You are on page 1of 12

ARTICLE IN PRESS

Social Science & Medicine 65 (2007) 2248–2259


www.elsevier.com/locate/socscimed

Ethnography/ethics
Michael Parker
Department of Public Health, The Ethox Centre, Gibson Building/Block 21, Radcliffe Infirmary Woodstock Road, Oxford OX2 6HE, UK
Available online 14 September 2007

Abstract

This paper situates discussion of the ethics of ethnographic research against the background of a theoretical and
methodological debate about the relationship between ethics and method, and about the relationships between research
methods and their objects. In particular, the paper investigates the implications of folding together the ethical and the
empirical in research and argues that this requires the development of new ethico-ethnographic methods for the
investigation of ethico-moral objects. The paper falls into three main parts. The first considers calls for what has come to
be known as empirical ethics, that is, for a more empirically informed bioethics, by way of an exploration of the integration
of ethnographic methods in bioethics, and concludes that approaches which see the ethical and the empirical as
‘complementary’ do not do justice to the methodological implications of enfolding the ethical and the ethnographic. The
second part juxtaposes this with calls for the integration of ethics in ethnography and, similarly, argues that the enfolding
of the ethical and the empirical in ethnography calls for the development of new methods. The paper goes on to
problematise the ‘negotiational’ approaches to informed consent preferred by many ethnographers, arguing that the
concept of negotiation, rather than offering a solution to the problem of consent, is itself ethically complex and in need of
analysis. The paper argues that, in the context of ethnographic research, the possibility of negotiational forms of consent
depends upon engagement between researchers and researched, with unavoidably ‘ethical’ concepts such as ‘respect’,
‘recognition’, ‘dignity’, ‘justice’ and so on, and that this poses methodological challenges to ethnography. The paper’s third
section explores the implications of these arguments for research practice, using The Genethics Club as an example.
r 2007 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.

Keywords: Ethics; Ethnography; Methodology; Informed consent; Genetics; Bioethics; Empirical

Introduction ways in which ethical issues have arisen in their own


empirical research, this paper aims to complement
The papers in this Special Issue are all concerned, these empirically oriented approaches with a theo-
in one way or another, with the relationship retically driven consideration of the relationship
between the ethical and the empirical. They are, in between ethical and empirical methods. The moti-
particular, concerned with exploring the role of vation for this paper is nevertheless grounded in an
ethical concepts such as informed consent, and of attempt to understand the relationship between the
ethical review by research ethics committees, in ethical and the empirical in my own research, most
empirical social science research in medicine. While notably in an on-going ethico-ethnographic re-
most of the other authors provide accounts of the search project, The Genethics Club, which investi-
gates the enactment of ethics in clinical genetics
E-mail address: michael.parker@ethox.ox.ac.uk practice. Whilst I shall not say much about this

0277-9536/$ - see front matter r 2007 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.
doi:10.1016/j.socscimed.2007.08.003
ARTICLE IN PRESS
M. Parker / Social Science & Medicine 65 (2007) 2248–2259 2249

research here at the outset, I return to it in the latter of significance he himself has spun, I take culture
part of the paper and, in the light of the preceding to be those webs, and the analysis of it to be
discussion, use it to illustrate the implications of my therefore not an experimental science in search of
arguments for research practice. The paper falls into law but an interpretive one in search of meaning.
three main parts. In the first I consider calls for (Geertz, 1973, p. 5).
what has come to be known as empirical ethics, that
The failure of bioethics to pay sufficient attention
is, for a more empirically informed bioethics, by
to meaning and culture means that its attempts to
way of an exploration of the integration of
apply ethical principles are bound to be insensitive
ethnographic methods in bioethics. In it I argue
to morally significant features of its object of
that approaches which see the ethical and the
concern (Kleinman, 1997, p. 48). By means of thick
empirical as ‘complementary’ do not do justice to
descriptions of how those who actually live in these
the methodological implications of enfolding the
worlds make sense of their own lives and those of
ethical and the ethnographic. In the second part I
others around them (Hammersley & Atkinson,
consider calls for the integration of ethics in
2006, p. 6; Hoffmaster, 2001, pp. 4–5.), ethnography
ethnography and, similarly, argue that the enfolding
offers the possibility of a bioethics better informed
of the ethical and the empirical in ethnography calls
about the meaning and intersubjective significance
for the development of new methods. In the paper’s
of the situation under consideration and of the local
third section I consider the implications of these
‘worlds of experience’ within which and in relation
arguments for research practice.
to which bioethical issues arise (Kleinman, 1999, p.
70). From this ‘naturalistic’ perspective the ethno-
Ethnography for bioethics grapher’s task is to understand the situated ration-
ality of the context within which people’s actions
In recent years there have been increasing calls for make sense.
a more empirically informed bioethics (DeVries,
1995; Fox, 1976; Hoffmaster, 1992, 2001; Hope, It is through ongoing interaction and a develop-
1999) and a greater emphasis on the importance of ing relationship with the individuals and groups
the empirical in bioethical deliberation. These have who belong to the milieu being explored that the
taken a number of different forms and have ranged researcher enters ever-more deeply—psychologi-
from pleas for empirical evidence to enrich philo- cally and interpersonally, as well as intellec-
sophical medical ethics (Hope, 1999) to those for tually—into its social structure and culture and
fully integrated hermeneutic approaches (Widder- the experiences, personae, and lives of those who
shoven, 2006). In this paper, I take as my focus people it. (Fox, 2004, p. 314).
arguments for the development of ethnographic The epistemological claim here is that it is
approaches to bioethics (Bosk, 1999, 2001; Davis, possible to understand what is involved for people
1991; Jennings, 1990; Kleinman, 1997, 1999). An themselves, i.e. to perceive local ‘webs of signifi-
example of this is Kleinman’s (1999) demand for the cance’ (Geertz, 1973) by spending significant ex-
incorporation of ethnographic methods into tended periods of time in the setting: participating,
bioethics in which he argues that bioethics lacks talking to people, observing what goes on, studying
what Geertz (1973), following Ryle (1971), calls documentary sources, exploring the meaningful
‘thick description’. In its most common forms, even roles of material objects, and collecting other
in many of those informed by empirical research, meaningful features of the setting. In short, through
Kleinman argues, bioethics fails to take seriously participant observation. In achieving this, the
the importance of the local realities within which ethnographer relies (to some extent) upon the
people, including patients, families and doctors everyday epistemological skills of social actors.
actually live and practice. This is an important
failing, because for Kleinman, following Geertz and Fortunately, the capacities we have developed as
Ryle, it is meaning that counts in the analysis of social actors can give us such access. As
such realities. participant observers we can learn the culture
or subculture of the people we are studying. We
The concept of culture I espouse, [y] is can come to interpret the world in the same way
essentially a semiotic one. Believing, with Max as they do, and thereby learn to understand their
Weber, that man is an animal suspended in webs behaviour in a different way to that in which
ARTICLE IN PRESS
2250 M. Parker / Social Science & Medicine 65 (2007) 2248–2259

natural scientists set about understanding the ing that the moral is more important than the
behaviour of physical phenomena. (Hammersley ethical. Indeed, in his own writing he places a great
& Atkinson, 2006, p. 8). deal of emphasis on the ethical and the application
of ‘universal standards’, e.g. in his critique of
In these ways it is argued, by Kleinman and
practices in Rwanda and Bosnia. His point in
others, ethnographers and through them bioethi-
highlighting the distinction is to draw attention to a
cists, can begin to get a ‘thick’ sense of the worlds of
methodological problem faced by bioethics, and to
the social actors under consideration.
the contribution moral ethnography might make to
Much of the situated rationality of interest to
overcome it. He argues that in order to be coherent
ethnographers will of course itself be moral. For
and adequate to its task, bioethics needs to develop
when an ethnographer studies kinship relations, the
both a method for ‘accounting for local moral
role of ‘gifts’, ‘signals of regard’, and so on, these
experience and a method of applying ethical
will in very many cases be productive, implicitly or
deliberation’ (Kleinman, 1999, p. 69, emphasis
explicitly, of entitlements, obligations, rights, duties,
mine) and sees this as a challenge bioethics will
or more nebulously of conceptions of what it means
only be able to meet if it incorporates complemen-
to live well. Indeed, Kleinman argues that local
tary ethnographic methods.
experiences are fundamentally moral (Kleinman,
1997, pp. 44–45). [y] bioethics is confronted with an extraordina-
rily difficult quandary: how to reconcile the
Why moral? Because they consist of the con- clearly immense differences in the social and
testations and compromises that actualize values personal realities of moral life with the need to
both for collectives and for individuals. Indeed, apply a universal standard to those fragments of
the individual-collective dichotomy is overdone; experience that can foster not only comparison
within these social processes values are nego- and evaluation but also action. For philosophers,
tiated and reworked among others in a space that the gulf between the universal and the particular
is thoroughly intersubjective. (Kleinman, 1999, may be regarded as an irksome and a perennial
p. 2—my emphasis). barrier; but bioethicists, like clinicians and policy
implementers, simply cannot function without
The value of ethnography, Kleinman argues, is
finding a way of relating ethical deliberation to
that it offers methods for coming to understand and
local [moral] contexts (Kleinman, 1999, p. 70).
make sense of these moral experiences, fragmentary
and lacking in coherence as they may be, from Bioethics, Kleinman argues, must become cap-
within, because it provides methods of entering into able of taking both local, networked, moral
these social spaces. And if the subject matter of experience and universal, transcendent ethical
ethnography is taken, as Kleinman argues it must ‘standards’ into account (Kleinman 1999, pp. 1,
be, to be the actualisation of values in the everyday 69), and his call for a complementary and con-
situated negotiations of meanings, then all ethno- structive relationship between bioethics and ethno-
graphy is, in effect, to be conceptualised as moral graphy is intended to lead to the development of a
ethnography (see also Dzur, 2002). methodologically coherent and empirically rich
Having placed particular emphasis on the ethno- approach to the ethical and moral dimensions of
grapher’s grasp of local moral practices, Kleinman medicine and health care.
goes on to introduce a distinction between the The positing of a complementarity between
ethnographer’s concern with the moral on the one bioethics and ethnography is not unproblematic as
hand and the bioethicist’s concern with the ethical a response to the separation of the ethical and
on the other. The use of this distinction is empirical however, because it rests upon the very
interesting. For him, whilst the moral consists of bifurcation it is intended to resolve. Bioethics and
the actual commitments, compromises and practices ethnography can only be coherently conceptualised
by means of which social participants negotiate as complementary and bioethics only be said to be in
what is at stake locally, ethics (the concern of the need of ethnography, insofar as disciplinary distinc-
bioethicist) is a universalising, principled or codified tions are held to exist between those concerned with
body of abstract knowledge about the definition the ethical and those concerned with the moral and
and realisation of the good. (Kleinman, 1997, p. 45) insofar as they can be considered to be concerned
In making this distinction, Kleinman is not suggest- with radically different objects. There are a number
ARTICLE IN PRESS
M. Parker / Social Science & Medicine 65 (2007) 2248–2259 2251

of reasons for being sceptical of these distinctions. practices and commitments (even if these are
Firstly, practice in ethnography has throughout its practices of contestation)—must inevitably fail to
history been explicitly or implicitly ‘ethical’. capture the ethico-moral complexity of forms of
Whether in the sense that it was associated with a everyday life in which consideration of ‘the values,
‘body of abstract knowledge held by experts about rules of conduct and character traits which are
‘the good’ and ways to realise it’ (Kleinman 1997, involved in right action, doing good, and living well’
p. 45); in its associations with colonialism (Pels, plays a significant role and in which local experi-
1999); or more recently in its perception of itself as ences are fundamentally ethico-moral (Ashcroft,
having a duty to represent or to ensure a voice to 2007). What this suggests is that a more interesting,
marginalised or vulnerable groups (Scheper- productive and plausible way to conceptualise the
Hughes, 1995). In this respect, ethnography has relationship between ethics and morals might be to
always embodied the ethical in the nature of its think of the moral as the commonly shared,
approach to the moral (Pels, 1999; van der Scheer & normalised practices and values which structure
Widdershoven, 2004). What this suggests is that, everyday life, and the ethical as constituted by
whatever else the incorporation of ethnography into situations in which, and by the extent to which, the
bioethics might do, it cannot be coherently con- moral is seen to be problematic, contested, in need
ceptualised as the complementing of ethical delib- of deliberation, analysis, or critique. Something like
eration with (non-ethical) empirical, moral, this account, to which I return later in this paper, in
richness. which the ethical is conceptualised as the enactment
Second, and relatedly, as Geertz makes clear, of the moral as problematic, i.e. as an object of
ethnography is in its very methodological self- concern, has the advantage of making possible a
understanding, a fundamentally interpretive enter- richer account of both morality and of ethics, and of
prise and for this reason too what it brings to the interplay between them and also has the
bioethics cannot be disentangled from values or advantage of making visible the fact that ethics is
ethics (Geertz, 1973). This is at least part of the itself enacted in practices. On this account, the
point intended to be captured by the concept of methodological problem of how best to understand
‘reflexivity’. the relationship between the moral and the ethical
becomes one shared by both the bioethicist and the
Reflexivity [y] implies that the orientations of
ethnographer, and not one for the bioethicist alone
researchers will be shaped by their socio-histor-
(Parker, 2007).
ical locations, including the values and interests
Thus, whilst Kleinmann is surely right to call for
that these locations confer upon them. What this
activity at the interface between bioethics and
represents is a rejection of the idea that social
ethnography, whatever ethnography brings to the
research is, or can be, carried out in some
table will not come free of ethics, values or morals.
autonomous realm that is insulated from the
Ethnography is, like bioethics, a practice situated in
wider society and from the particular biography
and concerned with ethico-moral ‘webs of signifi-
of the researchery. (Hammersley & Atkinson,
cance’. The incorporation of ethnography into
2006, p. 16).
bioethics will therefore not be coherently achieved
Thirdly, what the two problems above reveal is by conceptualising this as the complementing of
that the conceptualisation of the situated rationality ethical deliberation with empirical richness. Any
of local experience and of practices as fundamen- coherent response to the problem of how to
tally moral, and of the epistemological role of the understand the enfolding of ethics and morals will
ethnographer in terms of the description of these involve the generation of new ethico-ethnographic
moral practices, is itself deeply problematic. In methods for the investigation of genuinely ethico-
particular, the description of culture as fundamen- moral objects (Law & Urry, 2002).
tally moral is too thin. For many cultures, even that
of the culture of ethnography (as the concept of The ethics of ethnography
reflexivity shows), will involve and in some cases be
constituted by, interplay between the moral and the I began by considering calls for the use of
ethical. The identification of the empirical with the ethnography to complement bioethics. In what
moral—where the moral itself is identified with follows I explore moves in the opposite direction,
relatively unproblematic day-to-day normalised i.e. calls for increasing attention to be paid to the
ARTICLE IN PRESS
2252 M. Parker / Social Science & Medicine 65 (2007) 2248–2259

ethical dimensions of ethnographic research. These majority has however focused on the inadequacy of
have arisen both out of internal debate within the medical model that ethnographers have been
anthropology and from developments outside of the forced to follow and in particular its concept of
discipline. From inside, the theoretical and regula- informed consent as a mechanism for respecting and
tory turn to ethics has arisen out of the growing protecting the interests of those with whom the
realisation that anthropology’s own history has research is to be carried out. The concerns
been value-driven (by colonialism, by the obliga- ethnographers have about informed consent are
tions of ‘representation’ and so on), and that largely related to the fact that it has tended to be
ethnographic research has implications for the interpreted in anticipatory terms, i.e. based on the
communities it studies. The ethical turn in anthro- idea that implications of the research, its methodol-
pology has also been driven by important cultural ogy and research questions can be anticipated,
shifts outside the discipline, notably by develop- discussed and agreed to before the research has
ments in the regulation of medicine and medical begun. Strathern, for example, has argued that this
research. Changes in medicine have had profound is itself unethical.
and wide-ranging implications for research in other This could, I suggest, hold a new way of being
disciplines, including anthropology. The Nurem- demeaning to informants. It pushes the explora-
burg Code and the Declaration of Helsinki, for tory, indeterminate and unpredictable nature of
example, which were developed because of concerns social relations (between ethnographer and his or
about medical research, have led to a broad her third party) back onto a ‘point of produc-
expectation that all researchers, whatever their tion’, with the ethnographer as initiator. How-
discipline, should submit their research protocols ever much talk there is of collaboration or of
for consideration by an ethics committee (Strathern, conserving the autonomy of subjects or recogniz-
2000a, p. 294). The form of the ethical turn in ing their input into the research or taking power
anthropology (and other disciplines) has also been into account, this aspect of ethics in advance, of
affected by the substantive ethical issues arising in anticipate negotiations, belittles the creative
medical ethics, primarily the need to obtain power of social relations. (Strathern, 2000a,
‘informed consent’ from research participants. p. 295).
Driven to some extent by each of these sets of
It is important to recognise that such concerns do
forces, increasing attention has been given to the
not arise because ethnographers consider consent to
ethics of ethnography by professional associations
be unimportant. Indeed, ethnographers have, as
and funding bodies relevant to ethnographic re-
evidenced by the growing literature in this area,
search (Fluehr-Lobban, 2003). For example, the
become increasingly preoccupied with the need to
American Anthropological Association, British
involve, respect and appropriately represent host
Sociological Association, Association of Social
communities, and with the ethical dimensions of the
Anthropology of the UK and the Commonwealth,
discipline more broadly. The problem with many
and the Economic and Social Research Council,
professional codes, and with the deliberations of
have all in recent years developed codes of ethics or
many ethics committees for ethnographers, is that
ethical ‘frameworks’ (American Anthropological
they fail to recognise that consent needs to be
Association, 1998; Association of Social Anthro-
thought of differently in ethnography, where the
pologists of the UK and the Commonwealth, 1999;
research undertaken is based upon the tentative
British Sociological Association, 2002; Economic
development of research questions and analysis in
and Social Research Council, 2006). There has been
the context of emergent relationships of trust. At the
a great deal of resistance in anthropology to the
heart of these concerns is a belief that within the
development of professional codes of ethics how-
context of ethnography the obtaining of consent
ever and to the idea that ethnographic research
from those with whom the research is to be pursued
should be subject to ethical review by ethics
must involve developmental and creative processes
committees on the same terms as other forms of
incompatible with the concept of anticipatory
research (Pels, 1999). Some such resistance has
informed consent.
focused on claims that the harms associated with
ethnographic research are nothing like of the same Ethnographic consent is a relational and sequen-
order as those associated with clinical research in tial process rather than a contractual agreement
medicine (Murphy & Dingwall, 2007, p. 8). The and lasts throughout the period of research. [y]
ARTICLE IN PRESS
M. Parker / Social Science & Medicine 65 (2007) 2248–2259 2253

Typically, at the start of such research, consent is agreement’. The social spaces within which negotia-
both tentative and limited and the researcher’s tion about what matters locally takes place and
access to sensitive aspects of the setting may be within which cultural conflicts are resolved are
restricted. Over time, as the trust between the precisely those which are presupposed by the
researcher and host develops, access may be ethnographer to be radically different between
granted to previously restricted areas or interac- cultures and in need of interpretation on the basis
tions. (Murphy & Dingwall, 2007, p. 5). of extended research. These two points are not
unrelated of course, partly because both concern the
Increasingly, ethnographers have argued that possibility of emerging understanding and of shared
appropriate consent can only be achieved through meanings about what it means to carry out ethical
an ongoing and developmental negotiation of the research, but also because taken together they make
relationship between researcher and research hosts. it clear that what is under negotiation, that is
[y] we need an investigation of the possibility of ‘ethics’, will be shaped by the how of negotiation,
an emergent ethics, one which is no longer tied to that is ‘method’, and vice versa.
a specific community (such as a professional In the first section of this paper, I argued that the
association) but which locates ethical discussion coherent incorporation of ethnography into
in the negotiation of individual or communal bioethics could not simply be thought of as the
interests that is characteristic of the practice complementing of ethical deliberation with empiri-
of fieldwork. (Pels, 2000; in Strathern, 2000b, cal richness, but had to be seen as requiring both the
p. 163). development of new forms of ethico-ethnographic
knowledge production and the reconceptualisation
The concept of ‘negotiation’ is not unproblematic of the relationship between the ethical and the
as a basis for the identification and addressing of moral. In this second section, I have reached a
ethical issues in ethnography however. One reason similar conclusion in response to calls for the
for this is that, given the emphasis in ethnography incorporation of ethics into ethnography. An
on cultural difference, the call for negotiation begs adequate and appropriate approach to both the
the question of the extent to which the meaning of ethnography of ethics and the ethics of ethnography
what is being negotiated can in fact be established will be one which acknowledges that, in the
prior to the completion of the research. This is an negotiations between researcher and researched, it
important methodological consideration, for if the is not going to be possible to separate the what of
purpose of negotiation between the researcher and negotiation from its how. Negotiation requires the
the researched is to reach agreement about what is actualisation of values in an intersubjective project
to constitute ethical research practice, it will be of making moral sense where the object of the
essential for some degree of intersubjective agree- research, its method, and its ethics will be up for
ment to be possible about what is meant by, for grabs.
example, an ‘ethical consideration’. The ethno-
graphic assumption that understanding is not The liminal and the duplex
possible without thick description means that, from
within this practice, the possibility of negotiation Anthropologists have sometimes theorised ethno-
about ‘ethics’ cannot be taken for granted. That is, graphy as a ‘liminal’ discipline positioned astride, or
it is not easy to see how the ethnographer (or the perhaps creating, a threshold between two moral
member of the community hosting the research) can cultures. (Fluehr-Lobban, 2000, p. 2; Hammersley
be confident about just what it is that is under & Atkinson, 2006; Kleinman, 1999).
negotiation. A further and complementary reason
why the concept of a negotiational solution to the Ethnography is a method of knowledge produc-
problem of ethics in ethnography is problematic is tion by which the ethnographer enters into the
because in addition to it being unclear what exactly ordinary, everyday space of moral processes in a
is being negotiated, it is also going to be difficult for local world. The ethnographer, no matter how
the parties to be confident about the meaning of the successful she is in participant observation, either
processes of negotiation themselves. That is, it is not is or becomes an outsider- even if she begins as an
going to be clear, for any of the parties concerned, indigenous member of the community she
what it means for the other to ‘negotiate’ and ‘reach studies. She feels the tug of local obligations
ARTICLE IN PRESS
2254 M. Parker / Social Science & Medicine 65 (2007) 2248–2259

and the push of local practices, but for all of that negotiation of ethics cannot be separated from
she is never so completely absorbed by what is questions of methodology.
most at stake for community members that their
The fusion of ethics and method [y] seems to
world of experience is entirely hers. (Kleinman,
promise to constitute the scientific subject as an
1999, p. 5).
ethical one immediately, rather than by proxy
The implications of the arguments presented thus that entails a tendency to dissemble the expert
far are that the concept of ‘liminality’, when thought ‘self’ from the practice of research as such.
of as ‘standing at the threshold between two worlds’ (Meskell & Pels, 2005, p. 23).
does not go far enough towards capturing the Whilst Pels’ duplex position comes closer than
productive implications of folding ethics and that of liminality to resolving the relationship
ethnography together. In response to something between ethics and ethnography in ways compatible
like these considerations, Pels (Meskell & Pels, 2005; with the arguments discussed above, the concept of
Pels, 2005) argues for a more radical position than ‘duplexity’ also has significant limitations as a way
that of liminality, one he refers to as duplexity (Pels, of theorising the folding together of ethnography
1999). and ethics. For, whilst Pels’ intention is to replace
Like the archaeologists confronted with a Hopi the disciplinary separation of ethics and ethnogra-
scholar telling them a story with a moral, phy with an emergent ethico-ethnographic method
ethnographers are bound to acknowledge the grounded in negotiation, he attempts to do so whilst
moral ‘duplexity’ of research: the fact that holding on to the methodological centrality of
engagement with people living in one’s field of radical cultural difference. This means that in the
study requires one to negotiate ‘other’ values end, the concept of duplexity merely re-describes the
instead of implicitly assuming that our principles problem.
of ethics and expertise are universal. (Meskell & [y] the primary moral engagement of fieldwork
Pels, 2005, p. 8). is the negotiation of different moral complexes
An ethnographic role is duplex for Pels when it with each other. The necessity of living with
requires not only acknowledgment of the ethical double standards—in duplexity signifies a moral
dimensions of the positioning of ethnography, but topography of differences that pertains every-
also recognition of the fact that what must be where—not only among Yanomami but also
negotiated in cross-cultural encounters is both the when we study a biogenics company, participate
ethics of the research and its modes of knowledge in the definition of an archaeological site, or try
production. Duplexity suggests that a resolution of to get used to the linguistic conventions of an
the problem of enfolding ethics and ethnography in internal review board [y]. (Meskell & Pels, 2005,
research is only to be found in the intersubjective pp. 93–94).
and interdisciplinary negotiation of what such [y] I want to argue that since the late 19th
research is to become. century anthropology’s epistemological commit-
ment to cultural difference has made its morals
Thus, we have come full circle: rethinking ethics essentially duplex: without duplicitous intention
implies rethinking expertise, and that implies or moral corruption, anthropologists cannot but
rethinking modernity as well: as something that adopt ‘double standards. (Pels, 1999, p. 102).
emanates not from ‘us’ but from interaction. We
should locate ethics not in a Kantian, lawlike The arguments of the second part of this paper
universal nor in the postmodernist ‘moral self’ regarding the necessary conditions for meaningful
whose ethical relation to the elusive other we can negotiation show that it is not going to be possible
only take on trust, but in concrete practise of to take ethics seriously without also putting the
interaction with others. (Meskell & Pels, 2005, commitment to difference at risk. For any resolu-
pp. 8–9). tion of the relationship between ethics and ethno-
graphy will involve the problematising of both
The duplex role is then, for Pels, one in which ethics and method in an intersubjective commitment
there is an interactive fusion of ethics and method in to making moral and methodological sense across
the intersubjective and interdisciplinary actualisa- difference. This implies the possibility of an
tion of the values of research, and in which the emergent-shared understanding about both ethics
ARTICLE IN PRESS
M. Parker / Social Science & Medicine 65 (2007) 2248–2259 2255

and method in which each is shaped by the other. difference at risk. Just as it proved impossible to
That is, it is an approach in which the ‘creative import ethnography into ethics without changing
power of social relations’ is reaffirmed (Strathern, both the method and its object, so too has it proved
2000a, p. 295). This is not to suggest that difference in relation to the importing of ethics into ethno-
is unimportant. It is to argue however, that in the graphy. The importing of ethics, as negotiation, into
enfolding of ethics and ethnography something new ethnographic research turns such research into an
and shared is created and this requires that the intervention involving the negotiation of ethics and
interplay between researcher and researched be method with the research hosts and this is an
conceptualised not simply as the resultant of the intervention in which it is not going to be possible to
combination of differences nor simply as the avoid cross-cultural engagement with concepts such
recognition and valuing of difference, but rather as those listed above.
as involving the joint creation of something new.
It would be difficult to overestimate the metho- Ethics as an object of concern
dological impact of the concept of negotiation in
this context. For in addition to emphasising the I have argued that the folding together of the
creative power of social relations across difference, ethical and the empirical requires the development
it also brings with it another significant challenge. of new ethico-ethnographic methods for the inves-
The challenge arises because the shared under- tigation of ethico-moral objects. I have conceptua-
standings required for negotiation to work as the lised the moral as those commonly shared, relatively
mode of engagement at the heart of ethical research normalised moral practices which constitute and
practice will themselves be in large measure ethical. structure everyday life and have conceptualised the
When ethnographers call for a negotiational ethical as practices in which the moral is enacted as
approach to ethics (rather than one based in problematic or as the subject of deliberation,
professional codes, or in abstract principles), they arguing that many cultural practices will involve
implicitly acknowledge that there are non-negotia- interplay between the ethical and the moral. This
tional methods by which ethico-methodological means that research which enfolds the ethical and
issues might be resolved. This raises the question the ethnographic will take the enactment of ethics
of just what it is that makes negotiation better than and the interplay between ethics and morals as its
other available approaches to ethical research objects. One of the most distinctive features of
practice in ethnography, and this is an ethical ethics on this definition is that it is enacted as an
question. Whilst this paper is not the place to object of concern. As such, ethics involves the
pursue this discussion very far, it is clear that the enactment of moral practices as problematic,
call for negotiation is only going to be capable of worrying, the subject of deliberation and of
doing the work required of it in association within a potential revision. This means that ethics is an
constellation of other ethical concepts. What does it object the enactment of which opens up practice and
mean to say that an anthropologist should negotiate makes new kinds of encounters with experience
with her host community? Would the threat of possible.
violence if the host community did not cooperate That ethics is enacted in practices implies that the
with the research constitute negotiation? If not, mapping of the enactment of ethics as an object of
what is it that marks the significant difference concern and of the interplay between the ethical and
between the threat of violence and negotiation? At the moral will involve the tracking of the forms, uses
this point some kind of cross-cultural engagement and trajectories of this object over time and across
with thick ethical (rather than moral) concepts such practices-the mapping of its biographies (Appadur-
as ‘recognition’, ‘respect’, ‘suffering’, ‘justice’, and ai, 1986; Kopytoff, 1986). The enactment of ethics
‘dignity’ begins to look unavoidable for the as an object of concern in research folding together
possibility of any ethico-ethnography. And if ethics and ethnography will therefore be an object
concepts such as these are to be capable of characterised by movement.
delineating the ethical conditions for ethico-ethno- I have also argued that research enfolding the
graphic method, they must be capable of moving ethical and the ethnographic will be characterised
across cultural and practice boundaries. And for by the creative, intersubjective negotiation of
this to be possible, they must be a very special kind method and ethics by the researcher and the
of object. They must be capable of putting researched. This has the implication that such
ARTICLE IN PRESS
2256 M. Parker / Social Science & Medicine 65 (2007) 2248–2259

research will take the methodological form of an other ethical issues to those initially presented. Since
intervention, a cross-cultural engagement in which it began, the Genethics Club has seen approximately
the creative power of social relations is realised and 150 case presentations.
in which difference is put at risk. What this also My (the ethicist’s) role in the Genethics Club has
means is that ethico-ethnographic research of the been multi-faceted. Perhaps most importantly, I
kind proposed in this paper will not be research have been responsible for the continued mainte-
which attempts to hide in the background but will nance of the Genethics Club as a welcoming social
involve researcher and researched in the joint space for the enactment of ethics as an object of
enactment of and deliberative engagement with concern across multiple genetics practices in a
ethics as an object of concern. It suggests, that is, number of different locations. I have organised the
a research intervention which is itself implicated space to allow sufficient time for the presentation of
(explicitly) in the enactment of the moral as the cases. I have facilitated the subsequent discus-
problematic, i.e. as ethical. This points to a sion, ensuring that all who want to speak have a
particularly creative and productive use of reflex- chance to do so. I have tried to ensure that marginal
ivity, and of a singularly interesting form of research voices and perspectives are heard and taken
encounter (Fortun, 2000; Fortun & Fortun, 2005) seriously. I have used my knowledge of the
for the enactment and tracking of ethics as an object literature, my experience of previous Genethics
of concern. Club meetings, and my experience of work in a
I briefly referred, at the beginning of this paper, to genetics unit, to introduce issues and contrasting
a particular research experience of my own, the practices I think have been overlooked. I have
Genethics Club. In this concluding section I want to adopted a methodologically critical stance to
offer a preliminary sketch of how the Genethics established practices. In other words, I have
Club-and, specifically, my participation in and implicated myself in the enactment of the moral as
analysis of it-exemplifies the potential for ethico- problematic. At the same time, I have taken notes
ethnographic research of the type I have been and attempted to map and track the enactment of
discussing. ethics as an object of concern over the course of a
When the Genethics Club was established in meeting, and over the life of the Genethics Club,
2001, its aim was to provide a social space in which bearing in mind that my role is deeply implicated in
anyone working in clinical genetics in the United the enactment of ethics in this setting.
Kingdom, including nurses, counsellors, doctors, I conclude by commenting briefly on some of the
laboratory staff, and medical researchers, could features of ethics as an object of concern as it has
present and discuss ethical issues arising in their been enacted in the Genethics Club.
practice (www.genethicsclub.org). The clinical mod- One of the things that has become apparent as an
el for this intervention was the Dysmorphology on-going theme throughout the discussions at the
Club, a pre-existing regular national forum for the Genethics Club is how the problematisation of
presentation and discussion of difficult clinical cases everyday practices is often linked to the spatial and/
by members of different Regional Genetics Services. or temporal distribution of material objects. While
Since its inception, the Genethics Club has met 15 in an unproblematised situation, material objects
times. It has been popular with health professionals are seamlessly woven into every day practice—
and researchers, and attended on average by 45 family pedigrees are produced, blood samples are
people, involving several hundred different atten- taken, medical records are filed away etc., in some
dees overall, and including, on a regular basis, cases the movement of these material objects into
members of every clinical genetics service and NHS different physical locations, or even the particularity
laboratory in the country. Meetings of the Gen- of their arrangement or configuration, can serve to
ethics Club involve presentations by those working problematise those practices. An example of this
in genetics of ‘cases’ that they consider to present might arise where individual medical records are
ethical issues and to be problematic, either in brought together into a ‘family file’—a file which in
themselves or in relation to their implications for addition to containing the files of a number of
practice more widely. These case presentations have individual family members, also contains informa-
tended to be rich and have been followed by open tion relating to the family as a whole, e.g. a family
discussion, facilitated by an ‘ethicist’ (the author). pedigree drawing together pieces of information
Often, the discussions open up and generate many from several of the individual files, which may as a
ARTICLE IN PRESS
M. Parker / Social Science & Medicine 65 (2007) 2248–2259 2257

result constitute information about the family as a status of the other, who has not given consent, and
whole beyond that which any single individual also because there is the potential for this twin to be
family members knows. Such a family file has the informed of their genetic status without having
potential to be of help to clinicians in their received appropriate counselling and support, for
treatment of individual family members in verifying example in the midst of a family argument. On other
diagnoses and facilitating risk assessment, but occasions, or from the perspective of a different set
where the bringing together of this information in of practitioners, this type of case is presented as an
a single overarching picture reveals information object of ethical concern on account of the issue of
relevant to the care, or life choices of an individual duty of care to the patient in front of them. This is
who has perhaps not asked for such information because, were it to be decided that the provision of
(because they do not know it exists), such files have the test depended upon the consent of both twins,
problematised everyday accepted practices around for example in cases where the second twin is
the use and storage of medical information. demanding that the test should not go ahead, this
(Ashcroft, Lucassen, Parker, Verkerk, & Widder- would in effect be to provide a third party—with
shoven, 2005; Parker & Lucassen, 2004) In other whom the doctor may also be in contact—with an
words, the transformation of a moral practice into unacceptable veto over the provision of care to the
an object of ethical concern—the enactment of patient (Parker &Lucassen, 2003). The enactment of
ethics as an object of concern—is bound up with the this object of concern from the perspective of two
spatial arrangement and movement of material different sets of practitioners gives rise to ethics as a
objects. By the exploration of such cases, the multiple object of concern.
Genethics Club serves to enrich everyone’s under- The multiplicity of ethics as an object of concern
standing of ethics as an object of concern in their means that the Genethics Club, as a space which
practice. Importantly, it does this not by comple- brings together different health professionals-
menting ethical deliberation with empirical richness, geneticists, counsellors, nurses, and laboratory
but through the enfolding of the ethical and the staff—from a wide range of locations, is inevitably
moral (every day moral practice): the analysis shows also on some occasions a space characterised by the
how ethics is an assemblage constituted by the juxtaposition of diverse ethical practices: through
organisation of material objects in specific spatial the presentation and discussion of cases which
and temporal relations. would be enacted as ethically problematic in differ-
The above case illustrates that the movement of a ent ways in different locations. One of the things
biological sample or medical record from the clinic that has become apparent as an on-going theme in
to the laboratory, or across an international border, the Genethics Club is that the multiple enactment of
may well transform the ethico-moral object drama- ethics as an object of concern, combined with
tically, and the number of possible ethical objects of awareness of the possibility of the movement of
concern has multiplied. It may also be however that patients, samples, and even health professionals
a particular configuration of materials and practices between settings, can sometimes lead to the enact-
gives rise to an ethical object of concern that is ment of this multiplicity itself as problematic. Here,
already multiple (Mol, 2002). A particularly good the Genethics Club serves to enrich everyone’s
example of this is a frequently occurring case understanding of ethics by providing a space within
presented at the Genethics Club in which a genetic which it becomes apparent that everyday moral
test requested by one patient has the potential to practices can be problematised—enacted as an
reveal the genetic status of one of their relatives. object of ethical concern—by the juxtaposition of
This might happen, for instance, where one twin divergent practices, and the associated defamiliar-
wishes to take a presymptomatic test for breast isation. In the case of the twins described above, for
cancer but the other, who is genetically identical, example, the enactment of practice as problematic
either does not wish to have their status revealed, or in one setting in a different way to its enactment as
simply does not know that the test is being problematic in another itself comes to be seen as
considered. On some occasions these cases are problematic—as an ethical object of concern.
presented as an ethical object of concern on account Awareness that patients in one setting may gain
of the issues of consent and counselling. In such access to tests and treatments not available else-
cases, clinicians see the case as problematic both where, or that patients in one area, but not in
because a test on one twin will reveal the genetic another, may be ‘tested’ without their consent, has
ARTICLE IN PRESS
2258 M. Parker / Social Science & Medicine 65 (2007) 2248–2259

problematised practice in ways that put such Acknowledgements


difference at risk. This may lead those present to
make attempts to justify the maintenance of In thinking about and writing this paper I have
diversity of practice, that is to preserve difference, benefited tremendously from conversations with
or efforts to reach agreement about which shared and comments from several people: Steve Woolgar,
practice should be adopted from now on. In either Sarah Franklin, Simon Cohn, Alison Shaw, Ri-
case, such deliberations must involve the enactment chard Ashcroft, Bronwyn Parry, Sue Dopson, Mary
of ethical objects capable of moving across bound- Dixon-Woods, and above all, Mariam Fraser. The
aries between practices—between different clinics Genethics Club is organised by Angus Clarke, Tara
for example, or between the clinic and the labora- Clancy, Fiona Douglas, Ian Ellis, Anneke Lucassen,
tory—and this involves cross-cultural engagement and Michael Parker.
with thick ethical objects such as ‘justice’, ‘suffer-
ing’, ‘fairness’, ‘reciprocity’, ‘duty of care’ and so on
References
in something like the ways I discussed in the
previous section. A related on-going theme emer- American Anthropological Association. (1998). Code of Ethics of
ging from the Genethics Club is that, once enacted the American Anthropological Association. /http://www.
in relation to a particular case, such moving objects aaanet.org/committees/ethic/ethcode.htmS (Accessed 1/10/06).
can go on to put unproblematised practice and Appadurai, A. (Ed.). (1986). The social life of things: Commodities
difference elsewhere at risk, exerting an influence in cultural perspective. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
well beyond the ‘case’ under consideration. This Ashcroft, R. (2007). Ethical issues in statistical genetics. In D.J.
makes possible another way in which the Genethics Balding, M.J. Bishop & C. Cannings (Eds.), Encyclopedia of
Club serves to enrich understanding of ethics as an statistical genetics (3rd ed.). Chichester: Wiley; in press.
object of concern in genetics—through the delib- Ashcroft, R., Lucassen, A., Parker, M., Verkerk, M., &
erative exploration of the relationships between Widdershoven, G. (2005). Case analysis in clinical ethics.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
these moving objects and previously unproblematic Association of Social Anthropologists of the UK and the
practice. In such explorations, both the practices Commonwealth. (1999). Ethical guidelines for good research
and the mobile ethical objects of concern are put at practice. London: Association of Social Anthropologists of
risk and the creative power of social relations the UK and the Commonwealth. /http://www.theasa.org/
provides an opportunity for the opening up of ethics/ethics_guidelines.htmS (Accessed 1/10/06).
Bosk, C. (1999). Professional ethicist available: logical, secular,
practice, making new kinds of encounters with expe- friendly. Daedalus, 128, 47–68.
rience, and the emergence of new practices, possible. Bosk, C. (2001). Irony, ethnography, and informed consent. In
B. Hoffmaster (Ed.), Bioethics in social context (pp. 199–220).
Conclusion Philadelphia: Temple University Press.
British Sociological Association. (2002). Statement of ethical
practice. London: British Sociological Association. /http://
In this paper, I have investigated the implications www.britsoc.co.uk/equality/63.htmS (Accessed 1/10/06).
of folding together the ethical and the empirical in Davis, D. S. (1991). Rich cases: The ethics of thick description.
research. I began by considering pleas for the Hastings Center Report, 21(4), 12–17.
integration of ethnographic methods in bioethics, DeVries, R. G. (1995). Toward a sociology of bioethics.
and argued that approaches which see the ethical Qualitative Sociology, 18(1), 119–128.
Dzur, A. (2002). Democratizing the hospital: Deliberative-
and the empirical as ‘complementary’ are not able democratic bioethics. Journal of Health Politics, Policy and
to do justice to the methodological implications of Law, 27(2), 177–211.
enfolding the ethical and the ethnographic. I then Economic and Social Research Council. (2006). Research ethics
went on to consider calls for the integration of ethics framework. /http://www.esrcsocietytoday.ac.uk/ESRCInfo-
into ethnography and argued here too that the Centre/Images/ESRC_Re_Ethics_Frame_tcm6-11291.pdfS
(Accessed 1/10/06).
enfolding of the ethical and the empirical requires Fluehr-Lobban, C. (2000). Globalization of research and inter-
the development of new methods. The folding national standards of ethics in anthropology. Annals of the
together of the ethical and the empirical requires New York Academy of Sciences, 925, 37.
the development of new ethico-ethnographic meth- Fluehr-Lobban, C. (2003). Ethics and the profession of anthro-
pology: Dialogue for ethically conscious practice (2nd ed.).
ods for the investigation of ethico-moral objects. In
Walnut Creek: AltaMira Press.
the paper’s concluding section, I explored the Fortun, M. (2000). Experiments in ethnography and its
implications of these arguments for research prac- performance, /http://www.mannvernd.is/english/articles/
tice, using The Genethics Club as an example. mfortun.htmlS (Accessed 9.02.07).
ARTICLE IN PRESS
M. Parker / Social Science & Medicine 65 (2007) 2248–2259 2259

Fortun, K., & Fortun, M. (2005). Scientific imaginaries and Murphy, E., & Dingwall, R. (2007). Informed consent and
ethical plateaus in contemporary US toxicology. American ethnographic practice (contribution to special issue of SSM
Anthropologist, 107(1), 43–54. 2007).
Fox, R. C. (1976). Advanced medical technology—social and Parker, M. (2007). Deliberative bioethics. In R. E. Ashcroft, A.
ethical implications. Annual Review of Sociology, 2, 231–268. Dawson, H. Draper, & J. R. McMillan (Eds.), Principles of
Fox, R. C. (2004). Observations and reflections of a perpetual health care ethics (2nd ed., pp. 185–191). Chichester: Wiley.
fieldworker. Annals of the American Academy(595), 309–326. Parker, M., & Lucassen, A. (2003). Concern for individuals and
Geertz, C. (1973). The interpretation of cultures. New York: Basic families in clinical genetics. Journal of Medical Ethics, 29,
Books. 70–73.
Hammersley, M., & Atkinson, P. (2006). Ethnography: Principles Parker, M., & Lucassen, A. (2004). Genetic information: a joint
in practice. London: Routledge. account? British Medical Journal, 329, 165–167.
Hoffmaster, B. (1992). Can ethnography save the life of medical Pels, P. (1999). Professions of duplexity: A prehistory of ethical
ethics? Social Science & Medicine, 35(12), 1421–1432. codes in anthropology. Current Anthropology, 40(2), 101–136.
Hoffmaster, B. (Ed.). (2001). Bioethics in social context. Pels, P. (2000). The trickster’s dilemma: Ethics and the
Philadelphia: Temple University Press. technologies of the anthropological self. In M. Strathern
Hope, T. (1999). Empirical medical ethics. Journal of Medical (Ed.), Audit culture: Anthropological studies in accountability,
Ethics(25), 219–220. ethics, and the academy (pp. 135–170). London: Routledge.
Jennings, B. (1990). Ethics and ethnography in neo-natal Pels, P. (2005). ‘‘Where there aren’t no ten commandments’’:
intensive care. In G. Weisz (Ed.), Social science perspectives Redefining ethics during the darkness in El Dorado scandal.
on medical ethics. Philadelphia: University of Philadelphia In L. Meskell, & P. Pels (Eds.), Embedding ethics (pp. 69–99).
Press. Oxford: Berg.
Kleinman, A. (1997). Writing at the margin: Discourse between Ryle, G. (Ed.), (1971). The thinking of thoughts: What is ‘le
anthropology and medicine. Berkeley: University of California Penseur’ doing? In Collected papers II: collected essays,
Press. London: Hutchinson; pp. 1929–1968.
Kleinman, A. (1999). Moral experience and ethical reflection: Scheper-Hughes, N. (1995). The primacy of the ethical: Proposi-
Can ethnography reconcile them? A quandary for ‘the new tions for a militant anthropology. Current Anthropology,
bioethics’. Daedalus, 128(4), 69–97 (Fall 1999). 36(3), 409–440.
Kopytoff, I. (1986). The cultural biography of things: Commo- Strathern, M. (Ed.), (2000a). Accountabilityy and ethnography.
ditization as process. In A. Appadurai (Ed.), The social life In Audit culture: anthropological studies in accountability,
of things: Commodities in cultural perspective. Cambridge: ethics, and the academy. London: Routledge; pp. 279–304
Cambridge University Press. Strathern, M. (Ed.). (2000b). Audit culture: anthropological
Law, J., & Urry, J. (2002). Enacting the social. Department of studies in accountability, ethics, and the academy. London:
Sociology and Centre for Science Studies, Lancaster Uni- Routledge.
versity. /http://www.comp.lancs.ac.uk/sociology/papers/ van der Scheer, L., & Widdershoven, G. (2004). Integrated
Law-Urry-Enacting-the-Social.pdfS (Accessed 13/2/07). empirical ethics: loss of normativity? Medicine, Health Care
Meskell, L., & Pels, P. (Eds.). (2005). Embedding ethics. Oxford: and Philosophy(7), 71–79.
Berg. Widdershoven, G. (2006). How to combine hermeneutics and
Mol, A. (2002). The body multiple: Ontology in medical practice. wide reflective equilibrium? Medicine, Health Care and
Durham: Duke University Press. Philosophy(10), 49–52.

You might also like