You are on page 1of 8

Organizational

Psychology
Special forum on good theory Review

Organizational Psychology Review


3(2) 187–194
Organizational sciences’ ª The Author(s) 2013
Reprints and permission:
obsession with ‘‘that’s sagepub.co.uk/journalsPermissions.nav
DOI: 10.1177/2041386613479963

interesting!’’: Consequences opr.sagepub.com

and an alternative

Madan M. Pillutla
London Business School, UK

Stefan Thau
London Business School, UK

Abstract
We suggest that the organizational science’s increasing preoccupation with ‘‘interesting’’ theories
and ‘‘counterintuitive’’ facts can lead to nonreplicable findings, fragmented theory, and irrelevance.
The focus on the interesting and novel reveals a profound misunderstanding of the scientific
enterprise. Organizational scholarship will be better off if it reverts to according primacy to the
problem being solved over novel theory development.

Keywords
methodology, philosophy of science, research problems

Paper received 30 January 2013; revised version accepted 30 January 2013.

In an essay published in the Organizational agree. The state of our field and its obsession with
Psychology Review, Ferris, Hochwarter, and novel theoretical contributions is antithetical to
Buckley (2012) make the observation that our the goals of the scientific method (cf. Russell,
discipline’s emphasis on ‘‘revelatory contribu- 1931). As an ideal, the scientific method consists
tions’’ to theory has led to a fragmented and of a set of propositions arranged in a hierarchy,
disorganized body of research. They argue that with the lower level propositions being logical
the organizational science is full of theoretical deductions from higher level ones, and the higher
models that do not build on one another. We level propositions being logical inductions from

Corresponding author:
Madan M. Pillutla, Organizational Behavior Subject Area, London Business School, Sussex Place, London NW1 4SA, UK.
Email: mpillutla@london.edu

Downloaded from opr.sagepub.com at WASHBURN UNIV on January 13, 2015


188 Organizational Psychology Review 3(2)

the lower level ones. The hierarchy also requires as a classic and served as a basis for invigor-
that the propositions are commensurable. As ating much organizational sciences enquiry.
Ferris et al. (2012) eloquently summarize, the Arguing against what he considered to be
organizational sciences are far from this ideal and mediocre and uninspired research in the social
the excessive desire for theoretical novelty is sciences, he exhorted scholars to understand
largely to blame. what makes for interesting theories. Davis
We offer a complementary view in this essay (1971, p. 328) claimed that,
by suggesting that the field’s focus on the
‘‘interesting’’ (Davis, 1971) both in reporting Non-interesting social theories are often
on facts and in theories has also contributed to asserted on purpose by those who think that
the fragmented state of the field. The demand the business of social scientists is merely to
that both theory and results should satisfy criteria assert any theory that can be derived and
of what is interesting, we argue, is antithetical to confirmed according to the text-book rules
the scientific method and needs revisiting if we of theory construction and verification.
want to make progress. In particular, we contend
that the focus on the ‘‘interesting’’ has mutated He went on to claim, (Davis, 1971, p. 328), that
into a focus on finding counterintuitive ‘‘facts’’ ‘‘the mediocre in the social sciences and
and theories. This, in turn, creates two incentives (probably the natural sciences too) can be
to the scholarly community that are undesired defined as those who take the textbook rules of
from the standpoint of a positivistic model of scientific procedures too literally and too
science (Popper, 1935): (a) an incentive to exclusively.’’ Davis was right in noting that a
backward-engineer theories to explain counter- social scientist could have impact if they could
intuitive facts. The problem with this approach take on and challenge the assumptions of their
is that the resulting theories will have little audience. But the seemingly casual dismissal of
explanatory reach and (b) an incentive to find the scientific method as the province of the
facts that fit a counterintuitive theory. The prob- mediocre should provide a cautionary note
lem with this approach is that the resulting facts against the fulsome acceptance of his ideas.
will have little chance of replication. Rather than being cautious consumers, we
We argue that the focus on the interesting is think Davis’s exhortations have been taken on a
actually a misunderstanding of the scientific little too enthusiastically by organizational sci-
process. We also suggest that the adoption of entists in general and editors and reviewers of
Davis’s article as some kind of ‘‘how-to’’ conduct organizational journals in particular. It is note-
research is restricted to the organizational worthy that the organizational sciences seem to
sciences. We believe that theories do not need to be particularly swayed by his prescriptions.
be interesting, new, or full of counterintuitive Specifically, an analysis of citation patterns of
assumptions. Research problems, however, his article (Table 1) reveals that 71% of all
should be interesting and their definition should citations the article picked up (260 cites in total)
precede theory construction. We propose heur- can be attributed to the organizational sciences.
istics for how to define research problems. A hefty 83% of editorials citing the article have
been published in organizational journals. This
analysis suggests that the Davis article appears to
have had a disproportionate impact on the
The quest to be interesting organizational sciences. And the impact appears
Davis’s (1971) article, ‘‘That’s Interesting: to be a function of the weight placed on the
Towards a Phenomenology of Sociology and a criteria espoused in the article by the editors of
Sociology of Phenomenology,’’ has been hailed our journals. While some of these editorials (i.e.,

Downloaded from opr.sagepub.com at WASHBURN UNIV on January 13, 2015


Pillutla and Thau 189

Table 1. Pattern of citations for the Davis article in the Social Science Citation Index (SSCI) as on the 22nd of
January 2013.

Discipline Number of citations Citations classified as editorial

Management 133 24
Business 95 18
Sociology 22
Psychology-applied 19 4
Information science-library science 9 2
Psychology-multidisciplinary 9
Social science-interdisciplinary 9 1
Computer science-information systems 8 2
Psychology social 8 1
Education-education research 7

Eden & Rynes, 2003; Gill & Bhattacherjee, content or the logic of its form.’’—suggests the
2009; Markoczy & Deeds, 2009; Pearce, 2007; need to put his exhortation to be interesting in
Schwarz & Huber, 2008) use the article to make perspective. We are scientists first and sales-
the point about the kind of theories that make an men second. If the order gets inverted, as we
impact, the others seem to understand it as a argue has become the case when ‘‘interesting’’
guide to construct theory or develop research becomes the goal, we run the risk of perverting
problems. These editorials (e.g., Ahlstrom, 2011; the scientific enterprise.
Colquitt & George, 2011; Daft & Lewin, 1990; Our goal is not to argue for uninteresting
Reay & Whetten, 2011; Short, 2009) seem to work. We want to examine some of the conse-
communicate that articles need to be interesting quences of the prevalent trend of elevating the
in the Davis sense to warrant publication. interesting over the truth (and robust) and to
We agree that research problems must be sketch a route leading to a more balanced
interesting and attract the curiosity of the reader. organizational science that is both interesting
But the interestingness comes about from and robust. The time for reform is ripe because
describing a problematic state that demands the organizational sciences have an opportunity
explanation—for example, why is it that some to influence policy and practice in ways that we
studies find that network centrality is positively could not do in the past (Hambrick, 1994).
correlated with leadership success and others Books based on scholarship in the organiza-
find that it is negatively related to leadership tional and other social sciences are becoming
success? Mutually contradicting facts are an bestsellers; a perusal of the New York Times
example of interesting problems that demand best-seller list for business books has Kahne-
explanation as are facts that contradict theories. man’s (2011) Thinking Fast and Slow at Num-
Interesting theories are not, by themselves, ber 3 and Chip and Dan Heath’s (2010) book
worthy of investigation unless they are put to the Switch at Number 13. However, this influence
service of explaining research problems. is predicated on a robust body of knowledge
We think that Davis’s (1971) recognition of and our view is that the focus on the interesting
the distinction between interesting and truth— is preventing us from developing a replicable
he says (p. 343), ‘‘I believe it is as important to knowledge that can inform practice.
learn why a theory is found interesting in some The persistent emphasis on the interesting is
audience as it is to ascertain the truth of its troublesome because research designed to

Downloaded from opr.sagepub.com at WASHBURN UNIV on January 13, 2015


190 Organizational Psychology Review 3(2)

uncover counterintuitive results is sure to find we arrive at the particular facts from which our
some (Nickerson, 1998). Without efforts to also previous induction had started.
examine the replicability of these results and How many of the empirical observations and
their connections to theory, a distorted view of theoretical propositions in the organizational
reality emerges that yields an absurd view of the sciences attempt to build towards this ideal?
world rather than usable guidance from thought Not many. And a lot fewer with the current
and practice. In fact, if the social world was focus on novelty and interestingness. As Ferris
primarily counterintuitive, it would be an unin- et al., (2012) noted, the quest for revelatory
habitable place in which people would have theoretical contributions has led to fragmenta-
difficulty predicting what comes next. Surely, tion. Theories that are fundamentally different
this is not the case—people are not in a from one another cannot logically exist in the
permanent state of being puzzled by their same hierarchy. How would you judge the
counterintuitive surroundings. significance of a theory if it is not being used
(along with other theories) to formulate a more
general theory? How would you also judge the
The scientific method validity of a theory if journals and editors ask
Bertrand Russell’s (1931) summary of the for new theory in every paper rather than mul-
scientific ideal is familiar to most readers of this tiple tests of a theory?
journal.1 But it bears repeating. Science, he says, Similarly, the quest for novelty and inter-
starts from an observation of the particular, but is estingness of facts has infused them with sig-
concerned essentially with the general. Empiri- nificance without any regard to the knowledge
cal observation, no matter how interesting, is that they generate. Counterintuitive empirical
significant only to the extent that it helps to findings are valued because they are counter-
establish or refute some general law. Thus, the intuitive rather than because they advance or
significance of any observed fact is relative to validate a theoretical perspective. Also, they
knowledge, and the validity of any law depends cannot be verified because our journals do not
on the strength of the empirical evidence. publish independent replications. And finally,
According to Russell (1931), the ultimate their significance cannot be established as the
ideal of science is to have a set of propositions significance of the theoretical perspective they
arranged in a hierarchy, with the lowest level of advance can also not be verified as we already
the hierarchy being concerned with particular noted.
facts, and the highest with some general law. We would like to note that not all counter-
The hierarchy is connected in upwards by intuitive facts are without basis or usefulness in
induction and downwards by deduction. Spe- the social sciences. Quite the contrary! Some of
cifically, if facts, A, B, C, D, etc suggest, via the best-known theories in the organizational
induction, a certain general law, then they are all sciences and psychology have resulted from
seen as specific instances of the general law if examining counterintuitive facts. We examine
the law was true. Similarly, another set of facts two of them in the next section and then explain
suggests, via induction, another general law, and how current views towards counterintuitive
so on. All these general laws suggest, by facts differ from the earlier research and why
induction, a law of a higher order of generality. this approach is leading us to a dead end.
Now these laws are all instances of the more
general law. There will be many such stages in
passing from the particular facts observed to the
The role of counterintuitive facts
most general law as yet ascertained. From this Research in the organizational sciences has
general law we proceed in turn deductively, until resulted in a few stylized facts that inform

Downloaded from opr.sagepub.com at WASHBURN UNIV on January 13, 2015


Pillutla and Thau 191

further research and practices. The idea that landing was imminent. In their book, When
individuals escalate commitment to a failing Prophecy Fails, Festinger, Riecken, and
course of action is one of the better known such Schachter (1956) document how the believers
facts. Barry Staw’s (1976) classic paper on this met at a predetermined place and time, believ-
idea provides an outstanding example of how an ing they alone would survive the earth’s
examination of the counterintuitive resulted in destruction. When the appointed time came and
the formulation of a general model of investment passed without incident, rather than losing faith
behavior. Based on his observation that public in the prophecy, most chose to believe that the
failures in a policy (e.g., the U.S. involvement in aliens had given earth a second chance. Group
Vietnam) appear to create pressure on the deci- members now thought that the group was
sion maker to justify their original decision, empowered to spread the word that earth-
Staw hypothesized and designed a study to spoiling must stop. Festinger and his colleagues
investigate the proposition that failures create a concluded that when faced with acute cognitive
larger impetus for further investment than suc- dissonance (Had they been gullible simpletons?
cess. The results and the paper have had a lasting Had they given up their worldly ties and posses-
impact on the way we view investment decisions sions in vain?), most individuals simply
by managers and by organizations. They have changed the meaning of the current set of cir-
also spawned an entire field of enquiry as evi- cumstances and viewed the world failing to end
denced by the many academic studies across as a sign to reaffirm their faith.
different domains that followed from and built Cognitive dissonance theory, which explains
on this paper. What accounts for this success? this and other similar counterintuitive facts, has
First, the phenomenon was an interesting one been a very successful one in social psychology.
and worthy of understanding in its own right. Why is this theory so successful? First, despite
Understanding when people are likely to invest being based on counterintuitive findings, the
(time, money, and effort) in situations—when theory itself is very intuitive as it posits that
people increase investment in a decision despite individuals seek consonance between their
new evidence suggesting that the current cost of expectations and reality and that when dis-
continuing the decision outweighs the expected sonance occurs, they do one of three things, (a)
benefit—is of great practical importance. Sec- lower the importance of one of the discordant
ond, many empirical studies that followed the factors, (b) add consonant elements, or (c)
Staw study replicated the main findings and change one of the dissonant factors. Second, the
extended them; journals and editors clearly theory explains several otherwise puzzling and
provided more leeway for replication than seems seemingly irrational behaviors. And, finally, the
to be the case now. And third, the theoretical theory could explain a broad range of behaviors
explanation for this phenomenon was a special ranging from reactions to unfair treatment at
case of the well-established cognitive dissonance work (cf. Adams, 1965) to escalation of com-
model. mitment to failing courses of action.
This brings us to cognitive dissonance the- The cognitive dissonance example suggests
ory which is responsible for explaining some of that the examination of counterintuitive cases
the most interesting findings in social highlights factors that exist beyond the normal
psychology. According to most accounts, the range. They therefore help magnify and make
theory has its origins in Festinger’s attempts to clear the facts that account for particular
explain the slightly bizarre set of circumstances outcomes. Pondy (1979) provides a similar
surrounding a doomsday cult members’ dee- argument for the study of extreme cases.
pening (rather than diminishing) faith following The two examples provided before point to
the failure of a cult’s prophecy that a UFO two different ways in which an examination of

Downloaded from opr.sagepub.com at WASHBURN UNIV on January 13, 2015


192 Organizational Psychology Review 3(2)

the counterintuitive can lead to robust scientific ends. It results in an organizational science that
knowledge. In the case of cognitive dissonance, is fragmented. Worse, it makes it irrelevant.
counterintuitive observations resulted in testing As we have argued throughout this essay, the
a robust theory that could explain many other current trend towards ‘‘interesting’’ theories
important facts. In the case of escalation of and counterintuitive facts does not allow for
commitment, an examination of the counter- progress or for relevance. So what does? We
intuitive provided a robust understanding of the think that Popper’s (1935) view that problem-
phenomenon which was interesting in its own solving is at the heart of the scientific enterprise
right. However, in both cases, robust knowl- provides the best way forward.
edge resulted from replication and refine-
ment—an option that is increasingly not
available in journals focusing on novelty and Towards a problem-centred
interestingness. organizational science
For a relevant organizational science that is also
scientifically rigorous, the problem should
Consequences of the focus on the come first, then the theory. The theory itself
interesting may be dull or old, but as long as the problem is
one that is unsolved and of interest, it is
As we have argued, one of the consequences demanding theory that explains it. The problem
of our current focus on the counterintuitive itself may come in one of three forms:2
along with a reluctance to publish replications
is the increased fragmentation of our discipline. Two observed facts contradict each other
Another consequence is unreliable data. (e.g., people like high performers but peo-
Researchers could fake and fabricate data as ple also dislike high performers). A theory
there is a bias towards novelty and there is no which explains both facts, even if very
check that comes with a need to replicate. It is old, is a valuable one and a paper that
not just faked data that is a problem. A disci- examines it is a contribution.
pline that does not encourage replication and A well-established theory is contradicted by
instead values the novel and the interesting a fact (e.g., the theory that people dislike
invites ambitious academics to publish inter- high performers because they threaten
esting one-off findings without any concern their self-esteem is contradicted by the
about scrutiny (cf. Rosenthal, 1979, on the bias fact that people with high self-esteem also
towards publishing significant results). dislike high performers). The fact identi-
A final consequence is that we are at risk of fied here is a significant one in Russell’s
developing an absurd ‘‘science’’ of the coun- (1931) terms because it contributes to
terintuitive. Most of the behavior in the world is knowledge (in this case, providing some
intuitive and is still deserving of explanation evidence that the theory is bounded or
and testing. By focusing on the counter- even wrong).
intuitive, we fail to pay attention to a majority Two theories that explain the same fact con-
of behavior. If the counterintuitive behavior tradict each other in their assumptions.
was important (as in the case of escalation of (Theory A and Theory B both explain why
commitment) or used to test the robustness of a people dislike high performers but Theory
theory (as with cognitive dissonance), then we A assumes it is because high performance
are all for examining it. However, the current threatens people’s self-esteem and Theory
obsession with searching for counterintuitive B assumes it is because people are
findings does not appear to serve either of these envious.) This is a colloquial restatement

Downloaded from opr.sagepub.com at WASHBURN UNIV on January 13, 2015


Pillutla and Thau 193

of the proposition that the examination of sciences: How will we know it when we see
alternative explanations with a view it? Organizational Psychology Review, 2(1),
towards provisionally accepting the valid- 94–106.
ity of one over the other is good science. Festinger, L., Riecken, H. W., & Schachter, S.
(1956). When prophecy fails. Minneapolis:
The kinds of problems we describe before are University of Minnesota Press.
clearly worth studying. They are likely to be Gill, G., & Bhattacherjee, A. (2009). Fashion versus
important and generative as was the case with informing: Response to Baskerville and Myers.
the escalation research that we described in an MIS Quarterly, 33(4), 667–671.
earlier section. Research that puts the problem Hambrick, D. (1994). What if the academy actually
first is scientific. Such research is likely to be mattered? Academy of Management Review,
interesting and scholars who examine problems 19(1), 11–16.
are likely to have an impact. Heath, C., & Heath, D. (2010). Switch: How to
change when change is hard. New York: Broad-
Notes way Books.
1. Other respected philosophers of science, Karl Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking, fast and slow. Lon-
Popper is the most notable, have made similar don, UK: Penguin Books.
observations. Markoczy, L., & Deeds, D. L. (2009). Theory build-
2. We thank Wout Ultee and Rafael Wittek for the ing at the intersection: Recipe for impact or road
view that the best research problems are to nowhere? Journal of Management Studies,
contradictions. 46(6), 1076–1088.
Nickerson, R. S. (1998). Confirmation bias: A
References ubiquitous phenomenon in many guises. Review
Adams, J. S. (1965). Inequity in social exchange. of General Psychology, 2, 175–220.
Advances in Experimental Social. Psychology, Pearce, J. L. (2007). Organizational behavior
62, 335–343. unchained: Commentary on giving peace a
Ahlstrom, D. (2011). Clearing the first hurdle at the chance. Journal of Organizational Behavior,
Asia Pacific Journal of Management. Asia Pacific 28(8), 1097–1100.
Journal of Management, 27(2), 171–177. Pondy, L. R. (1979). Theories of extreme cases.
Colquitt, J. A., & George, G. (2011). Publishing in Working paper, College of Commerce, Univer-
AMJ – Part I – Topic choice. Academy of sity of Illinois, Urbana-Champaign.
Management Journal, 54(3), 432–435. Popper, K. (1935). Logik der Forschung (Logic of
Daft, R. L., & Lewin, A. Y. (1990). Can organization scientific discovery). Vienna, Austria: Springer.
studies begin to break out of the normal science Reay, T., & Whetten, D. A. (2011). What constitutes
straitjacket? An editorial essay Organization Sci- a theoretical contribution in family business?
ence,. 1(1), 1–9. Family Business Review, 24(2), 105–110.
Davis, M. S. (1971). That’s interesting! Toward a Rosenthal, R. (1979). The file drawer problem and
phenomenology of sociology and a sociology of tolerance for null results. Psychological Bulletin,
phenomenology. Philosophy and Social Science, 86(3), 638–641.
1, 309–344. Russell, B. (1931). The scientific outlook. London,
Eden, D., & Rynes, S. (2003). Publishing across UK: George Allen & Unwin.
borders: Furthering the internationalization of Schwarz, G. M., & Huber, G. P. (2008). Challenging
AMJ. Academy of Management Journal, 46(6), organizational change research. British Journal of
679–783. Management, 19(S1), S1–S6.
Ferris, G. R., Hochwarter, W. A., & Buckley, M. Short, J. (2009). The art of writing a review article.
R. (2012). Theory in the organizational Journal of Management, 35(6), 1312–1317.

Downloaded from opr.sagepub.com at WASHBURN UNIV on January 13, 2015


194 Organizational Psychology Review 3(2)

Staw, B. M. (1976). Knee-deep in the big muddy: A Columbia. His research focuses on norm viola-
study of escalating commitment to a chosen tions, reciprocity, trust, and self-regulation.
course of action. Organizational Behavior and
Human Performance, 16(1), 27–44.
Stefan Thau is an Associate Professor of Orga-
nizational Behavior at London Business
Author biographies
School. He received his PhD from the Univer-
Madan M. Pillutla is a Professor of Organiza- sity of Groningen. His research focuses on
tional Behavior at London Business School. He norm violations, reciprocity, trust, and
received his PhD from the University of British self-regulation.

Downloaded from opr.sagepub.com at WASHBURN UNIV on January 13, 2015

You might also like