
forms of homoplasy. Northcutt, following parts, including their contiguity relation-
Wiley (1981) and others, suggests a num- ships, are relatively stable. Even when
ber of guidelines for aiding this discrimi- structures derived from a common evolu-
nation, including: (1) sharing deep similar- tionary precursor have diverged in form
ities of form (as opposed t o merely so as to share no superficial resemblance
superficial resemblances), (2) sharing com- their relationships t o o t h e r structures
mon epigenetic precedence (i.e., derivation within the organism, both in the adult form
from common ontogenetic precursor and at various stages of development, will
structures), and (3) the existence of a con- exhibit sufficient similarity to indicate their
tinuity of intermediate forms in species homology.
intermediate in relationship between the T h e usefulness of topological criteria for
two being compared. All there criteria are the determination of homological similar-
versions of the identification of similarity ities derives from the fact that many mor-
in some form. phological traits (although not the under-
In this discussion I will not review the lying genes themselves) are determined by
various problems encountered in attempt- systemic interactions between morphoge-
ing to determine neural homologies in netic fields (or other converging morpho-
practice, nor will I discuss methodological genetic influences) and not by independent
strategies for circumventing these prob- local mechanisms. T h e information that
lems and the multiple criteria that must be determines a morphogenetic field inevit-
satisfied to provide a convincing case. These ably derives from multiple genetic sources
have been well reviewed elsewhere (Camp- interacting with one another sequentially
bell, 1982; Campbell and Hodos, 1970; and simultaneously during ontogenesis.
Ghiselin, 1976; Northcutt, 1984). T h e T h e resultant morphological trait is a bit
point of this discussion is to analyze the like a node within a network that has no
concept itself as it is applied to problems independent existence apart from, its rel-
of brain evolution because I think there is ative position. Such a node is defined by
reason to be suspicious of the assumptions its unique convergence of relationships with
implicit in its common usage. It is not the other nodes. If some of these relationships
empirical determination of homology that are lost or new ones are gained, continuity
is at issue, but the concept itself. I will argue with the previous state becomes ambiguous
that there is something fundamentally and depends on whether you focus on the
wrong with the notion of homology as it is relationships o r the nodes. Analogously, a
applied to the comparison of morpholog- single morphological feature may become
ical features that can become especially two if interdependent morphogenetic pro-
troublesome in the analysis of brain struc- cesses decouple in space o r time, but two
ture. features may also fuse t o become one if
previously noninteracting morphogenetic
Problems with the concept of homology processes become subsequently linked and
Homological relationships a r e most interdependent.
clearly exhibited in topological relation- This possibility is more likely in the brain
ships. A focus on topological continuity for than in other organs by virtue of the fact
identifying homology dates back to the ear- that brain traits are defined in terms of two
liest pre-evolutionary theories about the independent topological criteria: (1) cell
vertebrate "Bauplan" (an insightful his- lineage relationships of local populations
torical discussion is provided in Russell, that may determine local topological rela-
19 16). Because organisms are spatially tionships, cell structure, and molecular and
organized systems, position within a net- neurotransmitter characteristics; and (2)
work of relationships is crucial to conti- connectional relationships determined by
axons that link numerous separated tar- to happen in cerebral cortex, as indicated
gets, each likely derived from different cell by heterotopic transplantation experi-
lineages, which may also influence mor- ments) it might appear on these grounds
phological, cellular and functional char- that an ancestral target has simply become
acteristics of their various target struc- displaced to a new position, despite the fact
tures. Both cellular and connectional that cell lineages and some connectional
attributes interact during development to relationships did not follow this shift. With
determine the architecture and function of a large number of criteria in agreement,
a brain region. but cell lineage and a few connectional
Assuming that connectivity is capable of relationships do not follow this shift. With
changing during the course of evolution it difficult to decide between the deaffer-
is not hard to imagine the kinds of diffi- ented target o r the invaded target as the
culties that might arise in interpreting appropriate homologue of the ancestral
homologies. T h e position, cellular char- structure. At the level of the whole struc-
acteristics and even embryonic origins of ture the judgment is ambiguous and yet
a brain structure in a descendent species each underlying trait has a homologous pair
may be derived from a corresponding that can be traced in unbroken series to a
stricture in some ancestor, and the descen- common ancestral condition. It is not clear
dent structure's connectional relationships that shifting the analysis to these under-
may also be derived from connection pat- lying traits can escape similar problems at
terns in that same ancestor. Yet the par- a yet lower level. As we consider evolu-
ticular homologous circuit and homolo- tionary "interventions" that might alter
gous structure may not have been progressively earlier stages of ontogeny it
associated with each other in the brain of is possible to imagine increasing loss of
that ancestor. For example, it is conceiv- descent criteria in this manner.
able that qseries of evolutionary events can A similar complication can arise in the
cause afferents of one brain structure to effort to identify homologous sulci in rel-
invade some other structure, replacing the atively convoluted brains. Prior to the
"ancestral" afferents of the new target— development of techniques for unambig-
similar effects can be induced experimen- uously staining myelin o r neuron cell bod-
tally (see below). In this event a connec- ies the interpretation of sulcal homologies
tional or circuit homology will have been in different species brains was considered
maintained, probably retaining its func- the best clue to the structural homology of
tional characteristics, but the relationship underlying regions, and this approach
between cellularly defined homologues and dominated throughout the early part of
connectionally defined homologues will this century (Ariëns Kappers et al. , 1936).
have become dissociated. T h e structural Although it has recently been abandoned
homology can no longer be defined with as unreliable for most comparative work,
respect to position within a network and it still remains the only evidence for paleo-
the connectional homology can no longer neurology (working with the casts of fos-
be defined with respect to the structures silized crania). In the study of human evo-
that are connected. Continuity with the lution this has been t h e source f o r
ancestral form can nonetheless still be continuing heated debates over the origins
traced through the remaining descent rela- of "modern" human brain traits (e.g., Falk,
tionships in each case, though the number 1980, 1983, 1989; Holloway, 1981, 1984,
of topological criteria used to identify this 1985, 1988).
descent has diminished for each. Most cortical sulci are probably the result
Further deterioration of homology cri- of the interactions between the mechanical
teria can also be imagined. For example, if forces and constraints imposed by the cra-
the connectional relationships play a sig- nial cavity, differences in growth rates of
nificant role in determining the local brain areas, and relative elasticity of dif-
cytoarchitecture a n d neurotransmitter ferent areas of the developing cortex and
characteristics of a target area (this appears underlying white matter. If the underlying
neural substrate influencing the formation trait is only the surface expression of
of a sulcus changes o r becomes displaced underlying information. This information
with respect to cranial landmarks in sub- is encoded both in gene sequence and in
sequent lineages it may cause the position the topological and temporal conditions of
of the sulcus to follow. If this were the their expression in the developing organ-
typical case sulci might be relatively good ism. T h e confluence of multiple indepen-
indicators of underlying brain structure dent sources and kinds of epigenetic infor-
homologies. Alternatively, changes in bone mation to form a particular structure
growth patterns of the skull o r changes of implies that no particular individual thread
the absolute size of the brain with respect of information constitutes an indispensable
to the skull in subsequent lineages may pro- link between homologous structures. A
duce changes in mechanical forces influ- homology exists so long as some relation-
encing sulcal position and cause a sulcus to ships between the remaining sources of
shift to a new location without any corre- information are maintained. Alternatively,
sponding change in position of the original if separate threads of information are
neural substrate. In this case the link passed down from generation to genera-
between sulcal and neural homologies tion independently and only brought into
would be broken. However, if the appear- relation with one another in some descen-
ance of a particular sulcus is dependent on dent where their interaction produces a
the combined influence of both extrinsic novel structure, we must consider the
mechanical forces and intrinsic growth structure as emergent and neoplastic (the
processes of the neural tissue, then spatial newly established relationships between
separation of these two independent influ- these threads of information is itself a bit
ences may cause a sulcus to disappear and of information that is unprecedented) and
then reappear in some later lineage in yet also recognize the complete homology
which these influences again become of underlying component morphogenetic
realigned. This atavism would still be a case processes. T h e relationship is diagrammed
of homology, despite the discontinuity in in Figure 2. Because ontogenetic processes
descent. Finally, if a particular sulcus can are multileveled, homological relation-
be induced by either influence alone then ships must also be multileveled (Alberch,
spatial separation of extrinsic and intrinsic 1982; Fasolo and Malacarne, 1988), with
factors may also produce two sulci where homologies at higher levels not necessarily
one existed previously. I n this case, reduceable to those at lower levels. In addi-
although each is patristically homologous tion, homologies at every level above that
with the ancestral condition, it is unclear of the genes are to some extent ephemeral,
whether they can be said to be cladistically capable of dissolving and reconstituting in
homologous to each other. All of these pos- the course of evolution because they are
sibilities demonstrate the dangers of treat- determined only in relational terms. This
ing sulci as definitive markers of underly- also implies that the same bit of epigenetic
ing neural homologies. information expressed in a different con-
Similar problems with the strict descent text within the same organism must also
interprktation of homology have been be understood as homological.
noted with respect to non-neurological
comparative problems, causing some Homologies between the different
authors (e.g., von Cranach, 1976; Filler, parts of a brain
1986) to: suggest that the homology con- T h e interpretation of homolo gy as com-
cept should be entirely abandoned. But an mon information is crucial to another clas-
alternative approach is suggested by these sic use of the concept of homology: serial
problematic examples. T h e crucial ques- homology or homological multiplication of parts.
t ions we are trying to answer by identifying Repeated similar parts in the segments of
homologies are questions about continuity a worm, similar vertebrae in different posi-
of information (Van Valen, 1982). A mor- tions along the spinal column, similarities
phological structure or any other manifest in limb and digit structure, and bilaterally
symmetric parts of the body in general are ontogenetic interactions

all examples of homologous repeated parts.


Although not descended from any single
morphological phenotypes
ancestral structure, such homologous parts level
undoubtedly inherit their similarities of
form from a single ancestral source of epigenetic
developmental information. Within the process level

central nervous system there are examples


of classic serial homology in segmental
spinal cord circuitry, bilaterally symmetric
parts at all,levels, and multiple homologous
parts within every structure at many levels morphological phenotypes
homoplasy
of organization.
Starting on a small scale we recognize intervening
that nearly all neurons exhibit homologous epigenetic
homologies
variables
producing
axons, dendrites, synapses, etc. developmenlal
plasticity
within the same structure there are classes
of neurons with homologous patterns of FIG. 2. Developmental homologies. T h e multiple
level problem of developmental homologies is depicted
dendritic arborization, axonal targets and in a highly schematic form by representing interact-
neurotransmitters. Local circuit patterns ing morphogenetic processes as arrows and the resul-
of nearby neuronal groups also exhibit tant morphological traits as geometric shapes. T h e
homologies, such as are found among cor- upper figure shows that the homological relationships
could be analyzed either at the morphological level
tical lamina and cortical columns in iso- by comparing morphological (or even behavioral)
cortex. Even distributed functional circuits phenotypes o r at the epigenetic process level by com-
linking separate structures may be serially paring epigenetic mechanisms. Both are phenotypes
homologous: e.g., projections from differ- that indirectly represent underlying genotypes but
the higher level analysis condenses information rep-
ent' thalamic nuclei to different cortical resented at the lower level by distinct processes and
areas. Even structures that are superficially can thereby miss considerable underlying develop-
quite distinct may exhibit underlying mental homology. Nonetheless the higher level anal-
homologies at some levels but not others. ysis also takes into account conserved o r derived rela-
This might be the case for the relationship tionships between underlying developmental
mechanisms that may themselves be homologous in
between the hippocampus and the isocor- two lineages but which produce non-similar diverging
tex, which exhibit many features in com- phenotypes. Of course the actual condition involves
mon at the cellular level and have homol- many more than two levels. T h e lower level "epige-
ogous patterns of afferents and efferents netic mechanisms" are likely themselves the products
of relationships between yet lower level cellular o r
yet very different laminar architecture. molecular processes and the "phenotypic level" may
Homologies between different brain also be a set of epigenetic mechanisms of a higher
regions might possibly develop as a result level of complexity. Hierarchic analysis cannot be
of derivation from a common undifferen- avoided.
tiated ancestral structure, but descent
homology need not be defined at the struc-
tural level only. It may also result from homologous structures may appear simul-
independent expression of the same under- taneously in development by independent
lying epigenetic information. Similarly, expression of the same underlying infor-
during ontogeny homologies between cell mation activated by some common molec-
types may develop by descent from a com- ular trigger or internal timing mechanism.
mon embryogenetic cell lineage a n d Within a number of areas of the brain it
homologies between complex structures is likely that cell lineage is not the only and
may develop because they were each perhaps not even the major determinant
derived in a process of differentiation from of cellular, structural o r functional homol-
some common embryological structure. ogies. For a few brain areas there is now
However, because all cells share the same evidence that a single precurser cell can
genetic information, it is also possible that give rise to the multiple cell types within
that region (Rakic, 1988) and studies uti- cept of functional homology. It can be
lizing embryonic chimeras composed of two defined as the similarity and continuity that
immunologically distinguishable genomes exist between functions as a result of
demonstrate that cells from both lineages homologies between their substrates. T h e
are effectively scattered diffusely through- evolution of new functions by the modifi-
out all areas and representing all cell types cation of old structures is a common theme
(Goldowitz, 1987). Cell lineage probably in evolution. When the vertebrate fore-
determines many local biochemical char- limb evolved the capacity for flight in the
acteristics of neurons (Fasolo and Mala- evolution of birds, the skeletal, muscular
carne, 1988) and certain structural archi- and neural structures retained the general
tectonic features (e.g., Kuljis and Rakic, "Bauplan" of the ancestral terrestrial con-
1988) and it may provide gross areal dif- dition and also retained numerous func-
ferences distinguishing major morphoge- tional constraints. These have all played a
netic fields, but at the present time there role in shaping flying behavior in bird
is little positive evidence available on this species. Additionally, the peripheral motor
point and extensive evidence that extrinsic neural architecture (Sokoloff et al., 1989)
influences determine function and neural and even features of the central locomotor
connectivity to a large degree (O'Leary, "patterns" (Kaplan and Goslow, 1989)
1989). Timing of final mitosis and inter- exhibit strong similarities in birds and ter-
cellular interactions also appear to play sig- restrial quadrupeds, despite t h e o t h e r
nificant roles in determining neuronal cel- major functional differences that their
lular types and local structural and exclusive adaptations demanded.
functional characteristics. With the differentiation of new neural
In general, a major part of structural circuits from ancestral circuits and the
differentiation in the developing brain is elaboration of corresponding new func-
based on distributed information that is tional adaptations we can expect to trace
embodied systemically in its spatial-tem- functional homologies in the form of
poral organization and dynamically in the underlying functional similarities and con-
axonal interactions between indepen- straints. Even in extreme cases in which
dently derived neuronal populations. T h e neural structure is co-opted for new adap-
details of this process will be discussed in tations that are radically different than the
later sections, but in terms of homology ancestral function, the underlying homol-
this fact leads to an important conclusion. ogies will likely exert a major organizing
If the information distinguishing one influence on the form and range of vari-
region from others is not entirely embod- ability of the new function. This may eyen
ied within the cells of that region, but is be true of such a novel adaptation as the
expressed only as those cells are contacted syntactic structure of language (e.g., Reyn-
by invading axons and as its own axons olds, 1976; Lieberman, 1984; Deacon,
establish efferent terminations, then dif- 1990c), if some of the cortical systems that
ferent serially homologous structures came to serve language functions in the
within the brain (e.g., different cortical course of human evolution had been ante-
regions) do not ultimately determine their cedently adapted for other behaviors (e.g.,
own distinctions of structure and function. motor planning). Anatomical evidence for
Their unique specializations with respect such a view is presented by Deacon (1 988a,
to one another are instead derived from 1990c).
network relationships with other areas of Functional homologies should also be
the brain (both cortical and subcortical). exhibited by serially homologous struc-
tures within the same brain. For example
Functional homology the many homologous structural features
One last use of the concept of homology shared by all regions of isocortex suggest
tnust be introduced at this stage before that there should be strong functional
moving on to a discussion of some of the homologies shared by all of its functional
major theories of brain evolution: the con- subdivisions despite the radical differences
in modality of their input-output relation- we have appeared only recently after a long
ships (Diamond, 1979). T h e same may also period of brain evolution characterized by
be said of the different regions and sub- less intelligent species, our brain repre-
divisions of the basal ganglia (Alexander sents the pinnacle of some long evolution-
and Strick, 1986). Presumably, the affer- ary trend.
ents to each homologous area transmit dis- From these few assumptions a great many
tinct forms of information that are sub- predictions must follow, and so from the
jected to some common neural calculation outset we feel confident in assuming the
in each homologous area. For this reason, answers to a number of central questions:
different scenarios for the phylogenetic bigger brains are smarter brains; more
ancestry of brain structures that suggest complex brains are more developed brains;
different ancestor-descent relationships primates are smarter than other species;
bring with them different predictions con- our closest relatives, the great apes, are
cerning function. smarter than other primates; there is an
evolutionary trend toward increased intel-
PROGRESSION ligence; more intelligence is always a supe-
rior adaptation to less; brain evolution tends
The assumption of evolutionary progress toward increasing complexity and increased
T h e idea of progressive evolution is a relative brain size; earlier stages of brain
product of the uneasy marriage between evolution are characterized by more prim-
Darwinism and the scala naturae theories itive, relatively less differentiated and rel-
of the mid 19th century. It received its atively smaller brains than later stages; parts
clearest expression in the theories of Spen- of the brain that are relatively undiffer-
cer, Haeckel, Berg and Teilhard de Char- entiated are more primitive and parts that
din among o t h e r influential writers. are more complex are more recent; brain
Althou h evolutionary biologists in recent structures that enlarged most in ourselves
decades have learned to rigorously avoid and our close ancestors are the most highly
making such assumptions when thinking developed and most recent brain struc-
about a particular assemblage of fossils o r tures; the most recent human functions (i.e.,
a lineage of species, this habit of thought language) must be controlled by the most
is not so well entrenched in the neurosci- advanced, complex and recent structures
ences, nor in anthropology, psychology or in the brain; etc. All we need to d o is to
linguistics where theories and assumptions find out how the data concerning brain size
about human brain evolution are also likely and brain structure diversity demonstrate
to be found. T h e tendency is so pervasive these points! Presumably, whatever fea-
that evolution is often considered synon- tures of brain organization we use to com-
ymous with progress, whereas evolution- pare brains of different species, Homo sapi-
ary change without progress, even when ens should represent the extreme high end
directional, is often not considered evolu- of the scale (however this is defined in each
tion at all, merely "drift." case). I call this assumption the "Anthro-
T h e ubiquity of the idea of progress in pocentric Maxim."
brain evolution can be traced to what we T h e tenacious hold of anthropocentrism
believe we already know about our own on our thinking about brain evolution is
place in an intellectual chain of being. It great. What is needed is a biological equiv-
apparently goes without saying that humans alent of the "Copernican Revolution" to
are the smartest species to have ever lived---- finally shake it loose. Along with this
never mind that we are not sure what we implicit anthropocentrism we should also
mean by "smartest"-and it is also popular endeavor to root out the tendency to
knowledge that human evolution involved assume progressive trends in any aspect of
significant brain enlargement. Our brain brain evolution, unless and until all alter-
must also be the most complex, if for no native explanations have been exhausted.
other reason than the fact that our abilities There undoubtedly are progressive trends
are the most complex of any species. Since in brain evolution, but to clearly identify
them and to understand their significance and that more highly differentiated brain
we must demonstrate that they are not structures are more advanced than more
merely superficial correlates of other non- diffusely organized brain structures.
progressive trends. T o be able to do so Although we can probably assume that
requires that we first understand these there are some recent brains that a r e more
other trends. differentiated than any from fifty million
T h e a priori assumption of "advance- years ago, we cannot safely invert the logic
ment" in evolutionary sequences is a source and assume that the most undifferentiated
of many misunderstandings. Deacon contemporary brains are the least derived.
(1990a) reviews many of the assumptions Confounding variables such as absolute size
about brain evolution that derive from the and specific sensory-motor specializations
notion of evolutionary progress in brain may influence relative differentiation, and
size. Even theories that do not specifically problems in assessing homology as well as
invoke the notion of progression nonethe- sampling biases inherent in the phyletic
representation of species may introduce
less tacitly assume it in the process of iden-
tifying some structures as "advanced" and spurious correlates of differentiation that
others as "primitive." A primitive t o have nothing to do with primitiveness.
advanced ranking of living organisms o r In discussions of mammalian evolution
their structures must ultimately be based small bodied living insectivores are typi-
upon independent knowledge of the evo- cally treated as exemplars of the mor-
lutionary trend in question; otherwise the phologies of ancestral mammals. These so-
argument is circular. But when faced with called "basal insectivores" are assumed to
structures that leave no fossil evidence be "generalized" in their adaptation and
independent evidence is hard to obtain. "conservative" with respect t o evolution-
One possibility is to assume that the pro- ary trends, although caveats are usually
gressive ranking of soft-tissue structures suggested regarding the fact that each of
should correlate with other preserved indi- these groups represents some rather spe-
cators of the relative primitiveness o r cialized adaptations as well. T h e European
advancement of the organism as a whole. hedgehog (Elliot-Smith, 19 10; Ariëns Kap-
Overall similarity of traits from living pers et al., 1936; Filimonoff, 1949; Dia-
species to those in early fossil specimens ofmond and Hall, 1969; Valverde and López-
some lineage might suggest that the orga- Mascaraque, 1981; Sarnat and Netsky,
nization of brain structures is also equally 1981) as well as moles, tenrecs and micro-
comparable. It is of course necessary to chiropteran bats have all been cited as pos-
determine that the resemblances are not sessing conservative brain structure typical
superficial. and the result of convergent of an "initial" mammal brain (Sanides,
evolution. And even when this can be dem- 1969, 1970; Le Gros Clarke, 197 1; Glezer
onstrated there is never any guarantee that et al. , 1988). There are unfortunatel y a
the brain structures in question have been number of circular assumptions in the con-
as conservative as the rest of the mor- cepts of "primitive survivor" and "basal
phology. Even the external morphology of insectivore" (Martin, 1973) that also afflict
the brain, as may be revealed by endocasts, the concept of an "initial brain."
cannot be taken as a reliable indicator of Fossil specimens suggest that it is likely
underlying cellular a n d connectional that the eutherian mammal ancestor which
homologies. So a primitive external gave rise to the Paleocene-Eocene radia-
appearance of modern brains is an untrus- tions was of relatively small body size and
tworthy indicator of primitive brain orga- probably bore at least a superficial resem-
nization. blance to modern shrew-like insectivores.
In this regard there is considerable justi-
From simple to complex fication for selecting insectivores as exem-
It seems unquestionable that simpler plary of the ancestral condition. T h e pre-
brain structure precedes more complex sumption that the common ancestor was
brain structure in the course of evolution, somehow "generalized" or even that mod-
ern basal insectivores are "generalized" able that these brains are near some
species seems a little more puzzling, extreme in the spectrum of cortical orga-
although it is widely claimed. In many ways nization among eutherian mammals, but
members of these groups represent some this may not be conservatism. In fact, on
extremes of specialization. Consider, for the basis of brain traits selected for their
example, the echolocation specialization of value in determining cladistic relation-
microchiropteran bats, the fossorial o r ships, Kirsch et al. (1983) find that hedge-
nocturnal specializations of many shrews, hogs do not appear t o exhibit a prepon-
moles and hedgehogs, the aquatic special- derance of conserved traits, but just the
izations of some exceptional shrews, and opposite, they appear to possess one of the
of course the insectivorous specialization most derived mammal brains (Johnson,
itself. These facts must certainly relate to 1988).
their neurological adaptation. Of course It is clearly not the structure of the
there is every reason to suspect that the hedgehog body that motivates its choice as
common ancestor of eutherian mammals an exemplar. It exhibits highly specialized
was also specialized in some interesting spiny hairs for predator protection and has
ways, but given the radical difference in developed the ability t o role into a ball with
faunal context and likely niche specializa- only its spines exposed, it has relatively
tion there may be no corresponding spe- short, stubby limbs specialized for digging,
cialization represented in modern species. it has very rudimentary visual abilities with
T h e tree shrew Tupaia has been sug- clearly reduced eyes that are appropriate
gested by some as an appropriate living to its nocturnal-fossorial habit, and it has
model for a Paleocene precursor to pri- a well developed specialized snout and pre-
mates (Le Gros Clark, 197 1;Cartmill, 1972, sumably highly specialized olfactory abili-
1974), In terms of its size and many of its ties for insect predation. Campbell (1988)
non-neurological features it too might serve remarks that if the hedgehog were other-
as a reasonable stem mammal model. But wise the same but possessed a larger more
it is usually disqualified as an "initial brain" differentiated brain it would never have
model because it possesses a number of been considered an exemplar of the "ini-
"advanced" brain features, including mod- tial brain'' pattern. Gould (1977) notes that
erate encephalization and a differentiated in general it is unwise to choose the most
striate cortex and visual association cortex. undifferentiated extant member of a group
T h e cortex of Erinaceus, the European as a representative of its stem ancestor pre-
hedgehog, is often treated as a model of cisely because small bodied fast breeding
an ancestral mammalian cerebral cortex. forms are likely to be highly derived
Figure 3 depicts some of the known areal r-selected species. T h e choice of species
divisions of the hedgehog cortex along with with small undifferentiated brains is not so
an even more "primitive" tenrec brain. much motivated by external similarities
Some notable features of the isocortex of with known fossil types as by a priori
these species as compared to "advanced" assumptions about what is primitive and
brains include: relatively small size com- what is advanced.
pared to olfactory and limbic cortex, poorly T o carry this paradigm to its logical
distinguishable lamination, low level of extension, the hedgehog is probably not
myelination, poor differentiation from area the most extreme case that could be cited.
to area, lack of a clearly distinguishable Zilles and Rehkämper (1 988) point out that
agranular motor area, poorly granularized Erinaceus is actually somewhat advanced
koniocortical sensory areas, vagueness of with respect to some other basal insecti-
boundaries between architectonic areas, vores and therefore might not be the ideal
the apparent adjacency of sensory-motor exemplar of the "Grundtypus" for mam-
projection areas with little interdigitated malian brain organization. They note that
association cortex, and a relatively thick the brains of the tenrec Echinops and the
layer I (a limbic cortex characteristic) in all geogaline Geogale exhibit even less enceph-
areas of its isocortex. It seems unquestion- alization and exhibit fewer progressive fea-
lateral view

brain of a tenrec brain of a hedgehog


Centetes Erinaceus
FIG. 3. Hedgehog and tenrec brains as seen from above and the side labeled to show approximate positions
of the major sensory and somatomotor fields. Isocortex is indicated in gray in the left hemisphere of each
and limbic and olfactory cortex is white in the same hemisphere. Since most of the cortical representation is
unknown for the tenrec and only partially known for the hedgehog specific boundaries between areas are
not indicated. There is no intent to imply either undifferentiated cortex o r the existence of only single
sensory/motor fields. Note the low ratio of isocortex to limbic-olfactory cortex in these brains, especially the
small tenrec brain.

tures than that of Erinaceus. These authors tiation of the visual system and a corre-
conclude that Erinaceus is probably "not a spondingly heavy reliance on the olfactory
typical representative of a real basal insec- system. Evolutionary reduction or degen-
tivore" (Zilles a n d Rehkämper, 1988; eration of an essentially unused sense
emphasis in the original). Only in a context modality may induce dedifferentiation, but
where evolution is presumed to progress this does not likely follow an exactly
from simple to complex, from least en- reversed phyletic trend and may produce
cephalized to most encephalized, and from structural features that are quite distinct
generalized, inflexible and inefficient in from ancestral features. How can we be
function to specialized, flexible and highly sure that the relatively undifferentiated
efficient in function, can the search for the state of the cortex of these species is rep-
absolutely simplest mammalian brain be resentative of a retained primitive state
equated with the search for the ancestral rather than a recent specialization?
brain. Second, these exemplar species also rep-
There are two general attributes shared resent the very lowest limits of mammalian
b y essentially all the basal insectivores con- brain size. This is a problem because many
sidered primitive in brain organization that measures of structural complexity appear
should cause us to be cautious about gen- to be strongly correlated with brain size
eralizing from them. First, each of the can- (Tower, 1954; Haug, 1987; Deacon, 1990a;
didate exemplar species inhabits a noctur- and see the following section). Nearly all
nal-fossorial niche. This is probably no the attributes of "primitiveness" of mam-
accident. This adaptation has likely pro- malian brains are also typical attributes of
duced secondary reduction or dedifferen- very small brains, while those of "advance-
ment" are only expressed in relatively large ilar across a wider range of species than
brains. Progressivetrends measured with one exhibiting a number of easily discrim-
respect to these small insectivore species inated features. As a result, despite its
a r e significantly confounded with t h e apparently unbiased definition of polarity,
effects of differences of scale. Also if there the cladistic approach may be biased, so as
has been prolonged selection f o r size to pick out more generalized and less dif-
reduction in these species there may also ferentiated traits as characterizing a com-
be simplifications of brain structure of a mon ancestor. Evolutionary regression in
secondary character which d o not neces- certain lineages is potentially a source of
sarily follow a reverse phylogenetic trend. misleading bias as is the correlation of
absolute brain size with structural com-
Cladistic approaches plexity. Additionally, this approach is sen-
T h e cladistic approach to identifying sitive to the effects of convergent or par-
evolutionary trends offers some hope of allel evolution. It will be argued below that
resolving these ambiguities and avoiding parallelism is a major feature of mammal
the trap of implicit progressionism. By brain evolution.
replacing the assumption of evolutionary Nonetheless, the cladistic approach is in
deyelopment and increase in complexity some ways self-correcting in this regard. It
with a simpler empirically defined dichot- can be useful in discerning some of these
omy between conserved and derived con- biasing influences by using multiple sources
ditions one can arrive a t a relatively of information pooled to establish most
unbiased criterion for identifying evolu- parsimonious descent relationships and
tionary trends. T h e particular character- then reanalyzing individual trends. For
istics of the trait are irrelevant, only its example, the relative primitiveness of the
presence or absence in different groups is "basal insectivore" brain can be tested with
important. By pairwise comparison of the respect to three outgroups of mammals
presence o r absence of traits between whose phylogenetic affinities a r e well
species in progressively more distant out- known through other cladistic analyses: the
groups it is possible to decide which traits marsupials and the two living monotremes,
can be operationally defined as derived and t h e platypus Ornithorhinchus a n d t h e
which can be defined as ancestral o r con- echidna, or spiny anteater, Tachyglossus.
servative. Cladistic analysis has wide accep- Many of the characteristics of Erinaceus'
tance as a means for reconstructing phy- brain, including apparent adjacency of
ietic relationships between lineages, but it projection areas, minimal association cor-
has also been used extensively to trace the tex, high ratio of olfactory-limbic cortex
ancestry of specific traits. It has been par- to isocortex, poor laminar distinction, poor
ticularly useful for deciding between alter- granularization and poor differentiation of
native accounts of a trait's evolution architectonic areas, are not exhibited in
because it provides a measure of parsi- the brains of larger marsupials and mono-
mony. For example, Northcutt (1984) uses tremes. Have the apparently m o r e
the number of mutational events that must advanced traits also found in these out-
be postulated in order to explain the dis- groups evolved independently in the larger
tribution of certain vertebrate brain traits brains of all the mammalian lineages? T h e
according to different theories to decide more parsimonious interpretation is that
which of these theories provide the most many of these traits were present in some
parsimonious accounts. form in the common ancestor of all mam-
T h e Achilles heel of this approach with malian groups long before the recent
respect to brain evolution is that it will eutherian radiations. T h a t they fail to be
inevitably tend to favor identifying rela- exhibited by some of the brains in the
tively undifferentiated forms as more eutherian lineage (e.g., basal insectivoresj
primitive and differentiated forms as more and some brains in the marsupial lineage
derived. A structure lacking differentiat- (e.g., Didelphis virginiana) is not sufficient
ing features will tend to be glossed as sim- evidence to assume that they are derived.
Kaas (1989) applies an implicit cladistic Lack of positive evidence is not sufficient
approach to determine which cortical areas to deny homology but the availability of
in all mammals can be traced via descent positive evidence is sufficient to establish
from a common ancestor. He notes that in it.
all the major mammalian lineages (euthe- This can also be applied to questions con-
rian and metatherian) there are distinct cerning the origins of somato-motor areas.
visual, auditory and somato-motor projec- Lende (1969) demonstrated that in Didel-
tion areas within isocortex. H e concludes phis the somatosensory responsive cortex
that the common ancestor for all these lin- and the electrically excitable motor cortex
eages likely also possessed these differen- exhibited complete overlap and that in Eri-
tiated projection areas and not just an naceus there was a large region of overlap.
undifferentiated protoisocortex. Based on More recently some degree of overlap has
this evidence he rules out a widely cited also been demonstrated in rats (Donoghue
theory of cortical evolution proposed by et al., 1979). In carnivores and primates
Sanides (1970) that is based on the assump- (and probably ungulates) these areas are
tion that generalized undifferentiated iso- adjacent but completely segregated into
cortex preceded specialized sensory-motor distinct parallel somatotopic and muscu-
projection cortices in the course of cortical lotopic maps. Lende also argued that there
evolution. However, to be more explicit, was even some overlap of visual and audi-
what has been demonstrated is that dis- tory cortical areas in the opossum (although
crete somatic, auditory and visual projec- this finding has not been replicated). This
tion areas are expressed in mammal brains suggested to him that the ancestral state of
under all existing conditions and sizes, cortex was characterized by poor areal dif-
whereas some areas, particularly many ferentiation in which all the sensory modal-
association areas, fail to be expressed under ities exhibited nearly complete overlap with
many conditions, specifically in small brains. one another. However, at least one larger
T h e classic view that association cortex Australian marsupial, t h e brush-tailed
is new in comparison t o projection cortex opossum Trichosurus, exhibits considerable
in part derives from the apparent lack of segregation of somatic and motor fields
association cortex in basal insectivore brains (Haight and Neylon, 1978, 1979) and the
(but this assumption is criticized below) and monotremes appear to exhibit complete
its progressive domination of the cortical segregation of somatic and motor areas.
surface in "advanced" mammals. How- All of these facts- argue against assuming
ever, some of the larger marsupials and that the primitive condition was undiffer-
even the echidna appear to exhibit signif- entiated and completely overlapping and
icant expanses of association cortex in suggest that at least some degree of seg-
addition to primary sensory-motor projec- regation of these functional zones char-
tion areas. Apparently, under similar acterized the common ancestor of all mam-
developmental conditions- large brain ma1 groups.
size-this trait is expressed in every lin- But negative evidence can be cited to
eage of mammals. T h e common conditions support the view that the segregation of
required for expression of this trait in all somatic and motor modalities is a conver-
three lineages also lends confidence to the gent trait. This evidence comes from vari-
claim for homology as opposed to parallel ations in somatotopy of the sensory and
homoplasy. motor maps in the different groups. In most
T h e failure of basal insectivore brains to eutherian mammals studied the two fields
exhibit distinctly segregated association are arranged as mirror images of one
areas is not sufficient evidence to deny that another with respect to their common bor-
this trait is a shared ancestral trait. None- der, and exhibit this pattern even in species
theless the appearance of segregated visual, where there is considerable overlap of the
auditory and somato-motor areas in all two areas. However, in edentates and mar-
mammal brains is sufficient evidence to supials the two maps appear to be arranged
consider them as shared ancestral traits. in parallel as well as overlapped (Dom et
al., 1971; Lende, 1963, 1969; Magalhães- vastly increases the probability of conver-
Castro and Saraiva, 1971; Royce et al., gence and parallelism. In fact, many of the
1975; Saraiva a n d Magalhães-Castro, "advanced" traits of eutherian mammal
1975), and in a megachiropteran bat (Pter- brains could have been inherited from the
opus poliocephalus) the somatic map appears common ancestor of eutherian mammals
inverted from that typical of most other even if that ancestor failed to exhibit any of these
eutherian mammals (Calford et al., 1985). traits.
T h e monotremes appear to exhibit char- All three mammalian groups have likely
acteristics found both in some eutherian inherited neural developmental con-
and in som'e marsupial brains (Bohringer straints and tendencies from a common
and Rowe, 1977). Furthermore, the pat- ancestor that are expressed differentially
tern of thalamocortical connections to these in different contexts. It is possible that the
areas differs in eutherian and marsupial "initial" eutherian brain possessed the
brains. developmental information for these traits
This negative evidence is inconclusive but failed to express them because certain
because the differentiation of map orien- other conditions of their expression were
tation could occur independent of the seg- not met. Below it will be argued that the
regation of somatic and motor areas. T h e small size of these brains precludes the
unique status of the fox bat and edentate developmental expression of cortical par-
somatic maps in comparison to other mam- cellation processes necessary to produce
malian groups suggests that this is the case. multiple highly differentiated cortical
Map orientation appears to be a derived areas. Also the regression of the visual sys-
condition in these species. Variation of this tem in basal insectivores may f u r t h e r
trait occurs against the background of undermine these processes. Despite the fact
somatic and motor map segregation as an that ancestral traits might not be expressed
apparently older and more conservative in an intervening lineage there need be no
trait. T e only placental and marsupial interruption of their descent t o subsequent
mammals that do not exhibit segregation lineages, and their disappearance o r reap-
of somatic and motor projection areas also pearance in certain lineages cannot be
have relatively small brains. This further attributed to distinct mutation events and
suggests that this is a derived condition treated as distinct derived conditions. We
contingent on small size and not the ances- should be especially wary of this possibility
tral condition. in the choice of traits included for cladistic
Problems with these comparisons of cor- analysis.
tical areas stem from the fact that the traits This again underscores the importance
under consideration are not simple and the of thinking of homologies in informational
variables that correlate with the differen- terms. Even if we were to miraculously learn
tial expression of these complex traits have the details of morphology of the brain of
not been controlled for in the analysis. T h e the true eutherian ancestor we would per-
most important of these variables is brain haps still be a long way from understanding
size, but other factors are also clearly the initial conditions embodied in that initial
involved with regard to more subtle fea- brain that still influence the structure and
tures, such as map topography. Failure to the evolution of modern brains. What we
control for these factors inevitably leads to ultimately want to know is what information
their being confounded with descent rela- was embodied in the initial brain and in
tionships despite the fact that cladistic anal- the developmental mechanisms that built
ysis itself does not prejudge the primitive it.
or advanced status of a trait. T h e differ-
ential expression of a large number of traits Recapitulationism
with respect to brain size or the differential During embryogenesis there is a definite
expression of traits in brains with respect progression from smaller poorly differen-
to sensory specializations can be a serious tiated structures to larger highly differ-
problem for cladistic analyses because it entiated structures. Large species with rel-
atively differentiated brains must inevitably matured they passed through stages of cog-
pass through developmental stages in which nitive and emotional development that
their brains are small and poorly differ- corresponded to distinct "grades" of ani-
entiated. Consequently, t h e embryonic mal consciousness from reptilian to mam-
stages of larger more differentiated brains malian, from primitive mammal to pri-
will inevitably bear some superficial resem- mate, from primate to primitive human,
blance to the adult stage of small poorly and finally through the ascending stages
differentiated brains. Structures that dif- from "primitive savagery" to modern civ-
ferentiate later in development will thus ilization (e.g., Spencer, 1870; Baldwin,
appear to be added to an otherwise com- 1895). Various primitive human societies
mon substrate. Recapitulation assumes that and criminals were viewed as arrested at
adult structures in primitive species are some prior stage of development. Although
homologous to embryonic structures in the recapitulational structure of the brain
advanced species. Subsequent modifica- was assumed by many prominent 19th cen-
tions of brain structure have been added tury and early 20th century neurologists
in the more "advanced" species by extend- (e.g., Paul Broca, John Hughlings Jackson,
ing the ontogenetic process to include Ivan Pavlov, John Sherrington, and Sig-
additional later stages. This process of ter- mund Freud) probably the major catalyst
minal addition was presumed to link the for the formation of a comparative ana-
evolution of species to development in such tomical version of this theory came as a
a way that a scale of increasing complexity result of the synthesis of two sources of
in evolution was the inevitable outcome of neuroanatomical evidence just subsequent
a progressive increase of developmental to the turn of the 20th century.
information. Evolution is explained as an Paul Flechsig's (190 1) analysis of myelin-
augmentation of ontogenesis and more stained tissue from human fetuses at var-
"advanced" species are literally assumed to ious stages of development demonstrated
be further developed. a progression of myelination of isocortical
Despite the enormous theoretical power areas that began with primary sensory and
of this synthesis, the weight of comparative motor areas, continued to belt zones around
and ontogenetic evidence that has accu- these areas and culminated in relatively late
mulated against this doctrine in the last myelinating association areas (see Fig. 4).
century is overwhelming. Ontogenetic dif- This sequence was presumed to correlate
ferences that distinguish different lineages with developmental trends in which basic
may occur at any stage of development and sensory-motor abilities mature early in
are clearly not constrained to occur in lin- childhood and the "highest" intellectual
ear sequence with increasing phylogenetic abilities only appear late in developmeht.
.divergence. Although larger creatures tend It was also presumed to correlate with an
to exhibit longer ontogenesis than smaller evolutionary sequence from species with
creatures, larger creatures d o not have only crude sensory-motor habits a n d
additional stages added on and highly responses, to species with the capability of
derived members of a lineage d o not show complex and flexible associational learning
more developmental stages than highly abilities. T h e most developed associated
conservative members; differences in areas were assumed to be the newest in
development appear at many correspond- evolutionary terms and the last to develop
ing stages. However, despite the patent in ontogeny.
failure of this paradigm, numerous unrec- At roughly the same time .comparative
ognized recapitulationist assumptions still anatomists, using preparations that visu-
persist in the literature about brain evo- alized neuron cell bodies, produced maps
lution, primarily in the form of tacit ter- of the distinguishable cytoarchitectonic
minal addition assumptions. areas of the cerebral cortex for a number
Early recapitulationist theories of brain of mammalian species which appeared to
development suggested that as children demonstrate homologues for primary pro-
jection areas in all species, but no homo- lateral view
logues for many human association areas
in monkeys and no homologues for many
monkey association areas in other mam-
mals (e.g., Campbell, 1 905; Brodmann,
1909). It clearly appeared as though the
developmental t r e n d recapitulated a
sequence of additions of new cortical areas
leading up to the human brain. New, more
developed 'association areas were appar-
ently added to the brain of succeeding
species at the end of their maturational
development. T h e unusually long postna-
tal brain development of humans could also
be explained on the basis of the extra stages
of brain development that were appended
to, human ontogeny.
These assumptions corresponded with
the neuropsychological doctrine of the
time. It was assumed that the moment to
moment processing of sensory input
retraced this same hierarchy, developing
from the crude registration of sensory
information in projection areas, to the con-
struction of a perceptual gestalt in sensory
psychic areas, and finally to the elaboration
of multimodal associations with respect to
different remembered vercevtions, actions
and emotional experiences in association medial view
areas. Primitive animals and young chil- FIG. 4. Flechsig's myelogenesis figure of the human
dren only progressed through the initial brain is redrawn from the original leaving out Flech-
stages of this cognitive hierarchy. Although sig's numerical designation of myeloarchitectonic
the developmental recapitulation assump- fields. T h e darker areas represent the areas that mye-
tion has been abandoned, a more elaborate linate earliest in development and the white areas
represent the areas that myelinate latest. Insular cor-
version of this basic hierarchic functional tex is partially exposed. Note the progression from
interpretation remains the dominant con- primary to secondary to association areas of cortex.
temporary theory of sensory processing Note also the early myelination of limbic cortical areas
(e.g., Mishkin a n d Appenzeller, 1987; and pathways.
Maunsell and Van Essen, 1983), despite
many growing inconsistencies and t h e
availability of alternative interpretations
(e.g., Brown, 1988; Deacon, 1989a; Dia- will primarily address the issue of the
mond, 1982; Optican a n d Richmond, developmental sequence, but will return to
1987). the issue of the terminal addition of cor-
However, in hindsight we can see fun- tical areas in a later section.
damental flaws in both forms of evidence An alternative explanation for the pri-
for this correlation of ontogenetic devel- mary-secondary-tertiary hierarchy of my-
opment with apparent phylogenetic devel- elination of cortical areas can be derived
opment. Ultimately I will argue that both from a correlation between the total level
derived from a failure to control for factors of adult myelination achieved by these
having more to do with brain size than with structures and their apparent develop-
phylogenetic progression. In this section I mental schedule. T h e early myelinating
areas are also the most heavily myelinated tonic trend as well as other architectonic
in the adult and the latest myelinating areas trends led Sanides (1969, 1970, 1972) to
are the least myelinated in the adult propose that the terminal addition of cor-
(Bishop, 1959; Sanides, 1970). This rule tical areas in mammalian evolution might
also applies to noncortical structures: the actually be the reverse of that proposed by
relatively poorly myelinated reticular for- the traditional theorists—progressing from
mation of the midbrain exhibits one of the association areas to secondary areas t o pri-
latest and longest cycles of myelination of mary areas as the most highly developed.
any system (Yakovlev and Lecours, 1967) Although not a recapitulationist theory,
despite the fact that it is without doubt one because it makes no claims for develop-
of the most conserved structures in the ver- ment, it does nonetheless assume terminal
tebrate brain. This fact clearly contradicts addition in a phylogenetic sense, and an
the recapitulationist assumption. implicit progression from primitive t o
There are two possible interpretations advanced forms based upon the addition
of this correlation between total amount of more highly differentiated structures.
of myelination and the developmental time T h e neuropsychologist Jason Brown (1977,
course of myelination. First, since these 1988) has elaborated a self-consciously
assessments of myelination are based on recapitulationist theory of cortical func-
myelin-stained tissue sections in which more tion that is based upon Sanides' model of
densely myelinated tissue stains darker, phylogenetic progression, in which
there may be a level of nearly complete "microgenetic" processes of sensory anal-
staining opacity reached at an early devel- ysis proceed in a series of stages from lim-
opmental stage in areas that exhibit max- bic to association to specialized cortical
imal myelination whereas this level of areas rather than the other way around, as
staining opacity may never be achieved by is suggested in traditional models.
very poorly myelinated areas. In this case Both interpretations are based on mis-
the apparent heterochrony could be largely leading correlations that confound a num-
illusory. Alternatively, the deposit of my- ber of factors. T h e correlation between the
elin on axons destined to be heavily myelin- density of myelination in adults, the initi-
ated could take place at an absolutely faster ation and rate of myelination in develop-
rate (which appears to be indicated by the ment, and the overall level of myelination
data of Yakovlev and Lecours, 1967) and in brains of different sizes suggests that all
could begin earlier. It is probably an of these apparent comparative trends may
important corollary that the most heavily have less to do with any evolutionary
myelinated fibers are also often the largest sequence and more to do with certain con-
diameter axons that project relatively long servative functional and metabo1ic rela-
distances o r to highly specific targets. tionships between axons of differing sizes
There is also an important correlation and the glia that form their myelin sheaths.
between brain size and primitive-advanced T h e developmental differentiation of the
comparisons. Small insectivore and rodent brain occurs in the process of increasing
brains appear to be generally less myelin- the size of the brain. T h e evolution of
ated overall and exhibit less myeloarchi- increasingly differentiated mammal brains
tectonic differentiation from cortical area also correlates with t h e evolution of
to cortical area than the larger brains of increasing brain size. The similarities
primates (Sanides, 1970). Therefore if between brain development and brain evo-
myelination is to be used as a ruler of pro- lution may largely be the result of these
gression then the least myelinated areas parallelisms. In both, the confusing role of
should be considered the more primitive brain size and its many correlative struc-
areas and the most myelinated areas the tural scaling relationships underlies many
more advanced cortical areas (Bishop, of the misidentifications of evolutionary
1959). This runs exactly counter to the progress. T h e nature of some of these
apparent developmental progression. underlying correlations will be the subject
This apparent phyletic myeloarchitec- of the next section.
BRAIN SIZE the largest mammals on earth. If we think
of the brain as a computer and the body
The influence of anthropocentrism as the many users that are on line, vying
T h e significance of brain size is at once for processing time and memory storage,
the most broadly debated issue in the study then it becomes obvious that the effective
of brain evolution and probably also its most information processing capacity available
ubiquitous, misunderstood and troubling for any particular function is constrained
feature. More has been written about brain by the number of competing demands from
size than about any other topic concerning other sources. This has suggested to many
brain evolution. Like the notion of evo- that the ratio of brain to body is a more
lutionary progress, interest in brain size significant measure of available informa-
owes much to its apparent importance for tion processing capacity. Despite the fact
understanding human brain evolution. that they have absolutely larger brains, ele-
With a brain roughly three times larger phants and whales have a much lower ratio
than a primate of our size should possess, of brain to body than humans. But this
it is natural to assume that brain enlarge- observation is also unsatisfactory. Very
ment must hold the key to human unique- small birds and mammals have a higher
ness. But is brain enlargement symptom o r ratio of brain to body size than humans
cause in this transformation? Is relative and an even higher ratio of neuron num-
brain size alone the significant difference ber to body size.
o r is it a superficial consequence of more A satisfactory account of comparative
fundamental changes in brain organiza- brain size that ranked humans on top (and
tion? Size is also the easiest feature of the thereby preserved the intuition underlying
brain to study and so lends itself to broad the Anthropocentric Maxim) was discov-
comparative studies and studies of other ered at the end of the 19th century in the
possible correlates to brain size that might form of allometric analysis. Since that time
be of interest to researchers who otherwise the use of "subtraction criteria" based on
have little neuroscientific training. But the empirical brain and body size trends have
tendency to terminate the analysis of brain been assumed t o define that portion of the
difference with measurements of brain size brain mass that is functionally correlated
is a significant impediment to progress in with information processing demands of
the investigation of brain evolution, pre- the body. Deviations from these trends have
cisely because issues of brain size are insep- been assumed to respectively indicate
arable from issues of function and internal excess o r dearth of mental capacity (but
organization in some very fundamental see criticisms below). T h e importance of
ways. allometric analysis for the investigation of
T h e role of brain size in brain evolution patterns of relative growth and the sec-
appears deceptively simple. If the brain is ondary correlates of differences in size is
a computing device of some kind, then an paramount, not just as a criterion of sub-
increase in component processing ele- traction, but as a tool for drawing attention
ments should correlate with an increase in to the ways that biological processes can
information processing capacity. This intu- be affected by changes of scale. Allometric
ition appears to be borne out by the unsys- analysis has produced some remarkable
tematic observation that species with brains insights into the problem of relative growth
at the small end of the size range for ver- and has demonstrated some remarkably
tebrates exhibit mostly simple and stereo- regular patterns of size-related brain vari-
typic behaviors compared to those with ation from species to species and from evo-
brains toward the large end of the spec- lutionary epoch to epoch.
trum. This observation is not totally sat- T h e more detailed pursuit of allometric
isfactory. Some mammal brains exceed the relationships has shown that differences of
human brain in total volume and neuron brain size have consequences at every level
number-for example, elephant and whale of neuroanatomical and neurophysiologi-
brains. However, these species represent cal organization. Not all features of the
brain scale isometrically with size changes ative brain size and intelligence is open to
in brain evolution. This has serious func- serious question. T h e r e are distinctly dif-
tional consequences that have yet to be ferent brain-body trends for different
appreciated-much less understood-and mammalian taxa that can all provide equally
serious methodological consequences for valid-but not concordant-measures of
comparative studies because it immensely encephalization for an individual, t h e
complicates t h e task of determining somatic fraction of brain size that is pre-
homology. A failure to appreciate the sumed to be allometrically "subtracted" in
numerous architectonic and functional the estimation of encephalization cannot
consequences of differences in brain size be a simple linear factor as is often assumed,
lies at the heart of numerous misunder- and deviations from the empirical trend
standings about brain evolution, including cannot automatically be assumed t o cor-
issues of progression and the question of relate with mental adaptation as opposed
brain size evolution itself. to metabolic, ontogenetic o r somatic adap-
tations (Deacon, 1990a, b). More impor-
Is there a trend toward increasing tantly, the assumption that intelligence—
encephalization? much less comparative intelligence-is a
One of the earliest discoveries concern- single measurable scalar quantity is highly
ing brain evolution in mammals was that dubious from either a neurological o r an
mean brain size and relative brain size have evolutionary perspective and has never
increased with respect to our reptilian been adequately supported by comparative
ancestors and have increased since the intelligence testing (MacPhail, 1982; Gard-
beginning of the great eutherian mammal ner, 1983; Hodos, 1988; Deacon, 1990a).
radiations. This seems to be a clearly pro- This issue has been extensively discussed
gressive trend and suggests that brain size and debated elsewhere and so will not be
itself may be an adaptation under selection. reviewed here, except to point out both
But is it? If it is, then is there selection for the obvious progressionist and anthropo-
total brain size o r for relative brain size? centric assumptions that are inextricably
And what kind of evidence would be nec- bound up with the entire enterprise. Only
essary to demonstrate one o r the other? the issues surrounding phylogenetic inter-
T h e accepted answers to these questions pretations will be considered here.
have been phrased in terms of the evolu- Since the appearance of the first verte-
tion of intelligence, and have changed little brates, brains and bodies in many lineages
in form since well before the turn of the have enlarged by orders of magnitude. T h e
century. relative sizes of brains and bodies have also
Brain enlargement, both in absolute and changed. For an animal of a given body size
relative terms, has typically been referred the ratio of brain to body size has also
to as encephalization. Beginning with the increased in a number of lineages, though
work of Dubois (191 3) the term became not all. These general trends are capped
associated with a specific mathematical by the evolution of mammal brains. T h e
index: the measure of the relative devia- largest brains ever to have existed are now
tion of the ratio of brain to body size in a possessed by whales and the most extreme
species from the expected ratio for an aver- values of encephalization ever to have
age animal of the same body size, based on existed are now exhibited by dolphins and
trends for a given taxonomic group or for primates-particularly humans. Within any
some baseline comparison group (Bonin, taxonomic group of living vertebrates there
1937; Dubois, 19 13; Gould, 1966; Jerison, is a negative allometric relationship
1973: Stephan, 1969). Two major appli- between brain size and body size, such that
cations of these measures of encephaliza- adult individuals with larger body sizes tend
tion are the assessment of taxonomic and to exhibit lower ratios of brain to body size
phylogenetic differences of relative brain than smaller individuals. T h e scaling rela-
size and the assessment of species differ- tionship is approximately linear when ren-
ences in intelligence. Whether or not there dered in logarithmic coordinates but the
is any meaningful relationship between rel- particular slope and y-intercept of this line
FIG. 5. Allometric patterns of comparative vertebrate brain size and mammalian brain growth. Graph A,
on the upper left, depicts convex polygons that enclose all points of brain and body size for four major
vertebrate classes (from Jerison, 1973) along with an approximation of the polygon that would have enclosed
the stem mammals. Note the incredible mammalian brain and body size expansion from this precursor group.
Note also the overlap of teleost fishes and lizards and of birds and mammals and the lack of a scala naturae
trend from fish to mammals. Graph B, on the upper right, shows the trend line for carnivores and for the
domestic dog breeds. Arrows indicate measures of encephalization o r somatization for a small dog with respect
to the carnivore trend. This is intended to show that "encephalization" differences do not necessarily imply
selection on brain traits. Graph C, on the bottom left, shows an ontogenetic developmental trajectory for
brain and body growth in two typical mammals of different body size. T h e prenatal phase overlaps completely
for most species. Graph D, on the bottom right, shows ontogenetic curves for different mammalian species
and their relation to interspecific trends. Note that ontogenetic lines overlap for different size species during
the early ontogenetic phase. T h e shift of ontogenetic curves that distinguishes primates, cetaceans and ele-
phants from other mammals is shown in gray.

differs depending on the taxonomic group mechanism common to all mammals, and
under consideration. Proposals for possibly all vertebrates (Deacon, 1990b).
explaining the regularity and slope of these Ultimately no single explanation can
trends include the possibility that brain size account for the substantial differences in
tracks body surface (Snell, 189 1; Dubois, scaling relationship exhibited at different
19 13; Jerison, 1973), that brain size is con- taxonomic levels of analysis. Within a
strained by metabolic capacity which is also species the allometry is strongly negative
negatively allometric (Martin, 198 1; Arm- with slope on the order of 0.1 to 0.2,
strong, 1983),that because brain is derived whereas within a whole order o r whole ver-
from embryonic ectodermal tissue, the tebrate class the allometric slope is often
same growth control mechanisms may con- in the range of 0.6 to 0.8. See Figure 5a
trol mitosis in brain and body surface struc- and b.
tures (Deacon, 1990b), o r that target body T h e brain-body allometries of the dif-
size is controlled by neuron number via a ferent living vertebrate classes appear to
be distributed bimodally. T h e homeo- tational trade-offs involving large litter sizes
thermic classes-birds and mammals— and rapid reproductive rates characteristic
tend to scale together and the poikilother- of small r-selected species. These repro-
mic classes-fish, amphibians and rep- ductive specializations have been corre-
tiles-tend t o scale together, with homeo- lated with gestational constraints that affect
therms exhibiting a much larger brain growth (Martin, 1983; Deacon,
percentage of brain to body a t any given 1990b). Similar factors may also be impor-
body size (see Fig. 5a). In the evolution of tant for understanding marsupial brain size
birds and mammals there has clearly been development. It is possible that low esti-
an increase in encephalization over the mates of "basal" encephalization may be
ancestral reptilian condition as repre- misleading if they incorporate superim-
sented by modern reptiles. But using mod- posed developmental trade-offs that sec-
ern species as exemplars for ancestral rela- ondarily reduce encephalization. We
tionships it cannot be said that there has should expect that progressive removal of
been a steady increase in encephalization these constraints in lineages radiating into
from fish to amphibians t o reptiles t o birds K-selected, larger-body-size niches might
and mammals. In fact, some of the most result in an apparent " rebound" of
"primitive" fishes, the sharks and rays, encephalization. A similar "rebound" effect
comprising the Chondryichthes, exhibit has been suggested by Gould (1975) and
levels of encephalization that exceed all Deacon (1990b) in response to intense
other fishes, amphibians and reptiles, and selection for increasing body size in evo-
overlap the ranges for birds and mammals lution. Breeding experiments demonstrate
(Bauchot et al., 1979) . There is no clear that selection on body size produces body
scala naturae of encephalization. In con- size increase in successive generations with
trast, relative conservatism of the enceph- little correlated increase in brain size
alization relationship is demonstrated by (Atchley, 1984; Riska et al., 1984). Deacon
the extensive overlap of encephalization in (1990b) argues that after an initial rapid
different vertebrate classes. evolution of increased body size effected
Discerning the progressive encephali- by modifications of peripheral hormonal
zation of mammals relative to their reptil- mechanisms, continued stabilizing selec-
ian ancestors involves more subtle distinc- tion would tend to produce complemen-
tions, but the major step across this gap tary brain size increase as a more stable
appears to have already been taken by the central determiner of target body size.
time of the common ancestor of metatheri- T h u s t h e rapid radiations into m o r e
ans and eutherians (Ulinksi, 1986). In com- K-selected, large-body-size niches t h a t
parison with other mammalian lineages the characterized many mammalian lineages in
marsupials and the insectivores appear to the Eocene may have provided a biased
occupy the low end of encephalization, but sample of species for comparison to more
the monotremes appear on a par with the modern lineages.
mean for eutherian mammals. If the small T h e case for an increase in encephali-
brained basal insectivores and marsupials zation in primates, elephants and cetaceans
are characteristic in this regard of most is strengthened by independent evidence.
stem mammalian groups then most other From very early in embryogenesis all these
mammalian lineages have exhibited pro- species exhibit approximately double the
gressive encephalization. Such a trend is ratio of brain to body size found in any
demonstrated in the fossil record and has other mammal group at a comparable
been used as support for the claim that developmental stage (Count, 1947; Sacher
there has been a progressive trend toward and Staffeldt, 1974; Martin, 1983; Deacon,
increased intelligence in all these lineages 1990b). This difference is evident at the
(Jerison, 1973). earliest stages in which brains are discern-
T h e relatively lower encephalization of able in the developing embryo and so rules
many small bodied forms including basal out explaining this encephalization in terms
insectivores and rodents, may reflect ges- of the terminal addition of neural tissue
late in development (see Fig. 5c, d). Curi- Body size is a highly flexible and ecologi-
ously, the trajectory of brain-body growth cally significant variable, whereas brain size
for all three groups closely overlaps for the is a relatively inflexible and as yet poorly
entire fetal period, suggesting a common understood variable that may o r may not
brain growth mechanism. T h e brain-body correlate with differences in behavior. T h e
growth trajectories of the remainder of the search for changes in brain structure that
eutherian mammals also all appear to share correlate with addition or subtraction of
a common fetal trajectory, suggesting that neural tissue in evolution in order to
they all share a different common mech- account for encephalization is for this rea-
anism for determining brain growth. As son probably misguided; we might just as
with t h e encephalization difference well look for addition o r subtraction of the
between homeotherms and poikilotherms, many parts of the rest of the body.
this. embryological encephalization differ-
ence distinguishing primates, dolphins and Disentangling allometry and progression
elephants from the remainder of the When organisms get larger, either dur-
eutherian mammals appears as a distinct ing development o r in the course of evo-
discontinuity without intermediates. lution, all features of the organism are not
As a final comment on the encephaliza- scaled up isometrically. Even more trou-
tion issue it should be pointed out that the blesome for the comparative anatomist is
term itself reflects an underlying bias that the fact that homological relationships can
is part historical and part theoretical. Early appear to change with evolutionary changes
writers often did not clearly distinguish in size. Different structures may radically
absolute brain size from the relation of change size with respect to one another o r
brain size to body size in their discussions alter their relative position, structures may
of brain evolution (Gould, 198 1). T h e ulti- radically change shape due to unequal
mate interest has of course all along been growth rates among their parts o r single
the explanation of human brain size. But structures may divide o r differentiate to
measures of brain size with respect to body become two o r more distinct structures.
size are inherently relational. Increased This is the source of one of the most insid-
encephalization is also decreased somati- ious problems in evolutionary theory: the
zation, and vice versa (see Fig. 5b). One confusion of size related changes with evo-
need not necessarily assume neurological lutionary advancement. T h e secondary
explanations for differences in this rela- effects of change of size can include the
tionship. Although breeds of dogs differ apparent addition of new structures to old
enormously in degree of encephalization or the appearance of increased complexity
(from small highly encephalized dogs to in existing structures. It may be difficult t o
large poorly encephalized dogs) no one tell whether an increase in size has caused
doubts that body size is the selected vari- old structures to differentiate and subdi-
able and brain size the relatively less flex- vide o r whether the addition of new struc-
ible parameter. In fact, breeding experi- tures has caused an increase in size.
ments selecting progeny on the basis of As D'Arcy Thompson pointed out in his
either extremes of brain size o r extremes classic treatise on the effects of growth o n
of body size demonstrate that selecting for form (1917), most mechanical forces,
body size produces a poor correlated material properties and structural relation-
response in brain size whereas selecting for ships do not change isometrically with
brain size produces a highly correlated changes in size. Geometric effects are most
response in body size (Roderick et al., 1976; obvious — e.g., surface area to volume— but
Fuller, 1979; Atchley, 1984; Riska et al., also there are changes in the relative vis-
1984; Kruska, 1987). Given that a large cosity of fluids, diffusion rates of mole-
fraction of the variance in "encephaliza- cules, structural plasticity o r rigidity of
tion" within a species can be a consequence materials, rates of chemical reactions, etc.
of selection on body size, why should this Many of these non-geometric scaling allo-
not also hold for cross-taxa comparisons? metries result from the fact that ultimately
some components of organisms are of fixed trends. T h e fossil evidence clearly dem-
sizes (e.g., molecules and cells). In order to onstrates that with the demise of the dino-
maintain isometry of functional properties saurs, small mammal species rapidly
across major changes in size it is nearly adapted to fill niches for large bodied
always necessary for structures to enlarge forms. T h e mammalian radiations can be
at different rates. seen as markedly asymmetric with respect
Allometric analysis can help control for to body size (and correlated brain size). T h e
the influence of size, allowing one to com- lower limit of mammalian body size has
pare quantitative traits with the effects of probably not been significantly altered since
size subtracted. This "criterion of subtrac- the Paleocene but the upper limit has prob-
tion" is most often assumed to indicate that ably been extended about a millionfold
some functional relation has been main- compared to a typical basal insectivore!
tained in the face of the change in size. Brain size necessarily followed this trend,
This does not mean that such changes are although the extension of the upper limit
merely passive effects induced by the mass of'brain size, due to its negative allometry
of t h e organism. T h e y a r e inevitably with respect to body size, has probably not
"internal" facultative or genetic adapta- exceeded ten thousand times that of a typ-
tions to the imbalances or weaknesses ical basal insectivore brain. Parallel
induced by the change in size. Many of enlargement trends characterized numer-
these secondary adaptations may b e ous lineages of mammals.
encoded in the genome of the organism. I will argue that it is this remarkable par-
However, a trait that is somehow expressed allelism, and not some progressive selec-
facultatively, in a size graded manner, tion for increasing intelligence, that is
would have obvious advantages over one responsible for many pseudoprogressive
that is specific to a given range of sizes. In trends in mammalian brain evolution.
these cases size change should be consid- Larger whole animals were being
ered the "primary" adaptation and the selected-not just larger brains—but along
correlated reorganizations of structure can with the correlated brain enlargement in
be considered "secondary." each lineage a multitude of parallel sec-
A genetically encoded, size-correlated ondary internal adaptations followed.
trait that has evolved in response to the
functional demands of size change is a par- Allometry of brain traits any levels
adigmatic example of a derived condition. Mammalian brains range in weight from
But it also represents a conservative fea- around a gram to nearly ten thousand
ture to the extent that it is necessary to grams. Even within a single lineage like the
preserve some ancestral functional rela- anthropoid primates, in which individual
tionship. Functional homology is main- species share many strong similarities in
tained at the expense of structural homol- brain structure, there is more than a hun-
ogy. T h e reverse scenario is also possible— dredfold difference between the smallest
structural homology maintained by virtue and largest adult brains. Yet most micro-
of change in supportive functions to keep structural features change little in size from
pace with the effects of size. Finally, it is brain to brain. T h e maximum sizes of neu-
also possible for size change to be the "sec- ron and glial cell bodies increase slightly
ondary" adaptation. A change in size can from the smallest to the largest brains, but
be secondary to the production of some nowhere near the thousandfold scaling of
correlated effect that has itself become the the brains they comprise (Haug, 1987). T h e
trait of primary adaptive significance. This functional constraints on cell volume no
latter possibility will be suggested in the doubt set an asymptotic upper bound on
case of human brain size enlargement (see cell size that the largest neurons are likely
last section). approaching. T h e apparent tetraploidy of
In cases where size change is primary it the giant Betz cells of the human motor
would be inappropriate to consider the cortex likely indicates that these cells are
many secondary adaptations as progressive already forced to come up with unusual
ways to circumvent certain functional lim- projection neuron rnyelin sheath

itations of their large size.


T h e constraints on neural size also affect
the scaling of higher-order multi-neuronal
structures. For example, the diameter of
cortical columns as well as the number of
neurons within each column seems to
remain almost constant across brain size
.
glial cell

smaller brain
variation (Rocket et al., 1980). This may
also be the reason that many larger scale
morphological features like cortical thick- larger brain
ness increase only slightly from the small-
est to the largest brains (Rocket et al., 1980).
As a cdnsequence the disparity between
microstructure organization and macro- rnyelin sheath
structure organization grows incredibly
with increasing size. Since the macro-
morphology of the brain, including
distinct homogeneous structures and their
various functional subdivisions, is derived
by ontogenetic processes that function at local circuit neuron
(e.g. granule cell)

the microscopic cellular level, this growing


scale difference is inevitably reflected by FIG. 6. Local relationships contributing t o cytoar-
changes of large scale structure. Some of chitectonic allometry are depicted in this figure from
these. morphological changes may reflect in Deacon (1990b). T h e top figure depicts the situation
a relatively small brain and the lower figure depicts
distinct adaptations to these new micro- these same relationships in a slightly larger brain. In
structural demands, but it is likely that the small as compared t o large brains projection neurons
majority are simply the inadvertent con- possess short, small diameter axons, with relatively
sequences of the same ontogenetic pro- less myelin, smaller cell bodies, lower neuron t o glia
ratio, higher neuron densities, lower ratios of local
cesses operating in a vastly larger brain. circuit neurons to projection neurons, smaller size
This is illustrated by what can be called differences between the smallest and largest neurons,
cytoarchitectonic and myeloarchitectonic allom- etc.
etry (Deacon, 1990a). T h e linear and vol-
umetric increase in scale of the brain with
respect to relatively more conservative lim- metabolic and neurotransmission demands
its of cellular structure impose new con- of such an enlarged axonal volume and sur-
straints on neural and glial functions. Con- face area the cell body of the neuron must
sider what must happen to homologous also be enlarged, but since it depends on
long projection neurons in brains of the glial cells surrounding it for its meta-
increasing size. In order to maintain sim- bolic support the relative number of glia
ilar transmission velocities and transmis- must also increase. T h e same constraints
sion integrity longer axons need to have are not experienced by small local circuit
larger diameters and thicker myelin neurons. Since local circuits remain rela-
sheaths. If the target area has also expanded tively constant in volume (increasing no
in volume (as is typically the case as well) more than a few hundred percent across
then the terminal arbor of a typical axon huge brain size differences) these neurons
must also increase. This can be a significant should have to change relatively little to
factor given the exponential differential compensate for size (see Fig. 6).
between linear dimensions and volumes Given these two extremes, it becomes
since it requires a tremendous increase in obvious that the local cyto- and myelo-
length and number of branchings of an architecture of many brain structures will
axon to fill a larger volume with the same reflect the influence of size. In general, in
density of synapses. T o keep pace with the large brains as compared to small brains
there should be a number of regular trends: of a network might be the average number
In large brains there should be (1) some of nodes that must be passed through to
much larger cell types, but also a much find a link between any two arbitrary nodes.
greater difference between the smallest and In all but the smallest o r lowest connectiv-
largest cells, (2) a higher glia to neuron ity networks the number of connections
ratio in most regions, (3) a decreased mean tends to vastly outnumber the nodes. If one
density of neurons but an increase in the wants to increase the number of nodes in
range and variation of densities in different a network while maintaining the same
areas and subareas, (4) a significant increase average connectivity, then the number of
in axonal and dendritic arborization to fill connections that have to be added with each
the slightly increased volume of local cir- new node will grow factorially with each
cuits, (5) higher levels of myelination in addition. A factorial increase of this sort
general but a greater difference from the will rapidly lead to astronomical numbers,
most to least myelinated areas and sub- particularly in large highly connected net-
areas, and (6) since some areas may be spe- works, but even in networks with relatively
cialized for longer projecting cells with low connectivity very large changes in size
large soma and heavily myelinated axons will produce the same result. Except in
and other areas only for short projecting minimally connected networks, it will
cells or cells with small diameter, poorly become increasingly difficult to continue
myelinated axons these differences will be increasing the number of nodes within a
magnified between brain areas. T h e net network and retain the same level of con-
result will be greater architectonic differ- nectivity. This concept in diagrammed in
entiation within an area and between areas Figure 7.
in large brains as compared to small brains. Now consider these facts about the cen-
Few if any of these changes are likely the tral nervous system: One neuron may be
result of the evolution of new ontogenetic connected to thousands of others, accord-
mechanisms, but merely the local dynam- ing to some estimates; even in small mam-
ical responses of cells trying desperately to malian brains there are probably b lions
do what they would do in any brain. We of neurons; and there is a nearly tenthou-
can conclude from this that a n increase i n sandfold difference in volume between the
architectonic complexity with size is not a reli- smallest and largest mammalian brains.
able measure of progression and advancement, These simple statistics make it clear that
either for comparison of the brains of different network allometry must be one of the major
species or for comparisons of different areas factors responsible for the differences in
within the same brain. organization and function that distinguish
However, there are also a number of size large and small brains. But the brain is not
related changes for which architectonic a maximally interconnected network. Even
reorganization will be unable to compen- in a brain with a billion cells each con-
sate. Probably the most significant among nected to a thousand others at random the
these is a factor that can be called network average number of nodes se p aratin g any
allometry (Deacon, 1990a). Network allom- two will be on the order of twenty, and
etry is essentially a geometric principle brains are not nearly so diffusely orga-
analogous to surface to volume allometry. nized. Probably the majority of connec-
T h e size of a network is a function both of tions between areas of mammalian isocor-
the number of nodes in the network and tex and other cortical or subcortical areas
the number of connections between nodes. are reciprocal, and the connections within
Networks with every node directly con- the local circuits of the isocortex are prob-
nected to each other node can be consid- ably highly re-entrant and relatively self-
ered to exhibit a high level of connectivity contained within columnar modules. Also,
whereas networks with each node directly given the relative comparability of local
connected to only one or two others can circuit structure of isocortex from species
be considered low connectivity networks. to species, it is likely that intracortical con-
One measure of the average connectivity nections between columns may be limited
to neighboring columns and to specific tar-
get columns in other areas. It may then be network allometry network allometry
maintaining local maintaining global
a bit more useful to think of connectivity connectivity only connectivity

within the cerebral cortex in terms of


columnar modules as nodes rather than in
terms of individual neurons as nodes. A
separate network allometry might apply at
the columnar level since columns increase
in volume, number of axons and dendrites
but not neurons with increasing brain size.
Nonetheless, given the immense differ-
ences in scale that must be considered, even
a relatively poorly interconnected cortical
network will have to contend with connec-
tivity trade-offs in order to compensate for
network allometry.
There is clearly a significant increase in
the proportion of white matter to gray
matter in brains of ascending size, but this
is doubtless nowhere near what would be
required for connectional parity to be
maintained. I n order to evolve to significantly
larger sizes brains must decrease connectivity.
This trade-off undoubtedly has its costs.
The two most obvious costs of decreasing
IG. 7 . T h e problem of network allometry is rep-
connectivity with increasing size a r e Fresented by the example of a very simple network
reduced integration of distributed func- (figure from Deacon, 1990b). A series of nodes
tions and significantly increased transmis- (depicted as spheres) is connected reciprocally to each
sion and processing times. Larger brains are other (depicted by double arrows) in different size
not necessarily more efficient a n d more powerful networks with different extremes of connectivity.
Networks on the left exhibit low connectivity and
than smaller brains. In fact, these new func- those on the right exhibit maximum connectivity. N
tional costs of increasing size will demand = total number of nodes; C = total number of recip-
new secondary adaptations in order to rocal connections (note that in the nervous system
compensate in other ways. If a functional reciprocal connections are separate connections); Xn
area of cortex becomes enlarged in the = the number of other nodes to which any one node
is directly connected; Xc = the mean number of con-
course of evolution the mean interconnec- nections intervening between any two arbitrary nodes.
tivity of its columns will decrease. This will T h e growth of connections to nodes is a factorial
decrease the homogeneity and integrity of function of the number of nodes in a fully connected
activity patterns that can be maintained network and a linear function of the number of nodes
in a minimally connected network. Both low and high
within it and increase the time necessary connectivity networks require major functional and
for neural "calculations" involving the structural trade-offs with size increase.
whole area to be completed. These costs
can be minimized by breaking the one large
area into two relatively independent sub-
areas capable of processing the same infor- are necessary and both transmission time
mation in parallel, so long as they can be and integration costs will continue to
partially integrated with one another by mount. Of course there may also be advan-
specific interconnections. Although this tages, including the increased specificity
reorganizational strategy may compensate and reliability afforded by parallel redun-
in part for loss of local integration and pro- dant processing, o r alternatively, the pos-
cessing efficiency it cannot entirely com- sibility of subspecialization of different
pensate. And, if size continues to increase, subdivisions. T h e evolution of new struc-
additional parcellations into multiple areas ture and function as a result of such pro-
cesses will be discussed further in the next one of the contextual variables to which
section. these mechanisms is sensitive has changed
We can conclude that network allometry value. These changes might be referred t o
may force a variety of secondary reorgan- as secondary facultative adaptations t o dis-
izations of cortical architecture, including tinguish them from secondary adaptations
parcellation and multiplication of func- that actually involve the evolution of new
tional areas, as brains enlarge during evo- genetic and developmental information.
lution. This essentially forces large brains There is neither progression nor addition
to alter functional strategies for informa- in this sense, and the parallelisms that result
tion processing from those effective in small are not properly thought of as parallel
brains. A further factor to be considered homoplasy.
is the fact that the receptor systems pro- It is possible that the ontogenetic mech-
jecting to these cortical areas are also anisms utilized in parcellation of cortical
enlarging along with body and brain size, areas are sensitive to the demands of net-
although these probably exhibit a negative work allometry. T h e fact that axonal com-
allometry with body size. This must also petition plays the major role in determin-
play a significant role in determining at ing area parcellation and afferent and
what level of scale there will likely be efferent relationships within the develop-
breakup and parcellation of cortical areas. ing cortex (discussed in the next two sec-
It is far from clear to what extent there is tions) suggests that facultative mechanisms
net gain due to new functionality and may account for a considerable portion of
increased information storage or net loss the structural and connectional response
of efficiency and integration due to increas- to this functional demand. But it is likely
ing loss of connectivity as brain size t h a t specific genetic adaptations also
increases. We will need a better under- become available to streamline the facul-
standing of this trade-off before we will be tative response (via genetic assimilation) to
able to think clearly about the question of these demands during the course of evo-
comparative intelligence and its relation- lution. T h e addition of new secondary
ship to brain-body allometry. adaptations (derived conditions) is in order
to maintain the same function (conserved
Size and parallelism in mammalian condition), and can be seen as a sort of
cortical evolution "Red Queen effect" to the extent that the
These complex allometric consider- system is working harder and harder to try
ations complicate the evolutionary inter- and stay in the same place. T h e parallel-
pretation of comparative brain morphol- isms that have evolved to maintain func-
ogy. It is not a simple matter to track tional homology across a large range of
morphological changes and assign them brain sizes are likely the result of a com-
independent evolutionary causes. If in fact bination of underlying ontogenetic homol-
many "emergent" architectonic changes ogies shared by all mammals and specific
associated with brain size evolution are genetically encoded biases that modify the
simply the effects of common underlying responses of these ontogenetic mecha-
cellular mechanisms compensating for the nisms differently in different species.
effects of size, then it can be misleading to But it is not necessarily safe even to con-
treat them as "new" features. T h e only sider these microallometric changes as
difference in the information utilized in facultative adaptations with respect to size
the ontogenetic process is difference in size change. All that is demonstrated is a form
information-in the form of larger axonal of morphogenetic plasticity that is affected
volumes, greater variance of metabolic by size. In a related context, Smith-Gill
demands for different cell types, etc. If we (1 983) distinguishes two general classes of
focus on the deep informational homolo- developmental plasticity that clarify this
gies rather than on the surface structural point. The first he calls developmental con-
homologies it is clear that developmental version and the second he calls phenotypic
mechanisms have not been altered, rather modulation. In developmental conversion,
environmental cues activate alternative question the assumption that size increase
genetic mechanisms that are expressed in is caused by addition of new parts, since
the organism's development. These differ- the plastic responses of neural develop-
ent genetic expressions may produce alter- ment to size change inevitably produce dif-
native morphs by activating o r inhibiting ferentiation and subdivision of existing
growth processes affecting the structural structures at all supracellular levels of
development of certain tissues, by chang- organization. Although the majority of
ing cell surface affinities or messenger- architectonic trends in brain organization
receptor sire relationships in intercellular in mammalian lineages give the appear-
communication, o r even by inducing ance of increasing differentiation and com-
regressive processes,such as programmed plexity, we cannot disambiguate this from
cell death. In phenotypic modulation envi- the effects of local cellular plasticity and
ronmental cues modulate but do not select secondary facultative adaptation which
among'or alter genetic programs. This cannot be considered progressive in any
produces variation and adjustment of the sense. However, precisely because plastic
expression of genetic information but not phenotypic modulation is not necessarily
the selection of different alternative genetic adaptational, it cannot be assumed that it
programs. Smith-Gill notes that pheno- will preserve any semblance of functional
typic modulation does not necessarily imply isometry. And even if it is adaptational in
an adaptive response, ". . . adaptiveness of most cases it may fail t o be so at the
phenotypic modulation cannot be assumed extremes of size, where otherwise predict-
unless specific genetic mechanisms can be able metabolic and information processing
demonstrated." It is unlikely that the onto- demands may significantly diverge from
genetic responses of neural tissues to the ancestral patterns. If such inadvertent
influence of size are produced by specific departures from functional isometry con-
genetic alternatives, since these would have tribute useful capabilities o r potentialities
to differ for each range of size and for each they may contribute t o directional trends
brain' region. Rather, the facultative plas- in evolution. Alternatively, if the adapt-
ticity of neurons in response to the local ability of facultative responses induces
effects of size must be a case of phenotypic genetic assimilation of nongenetic pheno-
modulation. We cannot necessarily assume typic modulation mechanisms into genet-
that all aspects of this plasticity are adap- ically based developmental conversion
tive, even in the broad sense of adaptive mechanisms, the changes in response to
with respect to local metabolic and infor- size may produce irreversible evolutionary
mation processing demands. We can only changes. In this way secondary adaptations
assume that significantly maladaptive plas- to size may inadvertently provide the raw
tic responses will be strongly selected materials for the evolution of new func-
against. tional systems.
In conclusion, the evolution of mammals
is clearly characterized by a trend toward NEOGENESIS: THE EMERGENCE OF
increasing body size with a correlated N EW S TRUCTURE
increase in brain size, but it is unclear to
what extent there has been additional inde- The assumption that new adaptations
pendent selection for increased brain size require new structures
and brain differentiation in different lin- In many ways the fundamental question
eages. Even if there is not independent that evolutionary theory purports to answer
selection for brain size in a particular lin- is how new species with novel structures
eage, body size correlated increase in brain and functions come into being in the course
size can be expected to produce a series of of time. If anything can be called evolu-
architectonic and functional changes due tionary progress it is the creation of totally
to the plasticity of developmental processes new adaptations, not just the augmentation
a t the neuronal-synaptic level. In general, of existing adaptations. New brain areas
with respect to brain structure, we should with distinct cellular architecture and con-
nectivity appear in some lineages but not often been cited as an example of both
others, and it is almost certain that over neogenesis and of progressive evolution,
the course of mammalian brain evolution and is presumed to correlate with the
the number of discrete brain areas in the increased behavioral and cognitive abilities
most complex brains has steadily increased. of advanced species. T h e acquisition of new
This has suggested to many that new adap- functional abilities is also a central feature
tations and the augmentation of existing of human mental evolution. We conceive
structures are accomplished by the addi- of ourselves as possessing all of the cog-
tion of new structures t o an already func- nitive abilities of other species and then
tioning brain. But new structure may also some. Particularly novel in the course of
evolve by co-opting or reorganizing exist- evolution are human linguistic abilities. In
ing structures in some way. In this case the a behavioral sense this capability is clearly
resulting structure may be radically differ- an addition-functional neogenesis. It is
ent than its antecedent, and yet combine tempting to assume that the addition of
both novel attributes and pre-existing fea- such an unprecedented function necessar-
tures at different levels of organization. ily implies the genesis of novel neurological
How is it possible to distinguish between structures. With respect to apparent neo-
uniquely derived structural additions and genetic trends in the evolution of cortex
previous structures that have become rad- in other mammals, the addition of human
ically modified? language areas would seem to be a most
T h e history of vertebrate evolution in recent step in a long series of additions. In
general, including mammalian evolution, this context it is clear that the assumed
exhibits a trend toward diversification of ubiquity of neogenetic processes derives in
adaptations. T h e invasion of new niches part from its presumed importance for
inevitably requires adaptation of percep- human mental evolution.
tual, behavioral and cognitive processes to . .
meet the new demands. T o some extent Additive theories of cortical evolution
these are acquired at the expense of mod- T h e most well known theory of mam-
ifying previous neural systems, trading one malian brain evolution is the triune brain
function for the other. But the acquisition hypothesis proposed by Paul MacLean (1970,
of new abilities could also be achieved by 1973). It is an attempt to explain the dif-
addition of new functions to old with a cor- ference between mammal brains and non-
responding elaboration of the brain. Each mammal brains and how this difference
species is the culmination of a phylogenetic arose in the course of evolution. MacLean
sequence of adaptive changes that leave argues that the mammalian brain can be
their traces in the structure of its body and subdivided into three functionally and evo-
brain. There is a natural tendency to envi- lutionarily distinct regions. T h e first divi-
sion this as an accretionary process that sion, including the spinal cord, brain stem,
progressively adds new structure to old. midbrain, diencephalon, corpus striatum
This impression is supported by the appar- and olfactory apparatus are considered a
ent increase in brain complexity that cor- core structure common to all, terrestrial
relates with the scala naturae hierarchy of vertebrates. He calls this the reptilian brain
species leading from fish to mammals and or R-complex because, h e argues, this com-
from "primitive" mammals to "advanced" prises the entire brain in reptilian species.
mammals. T h e definition of evolutionary During mammalian evolution two addi-
progress is at every step completely depen- tional structural levels are added in
dent upon the identification of neogenesis. sequence: the paleomammalian brain, com-
One outstanding difference that is pre- posed primarily of limbic cortex and its
sumed t o distinguish primitive from associated forebrain nuclei and connec-
advanced mammalian brains is an increas- tions, and the neomammalian brain com-
ing number of architectonically and func- posed of the neocortex. With the accretion
tionally distinguishable cortical areas. T h e of each of these systems in the course of
increase in numbers of cortical areas has evolution comes the emergence of new
cognitive abilities and behaviors. With the addition of higher order brain structures
paleomammalian brain come complex must correlate with the appearance of
parental care, vocal communication, play, increasingly sophisticated cognitive abili-
and the "higher" emotions of bonding and ties and more flexible behaviors in the
caring. With the neomammalian brain course of evolution.
come higher order perceptual, motor and Ever since it first became possible to eas-
generally enhanced learning abilities that ily differentiate one cortical area from
free the organism from reliance on fixed another on the basis of cell architecture o r
action patterns and simple template based myelin content it was recognized that the
perception. The scheme is hierarchic and cortex of some mammals exhibited many
accretive. T h e reptilian brain is whole and more divisions into distinct areas than did
complete in and of itself (and presumably others. Efforts by the early comparative
can reassert itself as an autonomous force anatomists, including Brodmann, Camp-
in cases of high excitation or weakened bell, Elliot-Smith, and others, to determine
control from higher brain systems, as might homologies between these cortical areas in
occur with brain damage), and therefore different species suggested that apparent
the addition of new systems does not homologies could be identified for a num-
require major reorganization, simply ber of areas in most mammalian brains (see
superimposition of new axons into the cir- Fig. 8). Apparently, the primary projection
cuitry of this otherwise complete system. areas for vision, audition, and tactile senses
T h e additional connections need merely could be homologized in all mammals but
play an inhibiting and modulatory role with the multitude of interdigitated "nonpro-
respect t o the pre-existing substrate. jection areas" that were evident in the
Although this brain model has become human brain could not all be homologized
widespread in the popular literature and to areas in monkey brains, and many of the
in some psychological and educational the- "nonprojection areas" in monkey brains
ories, its influence in comparative neu- could not be homologized to yet smaller
roanatomy is tenuous at best. T h e limbic and more "primitive" brains.
cortical areas that presumably comprise the Flechsig's (1901) demonstration that this
paleomammalian brain have been homol- precedence of areas was also approxi-
ogized to cortical structures in nonmam- mately paralleled by maturational trends
mals by comparative anatomists since early (see Fig. 5) completed the evidence for a
in the century (e.g., Johnston, 1906; Crosby, grand synthesis. T h e evolution of ever
19 17; Elliot-Smith, 19 19; Dart, 1934; more complex associational abilities in
Abbie, 1940). In addition, more recent mammals was enabled by the elaboration
investigations have demonstrated that of additional higher order association areas
nonmammals also exhibit forebrain struc- of cortex that were both progressively fur-
tures and connections that undoubtedly ther removed from direct peripheral input
have homologues in mammalian neocortex and more interconnected with each other.
(e.g., Ebbesson, 1980; Karten and Shimizu, Just how these new areas of cortex became
1989; Ulinski, 1983). It also provides a sim- interdigitated between old areas was not
plistic view of behavioral differences clear to these authors, but the determi-
between mammals and nonmammals. It nation of homologies appeared to require
seriously underestimates the considerable the progressive addition of new structures
perceptual, motor and learning abilities of in a particular order of appearance.
nonmammalian species-particularly birds— One obvious way to account for new
and ignores the many elaborate social structure and new functional abilities
behaviors, modes of communication and appearing in the course of cortical evolu-
parental care that have been observed in tion is simply to hypothesize their insertion
nonmammals. Nonetheless, t h e triune into an already complete and functioning
brain theory has enjoyed a wide audience cortex. T h e prevailing neuropsychological
in large part because it captures a central theory of the early 20th century could
anthropocentric intuition: that terminal accommodate such a view. Like MacLean's
flattened mouse flattened macaque
cortex cytoarchitecture cortex cytoarchitecture
FIG. 8. Comparisons of the number of cortical areas of small and large mammalian brains. T h e four drawings
depict unfolded views of mouse and monkey cortical surfaces. A (mouse cortex) and B (owl monkey cortex)
are redrawn from Kaas (1989) and depict area maps determined electrophysiologically in these species. C
(mouse cortex) and D (macaque cortex) are redrawn from Caviness and Frost (1980) and Jouandet et al.
(1989), respectively, and depict cytoarchitectonic divisions (Krieg's numerical designations following Brod-
mann). T h e differences in configurations largely represent different "unfolding" techniques, some of which
minimize area distortion at the expense of total map integrity whereas others maintain continuity of the map
at the expense of area distortion. All are drawn to equal size for comparability.

subsequent Triune Brain hypothesis, the orderly addition of cortical areas in evo-
theory of the accretion of new cortical areas lution and the progressive elaboration of
necessitated a hierarchic conception of sensory motor processes in "higher" mam-
brain organization and function; Flechsig mals. T h e associationist assumption at the
(1900) and Campbell (1905) clearly artic- center of this theory was that higher order
ulated this complementarity between the mental associations are built from lower
FIG. 9. A graphic depiction of Campbell/Brodmann/Flechsig, Bonin/Sanides and Lende/Poliakov scenarios
for the addition or differentiation of new cortical areas in mammalian evolution. Although none of the
individual schemes is exactly identical with any other (and may not exactly correspond with those depicted)
they have been grouped into three distinct categories for depiction because of their underlying theoretical
similarities. T h e relative sizes of these brains are depicted in column A and show that the increase in distin-
guishable cortical areas is not independent of size. Column B shows an accretive scheme in which projection
areas a r e primitive and association areas are added derived characteristics in later brains. Column C shows a
progressive differentiation scheme in which association areas are considered most undifferentiated and there-
fore primitive and more specialized sensory and motor areas are assumed to be later derived conditions that
have differentiated in a series of stages out of previous levels of association cortex. Sanides additionally argues
that there is a dual origin of most major sensory/motor fields that determines differentiation at the intersection
of a dorsocaudally originating archicortical and a ventrorostrally originating paleocortical trend. This is not
depicted here. Column D shows a progressive differentiation scheme based on the parcellation and retraction
of initially diffuse overlapping projection fields into eventually discrete non-overlapping fields. T h e boundaries
of the initially overlapping projection fields are depicted by dashed lines. Later parcellation and reduction of
diffuse projections within each projection field is depicted as progressively darker regions of gray. T h e notion
of reduction of diffuse projections within a field is from Poliakov and is not discussed as a possibility by Lende,
whose theory focused only on the earliest stages of cortical evolution in mammals.

order simpler associations, and compli- the previous association area in the hier-
cated and flexible skilled responses are archy and provided an additional layer of
constructed by associations between sim- association processes superimposed upon
pler reflex responses. They argued that an already complete functional brain (see
association areas of cortex only received Fig. 9).
information from sensory projection areas Vestiges of this view are still widespread.
o r other association areas and served as the T h e pinnacle of this conception of the cor-
locus for higher-order associations between tical hierarchy is of course the addition of
sense data and motor programs from pri- language areas in the human brain-
mary areas. Association areas ultimately are inserted into an otherwise complete and
envisioned as an additional higher-order functional ape brain. T h e assumption that
reflex arc superimposed upon and elabo- Broca's area for speech is a new association
rating existing lower level reflex arcs area peculiar to the human brain has been
(Luria, 1980; Sherrington, 1906). There- represented in a number of schemes by the
fore association areas could be added as identification of some region within the
evolutionary after-thoughts with minimal third frontal convolution of the human
rewiring of other brain circuits. Each new brain that is assigned no homologous coun-
association area was one step removed from terpart in the monkey brain. T h e possibil-
ity that Broca's area has no prehuman by Allman (1990) and Kaas (1987, 1989).
homologue and could have been simply They argue that the multiplication of cor-
added on to an otherwise complete brain tical areas in many mammalian lineages
seems to be taken for granted in a number might be explained by the duplication of
of recent discussions of human brain evo- existing areas. They suggest that a new
lution (Passingham, 1981; Tobias, 1981; population of neurons could appear inter-
Falk, 1983) and language evolution (e.g., digitated in position between older popu-
Chomsky, 1972). Galaburda and Pandya lations as a result of some genetic accident
(1982) and Deacon (1984, 1988a, 1990c) that caused redundant production of the
provide architectonic and tracer evidence neurons from one of these regions (it is
that a homologue for Broca's area exists compared by Kaas, 1987 and 1989, to the
in the monkey brain, despite the fact that addition of an extra body segment in the
it plays no apparent role in vocal commu- evolution of lobsters; Gregory, 1935).
nication in monkeys. Recent studies of genetic mutants in fruit
A similar argument was presented by flies has demonstrated that at least in these
Geschwind (1964) and has been reasserted species genetic mutations can cause the
by a number of later writers concerning production of whole duplicate body sec-
the inferior parietal lobule of the human tions or limbs interdigitated between exist-
brain. Following the classic associationist ing structures. Allman (1 990) suggests
model of language processing, Geschwind that similar genetic mutations might
argues that this area plays a fundamental underly areal duplication events in mam-
role as an "association area of association malian cortical evolution. In fact, to account
areas." Its placement at the temporo-pari- for the number of such events that have
eto-occipital juncture seemed to ideally suit occurred this would have to be a somewhat
it for associating the outputs of association common sort of mutation.
cortices from different sensory modalities. It is unquestionable that new cortical
Since Geschwind conceived of word mean- areas have evolved in some of the larger
ings as complex associations between word mammal brains and that different lineages
sounds and a multitude of other sensory (e.g., cats and monkeys) exhibit different
associations abstracted from sensory expe- spatial arrangements and functional spe-
rience, an association area of association cializations of the cortical areas that have
areas would have to be the necessary sub- been added (Kaas, 1989). But is it reason-
strate for semantic processes. Posterior able to imagine that these areas have been
temporal-parietal-occipital damage often literally inserted between existing cortical
results in disturbances of semantic lan- areas by the addition of new neural tissue
guage comprehension. Geschwind argued in that position? This claim depends on the
that no homologue to this highest order possibility that functional areas of cortex
association area was evident in monkey are modular in their construction. T h e
cortices. According to this logic the addi- neurons that comprise a new cortical area
tion of this area during human evolution would need to be added along with speci-
was a necessary condition for language fications regarding intrinsic circuitry and
evolution. Language evolution becomes the afferent and efferent connections with
natural end point of a progressive process neighboring areas and subcortical sites.
of adding association areas on top of asso- This requirement is contradicted by
ciation areas in the course of mammalian developmental evidence that the afferent
brain evolution. This non-homology claim and efferent connections of a cortical area
has also been contradicted by subsequent are not specified by the information that
tracer experiments (e.g., Mesulam et al., is intrinsic to the cells in that area, but
1977; Seltzer and Pandya, 1980) and ani- rather by competitive interactions among
mal behavioral studies (e.g., Jarvis and competing axons from many areas. Even
Ettlinger, 1977). the transplantation of a section of cortex
Recently, a more sophisticated version into a novel position within a fetal brain
of an accretion theory has been suggested prior to the development of cortical con-
nections will not bring with it the functions less driven by reflex and habit. T h e newer
and connections appropriate to its site of the area then, the more indirect its link
origin (O'Leary and Stanfield, 1989; Stan- with the input and the more complex its
field and O'Leary, 1985; see discussion in functional properties. In this way the dif-
the next section). T h e transplanted area ferentiation of association areas from asso-
will develop functions and connections ciation areas could be correlated with an
appropriate to its new position. Thus, even additive functional hierarchy as well.
if some new area of cortex miraculously It turns out that many of the assumptions
appeared interdigitated between older cor- that initially supported this hierarchic
tical areas'in a developing brain it would scenario have been subsequently under-
not bring with it any new connectional or mined. T h e first difficulty to crop u p was
functional information. the discovery that association cortex did
not lack extensive subcortical connections
Is there an evolutionary sequence of (Diamond, 1982; LeGros Clark and North-
new cortical areas? field, 1939; Rose and Woolsey, 1949).
An alternative approach is to conceive Association areas cannot be conceived as
of new cortical areas as differentiating out added on top of a complete working sys-
of old areas rather than being created inde- tem, sending and receiving information
pendently adjacent to them. This has the only from adjacent lower level cortical
attractive property that new areas should areas. They have independent inputs and
continue to bear some functional and con- outputs and are thereby completely inte-
nectional interrelationship with their par- grated into the whole brain at every level
ent areas. Because there is a parent-descen- every bit as much as are "projection" areas.
dent relationship between areas there will More problematic still is the nature of these
also be an implicit sequential order of connections. T h e "highest" association
regional .evolution, depending on assump- areas exhibit extensive connections with
tions about the "initial brain." Correlated limbic cortical areas (Pandya and Yeterian,
with t h e order of the proposed evolution- 1985), whose evolution is presumed to pre-
ary sequence may also be an implied hier- date the evolution of primary projection
archy of increasing functional differentia- areas in all theories of cortical evolution.
tion and complexity. Recent tracer studies have also suggested
T h e comparative cytoarchitectonic stud- that association areas project to core mid-
ies of Brodmann (1909) and others brain and tectal areas and receive indirect
appeared t o corroborate associationist projections from these areas relayed
assumptions that association cortex was through the thalamus. They may even
newer than projection cortex and that some exhibit connectional topography that cor-
association areas could only be identified responds more to midbrain maps than to
in the most "advanced" brains. T h e order cortical sensory o r motor maps (Deacon et
of regional evolution of the cerebral cortex al., 1987). These features are also incom-
thus appeared to begin with primary sen- patible with the assumption that the "high-
sory receptive areas and motor output areas est" association areas are only connected
and involve the progressive differentiation with areas at the next hierarchic level down.
of ever higher association areas. In the ini- In many ways their principal links are to
tial state sensory and motor areas were some of the most primitive brain struc-
thought to be directly connected to one tures.
another to form direct reflex arcs. With Finally, there is the problem of archi-
the differentiation of new areas inserted tectonic a n d functional specialization.
between these primary areas the reflex arc Probably the most extreme architectonic
becomes more indirect and reflex action and functional specializations anywhere in
gives way to more complex and variable cortex can be found in the primary visual
associations between sensation and action. and motor areas of anthropoid brains. T h e
T h e more intermediate stages, the more primate striate cortex, for example,
complex the analytic capabilities and the exhibits highly derived cytoarchitecture
with distinct sublamination of layer IV, further specialized core areas developing
complex mosaic distribution of different within these specialized areas, and so on.
visual submodalities into a microscopic T h e ancient status claimed for association
matrix of architectonically distinct patches areas could account for their extensive
o r "tufts" (Livingstone and Hubel, 1988), connections with limbic structures and their
and approximately double the number of prominent links to midbrain systems. T h e
cells per cortical column of any other cor- progressive stages of differentiation also
tical area in any other mammal (Rockel et appear to correlate with connectional rela-
al., 1980). T h e s e a r e clearly recently tionships between cortical areas (Pandya
derived conditions that indicate a high and Yeterian, 1985). If it is assumed that
degree of functional and architectonic spe- cortical areas only retain connections with
cialization. T h e architecture of association their immediate precursors but not second
areas is generally less variable from area to generation precursors, this model could
area and species to species than is the explain the links between association areas
cytoarchitecture of specialized primary and limbic cortex as well as the lack of
areas (Sanides, 1970). This indicates that connections between limbic areas a n d
structural and functional specialization is either primary sensory-motor areas or their
not limited to and probably is less often adjacent belt areas.
exemplified in "higher order" association As noted earlier in this discussion, the
areas. most serious argument against Sanides'
Some of these arguments against the evolutionary sequence is the apparent exis-
classic view have also served as support for tence of specialized visual, auditory and
an almost exactly inverted view of regional somatic projection areas in all mammal
cortical evolution. Roughly inverted sce- brains, even in marsupials and mono-
narios have been proposed by Bishop tremes (Kaas, 1987). Even the primitive
(1959), von Bonin and Bailey (1961) and cortex of turtles exhibits representation of
Sanides (1969, 1970, 1975). Probably the visual and somatic responses in distinguish-
most ambitious and most widely adopted able regions crudely appropriate to their
of these is Sanides' theory of progressive topological position in mammalian cortex.
waves of cortical differentiation o r "Ur- An ancient status for these specialized sen-
trends." Sanides infers the sequential evo- sory areas contradicts Sanides' model.
lution of cortical areas from a trend toward One possible counter-response is to argue
increasing architectonic specialization that that the apparent homology between the
culminates in the evolution of specialized specialized primary sensory areas of
primary projection areas (see Fig. 9). Fol- advanced brains and the primary sensory
lowing the lead of Abbie (1942) and Dart areas of ancestral and conservative brains
(1934), Sanides argued that isocortical areas is incorrect. For example, von Bonin and
evolved from undifferentiated periallo- Bailey (1961) argue that the presumed
cortical zones along the borders of primi- homology between the hedgehog visual
tive hippocampal and olfactory cortex in a cortex and monkey primary visual cortex
series of stages of increasing differentia- is not supported by the cytoarchitectonic
tion. T h e trend is envisioned as a series of criteria Brodmann (1909) originally sug-
"growth rings" (Sanides, 1970) constituted gested. They conclude that it is far more
by progressively more specialized cortical similar to the more generalized areas of
areas differentiating out of relatively less visual association cortex. This interpreta-
differentiated areas. Areas that correspond tion is supported by the fact that in the
to the highest level association cortices in visual systems of the opossum and hedge-
the classic view comprise some of the most hog the thalamocortical projections of the
primitive ancestral areas in this view. T h e lateral geniculate nucleus (corresponding
most highly specialized areas in advanced to primary visual cortex projections) and
brains are envisioned to be the result of pulvinar nuclei (corresponding to extra-
specialized core areas developing within striate association cortex projections)
more generalized areas, and subsequently, extensively overlap (Diamond et al., 1985;
Kaas et al., 1970). Although the so-called of areas should be highest at its terminal
projection areas are specialized for receiv- end. If areas are capable of differentiatin g
ing relatively more direct information from out of other areas in the course of evolu-
peripheral sensors, all adjacent areas com- tion there should be an increasing number
prising a single modality receive indepen- of bifurcations as the process continues.
dent sensory afferents from the thalamus Each sense modality contains multiple asso-
and all share some thalamic connections in ciation areas at the same level of the cor-
common (Caviness and Frost, 1980; Dia- tical hierarchy but only one primary sen-
mond, 1982). sory area. This would not be likely if these
Hierarchic scenarios of cortical evolu- specialized areas represented a terminal
tion are appealing both because of their end in the evolutionary differentiation pro-
agreement with tacit assumptions about cess. And yet the extreme other end of the
mental progress and mental processes, and spectrum-paralimbic association areas—
because of the way they simplify the is not the level of the highest multiplicity
assumptions about connectional and func- of cortical areas either. In the visual modal-
tionaI integration associated with the addi- ity it appears that the most diversity and
tion of new parts to a complex brain. Add- multiplicity of cortical areas is found at
ing the new parts to the terminal end of a middle levels in the processing hierarchy.
growing hierarchy limits the presumed This is likely true of other modalities as
problems of integration with all lower well. This pattern is implausible in either
levels. It also provides an explanation for of the two general terminal addition sce-
the evolution of complex structures by narios.
demonstrating plausible intermediate steps Strict hierarchical terminal addition is
in complexity, differentiation and special- not the only possibility, nor is it necessarily
ization. One serious problem with both less complex than are non-hierarchic sce-
hierarchic schemes for explaining regional narios. Given that most cortical areas are
evolution of cortex is the constraint of the connected to more than one other area and
linear sequence itself. Ultimately, both the- that all are connected with distinct sub-
ories'are terminal addition theories. T h e cortical structures, there is no obvious sense
arguments in support of both are analo- in which a new cortical area can be thought
gous to those for terminal addition in gen- of as superimposed on an already complete
eral: addition of new structures to systems and functioning system-it must inevitably
that were complete in an adult of the pre- emerge in the middle of a complex inte-
ceding evolutionary stage; avoiding the grated network. Terminal addition con-
complication of inserting structural tributes no additional explanatory power
changes in the middle of a complex pro- toward solving the problem of the pre-
cess; and the assumption that additional established integration of new areas.
structures augment the function of the pre- Models of cortical evolution that make
ceding structures. As a result they are prone no assumptions about the order of appear-
to similar criticisms. It is not at all clear ance of cortical areas have been outlined
that cortical areas within any one brain are by Allman (1982,1990) and by Kaas (1987,
organized according to simple linear hier- 1989). They each argue that the multipli-
archies, nor is it obvious how cortical areas cation of cortical sensory areas of the visual
in different lineages can be homologized system can be explained by duplication of
with respect to a strict number of steps in existing cortical areas followed by subse-
the evolutionary sequence. For example, quent differentiation of function in the new
the primate visual system exhibits at least area. Presumably the new area will initially
two, and probably three or four, distinct share the same connections and cell types
processing pathways for different aspects as its older twin and gradually will come to
of visual perception that diverge from gain o r lose connections and exhibit mod-
striate cortex into distinct groups of asso- ifications in cellular architecture associated
ciation areas. Like a branching tree struc- with its changes in function. It is often the
ture, one would assume that multiplication case that adjacent cortical areas serving the
same sensory modality also exhibit con- might be too complex to be handled effi-
nections with similar structures elsewhere ciently by a single large visual area, do
in the brain-sometimes to separate divi- appear to be handled by only a few visual
sions of these structures, at other times areas in small brains. T h e r e is n o evidence
overlapping in connectivity, and it is not that "new" functions have evolved, only
unusual that neurons in common afferent that existing functions have become seg-
sources will send collateral branches of the regated and distributed to parallel visual
same axon t o adjacent cortical areas. processors. If processing all these modali-
Duplication of this sort would also account ties together in a single area is merely an
for the many striking homologies between efficiency problem, we should expect that
all isocortical areas. at least some very small brains would also
T h e duplication of an existing area is segregate visual functions into the almost
presumed to be a relatively innocuous acci- two dozen visual areas that endow large
dental mutation. However, the availability primate brains and that at least some large
of redundant areas frees one of the two brains would collapse visual processing into
from the constraints of the primary adap- only one o r two visual areas, but this is not
tation so that it is able to develop some seen. There are clearly size factors involved.
additional, complementary visual function. Accretion assumptions are not essential
In the primate visual system it is clearly the to explain the appearance of new cortical
case that distinct visual areas seem to be areas in mammalian evolution. A scenario
specialized for different submodality func- for the early stages of mammalian cortical
tions in vision, such as color, form and evolution was presented by Lende (1963,
movement perception. Thus, by duplica- 1969) that does not make any assumptions
tion and subsequent differentiation of about evolutionary precedence of cortical
function the entire collection of interde- areas. He argues that the pattern exhibited
pendent visual areas could have been pro- in the common ancestor to all mammals
duced. T h e apparently hierarchic arrange- (including marsupials and monotremes)
ment of these areas is not explicitly included cortical projection fields that were
explained in either model, but probably it extensively overlapping a n d t h e r e f o r e
could be argued that the one area that poorly differentiated from one another. By
retains the ancestral function becomes the a gradual process of differentiation over
more primary area and the differentiated the course of evolution each projection field
one becomes more secondary. Progression retracted with respect to the other until in
from one to the next in sequence could most modern species each projection field
then be explained simply on the basis of is exclusive of all others. In Lende's view
the influence of adjacent areas. the marsupial and basal insectivore cortices
Allman (1990) and Kaas (1987, 1989) represent a state where the retraction into
assume that new areas are added to an oth- separate territories is nearly complete, with
erwise complete visual system, inserted only somatic and motor areas still overlap-
between existing cortical areas. This is con- ping. Because it is purely a differentiation
sistent with their focus on advancement and model there is no addition of areas and no
augmentation of function as the prime distinction between old and new cortical
mover in the evolution of new cortical fields, just old and new patterns. A closely
areas-duplicated areas become recruited related theory of the evolution of connec-
to some new adaptive function that aug- tional differentiation has been proposed by
ments o r complements existing functions. Ebbesson (1980, 1984) and will be dis-
This argument is used to explain how dis- cussed in the next section.
tinct cortical visual areas have become spe- Lende's model was only intended to
cialized for distinct visual submodalities, explain the earliest stages of mammalian
such as color, movement, or form percep- cortical evolution (better resolution phys-
tion. A major criticism is that the separate iological recording techniques have largely
functional specializations of the different contradicted his claims about the lack of
visual areas, which Kaas (1989) suggests differentiation in primitive brains; Kaas,
isocortical evolution
by areal differentiation
FIG. 10. Depiction of a scheme of progressive differentiation of cortical areas from one another that does
not assume an evolutionary sequence in which some coexisting areas are older than o r ancestral to others.
T h e figures are meant to represent flattened cortical hemispheres with limbic cortical areas representing the
white perimeter of each and isocortical subareas represented by the gray areas contained within. Below each
of the three brains of increasing size is a block diagram of the ancestor-descendent relationship for the
progressive generation of new cortical subdivisions. T h e use of diverging shades of gray is intended to represent
the differentiation of both descendents of a subdivided ancestral area from the architectonic and functional
characteristics of this ancestor.

1987). However, a simple differentiation hierarchic terminal addition scenarios of


theory suggests some interesting alterna- regional cortical evolution. If multiple new
tive interpretations of area multiplication areas result from the differentiation of pre-
problems in more differentiated mamma- viously unitary areas it is not necessary that
lian brains. In these brains all the projec- one of the resulting areas be considered
tion areas are differentiated from one the homologue of the ancestral area and
another and, with the exception of the the other o r others be considered derived.
somatic and motor areas, they have also If we assume either that a new cortical area
been separated by interdigitated associa- results from duplication of an existing area
tion areas. T h e idea of progressive differ- o r that it differentiates out of some sector
ential retraction of previously diffusely of a pre-existing area and eventually takes
overlapping projections might account for on a function that is somehow comple-
differentiation of previously undifferen- mentary to that of the other area, then it
tiated association areas within each sensory should follow that both areas will be
modality. A single sense modality might be changed in the process.
conceived as becoming progressively seg- In this regard, the primary visual cortex
regated into differentiated submodalities. in primates cannot even be strictly homolo-
This hypothesis (represented in Fig. 9) does gized to the primary visual cortex in the
not necessarily predict that the interdigi- squirrel because in the squirrel many of the
tated cortex between primary areas should visual functions handled in the primary
be any more or less complex than projec- visual area are in the primate partially dis-
tion areas nor that it should be performing tributed to some of its many more numer-
any higher function. ous nearby visual areas. In a hypothetical
T h e assumption that one structure has "initial brain" with only one visual area all
to be older or more conserved than another the distinct submodality analyses would
is actually not even a necessary premise for have to be performed within that area—
luminosity, movement, color, form, spatial areas determined? This rewiring problem
relationships, local features, etc. There is is most troublesome for addition o r dupli-
no visual area in a brain with many visual cation hypotheses. If an area is completely
areas that performs all these functions. new its connections must presumably
Even a duplicate area and its progenitor invade territories in other structures that
should be expected to change with respect are occupied by projections from pre-exist-
to one another, in the course of subsequent ing areas, and it must itself be invaded by
evolution, so that neither resulting area will axons from other structures that would
be directly comparable to the original. Thus otherwise have found other targets in the
it is probably more accurate to view the brain. But area duplication does not escape
multiplication of cortical areas in terms of these problems. A duplicated area may have
progressive differentiation of all areas with all the afferent and efferent specificities
respect to one another. Both areas created appropriate t o the original area but there
after the subdivision of some previous area still must be overlap in efferent projections
will differ slightly from one another and from the duplicate and the original area as
from ancestral structure, and these differ- well as a dividing o r sharing of afferents.
ences will likely increase over time (see Fig. Any subsequent differentiation of t h e
10). From this perspective it does not mat- duplicated area from its progenitor likely
ter where in a cortical hierarchy the new also involves changes of connections,
division appears, the differentiation pat- including both the loss of many of those
tern will be essentially the same. shared with the original area as well as a
It cannot automatically be assumed that shift of its efferents to new targets.
there is any strict hierarchy from function- T h e possibility of connectional reorgani-
ally and architectonically simple to com- zation also suggests other options for neo-
plex cortical areas or from phylogenet- genesis. If connectional organization can
ically old to new cortical areas. A ranking be altered then it is not necessary for ,new
of areas with respect to relative phyloge- structure to be added for new functional
netic age or functional complexity is not areas to emerge, it is only necessary for
unambiguously reflected in neuroanatom- their underlying connections to change.
ical data and may not be consistent with Since ultimately the patterns of connection
developmental considerations of cortical determine function within the nervous sys-
differentiation. Nor are we justified in tem, all theories of neogenesis of cortical
assuming that the addition of new func- structure and function must address this
tional subdivisions of cortex correlates with issue. A theory that fails to explain how
an enhancement of function. T h e addition underlying connectional reorganization
of new cortical areas still needs to be exam- takes place is fundamentally incomplete.
ined with respect to the influence of brain T h e most obvious hypothesis for
size. Extensive multiplicity of cortical areas explaining the evolution of new connec-
is never seen in small brains, and the most tions is that they are simply added. Because
extensive multiplicity of areas appears only this hypothesis requires axons to enter
in very large brains (e.g., the human brain). novel target areas that are occupied by
This suggests that areal multiplication other connections and ultimately displace
might be the result of facultative devel- some of those connections o r form new
opmental responses to brain size and not synapses in that area, it has been called the
distinct genetic adaptations. invasion hypothesis. T h e basic features of this
process are diagrammed in Figure 11. Cells
Reorganization and the neogenesis of from one area either change their target
neural circuits o r produce collateral branches that invade
Whether we explain area multiplication a new target area. This idea has had a long
and functional differentiation in terms of history in comparative neuroanatomy (e.g.,
addition or differentiation there is still a Ariëns Kappers et al., 1936; Herrick, 1920)
major problem area that must be addressed: and seems essential to explain the appear-
How are the neural connections of these ance of certain neural pathways that occur
simple accretion hypothesis axonal invasion hypothesis

before duplication-addition after duplication-addition before axonal invasion after axonal invasion

/','
. . parcellation hypothesis equivalent cell population hypothesis

diffuse connectivity differential connectivity


before parcellation after parcellation before cell migration after cell migration

FIG. 11. Four commonly cited o r assumed rewiring hypotheses are depicted with source nuclei indicated by
shaded ellipses, cortical (or other nuclear) targets indicated by shaded boxes, and connections indicated by
black arrows connecting them. Antecedent and consequent conditions a r e shown in neighboring boxes. 'The
simple accretion hypothesis is depicted at the top left, in which a new structure is added t o the brain including
its own new connections. T h e invasion hypothesis is depictedat the top right, in which a new set of connections,
or connections originally targeting some other area, invade and establish synapses in a novel brain structure.
The parcellation hypothesis is depicted at the bottom left, in which previously diffusely interconnected
structures lose some of their diffuse connections in a complementary fashion so as to produce subdivisions of
each that are connectionally distinct. T h e "equivalent cell" hypothesis is depicted at the bottom right, in
which cells from one region migrate into another structure and attract their afferents t o this new structural
position.

in relatively recent lineages but not ances- comparative evidence demonstrates a


tral lineages (Northcutt, 1984). Invasion remarkable conservatism of connection
was long thought to be the explanation of patterns within all vertebrate brains despite
the progressive development of telence- radical differences in size, morphology and
phalic specializations in vertebrate evolu- differentiation. T h e overwhelming major-
tion. However, many of the telencephalic ity of major pathways seem to be evident
connections that were formerly thought in all vertebrates and probably represent
absent in anamniotic vertebrates have an inheritance from the common protover-
turned out to be demonstrable with axonal tebrate ancestor. Ebbesson argues that
tracing techniques (Ebbesson, 1980; there are no developmental or compara-
Northcutt, 1981). I n support of this tive cases that would require the assump-
hypothesis Northcutt (1984) argues that the tion that axons must have invaded an
presence of a spinothalamic pathway in all unusual target (although his own theory
reptiles, birds and mammals but in no other has been called unfalsifiable in this regard).
group but cartilaginous fishes and the pres- All connection changes in the course of
ence of palliospinal pathways only in birds vertebrate evolution can b e explained
and mammals are each best explained by entirely in terms of changes in the relative
invasion. numbers of preexisting connections-
However, Ebbesson (1980) questions the sometimes complete loss of connections-
plausibility of invasion on the grounds that in prior lineages. Ebbesson (1980) refers
to this as the parcellation theory of brain evo- dence (i.e., that members of two or more
lution. Invasion, he argues, either simply closely related taxa will follow the same
does not occur o r else is extremely rare. course of development to the stage of their
A schematic depiction of the parcella- divergence), this would mean that two
tion hypothesis is presented in Figure 11. species' developmental patterns would
Parcellation theory presumes that t h e coincide to the point of the first parcella-
ancestral condition consists of a relatively tion event that distinguished them, and
undifferentiated pattern of connections therefore that parcellation events that fol-
between two given structures. It is pro- low others in evolutionary time, and fur-
posed that progressive loss or retraction of ther parcel the same projection. system,
a selected subpopulation of these fibers is should also be expected t o occur subse-
responsible for subsequent differentiation quent to the first in development. This pre-
of each ancestral structure into two, con- dicts that early stages of brain development
nectionally and functionally distinct sub- should be characterized by the presence of
divisions. In the course of time further par- diffuse axonal projections and later stages
cellations of these separate projection would proceed through progressive par-
systems can result in yet further functional cellation processes.
specialization. This process would account In general terms this pattern of pro-
for increasing multiplication of areas and gressive culling of initially diffuse connec-
increased differentiation of functions in the tions is indeed exhibited in brain devel-
course of brain evolution. It also explicitly opment. Initial axonal projections appear
predicts many details of connectional orga- to be less selective and more exuberant than
nization that should correlate with areal the projections that survive to adulthood,
multiplication and differentiation in cor- and as a result fetal axons contact many
tex. Because subdivided areas originate more targets and a much wider variety of
from a single area they each will inherit targets than do adult axons. During sub-
most but not all of the connections of that sequent development these superfluous
ancestral area. For example if an extrastri- connections are culled, resulting in. con-
ate visual area in some ancestral lineage nections that are far more specific and
becomes subdivided in its descendents we topographically organized (Jacobson, 1978;
should expect that the lateral posterior Purves and Lichtman, 1980, 1985). T h e
(pulvinar) thalamic source of the ancestral details of this process will be discussed in
afferents would be the same for the descen- the next section.
dent subareas although perhaps subdi- Ebbesson (1980) argues that this devel-
vided into new subdivisions, and we should opmental pattern recapitulates the ances-
expect that the tectal targets of its efferents tral sequence of differentiation of each
should likewise be the same structure o r brain area and its connections. These tran-
some new subdivisions of that structure. sient connections within the fetal brain are
These predictions appear to be reflected therefore viewed as "fossils" of earlier pat-
in the organization of afferent and efferent terns of brain organization. Viewing cer-
connections of brains with relatively few tain transient events in neural. develop-
visual areas as compared to those with many ment as "fossils" may also help explain the
visual areas (Diamond et al., 1985; Kaas and appearance and subsequent elimination of
Huerta, 1988), as well as in other systems. whole classes of neurons during develop-
Ebbesson further argues that the evo- ment that serve as transitory targets for
lutionary history of parcellation events is projections ultimately destihed for other
recapitulated in developmental processes. targets. However, this strictly recapitula-
Parcellation must occur at some particular tionist interpretation is not critical to the
stage in the development of existing con- parcellation hypothesis and weakens its
nections in any organism and subsequent generality and predictive power. Although
further parcellation processes must be pre- Ebbesson's (1980) initial examples com-
ceded by this first parcellation. Following pare the adult organization of connections
von Baer's principle of character prece- in primitive fish to embryonic connections
in terrestrial vertebrates (and therefore tion theory. Each of these two mechanisms
have earned the criticism that it assumes a for connectional change correspondingly
crude scala naturae view of living species supports. additive versus differentiational
as well as strict terminal addition), the theories of brain structure evolution. T h e
underlying assumptions of parcellation parcellation hypothesis is most consistent
theory do not require terminal modifica- with area addition scenarios involving dif-
tion. T h e relative timing of fetal parcel- ferentiation of new areas from old areas
lation events need not be an exact reca- and is inconsistent with simple addition
pitulation of evolutionary events and the hypotheses that presume the invasion of
hierarchic 'dependency of one parcellation new axons. It is probably also inconsistent
event on another during development does with area duplication scenarios, since it
not necessarily imply a corresponding phy- would reject arguments about projection-
logenetic order as well. map duplication as invasion hypotheses.
A more flexible version of the theory can But in addition, parcellation is also
be articulated if we assume that a new par- inconsistent with many of the existing dif-
cellation process can affect connections at ferentiation theories of cortical evolution
any stage of brain development during the because it does not predict that ancestral
course of evolution. Parcellation processes cortical areas can remain unchanged as new
that alter connections early in ontogeny areas differentiate out of them. For this to
will operate on less differentiated connec- happen the older of the two areas would
tion patterns than parcellation processes have to maintain all of its previous con-
that occur later in ontogeny. Presumable nections and the newer area would be dis-
parcellation processes during development tinguished only by its lack of certain con-
depend on earlier parcellation processes, nections and not by the possession of
and so a subtle change at an early stage connections not also present in the older
might have radical consequences for adult area. Considering either thalamic afferents
structure. A wider range of reorganiza- o r subcortical efferents, it is clearly not the
tional effects should result from mutations case that there are cortical areas that pos-
that influence parcellation early in devel- sess all the connections of any of their
opment, particularly if subsequent parcel- neighbors; each has slightly different
lation events are undermined or biased by although often partially overlapping affer-
the earlier changes. But if changes in par- ents and efferents. T h e adjacency of affer-
cellation processes can occur at any devel- ent sources and efferent targets of neigh-
opmental stage, then brain development boring cortical areas as well as the partial
cannot be a strict recapitulation of the order overlap in some of these is strong support
of phyletic events in brain evolution. A very for the parcellation hypothesis.
early change may have been very recently Invasion is a necessary hypothesis for
acquired whereas a relatively late parcel- both additive and recapitulational theories
lation change may date to a much earlier of regional cortical evolution. Structural
evolutionary epoch. Recently acquired addition is doubly challenged by the par-
parcellation changes that affect an early cellation hypothesis because the latter de-
stage of development could fundamentally nies both the possibility that new structures
alter the pattern of all subsequent devel- can arise from nothing and the possibility
opmental events so that they no longer of invasion of new structures by axons that
reflect any meaningful phyletic series. did not contact it ancestrally. Even though
T h e parcellation hypothesis is the inverse they do not assume structural addition,
of the invasion hypothesis both in its mech- sequential differentiation theories, such as
anism and in the assumptions that it makes the traditional evolutionary hierarchy from
about ancestry-descent relationships of projection to association areas o r Sanides
brain structure. In more general terms, the inverted hierarchy from association areas
invasion hypothesis is an example of an to specialized sensory and motor core areas,
additive theory a n d t h e parcellation are also both tied to the assumption that
hypothesis is an example of a differentia- axon invasion events have been common-
place. If Ebbesson is correct in assuming they are connected. Target sites are under-
that these are rare events in evolution then determined but probably not undeter-
all of these hypotheses must be abandoned. mined by genetically pre-established
It is important to recognize that the par- molecular affinitiesbetween growing axons
cellation hypothesis is a stronger claim and potential target cell substrates. During
about what can and cannot happen in brain embryogenesis axons do in fact grow out
evolution. Invasion hypotheses do not deny from their cells of origin to invade differ-
the possibility that parcellation may play a ent structures distantly located in the brain.
major role in brain evolution. Invasion is En route to their genetically underdeter-
an additional assumption beyond parcel- mined target zones they also may pass
lation. One difficulty with denying any pos- through structures with which they estab-
sibility of invasion is that to do so often lish no synaptic contacts o r only transient
requires hypothesizing many more con- contacts. Both the active "exploratory"
nectional changes in order to explain a nature of embryonic axons and the pre-
phylogenetic difference that can otherwise specification of initial target zones are
be explained by only one o r two invasion potentially troublesome for parcellation
events (Northcutt, 1984). Although Ebbes- theory. However, permanent loss of many
son's argument for the ancient status of connectional affinities over the course of
preset axon-target affinities is also corrob- vertebrate evolution is entirely consistent
orated by evidence of the ancient and with the theory.
highly conservative nature of molecular cell Both the invasion hypothesis and the
communication and recognition mecha- parcellation hypothesis can probably be
nisms (Fasolo and Malacarne, 1988), such used t o explain almost any possible
specificity may be determined by complex arrangement of connections in the living
relationships of timing and hierarchically vertebrates. T h e invasion hypothesis makes
organized interactive effects that render many more assumptions regarding each
this specificity somewhat degenerate (Edel- individual rewiring event, whereas the par-
man, 1987). cellation hypothesis makes some other
A more fundamental criticism of par- rather troubling assumptions about the ini-
cellation theory in its strong form is that tial condition of vertebrates and often
it is preformationist (see numerous com- requires considerable theoretical, circum-
mentaries following Ebbesson, 1984). locution to explain what could be explained
Either some initial protovertebrate brain by a single invasion event. Each handles
(possibly long antedating the vertebrates) certain examples better than the other.
must be considered to have been com- A third alternative hypothesis, that to
pletely undifferentiated in connectivity and some extent can serve as a bridge between
therefore totipotential from an evolution- these two polar opposites, is the equivalent
ary standpoint, or some of the initial con- cell hypothesis suggested by Karten (1969;
nection patterns must have been pre- Nauta and Karten, 1970). On the assump-
formed from t h e start and require tion that the connectional relationship
explanation in some other way, e.g., inva- between two different cell groups within
sion. T h e first possibility is more consistent the brain is specified by some features spe-
with the exclusivity assumption of parcel- cific to those cells, their connection should
lation theory. be maintained even if one of these cell pop-
There is no stage of brain development ulations became displaced o r actively
that exhibits a corresponding totally inter- migrates to an entirely different location.
connected undifferentiated state. Although Karten (1969; Karten and Shimuzu, 1989)
there is some degree of initial overproduc- proposes this as a possible explanation for
tion of projections and poor differentiation the apparent homologies between thalamic
of target sites in the fetal brain these con- projections to the dorsal ventricular ridge
nections are neither totipotent nor com- in birds and to the isocortex in mammals.
pletelv undifferentiated. Most pairs of brain He argues that cells which in avian and
structures never pass through a stage where reptilian brains are destined to form the
dorsal ventricular ridge may take a differ-these trends and the theoretical assump-
ent migratory pathway in mammals and tions about homologies, progression, size
ended up in cortex. In the process they increase and cortical neogenesis have been
would also attract their thalamic afferentsshown to be seriously flawed. Although
to this new target site. T h e general formpatterns are evident it cannot be decided
of the equivalent cell hypothesis is sche- o n the basis of comparative evidence
matically diagrammed in Figure 1 1. With whether they are merely secondary archi-
respect to mammalian cortical evolution it tectonic adaptations to differences in brain
has the advantage of also accounting for size, adaptations for sensory-motor spe-
the significantly increased number of cellscialization, o r independent macroevo-
that occupy mammalian as compared to lutionary tendencies for increased cogni-
bird and reptile cortex. This hypothesis tive complexity and diversity. However, the
could thus explain the apparent "invasion" predictable relationships between these
of new thalamic afferents into the cerebraltrends and differences in brain size as well
cortex and also the apparent "invasion" of as the parallelisms exhibited in distant lin-
new subcortical targets by cerebral cortical
eages suggests that many of these patterns
cells without requiring the appearance of may instead be the result of underlying
any new connections or any change in the developmental homologies that a r e
underlying topology of connection pat- expressed differentially with respect to
terns. However, the theory makes strong brain size o r certain sensory-motor spe-
assumptions about the specificity of devel-cializations (e.g., regression of vision in
oping connections that may limit its gen- echolocating bats).
erality. A considerable body of new data is
Increasing the amount of comparative emerging concerning the development of
data will not by itself be able to help us the brain that can help sort out which evo-
choose between these alternative hypoth- lutionary hypotheses are tenable and which
are not. Obviously brains d o not evolve
eses. T h e homological ambiguities limit our
from one adult form to another, although
ability to clearly discern what is a new con-
nection and what is a modified ancestral this is often how brain evolution is por-
connection. And since each of the different trayed. In fact, most of the well established
hypotheses a r e sufficiently flexible t o theories of cortical evolution make no
account for nearly any pattern, we have assumptions at all about brain develop-
only parsimony assumptions to rely upon. ment processes (except possibly the
Unfortunately, the capricious nature of theerroneous assumption that they should re-
evolutionary process suggests that we capitulate phylogenetic trends). But phy-
should not place too much confidence in logenetic change in brain structure is the
parsimony arguments. Each of the alter- result of changes in the process of brain
native theories proposed to account for development a n d ultimately must be
connectional reorganization depends on explained in terms of developmental
specific assumptions about the ontogenetic mechanisms. T h e importance of ontogeny
processes that ultimately determine con- to the understanding of brain evolution is
nectional specificity. We can thus turn t onot that it recapitulates phylogeny-it
the ontogenetic data to look for develop- almost certainly does not-but that it con-
mental constraints that can rule out certain
strains the possible modes of variation that
versions of these hypotheses and develop- phylogenetic changes can exhibit (Alberch,
mental patterns that might suggest alter- 1982; Katz, 1982; Smith-Gill, 1983). If
native mechanisms. there are only certain ways that cell pop-
ulations, functional areas o r connections
ONTOGENY CONSTRAINS PHYLOGENY can develop within a brain, then patterns
Ontogeny of neural populations, of phylogenetic change will tend to be lim-
connections and functional areas ited accordingly and the possibility of par-
There are clear trends in mammalian allel evolutionary trends arising in inde-
brain evolution. However, the evidence for pendent lineages will be increased.
one area of a donor's cortex and trans-
planted to a different area of a recipient's
cortex (Fig. 12). In the mature brain the
transplanted cortical tissue takes on the
sensory or motor functions, assumes the
cytoarchitecture and even develops the
appropriate afferent and efferent connec-
tions characteristic of its new cortical posi-
tion rather than its place of origin (O'Leary
and Stanfield, 1989; Stanfield and O'Leary,
1985). T h i s relatively late, interactive
mature determination of cortical structure and
connections function has very significant implications
for the evolution of isocortical subdivi-
sions. T h e evolution of a new cortical
F IG . 12. Fetal cortical transplant experiment in rats region must therefore be a systemic pro-
in which either a frontal cortical sector is transplanted
to the posterior cortex of a host or a posterior cortical cess and not the result of the isolated local
sector is translated to the anterior cortex of a host. expression of genetic mutations.
In either case, when the animal matures it is found T h e structural and functional differen-
that the cortical efferents from these transplants proj- tiation of any cortical area is thus not spec-
ect to the appropriate targets for their new position ified by the specific local cell lineages that
rather than the target specified by their original posi-
tions (i.e., rostral sensory/motor areas send efferents constitute it, and takes place considerably
to the brainstem and spinal cord whereas posterior after neurogenesis has been completed for
visual areas send efferents to the tectum). all cortical areas. T h e determination of
what constitutes a distinct functional area,
where its boundaries are, how big it is with
A number of features of the neural respect to neighboring areas, the local spe-
developmental process in mammals are cializations of its myelo- and cyto-architec-
incompatible with scenarios of cortical evo- ture and its connections with other' areas
lution which assume that cortical areas can are all largely independent of which cells
appear, differentiate, or even change their constitute that area. New cortical areas that
relative sizes as independent units during appear in the course of evolution cannot
the course of evolution. This is because the have been added as whole units corre-
information that specifies the size, archi- sponding to specific populations of new
tectonic organization, afferent and effer- cells.
ent connections and therefore the basic Classic theories of additive cortical evo-
function of a cortical area during its devel- lution are clearly inconsistent with this
opment is determined by factors extrinsic constraint of cortical development because
to the cells that comprise that area. T h e it undermines any possibility of discrete
neurons that comprise the fetal cortex are terminal addition. It also undermines addi-
nearly all produced prior to the stage at tive theories of differential area expansion
which the cortex is invaded by thalamic as well (e.g., differential addition of cells to
afferents and prior to the stage at which association cortex with respect to primary
axons originating from cortical neurons cortex during cortical advancement). T h e
reach their targets. At this stage the cell addition of cells to one sector of cortex
groups in different positions on the cortical rather than another does not determine
mantle a r e effectively totipotent with which of the cells will or will not be included
respect to their ability to assume any of the within the functional regions that develop
different functional roles exhibited by cell in that sector. T h e enlargement of the cor-
groups in the adult cortex (O'Leary, 1989). tex cannot be thought of in piecemeal
T h e most striking evidence for this comes terms. Addition of new cortical areas can-
from fetal transplantation studies where not be the direct cause of the addition of
sectors of fetal cortex are removed from new brain mass. Given the fact that there
is no specific topographic information rep- of parcellation theory it was noted that the
resented in the developing cortex, cortical first axonal connections during develop-
expansion must be considered as a whole ment are over-exuberant and relatively
and area by area size determination must unselective. These initially diffuse project-
be a consequence of secondary processes. ing cortical afferents and efferents com-
T h e expansion of the total cortical man- pete for dwindling synapses within their
tle is probably not determined by a simple target areas. This competition results in a
increase in neurogenesis either. T h e target significant culling of axons and axon col-
size of the cerebral cortex is likely deter- laterals and some cell death. T h e relative
mined prior to neurogenesis for the struc- correlation of the neural activity of an axon
ture as a whole. During neurogenesis pre- with others in the near vicinity which relay
curser cells in a germinal layer deep to the similar information to an area is thought
developing cortex divide to produce neu- to play a significant role in determining
rons that leave this zone and migrate along which axons will be retained and which will
the length of special radial glial guide cells be eliminated (Purves and Lichtman, 1985).
that gxtend from the germinal layer to the T h e resultant parcellation of connections
surface of cortex. These guides effectively largely determines which structural and
limit tangential migration (although see functional characteristics will develop.
Walsh and Cepko, 1988, for discussion of This is demonstrated dramatically in the
exceptions) and serve to align succeeding case of cortical efferents. In an infant rat,
cells along this radial column occupying cells in layer V of all regions of the isocor-
ever more superficial positions. Radial tex appear t o give rise to axons that extend
guides and the germinal zone at their base into the spinal cord, but in the adult rat
probably form distinct proliferative units, only rostrally located somatomotor areas
or ontogenetic columns (Rakic, 1988). All contain cells with spinal projections. More
cell types within that columnar unit of cor- caudally located areas, specialized for visual
tex are derived from a common polyclonal o r auditory modalities, lose these spinal
precurser. Earlier it was noted that the connections but retain connections to the
number of cells within a column of cortex tectum (see Fig. 13). This explains why het-
of t h e same tangential dimensions is erotopic cortical transplants take on the
approximately the same in species with very connections and functions appropriate t o
different size brains (Rockel et al., 1980). their new cortical position. A similar pat-
This indicates that neurogenesis within an tern of overexuberant and relativelv undif-
ontogenetic columnar unit is invariable ferentiated connections followed by later
across species and irrespective of brain size. culling of a large number of these connec-
Cortical expansion must therefore be tions has been extensively documented for
understood in terms of the addition of more thalamocortical projections and for corti-
ontogenetic columns as opposed to the cocortical connections, among many other
increase of cell production within these systems (see reviews in Jacobson, 1978;
columns (Rakic, 1988). Since the multipli- Purves and Lichtman, 1980, 1985; Purves,
cation or germinal precursors which will 1988).
establish ontogenetic columns occurs prior Connectional interactions must also play
to the terminal differentiation of neurons the major role in determining the size that
from these precursors, the determination a source o r target structure will attain. T h e
of the size of the cortical mantle must be elimination or reduction of afferent con-
determined prior t o neurogenesis within nections to a cortical area during fetal
the cortex. development can cause it to be reduced in
T h e determination of area dimensions size, can cause neighboring areas to be-
and boundaries within the developing cor- come enlarged, and can cause a corre-
tex must occur subsequent to neurogenesis sponding displacement of t h e cortical
by virtue of o t h e r mechanisms. This boundary between them (Rakic, 1988).
appears largely to be the result of afferent Deafferentation does not seem to diminish
and efferent interactions. In the discussion the numbers of cells per cortical column
nections. It appears that alternative pro-
jections inevitably will substitute for the
lost afferents. However, some degree of
cell death-particularly at early stages—
may play a role in cortical parcellation and
distinguishes certain cortical areas from
others (Finlay and Slattery, 1983).
The displacement hypothesis
An alternative general model of connec-
immature tional reorganization processes that takes
connections
into account both allometric effects and
the competitive parcellation process that
sculpt cortical areas can be derived from
these developmental considerations. As a
result of investigating different problems
in comparative neuroanatomy, Deacon
mature (1984, 1988b), Finlay et al. (1987), Purves
connections
(1988) and Wilczynski (1984) have each
suggested that ontogenetic factors play a
central role in the reorganization of neural
FIG. 13. Exuberant efferent cortical projections and circuits in response to differences in neural
culling of connections in development is depicted with populations, regressive processes and per-
respect to frontal somatomotor areas and posterior
visual areas. Early in the development of an infant rat
turbations of maturation schedules, o r
pyramidal cells from layer V of nearly all cortical homoplaseous changes in peripheral sen-
regions have axons that reach these targets. These sory o r motor structures. These views are
exuberant axons are later culled in a parcellation pro- similar enough t o be capable of synthesis
cess driven by dynamic interactions between com- into a single general model of the struc-
peting axons and their targets.
tural reorganization processes underlying
most brain evolution.
in that area, only the number of columns T h e displacement hypothesis, as it can be
that are contained within a projection area. called, argues that loss of connections,
In other regions of the brain, more limited acquisition of additional connections o r
in their possible sources of afferent input replacement of one class of connections by
o r efferent targets, a loss of connections another occurs when competitive axonal
can induce significant cell death. This interactions are biased by contextual events
appears to be the case with many periph- during development. This can happed as a
eral afferent targets (e.g., the lateral genic- result of changes in relative size relation-
ulate nucleus, Rakic, 1988) and efferent ships (an extreme example of which might
sources (e.g., brain stem motor nuclei, Alley, be complete cell death for a particular tar-
1974; Sohal, 1976). This cell death is pre- get or source), changes in the amount o r
sumed to play a role in the functional intercorrelation of afferent information to
matching of peripheral afferents to target one system as opposed to another, or
neuronal populations without the need for changes in the relative importance of ini-
genetic changes in order to specifically tial axon-target affinities, or, changes in
match afferents and cell populations in developmental timing. Four possible modes
every instance of size change in evolution of connectional displacement are depicted
o r of peripheral homoplasy (Cowan, 1973; in Figure 14. Although the figure depicts
Cowan et al., 1984; Finlay et al., 1987; Wil- size relationships, this can be understood
czynski, 1984). T h e multipotentiality of metaphorically to represent competitive
cortical cells both for afferent and efferent biases of all kinds. For example, synchro-
connections probably accounts for the lack nization of target cell maturation and
of significant cell death due to loss of con- axonal arrival would increase the likeli-
axonal connectivity after axonal displacement axonal connectivity after
efferent target expansion efferent target reduction
hypothesis

ancestral condition

axonal connectivity
before allometric
reorganization

axonal connectivity after axonal connectivity after


afferent source expansion afferent source reduction

FIG. 14 . T h e displacement hypothesis is depicted with four possible interpretations of invasion-like effects.
In each case either the effective enlargement or reduction of targets or afferents (depicted by the size of the
structure) is invoked to explain the source of bias driving the displacement of connections from one target
to another. An analogous pattern could be produced by relative increases o r decreases of axon-target affinities
or by heterochronic advantages of some afferents over others that mature at different times. These could
also be depicted in this manner by assuming that the relative size of the structures depicted represents afferent-
target biases in general. Although displacement can also explain parcellation processes, these are not depicted
here. They would roughly follow Ebbesson's schema with the added provision that parcellation is not spon-
taneous, but must be induced by a change in the relative numbers of target synapses with respect to competing
axons o r changes in axon-target affinities. Even if enlargement of both afferent and target populations during
generalized size increase is isometric, there may be limited collateral extent of correlated axon activity such
that diffuse overlap of connectivity could not be maintained and axons from the same source would have a
better chance of eliminating interdigitate axons from more diverse origins.

hood of synapse formation with respect to hypothesis it assumes that the basic molec-
axons arriving out of synch with cell mat- ular affinities between initial connections
uration. As a result heterochronous and their targets a r e essentially conserva-
changes in developmental time schedules tive, and if anything, only change in
for different systems may be a source of response t o prior displacement events,
developmental bias analogous to differ- under selection to stabilize a newly adap-
ences in size of competing projections. T h e tive circuit against the regressive influ-
increased affinity for synchronously arriv- ences of competing biases. What is missing
ing axons should have the same effect as from both invasion and parcellation the-
relative enlargement of one source or tar- ories is a cause. Displacement theories
get area with respect to another. introduce cause in the form of regressive
Both invasion-like and parcellation-like processes (e.g., cell death or reduction of a
processes are explainable in this way. What peripheral sensory o r motor system) o r dif-
is different about displacement hypotheses ferential growth processes (e.g., unequal o r
is that they propose that all such events are hyperplasic neuron production, expansion
driven by competitive biases between dif- of some peripheral organ, o r hetero-
ferent axon populations and their pro- chronic change in maturation schedules for
spective targets and not by instructional different structures).
processes such as might be encoded in Finlay et al. (1987) suggest that regres-
molecular affinities. T h e strong form of sive events during development, such as
the displacement hypothesis denies both cell death and axon retraction, may account
the possibility of spontaneous axon inva- for total brain size variation, the elabora-
sion and also the possibility of spontaneous tion of specialized sensory, motor or cog-
parcellation. But like the parcellation nitive adaptations, and allometric dispro-
portions of specific systems during brain tor in major allometric changes. First, in
evolution. Widespread cell death appears order to play a significant role it must be
to be a normal developmental mechanism able to account for at least a major part of
for sculpting cell populations of intercon- the many thousandfold differences in brain
nected structures. T o a limited extent cell size. Small brains are simply not analogous
death may be exaggerated or eliminated to large brains that have experienced 99%
by variations in afferent populations o r cell death. T h e role of cell death is clearly
efferent associations. These effects are, limited to secondary "fine tuning" of inde-
however, buffered in systems with multiple pendently developed functionally inter-
afferent sources and efferent targets, and dependent systems (although it may reach
so can be expected to be most significant 80% in peripheral receptors). Second, as
in systems with highly limited connectional compared t o peripheral systems, the evi-
relationships. Neural populations of dence suggests that the total amount of cell
peripheral sensory and motor projections death is relatively small in most forebrain
a r e generally entirely dependent o n structures, even if peripheral structures
peripheral structures as afferent sources or relaying information to them are signifi-
efferent targets, respectively, and provide cantly reduced (Rakic, 1988). This prob-
the most notable examples of variation in ably correlates with the fact that forebrain
cell death. structures receive afferents from and send
A number of the changes in CNS orga- efferents to diverse cortical and subcortical
nization in response to the evolution of structures rather than just one, as in
novel sensory organs o r motor systems may peripheral structures. T h e cell d e a t h
thus be the result of such a sculpting pro- reported in areas like cortex appears t o be
cess. Wilczynski (1984) reviews evidence associated with cells maintaining transient
for the neural reorganization of CNS cell synapses during early phases of develop-
populations and connections in response to ment that may serve a preliminary organ-
some major vertebrate sensory and motor izing role for later stages. If there was sig-
specializations (e.g., auditory, electrical and nificant cell death in t h e normal
infrared reception) that show relatively development of cerebral cortex it would
subtle differences centrally in response to have to be relatively uniform because of
major changes of the periphery. Despite the remarkable uniformity of cell numbers
homoplaseous peripheral changes, central per area in all areas and all species. T h e
reorganization often recruits homologous initial production of neurons (or the initial
systems for similar perceptual processes. production of "ontogenetic units" with
H e argues that the interlocking of periph- fixed neuron production patterns) is prob-
eral and central reorganization in these ably much more important in determining
cases arises out of competitive develop- populations in most structures.
mental processes that match peripheral Finlay et al. (1987) also point out the pos-
functional requirements to central func- sible significance of heterochronous mat-
tional predispositions and match cell pop- urational processes for both cell death and
ulations to one another. Although there connectivity patterns. They argue that ear-
may be major changes in cell number in lier maturation or delayed maturation of
peripherally specialized nuclei as a conse- areas may introduce competitive biases in
quence of cell death there appear to be no normal axonal competition. Since some
"cascading" effects on cell death through- competitive processes may extend for only
out the remainder of their functional con- a few days, significantly delayed o r pre-
nections within the CNS. mature connections may be left out of the
T h e main point of the cell death hypoth- competition, with cell death o r connec-
esis proposed by Finlay et al. (1987) is to tional replacement resulting. Although
account for quantitative allometric changes Gould (1977) argues for the widespread
in the brain and brain structures. How- presence of heterochrony in other systems
ever, there are a number of reasons why (e.g., somatic growth and puberty) there is
cell death is unlikely to be a significant fac- little evidence concerning variance of mat-
uration schedules in the mammalian ner- Armstrong, 1985; Campos and Welker,
vous system at this time. However, time 1976; Deacon, 1988b; Gould, 1975; Pas-
scale effects may be significant in mam- singham, 1975; Sacher, 1970; Stephan,
malian brain evolution. T h e maturation of 1969). T h e systematic differentials in neu-
a small mammal brain may b e completed ronal production in different structures in
within the space of weeks whereas that of brains of different sizes should determine
a large brain may take many years. This correlated differences in structural parcel-
means that the absolute time scale of com- lation throughout. For example, the reg-
petitive-regressive events during matura- ular increase in proportion of visual asso-
tion can differ enormously despite the like- ciation cortex with respect to visual
lihood thqt, at the synaptic and cellular scale koniocortex in brains of increasing size may
the trophic processes that underly these reflect a growing competitive disadvantage
effects are the same for all mammal brains. for primary projections in the recruitment
T h e prolongation of these events in larger of cortical space determined by a growing
species might affect variability, degree of disproportion between the retina and its
differentiation o r sensitivity to extrinsic potential thalamic and cortical targets.
influences. In non-mammalian vertebrates As we examine species differences in
where neurogenesis may persist through- neural organization we should expect to
out the lifespan heterochrony may be a see certain necessary correlations between
more significant factor. changed connection patterns and the allo-
In previous papers I have also proposed metries of the various structures involved.
that axonal competition and other regres- For example, in cases where an invasion
sive processes play crucial roles in brain event is suspected to have taken place one
evolution (Deacon, 1984, 1988b, 1990c), would expect to find some corresponding
but I have focused largely on the possible deafferentation of the new target by a for-
influences of size relationships. If the mer projection source that has regressed
determination of initial cell number in most in size with respect to its target, o r some
structures takes place prior to major axonal unusual size increase in the new source
invasions, the major role of competitive and structure relative to its normal target, o r
regressive processes must be the subdivi- significant regression of its normal target.
sion of these neurogenetic fields with In cases where loss of connection is sus-
respect to each other. Even though no cell pected either cell death in the source or
death nor substantial cell saving may result target or, alternatively, displacement by a
from increases o r decreases of specific projection from a disproportionate com-
afferents o r efferent targets of a multiply peting afferent source would be expected.
connected structure within the CNS, such Failure to find these correlates either in
changes can substantially alter local axonal adult brains o r during development would
competition processes. Rather than axonal falsify a displacement interpretation.
competition determining the size of brain Displacement hypotheses are falsifiable
structures via cell death (probably only sig- in ways that parcellation o r invasion
nificant for peripheral structures), the rel- hypotheses are not because a displacement
ative sizes of interconnected brain struc- explanation is an account of a mechanism
tures should be a major determinant of not merely of a change in structure. T h e
patterns of axonal connection. displacement hypothesis is essentially an
Allometric effects are probably the most extension of well studied mechanisms of
common sources of bias, given the enor- developmental axonal plasticity. T h e pro-
mous range of brain sizes and the great duction of topographic functional and con-
ranges in the relationships between central nectional organization within a developing
and peripheral systems. These effects are area induced by reduction o r over-exag-
not limited t o unusual reorganization geration of input from some outside source
events. Deviations from isometry with phy- is the limiting case for developmental dis-
letic size increase is the rule among brain placement. T h e extension of this concept
structures as in peripheral organs (e.g., to incorporate allometric influences as a
major source of bias on major projection both its normal target and nearby low affin-
patterns completes the synthesis of allo- ity targets.
metric effects, neogenetic processes and An experimental example demonstrates
developmental processes. this possibility. Frost and Metin (1 985) and
Displacement interactions can also con- Sur et al. (1988) have demonstrated the
ceivably account for true invasions of axons possibility of inducing optic afferents to
into targets that even exuberant projec- project to inappropriate thalamic nuclei
tions would not otherwise contact. It is not and thus relay inappropriate sensory infor-
necessary to assume any changes in the mation to their cortical target areas. T o
actual affinities of axons for their targets, accomplish this in a developing rat they
only t h e reduction of t h e specificity destroyed all the normal targets of the optic
requirements for target affinity. This may projections (including lateral geniculate,
occur under some extreme conditions. In superior colliculus and visual cortex) and
an earlier section it was noted that the ini- additionally deafferented another tha-
tial target specificity of many neural con- lamic nucleus (e.g., either the ventrobasal
nections is significantly underdetermined. o r the medial geniculate nucleus) by cut-
This has been best documented for cortical ting ascending (spinothalamic o r tecto-
afferents and efferents but has also been thalamic) fibers. One of these procedures
noted widely in the developing nervous sys- is diagrammed in Figure 15. Despite the
tem. As a result, initial axonal projections fact that the misrouted connections inner-
invade a multitude of diffuse targets and vate anomalous thalamic targets which
may establish numerous transient synapses project t o non-visual cortical areas, cells in
that will later be eliminated. There prob- these areas exhibited response properties
ably are some predetermined affinity gra- appropriate t o visual cortex. This dem-
dients involved because these initial pro- onstrates that fundamental rewiring is
jections are far from entirely random. achievable by displacement and that the
Edelman (1987) has argued that this initial new connections thereby established can
affinity between axons and potential target differentiate their targets appropriate to
cells is the result of specific cell surface their new functions. However, it may be
molecules that exhibit a range of interac- significant in these cases that the alternate
tion o r "recognition" strengths (analogous thalamic and cortical targets are homolo-
to immunological binding relationships). gous with the normal targets at some level.
In order to produce distinct connections Similar natural experiments appear to be
these affinities need not be highly specific exhibited by different breeds of Siamese
so long as there is either a significant cats. These cats all have abnormal routing
threshold difference between nearby of ipsilateral projections to the contralat-
potentially competing projections or a era1 lateral geniculate with the result that
means for dynamic parcellation of rela- the visual field maps are misaligned. When
tively nonspecific projections, as is found the lateral geniculate projections reach the
in cortex. Extremely weak axon-target cortex they are dealt with in one of two
affinities can likely only exhibit themselves ways depending on the breed: 'they are
when all competing affinities are essentially either inactivated so as not to interfere with
eliminated o r when extremely strong com- the remainder of the map o r form an iso-
petitive biases are introduced. Elimination lated independent map that' is inserted
of alternative stronger affinity competitors adjacent to the otherwise normal map (Kaas
can occur if the majority of normally and Guillery, 1973; Guillery, 1974). What
occurring transient and permanent affer- factors bias the axonal competition toward
ents to an area are eliminated, o r if a nor- one o r the other option are not known.
mal target is essentially eliminated, forcing Analogous competitive processes may
axons to compete for alternative low affin- underly the evolution of new cortical areas.
ity targets. Strong biasing may also occur Simple invasion is astronomically unlikely
if a weak affinity afferent source becomes because it can only occur when there is a
disproportionately large with respect to significant loss of target affinity in one set
of axons and simultaneously a significant
increase in affinity for that same target area
by other axons that have also simulta-
neously lost affinity for their own target.
Each of these conditions involves an inde-
pendent mutational event that alters the
respective cell surface molecules or causes
certain whole classes of cells to die. In con-
trast, invasion by displacement need not
involve any changes in affinity o r signifi-
cant cell death. T h e only conditions
required are either significant allometric
disproportions between areas or the elim-
ination of some target area o r the elimi-
nation of some projection as a result of
some. degenerative event in evolution.
These conditions are probably not at all
uncommon in the course of evolution. Sig-
nificant allometric changes in proportions
between different structures and projec-
tion systems is the rule in all mammalian
and nonmammalian lineages where brain
size has changed by many orders of mag-
nitude. Such a principle may account for Normal connections
the parcellation trends in neocortical areas
seen in larger mammalian brains.

DISPLACEMENT THEORIES OF CORTICAL


EVOLUTION: FOUR EXAMPLES
Multiplication of cortical areas and their
differential allometry
T h e enlargement of the entire cortical
mantle with increasing brain size may influ-
ence cortical differentiation indirectly by Rerouting of connections
altering competitive interactions among after fetal lesions of visual
cortical afferents. There may be limits to targets maintains visual
the size of a single projection field deter- function in aberrant targets.
mined by the number of specific afferents FIG. 15. Misrouting of axons by target elimination
that are available o r bv intrinsic functional .
is demonstrated by, experiments in which the normal
constraints. If changes in the size of the targets of one projection a r e eliminated by lesion in
fetal development and the projections t o a different
cortical mantle a n d different thalamic (serially homologous) target a r e prevented from
nuclei are not isometric in the course of forming. In the case depicted here from Frost and
evolution then there may be correlated Metin (1985) the targets of the optic nerve- the lat-
changes in the relative size of correspond- eral geniculate nucleus of the thalamus [LG] and the
ing projection fields. Changes in propor- superior colliculus [SC]— and the target of the lateral
geniculate nucleus-the visual cortex [Vis]— were
tion may also be influenced by network damaged by fetal lesions as were the ascending somatic
allometry influences that impose func- sensory afferents of the medial lemniscus which would
tional costs on enlarging areas. Such con- normally synapse in the ventrobasal nucleus of the
straints might contribute to the break-up thalamus [VB]. Consequently, t h e optic fibers were
thereby induced t o invade the ventrobasal nucleus of
and duplication of cortical fields in brains the thalamus. T h e otherwise normal projection of this
of increasing size. T h e multiplication of nucleus t o the location of somatic cortex induced this
areas and the differential expansion of some area to behave as though it were visual cortex.
cortical areas with respect to others may visual association projections (Rakic, 1988).
also be influenced by the total size of the T h e relative negative allometry of the pro-
entire cortical mantle with respect to the jection nucleus of vision (the lateral genic-
sizes of other brain structures that are con- ulate nucleus) with respect to the volume
nected with it. This indirect influence is of the corresponding visual associational
suggested by the predictable allometric nuclei (the pulvinar complex) as well as with
scaling of the sizes of cortical areas with respect to the rest of the thalamus (Arm-
the total size of the isocortex across many strong, 1979; Hopf, 1965; Stephan et al.,
species (Passingham, 1975; Deacon, 1988b). 198 1) lends further support to a displace-
Probably the most significant determin- ment explanation for this evolutionary
ing factor in such cases is the relative size trend. Figure 16 diagrams the major fea-
of the afferent projection as compared to tures of this hypothesis in comparison to
its cortical target zone. A cortical target deafferentation experiments. Deafferen-
area that has expanded with respect to its tation as a result of adaptational loss o r
afferent projections is in some ways anal- reduction of a peripheral sense organ-as
ogous to a cortical area with a reduced in blind cave dwelling species, o r to a lesser
afferent projection. Either should produce extent in fossorial o r nocturnally special-
a decreased density of adjacent correlated ized species-should also produce this sort
inputs which may impair the ability of spe- of effect in cortical areal architecture, but
cific inputs to successfully out-compete and in a brain that is unusually small for this
eliminate diffuse inputs. In the case of pattern in that modality. Studies of such
depleted afferents (Rakic, 1 988) the size of naturally deafferented species has dem-
the differentiated area is reduced and space onstrated reduction of cortical represen-
is given u p to neighboring areas. Neigh- tation of these sensory areas but the issue
boring cortical areas would also face the of projection area to association area ratio
same difficulty. Parcellation of afferent has not been investigated.
projections to form duplicate adjacent pro- I t is possible that the process of area sub-
jections may thus be a result of reaching division may be a gradual evolutionary
some threshold of competitive instability event in areas with relatively diffuse topo-
determined in part by the size of the affer- graphic organization. Area boundaries may
ent map (which may itself be matched in not be discrete and connectional differ-
size to its peripheral representation by cell ences may exhibit a gradient-like organi-
death) and in part by the independently zation in these cases. Such incipient area
growing information processing costs of divisions should be more likely in associa-
network allometry within the cortex. tion areas lacking clear sensory o r motor
The increasing proportion of association topographic organization and we should
cortex to projection cortex that correlates expect to see increased individual variation
with increasing brain size could reflect pro- in these areas if this is the case. This pat-
gressive competitive disadvantages for tern should contrast with that of cortical
direct peripheral projection systems in areas that map topographically organized
some modalities, both in recruiting tha- representations of some peripheral modal-
lamic targets and in recruiting cortical tar- ity. In these cases area differentiation
gets via these thalamic projections. This should tend to be more discrete and pre-
would follow if the proportion of periph- dictable. T h e border between visual area
eral axons to central axons competing for 17 and 18 and between 18 and 19 is easily
targets declined with size. This kind of tar- distinguishable and correlate's with func-
get expansion would have parcellation tional map boundaries but the multiple
effects analogous to partial deafferenta- retinotopic maps within area 19 of the
tion. Visual deafferentation experiments monkey cortex are not easily correlated
in monkeys have demonstrated both a with any architectonic borders. T h e appar-
reduction in striate cortex area and an ent tendency for middle level cortical asso-
expansion into this territory by adjacent ciation areas to exhibit the greatest level
of subdivision and functional diversity from
species to species may be a correlate of the
relative fluidity of these divisions.
If the tendency for cortical circuits to
subdivide and differentiate their cortical
targets with respect to one another in
development is exaggerated by brain size
increase and brain size increase is corre-
lated with the evolution of increased body
size, then neither selection for augmented
specialized functions nor selection for gen-
eralized brain size increase (and increased
general intelligence) needs to b e involved
in order to explain cortical enlargement
and complexification. Multiplication of
cortical areas might be accounted for, not
as augmentation of function, but as a
response to a growing size differential
between peripheral projections and cen-
trally originating projections as well as a
response to deterioration of integration and
processing efficiency caused by the con-
comitant reduction of connectivity in a
larger cortex. Advancement of function is
not necessary to explain the multiplication
and differentiation of cortical areas. Func-
tional adaptation is not precluded, but to
demonstrate it requires more than dem-
onstrating an increase in cortical areas and
differentiation of functions within those
areas. These other correlates of size must
FIG. 16. Displacement theory of association area be "subtracted" before a proper assess-
expansion is depicted for visual areas in two hypo- ment of functional advancement can be
thetical brains of different sizes but receiving input made. Nonetheless, with the addition of
from eyes that differ little in size. T h e geniculo-striate duplicate areas o r with the differentiation
pathway is depicted by solid black arrows and dark
gray targets and the tecto-pulvinar-extrastriate path-
of functions into independent component
way is depicted by dashed gray arrows and light gray processes, new possibilities for specializa-
targets (assuming homology of the pulvinar and lat- tion arise that could not coexist in a com-
eral posterior nucleus). In the expanded brain of B mon area. This must certainly be a rich
there has been an expansion of the thalamus and the source for "preadaptations."
cortical target field potentially available for both pro-
jections but because the direct retino-thalamic pro- Once adaptive alternative connection
jection is not significantly larger it is not capable of patterns are established by whatever means
recruiting a correspondingly larger LGN from the there may be selection for changes in axon
expanded thalamus and may also be at a competitive affinities and other biasing factors that limit
disadvantage in competition for space within the supe-
rior colliculus as well with respect to other possible
competing inputs. However, the size of the afferents
to the pulvinar are appropriately enlarged and recruit
a large portion of the thalamus. T h e consequence for expansion of the pulvinary projection field may fur-
cortical parcellation is that the geniculo-cortical affer- ther induce its parcellation because of increased
ents are at a disadvantage in the competition for cor- regional differentiation of correlated activity, but also
tical territory with respect to pulvinar afferents and possibly because the information arriving in the pul-
so the striate cortex will occupy a reduced proportion vinar may include inputs that reflect the effects of
of the entire visual projection field. T h e additional partially displaced retino-tectal projections.
variability. Because of these develop- also seem to respect the general "level" of
mental biases, parcellation patterns will cortical area. Both origin and termination
become increasingly resistant to rever- patterns are more diffuse across lamina in
sions, even if the conditions that originally association areas (Barbus, 1986; Deacon,
induced parcellation are undermined. This 1 989a). Similar laminar connection pat-
suggests that size-induced parcellation pat- terns have also been identified in some areas
terns may persist even if brain size decreases of cat (Bullier et al., 1984), tree shrew
in subsequent lineage. Retention of corti- (Semsa et al., 1984) and rat cortex (Deacon
cal features consistent with a much larger et al., 1989), but there is too little infor-
brain has been documented in a number mation for non-primate species to be sure
of dwarf species (e.g.,Warren and Carlson, of its generality.
1986). This suggests that there may be T h e consistent association of termina-
functionai costs associated with brain size tion patterns with the architectonic and
reduction in evolution. T h e possibility for functional gradient between association
irreversible changes and corresponding areas and sensorimotor areas clearly indi-
asymmetrical selection against size reduc- cates that this hierarchy, which has been
tion brings us full circle to a possible pro- the central feature in all additive theories
gressive or directional tendency in brain of cortical evolution, must also be
evolution. accounted for in terms of parcellation and
displacement processes in evolution. Else-
where (Deacon, 1989a) 1 have referred to
Laminar segregation of afferents: these reciprocally directed pathways as
Implications for areal parcellation centrifugal (limbic-association-sensory/
and the origins of cortex motor cortex) and centripetal (sensory/
Connectional patterns between cortical motor-association-limbic cortex) projec-
areas appear to parallel the cytoarchitec- tions because they are oriented with respect
tonic differentiation of cortical areas. to areas specialized for peripheral infor-
Because of this regularity they may provide mation at the one extreme and areas con-
some insights into the connectional dis- cerned more with internal states of arousal
placements, invasions and parcellations that a t the other (see Fig. 18). This hierarchic
constitute area differentiation in evolu- chain of cortical areas within each func-
tion. Tracer studies of corticocortical con- tional modality increases in number of areas
nections in monkey brains have revealed and corresponding synaptic links as brains
characteristic laminar origin and termi- enlarge in evolution, yet replicates the same
nation patterns that seem to be general- systematic pattern of laminar connectivity
izable to many if not all regions of cortex with each addition. A number of research-
(Barbus, 1986; Deacon, 1985; Galaburda ers have linked this asymmetric reci p rocal
and Pandya, 1983; Jones et al., 1978; connectivity pattern to Sanides' evolution-
Maunsell and Van Essen, 1983; Primrose ary sequence of cortical differentiation (e.g.,
and Strick, 1985; Rockland and Pandya, Barbus and Pandya, 1982, 1987; Gala-
1979; Tigges et al., 1973, 1977). In gen- burda and Pandya, 1983; Pandya a n d Yet-
eral, connections that originate from asso- erian, 1985). This asymmetry is presumed
ciation areas and project to areas more spe- to be explainable as a terminal addition
cialized for a peripheral sensory o r motor process whereby new areas are always con-
function tend to originate largely from cells nected t o their immediately adjacent
in layer V of cortex and terminate in layers ancestral area by one sort of laminar con-
I and VI. Connections that originate from nection pattern and are reciprocated by its
specialized (e.g., primary) sensory a n d complement. Despite the rejection of San-
motor areas and project to association areas ides' theory on a number of grounds, the
tend to originate largely from cells in layer correlations it suggests must be accounted
I II of cortex and terminate predominantly for. With the repudiation of theories claim-
in layers III and IV (see Fig. 17). There ing terminal addition o r terminal differ-
are also subtle gradation differences that entiation of cortical areas, we are forced
parcellation of cortical laminar connectivity
in the process of areal parcellation of isocortex

corticocortical laminar connectivity before parcellation

corticocortical laminar connectivity after parcellation

FIG. 17. Laminar segregation of corticocortical connections due to functional parcellation of cortical areas
is depicted on the assumption that both the ancestral and developmentally prior state are an undifferentiated
laminar termination pattern. The hypothesized undifferentiated state is depicted in the upper figure as a
single cortical area with intrinsic connections. The subsequent loss of selected classes of connections with area
parcellation is depicted in the lower figure. Note that the culled connections are asymmetric with respect to
their directional orientation. Possible sources of competitive bias that might drive this asymmetric parcellation
during development are discussed in the text.

to explain this correlation between archi- This suggests that we should look for cor-
tectonic gradients, asymmetrically pat- responding biases, either in terms of het-
/
terned reciprocal connections, inverse erochronic, allometric o r functional dif-
maturational gradients, and the apparent ferences, that distinguish association areas
functional hierarchy of cortical areas in from specialized sensory/motor areas. In
terms of competitive biases and displace- fact, all three possible sources of bias can
ment processes in cortical development. be identified and are probably not inde-
At the present time there is no devel- pendent.
opmental information concerning corti- Another important clue concerning the
cocortical laminar differentiation pro- particular cortical lamina that distinguish
cesses. Nonetheless, speculation concerning these different cortico-cortical projections
the possible mechanisms involved can be comes from the finding that different
concentrated on a few plausible factors. For classes of thalamo-cortical projections also
corticocortical connections within a corti- appear to segregate according to termi-
cal area there does not seem to be this level nations in these same lamina. Multiple tha-
of laminar specification (Rockland and lamic nuclei project to each cortical area
Pandya, 1979). T h e differentiation of a new but tend to terminate in different lamina
cortical subdivision out of a single ancestral within the same area. It appears that prin-
area must therefore correlate with a loss cipal thalamic projection nuclei, whose
of projections to certain cortical lamina. projections are generally limited to a single
Furthermore the loss is different depend- architectonic area, tend to terminate in
ing upon whether the projection is in the columnar fashion within layers III and IV,
centrifugal o r centripetal direction. Since usually coinciding with the distribution of
the appearance of a new cortical division granule cells in those layers (Diamond,
must be a consequence of the competitive 1982; Frost and Caviness, 1980). Intralam-
parcellation-displacement processes, these inar thalamic nuclei, which exhibit rela-
systematic connectional losses likely cor- tively non-specific projections to many cor-
relate with competitive asymmetries tical areas, tend to terminate in layer VI
between different afferent populations. (Frost and Caviness, 1980; Herkenham,
1980; Rausell and Avendano, 1985). Other
nonspecific nuclei that project to many
areas within the same modality and midline
"limbic" nuclei, which also exhibit wide-
spread paralimbic cortex and association
cortex projections, tend to terminate in
layer I (Diamond, 1982; Friedman et al.,
1987; Frost and Caviness, 1980; Rausell
and Avendano, 1985). T h e non-specific and
limbic nature of thalamic projections t o
layers I and VI and the specific projections
to layers III and IV can be interpreted as
functionally analogous to their counter-
parts among cortico-cortical projections in
a number of ways. Middle layer projections
appear always to introduce information
associated with a source that is more
centripetal directly connected with the peripheral ner-
vous system than are their target, whereas
deep and superficial layer connections
appear to convey information that ulti-
mately derives from systems involved more
with the regulation of internal state, as well
as attentional and emotional arousal (Dea-
con, 1989).
Two important heterochronic matura-
tional factors differentiate cells and axons
in these cortical lamina. These correlated
heterochronic differences may account for
which lamina tend to be associated with
which afferents by virtue of their biasing
influence on axonal competition. Neurons
occupying positions that would be super-
ficial to layer II and deep to layer VI in the
adult brain mature before the cells of the
cortical plate and form a single primordial
centrifugal cortical layer. Cells in the outer layer called
FIG. 18. Centrifugal and centripetal corticocortical Cajal-Retzius cells exhibit two large
projections are depicted on idealized flattened maps "extraverted" dendrites that extend up
of the cerebral cortex of one hemisphere. Areas toward t h e pial surface a n d laterally,
depicted in darkest gray are koniocortical areas o r
specialized motor cortex, those in lightest gray are whereas cells in the deep layer called Mar-
association cortex, and the white perimeter repre- tinotti cells are of a distinct bi p olar shape
sents limbic cortex. T h e arrows represent multisy- with dendrites extending more superfi-
naptic pathways from area to area extending either cially a n d deeper. Cortical plate cells
from koniocortex (or motor cortex) to intermediate
association cortex to paralimbic association cortex to migrate into position in an inside-out pat-
limbic cortex (centripetal) or from limbic cortex to tern between these two cell layers. T h e ear-
paralimbic association cortex to intermediate associ- liest cortical plate cells to mature are the
ation cortex to koniocortex (or motor cortex). T h e deep layer V and VI pyramidal cells and
terms centripetal and centrifugal are chosen not the very last cortical plate cells to mature
because of their spatial connotations (which may be
somewhat confusing in this depiction) but because of are the most superficial pyramidal cells of
the orientation of these projections with respect to layers II and III and the granule cells of
the gradient between areas specialized for peripheral layer IV. Prior to the appearance of the
systems and those representing regulation of internal cortical plate neurons both primordial cell
state.
types appear to establish transient synapses
with early afferent projections (Marin-Pa- tition for synapses in the middle cortical
dilla, 1978). Although there is some dis- lamina may be biased by earlier myelina-
agreement on the ultimate fate of these tion of ai-eas that are more peripherally
early maturing cells most argue that they specialized.
are eliminated by programmed cell death An allometric bias is reflected in the
in most isocortical areas (although they expansion of association areas relative to
appear to pqrsist in entorhinal cortex and sensory/motor specialized areas in larger
in paralimbic isocortex in small species, and brains. As noted above, this suggests that
in all cortical areas in cetaceans; see next primary projection areas, which are more
section). directly linked to peripheral systems, are
Although it is not known what structures competitively constrained by the size of
give rise to the afferent projections that their afferent projections, whereas affer-
synapse on the transient cells above and ents to association areas have no such
below the developing cortical plate, it is extrinsic constraints. This may also be the
reasonable to assume that they arise from reason these areas appear to exhibit less
the same structures that will later inner- clearcut cytoarchitectonic divisions. T h e
vate' the corresponding deep and superfi- gradient in architectonic specialization is
cial lamina in the adult. T h e fact that the one of the primary bases for Sanides' argu-
thalamic afferents terminating in layers I ment.
and VI are nonspecific projections and do Functional differences are also consis-
not appear to respect cortical boundaries tently correlated with this gradient. For
(Caviness and Frost, 1980; Diamond, 1982) example, neurons in striate cortex appear
may reflect their arrival prior to cortical to be precisely "tuned" to specific, highly
plate afferents that subdivide the cortex localized stimulus attributes and are orga-
into-:discrete functional regions. If the nized according t o precise retinotopy
transient 'cells to which these early axons whereas neurons in inferotemporal visual
/
contact are later eliminated, these axons association areas, at the extreme opposite
may be displaced onto adjacent pyramidal end of the hierarchy, seem tuned to global
cell dendrites in the deepest and most stimulus attributes and exhibit very large
superficial lamina of cortex (see Fig. 19). receptive fields with no obvious topo-
Since different target cells within the cor- graphic organization. This is undoubtedly
tex mature at different times and different also a correlate of the relative directness
projections arrive at different times, tem- or indirectness of their respective retino-
poral correlation may play an important cortical afferent circuits (Kaas, 1989). At
role in biasing laminar connection patterns the sensory end of the spectrum of areas
from both thalamic and cortical sites. Early input from the periphery is highly variable
maturing cells located deep and superficial and functional correlation is only exhib-
to the cortical plate may correlate with the ited over very short distances, whereas at
early maturing projections and late matur- the association end input is primarily lim-
ing small cortical plate cells in layers III bic and likely highly intercorrelated over
and IV may correlate with relatively late relatively larger distances. Since functional
maturing projections. Differences in the specialization of cortical areas can be sig-
relative maturation times of cells and axons nificantly affected by sensory experience
from one cortical area to another might during early development it is almost cer-
additionally contribute to areal differences tain that differences in the correlation of
in laminar organization. afferent signals among adjacent axons play
Another possible heterochronic bias that a major role in determining which con-
may influence the asymmetric direction- nections persist into adulthood.
ality of these projections can be discerned Finally, the issue of network allometry
in the differential myelination of thala- should be considered. Given the fact that
mocortical fibers from principal thalamic break-up of previously integrated func-
nuclei projecting to these areas. Since my- tional areas effectively distributes process-
elination appears to precede from special- ing across a number of areas, functioning
ized areas to association areas the compe- to some extent in parallel, cortico-cortical
Pattem of isocortical neurogenesis
and probable programmed cell death

prior to the early invasion addition of cortical probable elimination of cells


cortical plate cortical plate cells plate cells to outside the cortical plate and
external layers specialization of granular layer

Hypothesis to account for development of


laminar specificity of cortical afferents

early non-specific displacement of non-specific


thalamic (+?) projections projections from eliminated
cells to cortical plate cells and
invasion of specific thalamic projections
FIG. 19. A theory of the displacement processes involved in laminar parcellation of cortical afferent con-
nections and a possible explanation of their relationship to neocortical origins. T h e upper figure diagrams
the events of corticogenesis assuming programmed cell death of cells that precede the formation of the cortical
plate (it is also possible that some of these precursor neurons are converted into neurons with different
morphologies in the mature cortex). Note that neurons forming the cortical plate migrate into position
between the two groups of cortical precursor cells above and below it and deposit in the uppermost layers of
the developing cortical plate. T h e lower figure depicts a displacement theory for the laminar segregation of
cortical afferents during cortical development. It is hypothesized that axons from early maturing non-specific
thalamic nuclei and possibly early maturing limbic areas establish synapses on the two populations of cortical
precursor cells and maintain them as cortical plate neurons are added and the two cell groups are forced
apart. After the formation of the cortical plate selective cell death of the precursor cells forces the axons
attached to them to seek alternative synaptic contacts. They are displaced onto the dendrites of cortical plate
neurons of the same lamina. These axons may have a competitive advantage because of their numbers and
functional maturity compared to the later arriving principal thalamic afferents that target cortical plate cells
in middle layers. T h e two independent populations of neurons, superimposed by the migration of the cortical
plate cells, with different maturation schedules and distinct classes of afferents, suggest the possibility that
t hey derive from independent phylogenetic origins-the precurser cells from the dorsal cortex and the cortical
plate cells from the dorsal ventricular ridge of a reptilian ancestor.
connections should be competitively about these brains that causes them to
selected during development that maxi- diverge from these otherwise ubiquitous
mize intercorrelated function and most trends will unquestionably provide impor-
efficiently distribute processing demands tant insights into the causes for the general
throughout the network. Such an inter- trends.
pretation is suggested by the "counter-cur- Some of the most striking exceptions can
rent" organization of these cortico-cortical be found in the dolphin brain (and pre-
connections (see Deacon, 1989). sumably in all cetacean brains). Many of
This analysis of laminar maturation and the unique architectonic features of the
connectional differentiation suggests an dolphin brain have been meticulously doc-
alternative interpretation for the origins of umented in a series of recent papers (Jacobs
mammalian isocortex that combines both et al., 1971, 1979, 1984; Morgane and
the equivalent cell hypothesis and invasion Jacobs, 1972; Morgane et al., 1982, 1985,
by displacement. My suspicion (also sug- 1986a, b, 1990). These findings concern-
gested in Marin-Padilla, 1978) is that these ing the dolphin brain are paradoxical in
transient cells are the homologues of the the context of traditional theories of mam-
cells of the ancestral dorsal cortex of rep- malian brain evolution because they sug-
tiles and that the cortical plate cells rep- gest that dolphin brains combine features
resent a phylogenetically later intrusion that are considerably highly advanced with
(following the equivalent cell hypothesis) features that are considered quite primi-
perhaps from ancestral dorsal ventricular tive and conservative (Glezer et al., 1988).
ridge positions. T h e death of the reptilian T h e highly advanced features of the dol-
dorsal cortex homologue cells in mam- phin brain are largely macroscopic mor-
malian ontogeny induces the displacement phological features, including a large brain
of their afferents onto the apical dendrites size, a high degree of encephalization, a
of these recently juxtaposed nonhomolo- highly convoluted cortex, a high ratio of
gods cells of the cortical plate. T h e cortical neocortex to total cortex (and therefore a
plate cells also maintain their original high ratio of neocortex to limbic cortex),
afferents and thereby establish a novel and apparently (although this is difficult to
integration of these ancestrally separated assess accurately) a large percentage of
and independent circuits. In this sense the association cortex. Dolphins also are con-
laminar termination pattern of centrifugal sidered to be among the most behaviorally
pathways links them with the ancestral dor- advanced species by many behavioral
sal cortex system (which has always been researchers (Herman, 1980; Würsig, 1989;
linked with limbic cortex) and the laminar but see critique by Gaskin, 1982). In con-
pattern of centripetal pathways links them trast, their conservative traits are largely
with the ancestral dorsal striatal (dorsal microscopic features, including relatively
ventricular ridge) system. thin and poorly laminated isocortex, essen-
tially agranular (and some would argue,
Cetacean brain evolution nonexistent) layer IV and therefore no typ-
In the preceding sections I have referred ically definable koniocortical areas, appar-
to a number of general trends in mam- ent lack of a gigantopyramidal cortex (i.e.,
malian brain evolution that appear to be architectonically specialized primary motor
strongly correlated with brain size. These cortex; although some evidence of this can
include both microscopic and macroscopic be discerned in the form of larger layer V
features of brains, all of which ultimately pyramidal cells), remarkably thick layer I
have to be understood in terms of biases with respect to the rest of the cortical lay-
and constraints that modify developmental ers, a well developed layer VI, densely
processes, and most particularly, axonal packed layer II, large "extroverted" cells
competition/parcellation processes. It is in layer II, poorly defined columnar orga-
therefore important to consider excep- nization, indistinct architectonic bound-
tional cases where these correlations do not aries, and apparent adjacency of sensory-
seem to hold. Understanding what it is motor projection areas with respect to
dorsal view association areas (see Fig. 20). Glezer et al.
(1 988) are compelled to designate a special
"conservative-progressive mode" of cor-
tical evolution to account for this anoma-
lous combination of features.
T h e dichotomy between macroscopic
morphological features and microscopic
cytoarchitectonic features is undoubtedly
significant for understanding this apparent
paradox. If gross morphological traits were
the only available evidence then the dol-
phin brain would be ranked along with the
human brain as a highly advanced brain.
Such traits as the ratio of neocortex t o lim-
bic cortex follow expected allometric pre-
dictions of a brain the size of a dolphin
brain. It is in fact even more convoluted
than might be expected from a terrestrial
brain of such size, but this can probably be
explained on the basis of its relatively thin-
ner cortex (compared to terrestrial mam-
mal brains of similar proportions—e.g.,
primate and human brains). Thus, with
respect to the production of initial cell pop-
ulations the dolphin brain probably shares
common mechanisms with all mammals.
But the production of cell populations and
the parcellation of those populations .into
distinct functional divisions and architec-
tonic fields occur independently at sepa-
rate developmental stages. The cortical
architectonic parcellation process occurs
subsequent to the production of the cor-
tical mantle. T h e allometric proportions
that will determine the proportion of iso-
cortex to limbic cortex and projection cor-
tex to association cortex are already estab-
lateral view lished, but the competitive interactions
which will subdivide and specialize these
FIG. 20. Drawing of the dolphin brain shown in sim-
plified form from above and from the side with an cortical targets have not begun at this stage.
indication of the topographic position of the different We must look to this latter process for a
sensory and motor projection fields. Although the clue to the peculiarities of the dolphin
areas depicted are presumed to be the primary pro- brain.
jection areas for these modalities, I prefer to reserve
judgement on this homological relationship. Assum-
T h e hypothesis I will suggest to explain
ing that the indicated areas are representative of the these architectonic peculiarities focuses on
proportion of neocortex occupied by primary areas the agranularity of dolphin cortex. T h e
it would appear that most of the dolphin isocortex is lack of layer IV granule cells throughout
composed of association areas. Limbic cortex is not the cortex of the dolphin brain is partic-
visible from the lateral view and is a relatively small
proportion of the total cerebral cortex as is appro- ularly remarkable because the origin of
priate for a mammalian brain of this size. Information granule cells is far more ancient than the
for this drawing is derived from Morgane et al. (1986a, divergence of Cetacea from the rest of the
eutherian stock. Despite the fact that small
brains are in general less "granularized"
(a feature that may in part be attributed to placement of thalamic afferents that lack
the fact that the size difference between their "normal" primary affinity targets.
granule cells and pyramidal cells in small T h e presence of unusual "extroverted"
brains is relatively slight), even the appar- cells in layer II whose large dendrites reach
ently primitive brain of the North Amer- up into layer I may also be explainable in
ican opossum Didelphis virginiana exhibits this way. These cells are present in fetal
a clearly defined and even subdifferen- mammals brains but are eliminated early
tiated layer IV that receives dense princi- in development and are the targets for
pal thalamic afferents (Johnson, 1988; transient synapses during the early stages
Walsh and Ebner, 1970), so the common of cortical differentiation (see discussion in
eutherian ancestor of cetaceans and other the previous section). T h e displacement of
eutherian mammals doubtless also pos- axons lacking their principal target into
sessed layer IV granule cells. Complete loss this layer at an early stage of development,
of this cell type and cell layer must be con- prior to the "normal" elimination of these
sidered a rare derived trait. cells, may allow them t o persist by estab-
The absence of granule cells is of pri- lishing permanent synapses with t h e
mary significance with respect to the pro- orphaned principal thalamic afferents.
cess of architectonic parcellation of corti- Since columnar organization is established
cal areas. During development of cerebral by competitive exclusion processes within
cortex, it is the competition between invad- layer IV and deep layer III, the lack of
ing axons from the major thalamic nuclei clearly delineated columnar organization
that is largely responsible for the specifi- undoubtedly results from the absence of
cation of topographic maps and establish- axonal competition in this layer. T h e lack
ment ,of functional a n d architectonic of clear architectonic boundaries and the
boundaries. As is well demonstrated by apparently clustered projection areas all
studies of the formation of somatosensory reflect this significant reduction of axonal
barrels in the rat and ocular dominance competition processes. However, the pres-
columns in the cat and monkey, the ter- ence of differences in relative cell sizes in
minations of these critical projections and different layers and differences in the den-
the principal layers in which this compe- sity of pyramidal cells in different areas
tition takes place are layers III and IV, (e.g., between somatosensory and motor
corresponding to the distribution of gran- areas, Morgane et al., 1986a), that corre-
ule cells in those layers (Jacobson, 1978). spond to similar differences in terrestrial
Experimental destruction of these tha- mammals, indicate that these features are
lamic afferents at an early stage (Rakic, probably controlled by factors other than
1988) or even elimination of peripheral thalamocortical connections, most proba-
sensory information t o these afferents bly their efferent terminations. T h e s e
(Woolsey and Wann, 1976) is capable of hypothetical effects of granule cell elimi-
profoundly altering the structure of the nation are depicted in Figure 2 1. Neuro-
resultant cortical map and even causing logical mutant mice that completely lack
functional-architectonic boundaries to be cerebral cortical granule cells should also
displaced (Rakic, 1988). exhibit many of these same characteristics.
Given the developmental importance of Study of these could serve as an informa-
this thalamofugal-granule cell relationship tive test case, although because of the great
for architectonic differentiation, it is clear size difference many of the most unusual
that elimination of this cell type and dis- features of the dolphin brain might not
placement of many or all of the thalamo- express themselves so obviously in a mouse.
fugal projections to other layers and other How and why cetacean brains lost their
cellular targets in the developing cerebral granule cells is a mystery. It is a trait that
cortex of the dolphin brain is bound to is probably shared by all cetaceans and so
profoundly alter all features of its tangen- was inherited from their common ancestor
tial and radial organization. T h e relatively subsequent to their divergence from ter-
thick layer I likely results from the dis- restrial mammals. T h e r e is some trace of
Monkey Dolphin

thalamic afferents thalamic afferents


FIG. 21. Granule cell degeneration hypothesis of the dolphin isocortex is depicted in comparison with the
pattern typical for terrestrial mammals represented by the monkey brain. In the diagram of monkey cortical
architecture the droplet shaped cells represent pyramidal cells the small spherical cells in middle layers
represent granule cells and other small interneurons and the ellipsoid cells represent small layer II cells. T h e
same shapes are used to depict cells in the diagram of the dolphin cortex with the exceptions that there are
no granule cells and some of the layer two cells are assumed to be embryologically retained "extraverted"
cells. Principal thalamic afferents that normally would target the granule cell populations in the cortical plate
are induced to establish alternative targets in the dolphin cortex in which granule cells are strangely absent.
These afferents without normal targets may establish synapses with embryonic cells in layer II that would
otherwise be eliminated after cortical plate formation in terrestrial mammals. These retained layer II extraver-
ted cells and the displaced thalamocortical axons cause layer I to be disproportionately thick and layer II to
be more densely packed than is observed in terrestrial mammal brains. Middle layers are also prevented from
normal competitive parcellation into columnar units, that otherwise would distinguish specialized koniocortical
areas. This suggests that dolphin cortical organization is neither conservative nor atavistic, but highly derived.

this degenerative process left because cial to the persistence of this trait. Consider
immature dolphin brains do exhibit a tran- the significance of the regression of many
sient but thin layer IV that disappears by specific sensory and motor systems in these
maturity (Garey and Leuba, 1986). It seems species associated with their aquatic adap-
unlikely that this loss can be rationalized tation. They are anosmic, they have sig-
as an adaptation. Given the total break- nificantly reduced visual requirements (and
down of cortical differentiation processes in this regard are comparable to fossorial
that resulted one would presume that this species and echolocating bats with second-
is a costly mutation, although even in the arily reduced visual systems), and they
mutant Reeler mouse, with its totally dis- exhibit significant reduction of the distal
rupted cortical architecture (but not lack- limbs, shoulder girdle and pelvis (which in
ing granule cells), the cortex still functions terrestrial vertebrates comprise the pre-
and allows for adequate perceptual and dominant afferent and efferent represen-
motor functions. T h e fixation and survival tation of the primary somatdsensory and
of this trait in cetaceans as opposed to any motor fields). Although many species have
other terrestrial lineage may be related to highly developed echolocation systems, this
their unusual and relatively complete adap- appears far more substantially represented
tation to the aquatic habitat. T h e lack of by collicular specialization (evidenced by
"granularized" competitors (e.g. , pin- the immensely expanded and highly dif-
nipeds) in this niche until much later in ferentiated inferior colliculus) than by cor-
mammalian evolution may have been cru- tical specialization. All these regressive fea-
tures appear to coincidentally correlate monkeys in one case and capuchin mon-
with the inability of the dolphin cortex to keys in the other) and one Old World mon-
architectonically differentiate. key's brain (Cercopithecus talapoin), than to
In summary, this exception appears t o the brains of any other Old World mon-
prove the rule in a rather striking and keys and apes. It is probably not coinci-
unambiguous way. T h e problems of deter- dental that those primates most closely
mining whether the dolphin brain is con- linked with Homo by these studies also rep-
servative or advanced o r conservative- resent relatively encephalized primates.
advanced are irrelevant. T h e dolphin brain When a structure by structure allometric
is none of these. It is highly derived. These analysis is performed it appears that the
problems that arose in the analysis at the human brain diverges from primate trends
level of comparative morphology and com- in a number of striking ways. Based on pre-
parative cytoarchitecture dissolve once we dictions from primate trends, the cerebral
approach the question from the perspec- cortex and cerebellar cortex of the human
tive of developmental homologies. brain are disproportionately large relative
to the diencephalon, corpus striaturn, brain
Human brain evolution stem and spinal cord (Deacon, 1984,
Assumptions about human brain evolu- 1988b). This is depicted in Figure 22.
tion are the ultimate source for many of T h e production of neurons that consti-
the misleading ideas that have haunted the tute cortical structures takes place well
study of brain evolution, so it is fitting that before any axonal parcellation processes
the exorcism of these ideas in this paper begin, and therefore, as noted earlier, the
should conclude with a discussion of the increase in cerebral cortex cannot be spe-
uniqueness of human brain evolution. Two cific to any particular region of cortex. T h e
unique characteristics of the human brain increase in radial dimensions of the cortical
stand out as central. T h e human brain is germinal field and in the number of onto-
roughly three times larger than would be genetic columns that will differentiate out
predicted for an anthropoid primate of of it must take place in the human brain
human body size, and human brains are prior to neural production within the cor-
capable of acquiring an unprecedentedly tex. T h e size disproportions between the
complex and flexible communication sys- expanded neocortical target field, the rel-
tem- language. T h e s e two facts a r e atively unexpanded population of thala-
undoubtedly linked. mofugal axons, and the relatively unex-
Beginning with the issue of human brain panded efferent subcortical targets of
size, it is important t o find out if this cortical neurons must significantly bias
increased cell production follows trends parcellation processes in all these areas
that are typical in other members of the during subsequent stages of differentia-
primate order. This can be ascertained by tion. One effect of this is apparent in devia-
comparing the relative sizes of the various tions of relative cortical area dimensions
major structural divisions of the human with respect to predictions based on the
brain with predictions based on trends for allometry of these structures in other pri-
primates in general. Initial evidence that mates. Some cortical areas appear signifi-
there is a deviation from predicted allo- cantly smaller than expected for a primate
metries comes from an examination of brain this size and others significantly
studies that have used brain structure vol- larger. For example, the visual cortex
umes to construct possible phylogenetic appears to scale appropriate to the size of
trees for primate ancestry. Two studies, its peripheral input (the retina) and its
using largely similar data but different principal thalamic nucleus, but does not
methods that control for the effects of brain occupy the proportion of cortex predicted
size (Douglas a n d Marcellus, 1975; for a primate brain of this size. Its periph-
Bauchot, 1982), have concluded that the eral sources are constrained by the small
human brain is more similar to either one human body size with respect to the large
of two New World monkeys' brains (woolly brain size. As a result they d o not scale to
thalamocortical parcellation thalamocortical parcellation
process in a brain with typical process in the human brain with
primate cortical nuclear proportions disproportionately enlarged cortex
FIG. 22. Schematic diagram of large-scale human
brain structure disproportions and their effects on
axonal competition processes during human devel-
opment as compared to development in the absence
of these human disproportions. With respect to the
predictions based on other primate brains, human
cortical structures (including the entire cerebral and FIG. 23. A diagram of some of the relative propor-
cerebellar cortices) are larger than expected with tions ofcortical fields in the human brain as compared
respect to brainstem, cerebellar, diencephalic and to predictions based on typical anthropoid primate
telencephalic nuclear structures. Since the cell pro- trends. T h e percentages represent absolute devia-
duction processes which determine the gross size of tions from the predictions for a primate brain of human
these major morphogenetic fields are completed prior size. Temporal, parietal, and motor area predictions
to their parcellation into functional subdivisions it is are based on too few data points to be significant, but
predicted that these disproportions will result in biased demonstrate a pattern that is consistent with the find-
displacement processes. T h e typical condition is ings for other areas and with the displacement
depicted by the three brains on the left. Brains A and hypothesis. T h e depiction of peripheral structures
B represent the normal developmental stages of cor- associated with different cortical areas is intended to
tical axonal parcellation of visual (gray cortex with indicate that cortical areas with relatively direct rep-
gray dashed arrows as afferents), somato-motor (black resentation of peripheral sensory o r motor systems
with black arrows) and prefrontal (gray with solid gray are constrained by these afferents or efferents in their
arrows) cortical fields in a large primate. T h e human competition for cortical representation. Figure taken
deviation from this is depicted by the three brains on from Deacon (1990b).
the right. Brains C and D represent the human devel-
opmental stages with constraint of visual and somatic
fields by their unexpanded peripheral afferents and motor areas as well as for visual areas (Dea-
displacement by prefrontal afferents producing a much con, 1984, 1988b; see Fig. 23).
enlarged adult prefrontal area. T h e competitive limitation of these pro-
jection systems translates into a competi-
tive advantage for other areas not con-
the level that would otherwise be predicted strained by peripheral afferents, which
on the basis of brain size (a brain this big must inherit the cortical surface area that
would be expected only in a very very large is left unrecruited as a result. T h e pre-
ape-the "King Kong" null hypothesis of frontal zone appears to be one major ben-
human brain evolution). T h e competitive eficiary of this competitive imbalance. It is
limits for these afferent systems are con- estimated to be approximately twice the
strained by the size of the peripheral input. size expected for a primate brain of human
Preliminary data suggest that this is prob- proportion (and this translates to six times
ably also the case for auditory, somatic and the size predicted for a primate of human
FIG. 24. Some predicted connectional consequences of prefrontal enlargement are represented by brain A
(typical primate brain structure allometry) as compared to B (human cortical-nuclear disproportion). Dis-
placement theory suggests that the enlargement of the number of prefrontal efferents competing for midbrain
targets as compared to diencephalic efferents will bias competition in favor of prefrontal projections which
will displace both some diencephalic, limbic and intrinsic midbrain axons from their normal targets. This may
lead to the relative dominance of prefrontal outputs over limbic and diencephalic outputs in control of midbrain
and brainstem vocalization centers and motor circuits. This may be linked to adaptations associated with
language skills and the loss of many stereotypic vocalizations in human evolution.

body size; Deacon, 1 984, 1 988b). Prefron- projections from the central gray and retic-
tal cortex is not a recipient of peripheral ular formation. Many of these prefrontal
inputs, but of inputs from other nonspe- and limbic cortical targets turn out to play
cific and polymodal systems of the mid- major roles in vocal call production in pri-
brain and cerebral cortex. It is thus buff- mates. T h e displacement of "normal"
ered by being synaptically removed from afferents of these areas and replacement
the cascading effects of peripheral bias that by a larger fraction of prefrontal axons may
affect other systems. It is probably not inci- have significantly altered their function.
dental that Broca's area for speech is con- Deacon (1990c) argues t h a t this may
tained within this enormously expanded account for the significantly reduced rep-
field. ertoire of stereotypic call types in humans,
This disproportionate prefrontal corti- as well as for the recruitment of some of
cal surface area is a secondary consequence these systems by cortical areas capable of
of the initial disproportion of the entire supporting complex skilled motor pro-
embryonic cortex with respect to its sub- gramming. T h e disproportions among
cortical-peripheral connections. These ini- cortical areas and the relative reduction of
tial disproportions biased axonal compe- thalamocortical as opposed to corticocorti-
tition for cortical representation in favor cal axons undoubtedly also played a role
of cortical areas whose afferents were not in altering cortical functions, some of which
constrained by peripheral systems. But this are related to the human language capac-
secondary disproportion of prefrontal areas ity.
itself must have other tertiary biasing con- Human brain evolution cannot be con-
sequences. Deacon (1990c) notes that effer- ceived in the terms of a conservative-pro-
ent projections of this system target limbic gressive scheme of mammalian brain evo-
cortical structures and a range of midbrain lution. Our brains are not at the pinnacle
structures. We can expect prefrontal pro- of any evolutionary trend. Rather the
jections to have a significant competitive human brain is an unusual divergent case.
advantage over other afferents to these T h e extreme disproportion of human brain
areas during development (see Fig. 24). T h e size with respect t o the human body size
midbrain targets of prefrontal projections with respect to other primates and mam-
also receive descending limbic cortical and mals is only a surface manifestation of a
hypothalamic projections and intrinsic complex allometric reorganization within
the brain, and is unlikely itself to be the and developmental strategies can lead us
crucial trait under selection in human evo- beyond a merely superficial understanding
lution. It is not just the increase in cortical of function to appreciate some of the
complexity nor the increased relative size deeper fundamental organizing principles
of the whole brain but the correlated reor- shared by all features of the brain.
ganization of underlying neural circuitry Neither the study of mammalian brain
that is probably most significant to human evolution nor even the study of human
uniqueness (see also Holloway, 1979). brain evolution is limited to merely theo-
Because the data that we possess con- retical exploration. We currently have
cerning the human brain are still neces- access to experimental tools that are ade-
sarily limited to morphological informa- quate to the task of analyzing the neural
tion and notably do not include detailed developmental processes that underly, can-
connectional data (due to the invasive alize and constrain brain evolution, and are
nature of present tracer techniques) direct capable of gathering the sorts of compar-
verification of these hypothetical reorgani- ative anatomical evidence that can eluci-
zations will have to wait. However, our date the variety of ways these processes
understanding of the processes that must have been expressed in evolution. This is
underly development of a brain with the an invaluable complement to other areas
allometric characteristics of the human of the neurosciences that are rapidly build-
brain can be further augmented by con- ing a database of comparative physiologi-
tinuing investigations of the relationships cal and behavioral information. O u r fail-
between allometric and developmental ure to immediately grasp the significance
processes shared by all mammals. T h e of these data for brain evolution has largely
details of human brain evolution are still been the fault of the unrecognized influ-
largely obscure. T h e hypotheses presented ence of some very old notions about evo-
here are based on a massively incomplete lution, the nature of mental processes;.and
set of data. And yet the basic underlying the place of humans in some cognitive scala
logic of allometric change and axonal dis- naturae.
placement processes during development T h e displacement hypothesis has led me
has provided an important new window to propose four highly speculative. expla-
through which to view these data and an nations of some major problems in mam-
indispensable guide to the gathering of malian brain evolution. But displacement
subsequent information about human brain theory does not depend on the correctness
structures and human development. of these particular interpretations. In fact,
it provides means to falsify them if they re
Conclusions incorrect. T h e theory clearly requires t a t
Understanding the evolutionary ances- patterns of brain evolution be ex p lained in
try of the brain's organization is not merely terms of the biasing of competitive devel-
an academic exercise. It is crucial to the opmental mechanisms a n d suggests
study of its basic functional processes as numerous possible candidates for' biasing
well. Few if any brain structures initially influences that are likely involved: includ-
evolved their present form precisely for ing (in order of likely importance) allo-
the purposes they now serve, and many metric relationships, cell death, hetero-
current brain systems may be the result of chronous changes in maturational events
lucky syntheses of previously separated cir- and changes in molecular affinities between
cuits o r else the result of fortuitous degen- cells and axons. T h e correlate's of displace-
erative events. Because the brain was not ment processes that are postulated t o
predesigned for its current adaptations the account for an evolutionary change must
strategies employed in its operation will not be physically exhibited by the develop-
likely yield to a purely functional physio- mental processes that construct living
logical analysis. More importantly, a n brains. If they are not observed then a dis-
understanding of the predispositions and placement explanation must be rejected o r
constraints inherited from past adaptations modified. T h e examples presented in this
paper have been chosen not as test cases the hominoid thalamus. I: Specific sensory relay
for the theory, but rather as exemplars of nuclei. Am. J. Phys. Anthrop. 51:365-382.
Armstrong, E. 1983. Relative brain size and metab-
the range of possible displacement effects olism in mammals. Science 220: 1302-1 304.
and their consequences. Whatever the ulti- Armstrong, E. 1985. Allometric considerations of
mate applicability of these individual the adult mammalian brain, with special emphasis
accounts, the general approach should at on primates. In W. Jungers (ed.), Size and scaling
in primate biology, pp. 115-146. Plenum Press,
least serve to focus attention on a number New York.
of previously unappreciated correlations Atchley, W. R. 1984. T h e effect of selection on brain
between biasing influences in neural devel- and body size association in rats. Genet. Res. 43:
opment and phylogenetic differences in 289-298.
adult brain structure. T o the extent that Baldwin, J. M. 1985. Mental development in the child
and the race. Macmillan, New York.
these biases are altered in brains of differ- Barbus, H. 1986. Pattern in the laminar origin of
ent sizes or can be manipulated by exper- corticocortical connections. J. Comp. Neurol. 252:
imental modification of neural population 41 5-422.
size or developmental timing, it should be Barbus, H. and D. N. Pandya. 1982. Cytoarchitec-
ture and intrinsic connections of the prefrontal
possible to develop explicit experimental cortex of the rhesus monkey. Soc. Neurosci. Abstr.
models of many evolutionary changes in 8:933.
brain structure. T h e ultimate test of a gen- Barbus, H. and D. N . Pandya. 1987. Architecture
eral theory is not just whether or not it can and frontal cortical connections of the premotor
account for the data that are already cortex (area 6) in the rhesus monkey. J . Comp.
Neurol. 256:211-228.
known, but also how useful it is in leading Bauchot, R. 1982. Brain organization and taxonomic
to new experimental approaches and new relationships in Insectivora and Primates. In E.
insights concerning the underlying hidden Armstrong and D. Falk (eds.), Primate brain evo-
logic of the systems we wish to understand. lution, pp. 163-175. Plenum Press, New York.
Bauchot, R., J. M. Ridet, and M. L. Bauchot. 1979.
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS Encephalization and evolutionary level in aquatic
vertebrates. Vie Milieu Biol. Mar. Oceanogr. 197:
I would like to thank Joseph Marcus for 253-266.
his comments and editorial assistance in Bishop, G. H. 1959. T h e relation between nerve fiber
preparing this manuscript. size and sensory modality: Phylogenetic impli-
cations of the afferent innervation of cortex. J.
REFERENCES Nerv. Ment. Dis. 128:84-114.
Bohringer, R. C. and M. J. Rowe. 1977. T h e orga-
Abbie, A. A. 1940. Cortical lamination in the Mono- nization of the sensory and motor areas of cere-
tremata. J. Comp. Neurol. 72:428-467. bral cortex in the platypus (Ornithorhynchus ana-
Alberch, P. 1982. Developmental constraints in evo- tinus). J . Comp. Neurol. 174:1-14.
lutionary processes. In T. Bonner (ed.), Evolution Bonin, G. von. 1937. Brain-weight and body-weight
and development, pp. 313-332. Springer-Verlag, in mammals. J. Gen. Psych. 16:379-389.
Berlin. Bonin, G. von and P. Bailey. 1961. Patterns of cere-
Alexander, G. E. and P. L. Strick. 1986. Parallel bral isocortex. Primatologia 11/2, Lief. 10:1-42.
organization of functionally segregated circuits Brodmann, K. 1909. Vergleichende Lokalisationslehre
linking basal ganglia and cortex. Ann. Rev. Neu- der Grosshirnrinde in ihren prinzipien dargestellt auf
rosci. 9:357-38 1 . Grand der Zellenbaus. A. Barth, Leipzig.
Alley, K. E. 1974. Morphogenesis of the trigeminal Brown, J. W. 1977. Mind, brain, and consciousness.
mesencephalic nucleus in the hamster: Cytogene- Academic Press, New York.
sis and neurone death. J. Exp. Morph. 31:99- Brown, J. W. 1988. The life of the mind. Erlbaum,
121. Hillsdale, New Jersey.
Allman, J. M. 1982. Reconstructing the evolution of Bullier, J., H. Kennedy, and W. Salinger. 1984.
the brain in primates through the use of com- Branching and laminar origin of projections
parative neurophysiological data. In E. Arm- between visual cortical areas in the cat. J. Comp.
strong and D. Falk (eds.), Primate brain evolution, Neurol. 228:329-341.
pp. 13-28. Plenum Press, New York. Calford, M. B., M. L. Graydon, M. F. Huerta, J. H.
Allman, J. M. 1990. Evolution of neocortex. Cerebral Kass, and J. D. Pettigrew. 1985. A variant of the
cortex, Vol. 8, Evolution and comparative anatomy of mammalian somatotopic map in a bat. Nature
cerebral cortex. Plenum Press, New York. (In press) 3 13:477-480.
Ariëns Kappers, C. U., C. G. Huber, and E. C. Crosby. Campbell, A. 1905. Histological studies on the localiza-
1936. The comparative anatomy of the nervous system tion of cerebral function. Cambridge University
of vertebrates including man, Vol. III. MacMillan, Press, Cambridge.
New York. Campbell, C. B. G. 1982. Some questions and prob-
Armstrong, E. 1979. A quantitative comparison of lems related to homology. In E. Armstrong and
D. Falk (eds.), Primate brain evolution, pp. 1-1 1. Deacon, T. W. 1990a. Fallacies of progression in
Plenum Press, New York. theories of brains size evolution. Int. J. Primatol.
Campbell, C. B. G. 1988. Primate survivors and neo- 11: 193-236.
cortical evolution. Behav. Brain Sci. 11:90-91. Deacon, T. W. 1990b. Problems of ontogeny and
Campbell, C. B. G. and W. Hodos. 1970. T h e con- phylogeny in brain size evolution. lnt. J. Prima-
cept of homology and the evolution of the ner- tol. 11:237-282.
vous system. Brain Behav. Evol. 3:353-367. Deacon, T. W. 1990c. T h e neural circuitry under-
Campos, G. B. and W. I. Welker. 1976. Comparisons lying primate calls and human language. Human
between brains of a large and small hystrico- Evol. (In press)
morph rodent: Capybara, Hydrochoerus and guinea Deacon, T. W., A. Sokoloff, and D. Wecht. 1987.
pig, Cavia (neocortical projection regions and Circular organization of connections linking mid-
measurements of brain subdivisions). Brain Behav. brain areas, sections of the mediodorsal thala-
Evol. 13:243-306. mus, and prefrontal areas in the rat. Soc. Neu-
Cartmill, M. 1972. Arboreal adaptations and the ori- rosci. Abstr. 13:304.9.
gin of the order Primates. In R. H. Tuttle (ed.), Deacon, T. W., D.-W. Wang, and A. Carpenter.
The functional and evolutionary biology of primates, 1989. Similarities and differences in the laminar
pp. 97-122. Aldine-Atherton, Chicago. organization of corticocortical connections in rat
Cartmill, M. 1974. Rethinking primate origins. Sci- as compared t o monkey. Soc. Neurosci. Abstr.
ence 184:433-436. 15:114.10.
Caviness, V. S., Jr. and D. O. Frost. 1980. Tangential Diamond, I. T. 1979. T h e subdivisions of the neo-
organization of thalamic projections to the neo- cortex: A proposal to revise the traditional view
cortex in the mouse. J. Comp. Neurol. 194:335- of sensory, motor and association areas. I n J.
368. Sprague and A. Epstein (eds.), Progress i n psycho-
Chomsky, N. 1972. Language and mind. Harcourt biology and physiological psychology, Vol. 8. Aca-
Brace Javonovich, New York. demic Press, New York.
Count, E. W. 1947. Brain and body weight in man: Diamond, I. T. 1982. T h e functional significance of
Their antecedents in growth and evolution. Ann. architectonic divisions of the cortex, Lashley's
N.Y. Acad. Sci. 46:993-1122. criticism of the traditional view. I n J. Orbach
Cowan, W. M. 1973. Neuronal death as a regulative (ed.), Neuropsychology after Lashley, pp. 101-1 35.
mechanism in the control of cell number in the Erlbaum, Hillsdale, New Jersey.
nervous system. I n M. Rockstein (ed.), Develop- Diamond, I. T . , D. Fitzpatrick, and J. M. Sprague.
ment and aging i n the nervous system, pp. 119-141. 1985. T h e extrastriate visual cortex. A historical
Academic Press, New York. approach to the relation between the "visuo-sen-
Cowan, W. M., J. W. Fawcett, D. D. M. O'Leary, and sory" and "visuo-psychic" areas. In A. Peters and
B. B. Stanfield. 1984. Regressive events in neu- E. G. Jones (eds.), Cerebral cortex, Vol. 4; Associ-
rogenesis. Science 255: 1258-1265. ation and auditory cortices, pp. 63-87. Plenum Press,
Cranach, M. von. 1976. Methods of inference from ani- New York.
mal to human behavior. Aldine, Chicago. Diamond, I. T. and W. C. Hall. 1969. Evolution of
Crosby, E. C. 19 17. T h e forebrain of Alligator mis- neocortex. Science 164:251-262.
sissippiensis. J. Comp. Neurol. 27:325-403. Dom, R., G. F. Martin, B. L. Fisher, A. M. Fisher,
Dart, R. 1934. T h e dual structure of the neopallium: and J. K. Harting. 197 1. T h e motor cortex and
Its history and significance. J. Anat. 69:3-19. corticospinal tract of the armadillo (Dasypus no-
Deacon, T. W. 1984. Connections of the inferior vemcincus). J. Neurol. Sci. 14:225-236.
periarcuate area in the brain of Macaca fascicu- Donoghue, J. P., K. L. Kerman, and F. F. Ebner.
laris. An experimental and comparative investi- 1979. Evidence for two organizational plans
gation of language circuitry and its evolution. within the somatic sensory-motor cortex. of the
Ph.D. Diss., Harvard University, Cambridge, rat. J. Comp. Neurol. 183:647-664.
Massachusetts. Douglas, R. J. and D. Marcellus. 1975. T h e ascent
Deacon, T. W. 1985. "Counter-current flow" of cor- of man: Deductions based on a multivariate anal-
tico-cortical information processing through the ysis of the brain. Brain Behav. Evol. 11:179-2 13.
laminar segregation of reciprocal connections. Dubois, E. 1913. O n the relation between quantity
Soc. Neurosci. Abstr. 1 1:203.1 of brain and the size of the body in vertebrates.
Deacon, T. W. 1988a. Cortical and midbrain con- Verh. Kon. Akad. Wetenschappen Amsterdam
nections of the intermediodorsal nucleus in the 16:647.
rat. Soc. Neurosci. Abstr. 14:328.1. Ebbesson, S. O. 1980. T h e parcellation theory and
Deacon. T. W. 1988b. Human brain evolution: II. its relation t o interspecific variability in brain
Embryology and brain allometry. I n H. Jerison organization, evolutionary a n d o n t o g e n e t i c
and I. Jerison (eds.), Intelligence and evolutionary development, and neuronal plasticity. Cell Tissue
biology, pp. 383-41 5. Springer-Verlag, Berlin. Res. 2 13: 179-2 12.
Deacon, T. W. 1989. Holism and associationism in Ebbesson, S. O. 1984. Evolution and ontogeny of
neuropsychology: An anatomical synthesis. In E. neural circuits. Behav. Brain Sci. 7:32 1-366.
Perecman (ed.), Integrating theory and practice in Edelman, G. M. 1987. Neural Darwinism. Basic Books,
clinical neuropsychology, pp. 1-47. Erlbaum, Hills- New York.
dale, New Jersey. Elliot-Smith, G. 1910. Some problems related to the
evolution of the brain. Lancet 1:1-6, 147-153, for a specialized subarea and changes with age.
22 1-227. J. Comp. Neurol. 247:491-496.
Elliot-Smith, G. 1919. A preliminary note o n the Gaskin, D. E. 1982. The ecology of whales and dolphins.
morphology of the corpus striatum and the origin Heineman, New York.
of the neopallium. J. Anat. 53:271-291. Geschwind, N. 1964. Development of brain and evo-
Falk, D. 1980. A reanalysis of the South African lution of language. Georgetown Univ. Monogr.
australopithecine natural endocast. Am. J. Phys. Ser. Language Linguistics 17: 155-170.
Anthrop. 53:525-539. Ghiselin, M. T. 1976. T h e nomenclature of corre-
Falk, D. 1983. Cerebral cortices of East African early spondence: A new look at "homology" and "anal-
hominids. Science 221: 1072- 1074. ogy." In R. B. Masterton, W. M. Hodos, and H.
Falk, D. 1989. Ape-like endocast of "Ape-man" Jerison (eds.), Evolution, brain and behavior: Per-
Taung. Am. J. Phys. Anthrop. 80:335-339. sistent problems, pp. 129-142. Erlbaum, New York.
Fasolo, A. and G. Malacarne. 1988. Comparing the Glezer, I. I., M. S. Jacobs, and P. J. Morgane. 1988.
structure, of brains: Implications for behavioral Implications of the "initial brain" concept for
homologies. In H. Jerison and I. Jerison (ed.), brain evolution in Cetacea. Behav. Brain Sci. 1 1 :
Intelligence and evolutionary biology, pp. 119-142. 75-116.
Springer-Verlag, Berlin. Goldowitz, D. 1987. Cell partitioning and mixing in
Filimonof, I. N. 1949. Comparative anatomy of the cere- the formation of the CNS: Analysis of the cortical
bral cortex of mammals. paleocortex, a rchicortex, and somatosensory barrels in chimeric mice. Devel.
intermediate cortex. [Trans. by V. Dukhoff, 1965]. Brain Res. 35:1-9.
Joint Pub. Res. Service, Office of Sci. Inf. Dept. Gould, S. J. 1966. Allometry and size in ontogeny
of Interior, Washington, D.C. and phylogeny. Biol. Rev. Camb. Phil. Soc. 41:
Filler; A. 1986. Axial character seriation in mam- 587-640.
mals. An historical exploration of the origin, Gould, S. J. 1975. Allometry in primates with empha-
development, use and current collapse of the sis of scaling and the evolution of the brain. Contr.
homology paradigm. Ph.D. Diss., Harvard Uni- Primatol. 5:244-292.
versity, Cambridge, Massachusetts. Gould, S. J. 1977. Ontogeny and phylogeny. Harvard
Finlay, B. L. and M. Slattery. 1983. Local differences University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts.
in early cell death in neocortex predict adult local Gould, S. J. 1981. The mismeasure of man. George J.
specializations. Science 2 19:1349-1 351. McLeod Limited, Toronto.
Finlay, B.L., K. C. Wikler, and D. R. Sengelaub. Gregory, W. K. 1935. Replication in evolution. Q.
1987. Regressive events in brain development Rev. Biol. 10:272-290.
and scenarios for vertebrate brain evolution. Brain
Guillery, R. W. 1974. Visual pathways in albinos. Sci.
Behav. Evol. 30: 102-1 17.
Amer. 230:44-54.
Flechsig, P. 1900. Über Projections und Associations
Zentren des menschlichen Gehirns. [On projec- Haight, J. R. and L. Neylon. 1978. T h e organization
tion and association centers of the human brain.] of neocortical projections from the ventropos-
Neurologie Zentralblatt 19. terior thalamic complex in the marsupial brush-
Flechsig, P. 190 1 . Developmental (myelogenetic) tailed opossum, Trichosurus vulpecula, a horserad-
localization of the cerebral cortex in the human ish peroxidase study. J. Anat. 126:459-485.
subject. Lancet 2:1027-1029. Haight, J. R. and L. Neylon. 1979. T h e organization
Friedman, D. P., L. G. Bachevalier, L. G. Unger- of neocortical projections from the ventrolateral
lieder, and M. Mishkin. 1987. Widespread tha- thalamic nucleus in the brush-tailed possum,
lamic projections to layer I of primate cortex. Trichosurus vulpecula, and the problem of motor
Soc. Neurosci. Abstr. 13:73.17. and somatic sensory convergence within the
Frost, D. and V. Caviness, Jr. 1980. Radial organi- mammalian brain. J. Anat. 129:673-694.
zation of thalamocortical projections. J. Comp. Haug, H. 1987. Brain sizes, surfaces, and neuronal
Neurol. 194:369-394. sizes of the cortex cerebri: A stereological inves-
Frost, D. O. and C. Metin. 1985. Induction of func- tigation of man and his variability and a com-
tional retinal projections to the somatosensory parison with some mammals (primates, whales,
system. Nature 3 17: 162. marsupials, insectivores, and one elephant). Am.
Fuller, J. L. 1979. Fuller BWS lines: History and J. Anat. 180:126-1 42.
results. I n M. E. Hahn, C. Jensen, and B. C. Dudek Herkenham, M. 1980. Laminar organization of tha-
(eds.), Development and evolution of brain size, pp. lamic projections to the rat neocortex. Science
190-204. Academic Press, New York. 207:532-534.
Galaburda, A. M. and D. N. Pandya. 1983. T h e Herman, L. M. (ed.) 1980. Cetacean behavior: Mech-
intrinsic architectonic and connectional organi- anisms and functions. Wiley, New York.
zation of the superior temporal region of the Herrick, C. J. 1920. A sketch of the origin of the
rhesus monkeys. J. Comp. Neurol. 22 1:169-184. cerebral hemispheres. J. Comp. Neurol. 32:429-
Gardner, H. 1983. Frames of mind: The theory of mul- 454.
tiple intelligences. Basic Books, New York. Hodos. W. 1988. Comparative neuroanatomy and
Garey, L. J. and G. Leuba. 1986. A quantitative study the evolution of intelligence. I n H. Jerison and
of neuronal and glial numerical density in the I. Jerison (eds.), Intelligence and evolutionary biol-
visual cortex of the bottlenose dolphin: Evidence ogy pp. 93-108. Springer-Verlag, Berlin.
Holloway, R. L. 1979. Brain size, allometry, and Kaas, J. H. 1989. Why does the brain have so many
reorganization: Toward a synthesis. In M. Hahn, visual areas? J. Cog. Neurosci. 1:12 1-135.
C. Jensen, and B. Dudek (eds.), Development and Kaas, J . H. and R. W. Guillery. 1973. T h e transfer
evolution of brain size, pp. 59-88. Academic Press, of abnormal visual field representations from the
New York. dorsal lateral geniculate nucleus to the visual cor-
Holloway, R. L. 1981. Revisiting the South African tex in Siamese cats. Brain Res. 59:61-95.
Taung australopithecine endocast: T h e position Kaas, J. H., W. C. Hall, and I. T. Diamond. 1970.
of the lunate sulcus as determined bv the ste- Cortical visual areas I and II in the hedgehog:
reoplotting technique. Am. J. Phys. Anthrop. 56: Relation between evoked potential maps and
43-58. architectonic divisions. J. Neurophys. 33:595-
Holloway, R. L. 1984. T h e Taung endocast and the 615.
lunate sulcus: A rejection of the hypothesis of its Kaas, J. H. and M. F. Huerta.1988. Subcortical visual
anterior position. Am. J. Phys. Anthro. 1984: system of primates. In H. D. Steklis (ed.), Com-
285-287. parative primate biology, Vol. 4: Neurosciences, pp.
Holloway, R. L. 1985. T h e past, present, and future 327-391. Alan R. Liss, New York.
significance of the lunate sulcus in early hominid Karten, H. J. 1969. T h e organization of the avian
evolution. In P. V. Tobias (ed.), Hominid evolution: telencephalon and some speculations o n the phy-
Past, present and future, pp. 47-62. Alan R. Liss, logeny of the amniote telencephalon. Ann. N.Y.
New York. Acad. Sci. 167: 164-179.
Holloway, R. L. 1988. Some additional morpholog- Karten, H. J. and T. Shimuzu. 1989. T h e origins of
ical and metrical observation on Pan brain casts neocortex: Connections and lamination as dis-
and their relevance to the Taung endocast. Am. tinct events in evolution. J. Cog. Neurosci. 1:29 1-
J. Phys. Anthro. 77:27-33. 30 1.
Hopf, A. 1965. Volumetrische Untersuchunger sur Kaplan, S. R. and G. E. Goslow. 1989. Neuromus-
vergleichenden Anatomie des Thalamus. J. Hir- cular organization of the pectoralis (pars thora-
forsch. 8:25-38. cicus) of the pigeon (Columba livia): Implications
Jacobs, M. S., A. M. Galaburda, W. L. McFarland, for motor control. Anat. Rec. 224:426-430.
and P. J. Morgane. 1984. T h e insular formation Katz, M. 1982. Ontogenetic mechanisms: T h e mid-
of the dolphin brain. Quantitative cytoarchitec- dle ground of evolution. In T. Bonner (ed.), Evo-
tonic studies of the insular component of the lim- lution and development, pp. 207-2 12. Springer-
bic lobe. J. Comp. Neurol. 225:396-432. Verlag, Berlin.
Jacobs, M. S., W. L. McFarland, and P. J. Morgane. Kirsch, J. A. W., A. I. Johnson, and R. C. Switzer.
1979. T h e anatomy of the brain of the bottlenose 1983. Phylogeny through brain traits: The mam-
dolphin (Tursiops truncatus). Rhinic lobe (rhinen- malian family tree. Brain Behav. Evol. 22:70-74.
cephalon): I. T h e archicortex. Brain Res. Bull. Kruska, D. 1987. How fast can total brain size change
4(Suppl. 1):1-108. in mammals? J. Hirnforsch. 28:59-70.
Jacobs, M. S., P. J. Morgane, and W. L. McFarland. Kuljis, R. O. and P. Rakic. 1988. Segregation of neu-
197 1. T h e anatomy of the brain of the bottlenose ropeptide Y-containing neurons outside cyto-
dolphin (Tursiops truncatus). Rhinic lobe (rhinen- chrome oxidase puffs in the monkey develops in
cephalon): I. T h e paleocortex. J. Comp. Neurol. the absence of visual input. Soc. Neurosci. Abstr.
141:205-272. 14:243.5.
Jacobson, J. 1978. Developmental neurobiology, 2nd ed. Le Gros Clark, W. E. 197 1. Antecedents of man. Edin-
Holt, Rhinehart, and Winston, New York. burgh University Press, Edinburgh.
Jarvis, M. J. and G. Ettlinger. 1977. Cross-modal Le Gros Clark, W. and D. Northfield. 1939. The
recognition in chimpanzees and monkeys. Neu- cortical projection of the pulvinar in the macaque
ropsychologia 15:499-506. monkey. Brain 60: 126-1 42.
Jerison, H. J. 1973. Evolution of the brain and intelli- Lende, R. A. 1963. Cerebral cortex: A sensorymotor
gence. Academic Press, New York. amalgam in the Marsupialia. Science 141:730-
Jouandet, M., M. Tramo, D. Herron, A. Hermann, 732. . ,

W. Loftus, J. Bazell, and M. Gazzaniga. 1989. Lende, R. A. 1969. A comparative appoach to neo-
Brainprints: Computer-generated two-dimen- cortex: Localization in monotremes, marsupials
sional maps of the human cerebral cortex in vivo. and insectivores. Ann. N.Y. Acad. Sci. 167:262-
J. Cog. Neurosci. 1:88-117. 275.
Johnson, J. I. 1988. Whose brain is initial-like? Behav. Lieberman, P. 1984. The biology and evolution of lan-
Brain Sci. 1 1:96. guage. Harvard University Press, Cambridge,
Johnston, J. B. 1906. The nervous system of vertebrates. Massachusetts.
P. Blackiston's Son and Co., Philadelphia. Livingstone, R. and D. Huebel. 1988. Segregation
Jones, E. G., J. D. Coulter, and S. H. C. Hendry. 1978. of form, color, movement, and depth: Anatomy,
Intracortical connectivity of architectonic fields physiology, and preception. Science 240:740-749.
in the somatic sensory, motor and parietal cortex Luria, A. R. 1980. Higher cotical functions in man
of monkeys. J. Comp. Neurol. 18 1:291-348. 2nd ed. (English trans.). Basic Books, New York.
Kaas, J. H. 1987. T h e organization and evolution of MacLean, P. D. 1970. T h e triune brain, emotion and
neocortex. In S. P. Wise (ed.), Higher brain func- scientific basis. In F. O. Schmitt (ed.), The neu-
tions. Recent explorations of the brain's emergent prop- rosciences: Second study program. Rockefeller Uni-
erties, pp. 347-378. John Wiley & Sons, New York. versity Press, New York.
MacLean, P. D. 1973. A triune concept of the brain profile of the vertebrate brain with sidelights on
and behavior. In T. J. Boag and D. Campbell the ancestry of the cerebral cortex. In F. O.
(eds.), A triune concept of the brain and behavior. Schmidt (ed.), The neurosciences: Second study pro-
University of Toronto Press, Toronto. gram. Rockefeller Press, New York.
MacPhail, E. 1982. Brain and intelligence in vertebrates. Northcutt, R. G. 1981. Evolution of the telenceph-
Clarendon Press, Oxford. alon in nonmammals. Ann. Rev. Neurosci. 4:301-
Magalhães-Castro, B. and P. E. S. Saraiva. 1971. Sen- 350.
sory and motor representation in the cerebral Northcutt, R. G. 1984. Evolution of the vertebrate
cortex of the marsupial Didelphis azarae azarae. central nervous system: Patterns and processes.
Brain Res. 34:291-299. Amer. Zool. 24:70 1-7 16.
Marin-Padilla, M. 1978. Dual origin of the mam- O'Leary, D. D. M. 1989. Do cortical areas emerge
malian neocortex and evolution of the cortical from a protocortex? Trends Neurosci. 12:400-
plate. Anat. Embryol. 152: 109-156. 406.
Martin, R. D. 1973. Comparative anatomy and pri- O'Leary, D. D. M. and B. B. Stanfield. 1989. Selec-
mate systematics. Symp. Zool. Soc. London 33: tive elimination of axons extended by developing
301-337. cortical neurons is dependent o n regional locale
Martin, R. D. 1981. Relative brain size and basal experiments utilizing fetal cortical transplants. J.
metabolic rate in terrestrial vertebrates. Nature Neurosci. 9:2230-2246.
293:57-60. Optican, L. M. and B. J. Richmond. 1987. Temporal
Martin, R. D. 1983. Human brain evolution in an encoding of two-dimensional patterns by single
ecological context. Fifty-second James Arthur units in primate inferior temporal cortex. III.
Lecture on the evolution of the human brain. Information theoretic analysis. J. Neurophysiol.
Am. Mus. Nat. Hist., New York. 57:162-178.
Maunsell, J. H. R. and D. C. Van Essen. 1983. T h e Pandya, D. and E. Yeterian. 1985. Architecture and
connections of the middle temporal visual area connections of cortical association areas. In A.
(MT) and their relationship to a cortical hier- Peters and E. G. Jones (eds.), Cerebral cortex, Vol.
archy in the macaque monkey. J. Neurosci. 3: 4, Association and auditory cortices, pp. 3-61. Ple-
2563-2586. num Press, New York.
Meculam, M.-M., G. W. Van Hoesen, D. N. Pandya, Passingham, R. E. 1975. Changes in the size and
and N. Geschwind. 1977. Limbic and sensory organisation of the brain in man and his ances-
connections of the inferior parietal lobule (area tors. Brain Behav. Evol. 11:73-90.
PG) in the rhesus monkey: A study with a new Passingham, R. E. 198 1. Broca's area and the origins
method for horseradish peroxidase histochem- of human vocal skill. Phil. Trans. R. Soc. London,
istry. Brain Res. 136:393-414. B 292: 167-175.
Mishkin, M. and T. Appenzeller. 1987. The anatomy Primrose, D. and P. Strick. 1985. T h e organization
of memory. Sci. Amer. 256:80-89. of interconnections between the premotor areas
Morgane, P. J., I. I. Glezer, and M. S. Jacobs. 1990. of the primate frontal lobe and the arm area of
Comparative and evolutionary anatomy of visual primary motor cortex. Soc. Neurosci. Abstr. 11:
cortex of the dolphin. In E. G. Jones and A. Peters 127.4.
(eds.), Cerebral cortex, Vol. 8. Evolution and com- Purves, D. 1988. Body and brain: A trophic theory of
parative anatomy of cerebral cortex. Plenum Press, neural connections. Harvard University Press,
New York. (In press) Cambridge, Massachusetts.
Morgane, P. J. and M. S. Jacobs. 1972. Comparative Purves, D. and J. W. Lichtman. 1980. Elimination
anatomy of the cetacean nervous system. In R. J. of synapses in the developing nervous system.
Harrison (eds.), Functional anatomy of marine mam- Science 2 10: 153-157.
mals, pp. 117-244. Academic Press, London.
Morgane, P. J., M. S. Jacobs, and A. Galaburda. 1985. Purves, D. and J. W. Lichtman. 1985. Principles of
neural development. Sinauer, New York.
Conservative features of neocortical evolution in
dolphin brain. Brain Behav. Evol. 26:176-184. Rakic, P. 1988. Specification of cerebral cortical areas.
Morgane, P. J., M. S. Jacobs, and A. Galaburda. Science 24 1: 170-1 76.
1986a. Evolutionary aspects of cortical organi- Rausell, E. and C. Avendano. 1985. Thalamocortical
zation in the dolphin brain. In R. J. Harrison and neurons projecting to superficial and to deep lay-
M. Bryden (eds.), Research on dolphins, pp. 71-98. ers in parietal, frontal and prefrontal regions in
Oxford University Press, Oxford. the cat. Brain Res. 347:159-165.
Morgane, P. J., M. S. Jacobs, and A. Galaburda. Reynolds, P. C. 1976. Language and skilled activity.
1986b. Evolutionary morphology of the dolphin In S. R. Harnad, H. D. Steklis, and J. Lancaster
brain. In R. Schusterman, F. Wood, and J. Thomas (eds.), Origins and evolution of language and speech.
(eds.), Dolphin cognition and behavior: A comparative Ann. N.Y. Acad. Sci. 280:1-914.
approach, pp. 5-29. Erlbaum, Hillsdale, New Jer- Riska, B., W. R. Atchley, and J. J. Rutledge. 1984.
sey. A genetic analysis of targeted growth in mice.
Morgane, P. J., W. L. McFarland, and M. S. Jacobs. Genetics 107:79-101.
1982. T h e limbic lobe of the dolphin brain: A Rockel, A.J., R. W. Hiorns, and T. P. S. Powell. 1980.
quantitative cytoarchitectonic study. J. Hirn- T h e basic uniformity in structure of the neocor-
forsch. 23:465-552. tex. Brain 103:221.
Nauta, W. J. H. and H. J. Karten. 1970. A general Rockland, K. and D. N. Pandya. 1979. Laminar
origins and terminations of connections of the Snell, 0. 1891. Das Gewicht des Gehirns und des
occipital lobe in the rhesus monkey. Brain Res. Hirnmantels der Saugetiere in Beziehung zu
179:3-20. deren geistigen Fahigkeiten. Sitz. Ges. Morph.
Roderick, T. H., R. E. Wimer, and C. C. Wimer. Physiol. (Munchen) 7:90-94.
1976. Genetic manipulation of neuroanatomical Sohal, G. S. 1976. An experimental study of cell
traits. I n L. Petrinovich and J. L. McGaugh (eds.), death in the developing trochlear nucleus. Exp.
Knowing, thinking nnd believing, pp. 143-178. Ple- Neurol. 5 1 :684-698.
num Press, New York. Sokoloff, A., T. W. Deacon, and G. E. Goslow. 1989.
Rose, J. and C. Woolsey. 1949. Organization of the Musculotopic innervation of the primary flight
mammalian thalamus and its relation to the cere- muscles, the pectoralis (pars thoracicus) and
bral cortex. Electroenceph. Clin. Neurophysiol. supracoracoideus, of the pigeon (Columba livia):
1:391-404. A HRP study. Anat. Rec. 225:35-40.
Royce, G. J., G. F. Martin, and R. N. Dom. 1975. Spencer, H. 1980. Principles of psychology, 2nd ed.
Functional organization and cortical architecture Longman Press, London.
in the nine-banded armadillo (Dasjpus novemcinc- Stanfield, B. B. and D. D. M. O'Leary. 1985. Fetal
tus). J . Comp. Neurol. 164:495-522. occipital cortical neurons transplanted to the ros-
Russell, E. S. 19 16. Form and function. John Murray, tral cortex can extend and maintain a pyramidal
London. tract axon. Nature 3 13: 135-137.
Sacher, G. A. 1970. Allometric and factorial analysis Stephan, H. 1969. Quantitative investigations o n
of brain structure in insectivores and primates. visual structures in primate brains. I n Proceed-
I n C. R. Novack and W. Montagna (eds.), The ings of the Second International Congress on Pri-
primate brain: Advances in primatology, pp. 245- mates 3:34-42. Karger, Basel.
287. Appleton Century Crofts, New York. Stephan, H., H. Frahm, and G. von Baron. 1981.
Sacher, G. A. and E. F. Staffeldt. 1974. Relation of New and revised data on volumes of brain struc-
gestation time to brainweight for placental mam- tures in insectivores and primates. Folia Prima-
mals: Implications for the theory of vertebrate tologica 35: 1-29.
growth. Am. Nat. 108:593-615. Sur, M., P. E. Garraghty, and A. W. Roe. 1988.
Sanides, F. 1969. Comparative architectonics of the Experimentally induced visual projections into
neocortex of mammals and their evolutionary auditory thalamus and cortex. Science 242: 1437-
interpretation. Ann. N.Y. Acad. Sci. 167:404- 1441.
423. Thompson, D. 1917. O n growth and form. Cambridge
Sanides, F. 1970. Functional architecture of motor University Press, Cambridge.
and sensory cortices in primates in the light of a Tigges, J., W. Spatz, and M. Tigges. 1973. Recip-
new concept of neocortex evolution. I n C. Noback rocal point-to-point connections between para-
and W. Montagna (eds.), The primate brain: striate and striate cortex in the squirrel monkey
Advances in primatology, pp. 137-208. Appleton (Saimiri). J. Comp. Neurol. 148:481-490.
Century Crofts, New York. Tigges, J., M. Tigges, and A. Perachio. 1977. Com-
Sanides, F. 1972. Representation in the cerebral cor- plementary laminar terminations of afferents to
tex and its areal lamination patterns. I n G. F. area 17 originating in area 18 and in the lateral
Bourne (ed.), Structure and function of nervous tis- geniculate nucleus in the squirrel monkey. J.
sue, Vol. 5, pp. 329-453. Academic Press, New Comp. Neurol. 176:87-100.
York. 'Tobias, P. V. 198 1 . T h e emergence of man in Africa
Sanides, F. 1975. Comparative neurology of the tem- and beyond. Philos. Trans. R. Soc. London B,
poral lobe in primates including man with ref- Biol. Sci. 292:43-56.
erence to speech. Brain Lang. 2:396-419. Tower, D. B. 1954. Structural and functional orga-
Saraiva, P. E. S. and B. Magalh„es-Castro. 1975. Sen- nization of the mammalian cerebral cortex. T h e
sory and motor representation in the cerebral correlation of neuron density with brain size.
cortex of the three-toed sloth {Bradypus tridacty- Cortical density in the finwhale with a note on
lus). Brain Res. 90: 181-1 93. the cortical neurone density in the Indian ele-
Sarnat, H. B. and M. G. Netsky. 1981. Evolution of phant. J. Comp. Neurol. 101:19-53.
the nervous system. Oxford University Press, New Ulinski, P. S. 1983. Dorsal ventricular ridge. Wiley,
York. New York.
Seltzer, B. and D. N. Pandya. 1980. Converging visual Ulinski, P. S. 1986. Neurobiology of the therapsid-
and somatic sensory cortical input to the intra- mammal transition. In N. Hottén, P. D. Mac-
parietal sulcus of the rhesus monkey. Brain Res. Lean, J. J. Roth, and E. Roth (eds.), The ecology
192:339-351. and biology of mammal-like reptiles, pp. 149-17 1.
Semsa, M., V. Casagrande, and J. Kaas. 1984. Cor- Smithsonian Institution Press, Washington, D.C.
tical connections of area 17 in tree shrews. J. Valverde, F. and L. López-Mascaraque. 198 1. Neo-
Comp. Neurol. 230:337-35 1. cortical endeavor: Basic neuronal organization in
Sherrington, C. 1906. The integrativeaction of the ner- the cortex of the hedgehog. Eleventh international
vous system. Yale University Press, New Haven. congress of anatomy, glial and neuronal cell biology.
Smith-Gill, S. J. 1983. Developmental plasticity: Alan R. Liss, New York.
Developmental conversion versus phenotypic Van Valen, L. 1982. Homology and causes. J. Morph.
modulation. Amer. Zool. 23:47-55. 173:305-312.
Walsh, C. and C. L. Cepko. 1988. Clonally related Woolsey, T. A. and J.R. Wann. 1976. Areal changes
cortical cells show several migration patterns. Sci- in mouse cortical barrels following vibrissal dam-
ence 141:1342-1345. age at different postnatal ages. J. Comp. Neurol.
Walsh, T. M. and F. F. Ebner. 1970. T h e cytoar- 170:53-66.
chitecture of somatic sensory-motor cortex in the Würsig, B. 1989. Cetaceans. Science 244:1550-1557.
opossum (Didelphis marsupialis virginiana), a Golgi Yakovlev, P. I. and A.-R. Lecours. 1967. The myelo-
study. J. Anat. 107:1-18. genetic cycles of regional maturation of the brain.
Warren, S. and M. Carlson. 1986. Topography of In A. Minkowski (eds.), Regional development of the
primary somatic sensory cortex (SI) in Old World brain in early life. A symposium. F. A. Davis Co.,
primates, Cercopithecus and Myopithecus. Soc. Neu- Philadelphia.
rosci. Abstr. 12:386.1. Zilles, K. and G. Rehkämper. 1988. T h e initial brain
Wilczynski, W. 1984. Central neural systems sub- concept: A work in progress. Behav. Brain Sci.
serving a homoplasous periphery. Amer. Zool. 11:105-106.
24:755-763.
Wiley, E. O. 1981. Phylogenetics. Wiley, New York.

View publication stats

You might also like