You are on page 1of 25

Réseaux.

The French journal of


communication

The intentions of communication


Pierre Livet, Pauline Ridel

Abstract
Summary: Analysis of communication usually strives to define the conditions for successful communication either in terms of
tautologous definitions or by requiring an impossible use of reflexive talents. This article offers a critique of the pragmatists
'theory of 'model' communication through a consideration of three levels of interaction: informative intention, communicative
intention and the intention to communicate.

Citer ce document / Cite this document :

Livet Pierre, Ridel Pauline. The intentions of communication. In: Réseaux. The French journal of communication, volume 2,
n°1, 1994. pp. 151-175;

doi : https://doi.org/10.3406/reso.1994.3265

https://www.persee.fr/doc/reso_0969-9864_1994_num_2_1_3265

Fichier pdf généré le 12/04/2018


8

THE INTENTIONS OF

COMMUNICATION

Pierre LIVET

Translated by Pauline Ridel

Summary: Analysis of communication usually strives to define


the conditions for successful communication either in terms of
tautologous definitions or by requiring an impossible use of
reflexive talents. This article offers a critique of the

pragmatists 'theory of 'model' communication through a


consideration of three levels of interaction: informative intention,
communicative intention and the intention to communicate. 151
THE INTENTIONS OF COMMUNICATION

first approach leads us into tautology, the


8 THE second, as I shall demonstrate, requires
reflexive talents that we are unable to put
into practice.
INTENTIONS
A third line of thinking connects with the
approach of Sperber and Wilson (1986).
They criticize, as I shall, the classic
OF
account according to which the object of the
pragmatists'
theory is 'a mechanism (of
communication) which, when it is
COMMUNICATION
correctly operated and is not interfered with
by noise, guarantees the success of the
communication.'*
For them, these
mechanisms assure communication a success
that is 'at best probable, but not certain".
The pragmatists believe in this theory of
'model* communication because they
conceive of communication in terms of code.
Communication then becomes an
operation of encoding for the speaker and of
decoding for the hearer. For Sperber and
Wilson, this theory supposes that the
meaning communicated is defined by the
encoded utterance, which the hearer has
only to receive. To this notion of
Pierre LIVET communication as code, Sperber and Wilson
oppose an 'inferential' conception. The
hearer must not merely decode but must
add to the transmitted message a grasp of
contextual data. The message itself is
always incomplete. The hearer must round
Analysis of communication usu-
it out by making inferences based on his
sally adopts what I will call the own knowledge and on the givens of the
point of view of 'model*
situation. Such a theory is characterized
communication. This involves
by the double concern of thinking of
defining the conditions in which a communication as an expansion of the code
communication can be said to be by inferences, while at the same time
successful and to correspond perfectly to the setting limits on the inferences deemed
model. Two approaches are possible: in possible; they cannot be infinitely
Searle's, defects of communication are extended and they must be efficient. We
left out of consideration, reducing the shall see however that this efficiency is
approach to a tautologous definition of not assured, at least with regard to the
the conditions for satisfactory problem of guarantees of the conditions
communication, and above all for their verification for successful communication, because
(Searle, 1985). The second path, taken for Sperber and Wilson, despite their
example by Strawson, seeks to overcome apparent rejection of the theory of 'model'
these defects in advance by adding
communication, still do not conceive of acts
constraints to the definition of true of communication as means of remedying
communication (Strawson, 1965). But while the
La Pertinence, Editions de Minuit, 1989, p. 33 (trans); Blackwell, 1986.
153
Pierre LIVET

the defects of communication, rather requirements of the theory of 'model'


than aiming to achieve perfect communication. But as we shall see, they
communication. encounter the same difficulties as that
theory.
Instead of dwelling now on the tautologies
of Searle (we will come back to them in The first problem to be considered is
connection with actualized language), I knowing to what extent a hearer can be
shall try to demonstrate that taking the assured of having correctly identified the
theory of 'model' communication as a meaning of a communication, its
framework for reflection soon leads to intention or, if you will, the rule governing the
aporia when we consider the problem of conduct of the communication. This is the
the conditions for validating communica- most general problem and it has been
, tion, its guarantees of success, and the raised by Kripke in his interpretive essay
conditions for its failure and breakdown. on Wittgenstein (Kripke, 1982). It goes
I shall then attempt to understand hand in hand with the notion of
communication as a body of procedures that informative intention. The second problem is that
enable us not to obtain model of the reflexivity of communicative
communication but to identify the failures in intention. Does this reflexivity require an
communication and overcome them in order infinite regression of first-degree intentions
to restart the process. Communication to second-degree intentions, and so on?
then is indeed, as Sperber and Wilson This problem was first raised by Straw-
assert, 'governed by an imperfect son, following Grice (Strawson, 1965) and
heuristic'. It is also true that 'the fact that I will refer to the ways in which it has been
communication encounters failures is handled first by Recanati then by Sperber
normal'. But instead of concluding that and Wilson. The third problem is posed
the study of communication should start by language acts. It has been said that
from this 'normal' situation, which, as it uttering them is sufficient to perform
must face up to the possibility of failure, them, or even that to state an intention to
must also comprise the means needed to carry them out, and for this intention to
overcome it, so as to avoid a breakdown be recognized, is to have performed them.
of communication and carry out ongoing They are therefore 'self-validating'. That
corrections, Sperber and Wilson draw the would be a remarkable privilege, which
conclusion that 'what is mysterious, what would at last give us access to
requires an explanation, is not the self-assured communication freed from the
failures of communication but its problems of validation and the need to
successes.'* correct possible failures. We will see that
In other words, the exception
(success), and only the exception, must this privilege has been greatly
be explained in order to understand the exaggerated.
rule. But, since the heuristic is imperfect,
successes will be partial. Now, a partial In tackling these three problems I will
success is also a partial failure, or even a review three levels of communication: the
failure that has been partially corrected level of informative intention, which
or prevented. Sperber and Wilson do not informs without communicating; the level
however take these failures and their of communicative intention; and the level
correction procedures as their point of of what Recanati terms the intention to
departure. They do not really move beyond the communicate (Recanati, 1979; Recanati,
theory that considers failures and their 1987), in which the informative intention
correction as makeshift solutions. They concerns precisely the possibility of
content themselves with weakening the modifying the attitudes of the communicating
* La Pertinence, p. 74.
154
THE INTENTIONS OF COMMUNICATION

parties towards others or, more exactly, 'that the recognition of sub-intention 1
their attitudes towards the attitudes of should be at least one of the reasons for
others. This is the level on which the reply by or the effect produced on the
communication aims to modify itself, as it receiver.* This sub-intention 1 comprised
were (Recanati, 1987, pp. 176-216). in the communicative intention can be
termed the 'informative' intention. The
We owe the definition of the first two levels communicative intention is distinct from
to Grice, who sought to reduce the the informative intention because it
semantic notion of meaning to that of pragmatic requires recognition of the former. I shall
intentions, and to reduce pragmatic therefore start with the informative
intentions of 'non-natural' meaning to intention, as it is the first level of
ordinary intentions. In his 1957 article communication.
'Meaning', and later in a 1968 article, he
defines the notion of 'non-natural'
meaning (linguistic meaning, but also Identification of the
gestures, etc.) as follows: 'For hearer A,
informative intention
speaker U has the intention that his
utterance x should produce an effect (reply)
E on A by means of recognition of that It is necessary then, in order to
intention.' (Grice, 1968). communicate, to wish to alert someone to a piece
of information and to make it available to
The aim is to reduce the intention of him. By breaking branches as I go, I can
'non-natural* inform my friend who is looking for me of
meaning to a simple
intention. Let us suppose that Paul, by a hand the path I have taken. This information is
gesture, points one way at a crossroads. not necessarily a communication, as my
The result of the intention of non-natural friend might simply conclude that when I
meaning on the receiver, providing the passed that way I broke the branches as
communication is successful, is that the I ran by. Or maybe I had the intention of
receiver infers that Paul has said x, or giving information about my passage
made the gesture x, with the intention without necessarily having the intention
that he, the hearer, should think that that he should recognize my intention to
Paul believes he knows the right way, and inform (in fact, it is sufficient that he
draws the conclusion that Paul does know should follow my trail) . It cannot therefore
it. But this result is precisely the be stated in this case that there has been
conjunction of the effect sought by the intention an intention to communicate, even
of non-natural meaning (the belief that though there has been an informative
Paul knows the right way) and the intention. It would perhaps be different if
recognition of the speaker's intention (he made I had used broken branches to form an
the gesture with the intention that the arrow shape on the ground. Nevertheless,
receiver should have that belief). an informative intention is not the same
Therefore, according to Grice, the intention of as a simple indication. It cannot be said
non-natural meaning (the communicative that fire has an informative intention in
intention) can be reduced to a 'simple' letting smoke rise into the air, and yet
intention. smoke is undoubtedly an indication of
fire. For there to be an informative
This simple intention is in fact rather intention, we must have the intention of giving
complicated. It encompasses a first sub- an indication, but not necessarily the
intention 1 : 'to produce a certain effect on intention that this intention should be
the receiver'; a second sub-intention 2: recognized.
'that the receiver should recognize
sub-intention Г; and a third sub-intention 3: The notion of informative intention can be
155
Pierre LIVET

translated into that of 'rule'. An counts for the action, we can never
informative intention defines a rule of action guarantee that the rule we propose as an
(make sure to break the branches, or to interpretation of the action is the right
let the smoke rise). It can be thought one. Kripke takes an as example the rule
possible to have an intention in an action of addition. I think I am applying the rule
without following a rule (we would have 'plus' when, by adding 68 and 57, 1 come
an end, but we would not define the up with the answer 125. 1 know that the
means). However, it seems impossible to rule 'plus' as I have used it in the past
have an informative intention without should give me, in this case, that result.
following a rule, because the idea of an end But a sceptic comes up to me and asks
(information) must be given using whether, in the past, I had not in fact been
available means (indications). But then the applying the rule 'quus', which gives the
problem of identification of the same results as addition so long as the
informative intention is equivalent to the problem numbers to be added do not exceed 57,
of identification of the rule that is but otherwise gives the answer 5. How
followed. Certainly we can interpret clues can I be sure that I have not until now
and acquire information without having been applying the rule 'quus' with the
to identify the informative intention itself. intention of reaching the answer 5 in the
But when we wish to move on to the stage case of 68 + 57? It can be seen that the
of communication we must obviously be problemintentions
others' is one ofbutdiscerning
also our own.
not More
only
able to identify the informative intention
because that is what gives meaning to the precisely, it is a question of being able to
clues. In considering the problem of prove to someone else that my intention
identifying the rule I am therefore already is such and such.
raising the problem of communication, but
Kripke shows that it is impossible to give
from the point of view of the hearer or the
this positive proof. All past facts are just
interpreter. I will go on to pose the same
as compatible with the hypothesis that I
problem from the point of view of the used the 'plus' rule as with the hypothesis
speaker, asking how the speaker can that I used the 'quus' rule (it was in fact
hope for recognition of his communicative
the first time that I had added numbers
intention. Up to this point the speaker or
exceeding 57). He says it is not a question
informer does not need to have the
of a simple problem of induction, or more
intention to communicate. He is not concerned
exactly it is not a question of predicting
whether the communicative intention of
someone else's replies, or my own. In that
his action is recognized; it is sufficient for
case we would remain at the level of
him that the information is received or
description. It is a matter of knowing what
inferred. The receiver however is already
meaning I wished to give to 'adding'. Was
trying to identify the informer's signifying it 'plus' or 'quus'? This question cannot
intention: what did he mean by breaking
be answered by resorting to dispositions.
branches, or making such a gesture?
Disposition is defined as the potentiality
But, as Kripke has shown, this to produce given behaviour in given
identification of the rule followed by the informer conditions. That is also a descriptive notion,
cannot be guaranteed. Kripke starts from which permits us to anticipate a certain
Wittgenstein's paradox of the rule: no sequence of events. However, Kripke
action can be determined by a rule, because stresses that the problem is not
rule.*
all actions can be determined by a descriptive but normative. The meaning of
In other words, because we can always 'adding' is the intention to follow a rule. It is
imagine a rule, however odd, that therefore a normative intention, which
* Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, p. 201.
156
THE INTENTIONS OF COMMUNICATION

confers the meaning 'plus' or 'quus' to the positive assurance, how we can add a
act of adding. It might be possible to make more positive note to Kripke's sceptical
the descriptive and the normative solution. We can be sure that no-one will
intersect at infinity. But the difficulty is that, ask us to prove that we are not using the
in order to prove to ourselves that in the 'quus' rule. We would have to be
past we have in fact had the normative, transported into a community that habitually
and therefore infinite, intention used the 'quus' rule to be asked questions
corresponding to the 'plus' rule, we have only about the way we add up. These questions
a body of finite data. The same difficulty would not be 'Can you prove to us that
arises if we resort to our dispositions, you use the "quus" rule?' but on the
since as they describe a sequence of contrary *Why do you not use the "quus"
potential events that can occur during our rule?' Or rather, they would simply say to
lifetimes, they too are finite. Nor can we us, as on Putnam's Twin Earth, *Why do
hope to resolve the question by producing you not use the "plus" rule?' and the
a computational model of ourselves, a strangeness for us of this question would
sort of computer that would simulate us make us suspect that the inhabitants of
perfectly, that we have built solely to that country meant some other rule by
operate under the 'plus' rule - because that.
another computational model built to follow
the 'quus' rule would just as perfectly So, to find out the informative intentions
simulate my past operations. of the other party we have available these
two certitudes:
Kripke does not however abandon us to
this aporia. To be sure, he admits the (1) As interpreters, we can always
impossibility of giving the sceptic a perceive that they are not using the
positive reply. But we can find a sceptical rule that defines the meaning, the
solution to a sceptical aporia. I cannot intention, of their information in the
positively assure the members of my sense in which we understand it;
community, including myself, that in the past
I have in fact used the 'plus' rule and not (2) As informers, when our use of
the 'quus' rule. But as I recognize that I the meaning of words is not in clear
am part of a community, I accept that contradiction with the rules of the
others can test my ability to use the 'plus' community, they will never ask us
rule. If, for adding numbers exceeding 57, to prove that we are in fact using the
I give the answer 5, 1 have not applied the explicit information we are giving in
'plus' rule. When the community, the sense we confer on it. They can
according to Kripke, accepts the conditional: 'If no doubt tell us that our
an individual follows such and such a information was ambiguous or had lapsed
rule, he must do this and that on such into error, that we did not give it its
and such an occasion', it does so only in proper meaning, but these are
its contraposed form: 'If he does not do simply refutations, not demands to
this and that on such and such an prove that our information does in
occasion, then he is not following this rule'. In fact carry the meaning we say it
short, we can have negative assurances does rather than some other
but not positive ones (Kripke, 1982, p. meaning. What is more, those who
108). criticize us must either show us
that our information is in
Nor could we prove that we were following contradiction with the rule that we say we are
the 'quus' rule. This remark gives us an following, or provide another rule,
indication of how this negative assurance another meaning, which does not
can be transformed into an apparently simply refer to the meaning we have
157
Pierre LIVET

proposed and add something to it. him and that he is driving in a way
On the contrary, they must base intended in principle to avoid him. Of
our information on this other course the approaching driver might want
meaning, and make the meaning we to crash into me, but in that case if I move
intended into a proposition derived to my left, he will again move to my left,
from this new meaning. thus giving me new information which
forces me to revise my hypothesis about
Asking the questions 'In what sense are his original informative intention.
you using such and such a word?', 'What
exactly is your informative intention?' is We can see how the procedure is
therefore meaningless, if we do not triggered. First of all we start with a
presuppose by that, and if we cannot framework hypothesis: drivers will avoid each
establish, that the use of the word or the other; and with a hypothesis of the act of
supposed informative intention are driving - most people drive on the right.
difficult to accept and do not fit the situation. As long as we can maintain these
We of course have to presuppose that the hypotheses by taking into account the
situation has a meaning, without being informative intentions of the driving methods
able to clarify it totally, since once again observed, we maintain these hypotheses.
the question of clarification itself only When a distortion arises, a conflict that
takes on meaning if the information given endangers our action or which does not
does not correspond with the situation. correspond to the expectations based on
This 'procedure' always requires a hypo- our hypothesis, then we revise our
thetically meaningful situation. This hypothesis of the act of driving and we assume
hypothesis is either accepted, although it that the other driver has an informative
can never be definitively confirmed, or is intention to warn us of the necessity of
called into question when the procedure this revision. When this hypothesis about
is set in motion. the other's informative intention also
contradicts our action, we revise our
We can observe this procedure in action framework hypothesis.
in a practical situation. Let us consider
the problem of driving in traffic. We will In other words, it seems that the
suppose first of all that there is no informative intention is bound up in these re-
highway code laying down whether we should examinations of practical or framework
drive on the right or the left. I tend to drive hypotheses. Having an informative
on the right. Suddenly I see a vehicle intention is therefore to take account of a
approaching in the other direction, on the distortion of the situation in relation to
driver's left-hand side of the road. Taking the hypotheses assumed to be followed by
evasive action, I first move further over to others, or to our own, and preferring to
the right, following my first hypothesis. If modify our action so as to sustain it rather
the other driver crosses back to his right- than see it fail. So information always
hand side I conclude that he realizes that seems to be linked to a negation. It is a
he has not followed the correct rule. I weak negation, because it is no more than
therefore maintain my own hypothesis. If a deviation, and it simply raises the
he moves even further to his left, I would problem of revising an intention or a rule. But
be obliged to steer to my left to avoid him we do not perceive the rule as such until
and I would question the validity and this difficulty arises. Rules are entities
generality of my hypothesis of driving. The that come into being, as retrospectively
deviations from the original direction supposed working or framework
therefore have an informative value in this hypotheses, only when their validity is
case: through them, each driver gives the questioned. It is therefore not surprising that
other the information that he has seen we are unable to prove their existence
158
THE INTENTIONS OF COMMUNICATION

when this validity is not challenged, and aware of this communicative intention.
that we are able to establish only their The first is that proposed by Grice, which
inadequacy. I mentioned in my introduction. For
Grice, the communicative intention is
made up of three sub-intentions:
The communicative intention
(1) To produce an effect on and
But does this not set us an even thornier elicit a response from the receiver;
problem? How can we know that the other
party entertains such a hypothesis? (2) That intention 1 should be
Where do these 'hypotheses' and recognized by the receiver;
'suppositions' about hypotheses come from, and
on what are they based? The problem is (3) That the satisfaction of 1
not really acute as long as we remain on depends partly on its being recognized
the level of informative intention, which (and therefore on the satisfaction of
does not pretend to be recognized by 2)
others but which aims simply to give
others the possibility of modifying their If we restrict ourselves to the informative
hypotheses. In the case of the two drivers intention we could at a pinch accept the
it is not important that the other should behaviourist definition of 1. All we need
hold the hypotheses that I attribute to do then is observe behavioural responses,
him; it is sufficient that we avoid each provided that we are not concerned to find
other, that our actions do not cancel each out whether other people's hypotheses
other out. In a situation in which action have changed as a result of our
can be deferred, as in the case of the information. But since in the case of the
broken branches, the informer leaves communicative intention we seek recognition
others complete freedom to recognize his of our intention by other people, we must
intention or not. Knowing whether or not pay attention to their intentions. The
the hypotheses imputed to him were effects that concern us are therefore no
correct is therefore a matter of indifference to longer simply in the order of behaviour
him. that can be observed from the exterior.
Recanti proposes redescribing intention 1
It is different when we turn to the subject as an intention to give 'reason to believe*
of communicative intention. In that case that a certain number of 'prototypical'
the communicator wishes not only that conditions have been satisfied. In doing
the receiver should receive the this, we require both more and less than
information made available to him but also that an observable behavioural effect. More,
he should recognize the intention of the because we suppose an unobservable,
communicator to give him this which refers to the mental states of the
information. Moreover, as the greater includes the receiver. Less, because the communicator
lesser, if the receiver is able to recognize does not mean to make others believe
this communicative intention, he will also something, only to give reason for belief.
have access to the information, since the The receiver is free to believe or not. This
communicative intention consists in precaution is necessary because I can use
having the informative intention recognized. irony when communicating and therefore
As Recanati notes, recognition of the not wish my receiver to take what I say
communicative intention is a sufficient literally. Intention 2 should therefore be
condition for its satisfaction. rewritten as an intention that 1 should be
recognized as an intention to give reason
In Meaning and Force, Recanati analyses to believe P (P being the prototypical
in detail the different ways of becoming conditions).
159
Pierre LIVET

We have thus both reinforced the wishes cannot be reached in 'real life' (Grice,
of the communicator (he wants his 1982). Recanati notes the equivalence,
intention to be recognized) and weakened his from the cognitive standpoint, of this
requirements for verification (he can only notion of an infinity of representations piled
hope to give reasons for this recognition, one on top of the other with the notion of
and not to guarantee it). But this reflexivity. If we were to define intention 2
reinforcement is in fact not yet sufficient. as being the intention that the
Strawson has given a famous communicative intention itself should be
counterexample. Paul intends to give Peter reason recognized, we would find ourselves in a
to believe *p\ He therefore has intention reflexive loop, circling from the
1. He displays proof that 'p' In a place communicative intention - the overall intention - to
where Peter cannot fail to see it. He does one of its sub-intentions, intention 2,
this knowing that Peter sees him do it. He which refers us back to the
therefore has intention 2, that Peter communicative intention. If we want to be able to
should have reason to believe that he has identify the content of these intentions,
intention 1 and should recognize we must be able to follow this circle to
intention 1. However, Paul knows that Peter infinity, and therefore have an infinity of
does not know that Paul knows that Peter representations at our disposal.
is watching him. It therefore seems that
the communicative intention, as Straw- But, Recanati says, we can weaken this
son says, is not 'open' (Strawson, 1965) notion of reflexivity by using a notion of
'default reflexivity'. The intention of the
and is not a real intention to
communicate. communicator is reflexive by default if he
has no intention which is inconsistent
To assure the 'transparency' of the with any of the (infinite number of)
communicative intention we must therefore intentions that would be implied by his
strengthen our requirements. Paul knows intention if it were authentically reflexive
that Peter sees him, we said. To avoid the (Recanati, 1987). So instead of having to
counterexample and the dissimulation, attribute an extremely complex intention
Peter must also know that Paul knows to the communicator, the reflexive
that Peter is watching. But a particularly intention, we say simply that he does not have
sophisticated mind could imagine a a certain type of intention. If we
counterexample of dissimulation at a unfortunately happen to demonstrate that he did
higher degree. To have a guarantee indeed have an intention inconsistent
against all dissimulation, to have a full with the intentions that make up the
communicative intention, Paul must reflexive pile, then we say there was no
therefore know that Peter is watching authentic communicative intention.
him, Peter must know that Paul knows Grice put forward a similar solution:
that Peter is watching him, Paul must when we come across a 'sneaky' intention,
know that Peter knows . . . and so ad tnftni- we cancel the credit that we had given to
tum. We therefore come round to the the speaker, who made us take his
notion proposed by Lewis in his book communication as a 'real-life' approximation
Convention (Lewis, 1969), that of common of the infinite series of intentions which is
knowledge. only an ideal limit (idem., p. 243). The
interest of 'default reflexivity1 lies in the
The difficulty is that it is not clear what it fact that we do not even have to specify
means to have an intention which what this ideal limit could be and how we
comprises an infinity of representations. Grice could give it an approximation.
recognized this regression to infinity
implicit in the communicative intention, but We can therefore rewrite intention 1 as a
he conceived of it as an ideal limit, which default reflexive intention to give the re-
160
THE INTENTIONS OF COMMUNICATION

ceiver reason to believe P (that a certain lems. In order to reach a conclusion, we


number of prototypical conditions have must know that no fact is inconsistent
been met). But we must also admit that with our hypothesis of normality. But
intention 2 must aim to recognize 1 as knowing that a conjunction of
default reflexive. Moreover, 2 must itself propositions is inconsistent means knowing that
be 'open' and therefore default reflexive, it is not a theorem. Now, although we have
which is the same as saying that the an efficient and decisive procedure for
overall intention made up of 1 and 2 is saying whether a proposition is a theorem
default reflexive. (ifwe run through the list of theorems that
can be generated, sooner or later we will
This notion of default reflexivity is one of come across the theorem we are looking
the most interesting points, but also one for), we do not have an efficient and
of the weakest, in Recanati's argument. decisive procedure for saying whether a
We find in it the idea later elucidated by proposition is a non-theorem. In fact, even if
Kripke: as long as we do not encounter we have not yet found it in the list of
any inconsistency with our hypotheses, theorems, that does not mean that it is
we should maintain them. But we can not further down the list, or possibly, in a
question the interest of this notion of the logical calculus that takes Peano's
'cognitive' standpoint. Does it save us the arithmetic into account, and which is therefore
infinity of representations necessary for subject to Gôdel's theorem, that it is
common knowledge? Does it provide us unknowable.
with a really 'finitisť procedure for testing
the communicative intention? Non-monotonic logics cannot therefore
provide an efficient definition of all their
To see things a little more clearly, we can conclusions. We are obliged to use the
compare this notion of default reflexivity procedure of the 'fixed point'. We start
with the notion of 'default reasoning' in from known facts. Then we bring into play
non-monotonic logics (Ginsberg, 1987; the hypotheses of normality, which we
Besnard, 1988; Grégoire, 1991; Kraus, term 'defaults'. We check whether
Lehman & Maggidor, 1990, pp. 167-207). anything in the facts is inconsistent with
These logics seek to formalize reasonings these hypotheses of normality. We then
based on hypotheses of typicality or draw conclusions which have this
normality. Typically, or normally, birds fly. As absence of inconsistency as their
long as we are told, without eleboratlon, 'justification*. We have thus generated what we call
that Titi is a bird, we continue to suppose an 'extension', since we have drawn
that it can fly and we use this hypothesis conclusions that the facts alone would not
as a basis for our predictions of its permit us to reach. Then we apply other
behaviour, for example that it would be useless defaults, based on these conclusions, and
to try to shut it up between four walls with so forth. The problem is that, in order to
no roof. But when we learn that it is an be sure that no inconsistency with one
ostrich, we revise our conclusions. The hypothesis of normality or another will
parallel is clear. As long as we have no arise, we must wait until we have drawn
information that is inconsistent with the all the conclusions from all these defaults:
normal characteristics of a bird, we the 'fixed point' is the whole body of the
continue to draw the conclusion that it can stable conclusions reached once all the
fly. As long as we have no information that defaults have been applied. We must
is inconsistent with the normal condition make sure that no justification will be
for a communication — its 'openness' — challenged in any extension and, as we
we continue to think that it is 'open*. have seen, we have no definitive
procedure to permit us to do this.
But the non-monotonic logics pose
161
Pierre LIVET

It is therefore not clear that the notion of but at the fact that Paul displays this
'default' is much more satisfactory from a proof in the presence of Peter, without
'cognitive' point of view - which requires Peter knowing that Paul has seen him and
mental operations that can be modelled at the fact that Paul claims to be
by an efficient calculus programme - than communicating 'openly'. It is clearly not
the notions of reflexivity or common 'normal' to wish to communicate while
knowledge. Recanati admits that from a making the communicative intention
logical point of view his notion offers no itself non-communicable.
advantage over that of reflexivity. But he
asserts that it is more satisfactory from a Then it is only in the case of a
psychological point of view. If by that he 'breakdown', of discovery of such an
means the cognitivist point of view, it is inconsistency in the communicative intention, that
we envisage the notion of 'openness'.* It is
nothing of the sort. To be sure, Recanati's
notion of default reflexivity is perhaps not like the notion of rules. They are both
identical with the default reasoning retrospective notions which take shape
notion of the nonmonotonic logics. In these, only in the case of failure, which must be
if we encounter an inconsistency we understood to mean the construction of a
revise the conclusion of the default negative proof.
reasoning but not its hypothesis; having So we can perhaps glimpse an escape
encountered a penguin, we continue to
route out of the inconclusiveness
think that birds normally fly. But it could inherent in default reasoning. It is indeed true
be asserted that the same goes for that the positive notion of 'openness' is
communication. When we encounter a case of
not in the order of the knowable, because
dissimulation, we do not however
it is simply waiting for a possible
question the hypothesis that 'normally' people
inconsistency, and because this is never
who are communicating do not wish to
definitively ruled out. But this matters little,
have communicational intentions not
since we use this notion as such, in all its
known to the other party. ineffectiveness. On the contrary, it is
proofs of 'non-openness' that must be
It seems nevertheless that we must retain effective. We have thus inverted the
the 'Kripke-esque' core of this argument. problem in relation to the givens of logic. It is
We can challenge the transparency, the the positive notion that is not knowable
'openness', of a communication, but we and it is non-theorems that we can
cannot prove this openness. Similarly, we encounter with certainly and construct. Of
will never be asked, when we are course this depends on our 'positive'
communicating, to prove that we really intend notion referring to the absence of an
to communicate 'openly'. This hypothesis inconsistency, while our 'negative' notions refer
that non-dissimulation is 'normal' must to efficient proof constructions.
be thoroughly understood. It in no way
rules out the possibility that a
communicator may keep certain information to Mutual manifestness
himself, and thereby dissimulate it. It
simply rules out dissimulation in the But one question remains. How can we
communicative intention, and not in the recognize that a gesture or a sign
information communicated. Strawson's manifests a communicative intention, that is,
example does not point the finger of precisely that type of intention that is
suspicion of dissimulation at 'the proof of p' satisfied simply by recognition? How can
- which could easily be tampered with - a gesture demonstrate that it bears a
the
• Wenotion
can of
therefore
planning
at (we
thismake
point plans
take up
only
thewhen
ideasroutine
that Lucy
conduct
Suchman
breaks
(1987)
down).
defends concerning
162
THE INTENTIONS OF COMMUNICATION

communicative intention and not simply manifest for each of them that they are
an informative intention? Sperber and these individuals with such and such
Wilson have tried to give a solution to this characteristics, primarily that of being in
problem and, in examining their reply, I this cognitive environment of
will come back to the problems involved intersection. It is therefore manifest to each of
in the notion of common knowledge. them that they are sharing this cognitive
environment. Since that is manifest to
Sperber and Wilson propose a weaker them, 'for any manifest hypothesis, the
version of this notion, that of *mutual fact that this hypothesis is manifest for
manifestness*. What does 'being manifest the individuals who share this
for an individual' consist of? He must be environment is itself manifest.' This hypothesis is
capable at the present moment of having then 'mutually manifest' [Pertinence, p.
a mental representation of this fact and of 70).
accepting this representation as true or
plausibly true [Pertinence, p. 65). An
individual's 'cognitive environment' is defined But some difficulties must still be
as all the facts that are manifest to him, clarified. What is an intersection between
that is, either those that are perceived or cognitive environments, if the cognitive
inferred or those that he is caqpable of environments are not realized but simply
perceiving or inferring. The authors then possible mental states? We can of course
emphasize the point that saying of a piece have recourse to the notion of the possible
of information that it is manifest for an world. A common cognitive environment
individual is to attribute to it a much would be the intersection between all the
weaker property than saying that it is possible worlds accessible to each
known to him, or even that he supposes individual, that is, the mental states accessible
it. A known fact is a true fact, at least if to each individual starting from their
we take the epistemic operator 'know that' present mental states. But as the
in its classical logical sense. A manifest inferential procedures are non-demonstrative,
(inferable) fact can be false. I may either they can be different. The relations of
have false information or I may have accessibility will therefore also be
applied my inferential procedures in an different. A question arises at this point: what
overbold way. For what is termed procedure will give me access to the
inference here is not restricted to logical common cognitive environment, at the
deductions, which are infallible. We intersection of these possible worlds? In other
accept 'non-demonstrative' inferences, terms, either this intersection is defined
which are for example inferences that are from the point of view of an omniscient
merely plausible, hazardous outside observer- and more than logically
generalizations, hypotheses created from a single omniscient, since he has to be in
case, and so on. Such inferences can lead possession of all the non-demonstrative
us to draw conclusions that do not fit the inferential procedures, which can
facts. sometimes be bizarre, like Kripke's 'quus'
rule - or it is accessible to normal
From the notion of the 'manifest fact', the individuals. If it is defined by a completely
authors shift to the notion of 'mutual omniscient observer, there is every chance
manifestness', replacing and weakening that it will not be enumerable. In fact, as
that of common knowledge. They suppose we can always add some oddity, even a
the existence of an intersection, a body of harmless peculiarity, at any stage of a
facts that are common to the cognitive non-demonstrative inference, nondemon-
environments of two individuals. These strative inferential procedures form a
common facts can include the identities non-recursively enumerable list, as I can
of the individuals themselves. It is then never be sure that I can exclude such an
163
Pierre LIVET

inference from the list of stimulus ostensive. Is this not a circular


non-demonstrative inferences. Each of these procedures argument? No, because the presumption
gives rise to a potentially infinite body of of pertinence depends simply on the
conclusions, of manifest facts. I cannot intention of the communicator. Here we
therefore guarantee to have taken into come back to mutual manifestness. The
account all the manifest facts in two or n communicator must have the intention of
cognitive environments so as to say making it manifest to the receiver that the
whether a fact is not accessible and stimulus is pertinent. Sperber and Wilson
manifest in them. But then neither can I define go one step further: 'Let us suppose that
the intersection of these cognitive it is mutually manifest for the
environments, because certain facts which communicator and the receiver that an ostensive
could nevertheless belong to this stimulus has been produced' (p. 235). It
intersection might have evaded me. is then mutually manifest that the
communicator must intend the stimulus to
The difficulties are redoubled when Sper- appear pertinent to the receiver.
ber and Wilson link the notion of mutual
manifestness with the principle of Of course, we reach this stage if the
pertinence to define what they call ostensive communication has been successful. But
communication. what happens when we are on the point
of communicating, when we imagine a
'Ostensive' stimuli are those gestures, gesture and wish to make it 'ostensive'?
cries or, more often, words and Does the communicator have to wish to
utterances, that enable a speaker to draw the make it mutually manifest that the
attention of a receiver to what he is doing, stimulus is ostensive. No doubt, but how
and at the same time direct that attention can he be sure that this is the case, or
to the intentions of the communicator hope to realize that intention? After all, he
[Pertinence, p. 331). In other words, the has no proof that what he wishes to
'ostensive' stimulus is regarded as solving communicate will belong to the mutual
the modern equivalent of the problem of cognitive environment, because he does not
the origin of languages. It is a question of know how to define the intersection of
knowing how we can draw the attention cognitive environments.
of others not only to our gesture but also
to the fact that this gesture is a vector of Sperber and Wilson seek to avoid this
communication. The 'ostensive' gesture difficulty by defining pertinence.
should enable the receiver to draw Pertinence for them is the optimal context,
inferences not only about our intentions but the one that permits the best possible
also about our communicative intentions. balance between effort and effect (p. 219),
For Sperber and Wilson then, between the cognitive effort and the
communication is 'ostensive-inferentiaT. The number of inferences and contextual
'ostensive' is regarded as triggering implications that can be drawn from the
inferences that are specific to information in that context. If only one
communication. The 'ostensive' stimulus derives its stimulus is the most pertinent among
communicational specificity precisely those that the communicator could use,
from its pertinence, or more exactly from then that is the ostensive stimulus. In
the fact that it arouses an anticipation or fact, as the receiver also thinks that all
presumption of pertinence. ostensive communication differs from
other stimuli by a presumption of
We see that in fact pertinence is not pertinence, and that he too is capable of
directly a property of the ostensive identifying this stimulus as the most
stimulus. It is much more the pertinent, he recognizes that the optimal
presumption of pertinence that makes the pertinence of a stimulus means that it is
164
THE INTENTIONS OF COMMUNICATION

ostensive and, using the same inferential thinks that the other is leading, and one
operations that permitted him to verify of them does not dance the tango very
that pertinence, he finds the pertinent well, we are heading for a fall. Moreover,
interpretation of what is being the communicator must obviously
communicated. So at a stroke he verifies the os- anticipate what will be pertinent to the receiver,
tensiveness of the stimulus and identifies or else we could suspect him of not having
the communicative intention. a real communicative intention. He is
therefore a guide who must be guided by
The problem is that all this relies on the the person he is guiding!
unicity of the pertinent stimulus. Now,
this stimulus is unique if the optimum of There are many points in their argument
pertinence is unique. But although it can at which Sperber and Wilson seem to
be unique, when context A comes before assume what is in question. The first
context В in dimension x of contextual unexplained point is this: if we share the
implications and dimension у of same cognitive environment, and this
minimized cognitive effort, this is not the shared cognitive environment includes
case when the two ranks on x and у the identities of the parties, then it is
intersect: we come up against the classic manifest to us that we are sharing this
problems of maximization in several cognitive environment. But what meaning
dimensions. We must then put the should be given to 'the identity of the
criteria in some order, put either effort or effect parties'? For it to be manifest to each of
first. But our authors prefer not to us that we are sharing this cognitive
choose, and for a while they assert the environment, this identity should be
notion of comparison 'other things being described in detail. We are in a room in
equal', which judges by effect, with the which a telephone is ringing, we both
effort presumed to be the same, or vice know that we are both in the room, we
versa, which nevertheless brings us back suppose that each of us can hear the
to the notion of optimality. telephone, we suppose that neither of us
is particularly expecting a call. So it is
Sperber and Wilson cannot in any case part of our mutual cognitive environment
guarantee that the interpretation of the that either of us could take the call. But
stimulus as pertinent by the receiver will there again, the notion of 'nearer' can be
be the same as the intention with which judged differently by each of us and it
the communicator chose the stimulus as becomes difficult to say that the other
pertinent - and so they decline to give us parry's notion of 'nearer' forms part of
such a guarantee. For them, and we can what is mutually accessible to us: he
only agree, communication is not a might usually react much faster than me,
process whose symmetry or reciprocity can but be more wrapped up in his thoughts
be guaranteed. There is no assurance that at that precise moment. Once I have been
the selection of a pertinent stimulus and given such specific information, his
the interpretation of this stimulus as temporary slowness will be accessible to me
pertinent will be operations that produce the and I will be able to infer it from the fact
same result. Communication is always that he does not rush to the telephone.
hazardous, and the risk is taken by the But perhaps I have entered an individual
communicator. Unfortunately, giving the extension of the 'mutual cognitive
communicator the role of guide does not environment', an extension which is peculiar
solve the problem. It is like dancing a to me and which is not in fact accessible
tango.* How can we know who has taken to the other party, because he himself has
the lead in the dance? If each partner entered another possible extension.
• Pertinence, p. 72.
165
Pierre LIVET

Here we come back to the problem of Englishwomen are redheads'. The


multiple extensions in non-monotonic constraint of minimizing effort does not
logics, which is natural since the notion therefore permit us to define a limited list
of accessible or inferable depends on of inferential procedures that are shared
hypotheses of normality, on premises by all. Nor does the constraint of
agreed to be normal and inferences maximizing contextual implications: the
agreed to be normal. Until we have settled contextual implications of saying 'all
this problem we cannot say that, in a Englishwomen are redheads' in the
cognitive environment that is presumed presence of a brunette are richer than
to be shared, knowing the identity of the those of 'Englishwomen have hair of all
parties makes it mutually manifest that colours'.
they share this cognitive environment,
and still less that, for any hypothesis that So for all its interest and cleverness, Sper-
is manifest to each individual, the fact ber and Wilson's argument includes
that this hypothesis is manifest to them several uncertain steps, which all repeatedly
is itself manifest. Once again, what is pose the same obsessing problem: how
manifest can be situated in extensions to can we assure ourselves that others
the basic body of information that are understand us and interpret our communi-
different for each individual. And if we cational stimuli in the same way as we do?
wish to assure the identity of these
It seems that we can nevertheless accept
extensions, it seems that we will have to fall the authors' preliminary statements:
back on a stronger notion than that of the
communication is a bet by the
mutual cognitive environment: common
communicator and its success is therefore not
knowledge, the drawbacks of which we
guaranteed. The notion of the openness of
have already seen. communication corresponds to this
The second unclear point is that of the wager. But we must then draw the
possibility of defining an intersection following conclusion: this notion of 'openness'
between cognitive environments, in order to of communication corresponds to a bet,
establish a mutual cognitive therefore it is a non-definitive,
environment. We have seen that, as in the non-efficient notion, and we use it exactly as
nonmonotonic logics, we must be able to such. On the other hand, the proofs of
exhaust the list of non-demonstrative 'non-openness' must be constructed in an
inferential procedures before we can say, efficient way. This therefore allows us to
from the outside and knowing all the know when the bet has been lost. Sperber
information about the two parties, what and Wilson give the impression that there
is not accessible to one or the other of is always a pertinent interpretation, and
them, and therefore what is mutually that the bet is always a winner ...
accessible. This list of non-demonstrative
conclusions cannot be completely We can see that here we are moving away
exhausted even by an omniscient observer, from Grice's conception, which made
and even less by the parties, who do not 'openness' an ideal communicational
know what information and inferential limit, always approached but never
procedures the other has at his disposal. reached. In fact it is never a question of
approaching open communication as an
There remains the possibility of sharply ideal in which dissimulations would be
curtailing this list, using only inferential failures. On the contrary, proofs of
procedures contained by the principle of dissimulation are the only 'successes', the
pertinence. But a nondemonstrative only efficient proof constructions that we
inferential procedure can be short and can demonstrate, and 'open'
bizarre, as in a generalization like 'all communication is only an inefficient outline hypo-
166
THE INTENTIONS OF COMMUNICATION

thesis. No-one therefore tries to attain it, The intention to communicate


since everyone supposes that it is valid
until it has been disproved. and language acts

Can the model of the communicative


intention be used to analyse language acts?
We can see the thinking common to both This is what Recanati holds/ Language
this solution and the problem of indenti- acts refer to an 'intention to
fying the informative intention. There too communicate'. The intention to communicate
we suppose that we can maintain our comprises, as does the communicative
hypotheses about the situation as long as intention, two sub-intentions:
we are not forced to revise our opinions.
Conversely, giving a piece of information (1) The intention to manifest by our
amounts to manifesting the possibility or utterance that we have a certain
necessity of such a revision. These two communicative intention;
aspects of the procedure are always
linked, since we interpret deviations from (2) The intention that the receiver
our hypotheses as being révisable should recognize this
according to the hypotheses that we maintain: communicative intention.
for example, I see the other driver moving It is therefore sufficient for the receiver to
to his left, I maintain the hypothesis that recognize the communicative intention
he wishes to avoid me, and I infer from for the intention to communicate to be
this that he drives on the left. This satisfied, since the receiver recognizes it
procedure permits us to attribute informative only if it is manifest. Recanati concludes
meaning to deviations from expected that this is what happens in the case of
behaviour, that is, to know exactly which explicit performatives, such as 'I promise'.
hypotheses we have to revise. But in By declaring in a performative way that he
interpreting the informative intention, we is carrying out a certain language act
do not envisage requiring the absence of (promising), the speaker expresses his
a counterexample in order to continue to intention to perform this act by this same
maintain our hypothesis. utterance. If the hearer takes him
seriously - the speaker could be using irony
The hypotheses that we maintain are in - and attributes to him the intention thus
fact simply our own. We can suppose that expressed linguistically, then this
they are also other people's, but we intention is satisfied by that attribution.
require no proof of this. It is in practice
sufficient for us to co-ordinate our Yet it is clear that we cannot take analysis
actions, whatever our real hypotheses might of the communicative intention as a direct
be. Thus in the informative intention we model for analysis of the intention to
restrict ourselves to decoding information communicate of the language act. The latter
as so many efficient revisions. differs in one respect: the receiver must
recognize not only our communicative
We do not venture into the domain of the intention but also our intention to carry out
inefficient. In the communicative this precise performative act. In contrast,
intention on the other hand, we envisage the communicative intention is general,
requiring the absence of a contrary proof, a as its individual content derives from the
demand that we maintain even though it informative intention, and because what
is inefficient. In the communicative the communicative intention adds to the
intention we use the inefficient as such. informative intention is simply the wish
* See Meaning and Force, p. 210, and in general the French source for this book: Les énoncés
performattfs. Editions de Minuit, 1979.
167
Pierre LIVET

that the receiver should recognize this but of the attitudes of our communica-
informative intention as open. tional partners with regard to the world
and to our own attitudes. Thus the
It is therefore not easy to see the meaning analysis offered by Searle, which sees
of 'the intention that this (a certain) directives as an attempt to change states of the
communicative intention should be world by means of words, is quite
recognized'. Does this specificity refer to the insufficient. The same goes for his analysis of
informative intention comprised in the declaratives, which he says are intended
language act? This is difficult to defend, to make our words conform to states of
as language acts indicate modalities of the world. On the contrary, they are
communication as well as information aimed either at modifying the supposed
that is already present. Saying 'I promise' attitudes of others towards a fact (the
is the same as saying *I promise to do this others were presumed to have doubted it)
thing'. We do not give an order without or at enjoining them to modify their
indicating what act must be performed. hypotheses about our own attitudes (contrary
So it is first these promised or ordered to what others thought, we continue to
acts that are the object of the informative believe this fact). And usually they have
intention, that which specifies. But then both these functions.
there comes the additional specificity of
the language act, which must therefore But how then can it still be asserted that
also be informative. Now, giving a piece of language acts, at least explicit
information allows us to revise a performatives, are 'self-realizing' or 'self-verifying'?
hypothesis. This is indicated by an imperative, They are no more so than any informative
for example, 'Close the door*. The door intention. Receivers must still not only
must be shut despite what we previously recognize the intention to communicate of
believed, or maybe we are thought not to the performative, but also modify their
have noticed that the door was open, and attitudes in the way indicated by the
we are being told to revise our hypotheses language act. And we have no guarantee of
on this point. that, any more than we could guarantee
that our receivers were taking our
But as the language act adds a informative intention into account. But then
supplementary specificity, information of the why say, following Austin, that it is
second degree, it too must therefore aim sufficient to utter a performative for the
at a revision of hypotheses. This is in fact language act to be thereby accomplished,
the case. When we give an order, we tend and following Searle, that it is not possible
to revise the other person's hypotheses to express a language act without
about his own information, and especially expressing the corresponding intentional
about the way in which he conceived of state (to apologize without expressing a
our own attitudes. Contrary to what he state of regret) (Searle, 1985, p. 24).
thought, we did not regard it as
permissible that the door should be open. Or Because informative intentions already
else, by giving an order, we show that we possess the 'reflexivity' (in a weak sense
did not expect that the person spoken to that I shall define) of communicative
would have closed the door on his own intentions. When I have only one simple
initiative. In a way, we are enjoining him informative intention I am not in fact
to enable us to revise our hypotheses and concerned about modifying the attitudes
our attitudes about him. of the other party towards my informative
intention. I simply suggest to him a
We see that the informative content of revision of his hypotheses. I do not try to
language acts properly so-called consists make him revise his attitudes towards my
of revisions not only of states of the world attitudes. But this is just what I want to
168
THE INTENTIONS OF COMMUNICATION

do with language acts. Thus a promise door is important to me, and he can
makes it manifest that I have revised my therefore no longer be indifferent with regard
attitude because of the attitude of the to this open door. Maybe he did not in fact
other party (I see that it could be an care whether the door was open or closed,
attitude of doubt) and that I want to but now he is at least concerned by the
convince him of my new (determined) fact that I would like the door shut. More
attitude, so that he will revise his attitude precisely, my concern may still be a
with regard to me. An order shows that I matter of indifference to him, but my attitude
want the other party to revise his attitude towards the door is henceforth 'marked'
(indifference or resistance), and so enable by a reference to my attitude towards the
me to revise my attitude of doubt about door. If the other recognizes my
his attitude, and so on. When we take into informative intention, I have modified his
account the attitudes of others with cognitive environment, whether he obeys my
regard to our own, and we wish to revise order or not. The same thing applies to a
those attitudes, we come close to the promise. So if the other recognizes my
communicative intention, which aims for informative intention, he knows that
recognition of our informative intention, and instead of not noticing his doubtful attitude,
therefore an attitude with regard to our I have taken it into account. Of course this
attitude. awareness can be limited to expressing a
change of attitude without acting on this
However, we could easily take into change, but the modification, whatever
account the attitudes of the other party with effect it may have, nonetheless exists.
regard to our attitdes, and try to get them
revised, merely by adopting some So recognition of the communicative
strategically appropriate behaviour, and intention is sufficient to modify the
avoiding any communication. The attitudes of the hearer with regard to the
informative content of language acts does attitudes of the speaker, quite simply
therefore possess the same property as because this recognition is itself a change of
the communicative intention - that of attitude. It is of course recognition of the
aiming to influence second-degree communicative intention in general
attitudes - but this property is not sufficient terms. But by recognizing the
to identify this content and a communicative intention we also recognize the
communicative intention. informative intention that it contains. The
general modification of attitude linked to
But of course language acts are 'non- the communicative intention is therefore
natural' utterances, or the expression of
specified via the informative intention.
a communicative intention. It is then But the aspect of modification of second-
clear that recognition of such a degree attitudes is already present in the
communicative intention, which is equivalent to recognition of the general communicative
aiming at a modification of the attitude of intention. Recognition of the informative
the receiver with regard to the attitudes of intention does not therefore need to
the speaker, already assures the establish this link between the attitudes of
modification of a second-degree attitude aimed the speaker and those of the hearer, and
at by the informative intention. When, by vice versa; it simply assures the specificity
giving an order, I manifest to another my of this reciprocal relationship.
attitude towards the state of affairs, or
towards my attitudes (if I think he is Of course, this 'recognition' does not
inclined to disobey me), it is sufficient for extend to fulfilling all the intentions of the
him to recognize this attitude to revise his speaker concerning these changes of
hypotheses about the state of affairs. He attitude. The order does not automatically
can no longer be unaware that closing the produce obedience and does not even
169
Pierre LIVET

eliminate indifference towards the giver of We also do not see what a 'non-open'
the order. It only modifies the indifference language act could mean. But this is quite
of the receiver to the attitude of the simply because we do not see what
speaker concerning the state of the world meaning there could be to a non-open
that the order is intended to change. By linguistic utterance, at least if we are
the same token the attitude of the receiver speaking in the presence of the person to
with regard to this state of the world whom it is addressed. We can of course
becomes 'marked' with reference to the dissimulate underhand intentions
attitudes of the giver of the order. But this behind promises, but that in no way affects
recognition, limited though it may be, is the realization of the intention to modify
still a recognition of the intention of the the attitudes of one party with regard to
language act in its specificity. the attitudes of the other.
However, if this analysis is correct, the
We see the difference between the particular importance given to language
satisfaction of an ordinary communicative acts by Austin loses many of its
intention and that of its informative justifications. Language acts fascinated us
intention. The classic informative primarily because we thought they enabled
intention was satisfied as soon as it was recog- us to act simply by speaking (that it is
nized, because recognition of the sufficient to promise to have made a
informative intention, and even more so promise). Berrendonner has shown that,
of the communicative intention, was more on the contrary, we speak because we
than what was aimed at by the cannot act (Berrendonner, 1982). In any
informative intention (it aimed at modifying an case, Austin was more interested in the
attitude with regard to the world, and the illocutionary aspect of all utterances than
recognition was an attitude with regard to in these particular cases of explicit
an attitude). Saying that it was sufficient performatives. But then Searle drew from this
to recognize the communicative intention the idea that the illocutionary force of the
in order to satisfy the informative language act permits us to pass from the
intention was therefore a triviality. The greater fact (the utterance) to the law (the
includes the lesser. The informative obligation of the promise). He also maintained
intention of the language act aims at this that language acts represent their own
recognition as a modification of an conditions for satisfaction. As he
attitude with regard to attitudes. It therefore constructs intentional acts as also
already has as broad an aim as the representing their conditions for satisfaction,
communicative intention. To say that he then has only to turn the process on
recognition of the communicative intention is its head and imagine that the conditions
sufficient to activate the satisfaction for satisfaction of my intentional states
process of the informative intention is are expressed conventionally by an
therefore no longer a triviality. But it is illocutionary form. This illocutionary form
nevertheless true, since manifestation of indicates a communicative intention aimed at
the communicative intention is sufficient making the hearer recognize the
to trigger reciprocal reflections on the conditions for satisfaction of my statement,
attitudes of the other. Moreover, as what is which spring from the conditions for
communicated is a particular type of satisfaction of my intentional states.
reciprocal reflection, manifestation of the
communicative intention, when it is For Searle, it then becomes bizarre to
recognized, is sufficient to produce the effect express a language act, apologizing for
of modification of attitudes aimed at by example, without meaning to express the
the informative intention - but this effect corresponding intentional state (regret for
is guaranteed only in its minimal form. having hurt or upset someone). Moreover,
170
THE INTENTIONS OF COMMUNICATION

it seems necessary to him that the I have changed my attitude, and so to


conditions for satisfaction of the language act modify his as well). All he can be sure of
(the promise or the order) should also about me is that I have 'marked' my
refer to the language act itself, since we attitude with the stamp of recognition of his
are deemed to be aiming at recognition of concern.
the communicative intention of these
conditions for satisfaction. Similarly, it is not true that an order has
But our analyses do not permit us to been obeyed only if the act that the hearer
make statements of this sort. To start has been told to do is carried out in
with, language acts obviously do nothing obedience to the order. The possible self-
but make some statement. We have seen reference of the conditions for satisfaction
that they have no special privilege, that of promises and orders to the orders
their aim is limited to modifying attitudes themselves cannot justify this
towards the attitudes of others, instead of requirement. In fact, if orders refer, in their
simply wishing to modify the basic conditions for satisfaction, to the orders
information that others might have. If it is themselves, it is simply because it is
sufficient to say these acts to perform recognition of the communicative intention
them, this is simply because the that ensures the only modification of
communicative intention of any utterance attitude that we can expect to obtain. In
opens the way to realization of these other words, any obedience to an order
modifications of second-degree attitudes. refers to recognition of the utterance of
the order as recognition of its
Furthermore, the modifications that we communicative intention. It is then necessary that
are certain of obtaining as soon as the this act be carried out with reference to
communicative intention is realized are in recognition of the communicative
no way equivalent to the conditions for intention, and that at the same time this
satisfaction of the intentional states set recognition should be carried over to the
out by Searle, and even less to the specific intention of the order - to mark a
conditions for satisfaction that would refer to state of affairs to be changed, with
the language act itself. When I give an reference to the attitudes of the speaker. But
order, the only result I can be sure of it is in no way self-referential, because the
obtaining if my communicative intention intention of the order, from the speaker's
is recognized is that the state of affairs my point of view, was more far-reaching and
order aims to change will be identified as was aimed at not simply marking, but at
being linked to my hypotheses about the revising, the attitudes of the hearer in
attitude of others. If I say: 'I order you to such a way as to eliminate any doubts
close the door', my hearer will 'mark' his about the attitude of the speaker. The
own attitude towards this door with the modification ensured by recognition of
stamp of my concern. But we can clearly the utterance is therefore not the one
guarantee neither that he will close the aimed at by the 'full' informative
door, nor that he will close it to obey my intention. There is indeed a loop, but it is not
order, nor even that he will not be complete. Searle rightly notes that
indifferent to my concern that the door should someone who replies: 'Look, I was Just going
be shut. In the same way, when I out, so if I leave it is not because you have
apologize I can very easily have no regrets at ordered me to* cannot easily be said to
all. But I cannot not wish to modify the have obeyed (Searle, 1985). But this is
opinion of the other party about my because this sentence makes a point of
attitude (I presume that he thought I was not denying that the marking of the act of
taking enough notice of his indignation, leaving has the slightest connection with
and I endeavour to make him believe that the attitudes of the giver of the order
171
Pierre LIVET

towards our man. And yet someone who tion can either be immediate (when I
replies: 'I am going to shut this door declare I am giving an order I cannot fail to
because it bothers you, but I find your give the order) or depend on a context
obsession with closed doors laughable and (when I declare 'the session open' I
I couldn't care less about your wishes' accomplish the act only if I have the authority
cannot be said to have disobeyed the to open the session).
order.
We can see immediately that it is not in
To sum up, it seems that the specificity of fact necessary to superimpose two speech
language acts has nothing to do with the acts, one the declaration and the other
self-referentiality of their conditions. what we wish to accomplish. It is
What self-referentiality they have derives sufficient to reduce the declarative act to the
simply from the fact that they are communicative intention.
utterances, and that they manifest a Communicating a speech act is sufficient to
communicative intention. And the miraculous accomplish it, as soon as this communicative
self-realization of performatives comes intention is recognized. Otherwise it is
down to their seeking to obtain acts difficult to see how expressing the
through modification of the attitudes of intention to perform the speech act could
others about our attitudes, or through realize it, since we would then have to
recognition of our attitudes about their recognize not only the speech act
attitudes. As they merge into the expressed but also the declarative speech
recognition of communicative intentions, they act.
obtain at least one minimal modification
of these second-degree attitudes. It is not Now, the declarative act implies that the
forbidden to require more of others, but speaker attributes to others attitudes of
that is all we can be assured of obtaining, doubt about the utterance of the speech
and that constitutes the limit of the self- act in question, and about the validity of
performatives.* this utterance. Saying 'I declare the
realization of
session open' is aimed at changing such
What then should we think about Reca- doubtful attitudes: yes, I really do have
nati's analysis of explicit performatives? the authority to declare the session open;
(Recanati, 1979). The act accomplished yes, the session really has been declared
by the performative, he tells us, is always open. It is clear that in a simple speech
a declarative act. We declare an intention, act (an order, a promise etc.) we do not
that of performing the language act suppose that others have doubtful
(speech) in question. This speech act is attitudes outside those directly related to the
therefore accomplished only indirectly. In speech act itself. It is not clear what
fact, when I say: 'I affirm that I am bearing this analysis could have in the case of
innocent', the content of the utterance is that the declarative speech act itself. Are we
I am innocent, and not 'that I affirm' my declaring what we declare? Do we
innocence. What the speech act declares suppose that the hearer entertains doubts
does not therefore have a bearing on the about the fact that we have made this
act itself. But it is certainly accomplished, declaration? That would undermine the
as in order to perform a speech act it is accomplishment of the performative
sufficient to express the intention of declarative act. So we must obviously reduce
performing it. The efficiency of this this recognition of the would-be déclara-

* the
to
as an
Weeffect
self-verification
should
thenote
self-that
verification
ofeven
performatives,
Recanati
'A cleans
hints,
since
thein
latrines',
fora slip
the statement
ofwhich
the pen,
of course
that will
'you he isattributes
clean
not sufficient
the alatrines'
strong
to verify
meaning
he gives
the
order, and which is certainly not a self-verification. The only self-verification, and that is not totally
reflexive, is the marking of the attitude of A towards the latrines as a function of the concern of
the speaker.
172
THE INTENTIONS OF COMMUNICATION

tive speech act to recognition of the tive intention once it has been recognized,
communicative intention. can we not find a counterexample to the
'openness' of the communicative
We can therefore simplify the analysis of intention? No, because the privilege of
performatives. The speaker does not language over gestures lies precisely in its
express the intention to perform a language assuring an 'openness' in a minimal
act. He expresses an informative sense. If I know the language, if I am in
intention. As in the case of all other informative the presence of the person who is
intentions, it is simply a matter of speaking to me and if the identification of the
modifying the attitudes of others. The difference speaker and the receiver present no
is that we have the intention of modifying difficulties, then a counterexample to the
the attitudes of the hearer with reference hypothesis of openness can no longer be
to the attitudes of the speaker. Moreover constructed. In fact, these
the speaker has the intention to counterexamples suppose systems in which, for
communicate this informative intention. example, the communicator's gesture can
be seen by the receiver, who is not visible
We have seen that the 'openness' of the
to the communicator, so that the receiver
communicative intention could never be may be unaware that the communicator
verified, because the absence of a knows that he can be seen. But in the
counterexample could never be verified in
face-to-face linguistic utterance, the only
an efficient way, and that on the contrary things that can be called into question are
it is these counterexamples that could
knowledge of the language, hearing
(and must) be constructed efficiently. But abilities, and each party's knowledge of the
the case of language acts shows us that, precise identity of the other.
in the framework of linguistic
communication, it even becomes impossible to
construct a counterexample to the minimal Dialogue assures us on the first two
realization of the informative intention. If points, and even if the third is not
the communicative intention has been realized, minimal recognition of the fact that
recognized, then this minimal the speaker is the one who is talking and
modification of attitude must be supposed to have that he is addressing the hearer (even if
been realized, because whatever escape he mistakes him for someone else) is
route the hearer might invent, he cannot realized. Thus we cannot construct
refute the existence of this minimal counterexamples to the openness of linguistic
modification. Or, if he does so, then he admits communication, even if we cannot always
that he has not recognized the prove this openness in an efficient way.
communicative intention (or that he is in That is a characteristic of any linguistic
contradiction with this recognition: this is the case utterance, whether it brings a speech act
in Searle's example, in which the subject into play or not. What the speech act adds
denies having revised his attitudes in any is the guarantee of minimal realization of
way after being given an order, which he the informative intention. Nevertheless,
nevertheless admits). But this any linguistic utterance, when it is
impossibility of constructing counterexamples to recognized as such, induces a modification of
the minimal realization of the informative attitude in the hearer (if only to make him
intention, once the linguistic recognize it as the utterance of a piece of
communication has been recognized, is not limited to information, even if the hearer takes no
language acts, it is a property of all notice of the Information) and therefore
linguistic communication. guarantees minimal realization of its
informative intention. The language act
But even if we cannot find a guarantees that the modification
counterexample to the realization of the obtained is the modification of an attitude
173
Pierre LIVET

concerning the attitudes of the other speaker's intention. There is no efficient


party. It can be seen that this is not such procedure for separating the wheat from
a great privilege. the tares, for saying whether we intended
to manipulate the order-giver or satisfy
But there is another property possessed his demands, since manipulation
only by language acts. When I reply: 'I consists precisely of assuring the other party
obey you' (while performing the required that his demands have apparently been
act) to someone who has given me an satisfied.
order, I guarantee the giver of the order
the minimal modification of attitude that We have therefore encountered in
is realized by any recognition of a communication several relationships between
language act. But he cannot hope that this the efficient and the non-efficient,
reply will also guarantee him that I am between what we can conclude and what we
acting only, or even essentially, in can only surmise.
obedience to his order. If I reply: 'I am doing (1) In the simple informative
this to obey you', I am in fact suggesting
intention we do not concern ourselves
to him that he can reconsider his anxiety, with the non-efficient we restrict
that I am really acting in order to obey
ourselves to efficiently constructing
him. But since this reply aims at the reasons for revisions of our
attitude of the speaker towards the
hypotheses and those of others.
attitude of the hearer, affirming to the giver
of the order that the attitude of his hearer (2) In the communicative intention
is really that which he wishes merely we use the non-efficient as such;
shows that the speaker's intention has and there again it is
been understood and that the hearer counterexamples to the openness of the
wishes him to revise his doubtful attitude. communicative intention that have
But that gives no assurance that this to be constructed in an efficient
revision would be well founded. We may way.
wish to dispel doubts about our reasons
for closing the door precisely because we (3) When the communicative
have closed it for reasons other than intention is expressed in a linguistic
obedience. All that is stated by this reply is utterance and in a face-to-face
that the hearer has taken note of the situation, it becomes impossible to
construct such counterexamples. The
order-giver's doubts. But wishing to
dispel these doubts could mean that we openness of the communicative
consider them either invalid or valid. intention is proved negatively,
although positive proof is always
We therefore find ourselves in a situation beyond our reach.
which is the inverse of that of the face-to-
(4) Finally, with utterances by
face linguistic utterance, as distinct from which we recognize satisfying the
indirect communication, in which we intentions of a language act ('I obey
could construct counterexamples to the you', 'I promise' etc.), it becomes
openness of communication. In the face-
impossible to refute the
to-face utterance this construction of counterexamples, which can therefore no
counterexamples is no longer possible, longer be efficiently constructed. As
although the openness of communication the positive demonstration of this
still remains a hypothesis which is un- satisfaction also remains non-
verifiable by efficient means. In this case, efficient, neither the refutation nor
on the other hand, it becomes impossible
the demonstration can be efficient.
to refute possible counterexamples to the
total (and not minimal) realization of the Have we therefore passed into the domain
174
THE INTENTIONS OF COMMUNICATION

of the non-efficient and the undecidable? examples. The moment our requirements
Not altogether: the existence of the become non-definitive or the
utterance itself is always efficient and counterexamples to these requirements can
definitive. The minimal realization of language themselves no longer be refuted
acts is always guaranteed. But we have effectively, then we are in the situation of
invented language acts because we are linguistic, and therefore conventional,
impelled by the desire to obtain communication, in which the
guarantees about the attitudes of others, towards construction of counterexamples to the minimal
our own attitudes, and this desire leads realizations of communication has
us to make non-definitive requirements, become impossible. But hi order to define
even though we can base them on the the exact extent of what communication
impossibility of invalidating recognition of can guarantee us, we must abandon the
the communication and coin them theory of 'model' communication and
through the minimal realization of conceive of communication neither as a
language acts. transmission of information nor as an
inference that permits us to increase our
When these conclusions are accepted, it knowledge by gaining access to pertinent
seems possible to reconcile a cognitive information, but as a mutual revision of
approach to communication (which our hypotheses, and therefore as the
strives to construct efficient procedures) rectification of our possible errors.
with some ethnomethodological theses on Communication is then principally a remedy
situated communication (the rules of an for the defects hi our knowledge and
act are only defined retrospectively, interactions. But it is also the only remedy
always on the basis of the current situation, for its own defects, and we cannot
and while making continual revisions). In therefore hope that it will attain any sort of
fact we can use non-efficient hypotheses perfection.
provided we have readjustment
procedures based on efficient counter-
References

BERRENDONNER, A. (1982): Eléments de LEWIS, David K. (1969): Convention. Harvard


pragmatique linguistique. Paris: University Press.
Editions de Minuit. RECANAT1, François (1979): Les énoncés per-
BESNARD, P. (1988): An Introduction to De- formatifs. Paris: Editions de Minuit.
Jault Logic. Berlin: Springer. RECANATI, François (1987): Meaning and
GINSBERG, P. (1987): In Readings in Force. Cambridge: Cambridge
Nonmonotonic Reasoning. Morgan Kauf- University Press.
mann. Reading.
SEARLE (1985): L'Intentionalité, translation.
GREGOIRE, P. (éd.) (1991): Logiques non Pichevin. Paris: Editions de Minuit.
monomodes et intelligence artificielle. Paris:
Hermès. SPERBER. Dan & WILSON, Deirdre (1986):
Relevance - communication and
GRICE, M.P. (1968): 'Utterer's Meaning, cognition. Oxford: Blackwell. French trsln: La
Sentence Meaning and Word-Meaning*, in Pertinence, 1990, Ed. de Minuit.
Foundations ofLanguage 4.
STRAWSON, P.F. (1965): 'Invention and
KRAUS, S. LEHMAN, D. & MAGIDOR, M. Convention in Speech Acts', in The
(1990): Meaning revisited. In: Mutual Philosophical Review, Vol. LXXIII, No. 4,
Knowledge, ed. N. Smith. Academic October 1965. Translated in Etudes de
Press, 1982. logique et de linguistique. Paris: Le Seuil.
KRIPKE, Saul A. (1982): Wittgenstein, on SUCHMAN, Lucy (1987): Plans and Situated
Rules and Private Language. Oxford: Actions. Cambridge: Cambridge
Basil Blackwell. University Press.
175

You might also like