You are on page 1of 29

pdf version of the entry

Cancer
https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2019/entries/cancer/ Cancer
from the Summer 2019 Edition of the First published Tue May 7, 2019; substantive revision Wed Jun 19, 2019

Stanford Encyclopedia Cancer is a worldwide epidemic. It is the first or second leading cause of
death before age 70 in ninety-one countries, as of 2015. According to the
of Philosophy International Agency for Research on Cancer, “there will be an estimated
18.1 million new cancer cases and 9.6 million cancer deaths in 2018,” and
cancer is expected to be the “leading cause of death in every country of the
world in the 21st century” (Bray, et al. 2018). While overall cancer
mortality has declined in the U.S. annually since 2005, progress has been
slow in some cases, and mortality is rising in others. In particular, “death
Edward N. Zalta Uri Nodelman Colin Allen R. Lanier Anderson
rates rose from 2010 to 2014 by almost 3% per year for liver cancer and
Principal Editor Senior Editor Associate Editor Faculty Sponsor
by about 2% per year for uterine cancer,” and, “pancreatic cancer death
Editorial Board
https://plato.stanford.edu/board.html rates continued to increase slightly (by 0.3% per year) in men” (Siegel, et
al. 2017). Perhaps not surprisingly, then, cancer is a central topic of
Library of Congress Catalog Data
ISSN: 1095-5054
biomedical research, drawing millions of federal dollars annually. In 2019,
the U.S. National Cancer Institute (NCI) will allocate $5.74 billion in
Notice: This PDF version was distributed by request to mem- federal dollars, a $79 million increase over 2018 (NCI, 2019—see the
bers of the Friends of the SEP Society and by courtesy to SEP Other Internet Resources). A search for the term “cancer” in PubMed
content contributors. It is solely for their fair use. Unauthorized returns over three million hits.
distribution is prohibited. To learn how to join the Friends of the
SEP Society and obtain authorized PDF versions of SEP entries, Despite this, cancer—and scientific research on cancer—has received
please visit https://leibniz.stanford.edu/friends/ . relatively little attention from philosophers of science. However, this is
starting to change, as cancer, and scientific research on cancer, raises a
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
Copyright c 2019 by the publisher variety of compelling philosophical questions. This entry will focus on
The Metaphysics Research Lab four topics, which philosophers of science have begun to explore and
Center for the Study of Language and Information
debate.
Stanford University, Stanford, CA 94305
Cancer First, scientific classifications of cancer have as yet failed to yield a unified
c 2019 by the author
Copyright
Anya Plutynski taxonomy. There is a diversity of classificatory schemes for cancer, and
All rights reserved.
while some are hierarchical, others appear to be “cross-cutting,” or non-
Copyright policy: https://leibniz.stanford.edu/friends/info/copyright/

1
Cancer Anya Plutynski

nested. Initially, researchers investigating cancer genomics seemed to Third, cancer is in part a byproduct of our developmental and life history,
think such issues might be resolved by molecular “subtyping”. However, as well as our evolutionary history. Cancer progression can be compared
genomic sequencing and its sequelae—transcriptomics, proteomics, to a reversion of development, or, to the evolution of multicellularity.
epigenomics, etc.—have, if anything, complicated cancer classification. Thus, cancer raises intriguing questions about how we conceive of
This literature thus raises a variety of questions about the nature of the “functions”, “development”, and the role of our evolutionary history and
disease and disease classification: Are there some classifications that are particularly, selective trade-offs, in vulnerability to disease.
more useful, or better than others? What makes a classification a good
one? What does it mean to track more or less “natural” distinctions in the Last but not least, cancer research provides a case study for consideration
context of disease? Is such talk of the “naturalness” of disease categories of the roles of values at the science-policy interface. Epidemiological and
simply confused? The problem of cancer classification is complicated by toxicological research on cancer’s causes informs toxics law and
the fact that cancer progression is a process with a complex natural regulatory policy, which raises a variety of questions about the nature of
history. Thus, cancer serves as a challenging case for disease evidence and inductive risk in such contexts. Cancer research also
classification, and also for demarcating disease from health, raising provides a test case for debates about the challenges facing translational
intriguing questions about the potential role(s) of precautionary values in medicine and precision medicine. Moreover, the complexity of cancer
cancer diagnosis. causation provides an opportunity and a challenge for those who take data
and theoretical integration to be an ideal for science. With so many, and
Second, philosophers of science have historically taken the aim of science such diverse types of cancer research, integration presents many
to be arriving at true theories. However, scientists studying cancer come challenges. Indeed, this is one of the many reasons why translating “basic”
from a variety of disciplines, with different scientific as well as practical science into the clinic can be enormously difficult.
aims. Perhaps it is not surprising, then, that historians and philosophers of
science do not seem to agree on how best to characterize the aim and 1. Defining and Classifying Cancer
structure of cancer research; it is far from clear whether the appropriate 1.1 Cancer’s Intrinsic Heterogeneity
characterization of the aim is arriving at true theories, or even whether the 1.2 Cancer’s Variable Natural History
proper units of analysis are “theories”, or instead, “models”, “explanatory 2. Explaining Cancer: Theories, Models and Mechanisms
frameworks”, “research programs”, “paradigms”, or perhaps, 2.1 The Mechanistic Picture of Cancer
“experimental traditions”. With the rise of “big data” science—such as the 2.2 Complicating the Mechanistic Picture: Tissue Organization,
Cancer Genome Atlas Project (or TCGA)—and “systems” approaches to Stem Cells and Systems Theory
the study of disease, both philosophers and historians of science are 3. Cancer as a Byproduct: Evolution, Development, and Aging
rethinking how best to describe and explain these distinctive kinds of 4. The Science-Value Interface and Aims of Cancer Research
scientific inquiry. Bibliography
Academic Tools
Other Internet Resources

2 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2019 Edition 3


Cancer Anya Plutynski

Related Entries with many of the same features (at least initially), may evolve in different
ways, and have different vulnerability to treatment (Marusyk, et al. 2012).
How, then, are we to classify such poorly behaving kinds?
1. Defining and Classifying Cancer
Classifications of cancer have largely been in service of diagnosis,
What is cancer? Is cancer one disease, or many? If many, how many prognosis, and treatment decisions. Oncologists, surgeons and pathologists
cancers are there? One might think that such questions are merely typically classify cancer types and subtypes, in light of organ and tissue
empirical. However, it turns out that defining and classifying cancer is type of origin (such as leukemia, or glioma), broadly shared signs and
contested, for at least two reasons. First, there is little agreement on how to symptoms, disease course, gross histopathology (size, shape and rate of
classify disease, more generally. Second, cancer itself poses a variety of division of cells), and “biomarkers” (e.g., estrogen sensitivity, genetic
challenges—both in terms of its intrinsic heterogeneity, and in light of its profile). Solid tumors (of the lung, for instance) may be classified as either
variable natural history. In section 1.1, we will consider challenges facing “benign,” or “malignant,” and malignant cancers can present at different
cancer classification in light of cancer’s intrinsic heterogeneity, and in “stages” and have different “grades.” Pathologists use various measures
section 1.2, we will consider challenges facing cancer classification in (e.g., size, extent of lymphatic involvement, number of metastases,
light of its variable natural history. number of lymphocytes (white blood cells)) to estimate stage of
progression of the disease. “Grade” is a term used to classify solid tumors
Prima facie, what distinguishes diseases are typical symptoms, disease
in light of other measures (e.g., degree of “dedifferentiation” of cells in a
course, and a common cause. The last criterion—common cause—is
tumor—or loss of characteristics typical of a breast, prostate, or colon
inherited from a model of disease classifications that grew in part out of
cells and tissue) and is taken to indicate likely disease course. Decisions
the successes of the germ theory of disease (Carter 2003). Following
about staging criteria are conventionally agreed upon by specialists in
Koch’s postulates (1884), what enables one to distinguish diseases is the
oncology and pathology, though informed by the best available evidence.
ability to isolate a causal agent as present in each and every case of
Early stage disease can be very difficult to classify, and thus also to know
characteristic symptoms. Unfortunately, such a model of disease is not
whether (or how) treat. And, some cancers seem particularly recalcitrant to
terribly helpful for cancer. Cancer can be present without clinically
treatment. This led researchers to ask: Are there distinctive genetic or
detectable symptoms, has variable disease course, and is a “multifactorial”
molecular “signatures” of each cancer that can help us estimate risk of
disease—there are many causes of cancer. It is rather difficult to pick out a
progression, or chances of recurrence, as well as predict responses to
“causal bottleneck” uniquely necessary for cancer, let alone each cancer
treatment? Perhaps these molecular signatures are the key to a natural
type and subtype. While cancers are typically classified by their cell-of-
taxonomy of cancer types and subtypes?
origin—or the tissue, or organ, and cell-type where they originated (e.g.,
squamous cell carcinoma of the skin or ovaries), it turns out that cancers 1.1 Cancer’s Intrinsic Heterogeneity
can contain mixes of different cells of origin, and cancers arising in the
same cells or tissues can have very different features. Moreover, cancers

4 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2019 Edition 5


Cancer Anya Plutynski

The Cancer Genome Atlas (TCGA) project, a federally funded U.S. ones matter, how, and how much, in different cancer types and subtypes,
research program, supported jointly by the National Cancer Institute (NCI) and indeed, over the course of cancer progression, is a difficult puzzle to
and National Human Genome Research Institute (NHGRI), sought to solve. Complicating this further, a cancer may contain several
characterize the genomic features of each cancer type and subtype, subpopulations of cells (or, multiple evolving lineages), with different
resulting in thirty-three “marker” papers, laying out molecular features of numbers and types of mutations within each lineage. That is, cancers have
each cancer type, often yielding novel subclassifications of each type. For varying types and degrees of “intratumor heterogeneity.” So, samples of a
example, in 2016, a working group affiliated with TCGA published tumor taken when cancer is first diagnosed may be representative of only
“Comprehensive Pan-Genomic Characterization of Adrenocortical one subpopulation of an early stage of a dynamic process. Such samples
Carcinoma,” which identified three subtypes of adrenocortical carcinoma, may not be representative of the genomic changes of greatest relevance to
and in 2015, another working group published “Comprehensive Genomic treatment-resistant late stage disease. Yet, it is late-stage disease that we
Characterization of Head and Neck Squamous Cell Carcinomas,” which need better tools to more effectively intervene upon; most cancers—if
identified specific mutations associated with human-papillomavirus- caught early—can be treated relatively effectively.
associated versus smoking-related head and neck cancers. While TCGA
did result in a more comprehensive understanding of cancer biology, it All this would be challenging enough as it is, but there is a yet further
also raised many questions. One particular challenge has been determining challenge to cancer classification. Cancers arising in the same tissue or
which mutations to which genes are the “drivers” of cancer, or which ones organ can be more genetically dissimilar than cancers arising in different
enable cancer cells to “succeed” in an environment that would (ordinarily) tissues or organs. Or, “cell-of-origin influences, but does not fully
prevent their growth. Cancer genomes have many mutations, so a central determine, tumor classification” (Hoadley, et al. 2014, 2018). Genomic
puzzle has been determining which among the many changes to cancer information, far from providing a way to sort all cancers into a Linnean
genomes are causally relevant to cancer progression. Solving this puzzle hierarchy, instead yields what philosophers have called cross-cutting
has been difficult, because cancers are far more heterogeneous than they classifications (Khalidi, 1998). One might think genetic profile should
initially anticipated. Or, perhaps it is better to say: sorting the “signal” trump tissue or cell of origin for purposes of classification. But it turns out
from the noise has proven more difficult than anticipated, as Meyerson, et that where a cancer arises in the body is rather important to know.
al. (2010) explains, paraphrasing Tolstoi: Characteristics of the tissues and organs in which a cancer arises shape the
course of disease in a complex fashion (Öhlund, et al. 2017; Fessler, et al.
… normal human genomes are all alike, but every cancer genome 2016). Moreover, the rise of epigenomics, proteomics, and
is abnormal in its own way. Specifically, cancer genomes vary transcriptomics, and “regulomics” generates further challenges with
considerably in their mutation frequency,… in global copy number classification, suggesting genomic information needs to be supplemented.
or ploidy, and in genome structure… (Meyerson, et al. 2010) For instance, it turns out changes in microRNA in cancer cells—non-
coding RNA, which affects the expression of genes—can affect cancer
In other words, there are very different rates, numbers and types of initiation, progression, and responses to drugs (Hrovatin, et al. 2018). This
mutations across and within different cancer types and subtypes. Which is just one of several “extra-genomic” factors that play an important role in

6 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2019 Edition 7


Cancer Anya Plutynski

cancer causation and thus, presumably, ought to play at least a partial role Several philosophers have weighed in on the matter of the nature of
in informing cancer taxonomy. disease and disease classification (see, e.g., Ereshefsky, et al. 2015; Lange
2007; Broadbent 2009 and 2015; Williams 2011; Khalidi 2013; Sorenson
This does not exhaust all factors of causal relevance to cancer onset, and 2011). The questions these authors are addressing are both epistemic—
thus also (at least potentially) classification. Family history and inherited what warrants choice of criteria of classification of disease—and
(as opposed to somatic) mutations, life history (e.g. parity, or number of metaphysical—given diseases like cancer lack “essential” properties, is it
children, and age at first birth), environmental exposures, and histories of correct to think of disease “kinds” as “natural”?
infection, inflammation, and immune response, contribute differentially to
cancer’s age of onset, rate of progression, histopathology, and response to Lange (2007) for instance, argues that, “a disease is a natural kind of
treatment. For instance, infectious agents (e.g., HPV- or HCV-) are incapacity that features in interesting function-analytic explanations of
associated with cervical and liver cancers, and some proportion of other unhealthful incapacities”(Lange, 2007, 266). Cancer is not a “natural
esophageal cancers (Cancer Genome Atlas, 2015). Cancers of the prostate kind,” in his view, because the “typical patterns of disruption of cell birth
and breast are associated with hormonal environments, which are in turn and death” characteristic of cancer are multiply realized. Categories like
affected by parity (number of pregnancies). “Pregnancy-associated” breast “breast cancer” or “lung cancer” seem to be increasingly replaced in
cancers are cancers that arise during or shortly after pregnancy (see, e.g., modern medicine by appeal to molecular subtypes. Molecular subtypes of
Schedin 2006). The “same” cancer in the same tissue or organ can be cancer are not, however, “natural kinds of incapacity,” on Lange’s view,
classified as either “somatic,” or “familial”—due in part to whether the and so are not distinct diseases. Indeed, many “disease kinds” lack
patient possesses inherited mutations, such as those with Li Fraumeni unifying “function-analytic” explanations. Thus, modern medicine has, in
syndrome. Smoking associated lung cancers and non-smoking associated a sense, led to the “end of diseases” as natural kinds. In a similar vein, but
lung cancers are distinct genetically, epigenetically, and phenotypically for very different reasons, Sorenson (2011) argues that diseases are “para-
(i.e., in terms of both gross pathology, and course of progression, as well natural” kinds. Insofar as diseases are “deficiencies,” or “departures from
as response to treatment). Which of these several causal factors ought to the norm,” they lack the “integrity” or “internal nature” characteristic of
figure centrally in classification? Depending upon how fine-grained a natural kinds. Diseases are “reflections” of natural kinds of process. They
characterization of the causal basis of cancer one adopts, there could be “inherit the lawfulness and projectability of the natural kinds that shape
hundreds or thousands of cancer types and subtypes. It’s far from clear them.” In other words, both Lange and Sorenson seem similarly skeptical
whether there is one obvious choice of causal basis that best reflects that diseases are natural kinds.
anything like a “natural” division of type and subtypes. Indeed, this case
raises the larger question of whether one can or should expect a univocal In contrast, while Broadbent (2009, 2015), Williams (2011), and Khalidi
classification of multifactorial disease, or indeed, of disease more (2013) agree that diseases lack essential properties, they claim that disease
generally. Are diseases, such as cancer, “natural” kinds? Or, are they classifications in light of distinctive causes, or types of cause, either pick
simply ways of carving up the world that we happen to find useful? Is the out distinctive “deviations from normal functional ability,” or (in Khalidi's
‘naturalness’ of a classification in science a matter of degree? case) homeostatic property cluster kinds. For instance, Broadbent’s (2009,

8 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2019 Edition 9


Cancer Anya Plutynski

2015) “contrastive” model of disease classification roughly takes diseases what they take to be the “hallmarks” of cancer: “a small number of
to be distinct in light of distinctive causes. Where there is a difference in at molecular, biochemical, and cellular traits—acquired capabilities—shared
least one of a set of causes shared by “controls” and “cases” (where cases by most and perhaps all types of human cancer.” They identified these “six
are identified in light of “parts and processes deviating (negatively) from essential alterations in cell physiology that collectively dictate malignant
normal functional ability”), we have a distinct disease. Broadbent takes growth” as: self-sufficiency in growth signals, insensitivity to antigrowth
this account to explain why, for instance, “cervical cancer is a disease, but signals, evasion of apoptosis (cell death), sustained angiogenesis (the
HPV-itis is not.” Though, it’s not clear that HPV-itis is not properly ability to develop a blood supply), tissue invasion and metastasis
regarded as a legitimate disease category; or, at least, this case raises an (Hanahan, et al. 2000, 57). By way of example of a caretaker, TP53 is
interesting question as to whether potential, rather than overt, dysfunction called a tumor suppressor, because it carries the function of sensing and
is more central to disease designation. In public health contexts, whether a responding to signals associated with cell damage, typically inducing
strain of HPV causes cancer or not is not as important as deploying apoptosis, or cell death. It is one of the only genes mutated in a majority of
interventions that limit the spread of HPV more generally. Strains of HPV cancers sequenced (Bailey, et al. 2018), and Weinberg (2013) characterizes
that do not currently cause cancer could well evolve the capacity to do so. it as “master guardian and executioner,” in that it prevents further
So, perhaps from a public health perspective, “HPV-itis” is a perfectly mutations by inducing cell death where there are signs of trouble. On
legitimate disease category. That is, from a preventive medicine Khalidi’s view, one ought to understand disruption of these very specific
perspective, what matters is that a disease category is a good one for capacities as a “homeostatic mechanism” for cancer.
predicting and intervening, even where functional disruption does not
always (or even most of the time) eventuate. Which choice of At first blush, this seems a vivid case of a homeostatic property cluster
classification we ought to make in demarcating disease types, in other kind. However, demarcating mechanisms is far from straightforward.
words, might depend on not only on which contrast we are interested in Where we take a mechanism to begin and end is in large part a pragmatic
explaining retrospectively, but also which kind of intervention we wish to matter (Craver 2009); so, depending upon how we carve up the
promote prospectively. “homeostatic mechanisms for” cancer, we can yield many or few cancer
subtypes. As perhaps may have been expected, Hanahan and Weinberg’s
Khalidi (2013) argues that cancer might be a homeostatic property cluster initial picture has been complicated since 2001. In 2011, Hanahan and
kind. Khalidi argues that cancer is driven by “homeostatic” mechanisms— Weinberg updated their hallmarks to include four more: “genome
namely, mutations to “caretaker” genes, or genes that play a “gatekeeping” instability, which generates the genetic diversity that expedites their
role in preventing or permitting the emergence of a tumor. Acquisition of acquisition, and inflammation, which fosters multiple hallmark
mutations to specific “caretaker” genes, on this view, serve a function akin functions… reprogramming of energy metabolism, and evading immune
to Boyd’s (1999) “homeostatic mechanisms,” in that they permit the destruction.” And, “In addition to cancer cells, tumors exhibit another
further acquisition of “hallmark” properties of cancer cells. Khalidi is dimension of complexity: they contain a repertoire of recruited, ostensibly
drawing upon a very common view of cancer, articulated by two famous normal cells that contribute to the acquisition of hallmark traits by creating
cancer researchers, Hanahan and Weinberg (2000, 2011). They identify the tumor microenvironment” (2011, 646). In other words, hallmarks of

10 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2019 Edition 11


Cancer Anya Plutynski

cancer appear to no longer involve all and only intrinsic properties of One further complication surrounding classification in the case of cancer,
cancer cells, but also dynamic interactions between cancer cells and the is that cancers have variable disease course (Foulds 1958; Cairns 1975;
immune system and extra-tumor environment. This may not be such a Lynch 2007; Bertolaso & Dupré 2018). Not all cancers progress uniformly
serious challenge to Khalidi’s view that caretaker mutation are to metastasis and death; some growths progress slowly or not at all. Some
mechanisms for cancer; one could, arguably, just expand the mechanisms very common cancers (in the prostate and thyroid) are either slow
for homeostasis to the tumor microenvironment. However, such a strategy growing, or tend to remain “indolent” (Esserman, et al. 2013; Siegel, et al.
is complicated by the context-sensitivity of mechanism activation. Many 2017). There is some disagreement in the medical community about how
cells on the surface of the skin as we age possess as many mutations to to characterize such cases; it’s unclear in many cases whether they are best
“caretaker” genes as those in a breast tumor, but most such skin cells are viewed as very slow growing precancerous lesions, or perhaps ought not
shed (Martincorena, et al. 2015). The “same” mechanisms may well lead be characterized as “cancer” at all. Such cases raise a host of practical
to harm in one context, and be entirely harmless in another. questions about the merits of screening, and the risk of overdiagnosis—the
diagnosis of disease that might never have progressed in the lifetime of the
The larger concern cases like this raise is whether there is one way to patient (see, e.g., Walker & Rogers 2016; Hofman 2017; Esserman, et al.
privilege choice of causal basis for classifying diseases like cancer. 2013; Welch & Black 2010), but they also raise interesting philosophical
Different choice of temporal or spatial scale, or more or less fine-grained questions about the nature of disease.
characterization of causal processes, might yield multiple, overlapping
disease classifications. While some may be willing to bite this bullet, and Some philosophers (Schwartz 2014), drawing upon the biostatistical
indeed, endorse pluralism and non-hierarchical classifications (see, e.g., theory of disease as departure from age and sex-typical function (Boorse
Khalidi 1998, 2013), others might be concerned that this would yield too 1977), argue that we ought to classify such early stage cancers as risk
permissive an array of disease types. More generally, whether and how factors, rather than disease. Such growths are not disease, on this view,
scientific researchers and clinicians are likely to to converge on a common because they are not atypical and do not as yet impair function—in fact as
classification for cancer raises some interesting puzzles about the aims and many as one half of men over 60 have some lesions the prostate (Welch &
methods of classification in the biomedical sciences more generally. That Black 2010). Reclassification of such cancers as mere risk factors, it’s
genomic features of cancer are unlikely to unproblematically yield a hoped, will prevent overdiagnosis and overtreatment. Other philosophers
natural taxonomy suggests that a reductive picture of disease classification less sympathetic to the biostatistical approach (e.g., Reid 2016) argue that
is more generally implausible. It seems that classifications of disease like this approach fails to acknowledge how the practice of diagnosis is itself a
cancer form a kind of ‘hybrid’—they are intended to capture natural sort of risk-benefit calculation, informed in part by our knowledge of the
regularities and their causes, but also to be of use for a wide array of prevalence of early stage growths like DCIS (ductal carcinoma in situ), or
agents with different purposes. It’s unclear whether all these purposes can indolent prostate disease, and in part by more or less precautionary values.
be served by one univocal method or set of classificatory criteria. As we’ve learned how common such indolent diseases are, with the
growing realization that many such growths do not progress, it seems that
1.2 Cancer’s Variable Natural History they fall into some further (and less well-defined) category. It seems this

12 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2019 Edition 13


Cancer Anya Plutynski

debate is not only a scientific or empirical one, but also a normative one; (Slater 2014; Ereshefsky, et al. 2015). For instance, Ereshefsky, et al.
much like debates about PTSD or obesity, there are normative dimensions (2015) argue that all and only categories that serve the needs of
to how we define and classify disease. Labeling can have both positive and “progressive” research programs are legitimate.
negative consequences for patients, clinicians, insurers, not to mention
developers and producers of screening, medical device, and Given the complex causal pathways and heterogeneity of cancer, perhaps
pharmaceuticals (Ereshefsky 2009). Overdiagnosis of early stage disease it is not surprising that, as Bertolaso (2016) argues, the history of attempts
can lead to serious harms; not least, treating a “cancer” that may or may to identify defining features of cancer, let alone arrive at a unified theory,
not progress in the lifetime of a patient is costly and harmful to quality of have floundered. Either cancer is defined so vaguely as to include non-
life. pathological states, or focused so narrowly on a specific class of causes as
to rule out cases that might otherwise be included. Among the many
One hope driving the precision medicine research program is that the definitions she canvases are: “abnormal proliferation,” “unregulated
identification of biomarkers of aggressive disease will resolve these growth,” “a disease of cell differentiation rather than multiplication,” “the
ambiguities with respect to early stage disease, as well as identify targets result of destruction of tissue architecture,” “a systems biology disease,”
of effective treatment (see, e.g., Collins, et al. 2005). However, as we have “blocked ontogeny,” a disease of “suppressed (sic) immune function,” a
seen, interpreting genomic data has been far from straightforward, and “metabolic” and of course, a “genomic” disease. Such a variety of
classifying cancer types and subtypes by appeal to genomic information definitions is, Bertolaso argued, due to the fact that cancer has many
alone can lead to a loss of important information. While genomic and causes, and many effects; moreover, it involves many different types of
molecular data is no doubt useful, it is not necessarily decisive. dysregulation, at a variety of temporal and spatial scales. Suffice it to say,
it is no small challenge to identify defining features of cancer, let alone
In sum, much like genes and species, diseases like cancer lack essences, arriving at a unified “theory” of disease etiology.
are heterogeneous, blur together at the edges, are caused in many different
ways, and have variable dynamics. Perhaps inconsistent classifications are One might well ask, however, whether the lack of a unified theory of
simply to be expected in such cases. That this is so does not (necessarily) cancer is a cause for concern? Is this a sign of immature science? Kincaid
show that we ought to give up on realism about disease kinds; indeed, has argued to the contrary (2008), “biomedical science can make
perhaps we ought to endorse “promiscuous realism” (Dupré 1996). As significant progress without precise definitions of disease, without full-
knowledge has grown, and practical interests shift, on this view, fledged theories of disease and of normal biological functioning, and
classifications can multiply and even cross-classify the same kinds. This is without disease entities being natural kinds” (p. 368). Pointing out how
nothing to fear, so long as the kinds we countenance do the predictive or tumor microenvironment shapes how cancer cells behave as they do,
explanatory work intended for them, in the context intended. Others have Kincaid argues that “There is no clear definition of what constitutes a
a somewhat less permissive view, however, arguing that there need to be cancerous cell in terms of necessary and sufficient conditions. However,
some empirical constraints or other on classification of “scientific kinds,” no one thinks that cancer research should stop until we get this definition
whether or not these categories count as examples of “natural” kinds settled, or that creating linguistic uniformity is important for

14 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2019 Edition 15


Cancer Anya Plutynski

understanding the science. The science certainly makes progress in mutually exclusive relations with one another. As new questions arose,
nonetheless… Likewise, there is no parsimonious theory of the disease and new information was discovered, this explanatory framework became
and the normal functioning from which it is a deviation. Instead, we have elaborated; depending upon how permissive or restrictive our
piecemeal causal explanations” (p. 373). Kincaid is correct. Much of characterization of this framework, it need not be viewed as at odds with,
cancer research is piecemeal in character, offering partial and locally for instance, attention to the tissue microenvironment in cancer. This sort
constrained characterizations of the loss or promotion of some particular of multifaceted approach is perhaps what one ought to expect for such a
activity of a cell associated with this or that mutation typical of cancer heterogeneous disease, where causes and effects can be described at very
cells. Whether we require a unified theory of cancer remains an open different temporal and spatial scales. Much like other complex,
question. Or, at least, the question of what function such a unified theory multifactorial diseases, cancer is not a single phenomenon, but a
might serve is a matter of some debate. This is reflected in the fact that the heterogeneous class of disease processes, with few definitive properties or
research program seeking to identify genetic mechanisms associated with unique causes. This makes not only classification, but also explanation,
cell birth and death has received so many different names: the “oncogene enormously difficult, as we will see below.
paradigm,” (Bishop 1995; Morange 1997) “vision,” (Morange 1997),
“theory,” (Sonnenschein & Soto 2008), “model” (Temin 1974; Vogelstein 2. Explaining Cancer: Theories, Models and
& Kinzler 1993), “theory-method package” (Fujimura 1988, 1992), and Mechanisms
recently, “framework” (Blassime, et al. 2013).
What does it mean to explain cancer? The question is ambiguous, and
One suggestion that seems plausible is that a better way of framing the fraught. For, by “cancer” one could have several targets of explanation in
project of cancer research involves commitment to an “explanatory mind: the transformation of a cell into a “cancer cell,” the (general)
framework.” For instance, Blassimie, et al. (2013) characterize the search process of carcinogenesis, the process of invasion and metastasis in solid
for oncogenes as an “explanatory framework”: “causal patterns, schemata tumors, the emergence and roles of intratumor heterogeneity, differential
(in the sense of Darden 2002), intuitions, hypotheses, evidential standards rates of incidence of different cancer types, patterns of cancer incidence or
and various bits of evidence and data coming from different experimental mortality in different environments, socioeconomic groups, races, ages, or
settings and instrumental devices,” which “establish selective and local sexes. Each of these explanatory targets arguably calls for quite different
criteria of causal relevance that drive the search for, characterization and kinds of explanation and not only different explanatory information.
use of biological mechanisms.” Rather than consisting of sets of laws or Cancer scientists make appeals to generalizations of wide scope, for
general principles, such frameworks help generate strategies in the search instance, and will also offer detailed, specific mechanistic explanations of
for causes, and narrow the field of inquiry. Blassime, et al. argue that specific outcomes. The fact that these explanations are different in kind
“explanatory frameworks allow for changes of scientific perspective on may (in part) explain why there appears to be such a variety of views
the causal relevance of mechanisms without necessarily fully replacing amongst philosophers concerning the aim and character of explanation and
previous explanatory frameworks” (p. 375). Explanatory frameworks, in progress in cancer research. There is, of course, a long history of debate
other words, can “coexist” or be “gradually displaced,” rather than stand

16 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2019 Edition 17


Cancer Anya Plutynski

among philosophers of biology concerning norms of explanation. It’s still This picture of cancer was pieced together over decades from various
hotly debated whether, for instance, all explanations in the biological sources of evidence—from Virchow’s observations of chromosomal
sciences must identify causes, or mechanisms, or whether “mathematical” abnormalities in cancer cells, to epidemiological patterns of incidence in
or “equilibrium” explanations are distinct in kind, and how “network” cancer, to the discovery of the “src” gene—one of the first mutations
models or “systems theoretical” explanations are distinct from other kinds found to be associated with cancer. This vision of cancer as the product of
of explanation, are all live debates (See the entries on scientific oncogenes replaced a “regulatory” view of cancer, according to which
explanation and philosophy of systems and synthetic biology). However, cancer was a “breakdown in normal constraints on growth” (for a history,
there is also a history of dispute amongst cancer scientists about both see, e.g., Morange 1993, 1997, 2003). Not coincidentally, the “oncogene
competing research agendas and explanatory strategies. paradigm” arose at the same time that some of the first bioengineering
technologies, which enabled early cancer researchers to use the techniques
2.1 The Mechanistic Picture of Cancer of molecular biology to study identify genes associated with cancer
progression (Fujimura 1987). While this is a reductionist research
As mentioned above, for most of the last twenty or so years of the 20th
program, in the sense that the aim is to decompose the system of interest
Century and the first decades of the 21st, the central concern of the
and understand the parts in operation, not all early advocates of the
majority of cancer researchers seems to have been identification of
multistage theory were cell and molecular biologists. Two of the first
mechanisms at the cell and molecular level that regulate cell birth and
advocates of a multi-stage theory of carcinogenesis—Armitage and Doll—
death. Two characteristic features of cancer cells are their uncontrolled
found that curves of average lifetime incidence of lung cancer in smokers
growth, and failure to undergo cell death. This is often accomplished via
appeared to have the same shape as that of nonsmokers, simply shifted to
changes to the “cellular machinery,” or mutations and associated
earlier ages. This suggested that cancer could arise from a rate-limited
disruption of pathways associated with regulation of cell division or cell
series of insults acquired over the life course. Since the 1980s, hundreds of
death (Hanahan & Weinberg 2001). So, it is natural to assume that
genes have been identified, mutations to which are associated with the
explaining cancer requires identifying the chromosomal alterations,
hallmarks of cancer. Carcinogenesis, on this view, results from damage to
mutations, and epigenetic changes to cells that give them distinctive
DNA, or errors in the process of cell division, as well as either
capacities of a cancer cell, as well as describe the ways in which these
endogenous factors (various hormonal or other factors that promote cell
mutations systematically yield these effects. This framework for
growth), or exogenous factors (infection, and inflammation), which over
explaining cancer has been characterized as “somatic mutation theory,”
time can lead to dysregulated cell growth.
insofar as cancer is viewed as a product of a series of mutations to cells
during somatic cell division. Onset of cancer, on this view, may be In one paradigmatic example, Vogelstein and his group collected tissue
accelerated either by inheritance of “oncogenes” or “tumor suppressors,” samples (premalignant polyps) from patients with a familial or inherited
or by damage to DNA, for instance, due to smoking or UV radiation. form of bowel cancer (FAP, or familial adenomatous polyposis). They
discovered that mutations to genes associated with various cancers
accumulated in series of steps, what has been called the “Vogelstein

18 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2019 Edition 19


Cancer Anya Plutynski

cascade.” The study of familial or strongly inherited forms of cancer Even advocates of the mechanistic perspective have argued that it needs to
(cancers that appear at relatively young ages, and occur in families) has be amended to accommodate the complex causal processes involved in
enabled the identification of several genes, mutations to which (whether cancer’s etiology. For instance, according to Bechtel (forthcoming), a
inherited or acquired during somatic cell division) play a role in cancer: linear picture of mechanisms for cancer leaves out an important
APC, RB, and p53 (associated with familial adenomatous polyposis, dimension. He characterizes the mechanisms associated with apoptosis,
retinoblastoma, and Li Fraumeni syndrome, respectively). for instance, as made up of two types: “primary” and “control”
mechanisms. Failure to respond to signals promoting apoptosis in cancer
This picture of explaining cancer might be expected to resonate quite well may be a result of disruption in either one (or both) such mechanisms.
with the picture of scientific explanation advocated by what has been Advocates of the mechanistic perspective have failed, Bechtel argues, to
called the “new mechanists.” According to this view, one of the central attend to the complex negative feedback processes of control and
aims of biological scientists is the identification of mechanisms. The constraint affecting primary mechanisms. As evidence of the significance
biological sciences, on this view, are unique in their focus on mechanisms, of such control mechanisms, he points out how cancer researchers utilize
rather than laws or general principles, of the sort (typically imagined) to novel methods, such as network analysis to identify regulatory networks
be central to the physical sciences. A mechanistic explanation identifies or feedback loops, associated with specific functions. Bechtel’s distinction
parts and processes that typically yield specific outcomes of interest between “primary” and “control” mechanism raises some interesting
(Machamer, et al. 2000). If we wish to understand regulation of apoptosis questions about the organization of causal pathways in cancer. Whether
(cell death), for instance, we might identify particular genes and proteins such pathways are, for instance, relatively fixed or static in organization, is
that play an important role in cell senescence, and determine how their an open question. Moreover, the category of “controller” versus “primary”
activity and organization yield (or fail to yield) a given outcome. This mechanism itself may be relatively fluid, or context dependent. The
mechanistic picture of the aims and character of explanation in the “same” mechanism in a different environment might exert different
biological sciences seems prima facie to characterize current cancer controls, and, control mechanisms may themselves be viewed as primary,
research quite well, or at least the past 25 years of this research. given one’s characterization of the function that is the subject of inquiry.

However, several philosophers have argued that this picture fails to 2.2 Complicating the Mechanistic Picture: Tissue Organization,
capture the diverse explanatory strategies carried out by cancer scientists, Stem Cells and Systems Theory
at least currently. For instance, some have argued that this fails to take into
consideration more “organicist” or “holistic” views of cancer causation, Some critics of the somatic mutation theory and its associated search for
which they contrast with a “reductionist” approach in cancer research mechanisms of cancer at the cell and molecular level are far more radical
(Bertolaso 2009). Some also argue that apparently competing perspectives in their ambitions. In the late 1990s, and early 2000s, two researchers
can be fruitfully integrated (Bertolaso 2011; Marcum 2005; Malaterre proposed what they took to be an alternative theory or “paradigm” to the
2007). “somatic mutation theory” (SMT), namely, the Tissue Organization Field
Theory (or, TOFT) (Soto & Sonnenschein 2000). Soto and Sonnenschein

20 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2019 Edition 21


Cancer Anya Plutynski

object not only to reductionist methodology, but reductionist assumptions artificial” contexts, and echoes concerns of researchers that the use of
about the causes of cancer. That is, their concern is not only with immunodeficient mice to study cancer stem cells, for instance, may or may
experimental approaches that focus on dysregulated growth of cancer cells not warrant the conclusions they claim to establish. Xenotransplantation,
in cell culture, but also with the claims regarding the role of mutations in for instance, has been used to articulate and test hypotheses about
cancer. In their view, cancers are not the result of mutations, but instead “intrinsic tumorigenicity” of some cells, particularly cells expressing a
“alterations in the communication among cells and tissues that affect particular antigen, ABCB5+, which were then designated “cancer stem
tissue architecture” (2013, p. 90). On this view, mutations do not lead the cells” in light of their capacity to form tumors in nude mice (Germain,
way—or, directly affect these signaling pathways—but follow upon 2013, p. 9). The problem with using these tools, however, is that the
disruptions to tissue organization. It is these alterations of patterns of matter of when and whether a cell is “tumorigenic” varies across different
interaction between cells that leads to “downward causation effects” on backgrounds—in immune deficient mice, lacking a particular receptor
cells and cellular components, inducing aneuploidy and mutations (Soto & (interleukin-2 gamma receptor, or Il2rg), tumors will grow, but not in mice
Sonnenschein 2006; Sonnenschein & Soto 2008). Arguments such as this with such a receptor. Which experimental context is relevant to
one raise several interesting philosophical questions. First, Soto and understanding how and why cancer is caused by “stem cells,” thus
Sonnenschein are skeptical of the scientific methodology supporting SMT. depends upon which causes we wish to isolate, and how. As Germain
They bring attention to some interesting broader questions as to when are points out,
we warranted in inferring from cell culture or model organism work to
general claims about cancer etiology. On the one hand, human tumors do not develop “in the void”:
cancer patients are seldom so immunodeficient, and immune
Given that the development of cancer is an immensely complex causal response is an important part of cancer development and of
process that cannot be observed directly, many scientific claims about variability in outcomes. A notion of tumorigenicity independent of
cancer’s causes are based on indirect inference, using model organisms or this pressure seems to be an idealization that lacks practical
cells in culture. For instance, tumors are grown in nude mice using relevance. On the other hand, it seems scientifically worthwhile to
xenotransplantation, or, tumors are observed to grow in mice in which isolate the different components influencing the malignancy of
“driver genes” are “knocked out.” Soto and Sonnenschein have argued that cancer cells, so that we might exclude the effects of the immune
the artificial experimental circumstances that have enabled or promoted system; tumorigenicity is one thing, evasion of immune
the study of cancer “genes” render judgments about their causal efficacy surveillance is another. (Ibid, p. 10)
suspect; in principle, they claim, it’s consistent with these experiments to
suggest that these mutations are mere effects of the true causes of A second question that Soto and Sonnenschein's work raises is whether
carcinogenesis. Whether or not one agrees with their conclusions about “downward causation” is at work in cancer. Several philosophers have
TOFT v. SMT, they do raise methodological questions worth exploring weighed in on this question (Malaterre 2011; Bertolaso 2016; Green
about the scope and limitations of model organism work. Germain (2013) 2019). Malaterre (2011) argues that advocates of TOFT need not commit
points out that cancer in these xenotransplantation experiments are “highly to non-reductive physicalism, or emergent properties. Instead, he argues,

22 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2019 Edition 23


Cancer Anya Plutynski

Soto and Sonnenschein are drawing attention to dynamic relationships cases.


between variables that supervene over molecular and cellular activities, Proteins in the extracellular matrix affect self-organization of
and a “higher level,” or less granular explanation of cancer etiology may mammary epithelial cells in culture (Bissell 1981; Weaver, et al.
be preferred in some contexts, both for pragmatic and epistemic reasons. 2002; Nelson, et al. 2006). That is, tissue organization can suppress
Malaterre makes appeal to Woodward’s (2010) argument that choice of or promote the neoplastic behavior of malignant cells (Weaver, et al.
causal variables often involves appeal to something like a notion of 1997, 2002). For instance, Paczek (2005) shows that the malignant
“proportionality,” such that, depending on the target of inquiry, we may be phenotype can be altered by stiffness of the extracellular matrix, in
“led to the incorporation of more fine-grained detail in the specification of colonies of mammary epithelial cells (MECs).
causes […] or toward specifications that abstract away from such detail”
(2010, 299). All of these phenomena are taken as evidence that there are features of the
tissue microenvironment that affect either the induction of or progression
Soto and Sonnenschein would likely reject this analysis, insofar as their of cancer, and such features are not reducible to, or explainable in terms of
argument was not simply that tissue organization is deserving of our properties or processes at or below the cell and molecular level. Further,
attention, for pragmatic reasons, but “that carcinogenesis resulted from the Soto and Sonnenschein claim that the somatic mutation theory cannot
disruption of the reciprocal interactions between stroma and epithelium.” account for these observations, and that they can only be accommodated
Or more precisely, “the cancer phenotype is an emergent phenomenon on a view that takes that tissue architecture itself as causally relevant to
occurring at the tissue level of organization” (2006, p. 371). What the progression of disease, which is described in this case as downward
evidence is offered up for this kind of causal relationship? There are three causation.
sources of evidence that Soto and Sonnenschein have emphasized as of
relevance to their defense of “organicism” and TOFT: Do such cases genuinely count as downward causation in, for instance,
Kim’s (1999) sense? After all, strictly speaking, the idea that causation is
Embryonal cells can produce neoplasms when misplaced in adult synchronic across the whole and part of the same entity seems
tissues, and revert to normalcy when placed in an early embryo contradictory. Soto and Sonnenschein accept this criticism, and propose
(Stewart & Mintz, 1981). In other words, the neoplastic phenotype that the kind of causation they are invoking is not synchronic, but
can be both induced or normalized or reversed, without any change in “diachronic emergence”: “cellular and tissue events occurring before the
the cell itself. According to critics of the somatic mutation theory, expression of a particular set of genes takes place may act downwardly
such outcomes cannot be explained on the somatic mutation theory, modifying the expression of these genes at a later time” (Soto, et al. 2008,
since there is no intrinsic mutational change in such cells. 271).
Some neoplasms tend to arise in areas of contact between two types
of epithelium. During development and adult life, there can be This, however, seems to be not as radical a metaphysical thesis as talk of
changes of tissue organization at just such points of interaction, downward causation may initially suggest. Indeed, Soto and Sonnenschein
which may well be responsible for the induction of tumors in these seem to simply refer to a form of constraint. Green (2019) takes

24 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2019 Edition 25


Cancer Anya Plutynski

“downward causation” to mean just this: “the role of solid-state tissue lab (Weaver, et al. 1997, 2002) seems to indicate that structural features of
properties in tumor progression can be interpreted as a form of downward the extracellular matrix somehow either prevent the emergence of disease,
causation, understood as constraining relations between tissue-scale and or can accelerate it. It seems such examples do not point to “downward
micro-scale variables” (p. 1). She notes that while this suggestion is “a causation,” but instead suggest that we need to expand our understanding
‘weaker’ form of downwards causation than the one Kim (2000) and of the causes of cancer to include maintenance of tissue integrity. That is,
others oppose,” and so departs from standard use of the expression (at the case of cancer seems to require a richer, more integrative and
least among philosophers of mind), the advantage of this weaker notion interdisciplinary approach to investigating cancer.
that it better captures what scientists have in mind when arguing for the
“necessity of higher-scale features for the realization and understanding of Another major research program that in some ways challenges a
biological phenomena.” Similarly, Bertolaso (2016) argues that: mechanistic picture of cancer (or at least some (Laplane, 2016) see as
opposed to the “classical view” of cancer) is the “cancer stem cell” theory
The biology of cancer shows that the stability of constitutive (CSC). However, the idea of cancer stem cells has been somewhat
elements depends on the organization, and that there is a source of controversial, in part due to the experimental models used to establish and
regulation in the biological context. Cells change their behavior identify cancer stem cells. Fagan (2016) characterizes the notion of a
depending on their functional integration in the tissue. Alteration in cancer stem cell, as well as the current state of the field, succinctly as
cell communication alters gene expression, and the loss of follows.
integration of cells within a functional tissue leads to genetic
instability and apoptosis. The collapse of levels, as characterized in Cancer stem cells (CSCs) are thought to be a small subpopulation
cancer, results from the loss of general functional integration of a of self-renewing stem cells within a tumor or blood-borne cancer,
biological entity. This means that the structure itself, once which are responsible for maintaining and growing the
constituted, determines the relationships among the parts and the malignancy. This idea has significant clinical implications. If the
stability of the parts… The dynamic structure has… causal CSC model is correct, the current clinical strategy of seeking to
relevance. (2016, p. 87) eradicate all cancer cells should be revised, to specifically target
CSC.
She characterizes this as an instance of synchronic reflexive emergence
—“a different mode of causation. In such a mode, effects are not The cancer stem cell theory in part is descended from the view that
expressed in terms of a progression of events, but of maintenance of states cancers are in several ways akin to ordinary tissue (though distorted),
at different levels of biological organization” (Bertolaso 2016, p. 95). containing a mixture of proliferating stem cells and their more
differentiated products. This view played an important role in cancer
It seems that each of these authors is pointing to an important role for research in the 1960s and 1970s, and is sometimes called the
structural organization in the maintenance of homeostasis as playing an “developmental” theory of cancer, in light of the fact that it takes cancer to
important role in carcinogenesis. Indeed, evidence provided by Bissell’s be a disease of “development,” or cellular differentiation in particular

26 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2019 Edition 27


Cancer Anya Plutynski

(Pierce & Speers 1988, Morange 2015, Laplane 2016). This model of particular, evolutionary processes. Moreover, the CSC theory has the
cancer etiology was revived in the 90s, when Lapidot, Bonnet, and Dick advantage that it “connects basic research and intervention by suggesting
identified “leukemic stem cells” (Lapidot, et al. 1994, Bonnet and Dick new therapeutic strategy” (Laplane 2016, 28)
1997), and was expanded upon in the early 2000s with the identification of
an analogous cell population in breast cancer, suggesting that CSCs are a Fagan (2016) argues, to the contrary, that on a “model-based” approach,
general feature of all cancers (Al-Hajj, et al. 2003). it’s not clear that these two theories are inconsistent. Indeed, Laplane
(2017) has more recently pointed out how the CSC can serve to
The notion that there are subpopulations of cells within a tumor that play a supplement the evolutionary perspective. The presence and number of
distinctive role—either in initiating a cancer, or in seeding new cancers, cancer stem cells can, it has been suggested, affect the rate and nature of
has been influential in current research, suggesting new avenues for both evolutionary change in a population of cancer cells. Essentially, if all cells
treatment and prevention. Historically the cancer stem cell theory (CSC) in a tumor are descended from one or a few cancer stem cells, this restricts
was framed in opposition to the somatic mutation theory (e.g. Reya, et al. population size, and thus suggests that to a large extent cancer progression
2001; Wicha, et al. 2006; Shipitsin, et al. 2007). Laplane (2016) has is driven by drift, rather than selection. Rather than see the two theories as
argued that the cancer stem cell theory (CSC) has various advantages over mutually exclusive, in other words, we might see the two as
the alternative, which she calls the “classical” theory. Laplane takes the complementary, in the process of integration, or overlapping models.
following to be the four fundamental theses of CSC theory:
All this discussion of the role and nature of cancer stem cells, however, is
1. CSCs are capable of self-renewal, thus producing new CSCs. complicated by the fact that there is a great deal of dispute around what
2. CSCs are capable of differentiation, thus producing cells of different counts as a cancer stem cell. Both Laplane and Fagan draw attention to the
phenotypes. fact that the concept of cancer stem cell is multiply ambiguous, in at least
3. CSCs represent a tiny subpopulation of cells, distinct from other the following ways:
cancer cell populations and are, in theory, isolatable.
4. CSCs initiate cancers. First, when we speak of cancer stem cells, we may be referring to
their capacities or properties, or to their historical role or genealogy,
The first two claims concern the concept of a stem cell; the latter two i.e., to the fact that they were the cells from which other cancer cells
claims concern carcinogenesis itself: how cancer arises. It’s the latter two originate. That is, some take cancer stem cells to be defined in terms
theses that Laplane takes to be in tension with the “classical” theory. of their distinctive capacities and some in terms of their relationship
Laplane argues that CSC theory is more “parsimonious”, because it to other cells—in particular, to their ancestor-descendent
“explains cancer development, propagation and relapse” from a “limited relationships in a population of cells in a tumor. The “cancer stem
number of hypotheses” (Laplane 2016, 28). In contrast, the classical view cell model” is sometimes simply taken to refer to any model of a
neither predicts nor explains cancer heterogeneity, or relapse, but must tumor that treats the population of cells as having a hierarchical
invoke special (“additional” or “ad hoc” theories) to explain them, in relationship, where one or a few cells propagate the tumor, whether

28 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2019 Edition 29


Cancer Anya Plutynski

or not those cells have distinctive properties that cause them to stand In sum, there appear to remain several open questions about the nature of
in that relationship. cancer stem cells, and more generally, how to best intervene upon cancer
Second, there are several different kinds of historical role that CSCs to successfully eradicate the disease. According to the model of the
might play: They may be all and only those cells that initiate a cancer disease inherited from the latter third of the 20th Century, somatic
under natural conditions, they may be those cells which propagate a mutations, acquired over a lifetime, to the acquisition of cancer’s
cancer in situ, or they may be those cells that are capable of “hallmarks.” So, the best strategy for intervention may be targeting
propagating a cancer in an experimental animal. specific pathways associated with these hallmarks. In contrast, according
Third, some take the concept of CSC to be restricted to normal stem to the Tissue Organization Field Theory (TOFT), changes in tissue
cells, which some believe are the most likely precursors to cancer. organization yield carcinogenesis. Thus, the best strategy for intervention
Others hold that cells that originate a tumor have stem-like properties might be finding ways to intervene in the tissue microenvironment, so as
but may or may not derive from normal stem cells. to create an environment less hospitable to the growth of cancer cells.
According to the cancer stem cell theory, cancer arises in cells that have
What’s clear is that some populations of cells in a tumor appear to have distinctive properties: continuous renewal, and indefinite growth,
“stemness” properties—the ability to renew oneself. What is less clear is permitting the emergence of new disease. On this view, eradicating these
whether these capacities are context sensitive, and how and by which cells stem cells seems essential to cancer treatment. Philosophical work on
they may be acquired. The plasticity of many types of cancer cells cancer causation and explanation can better illuminate the competing
suggests that they may acquire a stemness phenotype, and even shift back presuppositions of different approaches, clarify their commitments, and
to non-stem phenotype. Given this, it appears that the CSC is just one of a offer insights into fruitful integration of new data. It is already clear that
continuum of general views, some of which take only specific types of philosophical discussions of ambiguities in how we define and measure
cells to be precursors to cancer and others which grant that many different stemness is essential to understanding how best to prevent recurrence and
types of cells have the potential to develop such properties. That is, the treat the disease (Clevers 2016).
real question at issue is whether the cells that initiate a tumor are in some
way distinctive or require distinctive precursors, and how properties of Philosophical discussions of how and why TOFT and CSC challenge a
stemness are acquired. Whether stemness is intrinsic or acquirable, niche- simple reductionist picture of cancer etiology are only two of several
dependent or independent, moreover, will drastically change the examples. Other philosophers have described (or critiqued) evolutionary
therapeutic strategy. The CSC model (the idea that CSC are at the origin of explanations of cancer (especially models of multilevel selection)
cancer development, resistance to treatment, and relapse) might be true (Germain 2012a; Lean and Plutynski 2016; Germain and Laplane 2017;
and yet CSC-targeting strategy might fail. Indeed, what kind of property Plutynski, 2018). Still others emphasize systems biology-based
“stemness” is may vary across cancers, and even over time within a cancer approaches to cancer (Bertolaso 2016; Plutynski & Bertolaso 2018), or the
(Laplane and Solary 2019). important role of a developmental perspective (Laplane 2016, 2018; Fagan
2017). Others still emphasize how one might model cancer as an
infectious disease (Liu, et al. 2017), and or an evolutionary-developmental

30 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2019 Edition 31


Cancer Anya Plutynski

process (Liu 2018). What all these philosophers seem to emphasize is that the course of our life and evolutionary history. The best perspective to take
the study of mechanisms associated with cancer at the cell and molecular on this may be a “multilevel” evolutionary perspective—i.e., thinking of
level requires supplementation to better predict and explain the origin of evolution by natural selection as operating at different temporal and spatial
the disease, and design effective therapies. In addition, Pradeu scales, both sequentially, and in some cases, simultaneously, sometimes
(forthcoming) has recently pointed out how the immune system plays an yielding unfortunate “cross-level byproducts” of selection at one temporal
apparently “paradoxical” dual role in cancer, both acting to prevent and and spatial scale, for entities or processes at other temporal or spatial
promote cancer. This raises interesting questions about the function of the scales (cf. Okasha 2007).
immune system, as well as the appropriate way of understanding
“organism,” “self” and “non-self” in biological contexts. There remain First, it is relatively uncontroversial that understanding a species’
interesting questions about how to integrate various perspectives on this evolutionary history, and the selective trade-offs they face over the course
complex disease. of their life history, can inform our understanding of how and why they are
more or less vulnerable to disease. For instance, some species are more
3. Cancer as a Byproduct: Evolution, Development, vulnerable to cancer than others. Why? Comparative biology—the
comparison of different species—may help us identify mechanisms
and Aging
associated with disease vulnerability, onset and progression, when they
Dobzhansky (1973) wrote that “nothing in biology makes sense except in arose, where and why they are shared, as well as how they have diverged
light of evolution.” Can evolutionary thinking shed light on cancer? After (Aktipis, et al. 2015). Comparing and contrasting how development,
all, cancer is ordinarily understood to be a case of failure of otherwise immunity, and other mechanisms of suppression of cancer across species
functional controls on cell birth and death. At first pass, this view seems can help cancer researchers identify targets of opportunity for either
fundamentally at odds with taking an evolutionary perspective on cancer. treatment or prevention of cancer. In addition, we can look to unique
For, how can something that is an exemplary case of “dysfunction” count features of our own evolutionary history in order to explain patterns of
as an evolutionary process or product of adaptive evolution? Moreover, disease incidence, suggesting selective “mismatches” with our ancestral
how ought we to square this picture of cancer with the fact that cancer environment, a kind of “byproduct” explanations of our vulnerability to
cells seem to co-opt developmental processes—i.e., the process of “de- diseases. This enterprise is broadly characterized as “evolutionary
differentiation” typical of early embryonic cells? Is cancer a byproduct of medicine” (Crespi, et al. 2005; Gluckman, et al. 2009; Stearns & Koella
development? Finally, cancer seems to increase in incidence as we age. Is 2008; Sun, et al. 2014).
cancer simply a byproduct of aging? Relatedly, if—as some argue—aging
While the broad principles behind evolutionary medicine are relatively
itself is selected for (a contested question!), is cancer in some sense
uncontroversial—we all are evolved organisms after all—philosophers of
“adaptive”? All these perspectives on cancer require us to perhaps rethink
biology have been skeptical of particular claims about how our
the nature of function and dysfunction, or at least better understand how
evolutionary history has shaped our vulnerability to disease. Some such
there are trade-offs in fitness at different temporal and spatial scales over
claims have been particularly contentious, either because the nature of the

32 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2019 Edition 33


Cancer Anya Plutynski

disease itself is not well characterized (especially mental illness, for “Mismatch” hypotheses suggest that traits that may have been adaptive in
instance), or evidence in support of evolutionary “mismatch” with our the past leave us vulnerable to disease in our current environment. For
ancestral environment is both scant and disputed. Particularly where instance, many advocates of evolutionary medicine have argued that the
alternative explanations may well involve attributing responsibility to, high correlation between nulliparity and cancer risk might be explained by
e.g., pollutants, or choices in lifestyle that are politically or socially our evolutionary history. The argument is that women in the evolutionary
sensitive, philosophers of science have been particularly skeptical. Some past were pregnant for much of their lives, starting at an earlier age; breast
have argued that many arguments in evolutionary medicine make development and differentiation was thus adapted to a lifetime of frequent
“adaptationist” assumptions, i.e., assumptions that a given trait is adaptive, pregnancy and nursing. Delaying or avoiding pregnancy changes the
or selectively advantageous, founded on at best “just so” stories (Valles developmental processes typical for our species, and might expose women
2011; see also Murphy 2006). to more cycles of estrogen, which could increase breast cancer risk. Of
course, such hypotheses are contentious; there is always the potential for
Of course, there are better and worse such arguments; the best arguments confounding causes (in this case, of increased cancer risk due to a variety
consider not only the widest array of evidence, but also trade offs in of risk factors at work in modern society) (Greaves 2000). Nonetheless, it
fitness, as well as the role of constraints arising out of development and has been known for centuries that nulliparity (not having children) raises
life history. For instance, traits adaptive early in life may yield fitness costs breast cancer risk, and since at least the 1970s, it’s been widely known (at
later in life. A vivid example of a trade-off in fitness is androgenic least in the cancer research community) that the more children one has,
hormones; such hormones predispose men to higher prostate cancer risk, starting at a younger age, the lower the risk of breast cancer. In a 1970
but they may also yield an advantage early in life, in terms of increasing case-control study conducted at eight different locations around the globe,
sperm production, relative growth and size at sexual maturity, and thus a WHO group led by McMahon et al., estimated that “breast cancer risk
(potentially) access to mates and resources. Some defenders of for women having their first birth under the age of 20 years is about half
evolutionary perspectives on medicine claim that high prostate cancer risk that for nulliparous women,” and that “women having their first child
in taller men may thus be a case of a “mismatch” between our ancestral when aged under 18 years have only about one-third the breast cancer risk
and current contexts (see, e.g., Summers, et al. 2008 for discussion). of those whose first birth is delayed until the age of 35 years or more.”
Presumably, philosophers are likely to contest such arguments on a variety Evolutionary “byproduct” explanations appeal to our evolutionary history
of grounds—either speculative assumptions about the adaptive advantage to explain this observation.
of size or early age of sexual maturity in our evolutionary past, or
concerns about how or how much variability in hormones contributes Another type of “byproduct” explanation of cancer—though one that
either to body size or cancer risk. Though, this provides an interesting case appeals to a much more distant event in our evolutionary history—is that
study for considering how hypotheses about the role of sex and age in cancer is a product of the emergence of multicellularity. At one point in
disease risk are tested, an area of growing interest. the very distant past, single celled organisms formed collectives that
cooperate; these collectives eventually became multicellular organisms.
Any collective of cells, especially collectives whose survival and

34 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2019 Edition 35


Cancer Anya Plutynski

reproductive success depends on functional organization, are potentially the capacities that invasive cancer cells acquire (the capacity to invade and
vulnerable to breakdown in cooperative organization. On this view, then, metastasize) are in fact due to a change in phenotype from epithelial to
cancer is a product of breakdown in mechanisms that permitted the mesenchymal type cells, and losing adhesive properties enables such cells
emergence of multicellularity—the mechanisms that protect us from to invade the lymph and blood system. Lean and Plutynski (2016) have
“revolt from within” are not error-free, and over time will fail. According argued that cancer may in some ways parallel the patterns of emergence of
to Greaves and others (Greaves, et al. 2012; Merlo, et al. 2006) the multicellularity as characterized by Damuth and Heisler (1988), shifting
evolutionary picture of cancer dovetails nicely with the somatic mutation over the course of emergence of disease from a simple selective process
theory; somatic cells divide and acquire mutations during our lifetimes; between individual cells to several kinds of multilevel selective process
some of these mutations involve failures in regulatory pathways that (MLS1 to MLS2). Critics contest that the process of metastasis only
ordinarily “enforce” functional organization, and thus cooperation. In this weakly mimics MLS2, however (Germain, et al. 2017).
way, an evolutionary perspective—understanding how evolution of
multicellularity required the emergence of cooperative organization—is To be sure, there are both analogies and disanalogies between evolution in
essential to understanding cancer. Moreover, on this view, cancer itself whole organisms, and the evolving population of cancer cells in a tumor
may be viewed as an evolutionary process—the emergence of adaptive (Germain 2012). However, thinking of cancer as a dynamic, evolutionary
features of cancer cells, where these “adaptations” enable short term process, has great potential for applications in cancer treatment, and
“fitness,” or relative success at survival and reproduction. Several perhaps also, in prevention. For instance, some have suggested that we
scientists have developed theoretical models of this process, linking it to might give young girls drugs or nutritional supplements that remodel the
empirical data, e.g., on the emergence of chemotherapy resistance (Frank breast in ways akin to pregnancy, as a way to prevent the emergence of
2007; Wodarz & Komarova 2015). breast cancer (Katz, et al. 2015). Others suggest that modeling the
evolution of multi-drug resistance may help prevent one of the major
On this view, cancer is a both a process and byproduct of multi-level causes of cancer mortality. Drugs can be more or less effective in different
selection, where selection may be understood as operating at several levels patients, and lose their effectiveness over time. An evolutionary
of biological organization simultaneously, or sequentially (Damuth, et al. perspective on cancer may shed light on how drug resistance comes about,
1988; Lean, et al. 2016). That is, cancer cells may bear adaptations, and, in patients with more or less intratumor heterogeneity (Greaves 2000,
they are also evolutionary byproducts of selective processes at other level 2007; Frank & Nowak 2004; Merlo, et al. 2006; Greaves and Maley,
of organization. It appears that cancer cells co-opt or hijack otherwise 2010).
adaptive features of organisms. Signaling pathways that are ordinarily in
service of adaptive functions in early stages of development or wound A third type of byproduct explanation for cancer is the view that cancer is
healing are reactivated in (some) cancer cells, in service of the transition a disease of aging—that is, cancer incidence by and large increases as we
to metastasis. This is a classic example of a cross-level selective byproduct age, perhaps in part as a byproduct of breakdowns in mechanisms
(Okasha 2005, 2006). Traits advantageous at one level in the organization associated with immune response and tissue integrity. This claim raises
of multicellular organisms may be coopted by component parts. Some of some broader questions about how we assess function and dysfunction, or

36 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2019 Edition 37


Cancer Anya Plutynski

how we assess function at different temporal and spatial scales of analysis, “carcinogenic” have significant public health import, and thus raise a
as well as how we understand the role of the immune system and the variety of philosophical questions about evidence, values risk, and
integrity of the organism as an individual. Indeed, all evolutionary and precaution (Mayo, et al. 1994; Cranor 1993, 2006, 2011, 2018).
byproduct explanations of cancer raise similar philosophical questions
about hypothesis testing, as well as definitions of “function” and Evidence for such claims is often indirect, and underdetermination is rife.
“individuality,” both at the individual and group level, and over the course In tests of carcinogenicity, there is a choice of levels of significance, and
of one’s life history. On the evolutionary view of cancer, for instance, even optimally done epidemiological studies, or toxicological studies, for
cancer cells are in some sense highly adaptive (Hausman 2011; Germain instance, at best lend high probability to claims about health risk. In such
2012; Godfrey-Smith 2009). One relatively controversial view of aging, contexts, there is “inductive risk”, or the risk of error either in over- or
first proposed by August Weisman, is that aging has the evolutionary under-estimation of actual risk of cancer, and thus, room for values to play
advantage—effectively clearing the way for the young. If indeed cancer is a role. Several philosophers of science have weighed in on this matter of
a necessary byproduct of aging, and aging is selected for, then on one when and whether values ought to play a role in such contexts, as well as
view, cancer may be thought of as adaptive. Such a view raises a variety of which values, in particular precautionary judgments that may have import
questions about evidence and adaptationist explanations (see SEP entry on for policy or law (see, e.g., Mayo 1988; Douglas 2000, 2009; Brown 2013;
“Adaptation”). They also raise questions about the merits of group versus Steel 2007, 2010, 2015; Elliott 2011; Shrader-Frechette 1993, 1994, 2002,
individual level selection hypotheses. Moreover, the dual role of the 2004; and Mitchell 2009). As one might imagine, there is also a
immune system in both preventing—and paradoxically, in some cases, substantive history of debate among epidemiologists, public health
promoting cancer—raises interesting questions about the nature of scientists, scholars of the law, around when we have good reason to claim
biological individuality, as well as how we define “immunity” an the role that X or Y is carcinogenic, or what counts as good or “good enough”
of the immune system in setting out the boundaries of the organism. (For a evidence, going back to the dispute between Doll and Hill and their
vivid discussion, see, e.g., (Okasha 2006; Godfrey-Smith 2009; Bouchard detractors, regarding the causal link between smoking and lung cancer
& Huneman 2013; Clarke 2011, 2013; Love & Brigandt 2017; Bueno, et (Hill, 1965). For a compelling history of this literature, see, e.g., Proctor
al. 2019; Pradeu 2012, 2013, 2016, 2019). (1995), or more recently, Oreskes, et al. (2011). Problems of
underdetermination are no less rife in the context of assessments of
4. The Science-Value Interface and Aims of Cancer “effectiveness” of cancer screening and prevention (see, e.g., Solomon
2015; Stegenga 2017; Plutynski 2017. (For a discussion, see the entry on
Research
philosophy of medicine.)
There are several ways in which biomedical and public health research on
Second, much of basic cancer research—e.g., research on the cell and
cancer intersects with debates about the proper role of values in science.
molecular bases of the disease—is supported by federal funds, which often
First, epidemiological and toxicological research is used in support of
are allocated in the hopes that such research will (eventually) yield better
regulatory policy and toxic tort law. Decisions about when and what is
health outcomes. Yet, the relationship between “bench and bedside” is, by

38 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2019 Edition 39


Cancer Anya Plutynski

all accounts, extremely indirect, and shaped by many factors outside of the perhaps also unnecessary or unwarranted use of medical screening and
merits of the science itself. So, it’s unclear whether and how “basic” testing (Aronowitz 2007, 2009, 2015).
cancer science ought to be evaluated in light of whether or how it leads to
better health outcomes. However, this is hard to avoid, particularly when On the other hand, cancer research has led to important innovations in
so many lives depend upon a research program’s promised outcomes. science and medicine with impacts much wider than cancer itself.
Moreover, particularly in the U.S., regulations on research by, e.g., the
This whole matter is complicated by the fact that the study of cancer is FDA on the design and conduct of clinical trials for approval of drugs, for
itself big business. Indeed, some compare cancer research and medicine to instance, may in part be slowing research and leading to excessive costs.
a “medical industrial complex.” Cancer pharmaceuticals, medical devices, Some argue that we ought to lift restrictions on such tests for novel and
and cancer research more generally, are major drivers of the economy. On more “precise” (or targeted) drugs that might benefit very few. Such
the one hand, given the loss of life due to cancer, one could argue that the matters are of course intertwined with larger debates among both
time and energy devoted to cancer care and research is proportional to the clinician-researchers and philosophers of medicine around when and
threat. Löwy (1996) in her Between Bench and Bedside characterizes this whether we have sufficient evidence to claim that, e.g., this or that mode
as the “white” (optimistic) reading of the situation. Arguably, however, of intervention is effective. In part, such debates are shaped by the
many other diseases, often those more prevalent in “developing” parts of economic costs of large clinical trials, and in part, by epistemic issues
the world, cause far more extensive loss of life. As Reiss and Kitcher around what and how we can and should measure, in making claims to
(2009) and Reiss (2009) have argued, from a “Millian” perspective, we “effective” intervention (Ashcroft 2002; Cartwright 2011; Howick 2011;
ought to be expending our resources on those diseases that proportionally Stegenga 2015; Teira 2011; Teira, et al. 2015; González-Moreno, et al.
cause the greatest loss of life, and so, at least from a strictly maximizing 2015; Deaton, et al. 2018).
utilitarian perspective, these diseases have a greater claim on our
investments. The vast funds invested in cancer research—at least during One area where such questions are particularly fraught is “precision”
the past 25 years or so—have done very little to shift mortality rates. This medicine; Obama’s Reinvestment act budgeted a significant component
leads to what Löwy might call the pessimistic answer to this question. toward cancer genomics, with the idea that a more fine grained analysis of
According to one line of thinking, the centrality of cancer in biomedical the molecular and genomic features of cancer would promote more
research is a product of several historical, economic, institutional, and effective prediction and control of cancer risk, enable detection of cancers
social forces in combination, some of which are self-perpetuating (Proctor at much earlier stages, and less debilitating, more targeted treatments.
1995; Fujimura 1996; Clarke & Fujimura 2014). Ever since Nixon’s 1971 With better technologies and more fine-tuned risk information, the practice
call for a “war” on cancer, advertised implications for cancer treatment or of medicine has been shifting from diagnosis (and treatment) of disease, to
prevention have been used to bolster much of basic research into genetics, constant surveillance and intervention on disease risk, as well as higher
genomics, and cell and molecular biology, fostering investment in rates of overdiagnosis and overtreatment (diagnosis and treatment for a
biotechnology. Some have argued that this has led to an unduly excessive, proto-disease state that may never have progressed in the lifetime of a
or disproportionate fear of cancer as a disease, an excess of anxiety, and patient) (Welch, et al. 2011; Esserman, et al. 2014). Moreover, one

40 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2019 Edition 41


Cancer Anya Plutynski

concern some have raised about precision oncology is that it has been less Aktipis, C.A., Boddy, A. M., Jansen, G., Hibner, U., Hochberg, M. E.,
successful than hoped or advertised (Prasad & Gale 2016, Prasad, et al. Maley, C. C., & Wilkinson, G. S. , 2015, “Cancer across the tree of
2016). Such skepticism should raise genuine concerns—especially given life: cooperation and cheating in multicellularity”, Philosophical
the hopes of patients and families hanging upon the promises of such Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 370(1673):
treatments, and the overall costs of both cancer care, and precision 20140219.
medicine research. In sum, current practices of cancer research, screening Al-Hajj, M., & Clarke, M. F., 2004, “Self-renewal and solid tumor stem
and treatment raise a number of questions: How ought we to allocate cells”, Oncogene, 23(43): 7274.
research funds in cancer research? How is investment in precision Aronowitz, R. A., 2007, Unnatural history: Breast cancer and American
medicine likely to yield the benefits promised? When is medical society, New York: Cambridge University Press.
intervention on disease risk (rather than disease itself) unduly excessive? –––, 2009, “The converged experience of risk and disease”, The Milbank
What exactly does it mean to speak of effective medical intervention? Is Quarterly, 87(2): 417–442.
overdiagnosis and overtreatment a serious harm, or is it simply an –––, 2015, Risky medicine: our quest to cure fear and uncertainty,
inevitable byproduct of an otherwise effective strategy—treating disease Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
risk? How ought clinicians to communicate about risk and benefit of novel Ashcroft, R., 2002, “What is clinical effectiveness?”, Studies in History
targeted interventions to patients, especially where there are gray areas of and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy
benefit and harm? Are the (frequently) excessive costs of, and inequitable of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 33(2): 219–233.
access to, cancer care, matters of justice? Bailey, Matthew H., Collin Tokheim, Eduard Porta-Pardo, Sohini
Sengupta, Denis Bertrand, Amila Weerasinghe, Antonio Colaprico, et
Cancer research—and especially the hope and hype surrounding precision al., 2018, “Comprehensive characterization of cancer driver genes
medicine—provides a focused lens through which to consider problems and mutations”, Cell, 173(2): 371–385.
central to critical examination of the concepts and methods of the Bechtel, W., 2015, “Generalizing mechanistic explanations using graph-
biomedical sciences. That is, cancer and the scientific study of cancer theoretic representations”, in Explanation in Biology, P.A. Braillard
illustrate challenges facing disease classification, fuzzy borders between & C. Malaterre (eds.), Dordrecht: Springer. pp. 199–225.
disease versus health, the problems with genetic essentialism, the ever- –––, (forthcoming), “The importance of constraints and control in
present reference class problem and ever promised solutions, as well as biological mechanisms: Insights from cancer research” British
specific ways in which underdetermination of evidence in biomedicine Journal for the Philosophy of Science.
shapes matters of justice in public health. Moreover, it provides a case Bertolaso, M., 2009, “Towards an integrated view of the neoplastic
study in how matters of evidence, disease status, and questions of values phenomena in cancer research”, History and philosophy of the life
and justice are deeply intertwined. sciences, 31(1): 79–97.
–––, 2011, “The two sides of the hourglass: Analytic and synthetic
Bibliography approaches in cancer research”, Ludus vitalis: revista de filosofía de

42 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2019 Edition 43


Cancer Anya Plutynski

las ciencias de la vida, 19(35): 73–95. Broadbent, A., 2009, “Causation and models of disease in epidemiology”.
–––, 2011, “Hierarchies and causal relationships in interpretative models Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in
of the neoplastic process”, History and philosophy of the life History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences,
sciences, 33(4): 515–535. 40(4): 302–311.
–––, 2016, Philosophy of Cancer, Dordrecht: Springer Science+ Business –––, 2014, “Disease as a theoretical concept: The case of ‘HPV-itis’”,
Media Dordrecht. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in
Bertolaso, M., and Dupré, J. (2018) “A processual perspective on cancer”, History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences,
in Everything flows: towards a processual philosophy of biology, D.J. 48(1): 250–257.
Nicholson & J. Dupré (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. Brown, M. J., 2013, “Values in science beyond underdetermination and
321–336. inductive risk”, Philosophy of Science, 80(5): 829–839.
Blasimme, A., Maugeri, P., & Germain, P. L. (2013). What mechanisms Bueno, O., Chen R.-L., & Fagan, M.B. (eds.), 2019, Individuation,
can’t do: Explanatory frameworks and the function of the p53 gene in Process, and Scientific Practices, Oxford, New York: Oxford
molecular oncology. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science University Press.
Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Cairns, J., 1975, “Mutation selection and the natural history of cancer”,
Biomedical Sciences, 44(3): 374–384 Nature, 255(5505): 197.
Bonnet, D., & Dick, J. E. (1997). Human acute myeloid leukemia is Cancer Genome Atlas Network, 2015, “Comprehensive genomic
organized as a hierarchy that originates from a primitive characterization of head and neck squamous cell carcinomas”,
hematopoietic cell. Nature medicine, 3(7): 730. Nature, 517(7536): 576.
Bouchard F, Huneman P (2013) From Groups to Individuals: Perspectives Cantor, D., 2018, “Cancer: Radical Surgery and the Patient”, in The
on Biological Associations and Emerging Individuality, Cambridge, Palgrave Handbook of the History of Surgery, pp. 457–477. London:
MA: MIT Press. Palgrave Macmillan.
Bourret, P., Mogoutov, A., Julian-Reynier, C., & Cambrosio, A. (2006). A Carter, K. C., 2003, The Rise of Causal Concepts of Disease: Case
new clinical collective for French cancer genetics: A heterogeneous Histories, Aldershot: Ashgate.
mapping analysis. Science, Technology, & Human Values, 31(4): Cartwright, N., 2011, “A philosopher's view of the long road from RCTs to
431–464. effectiveness” The Lancet, 377(9775): 1400–1401.
Boyd, Richard, 1999, “Homeostasis, Species, and Higher Taxa”, in Clarke E., 2013, “The Multiple Realizability of Biological Individuals”,
Species—New Interdisciplinary Essays, R. Wilson (ed.), Cambridge: Journal of Philosophy, 110(8): 413–435.
MIT Press, pp. 141–185. –––, 2011, “The Problem of Biological Individuality”, Biological Theory
Braillard, P. A., & Malaterre, C., 2015, Explanation in Biology: An 5(4):312–325
Enquiry into the Diversity of Explanatory Patterns in the Life Clarke, A. E., & Fujimura, J. H. (eds.), 2014, The right tools for the job:
Sciences (Vol. 11). Dordrecht: Springer. At work in twentieth-century life sciences, Princeton University Press.

44 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2019 Edition 45


Cancer Anya Plutynski

Clevers, H., 2016, “Cancer therapy: defining stemness”, Nature, Philosophy of molecular medicine: Foundational issues in research
534(7606): 176. and practice, New York: Taylor & Francis.
Collins, F. S., & Barker, A. D., 2007, “Mapping the cancer genome”, Fessler, E., & Medema, J. P., 2016, “Colorectal cancer subtypes:
Scientific American, 296(3): 50–57. developmental origin and microenvironmental regulation”, Trends in
Craver, C. F., 2009, “Mechanisms and natural kinds”, Philosophical cancer, 2(9): 505–518.
Psychology, 22(5): 575–594. Foulds, L., 1958, “The natural history of cancer”, Journal of chronic
Crespi, B., & Summers, K., 2005, “Evolutionary biology of cancer”, diseases, 8(1): 2–37.
Trends in ecology & evolution, 20(10): 545–552. Frank, S. A., 2007, Dynamics of cancer: incidence, inheritance, and
Damuth J, Heisler IL, 1988, “Alternative formulations of multilevel evolution, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
selection”, Biology and Philosophy, 3:407–430. Fujimura, J. H., 1987, “Constructing ‘Do-able’ Problems in Cancer
Deaton, A., & Cartwright, N., 2018, “Understanding and Research: Articulating Alignment”, Soc. Stud. Science, 17(2): 257–
misunderstanding randomized controlled trials”, Social Science & 293.
Medicine, 210: 2–21. –––, 1996, Crafting science: A sociohistory of the quest for the genetics of
Douglas, H., 2000, “Inductive risk and values in science”, Philosophy of cancer, Harvard University Press.
science, 67(4): 559–579. Germain, P-L. 2012, “Cancer Cells and Adaptive Explanations”, Biology
Dupré, J., 1995, The disorder of things: Metaphysical foundations of the and Philosophy 27 (6):785–810.
disunity of science, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. –––, 2014, “Living instruments and theoretical terms: Xenografts as
Elliott, K. C., 2011, Is a little pollution good for you?: Incorporating measurements in cancer research”, in New Directions in the
societal values in environmental research, New York: Oxford Philosophy of Science, pp. 141–155, Cham, Switzerland: Springer.
University Press USA. Germain, P. L., & Laplane, L. 2017, “Metastasis as supra-cellular
Ereshefsky, M., 2009, “Defining ‘health’ and ‘disease’”, Studies in History selection? A reply to Lean and Plutynski”, Biology & Philosophy,
and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy 32(2): 281–287.
of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 40(3): 221–227. Godfrey-Smith, P. 2009, Darwinian populations and natural selection,
Ereshefsky, M., & Reydon, T. A., 2015, “Scientific kinds”, Philosophical Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Studies, 172(4): 969–986. González-Moreno, M., Saborido, C., & Teira, D. 2015, “Disease-
Esserman, L. J., Thompson, I. M., Reid, B., Nelson, P., Ransohoff, D. F., mongering through clinical trials”, Studies in History and Philosophy
Welch, H. G., … & Bissell, M., 2014, “Addressing overdiagnosis and of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological
overtreatment in cancer: a prescription for change”, The Lancet and Biomedical Sciences, 51: 11–18.
oncology, 15(6): e234–e242. Greaves, M., 2001, Cancer: the evolutionary legacy, Oxford: Oxford
Fagan, M., 2016, “Pathways to the clinic: cancer stem cells and challenges University Press.
for translational research”, in G. Boniolo & M.J. Nathan (eds.), Greaves, M., & Maley, C. C., 2012, “Clonal evolution in cancer”, Nature,

46 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2019 Edition 47


Cancer Anya Plutynski

481(7381): 306. Perspectives in biology and medicine, 51(3): 367–378.


Green, S., forthcoming, “Is there a ‘right’ level or scale of analysis? Some Lapidot, T., Sirard, C., Vormoor, J., Murdoch, B., Hoang, T., Caceres-
lessons from cancer research”, in J. diFrisco, D. Brooks, & W. Cortes, J., … & Dick, J. E., 1994, “A cell initiating human acute
Wimsatt (eds.), Hierarchy and Levels of Organization, The Vienna myeloid leukaemia after transplantation into SCID mice”, Nature,
Series in Theoretical Biology, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. 367(6464): 645.
Green, S. Serban, M. Scholl, Jones, N. Brigandt, I. and Bechtel, W., 2018, Laplane, L., 2018, “Cancer stem cells modulate patterns and processes of
“Network analyses in systems biology: New strategies for dealing evolution in cancers”, Biology & Philosophy, 33(3–4): 18.
with biological complexity”, Synthese, 195:1751–1777 –––, 2016, Cancer Stem Cells, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Hanahan, D., & Weinberg, R. A., 2000, “The hallmarks of cancer”, Cell, Laplane, L. and Solary, E. 2019. “Philosophy of Biology: Towards a
100(1): 57–70. classification of stem cells”, eLife 2019;8:e46563 DOI:
–––, 2011. “Hallmarks of cancer: the next generation”, Cell, 144(5): 646– 10.7554/eLife.46563.
674. Lean, C. and Plutynski, A., 2016. “The Evolution of Failure: Explaining
Hausman, D. M., 2012, “Health, naturalism, and functional efficiency”, Cancer as an Evolutionary Process”, Biology and Philosophy 31(1):
Philosophy of Science, 79(4): 519–541. 39–57.
Hoadley, Katherine A., Christina Yau, Denise M. Wolf, Andrew D. Love AC, Brigandt I., 2017, “Philosophical Dimensions of Individuality”,
Cherniack, David Tamborero, Sam Ng, Max DM Leiserson, et al., in S. Lidgard and L.K. Nyhart (eds.), Biological Individuality:
2014, “Multiplatform analysis of 12 cancer types reveals molecular Integrating Scientific, Philosophical, and Historical Perspectives,
classification within and across tissues of origin”, Cell 158(4): 929– Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
944. Love, A. M. Travisano, K. Liu., 2017, “How Cancer Spreads:
Hoadley, K. A., Yau, C., Hinoue, T., Wolf, D. M., Lazar, A. J., Drill, E., … Reconceptualizing a Disease”, in G. Boliolo & M. J. Nathan (eds.),
& Akbani, R., 2018, “Cell-of-origin patterns dominate the molecular Philosophy of Molecular Medicine: Foundational Issues in Research
classification of 10,000 tumors from 33 types of cancer”, Cell, and Practice, New York and London: Routledge. pp. 100–121.
173(2): 291–304. Löwy, I., 1996, Between bench and bedside: science, healing, and
Howick, J. H., 2011, The philosophy of evidence-based medicine, interleukin-2 in a cancer ward, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley & Sons. Press.
Khalidi, M.A.K., 1998, “Natural kinds and crosscutting categories”, The Machamer, P., Darden, L., & Craver, C. F., 2000, “Thinking about
Journal of Philosophy, 95(1): 33–50. mechanisms”, Philosophy of Science, 67(1): 1–25.
–––, 2013, Natural categories and human kinds: Classification in the Malaterre, C., 2007, “Organicism and reductionism in cancer research:
natural and social sciences, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Towards a systemic approach”, International Studies in the
Kincaid, H., 2008, “Do We Need Theory to Study Disease?: lessons from Philosophy of Science, 21(1): 57–73.
cancer research and their implications for mental illness”, –––, 2011, “Making sense of Downward Causation in Manipulationism

48 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2019 Edition 49


Cancer Anya Plutynski

(with Illustrations from Cancer Research)”, History and Philosophy paradigm, 1975–1985”, Journal of the History of Biology, 30(1): 1–
of the Life Sciences (33): 537–562. 29.
Marcum, J. A., 2005, “Metaphysical presuppositions and scientific –––, 2003, “History of cancer research”, Encyclopedia of life sciences,
practices: Reductionism and organicism in cancer research”, London: Nature Publishing Group
International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 19(1): 31–45. –––, 2007, “The field of cancer research: an indicator of present
Mariotto, A. B., Robin Yabroff, K., Shao, Y., Feuer, E. J., & Brown, M. L., transformations in biology”, Oncogene, 26(55): 7607–7610.
2011, “Projections of the cost of cancer care in the United States: –––, 2015, “Is There an Explanation for… the Diversity of Explanations in
2010–2020”, Journal of the National Cancer Institute, 103(2): 117– Biological Studies?”, in Braillard, P. A., C. Malaterre, eds.
128. Explanation in Biology: An Enquiry into the Diversity of Explanatory
Martincorena, Iñigo, Amit Roshan, Moritz Gerstung, Peter Ellis, Peter Van Patterns in the Life Sciences, Dordrecht: Springer, pp. 31–46
Loo, Stuart McLaren, David C. Wedge, et al. “High burden and Nelson, C. M., & Bissell, M. J., 2006, “Of extracellular matrix, scaffolds,
pervasive positive selection of somatic mutations in normal human and signaling: tissue architecture regulates development,
skin”, Science 348, no. 6237 (2015): 880–886. homeostasis, and cancer”, Annu. Rev. Cell Dev. Biol., 22: 287–309.
Maugeri, P. and Blasimme, A. 2011. “Humanized Models of Cancer in Öhlund, D., Handly-Santana, A., Biffi, G., Elyada, E., Almeida, A. S.,
Molecular Medicine: The Experimental Control of Disanalogy”, Ponz-Sarvise, M., … & Chio, I. I. C., 2017, “Distinct populations of
History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 33 (4): 603–621. inflammatory fibroblasts and myofibroblasts in pancreatic cancer”,
Mayo, D. G., & Hollander, R. D. (eds.), 1994, Acceptable evidence: Journal of Experimental Medicine, 214(3): 579–596.
Science and values in risk management, Oxford: Oxford University Okasha, S., 2005, “Multilevel selection and the major transitions in
Press on Demand. evolution”, Philosophy of science, 72(5): 1013–1025.
Mayo, D. G., & Spanos, A., 2006, “Philosophical scrutiny of evidence of –––, 2006, Evolution and the levels of selection, Oxford: Oxford
risks: From bioethics to bioevidence”, Philosophy of Science, 73(5): University Press.
803–816. Oreskes, N., & Conway, E. M., 2011, Merchants of doubt: How a handful
Merlo, L. M., Pepper, J. W., Reid, B. J., & Maley, C. C., 2006, “Cancer as of scientists obscured the truth on issues from tobacco smoke to
an evolutionary and ecological process” Nature reviews cancer, global warming, New York: Bloomsbury Publishing USA.
6(12): 924–935. Pierce, G. B., & Speers, W. C., 1988, “Tumors as caricatures of the
Mitchell, S. D., 2009, Unsimple truths: Science, complexity, and policy, process of tissue renewal: prospects for therapy by directing
Chicago: University of Chicago Press. differentiation”, Cancer research, 48(8): 1996–2004.
Moss, L., 2004, What genes can't do, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Plutynski, A. 2012, “Ethical Issues in Cancer Screening and Prevention”,
Morange, M., 1993, “The Discovery of Cellular Oncogenes”, History and Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 37 (3):310–323.
Philosophy of the Life Sciences, 15(1): 45–58 –––, 2013, “Cancer and the Goals of Integration”, History and Philosophy
–––, 1997, “From the regulatory vision of cancer to the oncogene of Science Part C (4):466–476.

50 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2019 Edition 51


Cancer Anya Plutynski

–––, 2017, “Safe or Sorry? Cancer Screening and Inductive Risk”, in Fundamentos de la Ciencia, 24(3): 263–282.
Exploring Inductive Risk: Case Studies of Values in Science, K.C. Schedin, P., 2006, “Pregnancy-associated breast cancer and metastasis”,
Elliott & T. Richards (eds.), pp. 149–171. Nature Reviews Cancer, 6(4): 281.
–––, 2018, Explaining Cancer: Finding Order in Disorder, New York: Schwartz, P. H., 2007, “Defining dysfunction: Natural selection, design,
Oxford University Press. and drawing a line”, Philosophy of Science, 74(3): 364–385.
Pradeu, T., 2012, The Limits of the Self: Immunology and Biological –––, 2008, “Risk and disease”, Perspectives in Biology and Medicine,
Identity, New York: Oxford University Press. 51(3): 320–334.
–––, 2013, “Immunity and the emergence of individuality” in From –––, 2014, “Small tumors as risk factors not disease”, Philosophy of
Groups to Individuals: Evolution and Emerging Individuality, F. Science, 81(5): 986–998.
Bouchard and P. Huneman (eds.), Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp Shrader-Frechette, K. S., 1993, Burying uncertainty: Risk and the case
77–96 against geological disposal of nuclear waste, San Francisco:
–––, 2016, “The many faces of biological individuality”, Biology and University of California Press.
Philosophy, 31:761–773. –––, 2002, Environmental justice: Creating equality, reclaiming
–––, forthcoming, Philosophy of Immunology: Understanding the Central democracy, New York: Oxford University Press.
Role of the Immune System in Today’s Biology and Medicine, –––, 2007, Taking action, saving lives: our duties to protect environmental
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. and public health, New York: Oxford University Press.
Prasad, V., & Gale, R. P., 2016, “Precision medicine in acute myeloid –––, 2012, Risk analysis and scientific method: Methodological and
leukemia: Hope, hype or both?”, Leukemia research, 48: 73–77. ethical problems with evaluating societal hazards, Netherlands:
Prasad, V., Fojo, T., & Brada, M., 2016, “Precision oncology: origins, Springer Science & Business Media.
optimism, and potential” The Lancet Oncology, 17(2): e81–e86. Siegel, R. L., Miller, K. D., & Jemal, A., 2017, “Cancer statistics, 2017”,
Proctor, R. N., 1996, Cancer Wars: How Politics Shapes What We Know CA: a cancer journal for clinicians, 67(1): 7–30
and Don’t Know About Cancer, New York: Basic Books. Slater, M. H., 2014, “Natural kindness”, The British Journal for the
Reid, L., 2017, “Truth or Spin? Disease Definition in Cancer Screening”, Philosophy of Science, 66(2): 375–411.
Journal of Medicine and Philosophy: A Forum for Bioethics and Solomon, M., 2015, Making medical knowledge, New York: Oxford
Philosophy of Medicine 42 (4):385–404. University Press, USA.
Reiss, J., 2010, “In favour of a Millian proposal to reform biomedical Solomon, M., Simon, J. R., & Kincaid, H. (eds.)., 2016, The Routledge
research”, Synthese, 177(3): 427–447. companion to philosophy of medicine, New York: Taylor & Francis.
–––, 2015, “A pragmatist theory of evidence”, Philosophy of Science, Sorenson, R., 2011, “Paranatural Kinds” in Carving Nature at Its Joints:
82(3): 341–362. Natural Kinds in Metaphysics and Science, J. K. Campbell, M.
Reiss, J., and Kitcher, P., 2009, Biomedical research, neglected diseases, O'Rourke, & M. H. Slater (eds.), Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. 113–
and well-ordered science. THEORIA. Revista de Teoría, Historia y 128.

52 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2019 Edition 53


Cancer Anya Plutynski

Soto, A. M., & Sonnenschein, C., 2012, “Is systems biology a promising epithelium”, Cancer cell, 2(3): 205–216.
approach to resolve controversies in cancer research?”, Cancer cell Williams, Neil E., 2011, “Arthritis and nature’s joints”, in Carving Nature
international, 12(1): 1–5. at Its Joints: Natural Kinds in Metaphysics and Science, Joseph Keim
–––, 2004, “The somatic mutation theory of cancer: growing problems Campbell, Michael O'Rourke, & Matthew H. Slater (eds.),
with the paradigm?”, Bioessays, 26(10): 1097–1107. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 199–230.
–––, 2005, “Emergentism as a default: cancer as a problem of tissue Zheng, Siyuan, Andrew D. Cherniack, Ninad Dewal, Richard A. Moffitt,
organization”, Journal of Biosciences, 30(1): 103–11 Ludmila Danilova, Bradley A. Murray, Antonio M. Lerario, et al.,
Steel, D., 2007, Across the boundaries: Extrapolation in biology and 2016, “Comprehensive pan-genomic characterization of
social science, Oxford: Oxford University Press. adrenocortical carcinoma”, Cancer cell, 2995: 723–736.
–––, 2010, “Epistemic values and the argument from inductive risk”,
Philosophy of Science, 77(1): 14–34. Academic Tools
–––, 2015, Philosophy and the precautionary principle, New York:
Cambridge University Press. How to cite this entry.
Stegenga, J., 2015, “Measuring effectiveness”, Studies in History and Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP
Society.
Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of
Look up this entry topic at the Indiana Philosophy Ontology
Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 54: 62–71.
Project (InPhO).
–––, 2018, Medical Nihilism, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers, with links
Teira, D., & Reiss, J., 2013, “Causality, impartiality and evidence-based to its database.
policy”, in Mechanism and causality in biology and economics Illari,
P., Russo, F., and Williamson, J., eds., Dordrecht: Springer, pp. 207– Other Internet Resources
224.
Weinberg, R., 2013, The Biology of Cancer, New York: Garland science. NCI Budget and Appropriations, (National Cancer Institute)
Weaver, V. M., Petersen, O. W., Wang, F., Larabell, C. A., Briand, P., eLife Cancer Biology
Damsky, C., & Bissell, M. J., 1997, “Reversion of the malignant Philosophy in Cancer Biology Workshop, Bordeaux (2018)
phenotype of human breast cells in three-dimensional culture and in The Cancer Genome Atlas (TCGA) Program, maintained by the
vivo by integrin blocking antibodies”, The Journal of cell biology, National Cancer Institute, at the National Institutes of Health, USA.
137(1): 231–245.
Weaver, V. M., Lelièvre, S., Lakins, J. N., Chrenek, M. A., Jones, J. C., Related Entries
Giancotti, F., … & Bissell, M. J., 2002, “β4 integrin-dependent
formation of polarized three-dimensional architecture confers genomics and postgenomics | health | mechanism in science | medicine,
resistance to apoptosis in normal and malignant mammary philosophy of | systems and synthetic biology

54 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2019 Edition 55


Cancer

Copyright © 2019 by the author


Anya Plutynski

56 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy

You might also like