You are on page 1of 17

Conceptualizing Culture: Possibilities for Political Science

Author(s): Lisa Wedeen


Source: The American Political Science Review, Vol. 96, No. 4 (Dec., 2002), pp. 713-728
Published by: American Political Science Association
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3117506 .
Accessed: 13/02/2015 11:51

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

American Political Science Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to
The American Political Science Review.

http://www.jstor.org

This content downloaded from 128.235.251.160 on Fri, 13 Feb 2015 11:51:52 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
American Political Science Review Vol. 96, No. 4 December 2002

ConceptualizingCulture: Possibilities for Political Science


LISA WEDEEN University of Chicago
is essay makes a case for an anthropological conceptualization of culture as "semioticpractices"
and demonstrateshow it adds value to political analyses. "Semioticpractices" refersto theprocesses
of meaning-making in which agents' practices (e.g., their work habits, self-policing strategies,and
leisure patterns) interact with their language and other symbolic systems. This version of culture can be
employed on two levels. First, it refers to what symbols do-how symbols are inscribed in practices that
operate to produce observable political effects. Second, "culture"is an abstract theoretical category, a lens
thatfocuses on meaning, ratherthan on, say,prices or votes. By thinking of meaning construction in terms
that emphasize intelligibility, as opposed to deep-seated psychological orientations, a practice-oriented
approach avoids unacknowledged ambiguities that have bedeviled scholarly thinking and generated
incommensurable understandings of what culture is. Through a brief exploration of two concerns central
to political science-compliance and ethnic identity-formation-this paper ends by showing how culture
as semiotic practices can be applied as a causal variable.

n epistemologiesrangingfrom literarystudies to in the West,these studiesattemptedto show how cul-


rationalchoice theory,issues broadlyconstruedas tural attitudesand beliefs either hinderedor enabled
"cultural"have been animatingacademicdebates, "progress"(Banfield1958;McClelland1961,1963;Pye
encouraginginterdisciplinaryexchanges,and inspiring 1965).Conceivedin termsof an alleged set of residual
battlesover the methods,evidence,and goals of schol- valuesandnorms-what SherryOrtner(1997,8-9) has
arlyresearch.'In this essay,I offer a criticalanalysisof aptly characterizedas "a deeply sedimented essence
the problemsinvolvedin currentusagesof the term in attaching to, or inhering in particulargroups"-this
politicalscience,make the case for a conceptualization notion of culture was prominentin the sociology of
of culture as semiotic practices,and show why it has Talcott Parsons (1949, 1951, 1965) in modernization
value for, and how it might be employed by, political theory,and in the Americanculturalanthropologyof
scientists. Franz Boas (1986, 1911), MargaretMead, and Ruth
In politicalscience,the conceptof cultureused to be Benedict ([1934] 1989), as well as in the behaviorist
associatedprimarilywiththe literatureon politicalcul- revolutionof the 1950sand 1960s.In politicalscience,
turethatemergedin the contextof postwarpoliticalso- it was Gabriel Almond's (1956) seminal essay, along
ciology,withits interestin policyinitiativesintendedto with his subsequentcollaborationwith Sidney Verba
reproducethe conditionsof Westerndemocratization (1963),thatproducedone of the mostinfluentialunder-
abroad(Somers1995,114).DerivedfromMaxWeber's standingsof politicalculturein terms of "orientations
([1905] 1958) classic analysisof the "electiveaffinity" toward the political system,"whereby some popula-
between the Protestantethic and the rise of capitalism tions had civic "cultures"and othersdid not.2 Samuel
Huntington's1993articlein ForeignAffairs,"TheClash
of Civilizations?"andhissubsequentbook TheClashof
Lisa Wedeen is Assistant Professor of Political Science, Univer- Civilizationsand the Remakingof WorldOrder(1996)
sity of Chicago, 5828 South University Avenue, Chicago, IL 60637 markperhapsthe mostprominentandpolemicalrecent
(l-wedeen@uchicago.edu).
The author wishes to acknowledge the valuable comments re- exampleof this kindof politicalculturalismin political
ceived on this paper from colleagues, students, friends, and compan- science.
ions. In particular, I would like to thank Nadia Abu El-Haj, Carles Politicalculture accounts,with their tendencies to-
Boix, Matthew Cleary, John Comaroff, Yasmin A. Dawood, Michael wardculturalessentialism,haverightlycomein for crit-
Dawson, Sujatha Fernandes, Andreas Glaeser, Deborah Gould, icismby manypoliticalscientists.Rejectingsuch views
Stathis Kalyvas, Mathew Kocher, David D. Laitin, Adria Lawrence,
Doowan Lee, Patchen Markell, Jennifer Mitzen, Anne Norton, as either fundamentallytautologicalor empiricallyin-
Hanna Pitkin, Don Reneau, Martin Riesebrodt, Jennifer Rubenstein, valid,somecriticshaveoptedfor one or anotherstrictly
Danilyn Rutherford, James C. Scott, William H. Sewell, Jr., Ronald "materialist"approach,objectingto the consideration
Suny, Evalyn Tennant, Jeffrey Tulis, Robert Vitalis, and Alexander of culturalvariablesin any form (see, e.g., Hirschman
Wendt. I am also grateful to Michael Chwe for providing me with a
copy of his manuscript. Previous versions of this essay were presented 1984, Jackmanand Miller 1996, and Tilly, 1975, 603-
to audiences at the University of Chicago's Comparative Politics 21).3 The ascendanceof methodologicalindividualism
Workshop, the Wilder House Center for the Study of Politics, History,
and Culture, and the American Political Science Association's annual
2 This
meeting (summer 2000). This essay is dedicated to the memory of summary of the political culture school admittedly simplifies a
Michael P Rogin. complex group of approaches. In political science, the "classic" study
1 Kroeber and Kluckhohn's (1952) historical overview of the chang- was Gabriel A. Almond and Sidney Verba's (1963) The Civic Culture:
ing meanings of the word "culture" in German, French, and English Political Attitudes and Democracy in Five Nations. See also Pye 1965,
estimated that there were over 160 definitions in use in the 1950s 512-60. For one of the most recent influential books in this genre,
(Brownstein 1995, 313; Steinmetz 1999, 5). Raymond Williams (1983, see Putnam, Leonard, and Nanetti 1993. For an insightful extension
90) limited his analysis to four main ordinary and academic uses, but of Putnam's concept of "social capital," see Boix and Posner 1996.
he also observed that culture was "one of the two or three most com- 3 Middle East studies is one field in which the concept has been espe-
plicated words in the English language" (Sewell 1999, 39; Steinmetz cially charged. I have in mind scholars such as Lisa Anderson, Kiren
1999, 5). Aziz Chaudhry, and Michael Hudson, all of whom use "culture" to

713

This content downloaded from 128.235.251.160 on Fri, 13 Feb 2015 11:51:52 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
ConceptualizingCulture December 2002

and rational choice theory in the mid-1980s also led refers to what language and symbols do-how they are
practitioners to argue that the analysis of group val- inscribed in concrete actions and how they operate to
ues or customs such as those associated with the term produce observable political effects. In this sense, cul-
culture was irrelevant to political inquiry (Przeworski ture can be used as a causal or explanatory variable.
1985). Politics concerned material interests and the rel- At the same time, insofar as semiotic practices are also
ative success or failure of the individuals articulating the effects of institutional arrangements, of structures
them. Symbolic displays and rhetorical practices were of domination, and of strategic interests, activities of
epiphenomenal. meaning-making can also be studied as effects or de-
Although individual rational choice theorists have pendent variables. Second, culture as semiotic practices
often been at pains to reject culturalist arguments as is also a lens. It offers a view of political phenomena
tautological, untestable, or beside the point, faced with by focusing attention on how and why actors invest
explaining postcommunist upheavals, ethnic violence, them with meaning. While every activity has a semiotic
"identity" politics, religious "fundamentalism,"and the component, the point here is not to assert that poli-
ongoing problems of democratic transitions, others tics must be examined from a semiotic-practical point
have resorted to culture as a "fallback" position, a way of view. Whether one does or does not explore pro-
of accounting for divergent and often disappointing cesses of meaning-making will be determined by the
political outcomes (Kuper 1999, 10). By claiming that particular research problem one confronts. At issue
"cultures" have "peculiarities" that explain the failure are approaches to political phenomena that do seek
of those nation-states to democratize, or by asserting to encompass cultural considerations. Unlike current
that political conflict is the outcome of "irreducible cul- invocations of culture in political science, in an em-
tural differences" (Bates et al. 1998; Greif 1994, 912-50; pirically grounded, practice-oriented approach to cul-
Rogowski 1997, 14), these theorists have responded to ture, meanings are understood to exist inside historical
genuine explanatory needs by reviving an outmoded processes, which themselves are always enmeshed in
and unhelpful understanding of the concept. A con- changing relations of power (Asad 1993, 43).
cept of culture defined from the perspective of political A practice-oriented cultural approach can help us ex-
science, but informed by the debates in critical anthro- plain how political identifications are established; how
pology, would require changes in the ways the term is rhetoric and symbols not only exemplify but also can
applied and in how political phenomena are analyzed produce political compliance; why some political ide-
and explained.4 ologies, policies, and self-policing strategies work better
The purpose of this essay is to show how a critical un- than others; what terms such as "democracy" (Schaffer,
derstanding of culture as practices of meaning-making 1998) and "religion" mean to political actors who in-
facilitates insights about politics, enabling political sci- voke or consume them and how these perceptions
entists to produce sophisticated causal arguments and might affect political outcomes; and why particular ma-
to treat forms of evidence that, while manifestly po- terial and status interests are taken for granted, are
litical, most political science approaches tend to over- viewed as valuable, or become available idioms for dis-
look. Studying meaning-production entails analyzing semination and collective action. By paying attention
the relations between agents' practices (e.g., their work to the ways in which certain meanings become author-
habits, gendered norms, self-policing strategies, and itative while others do not, political scientists can use
leisure patterns) and systems of signification (language this practice-oriented concept of culture to help explain
and other symbolic systems) (Sewell 1999; see also why recognizable events or empirical regularities oc-
Ortner 1997). The words "semiotic practices" are short- cur. At a minimum, studying culture by identifying rel-
hand for this approach. This conceptualization oper- evant semiotic practices has added value to the extent
ates on two levels. First, culture as semiotic practices that it allows for nuanced, valid understandings of pol-
itics that are capable of undermining previous beliefs
mean identifiable essences or sedimented values inhering in particu- and affecting our prior assumptions about the world.5
lar groups. Chaudhry (1994), in particular, tends to confuse Samuel This article is divided into two parts. In Part One,
Huntington's invocations of the term with any interest in "culture" I examine the shared problems and epistemological
or cultural studies. See also Anderson 1995, 77-92, and Hudson 1995,
61-76. disagreements that have hobbled debates about cul-
4 Two political scientists who do follow debates in critical anthro- ture among political scientists of various orientations.
pology and consider everyday practices and systems of signification Without overlooking what may be irreconcilable dif-
in their work are James C. Scott (1985, 1990) and Timothy Mitchell
(1988). To my knowledge, neither has theorized culture explicitly,
ferences, I suggest possibilities for fruitful collabora-
however, nor have they focused on the conceptual conundrums posed tion. In Part Two, I begin by discussing what practices
by the term. A recent book attempting to bring anthropologists
working on the "culturally specific" into conversation with rational
choice theorists in political science was designed to debate the nature 5 By "valid" I mean-as Bowen and Petersen (1999, 12) write-
and importance of comparison. Although the encounter may have "the degree to which the account of something picks up processes,
enabled participants to share "a sense that the world's complexity ideas, or relationships that are indeed there in the world. Insisting
demands some respect," the engagement did not (nor was it intended on 'validity' does not imply a correspondence theory of truth (that
to) produce clear understandings of what "culture" means (Bowen a true description maps one-to-one onto the world), but only that
and Petersen 1999, 2). Indeed anthropologists associated with the some descriptions are better than others, and that the kinds of things
project unwittingly reproduced some of the confusions I identify in anthropologists do when in the field -checking with many people, lis-
Part One. For debates about the culture concept in anthropology and tening in on discussions, and living through events-are particularly
elsewhere, see Bonnell and Hunt 1999, Clifford 1988, Clifford and good ways to arrive at a good description." I would argue that good
Marcus 1986, Fabian 1983, Gupta and Ferguson 1997. descriptions help to ensure accurate explanations of political life.

714

This content downloaded from 128.235.251.160 on Fri, 13 Feb 2015 11:51:52 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
American Political Science Review Vol. 96, No. 4

of meaning-making are and how we should go about values. As a result, cultural essentialist explanations of
studying them. I propose an account of meaning based political outcomes such as ethnic or religious violence
on intelligibility and then examine concrete method- tend to naturalize categories of groupness, rather than
ological strategies for how a version of culture as exploring the conditions under which such experiences
semiotic practices might be applied as an explanatory of groupness come to seem natural when they do.
or independent variable in political analyses. Through a Some practitioners of rational choice theory use cul-
brief exploration of two concerns central to current re- ture similarly to refer to an already-given community
search about politics-compliance and ethnic identity- that can be studied by listing its fixed shared beliefs or
formation-I show how culture can operate as a causal values. The APSA-Comparative Politics Newsletter of
variable, as well as a corrective to prevailing assump- summer 1997 (see "Notes from the Annual Meetings:
tions about political life. Culture and Rational Choice." 1997), which features
summaries from a roundtable debate entitled "Can the
Rational Choice Framework Cope with Culture?" as
PARTONE: "CULTURE"IN POLITICAL well as solicited contributions, provides a case in point,
SCIENCE exemplifying the conceptual confusions and empirical
problems in current formulations of culture. On the one
Culture Concepts hand, scholars contributing to the Newsletter and those
invoked within its pages have various understandings
Declaring the onset of "a new phase in global his- of culture and how it works-as common knowledge
tory," Samuel Huntington defines "the fundamental (Chwe 2001), as symbolic action (Johnson 1997), as "be-
sources of conflict" in the current world, not as eco- liefs off the equilibrium path behavior" (Greif 1994),
nomic or ideological in nature, but as "cultural." For as pertaining "directly to the production of preference
Huntington, each civilization has a primordial cultural orderings" (Lustick 1997), and as "a socially shared and
identity, so that the "major differences in political and logically interrelated set of symbols, codes, and norms"
economic development among civilizations are clearly (Rogowski 1997 and Lustick 1997). "Culture" is used
rooted in their different cultures." He warns, "Culture in these examples as an analytic concept, which, as
and cultural identities.., .are shaping the patterns of William H. Sewell, Jr. (1999, 39), points out, is usu-
cohesion, disintegration, and conflict in the post-Cold ally "contrasted to some other equally abstract aspect
War world.... The rivalry of the superpowers is re- or category of social life that is not culture, such as
placed by the clash of civilizations" (Huntington 1993, economy, politics or biology." On the other hand, these
22; 1996, 20, 28, 29). For Huntington, "culture" refers same scholars invoke "culture," as Huntington would,
to the purported enduring values harbored by "highly to denote the beliefs, values, and customs of a specified
integrated civilizations"-also sometimes confusingly group. Despite Rogowski's dismissal of the tautological
termed "cultures." arguments of "political culture" theorists, for example,
This understanding of culture as a specific group's he nonetheless takes for granted the existence of "re-
primordial values or traits is untenable empirically. It spective cultures" with possible "culturalpeculiarities"
ignores the historical conditions and relevant power and "irreducible differences," so that "culture" refers
relationships that give rise to political phenomena such both to a "socially shared and logically interrelated set
as "democratization," ethnic conflicts, and contempo- of symbols, codes, and norms" and to a particular com-
rary radical Islamicist movements. The group traits ver- munity, such as "Catholic culture" (Rogowski 1997,14).
sion of culture, moreover, rides roughshod over the Similarly,James Johnson's (1997, 9) knowledgeable ac-
diversity of views and the experiences of contention count of "culture" as a symbolic system or as symbolic
within the group or groups under study. In the case action is sometimes confused with "cultures"-the plu-
of Huntington's depiction of the Middle East, for ex- ral, concrete, highly integrated worlds within which
ample, such claims of sedimented essences have led symbolic systems (cultures) operate.
scholars of culture to pass over such now obviously ur- Despite the multiple understandings of the cul-
gent matters as the contemporary nature of Islamicist ture concept, all of these formulations share prob-
movements, the causes of their recent emergence, and lems that can be traced at least in part, to political
the ways in which communities of argument exist over scientists' heavy reliance on Clifford Geertz (whose
what makes a Muslim a Muslim, what Islam means, and own understandings of the term were influenced by his
what, if any, its political role should be. Treating culture teacher, Talcott Parsons, and by Max Weber).6 Geertz's
as a set of traits that purportedly distinguish one group
from another also neglects the terrains of solidarity and
6
fluidity that exist among groups, the ways in which po- I have in mind Geertz's Interpretation of Cultures: Selected Essays
litical communities of various sorts have depended on (1973); Local Knowledge: Further Essays in InterpretiveAnthropol-
the cross-fertilization of ideas and practices. In short, ogy; and his important case study, Negara: the TheaterState (1980). In
Gary King, Robert O. Keohane, and Sidney Verba's (1994) influen-
by ignoring historical processes and specific relations tial political science handbook Designing Social Inquiry, the authors
of political power, the treatment of culture in politi- rely on one essay by Geertz, "Thick Description," to discuss culture
cal science has downplayed the heterogeneous ways in (pp. 37, 38-40). Abner Cohen's (1974) Two-Dimensional Man: An
which people experience the social order within and Essay on the Anthropology of Power and Symbolism in a Complex
Society-a rational choice analysis of the strategic manipulation of
among groups, while exaggerating the commonality, symbols-was also important to rational choice students of culture
constancy, and permanence of intragroup beliefs and (Johnson 1997; Laitin 1986, 1998, 1999).

715

This content downloaded from 128.235.251.160 on Fri, 13 Feb 2015 11:51:52 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
ConceptualizingCulture December 2002

definition of a "system of symbols" was one that insisted (1986, 16) Geertz's "thick descriptions" of systems of
upon coherence-on a reified, frozen system of mean- signification were "methodologically useful" because
ing, rather than on what symbols do. When he studied they registered "the deeply held values of a cultural
Bali, for example, he looked for a closed and already group." For Laitin (1986, 16),
configured set of meanings and, thus, was blind to the
processes by which ongoing practices and systems of The databaseconsistsin symbolicstructures.Only with a
meaning change, are sites of political struggle, and gen- keen understandingof the meaningsembeddedin shared
erate multiple significations within social groups. Thus symbols..,.can one adduce culturalpreferenceswithout
Geertz could invoke the same word "culture" to con- tautologicallyclaimingthat preferencescan be derived
fromthe behaviorof actorswhoareassumedto be rational.
note both a fixed, synchronic entity, such as Balinese
"culture,"and the performances through which the re- Geertz invited political scientists such as Laitin to
searcher interprets meanings, such as cockfights, teeth
pay attention to culture as a system of symbols from
filing rituals, state pageants, and funeral rites. The dual which researchers could read meaning, but political
connotations of culture as an already given community scientists thereby adopted many of the problems of the
and as a symbolic system were often made analytically Geertzian concept of culture: that the system was rei-
compatible in Geertz's work by the suggestion that the fied and fixed, that it was identifiable as bounded, and
tight integration of a particular, bounded culture was that meanings were always already set in a given "text."
determined by its semiotic coherence as a system of
Thus in Laitin's reading of Geertz, culture refers both
meanings. The insistence on semiotic coherence led to "systems of symbols" and to the "deeply held val-
Geertz to ignore possible discrepancies between the ues of a cultural group" (emphasis mine). This slippage
representation of events, conditions, and people and could remain unacknowledged because, for Laitin, as
the ways in which such representations were received, for Geertz, to refer to culture as a system of symbols
negotiated, and subjected to risks by those who pro- was to claim that culture was a contained system of
duced and consumed them (Wedeen 1999). People's
own divergent interpretations of what a particular rit- "deeply held" values and beliefs. Of course Laitin's
insistence that "thick descriptions" could be treated
ual or practice meant were of little significance. Analy- as a "database" may seem odd, given Geertz's philo-
ses of meaning-making focused on an already given,
sophical insistence on ethnography as an enterprise
consensually understood "cultural schema" continu- mediated through the anthropologist's creative inter-
ally performed by actors of particular "cultures" who pretation. Geertz's own penchant for treating a par-
were seemingly unaffected by historical changes. For ticular practice, such as the Balinese cockfight, as
Geertz, power and processes of meaning-making be- synecdochic for Balinese culture made him a partic-
came purely symbolic, as did culture and analyses of
ularly blatant and, in many ways, self-professed medi-
it.7 In his "significative system" there is no agency, only ator. In short, political scientists beholden to Geertz
an intelligible, seamlessly coherent script or master nar-
rative that actors follow in particular "cultures."Such improved over the political culture literatures of old
theorizations of culture also led Geertz to sample on the by producing theoretically motivated work that em-
phasized the importance of symbols and took ethno-
dependent variable, selecting symbols and meanings graphic evidence seriously. However, Geertzians of
that were particularly prone to coherence or system- various stripes unwittingly conflated various uses of cul-
aticity (Sewell 1999: 47). ture in their analyses, thereby perpetuating confusions
Despite these problems, Geertz's (1973) enormously and compromising the term's explanatory purchase by
influential book, The Interpretation of Cultures, gave
some political scientists a compelling reason to take insisting on the semiotic coherence of a particular com-
munity, system of symbols, or "culture." Culture be-
symbols seriously. As David Laitin (1986, 12) argued, came not only what a group has-beliefs, values, or
"Symbols are important because they provide to indi- a symbolic system-but what a group is (a Balinese
viduals a sense of meaning. For Geertz, these symbols
culture). More importantly, theories of culture tended
or, better, the various systems of symbols constitute to render historicized analyses of practice and process
'culture."' Geertz's refusal to produce falsifiable argu-
ments was at odds with the positivist project of rational impossible or irrelevant, explaining political outcomes
as the result of empirically untenable, untestable as-
choice theory, but his attention to meaning allowed po- sertions of uniformity and fixity. Most political scien-
litical scientists such as Laitin to discover "the nature tists continue to think of culture as connoting fixed
of group values" (Laitin 1986, 16). According to Laitin group traits.

7 Some critics of Geertz charge that he has no understanding of, or


interest in, power relations, but this seems unfair. As Geertz (1980, Real Differences: The Individualist
120) suggests in his study of political spectacles in nineteenth century Orientation as an Example
Bali, "The pageants were not mere aesthetic embellishments, cele-
brations of a domination independently existing: they were the thing Despite shared problems in formulations of the con-
itself." Moreover, in his famous essay "Thick Description," Geertz
claims (1983) that his "interpretive approach," unlike the structural- cept, divergent political, methodological, and episte-
ism he opposes, is going to take into account considerations of power mological commitments also divide political scientists
and history. His ethnographic work, however, does not execute this and are responsible for treatments of culture being less
intention. robust than they otherwise might be. One commonly

716

This content downloaded from 128.235.251.160 on Fri, 13 Feb 2015 11:51:52 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
American Political Science Review Vol. 96, No. 4

cited rift is betweenrationalchoice theoristsandinter- nal choice and agent-basedanalyses.8Dissatisfaction


pretive social scientists(on interpretivesocial science, with the externalizationof preferencesin neoclassical
see Rabinow and Sullivan 1987). Although I do not economicshas encourageda focus in politicalscience
intend to reify this distinction,different assumptions, on preferenceformation,includingattemptsto make
vocabularies,sourcesof information,and standardsof preferences "endogenous"to the models. This con-
evidence have producedrecognizablecommunitiesof cern has led some rationalchoice theorists to exam-
argument.Unequal access to institutionalpower and ine how politicalidentitiesandpreferencesare formed
to materialresourceshas also created experiencesof (Gerber and Jackson1993;Hardin1995;Laitin 1998).
groupnessthathinderscholarlydiscussion.Formy pur- Yet even in as impressivea study as Laitin's (1998)
poses here, one key differenceis the importancethe Identityin Formation:The Russian-SpeakingPopula-
individualplaysin analysesof politicallife. tions in the NearAbroad,the phenomenonof identity
In rationalchoicetheory-as in the behavioristpolit- is ultimatelyreducedto a strategicchoicein whichindi-
ical cultureliterature-the individualis the privileged vidualactorscalculatewhetherto switchfromRussian
unit of analysis,even if individualresponsesare subse- to the titularlanguageon the basis of what they think
quentlyaggregatedfor statisticalpurposes.As George others will do. These works assumewithout question
Steinmetz(1999, 19) argues,"Thisindividualisticbias that individualscan be adequatelyconceived for pur-
[is] at odds with the point made even by Parsonsthat poses of political science as goal-orientedbeings at-
cultureis not (or not primarily)a propertyof individ- tempting to maximize their interests, given existing
uals."This bias tends to produce argumentsin which constraints(Tsebelis1997,16).Indeed,a "constructed"
ideas, beliefs, or values, such as "nationalpride,"are identity,for Laitin(1998,3-35), is synonymouswith a
often "misleadinglywrenched"from"thesocial condi- strategicallychosenone. Laitin'sethnographicsections
tions in which they [are] embedded and withinwhich are thus devoted to sorting out what his informants
they receive [...] their specific meaning."Similarly, were strategicabout, rather than analyzing"identity
"individualism," as AlexanderWendt(1999, 166, 169) in formation"-how selves are constitutedor how lan-
pointsout, impliesthatpersonsare "independentlyex- guage might actuallyoperate, or not, to generate felt
isting"ratherthan constitutedthroughtheirlinguistic, identifications.
institutional,and practicalrelationswith others. Rationalchoice theoristsin politicalscience may,of
Interpretivist approaches, among which can be course, differ in the degree of rationalitythey accord
counted the importantinnovationof practiceanthro- to agentsor disagreeabouthow to understandequilib-
pology in the 1980s, frequently invoke an agentive rium, but they are likely to share the common belief
individual,but they do not assumea maximizing,cost- among economists that "institutionsand patterns of
benefit calculatorwho is unproblematicallydivorced behaviorcanbe explainedas the productor outcomeof
from actualhistoricalprocesses(e.g., Bourdieu 1978). many individualdecisions"(Young1998,4). Interpre-
The rationalchoice formulationof the decontextual- tivists might questionnot only the view of individuals
ized, universalizableindividual,whose ideas, beliefs, such studiesput forth,but also the degree of power or
and values can be extractedfrom the social and polit- efficacy that individualshave within institutions.The
ical conditionsunderwhichthey were generated,pro- main point to be registeredhere is simplythat insofar
ducesobjectsof inquirythatareincommensurablewith as individualismpresupposesagentswho are forward-
interpretivistsocial science. Of course many rational looking strategists forever calculating costs and
choice theoristsdo analyzethe conditionsunderwhich benefits,there will be a seriousontologicaland episte-
individualsmake choices.The individualistbias, how- mologicaldividebetween most rationalchoice and in-
ever, tends to require that culture be conceptualized terpretivisttheorists.9Interpretivistscan rightlyclaim,
as a "constraint"on individual'sstrategicactions, or in my view, that individualistassumptionspreventra-
"as informationfor equilibriumselection,"or, in the tionalchoicescholarsfromposingquestionsthatareof
plural,as "manifoldequilibria"(Tsebelis1997).An ap- manifestimportanceto politics,not the least of which
proachto cultureas processesof meaning-construction, is how interestsare collectivelygeneratedanddefined,
in contrast,assumesthat actorsunderstandthemselves or how we come to know that people maximizetheir
as individualsand as strategic,and as groupmembers interests,if theydo. Thesedisagreementsareimportant
and nonstrategic, and that such self-understandings ones. It remains to be seen whether further substantive
are always mutually constituted and affirmed by oth- discussion will be worthwhile, but there is no need for
ers. Meaning-making, in short, implies a social process such disagreements to foreclose possibilities of coop-
through which people reproduce together the condi- eration. Nor is there any theoretical warrant, from ei-
tions of intelligibility that enable them to make sense ther side of the epistemological divide, for resisting the
of their worlds-a point to which I return in Part Two.
Such a view of culture restores a manifestly collective
aspect to political analyses that many individualist ac- 8 For a sophisticated consideration of learning and adaptation in
counts lack, without requiring the shared coherence rational choice theory, see (the economist) Young (1998). For a
that many culturalist accounts exaggerate. computational model that attempts to explain how "culture" dis-
seminates, see Axelrod 1997, 148-77.
With innovations in game theory and computational 9 David Laitin (1999) does point out that this understanding of the
modeling, scholars have begun to introduce learn- individual is not necessary from a rational choice perspective, but he
ing, information updating, and adaptation into ratio- does not operationalize another one.

717

This content downloaded from 128.235.251.160 on Fri, 13 Feb 2015 11:51:52 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
ConceptualizingCulture December 2002

introduction into political science of a post-Geertzian is subject to change, or is implicated in political rela-
anthropological conceptualization of culture. tionships of leverage and domination, we can produce
robust explanations of why people coordinate their
FruitfulCollaboration actions when they do, while avoiding erroneous causal
inferences.
The fact that rational choice theory has engaged with To be fair, nothing inherent in the idea of common
studies of culture invites conversation, and possibly
knowledge interferes with asking how that knowledge
productive argument, between methodological individ- is acquired or changed, although little practical work
ualists and interpretivists. Game theorists, in particular, has been done on such matters thus far. To put my
have begun to use culture to connote "common knowl- criticisms in the language of rational choice theory:
edge" in their analyses. "Common knowledge" helps (a) Common knowledge is one of the descriptors of
to solve games in which preferences and capabilities an equilibrium state; (b) "given that the coordination
generate "multiple equilibria"-stable outcomes from dynamics on which common knowledge models oper-
which a rational actor has no incentive to deviate. The ate have multiple equilibria, change to different equi-
idea of common knowledge enables rational choice libria is theoretically possible; (c) the problem is that
theorists to solve these games by identifying "focal
noncooperative game theory hasn't seriously modeled
points around which actors' expectations can con- the move from one coordination equilibrium to an-
verge, thereby limiting transaction costs and enhanc- other. Noncooperative coordination games with multi-
ing the possibilities for coordination under conditions ple equilibria are potentially dynamic," but so far have
of complexity and uncertainty" (Schelling 1960, 55-56; been clunky and static.11
Chwe 2001, Goldstein and Keohane 1993, Weingast Other problems with current uses of common knowl-
1995, and Wendt 1999).10 An oft-repeated example
is Schelling's "tacit coordination (common interests)" edge make it less helpful than it otherwise might
be. In a typical example-Michael Suk-Young Chwe's
problem: "You are to meet somebody in New York (2001, 7) ambitiously eclectic book, Rational Ritual:
City. You have not been instructed where to meet; you Culture, Coordination, and Common Knowledge-
have no prior understanding with the person on where common knowledge means "knowledge of others'
to meet; and you cannot communicate with each other.
You are simply told that you will have to guess where to knowledge of others' knowledge, and so on." But
the examples of common knowledge Chwe provides
meet and that he is being told the same thing and that
muddy his analysis and multiply the meanings of the
you will just have to try to make your guesses coincide" term. Sometimes "common knowledge" means the
(Schelling 1960, 55-56). Schelling (1960, 55) tried this condition of having the awareness that other people
problem on an unscientific sample of respondents from know what you know, and sometimes it seems to indi-
New Haven, Connecticut, and found that an "absolute cate the process of coming to know that others know.
majority" managed to meet at Grand Central Station's The "publicity"of public ceremonies sometimes gener-
information booth, and virtually all persons succeeded ates common knowledge; at other times publicity refers
in meeting at 12 noon. to "common knowledge generation" (compare pp. 8
Some of the problems with culture as common and 18). Most importantly, "common knowledge" slips
knowledge are indicated by the example. The concept from referring to the knowledge that other people are
tends to assume the shared quality or commonness of
seeing the same commercial, ritual, or television pro-
knowledge rather than to question how-or the ex- gram to referring to the knowledge that others under-
tent to which-such understandings are, in fact, tac- stand what they see in the same way. And Chwe seems
itly understood or consensually shared. In other words, to imply that "common knowledge" is the knowledge
"common knowledge" derives from a consideration of that others know that they are interpreting what they
knowledge that can reasonably be considered common, see in the same way that each individual viewer does.
rather than from a consideration of culture as a man- How do we researchers know (without ethnographic
ifold outcome of human activity. How do we know or survey work) that "everyone knows that everyone
whether the outcome in Schelling's Grand Central sta- knows it" or that "knowing it" means the same thing
tion example demonstrates common knowledge, or, to everyone in question? Perhaps Chwe's assumptions
say, the practicalities of train schedules, or some com- about coordination and conformity have to do with
bination of the two? Are those who do not have this
the primary areas with which he was concerned: ad-
common knowledge outside culture? In those who use
vertising and rituals. But the latter are often less about
Schelling's account, "common knowledge" seems anal- generating actual coherence than about representing
ogous to nature, a background condition-always al- it publicly. The "common knowledge" that the regime
ready there. By naturalizing the concept of culture in can orchestrate the ritual is not matched by the "com-
this way, rational choice theorists forgo the ability to mon knowledge" of what that ability means: Does it
know whether common knowledge actually exists in
prove societal coherence or demonstrate state power
any particular instance or whether another, unspeci- or both, for example? Furthermore, Chwe's operating
fied, variable is doing the work of coordinating action. assumption is that people will want to conform. What
By tracking how common knowledge gets produced, about instances of resistance and transgression? What

10 Game " This is David Laitin's formulation in a personal communication


theory's adoption of culture as "common knowledge" is
discussed in Wendt 1999, chap. 4). with the author.

718

This content downloaded from 128.235.251.160 on Fri, 13 Feb 2015 11:51:52 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
American Political Science Review Vol. 96, No. 4

of critiquesof prevailingnormativeorders?What of rational choice, or dismissiveof the culture concept


desires to be different,to be unusual,or to stand out? altogether-would benefitfrombecomingfamiliarwith
What of ambivalence?I can imagineconditionsunder an anthropological,diachronic,practice-basednotion
which people conform,basing their actions,as Chwe of culture.
and others assume,on what they think others are go- Contemporarywork on culturein anthropology,al-
ing to do, but I cannotimaginethat such pressuresare though indebtedto Geertz's culturalanthropologyof
alwaysoperative,let alone decisive.Certainly,they are the 1960s and 1970s, also acknowledges important
not exhaustivelydescriptiveof politics. critiquesof that tradition.Recent years have seen an-
In short,the conceptof commonknowledgeassumes alysts,influencedby practicetheory in anthropology,
a coherentlogic and a level of consensusthat may not challenge culture (in its abstractsense) as a seamless
be empiricallydemonstrable.It is unclearwhat added system of meaningswhose consistencyis logical and
value scholars derive from this a priori treatmentof resistantto change.Anthropologistsinspiredby works
knowledge as common or of desires to conform as as diverseas thoseof MichelFoucault,PierreBourdieu,
given. One justificationmight be, as Laitinpoints out, JacquesDerrida,and Michel de Certeauhave empha-
that "if a model has observable(and testable) impli- sized the fragility,ambiguities,and historicalruptures
cations,it can be empiricallysupportedwithoutdirect evident in symbolicsystems.13When examiningsemi-
informationon the values of the independentvariable otic practices,these theorists have invited us to see
(in this case, the existence of commonknowledge)."'12 practices,texts,andimagesas signswhosemeaningsare
Yet scholarsmay therebyimputethe presenceof com- both fixedby conventionsand also alwaysat risk-part
mon knowledge when it does not exist or when de- of overlappingsemioticsystemsopen to variousinter-
grees of common knowledge more accuratelyreflect pretationsand saturatedby complicated,contentious
citizens' experience. Indeed, such studies often pro- relationshipsof power. "Power,"despite the term's
duceargumentsthatrelyon the assumptionof common considerableconceptualfuzziness,becomesmore than
knowledge in order to prove it. By assumingdeeply just "leverage"in these accounts.It is many-sided,elu-
embedded understandingsrather than showing their sive, and diffuse (Comaroffand Comaroff 1991). To
existence, scholarstend to produce static, synchronic study culture in the critical anthropologysense is to
argumentsthat do not registertransformationsin lev- explorethe processesof meaning-construction in which
els, or fracturesin systems,of knowledge.Moreover, people's practices and their material realities-their
Chwe's version of common knowledge is sometimes political, economic, and social situations-operate in
generatedby "culturalpractices,"suchas ritualsor per- dialecticalrelationshipwith their systems of significa-
formances,and sometimes seems to be what culture tion. By "dialectical"I mean a relationshipin which
means. His reliance on a Geertzianunderstandingof actors'practicesand their systems of significationdo
culture makes the work vulnerableto the conceptual more than merely influenceeach other. Practicesand
confusions,empiricaltroubles,and theoreticallimita-
tionsdiscussedabove.In otherwords,"commonknowl-
13
edge"often operatesas a fixed,frozen,"alwaysalready Despite the different epistemological orientations of these theo-
there"category,muchlike a Geertzianscriptor schema rists, they are often grouped together under the vague rubricof "post-
modernism" or, sometimes, "poststructuralism."Anthropologists, in
does. particular, have been inspired by Bourdieu's theorizations of practice
Political scientists' reluctance to tackle post- in Outline of a Theory of Practice (1977) and The Logic of Practice
Geertziantheorizationsof the conceptforeclosespos- (1990), but Bourdieu's own ethnographic work remains structuralist
sibilitiesof learningfrom, and contributingto, current in its execution-identifying the systems of parallels and oppositions
that reveal the structure of a society. Emphasizing ambiguities and
workon culture.Thisreluctancemayhavesomethingto historical ruptures has led some practice-oriented anthropologists to
do withthe unfamiliarityof the languageused, particu- cite passages from Foucault's The History of Sexuality, Volume One
larlyin poststructuraliststudiesof culture.In addition, (1978) that stress resistance, although there is nothing inherent in a
the disavowalof modernizationtheory in politicalsci- study of practices (or in Foucault's work) that makes this necessary or
ence hasnot been as total as it wasin anthropology.Nor even obvious. For a particularly sophisticated example, see Comaroff
have political scientists engaged in the self-reflexive 1985. In Comaroff and Comaroff 1991 this emphasis on resistance
is coupled with a study of the workings of colonial ideology and
work on knowledgeproductionthat has animatedre- "hegemony," inspired, in part, by Gramsci's (1971) Selections from
search in other disciplines. The focus on the mentalit6 the Prison Notebooks. Postcolonial studies more generally invoke
of the researcher among 1980s anthropologists-which the term "practices" and investigate the dynamics of power and re-
sistance to colonial domination, but most scholars assert the power
is often what self-reflexivity entailed-dissuaded polit- of discourses rather than the ways in which such discourses actually
ical scientists from reading anthropology, as did po- operate in practice. James C. Scott's (1985, 1990) work in political
litical scientists' preferences for conceptual parsimony science may also be viewed in the resistance tradition, as can the
over the complicated, messy narratives of anthropolog- projects emerging out of subaltern studies. For an essay surveying the
literature and critical of romanticizing resistance, see Abu-Lughod
ical inquiry. Attacks on positivist social science gener-
(1990,41-55). Recent studies in practice-oriented anthropology (and
ated by poststructuralism may also have driven away sociology) have begun to reverse the trend, minimizing the role of
some political scientists. Whatever the reason, all stu- resistance and focusing on the ways in which scientific and social
dents of politics-whether dependent on Parsonian practices generate hegemony. These works are also beholden to pas-
versions of political culture, appreciative of Geertz and sages in Foucault's History of Sexuality, as well as to his theorizations
of power in Discipline and Punish (1979). Nadia Abu El-Haj's (2001)
Facts on the Ground is exemplary, demonstrating how the practice
of archaeology and its disciplinary dynamics work to substantiate
12 Personal communication with the author. historical claims and remake conceptions of territory in Israel.

719

This content downloaded from 128.235.251.160 on Fri, 13 Feb 2015 11:51:52 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
ConceptualizingCulture December 2002

signification are defined and generated in reference like actions (as opposed to "behaviors"), are also, in the
to each other, yet can come into conflict, both con- sense that I use the term, unique to human beings. Like
ceptually in their meanings and causally in the world, actions, they involve "freedom, choice, and responsibil-
so that the only way of handling such material is by ity, meaning and sense, conventions, norms and rules"
synthesis-i.e., by maintaining an overview that in- (Pitkin 1993, 242). They may be self-consciously exe-
cludes both sides without stifling the conflict or deny- cuted, but they need not be. They tend to be intelligible
ing their logical incompatibilities.14 As we shall see, a to others in context dependent ways. Practices, like hu-
dialectical understanding of culture allows us to view man actions, are ultimately "dual," composed both of
meaning-making activities as being both stable and what "the outside observer can see and of the actors'
changeable, both a single system and internally var- understandings of what they are doing" (Pitkin 1993,
ious and conflicted, an aspect of both structure and 261). What a practice approach has made possible in an-
agency, both (potentially) an independent and a de- thropology is an attention to politics, to social asymme-
pendent variable, depending on the research question try, historical contingencies, and political domination,
and strategy adopted. This conceptualization connotes key dimensions of both action and structure (Ortner
dynamism rather than stasis and allows for inconsis- 1984, 147). In contrast, the way the concept of culture
tency rather than simply implying strict coherence.'5 has generally been understood in political science has
Culture in these accounts does not refer to essential limited its utility for political analysis. To the extent
values that identify a particular group or to particu- that "culture" suppresses lived political experience in
lar traits that isolate one group from another. Rather, its Parsonian, Huntingtonian, and Geertzian formula-
culture designates a way of looking at the world that tions, it sacrifices explanatory power.
requires an account of how symbols operate in practice, Our conceptualizations have constrained our way of
why meanings generate action, and why actions pro- knowing and the kind of work we do. The concept of
duce meanings, when they do. Such a version of culture "political culture" or "common knowledge" with which
does not require forsaking parsimony or the generaliz- most political scientists operate presupposes an inter-
ing impulses many political scientists value. Focusing on nal coherence and stability that is indefensible empir-
semiotic practices dialectically may require, however, a ically. My objective is to shift our conceptualization
theorization of how specifiable contradictions and am- away from culture as a fixed system of meaning to cul-
biguities themselves work to produce political order, ture as the practices of meaning-making through which
stimulate change, or generate leverage in negotiations. social actors attempt to make their worlds coherent.16
It would be tempting to see this view of culture as In Part Two, I show that by adopting a notion of culture
mapping neatly on to the familiar structure-agency bi- as semiotic practices, political scientists can ask novel
nary. Indeed, practice theorists themselves often ar- questions, use new kinds of evidence, embrace fresh
gue that practice is "not an antagonistic alternative perspectives, and develop original answers to concerns
to the study of systems or structures, but a necessary of abiding relevance to politics.
complement to it" (Ortner 1984, 147). I want to ar-
gue somewhat differently: Systems of signification and
practice entail both structure and agency. The word PARTTWO:THEPOLITICS
"systems," of course, implies structure, but the lan- OF INTELLIGIBILITY
guage and symbols constitutive of any "system of sig-
nification" are created, reproduced, and subverted by Thinking Through Practices
agents speaking and acting in the world. I am not sure of Meaning-Making
that there can be human signification without agency-
Understanding semiotic practices requires an analysis
people doing the work of interpreting and making in- of the ways in which people use words, establish and
telligible signs. We nevertheless reproduce ourselves as
interpret signs, and act in the world in ways that foster
agents or "subjects"within the confines of institutional
and semiotic "structures," what game theorists call intelligibility. Intelligibility, in turn, works on multiple
levels. Certain kinds of practices are intelligible and
"choice under structural constraint." Practices, more-
their meanings can be ascribed and described without
over, often have a structure to them (e.g., habits, rou-
much knowledge of language and context. The political
tines, and institutional roles) at the same time that they
refer to agents acting in the world, as the term "prac- theorist, Hanna Pitkin, whose work draws on ordinary
tice" suggests. Practices are actions or deeds that are language philosophy, gives one example. We might be-
gin by saying, "I don't know what they mean to be
repeated over time; they are learned, reproduced, and
doing, but I can see that in fact their movement scat-
subject to risks through social interaction. Practices, ters those seeds in fertile spots, and later they harvest
the fruit. It may be a game or a religious ceremony or
14 I am grateful to Hanna Pitkin for
suggesting that I bring this theme something else, but in fact they are planting" (Pitkin
to the fore.
15 Recent essays on "culture" in social movement theory often em-
1993, 258). To discover whether the scattering of seeds
is a game, a religious ceremony, or something else,
phasize the term's contestatory elements. But we do not learn what
culture means or what would make a culture one culture (rather ethnographic fieldwork or survey research data or both
than two or 12). Nor do we have a sense of what would make a
symbolic system one system (and systematic) to the extent that it is. 16 This formulation is beholden to an
We learn only that "culture" is not static. See, for example, Johnston anonymous reviewer, to whom
and Klandermans (1995). I am grateful, at American Political Science Review.

720

This content downloaded from 128.235.251.160 on Fri, 13 Feb 2015 11:51:52 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
American Political Science Review Vol. 96, No. 4

may be required. We would thus be able to consider Contrary to the claim made by some anticulturalists
the attitudes of those who partake in the practice, the that studies of culture tend toward too much speci-
language they use to describe it, and the fieldworker's ficity and are hostile to the generalizing impulses of
interpretation of what is transpiring. We might con- comparative politics or of social science more broadly,
ceive of political practices similarly by saying: I don't the approach to culture I am recommending requires
know what they mean to be doing, but I can see that looking at multiple cases of habit and usage. These
in fact their movement takes a pen and checks off a cases may be confined to a specific geographically
box with a name beside it on a piece of paper, deposits bounded nation-state, but they certainly need not be.
that paper in a box, and later they tally the number Studying culture should not entail insisting on a coun-
of times each name is checked off and the one with try's allegedly specific characteristics, values, or be-
the most votes makes political decisions for the next liefs. The conceptualization of culture I am recom-
four years. It may be a game, a religious ceremony, a mending would specifically exclude any such judgment.
farce, a political event, or something else, or it may be a Nor need a cultural approach exaggerate the coher-
combination of these things. In many cases, what infor- ence of perceptions and practices that structure pol-
mants say they are doing and what the social scientist itics. In this increasingly information-reliant, transna-
claims they are doing are not either/or choices. Rather, tional world, discrete societies, peoples, or "cultures"
informants are "doing one by way of the other" (Pitkin are far less likely to be wholly discrete than they ever
1993, 259). Social scientists must be able to know and were before, and it is easy to adduce historical ev-
to show that their interpretation is based on a grasp idence that notions of cultural isolation or "purity"
of native intelligibility, that in checking off a ballot the have always been based more on myth or political in-
citizen is affirmingthe community's norms, or voting, or tention than on fact. The notion of boundedness was
both, or neither. To demonstrate that voting is a way of always "constructed"-in the minds of cartographers
affirming the community's norms, social scientists may drawing the boundaries of nation-states, for example,
have to relate the practice to local concepts, texts, and and by researchers' own categories of groupness or
traditions. They may also check whether such practices locale.
actually work to affirm the community's norms by ex- This is not to argue that geographical territories and
amining the practice's effects-the ways in which such semiotic practices are never correlated. There may
practices are negotiated by, and generate consequences at times be what Sewell (1999, 49-50) calls a "thin
for, those who participate in them. How social scientists coherence"-a variable, contested, incompletely inte-
deal with ambiguity,complexity, and the fact of multiple grated way in which the inhabitants of a specific terri-
significations will depend on the questions asked and tory share a set of semiotic practices. It is probably easy
the objectives desired. Although multiple significations to agree, for example, that people who live in France are
often exist, they are not limitless, as the examples of by and large committed to some form of republicanism.
scattering seeds or checking off a ballot make obvious. Any political analysis that seeks to discuss the relation-
The contexts within which an action occurs help deter- ship between republicanism and Frenchness must take
mine the range of significations that are possible and into account the following: (1) Republican ideas can
pertinent. come to stand for Frenchness because of the ways in
The advantages of conceiving of meaning-making which they have been used (by politicians, historians,
practices in terms of levels of intelligibility are as fol- and advertisers) to objectify what it means to be French
lows: Intelligibility does not presuppose grasping an (see Handler's [1988] study of Quebec); (2) non-French
inner essence or getting into the heads of informants people may also subscribe to republican ideals; (3) not
who are captive minds of a system but, rather, centers all French people adhere to republican ideals; (4) not
on the ways in which people attempt to make appar- all French people interpret republicanism or under-
ent, observable sense of their worlds-to themselves stand its significance in the same way; (5) antirepubli-
and to each other-in emotional and cognitive terms. can French people may not have the same relationship
In stark contrast to grasping an inner essence, such a to republicanism as do antirepublican thinkers and citi-
conceptualization of culture and of meaning requires zens elsewhere, but they may; and (6) it is not clear who
thinking pragmatically,discovering what we know (that counts as a "French" person. Recognizing these possi-
seeds are beings scattered or ballots are being checked bilities invites theorizing about the historical relation-
and counted) and what we need to know (what work ship among regional political practices, nation-building
this seed scattering or ballot tallying is doing, for ex- policies and imagery, and the production of republican
ample), even when we have only a minimal familiar- ideals in France, while also facilitating comparisons and
ity with context and language. It then prompts us to contrasts with other groups or geographical locations.
probe deeper, to ask questions about the conditions Semiotic logics are themselves an effect of people's ac-
under which specific material and semiotic activities tions, institutional power, and historical circumstances.
emerge (terrorism, for example), the contexts within State institutions, like theoreticians of culture, may,
which they find public expression, the work they do in Sewell's (1999, 57) words, "subject potential semi-
in the world, and the irregularities they generate in otic sprawl to a certain order-to prescribe (contested)
the process of reproduction. In short, the approach I core values, to impose discipline on dissenters, to
am recommending generates empirical findings with describe boundaries and norms-in short, to give a
observable implications of manifest importance to certain focus to the production and consumption of
politics. meaning."

721

This content downloaded from 128.235.251.160 on Fri, 13 Feb 2015 11:51:52 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
ConceptualizingCulture December 2002

An understanding of meaning-production as a pro- relations among signs and a group of people able to
cess through which conventions become intelligible to recognize them-is critical for our thinking about the
participants through observable usages and effects sug- political import of meaning-production (Sahlins 1985,
gests that meanings are open to various and chang- 143-56; Saussure 1959; Sewell 1999, 23-24). Intelligibil-
ing interpretations, while also sometimes appearing to ity does not imply that linguistic or semiotic meanings
be overly coherent, fixed, or inevitable. The analyst's are stable, but it does require at least enough stability so
task, then, may not be to specify the relationships that what one actor learned still applies when another
that govern this semiotic logic (structuralism), or to speaks. Put differently, intelligibility suggests that insta-
search for silently intended meanings (hermeneutics), bilities in discourse and in practices make sense only
but rather to identify the range of semiotic practices rel- within the signifying operations of a shared concep-
evant to explanations of a given political phenomenon tual system (Saussure 1959; Sewell 1999, 50; Wedeen
and explore how such semiotic practices work. Con- 1999, 85).
sider, for instance, the study of patriotism in the United Initially, this formulation of intelligibility may seem
States. We might select pledging allegiance to the flag similar to a "common knowledge" approach, but
as one semiotic practice in the range a scholar in- intelligibility differs from common knowledge in at
vestigates in studying patriotism in the United States. least two fundamental ways. First, "intelligibility"
We would want to do more than analyze its con- refers to conditions that are observable rather than
tent or infer symbolic patriotism from its family re- assumed. Second, intelligibility connotes a minimalist
semblance to flag ceremonies elsewhere. We would sense of what is shared rather than a highly integrated
inquire into the effects of the relationship between one; a common conceptual system (intelligibility) is
pledging allegiance and patriotism, a task that calls not the same as a shared episteme ("common knowl-
for a number of additional studies. We might research edge"). When we see children pledging allegiance to
the history of pledging allegiance, including the mech- the flag in elementary school, we do not think that they
anisms by which the ritual was enforced over time. We are ordering an ice cream soda at the drugstore. The
might observe the practice ethnographically in areas words that they utter signal that they are reciting an
selected for their varying regional, ethnic, racial, class, oath of loyalty to the United States and that the flag
and political affiliations. We might conduct open-ended symbolizes the United States. We do not know whether
interviews and surveys, asking a wide variety of peo- they experience this particular recitation as an avowal
ple about the meanings they attribute to pledging al- of their patriotism or indeed whether they ever have
legiance and the effects it produces in them: Was the such feelings. We do know, however, because of our
flag salute mind-numbing, uplifting, apathy-inducing, shared experiences of language acquisition, that their
or irrelevant? Finally, we might collect transgressive action is intelligible as an outward demonstration of
materials, such as evidence from court cases and protest allegiance. Wittgenstein argues that we learn the mean-
movements, as well as source materials from "popu- ing of words such as "flag" and "allegiance" through
lar culture" media, such as newspaper reports, films, other people's uses of words in contexts such as pledg-
jokes, cartoons, and songs, that may offer alternative ing allegiance to the flag. According to Wittgenstein
ways of seeing the pledge of allegiance. Such an anal- (1958, 225) "What 'determining the length' means is
ysis would allow us to discern whether the pledge of not learned by learning what length and determining
allegiance could be a banal, routinized practice, an are; the meaning of the word 'length' is learnt by learn-
activity invested with and productive of patriotism, ing, among other things, what it is to determine length"
or both. (Wittgenstein 225). Similarly, the meaning of the word
Although the meanings people might attach to a "flag"is learned by learning, among other things, what
particular practice such as pledging allegiance to the it is to pledge allegiance to it.
flag are multiple and unstable, to be intelligible-by To summarize, "meaning" connotes intelligibility,
definition-they need to be recognizable by others. As which is produced through and compounded by re-
Ferdinand de Saussure argued, the meaning of a sign is peated, context-dependent use that is observable.
a function of its contrasts with other signs in a semiotic Language and symbols are intelligible insofar as they
system. People form a semiotic community to the ex- are made manifest through practices. Practices make
tent that they recognize the same set of contrasts and sense because they are reproduced historically and
therefore are able to engage in mutually comprehen- conceptualized through language. Practices and signs
sible symbolic action.17 Resistance and obedience are may be "thinly coherent" (Sewell) in the sense that
intelligible insofar as they make reference to this shared they relate differentially to other signs (Saussure)
set of oppositions, without which political activities or and yet have a recognizable range of applications
speech acts would hardly make sense. Saussure's ac- (Wittgenstein). Yet they rarely exhibit the sort of highly
count may exaggerate coherence, but his insight-that integrated, logical consistency attributed to them by
intelligibility requires both a minimally shared set of structuralists or by semioticians such as Geertz. At-
tention to dynamism, risk, misunderstandings, ambi-
guity, and historical encounter calls for an analysis of
17 Saussure's (1959, 14) concerns were with language, which he saw
the effects of semiotic practices: the ways in which, for
as "the social side of speech, outside the individual who can never
create nor modify it by himself; it exists only by virtue of a contract example, official rhetoric in Syria or negative political
signed by the members of the community." For his discussion of the advertisements in the United States affect people's
nature of the linguistic sign, see pp. 65ff. actions and interpretations, which, in turn, play a

722

This content downloaded from 128.235.251.160 on Fri, 13 Feb 2015 11:51:52 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
American Political Science Review Vol. 96, No. 4

role in determining future actions. Systems of signs space with monotonous slogans and empty gestures,
are inscribed in material, observable practices; semi- draining citizens' political energies. The insinuation of
otic practices produce material effects, the observable formulaic rhetoric and self-serving state symbolism into
implications of which are so important for positivist the daily lives of citizens habituated people to per-
social science. And material effects reproduce systems form the gestures and pronounce the slogans constitu-
of signification, which are communally intelligible and tive of their obedience. Representations of power and
therefore open to interpretation. obedience in Syria also operated to generate power
and obedience by disseminating credible threats of
ApplyingSemiotic Practices punishment. Although threats, to be credible, must at
least occasionally be carried out, in general they suffice
How might this understanding of culture as the dialec- to ensure the compliance of most citizens. In coercive
tical relationship between people's practices and sys- compliance, people obey because they fear being pun-
tems of signification be applied as an "explanatory" ished. The images of citizens delivering panegyrics to
or "independent" variable in current political science Asad's rule, collectively holding aloft placards forming
research? Through an investigation of two examples- his face, signing oaths in blood, or simply displaying
compliance and ethnic identity-formation-I show how pictures of him in their shop windows communicated
culture (as semiotic practices) can be used in causal to Syrians throughout the country the impression of
analyses. Asad's power independent of his readiness to use it.
First, in Ambiguities of Domination: Politics, And the greater the absurdity of the required per-
Rhetoric, and Symbols in Contemporary Syria, I formance, the more clearly it demonstrated that the
(Wedeen 1999) examine the ways in which a particular regime could make most people obey most of the time.
set of semiotic practices (in this case, patently spurious Studying Syrian "political culture" in this sense does
official speeches and the ironic distancing strategies of not entail identifying the traits that inhere in Syrians,
the citizenry) works to produce political compliance. but investigating the rhetorical practices and symbols
The object in that study was the "cult" of Syrian Presi- that generate compliance for the regime.18
dent Hafiz al-Asad-all of the rhetorical practices and On the basis of ethnographic research, I demonstrate
official imagery that substituted for discussion of sub- that Syrians under Asad both recognized the disci-
stantive political issues in public. For much of Asad's plinary aspects of the cult and found ways to undermine
rule (1970-2000) his image was omnipresent. In news- them. The fact that so many tolerated, politically critical
papers, on television, and during orchestrated spec- cartoons, films, and television comedies were published
tacles, Asad was praised as the "father," the "gallant or circulated raises the question of why a regime would
knight," even the country's "premier pharmacist." Yet allow symbolic affronts to its official claims of omnipo-
most Syrians, including those who created the official tence. To ask the question differently: To what extent
rhetoric, did not believe its claims. The book asks, Why can such individual artistic "victories" be politically ef-
would a regime spend scarce resources on a cult whose fective ways to resist a regime's politics of "as if"? On
rituals of obeisance are transparently phony? The an- the one hand, these practices were politically effective
swer: Because it works. The book concludes that Asad's to the extent that they counteracted the atomization
cult operated as a disciplinary device, generating a pol- and isolation fostered by public dissimulation. Whereas
itics of public dissimulation in which citizens acted as seeing others obey may have made each feel isolated
if they revered their leader. By inundating daily life in his/her unbelief, a shared giggle, the popularity of a
with tired symbolism, the regime exercised a subtle, comedy skit, and the circulation of cartoons and trans-
yet effective, form of power. The cult worked to en- gressive stories enabled people to recognize that the
force obedience, induce complicity, isolate Syrians from conditions of unbelief were widely shared. Both per-
one another, and set guidelines for public speech and mitted and prohibited methods of registering resistance
behavior. were thus partially effective to the extent that they re-
Studying "culture" as semiotic practices with polit- asserted this widely shared experience of unbelief. At
ical effects can lead to surprising findings. Contrary the moment when a joke is told and laughter resounds
to conventional wisdom, the rhetoric and symbols of in the room, people are canceling the concrete isolation
Asad's cult did not produce "legitimacy," "charisma," and atomization manufactured by a politics of "as if."
or "hegemony," enabling political leaders to win sup- They are affirming to themselves and to others their
port for themselves and their policies by fostering col- shared status as unwilling "conscripts" (Scott 1990, 15).
lective ethnic, national, or class identifications. Yet On the other hand, and paradoxically, it is precisely
Asad's cult was neither epiphenomenal nor unimpor- this shared acknowledgment of involuntary obedience
tant. A focus exclusively on material concerns does not that can make a cult so powerful. Asad's cult was pow-
explain why the Syrian government expended exorbi- erful, in part, because it was unbelievable. Acts of trans-
tant sums of money and scarce material resources on gression might counteract the atomization and isolation
symbolic production, instead of marshalling its limited a politics of "as if" produces, but they also shore up
funds for either increases in punitive enforcement or another disciplinary mechanism, namely, the ways in
the positive inducements that goods and services could which such a cult relies on an external obedience
offer. Ambiguities of Domination shows how official
rhetoric and images not only exemplify but also pro- 18 For a sociological formulation of how "culture" as a repertoire or
duce power for a regime. Asad's cult cluttered public "tool kit" influences "strategies of action," see Swidler 1986.

723

This content downloaded from 128.235.251.160 on Fri, 13 Feb 2015 11:51:52 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
ConceptualizingCulture December 2002

produced through each citizen's unbelief. Asad's cult work in tandem to generate compliance. The same de-
disciplined citizens by occasioning continual demon- pendent variable, compliance, could be explained by
strations of external obedience. External obedience, arguing that the cult creates charisma. But political sci-
unlike good judgment or conviction, depends on a self- entists lose empirically and theoretically by failing to
conscious submission to authority that is predicated on understand that the mechanisms shoring up the regime
not believing. Recognizing the shared conditions of un- are both the "as if" habitual rituals and the practices
belief thus reproduces this self-consciousness, without of transgression. The patterns we see are not reliant
which a politics of "as if" could scarcely be sustained. on a notion of culture as fixed or natural. Rather, the
In short, such resistance might counteract the atomiz- fissures, tensions, and instabilities in meaning-making
ing effects of a personality cult, but it also reinforces practices actually work to produce social order, albeit
the cult's own mechanisms of enforcing obedience. As a fragile one. The explanations the book provides give
the philosopher Slavoj Zizek (1991) points out, even if us a new theory of how symbols operate, why regimes
people keep their ironical distance, even if they demon- spend scarce resources on their deployment, and why
strate that they do not take what they are doing seri- political scientists ought to take such modes of social
ously, they are still complying, and compliance is what control seriously.
ultimately counts politically. Turning now to the second example, recent work on
Studying the ways in which semiotic practices pro- ethnic identity-formation and ethnic violence in polit-
duce compliance for a regime need not be confined to ical science could produce empirically more sophisti-
authoritarian cases. One could also imagine scholars of cated causal accounts and more fine-grained coding
voting behavior, for example, considering the ways in schema by taking "culture" as semiotic practices seri-
which consistently false campaign promises might op- ously. Here is one possible application: Whereas under-
erate to depoliticize the electorate. Similarly, scholars standings of the "nation" as constructed and imagined
of capitalism might analyze advertising campaigns, in- are now taken for granted, "ethnicity" often operates
vestigating how images of the "good life"-of comfort, in datasets as a given category of belonging. People are
efficiency, and love-are marketed, consumed, and re- Hutu or Tutsi, Slavs or Germans. Consequently, some
sisted. Such analyses would go beyond readings of pub- work on ethnic violence, particularly in international
lic opinion polls, campaign promises, or advertisements relations, suffers from the tautological reasoning of for-
as texts and look both toward their effects (the sorts of mer "political culture" analyses: Interethnic tension is
reactions they stimulate) and to these various practices caused by the tensions of interethnicity (Brown et al.
as themselves effects of specific, historically contingent 1996). As Fearon and Laitin (1996, 715-35), point out,
relations of political power. interethnic relations are more often characterized by
Existing political science frameworks either fail to cooperation than conflict, which suggests that imag-
pay attention to rhetoric and symbols, which means inings or "constructions" of ethnicity may be more
that they have no account of the work symbols do, or important than its seemingly objective existence. Put
make claims about symbols that are unwarranted or more radically,ethnicity may be less objectively real, or
untested empirically (that they generate "legitimacy," more variable, than some researchers tend to assume.
for example). As noted in Part One, some scholars Yet even scholars sympathetic to constructivism have
use the term culture to refer to an entirely different been slow to apply its lessons, in part because the cod-
area of inquiry-the identification of purported group ing work entailed in generating a large, constructivist-
traits.The way in which we conceptualize culture affects oriented dataset would be difficult to do (a subject to
the kind of research we do and the evidence we bring which we shall return).
to bear on our projects. Analyzing culture as semiotic Work by anthropologists, such as Liisa H. Malkki's
practices has significant empirical and theoretical pay- (1996) "National Geographic: The Rooting of Peoples
offs for political science. Interpreting semiotic practices and the Territorialization of National Identity among
overcomes the difficulties of what Timur Kuran (1995) Scholars and Refugees," suggests the political conse-
calls "preference falsification," giving us insight into quences of different levels of intensity in ethnic identi-
the attitudes of citizens, which may be particularly dif- fication. Malkki's case examines forms of Hutuness-
ficult to discern in authoritarian regimes. My work also various ways in which semiotic practices (narratives of
allowed me to pose a puzzle that had been ignored identification and everyday activities) register experi-
by political scientists, namely, Why would a regime ences of belonging that are not captured in standard
use rituals of obeisance that are transparently phony? categorizations of ethnicity. As Malkki shows, residents
The evidence I gathered to code unbelief-published of a refugee camp established in western Tanzania after
and prohibited cartoons, underground and tolerated the Burundi massacres of 1972 experienced themselves
comedy skits, short stories, and risky political jokes- as "pure" Hutus, whereas Hutu-Burundi refugees liv-
suggests the utility of these materials for the analysis of ing in the township of Kigoma did not. Camp refugees
lived political experience. And the process of collect- constructed their sense of national belonging to Bu-
ing such evidence prompted new questions about the rundi and their ethnic identification with Hutuness
extent to which individual artistic practices could be in terms of moralizing commentaries about heroism
considered resistance to the cult's mechanisms of so- and homeland. In contrast, town refugees championed
cial control. Moreover, the book's dialectical approach a rootless and mobile cosmopolitanism-a creolized
allows us to see how both the rituals of obeisance and "impurity."They were not essentially Hutu but, rather,
the transgressive practices poking fun at political life just "broad persons" (Malkki 1996, 446, and Eley and

724

This content downloaded from 128.235.251.160 on Fri, 13 Feb 2015 11:51:52 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
American Political Science Review Vol. 96, No. 4

Suny's [1996, 432] commentary on Malkki; see also measure the intensity of identity indirectly, through
Malkki 1995). A semiotic-practical analysis of ethnic a specification of factors or components that are
identity-formation would compare the relationship be- measurable.20
tween everyday practices and the rhetoric of belonging For example, we might have theoretical reasons to
within refugee camps with the language and everyday think that interstate war affects nationalist sentiment
practices of those outside the camps. For formal model- and thus use it as one factor. But we might also have
ers or the quantitatively minded, developing a dataset sound theoretical justifications for arguing that it is
based on an intensity scale accounting for people's the threat of interstate war that consolidates nation-
experiences of identification would produce a more alist sentiments. We might then consider factors of a
precise and generalizable explanation of how the lived semiotic-practical nature, such as narratives of conspir-
conditions of ethnic identity-formation might deter- acy or threat and the impact these have on citizens.
mine conflict when they do. Attention to the production That impact might be registered in newspaper reports,
of cosmopolitan understandings might also help to ex- protest movements, the formation of organized groups,
plain the absence of ethnic conflict in cases where such and political speeches, songs, sporting events, and tele-
identifications are weak. vision serials. Ethnographic and historical work might
Coding ethnic groups is an inherently perilous en- also be used to check various cases, to see, for example,
terprise. The importance of particular identifications how the categories of Hindu and Muslim have changed
changes over time, yet scholars have tended to rely on from 1850 to the present, so that a dataset on Indian
"objective" measures that are one-dimensional, such as riots or one that incorporated intensity measures could
linguistic or religious affiliations. These markers may account not only for violence, but also for the shift-
have little to do with people's experiences of identi- ing relevance of appeals to ethnicity in riots. We might
fication. Authoritative compendia of linguistic or reli- look for evidence of intensity in the content of state-
gious distinctions may suggest the existence of groups initiated formulations of national identity in laws and
whose members do not see themselves as a community public spectacles. A semiotic practical approach would
or whose shared language or religion have no political also require us to register the observable effects these
salience. Yet because a research project may depend have on various populations of citizens, perhaps by
on specifying potential ethnic groups, scholars have to conducting surveys. In addition, we might supply the-
develop criteria for thinking about what makes a group oretical reasons for how the presence or absence of
a group and under what conditions experiences of po- catalyzing events, such as September 11, strengthens
litical identification might crystallize along, say, ethnic nationalist feelings and use that as a factor; a semi-
lines. otic practical approach could help us determine what
One promising way to improve on, if not avoid, counts as a catalyzing or traumatic event. The location
the estimate bias bedeviling datasets such as Ted of a population in a poor, resource-deprived area could
Gurr's (1997) MAR one, is to think about degrees of also be an indicator of group intensity. Malkki's work
ethnicity-of Hutuness or Tutsiness or Kurdishness or on refugees suggests that continual, quotidian experi-
Irish American-ness. To do that, a scholar could first ences of severe poverty can induce intense feelings of
list the range of identifications that might take on po- groupness, although these may not be articulated along
litical salience, given specifiable criteria, while explain- explicitly economic lines. Indeed, political economists
ing why others are unlikely to do so. Thus, at the very who assert that the poor as a group are prone to revolt
least we would have to come up with reasons why cod- when they have nothing to lose might explain varia-
ing the intensity of ice cream eaters or Pittsburghers tions in actual, organized revolts among "the poor"
would seem silly, while coding the intensity of Hutus by considering the role semiotic practices play (Boix
and Tutsis would not. Harder to justify is the inclu- n.d.; Lipset 1959, 1960; Stokes and Boix n.d.). What
sion or exclusion of various linguistically distinct sub- work is done by myths such as the Horatio Alger story,
groupings of Ashantis in Ghana or of Spanish-speaking for example, in reproducing convictions that economic
Californians in the United States, but a semiotic practi- conditions can be ameliorated through individual ef-
cal approach invites those studying "identity" issues to fort rather than through collective action? By taking
research the conditions under which certain practices culture as semiotic practices seriously, causal accounts
take on political meaning and intensify political claims will be more nuanced and precise, even if an accurate
of group affiliation.19 Listing actual communities and coding schema for large datasets eludes social scientists
potential ones in terms of the intensity of groupness intent on constructing one. Datasets that can take into
for a large dataset might require, as Matthew Kocher account intensity in the ways sketched above should be
has argued, treating ethnic or nationalist identification more accurate than current ones.
as a phenomenon that cannot be measured directly,
but only inferred from a correlation matrix. Factor 20 Mathew Kocher has pointed out to me that the locus classicus
and principal components analysis might be used to for factor analysis is IQ. Like intensity of identity, we cannot mea-
sure intelligence directly, so scientists have devised a number of tests
that operate as "functions of intelligence." A relevant example of
19 am indebted to Matthew Kocher for
I sharing his thoughts on confirmatory factor analysis is Laitin's (1998, 217-42, 392-4) use of
ethnic identifications and his experiences attempting to recode the the "matched guise" test created by Wallace Lambert. Laitin used
MAR dataset. In a private conversation, he used the example of confirmatory factor analysis to construct indices of "friendship" and
trying to code a "subgrouping" of Ashanti in Ghana to demonstrate "respect" out of survey responses from bilingual students in the for-
the persistent dangers of estimate bias and of infinite regress. mer Soviet Union.

725

This content downloaded from 128.235.251.160 on Fri, 13 Feb 2015 11:51:52 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
ConceptualizingCulture December 2002

These examples are suggestive of how studying cul- are irrelevant to rational choice theorists. Similarly,
ture offers us new purchase on perennial and in- epistemological concerns with stability, order, and gov-
tractable issues in political science. Paying attention ernance make those who emphasize the "science" part
to symbolic displays of power, for example, pro- of the discipline or who look to economics for inspi-
vides scholars with the opportunity to understand ration less compelling to interpretivists than philoso-
the dynamics of political compliance and to explain phers and anthropologists are. For those with an
why regimes spend scarce material resources on such interest in culture on both sides of the divide, how-
displays. Scholars can document empirically the skir- ever, there is no reason not to move beyond the
mishes that take place between ruler and ruled as they traditional understanding of political culture. A
are represented in the regime's idealized presentation semiotic practices approach avoids the ahistorical,
of itself and in people's reception of it. They can also empirically untenable formulation of culture currently
theorize the ways in which symbols themselves create, invoked by political culture and some rational choice
sustain, and undermine the disciplinary circumstances theorists. And it gives us explanatory purchase on
through which any regime exercises some of its power. key dependent variables, such as compliance and eth-
Studying semiotic practices generates explanations of nic identity-formation. Researching dynamic semiotic
how political identifications are formed, instances of practices enables both accounts of general political pro-
groupness crystallized, and alternative possibilities cesses and nuanced causal arguments about particular
of belonging foreclosed. Investigating semiotic prac- cases in ways that are more theoretically robust and
tices can also help scholars to establish important cri- empirically accurate than mainstream formulations of
teria for differentiating passionate forms of solidarity culture in political science currently permit.
from vague, mildly constraining experiences of "affin-
ity and affiliation" (Brubaker and Cooper 2000, 21).
Establishing such criteria would enhance studies of na- REFERENCES
tionalism, ethnic conflict, identity-formation, collective Abu El-Haj, Nadia. 2001. Facts on the Ground: Archaeological Prac-
action, and hegemony. A semiotic practice-oriented ap- tice and TerritorialSelf-Fashioning in Israeli Society. Chicago: Uni-
proach can also assist in answering important questions versity of Chicago Press.
such as, When will a subversive organization invoke Abu-Lughod, Lila. 1990. "The Romance of Resistance: Tracing
Transformations of Power through Bedouin Women." American
ethnicity to activate violence? How intense are people's Ethnologist 17 (February): 41-55.
identifications in particular nation-states? When will Almond, Gabriel. 1956. "Comparative Political Systems." Journal of
states experience violence from groups who claim eth- Political Systems (August): 391-409.
nicity? When will organizations that claim to represent Almond, Gabriel A., and Sidney Verba. 1963. The Civic Culture:
ethnic groups form? When will they be successful at Political Attitudes and Democracy in Five Nations. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press.
mobilizing support around ethnic or national claims? Anderson, Lisa. 1995. "Democracy in the Arab World: A Critique
and How do groups manage to gain public support of the Political Culture Approach." In Political Liberalization and
and to get their claims taken seriously? A semiotic Democratization in theArab World:Comparative Experiences, eds.
Rex Brynen, Bahgat Korany,and Paul Noble. Boulder, CO: Lynne
practice-based approach also draws our attention to Rienner: 77-92.
the problems of presuming ethnicity as an objective
Asad, Talal. 1993. Genealogies of Religion: Discipline and Reasons
marker. Large datasets using objective categories suf- of Power in Christianity and Islam. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins
fer from selection bias toward conflict (Fearon and University.
Laitin 1996). An intensity measure, devised through a Axelrod, Robert. 1997. The Complexity of Cooperation: Agent-
combination of statistical techniques and ethnographic Based Models of Competition and Collaboration. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press.
ones, might produce more reliable large datasets or, Banfield, Edward C. 1958. The Moral Basis of a Backward Society.
at least, point scholars in new directions. Generaliz- New York: Free Press.
able arguments about the conditions under which as- Bates, Robert H., Rui J. P de Figueiredo Jr., and Barry Weingast.
1998. "The Politics of Interpretation: Rationality, Culture, and
criptive identifications get produced, or become the Transition."Politics and Society 26 (4): 603-42.
basis for organized resistance, or rigidify in state in-
Benedict, Ruth. [1934] 1989. Patterns of Culture. Boston: Houghton
stitutions focus attention on the meanings of ethnic- Mifflin.
ity in practice, thereby acknowledging some of the Boas, Franz. 1896. "The Limitations of the Comparative Method of
actual complexities of political identification, without Anthropology." Science 4: 901-8.
Boas, Franz. 1911. The Mind of Primitive Man. New York:Macmillan.
forsaking commitments to causal stories or large-n Boix, Carles. N.d. Democracy and Redistribution. Cambridge: Cam-
work.
bridge University Press. Forthcoming.
Boix, Carles, and Daniel Posner. 1996. "Making Social Capital Work:
A Review of Robert Putnam's Making Democracy Work: Civic
Traditions in Modern Italy." Working Paper Series. Cambridge,
CONCLUDING REMARKS MA: Harvard University Center for International Affairs.
Bonnell, Victoria E., and Lynn Hunt, eds. 1999. Beyond the Cultural
The gulf between interpretivists and rational choice Turn:New Directions in the Study of Society and Culture.Berkeley:
theorists may be too wide to bridge. In many ways, University of California Press.
the concerns of rational choice theorists and interpre- Bourdieu, Pierre. 1977. Outline of a Theory of Practice. Cambridge:
tivists are simply incommensurable. Epistemological Cambridge University Press.
Bourdieu, Pierre. 1990. The Logic of Practice. Cambridge: Polity
commitments to uncertainty, ambiguity, and messiness Press.
invite interpretivists to focus on social movements, Bowen, John, and Roger Petersen, eds. 1999. Critical Comparisons
political resistance, and modern power in ways that in Politics and Culture. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

726

This content downloaded from 128.235.251.160 on Fri, 13 Feb 2015 11:51:52 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
American Political Science Review Vol. 96, No. 4

Brown, Michael E., Owen R. Cote, Jr., Sean M. Lynn-Jones, and Huntington, Samuel. 1996. The Clash of Civilizations and the Remak-
Steven E. Miller. 1996. Nationalism and Ethnic Conflict:An Inter- ing of World Order. New York: Simon and Schuster.
national Security Reader. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Jackman, Robert W., and Ross A. Miller. 1996a. "A Renaissance of
Brownstein, Larry.1995. "A Reappraisal of the Concept of'Culture."' Political Culture?" American Journal of Political Science 40 (3):
Social Epistemology 9 (4): 311-51. 632-59.
Brubaker, Rogers, and Frederick Cooper. 2000. "Beyond 'Identity."' Jackman, Robert W., and Ross A. Miller. 1996b. "The Poverty of
Theory and Society 29: 1-47. Political Culture." American Journal of Political Science 41 (3):
Chaudhry,Kiren Aziz. 1994. "The Middle East and the Political Econ- 697-716.
omy of Development." Items 48 (June-September): 41-49. Johnson, James. 1997. "Symbol and Strategy in Comparative Political
Chwe, Michael Suk-Young. 2001. Rational Ritual: Culture, Co- Analysis." APSA-CP 8 (2): 6-9.
ordination, and Common Knowledge. Princeton, NJ: Princeton Johnston, Hank, and Bert Klandermans, eds. 1995. Social Movements
University Press. and Culture. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Clifford, James. 1988. The Predicament of Culture:Twentieth-Century King, Gary, Robert O. Keohane, and Sidney Verba. 1994. Designing
Ethnography, Literature, and Art. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Uni- Social Inquiry: Scientific Inference in Qualitative Research. Prince-
versity Press. ton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Clifford, James, and George Marcus, eds. 1986. Writing Culture: The Kroeber, A. L., and C. Kluckhohn, eds. 1952. Culture: A Critical
Poetics and Politics of Ethnography. Berkeley: University of Cali- Review of Concepts and Definitions, Vol. 47. Papers of the Peabody
fornia Press. Museum of American Archaeology and Ethnology. Cambridge,
Cohen, Abner. 1974. Two-Dimensional Man: An Essay on the An- MA: Harvard University, The Museum.
thropology of Power and Symbolism in Complex Society. Berkeley: Kuper, Adam. 1999. Culture: The Anthropologists' Account. Cam-
University of California Press. bridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Comaroff, Jean. 1985. Body of Power, Spirit of Resistance. Chicago: Kuran, Timur. 1995. Private Truths, Public Lies. Cambridge, MA:
University of Chicago Press. Harvard University Press.
Comaroff, Jean, and John Comaroff. 1991. Of Revelation and Revolu- Laitin, David D. 1986. Hegemony and Culture:Politics and Religious
tion, Vol. 1. Christianity,Colonialism, and Consciousness in South Change among the Yoruba. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Africa. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Laitin, David D. 1997. "Game Theory and Culture."APSA-CP 8 (2):
Eley, Geoff, and Ronald Grigor Suny. 1996. Becoming National: A 9-11.
Reader. New York: Oxford University Press. Laitin, David D. 1998. Identity in Formation: The Russian-Speaking
Fabian, Johannes. 1983. Time and the Other: How Anthropology Populations in the Near Abroad. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University
Makes Its Object. New York: Columbia University Press. Press.
Fearon, James D., and David D. Laitin. 1996. "Explaining In- Laitin, David D. 1999. "Identity Choice Under Conditions of
terethnic Cooperation." American Political Science Review 90(4): Uncertainty: Reflections on Selten's Dualist Methodology." In
715-35. Competition and Cooperation: Conversations with Nobelists
Foucault Michel. 1978. The History of Sexuality, Volume One: An about Economics and Political Science, eds. James E. Alt,
Introduction. Translated by Robert Hurley. New York: Pantheon Margaret Levi, and Elinor Ostrom. New York: Russell Sage
Books. Foundation.
Foucault Michel. 1979. Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison. Lipset, Seymour Martin. 1959. "Some Social Requisites of Democ-
Translated by Alan Sheridan. New York: Vintage Books. racy:Economic Development and Political Legitimacy."American
Geertz, Clifford. 1973. The Interpretation of Cultures. New York: Political Science Review 53 (1): 69-105.
Basic Books. Lipset, Seymour Martin. 1960. Political Man: The Social Bases of
Geertz, Clifford. 1980. Negara: The Theater State in Nineteenth Cen- Politics. Garden City, NY: Doubleday.
tury Bali. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Lustick, Ian S. 1997. "Culture and the Wager of Rational Choice."
Geertz, Clifford. 1983. Local Knowledge: Further Essays in Interpre- APSA-CP 8 (2): 11-14.
tive Anthropology. New York: Basic Books. Malkki, Liisa H. 1995. Purity and Exile: Violence, Memory, and Na-
Gerber, Elisabeth R., and John E. Jackson. 1993. "Endogenous Pref- tional Cosmology among Hutu Refugees in Tanzania. Chicago:
erences and the Study of Institutions." American Political Science University of Chicago Press.
Review, 87(3): 639-56. Malkki, Liisa H. 1996. "National Geographic: The Rooting of Peoples
Goldstein, Judith, and Robert Keohane, eds. 1993. Ideas and Foreign and the Territorialization of National Identity among Scholars and
Policy. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Refugees." In Becoming National: A Reader, ed. Geoff Eley and
Gramsci, Antonio. 1971. Selections from the Prison Notebooks. eds. Ronald Grigor Suny. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Quintin Hoare and Geoffrey Nowell-Smith. London: Lawrence McClelland, David C. 1961. The Achieving Society. Princeton, NJ:
and Wishost. D. Van Nostrand.
Greif, Avner. 1994. "Cultural Beliefs and the Organization of Soci- McClelland, David C. 1963. "National Character and Economic
ety: A Historical and Theoretical Reflection on Collectivist and Growth in Turkey and Iran." In Communications and Political De-
Individualist Societies." Journal of Political Economy 102: 912-50. velopment, ed. Lucian W. Pye. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Gupta, Akhil, and James Ferguson, eds. 1997. Culture, Power, Place: Press.
Explorations in Critical Anthropology. Durham, NC: Duke Uni- Mitchell, Timothy. 1988. Colonising Egypt. Berkeley: University of
versity Press. California Press.
Gurr, Ted Robert. 1997. Minorities at Risk: A Global View of Eth- "Notes from the Annual Meetings: Culture and Rational Choice."
nopolitical Conflicts. Washington: United States Institute of Peace. 1997. APSA-CP (Summer): 5-21.
Handler, Richard. 1988. Nationalism and the Politics of Culture in Ortner, Sherry B. 1984. "Theory in Anthropology Since the Sixties."
Quebec. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press. Comparative Studies in Society and History 26: 126-66.
Hardin, Russell. 1995. One for All: The Logic of Group Conflict. Ortner, Sherry B. 1997. "Introduction." Representations 59 (Sum-
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. mer): 1-13.
Hirschman, Albert 0. 1984. "A Dissenter's Confession:'The Strategy Parsons, Talcott. 1949. The Structure of Social Action, Vol. 2. New
of Economic Development' Revisited." In Pioneers in Develop- York: Free Press.
ment, eds. Gerald M. Meier and Dudley Seers. New York: Oxford Parsons, Talcott. 1951. The Social System. New York: Free Press.
University Press. Parsons, Talcott. 1965. "Culture and the Social System: Introduction."
Hudson, Michael. 1995. "The Cultural Approach to Arab Democra- In Theories ofSociety: Foundations ofModern Sociological Theory,
tization: The Case for Bringing It Back in, Carefully." In Political ed. Talcott Parsons, Edward Shils, Kaspar D. Naegele, and Jesse
Liberalization and Democratization in the Arab World:Compara- R. Pitts. New York: Free Press, 963-93.
tive Experiences, eds. Rex Brynen, Bahgat Korany, and Paul Noble. Pitkin, Hanna Fenichel. 1993. Wittgensteinand Justice. Berkeley: Uni-
Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner: 61-76. versity of California Press.
Huntington, Samuel. 1993. "The Clash of Civilizations?" Foreign Af- Przeworski, Adam. 1986. "Marxism and Rational Choice." Politics
fairs 72 (3): 22-49. and Society 14: 379-409.

727

This content downloaded from 128.235.251.160 on Fri, 13 Feb 2015 11:51:52 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
ConceptualizingCulture December 2002

Putnam, Robert, Robert Leonard, and Raffaella Y. Nanetti. 1993. Stocking, George W., Jr. 1982. Race, Culture,and Evolution: Essays
Making Democracy Work:Civic Traditionsin Modern Italy. Prince- in the History of Anthropology. Chicago: University of Chicago
ton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Press.
Pye, Lucien W. 1965. "Comparative Political Culture." In Political Stocking, George W., Jr. Victorian Anthropology. 1987. New York:
Culture and Political Development, ed. Lucien W. Pye and Sidney Free Press.
Verba. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 512-60. Stokes, Susan, and Carles Boix. N.d. "Endogenous Democratiza-
Rabinow, Paul, and William M. Sullivan, eds. 1987. InterpretiveSocial tion." Forthcoming.
Science: A Second Look. Berkeley: University of California Press. Swidler, Ann. 1986. "Culture in Action: Symbols and Strategies."
Rogowski, Ron. 1997. "Rational Choice as a Weberian View of Cul- American Sociological Review 51 (2): 273-86.
ture."APSA-CP 8 (2): 14-15. Tilly, Charles. 1975. "On the History of European State-Making."
Sahlins, Marshall. 1985. Islands of History. Chicago: University of The Formation of National States in Western Europe. Princeton,
Chicago Press. NJ: Princeton University Press.
Saussure, Ferdinand de. 1959. Course in General Linguistics. New Tsebelis, George. 1997. "Rational Choice and Culture."APSA-CP 8
York: McGraw-Hill. (2): 15-18.
Schaffer, Frederic C. 1998. Democracy in Translation:Understanding Weber, Max. 1958. The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism.
Politics in an Unfamiliar Culture. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Transl. Talcott Parsons. New York: Scribner.
Press. Wedeen, Lisa. 1999. Ambiguities of Domination: Politics, Rhetoric,
Schelling, Thomas. 1960. The Strategy of Conflict. Cambridge, MA: and Symbols in Contemporary Syria. Chicago: University of
Harvard University Press. Chicago Press.
Scott, James C. 1985. Weapons of the Weak:Everyday Forms of Peas- Weingast, Barry. 1995. "A Rational Choice Perspective on the Role
ant Resistance. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. of Ideas: Shared Belief Systems and State Sovereignty in Interna-
Scott, James C. 1990. Domination and the Arts of Resistance: Hidden tional Cooperation." Politics and Society 23: 449-64.
Transcripts.New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Wendt, Alexander. 1999. Social Theory of International Politics.
Sewell, William H., Jr. 1999. "The Concept(s) of Culture." In Be- Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
yond the Cultural Turn, ed. Victoria E. Bonnell and Lynn Hunt. Williams, Raymond. 1983. Keywords. 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford Uni-
Berkeley: University of California Press, 35-61. versity Press.
Somers, Margaret R. 1995. "What's Political or Cultural about Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1958. Philosophical Investigations. 3rd ed.
Political Culture and the Public Sphere? Toward an Historical Transl. G. E. M. Anscombe. New York: Macmillan.
Sociology of Concept Formation." Sociological Theory 13 (2): Young, Peyton. 1998. Individual Strategyand Social Structure.Prince-
113-44. ton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Steinmetz, George, ed. 1999. State/Culture:State Formation After the Zizek, Slavoj. 1991. The Sublime Object of Ideology. New York:
Cultural Turn. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Verso.

728

This content downloaded from 128.235.251.160 on Fri, 13 Feb 2015 11:51:52 AM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

You might also like