You are on page 1of 6

Deductive vs non-deductive arguments

Not every argument is offered with the same intention. Sometimes


arguments are offered to prove that something is definitely the case;
other times they are offered to show that something is likely or very
likely to be true, while leaving it possible that the conclusion may,
improbably, turn out to be false.

Before you can tell whether the premises of an argument provide


appropriate support for the conclusion, you need to decide which standards
to use in your evaluation, and this depends on whether you have an
argument of the first or the second kind. The topic for this segment is the
distinction between the two, and we will express it as a difference between
deductive and non-deductive arguments.

Remember that arguments are groups of statements some of which, the


premises, are offered in support of others, the conclusions. There are two
kinds of support that premises can give for a conclusion: deductive and
non-deductive. When the premises of an argument support the conclusion
deductively, we say that the conclusion follows deductively from the
premises. Deductive support is the strongest kind of support that premises
can give to a conclusion. When the premises of an argument support the
conclusion to some significant degree, but do not support it deductively,
we say that they support it non-deductively. In this case, the argument is
non-deductive.

If you want, you can think of successful deductive arguments as providing


conclusive support for their conclusions, assuming the truth of their
premises, whereas successful non-deductive arguments give probable, but
not conclusive, support for their conclusions.

Let’s start with deductive arguments.

 Definition: A deductive argument is an argument for which the


premises are offered to provide logically conclusive support for its
conclusion.

If a deductive argument succeeds in providing conclusive support for its


conclusion, it would be absurd for the premises to be true and the
conclusion false. The kind of support intended in deductive arguments is
infallible, inevitable, necessary, “bomb-proof”…

There are phrases people may use in arguments to indicate that they are
deductive.

Deductive argument indicators

it necessarily follows that …

it logically follows that …

it absolutely, necessarily, or certainly follows that …


Deductive argument indicators

Here are some examples of deductive arguments:

Every witch is a widow. So it necessarily follows that every witch is


female.

It’s good to read the Bible on as many days of your life as possible.
Therefore, any day is a good day to start reading the Bible every day.

The number of chicks in the pen is less than 10. The number of chicks in
the pen is more than 6. It’s not 7 and it is not 9. The number of chicks in
the pen is an integer, because you can’t really have half a chick in the pen.
Certainly, then, the number of chicks in the pen is 8.

A good historical case of deductive reasoning goes back to Euclid. Euclid


is the author of The Elements, thirteen books collating just about
everything the Greeks knew in geometry. Starting from a list of postulates
—as premises in arguments—Euclid shows how to prove important
theorems, such as the famous Pythagorean Theorem: the square of the
hypotenuse of a triangle is equal to the sum of the squares of the other two
sides (you might remember this from the equation c2=a2+b2):
The way Euclid proved the Pythagorean theorem was a very good instance
of deductive reasoning. Euclid argued in such a way that if all his
postulates were true, then the Pythagorean theorem must also be true, with
no room for doubt. If you change the postulates then the Pythagorean
theorem may no longer be true. But that doesn’t change the fact that
Euclid’s argument from his five postulates—as premises— to the
Pythagorean Theorem offers conclusive support for its conclusion. Euclid
was applying deductive reasoning to geometry.

Many philosophers and scientists over the centuries have tried to mimic
Euclid’s style of reasoning by providing deductive arguments for their
views. However, such standards for arguments cannot always be met
successfully. And that’s where non-deductive arguments come into play.

 Definition: A non-deductive argument is an argument for which the


premises are offered to provide probable – but not conclusive –
support for its conclusions.
In a good non-deductive argument, if the premises are all true, you would
rightly expect the conclusion to be true also, though you would accept that
it may be false.

If you like, think of non-deductive arguments in terms of bets. If the


premises of a good non-deductive argument are true, then you would be
happy to bet that the conclusion is also true. The argument would have
provided you with the confidence that your bet is a sensible one, but –
since it is a bet, after all – you would accept that the conclusion may turn
out false and you may lose.

As with deductive arguments, there are phrases people may use to indicate
that arguments are non-deductive.

Non-deductive argument indicators

it is likely that …

it is probable that …

it is plausible that …

Here are some examples of non-deductive arguments.

It’s cloudy today, so there’s a high probability that it will rain today.

The greediest person who was left alone in the room is Aunt Mary.
Chances are that Aunt Mary is the one who stole the apple tart.
Every observed witch is a widow, so it’s likely that every witch is a
widow.

Only all the observed wizards that we’ve seen so far were widowers. So
the next one we expect to be a widower.

To indicate that an argument is non-deductive in standard form we write


“Therefore, probably” as in:

P1: It's cloudy today. Therefore, probably, C: It will rain today

Now, this whole discussion raises a further question: how are we to decide
whether arguments are deductive are non-deductive?

This is a difficult question. Part of the difficulty is that the answer varies
with context. Mathematicians only accept deductive arguments, because
they are after certain knowledge. Mathematicians are not going to accept
arguments that are merely strong. They want deductive arguments. But in
a court of law, we cannot only expect deductive arguments. It would be
much too demanding and we would almost never be able to put criminals
in jail. Instead, cases have to be established beyond reasonable doubt, so
that we are very confident in our conclusions, even though we are aware
that we might be wrong. We need to strike the right balance, as we don’t
want it to be too easy to put people in jail either.

Part of the answer also lies in the principle of charity. The idea is quite
simple. Most people are not aware of the distinction between deductive
and non-deductive arguments, and they may try and prove things
(deductively) when a non-deductive argument would be much more
suitable. In that case, the principle of charity tells you to treat the argument
as being non-deductive.

© Patrick Girard, University of Auckland

You might also like