You are on page 1of 168

Quaestiones

Quaestiones Disputatae
Franciscan University of Steubenville

Quaestiones
Disputatae
1235 University Blvd

Disputatae
Steubenville, OH 43952

www.quaestionesdisputatae.com

The Power of Beauty


Selected Papers on
A Journal of
Philosophical Inquiry the Power of Beauty
and Discussion

Issue Edited by
Theresa Farnan
Volume 6
N o. 2

ISSN: 2150-5756 Volume 6, No. 2 Spring 2016


Quaestiones Disputatae Quaestiones Disputatae is a journal of philosophy inspired by the medieval
dialectical form of the “disputed question”: a method of philosophical dis-
Editor: cussion aimed at addressing the relevant issues of the time. In the spirit of
Alex Plato, Franciscan University of Steubenville the medieval quaestiones disputatae, this journal addresses significant questions
and topics of contemporary philosophic interest. Recognizing that signifi-
Assistant Editor: cant philosophical contributions are found among philosophers of various
Kevin F. Kwasnik, Franciscan University of Steubenville backgrounds and outlooks, the journal is, therefore, not limited to a particu-
lar period of philosophy, nor is it representative of a specific philosophic
Editorial Assistant: school or point of view.
Jacob Smith, Franciscan University of Steubenville
Each issue has a special theme. An issue may focus on a topic in a particular
Board of Advisors: area of philosophy, such as logic, philosophy of science, political philosophy,
or aesthetics; on the work of a significant philosopher such as Proclus, Duns
Joseph M. Boyle, University of Toronto Scotus, or Husserl; on the examination and study of an important text of
John Deely, University of St. Thomas, Houston philosophy such as the Enneads of Plotinus, or Formalism in Ethics and Non-
Alfred Fredosso, University of Notre Dame Formal Ethics of Values by Max Scheler; or on the valuable contributions of a
Robert P. George, Princeton University particular philosophical school or movement such as Cambridge Platonism,
Stephen Gersh, University of Notre Dame Scottish Realism, or Paduan Aristotelianism.
Christina M. Gschwandtner, University of Scranton
Siobhan Nash-Marshall, Manhattanville College Quaestiones Disputatae aims at a genuine philosophia perennis that respects the
Timothy Noone, Catholic University of America tradition of philosophy but also recognizes philosophy to be a dynamic and
Giorgio E. Pini, Fordham University progressive discipline, one that is more than its history. In this way, it can be
Nicholas Rescher, University of Pittsburgh a forum for philosophers to discuss and share their work, and to participate
Linda Zagzebski, University of Oklahoma in a meaningful dialogue with others.

Subscription Information:

We are pleased to announce that The Catholic University of America Press will Contact Information:
be managing subscriptions to Quaestiones Disputatae beginning this fall (2014). All correspondence concerning Quaestiones Disputatae, submissions, or the
Those interested in subscribing may inquire at http://cuapress.cua.edu/ Annual Conference in Christian Philosophy hosted by Franciscan University
journals/quaestionesdisputatae.cfm, via email at jrnlcirc@press.jhu.edu, or of Steubenville should be directed to:
by calling 1-800-548-1784. Individual subscriptions are $40 per year and
institutional subscriptions are $100 per year. Single issues are $20 for
individuals and $60 per issue for institutions. No additional shipping and Alex Plato, Editor
handling costs for U.S. purchases, but please add $15 for international shipping. Quaestiones Disputatae
Discover, MasterCard, Visa or American Express are accepted. Residents of Franciscan University of Steubenville
MD, VA, and DC should add applicable taxes. Quaestiones Disputatae is also 1235 University Blvd
available electronically through The Philosophy Documentation Center at Steubenville, OH 43952
http://www.pdcnet.org/qd. Checks may be made out to “The Catholic qdphilosophyjournal@gmail.com
University of America Press” and sent to:
Quaestiones Disputatae
P.O. Box 19966 Copyright © 2016 Quaestiones Disputatae
Baltimore, MD 21211-0966 ISSN: 2150-5756
Quaestiones
Disputatae
The Power of Beauty
Theresa Farnan, Special Guest Editor

2016
Quaestiones Disputatae
2

Quaestiones Disputatae

Vol. 6, No. 2 Spring 2016

Contents

Introduction to THE POWER OF BEAUTY


Theresa Farnan . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 4

“Grace That Shimmers on the Surface of Beauty”:


Beyond Platonic-Aristotelian Form, a Stoic Vision of Primary Causality
Christopher S. Morrissey . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 10

Beauty and Motivation in Aristotle


Brian Donohue . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 26

The Metaphysics of Moral Values and Moral Beauty


Marcus Otte . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 44

Beauty as Anomaly: Why Does the Bush Not Burn Up?


Linus Meldrum . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 62

The Beauty that Pierces the Heart:


Joseph Ratzinger’s Christological Understanding of Beauty
Alessandro Rovati . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 77

Beauty and Hermeneutic Identity in Consecrated Life:


*DGDPHUDQGWKH´,FRQRI WKH7UDQVÀJXUHG&KULVWµ
Sister Mary Eucharista, SMMC . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 94

Dietrich von Hildebrand as Ambassador to the East:


A Philokalic Reading of His Writings on Beauty
Daniel VanderKolk . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 108

The Beauty of Marital Love in the Thought of Saint John Paul II


Richard Sherlock . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 120

Beauty, the Person, and Disability:Understanding (and Defending)


the Intrinsic Beauty and Value of the Person with Disabilities
Theresa Farnan . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 132

Beauty and Desecration


Roger Scruton . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 150
3

Introduction to THE POWER OF BEAUTY

On December 10, 1974, Nobel laureate Alexandr Solzhenitsyn delivered an


address on the power of beauty and the arts to change the world. Taking as
his point of departure Dostoyevsky’s insight that beauty will save the world,
and shaped by his own experience of the power of literature to unmask
totalitarianism, Solzhenitsyn spoke on the relationship of beauty, truth, and
goodness, and the distinctive nature of the power of beauty.
One day Dostoevsky threw out the enigmatic remark: “Beauty
will save the world.” What sort of a statement is that? For a long
time I considered it mere words. How could that be possible?
When in bloodthirsty history did beauty ever save anyone from
anything? Ennobled, uplifted, yes—but whom has it saved? …
There is, however, a certain peculiarity in the essence of beauty,
a peculiarity in the status of art: namely, the convincingness of
a true work of art is completely irrefutable and it forces even an
opposing heart to surrender….1
For Solzhenitsyn, the beauty of a work of art was not merely a product of
skill or ability, nor did it exist as a vehicle for mere self-expression. On the
contrary, art, if it is to be a true work of art, if it is to be truly beautiful, leads
its audience to a deeper understanding of truth, especially the truth about
other human beings. Art has the ability to circumvent the defenses we erect
around our hearts; the more we wish to turn away from experiences that we
do not wish to see or acknowledge, the more art insists that we look. These
encounters with beauty lead us further, sometimes reluctantly, to personally
embrace truth and goodness.
So perhaps that ancient trinity of Truth, Goodness and Beauty is
not simply an empty, faded formula as we thought in the days of
RXUVHOIFRQÀGHQWPDWHULDOLVWLF\RXWK",I WKHWRSVRI WKHVHWKUHH
trees converge, as the scholars maintained, but the too blatant,
too direct stems of Truth and Goodness are crushed, cut down,
not allowed through—then perhaps the fantastic, unpredictable,
unexpected stems of Beauty will push through and soar to that
very same place, DQGLQVRGRLQJZLOOIXOÀOOWKHZRUNRI DOOWKUHH"«

1
Alexandr Solzhenitsyn, “Nobel Lecture,” Nobelprize.org, accessed August
31, 2015, http://www.nobelprize.org/nobel_prizes/literature/laureates/1970/solz-
henitsyn-lecture.html
4
In that case Dostoevsky’s remark, “Beauty will save the world,” was
not a careless phrase but a prophecy? After all HE was granted to
see much, a man of fantastic illumination.2
How does beauty do this? And what is the role of the artist? Perhaps it will
be more illuminating to start with the second question. Solzhenitsyn suggests
that the artist, “recognizing a higher power above, gladly works as a humble
apprentice beneath God’s heaven”3 In other words, his role is “to be more
keenly aware than others of the harmony of the world, of the beauty and
ugliness of the human contribution to it, and to communicate this acutely to
his fellow-men.”4
How does the artist do this? “From man to man, as he completes
his brief spell on Earth, art transfers the whole weight of an unfamiliar, life-
long experience with all its burdens, its colours, its sap of life; it recreates in
WKHÁHVKDQXQNQRZQH[SHULHQFHDQGDOORZVXVWRSRVVHVVLWDVRXURZQµ5
Through his art, the artist brings cultures and civilizations into conversation,
making the joys and sufferings of those far away near to all who encounter
his art. The artist’s vivid depictions of others’ experiences reveal what would
otherwise remain hidden and give voice to the voiceless. In this way, the artist
can bridge the divides of time, culture, and distance.
But the power of beauty involves more than creating moments of
empathy that would otherwise not be possible. In representing or recreating
the experiences of others, the artist also appeals to the interior, spiritual di-
mension of the human being. Those who view what is truly beautiful cannot
avoid being moved by it, as it stirs the imagination and evokes a sense of
longing for that which transcends the self, a longing ultimately for the One
who is the source of beauty. This encounter with the Divine enables human
beings to look beyond the material world and grounds our conviction that
each human person is precious and of tremendous worth. Without the ability
to be moved by beauty and by goodness, the fate of humanity would be bleak
indeed.
For Solzhenitsyn, beauty is inseparable from responsibility and obli-
gation. The artist has a responsibility not to retire “into his self-made worlds
or the spaces of his subjective whims,” for in doing so he will “surrender the
real world into the hands of men who are mercenary, if not worthless, if not
insane.”6 Those who appreciate and view art have an obligation not to give
into what Solzhenitsyn described as the “sickness of the will of successful
people … the daily condition of those who have given themselves up to the
2
Ibid.
3
Ibid.
4
Ibid.
5
Ibid.
6
Ibid.
5
thirst after prosperity at any price, to material well-being as the chief goal of
earthly existence,” electing “passivity and retreat, just so as their accustomed
life might drag on a bit longer.”7 Art that is imbued with truth and goodness
should move its recipients to reject falsehood and violence, to internalize,
safeguard and treasure the humanity of others.
And thus we return to Solzhenitsyn’s insights about the power of
beauty—that even when humans reject the stated demands of truth and
goodness, they can be moved by the subtle, yet insistent tug of beauty to
recognize those same demands. When human beings retreat into the shelter
of their own self-centered existence, beauty beckons them back to the shared
conversation of humanity. Even as human beings struggle to maintain the
LOOXVLRQWKDWWKH\FDQGHÀQHDQGFRQWUROUHDOLW\WUXWKDQGEHLQJEHDXW\JHQ-
tly reproaches them by evoking the presence of One who is Beauty, Truth,
Goodness, Being.

* * *

Many participants from different disciplines—philosophers, theologians, art-


ists of all genres, writers, and many other people—united by their desire to
LQYHVWLJDWHEHDXW\DQGDHVWKHWLFVVSHFLÀFDOO\WKHSRZHURI EHDXW\JDWKHUHG
together on October 24–25 of 2014 for a conference on The Power of Beauty.
The conference was, like Solzhenitsyn’s speech, inspired by Dostoyevsky’s
assertion that “Beauty will save the world.” The conference provided an op-
SRUWXQLW\WRUHÁHFWRQWKHQDWXUHRI EHDXW\LWVUHODWLRQWRWKHJRRGDQGLWV
power to shape and transform persons and culture. It was two days of unique
and fruitful scholarship. The papers of this volume represent the thoughtful
discussion that took place at that conference. Through the selected papers of
this volume, readers have the same opportunity as the participants to engage
LQVHULRXVUHÁHFWLRQRQWKHPHDQLQJRI EHDXW\WKHUROHRI WKHDUWLVWDQGLQ-
deed, the responsibility that we all share, not only to be open to the power of
beauty, but to be agents of the transformative power of beauty.
 7KHHVVD\VLQWKLVFROOHFWLRQUHÁHFW6RO]KHQLWV\Q·VFRQÀGHQFHLQWKH
power of beauty to move human beings toward the Divine and to bridge the
GLIÀFXOWLHVWKDWVHSDUDWHKXPDQEHLQJV7KLVFROOHFWLRQRI VFKRODUO\SDSHUV
covers a vast range of topics and interests, from beauty in medicine to discus-
sions of different schools of architecture, from investigations into the nature
of beauty per se, to beauty in the human person, and to beauty as represented
through art and culture. The wide array of topics is complemented by the in-
terdisciplinary range of these papers, including meditations on art, theology,

7
Ibid.
6
and philosophy. Nevertheless, the papers are united by continually returning
to the central question: What is the power of beauty, and how exactly does it
save the world? The diversity and interdisciplinary nature of these essays is a
ÀWWLQJWULEXWHWRWKHSRZHURI EHDXW\
The selected papers are organized roughly around three themes: the
nature of beauty itself and its relation to goodness and being; the vertical di-
mension of the power of beauty, that is, its ability to lead us to God; and the
horizontal dimension of the power of beauty that Solzhenitsyn so eloquently
describes, namely, its ability to bring humans closer to each other.
 7KHÀUVWJURXSLQJRI SDSHUVRQWKHLQWULQVLFUHODWLRQVKLSRI EHDXW\
to goodness and being includes three selections. In his essay “Grace That
Shimmers on the Surface of Beauty”: Beyond Platonic-Aristotelian Form,
a Stoic Vision of Primary Causality, Christopher S. Morrissey takes Ploti-
nus’s description of “grace that shimmers on the surface of beauty” as a
perennial philosophical insight into the relationship between primary and
secondary causality. Mapping Stoic insights about the world and causality
onto Scholastic insights about the relationship of primary and secondary
causality, Morrissey draws us into a deeper contemplation of the relationship
between beauty and Divine being. His essay grounds the power of beauty in
the immanence of God as the primary cause of all being and thus of all that
is beautiful. This Divine immanence not only causes beauty, but also serves
as the reason why beauty in creation irresistibly draws us to its Divine source.
Brian Donohue’s essay, “Beauty and Motivation in Aristotle,” ex-
plores the theme of beauty and its relation to the good. He discusses two
questions: what is Aristotle’s conception of kalon (beauty-goodness), and
how does this idea of kalon play out in Aristotle’s ethical theory? Donohue
describes the transformative power of beauty; namely, that the soul that con-
templates beauty becomes beautiful in itself and is moved to show beauty in
its pursuit of virtue. In his discussion, grounded primarily in Aristotle’s Nico-
machean Ethics, Donohue provides the foundation for understanding beauty’s
motivating power, a power that is inseparable from its relationship to the
good.
Marcus Otte considers the theme of beauty’s intrinsic relationship to
the good in his essay, “The Metaphysics of Moral Values and Moral Beauty,”
and explores it in the writings of Dietrich von Hildebrand. Otte proposes
that von Hildebrand’s account of how being is made good or beautiful by
values is complemented by the architecture of Scholastic accounts of meta-
physics; at the same time, Otte discusses how Scholastic metaphysics should,
at the very least, be able to account for the values that von Hildebrand de-
scribes. Otte uses this discussion to challenge both philosophical schools to
be open to new insights about the nature and power of moral beauty and its
relationship to the good.
7
The second theme taken up in this collection is beauty’s power to
draw human beings closer to God. Three papers explore this aspect of the
SRZHURI EHDXW\,QWKHÀUVW´%HDXW\DV$QRPDO\:K\'RHVWKH%XVK1RW
Burn Up?,” Linus Meldrum links the use of anomaly in art to its Divine use
in salvation history. Just as anomaly draws the viewer into the mind of the
artist, so too God used anomaly to draw Moses into a more intimate en-
counter where Moses could “rest” in the Divine mind. The anomaly of the
burning bush illustrates the power of unexpected beauty to awaken the mind
and draw humans closer to God.
Continuing to develop the theme of the power of beauty to draw us
to God, Alessandro Rovati looks at the Christological dimension of beauty in
his essay, “The Beauty that Pierces the Heart: Joseph Ratzinger’s Christolog-
ical Understanding of Beauty.” Rovati considers the implications of beauty
WDNLQJÁHVKLQWKH,QFDUQDWLRQDQGWKHLPSOLFDWLRQVRI LWIRUDUWHVSHFLDOO\LQ-
sofar as it became an important medium for worship and evangelization. Ro-
YDWLDOVRWRXFKHVRQWKHUHODWLRQVKLSEHWZHHQWKH&KXUFKDQGDUWLVWVÀQGLQJ
in the Christological dimension of beauty the basis for fruitful cooperation.
Sister Mary Eucharista, SMMC, looks at the eschatological dimen-
sion of beauty in her essay “Beauty and Hermeneutic Identity in Consecrated
/LIH*DGDPHUDQGWKH¶,FRQRI WKH7UDQVÀJXUHG&KULVW·µ'UDZLQJLQVLJKWV
from Saint John Paul II’s Vita Consecrata as well as Gadamer’s essay The Rel-
evance of the Beautiful, Sister Mary Eucharista explores the meaning of the
FRQVHFUDWHGUHOLJLRXVVLVWHUEURWKHURUSULHVWDVDQLFRQRI WKH7UDQVÀJXUHG
Christ. As icons, the very image of the consecrated religious initiates dialogue
with others. Spoken or unspoken, this dialogue inspires wonder, questioning,
UHÁHFWLRQ DQG PHGLWDWLRQ UHPLQGLQJ RWKHUV RI  WKHLU WUDQVFHQGHQW GHVWLQ\
the beauty that radiates from their identity as consecrated religious challenges
others to become aware of the transcendent, and calls to mind the hope of
joining in the Eternal Festival, the union with the One who is Beauty.
 7KHÀQDOWKHPHWKDWWKLVFROOHFWLRQRI HVVD\VDGGUHVVHVLVWKHSRZHU
of beauty to overcome obstacles dividing persons. In his essay, “Dietrich
von Hildebrand as Ambassador to the East: A Philokalic Reading of His
:ULWLQJVRQ%HDXW\µ'DQLHO9DQGHU.RONORRNVDWWKHLQÁXHQFHRI WKHPhilo-
kaliaRQ'RVWR\HYVN\DQGRWKHULQÁXHQWLDOWKLQNHUVLQWKH(DVWHUQ2UWKRGR[
tradition. Turning to the writings of Dietrich von Hildebrand, VanderKolk
ÀQGVFRPPRQJURXQGHVSHFLDOO\LQYRQ+LOGHEUDQG·VWUHDWPHQWRI EHDXW\
as known intuitively, almost mystically. This suggests that continued study
of beauty using the Philokalia and von Hildebrand’s Aesthetics can provide
an opportunity for future dialogue, perhaps bridging the intellectual divide
between those traditions.
Richard Sherlock’s essay, “The Beauty of Marital Love in the Thought
of Saint John Paul II,” considers marriage as a relationship of intrinsic beau-
8
ty that, by its nature, forges unity between a man and a woman. Using insights
from the writings of Saint John Paul II, Sherlock demonstrates that the core
elements of beauty are found in marriage. Marriage, in its essence, unites a
man and a woman in a relationship of beauty that is an intimation of the
Eternal beauty of God’s love for each person; hence, the union of a man
and woman in marriage is a compelling illustration of the power of beauty to
create transformative relationships able to unify human beings and ultimately
drawing them closer to God.
Theresa Farnan’s essay, “Beauty, the Person, and Disability: Under-
standing (and Defending) the Intrinsic Beauty and Value of the Person with
Disabilities,” examines how issues of beauty and appearance can be used
to marginalize vulnerable and disabled persons, even to the point of deny-
LQJWKHLUULJKWWROLIH$VWKHLQÁXHQFHRI XWLOLWDULDQLVPJURZVVWURQJHULQ-
fanticide and eugenic abortion are increasingly proposed as solutions to the
challenges of disability, making those who are visibly disabled easy targets.
Farnan examines the role that physical appearance and perception of beau-
ty play in attempts to depersonalize the disabled in order to inspire further
conversation about and investigation into beauty, personhood and disability,
thereby creating a context that can counter utilitarian denials of the dignity
and worth of persons with disabilities.
 7KH ÀQDO SDSHU LQ WKLV FROOHFWLRQ LV ´%HDXW\ DQG 'HVFUDWLRQµ E\
Roger Scruton. The placement of this essay at the end of the collection is
intentional; the reader will have a sense, as the participants in the conference
did, of Scruton’s essay as a keynote address. The paper is a culmination of
careful study and robust discussion of many criss-crossing issues and themes
surrounding the central unifying idea of the power of beauty. Scruton con-
siders the role of beauty and aesthetic activity in ordinary human life and civ-
ilization as a whole. He then tackles the troubling question of how to defend
beauty from a culture that seeks to desecrate it, either through bad imitations,
such as kitsch, or through outright attempts to subvert and destroy it. In the
course of his essay, Scruton uses the topics of art and beauty as a window
into what it is to be human and to explore the nature and meaning of civili-
zation and culture.
Finally, this introduction would not be complete without noting per-
haps the most important insight shared in common by all the conference pre-
VHQWDWLRQVDQGEHDXWLIXOO\H[HPSOLÀHGLQWKHHVVD\VRI WKLVFROOHFWLRQ%HDXW\
in this world ultimately points us to the One who is the source and summit of
beauty, the Master craftsman, whose creatio ex nihilo provides the inspiration,
measure and guide for artists and their audience. The splendor and beauty of
the created world whisper to all humanity of the presence of the One who
is beauty and goodness, and who loves humanity so much that he lavishes
beauty on creation. Philosophers and theologians have long puzzled over the
9
exact nature of the relationship between beauty, truth and goodness; howev-
er, for those who encounter beauty, the most important question is not how
beauty is related to truth and goodness, but where beauty leads us. As Saint
John Paul II eloquently reminds and then encourages us,
Beauty is a key to the mystery and a call to transcendence. It is an
invitation to savour life and to dream of the future. That is why
the beauty of created things can never fully satisfy. It stirs that
hidden nostalgia for God which a lover of beauty like Saint Au-
gustine could express in incomparable terms: “Late have I loved
you, beauty so old and so new: late have I loved you!”
Artists of the world, may your many different paths all lead to
WKDWLQÀQLWH2FHDQRI EHDXW\ZKHUHZRQGHUEHFRPHVDZHH[KLO-
aration, unspeakable joy.8

Theresa Farnan,
Guest Editor

8
John Paul II, Letter to Artists, April 4, 1999, http://w2.vatican.va/content/
john-paul-ii/en/letters/1999/documents/hf_jp-ii_let_23041999_artists.html. Note
26 reads, “Sero te amavi! Pulchritudo tam antiqua et tam nova, sero te amavi!: Con-
fessions, 10, 27: CCL 27, 251.”
Christopher S. Morrissey 11

“Grace That Shimmers on I believe Plotinus’s distinction—between beauty and its immanent,
animating grace—is not merely Neoplatonic, but a perennial philosophical
the Surface of Beauty”: insight that may also be found in Stoicism. This same insight is especially
echoed in the distinction made by Scholastic metaphysics between secondary
Beyond Platonic-Aristotelian Form, causality (the action of created things) and primary causality (the action of
a Stoic Vision of Primary Causality God immanent within created things). Secondary causality may be studied,
and when scientists do so, they are quite capable of affirming the beauty
seen on this secondary level of causality. Yet the Roman Stoic Seneca, for
Christopher S. Morrissey example, in his Letter 65, speaks of how beyond the much more apparent level
of secondary causality, there is really only one type of cause; namely, primary
causality—the activity of the first cause.3 I believe this Stoic theme (“there is
really only one type of cause”) is also related to the perennial wisdom of the
Introduction: Beauty and a Unifying Stoic Theme Scholastic distinction, in that the fundamental insight about primary causality
is likewise being echoed. So let us now explore this theme.
Plotinus the Neoplatonist speaks of the “grace that shimmers on the surface In An Essay on the Unity of Stoic Philosophy, Johnny Christensen at-
of beauty”1 as being the divine Life that, when added to beauty, inflames tempts a reconstruction of “the basic schema of Stoic philosophy.”4 He
love. By a natural movement, the soul ascends, thanks to the wings given to notes many apparent similarities between the approach of modern physics
it by the giver of this gracious love. Along the way of ascent, the impetus to and of Stoic physics, but what I believe is missing from his account is the
contemplate the giver directly is gradually bestowed. The vision of spiritual key role regarding beauty that I find in the Stoic vision. I argue that when
beauty in the audible and visible is indeed a premonition of what lies behind beauty can be seen in all things (for example, in those meditations of Marcus
the world of Forms; but “form is only the trace of that which has no form,” Aurelius that contemplate themes of Stoic physics), then God is being seen
says Plotinus.2 The experience of the grace immanent in beauty is thus pre- as immanent in all things. Technically, I would describe this most fundamen-
cisely what directs us to that transcendent source that both engenders form tal, meditative experience of beauty as constituted by primary causality being
and also bestows the grace shimmering upon its beautiful surface. caught sight of within the innermost operations of secondary causes.
From the standpoint of one who constructs mathematical models,
like the modern physicist, it may seem that in the universe there is really only
1
“To be sure, if the soul remains within the Intellect, it sees beautiful and one type of cause—“nature itself, viewed primarily as structure”5—but this
venerable things, but it still does not have all that it is looking for. It is as though prejudice, which the habit of mind developed by the specialist in modern
the soul were approaching a face which, although beautiful, was not yet capable physics inevitably fosters, is different from Stoic meditations on causality. I
of stimulating our sight, since there did not shine forth from it that grace which
think the Stoic approach seeks rather to distinguish the primary divine cau-
shimmers on the surface of beauty” (Ἐὰν δὲ μένῃ ἐν νῷ, καλὰ μὲν καὶ σεμνὰ
θεᾶται, οὔπω μὴν ὃ ζητεῖ πάντη ἔχει. Οἷον γὰρ προσώπῳ πελάζει καλῷ μέν, οὔπω
δὲ ὄψιν κινεῖν δυναμένῳ, ᾧ μὴ ἐμπρέπει χάρις ἐπιθέουσα τῷ κάλλει)(Plotinus, En- 3
Seneca, Lucius Annaeus, Ad Lucilium Epistulae Morales, ed. and trans. Richard
neads VI.7.22.22–24 in Pierre Hadot, Plotinus or the Simplicity of Vision, trans. Michael M. Gummere, 3 vols. (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press; London, UK:
Chase, 3rd ed. [Chicago, Illinois: University of Chicago Press, 1993], 49 [references William Heinemann, Ltd., 1917–1925). Hereafter, citations to Seneca’s Epistles are
to Simplicity of Vision are keyed to the 1998 paperback edition]; Greek text from from this text.
http://remacle.org/bloodwolf/philosophes/plotin/enneade67a.htm). 4
J. Christensen, An Essay on the Unity of Stoic Philosophy, 2nd ed. (University
2
“Form is only the trace of that which has no form; indeed, it is the lat- of Copenhagen, Denmark: Museum Tusculanum Press, 2012), 9. Published as J.
ter which engenders form” (Τὸ γὰρ ἴχνος τοῦ ἀμόρφου μορφή, τοῦτο γοῦν γεννᾷ Christensen, “Equality of Man and Stoic Social Thought,” in I. Kajanto, ed., Equality
τὴν μορφήν, οὐχ ἡ μορφὴ τοῦτο, καὶ γεννᾷ, ὅταν ὕλη προσέλθῃ) (Plotinus, Enn. and Inequality of Man in Ancient Thought, Commentationes Humanarum Litterarum
VI.7.33.30–31, in Hadot, Simplicity of Vision, 58; Greek text from http://remacle. 75 (Helsinki: Societas Scientiarum Fennica, 1984), 45–54. Originally published as J.
org/bloodwolf/philosophes/plotin/enneade67a.htm). Christensen, An Essay on the Unity of Stoic Philosophy, Scandinavian University Books
(Copenhagen: Munksgaard, 1962).
© Christopher S. Morrissey, Quaestiones Disputatae, Vol. 6, No. 2 (Spring 2016) 5
Christensen, The Unity of Stoic Philosophy, 21.
Christopher S. Morrissey 11

“Grace That Shimmers on I believe Plotinus’s distinction—between beauty and its immanent,
animating grace—is not merely Neoplatonic, but a perennial philosophical
the Surface of Beauty”: insight that may also be found in Stoicism. This same insight is especially
echoed in the distinction made by Scholastic metaphysics between secondary
Beyond Platonic-Aristotelian Form, causality (the action of created things) and primary causality (the action of
a Stoic Vision of Primary Causality God immanent within created things). Secondary causality may be studied,
and when scientists do so, they are quite capable of affirming the beauty
seen on this secondary level of causality. Yet the Roman Stoic Seneca, for
Christopher S. Morrissey example, in his Letter 65, speaks of how beyond the much more apparent level
of secondary causality, there is really only one type of cause; namely, primary
causality—the activity of the first cause.3 I believe this Stoic theme (“there is
really only one type of cause”) is also related to the perennial wisdom of the
Introduction: Beauty and a Unifying Stoic Theme Scholastic distinction, in that the fundamental insight about primary causality
is likewise being echoed. So let us now explore this theme.
Plotinus the Neoplatonist speaks of the “grace that shimmers on the surface In An Essay on the Unity of Stoic Philosophy, Johnny Christensen at-
of beauty”1 as being the divine Life that, when added to beauty, inflames tempts a reconstruction of “the basic schema of Stoic philosophy.”4 He
love. By a natural movement, the soul ascends, thanks to the wings given to notes many apparent similarities between the approach of modern physics
it by the giver of this gracious love. Along the way of ascent, the impetus to and of Stoic physics, but what I believe is missing from his account is the
contemplate the giver directly is gradually bestowed. The vision of spiritual key role regarding beauty that I find in the Stoic vision. I argue that when
beauty in the audible and visible is indeed a premonition of what lies behind beauty can be seen in all things (for example, in those meditations of Marcus
the world of Forms; but “form is only the trace of that which has no form,” Aurelius that contemplate themes of Stoic physics), then God is being seen
says Plotinus.2 The experience of the grace immanent in beauty is thus pre- as immanent in all things. Technically, I would describe this most fundamen-
cisely what directs us to that transcendent source that both engenders form tal, meditative experience of beauty as constituted by primary causality being
and also bestows the grace shimmering upon its beautiful surface. caught sight of within the innermost operations of secondary causes.
From the standpoint of one who constructs mathematical models,
like the modern physicist, it may seem that in the universe there is really only
1
“To be sure, if the soul remains within the Intellect, it sees beautiful and one type of cause—“nature itself, viewed primarily as structure”5—but this
venerable things, but it still does not have all that it is looking for. It is as though prejudice, which the habit of mind developed by the specialist in modern
the soul were approaching a face which, although beautiful, was not yet capable physics inevitably fosters, is different from Stoic meditations on causality. I
of stimulating our sight, since there did not shine forth from it that grace which
think the Stoic approach seeks rather to distinguish the primary divine cau-
shimmers on the surface of beauty” (Ἐὰν δὲ μένῃ ἐν νῷ, καλὰ μὲν καὶ σεμνὰ
θεᾶται, οὔπω μὴν ὃ ζητεῖ πάντη ἔχει. Οἷον γὰρ προσώπῳ πελάζει καλῷ μέν, οὔπω
δὲ ὄψιν κινεῖν δυναμένῳ, ᾧ μὴ ἐμπρέπει χάρις ἐπιθέουσα τῷ κάλλει)(Plotinus, En- 3
Seneca, Lucius Annaeus, Ad Lucilium Epistulae Morales, ed. and trans. Richard
neads VI.7.22.22–24 in Pierre Hadot, Plotinus or the Simplicity of Vision, trans. Michael M. Gummere, 3 vols. (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press; London, UK:
Chase, 3rd ed. [Chicago, Illinois: University of Chicago Press, 1993], 49 [references William Heinemann, Ltd., 1917–1925). Hereafter, citations to Seneca’s Epistles are
to Simplicity of Vision are keyed to the 1998 paperback edition]; Greek text from from this text.
http://remacle.org/bloodwolf/philosophes/plotin/enneade67a.htm). 4
J. Christensen, An Essay on the Unity of Stoic Philosophy, 2nd ed. (University
2
“Form is only the trace of that which has no form; indeed, it is the lat- of Copenhagen, Denmark: Museum Tusculanum Press, 2012), 9. Published as J.
ter which engenders form” (Τὸ γὰρ ἴχνος τοῦ ἀμόρφου μορφή, τοῦτο γοῦν γεννᾷ Christensen, “Equality of Man and Stoic Social Thought,” in I. Kajanto, ed., Equality
τὴν μορφήν, οὐχ ἡ μορφὴ τοῦτο, καὶ γεννᾷ, ὅταν ὕλη προσέλθῃ) (Plotinus, Enn. and Inequality of Man in Ancient Thought, Commentationes Humanarum Litterarum
VI.7.33.30–31, in Hadot, Simplicity of Vision, 58; Greek text from http://remacle. 75 (Helsinki: Societas Scientiarum Fennica, 1984), 45–54. Originally published as J.
org/bloodwolf/philosophes/plotin/enneade67a.htm). Christensen, An Essay on the Unity of Stoic Philosophy, Scandinavian University Books
(Copenhagen: Munksgaard, 1962).
© Christopher S. Morrissey, Quaestiones Disputatae, Vol. 6, No. 2 (Spring 2016) 5
Christensen, The Unity of Stoic Philosophy, 21.
12 A Stoic Vision of Primary Causality Christopher S. Morrissey 13
sality from secondary physical causality. Stoicism thereby affords insight into Dicunt, ut scis, Stoici nostri duo esse in rerum natura, ex quibus
how meditations upon causes can, in turn, become visions of beauty. Let us omnia fiant, causam et materiam. Materia iacet iners, res ad om-
study this at work in the example already mentioned of Seneca. nia parata, cessatura, si nemo moveat. Causa autem, id est ratio,
materiam format et quocumque vult versat, ex illa varia opera
producit. Esse ergo debet, unde fiat aliquid, deinde a quo fiat.
Seneca’s Causal Meditation on the Divine Immanence Hoc causa est, illud materia. (Seneca, Ep. 65.2)
This way of thinking about causation within the universe focuses on
Seneca, in Letter 65, discusses the controverted question whether there is the extrinsic aspects of things, concerning which there is an external efficient
really only one type of cause, but does not really deny that many different cause acting upon and configuring the material cause. This focus upon mech-
types of causes may be distinguished. Instead, the point of the exercise is anistic extrinsic causality may be characteristic of the early modern scientific
to glimpse the way in which divine activity in the world must be seen as the worldview, which achieved success in mathematical modeling of efficient and
primary causal action, in relation to which all other causes are secondary.6 material causes.8 But is it the same as, or even prefigured in, the Stoic view?
The exercise begins with recognition of the asymmetrical structure Seneca, to be sure, immediately adduces the traditional Aristotelian example
of the world. Modern physics would speak of matter in asymmetrical rela- of the sculptor and his material: “Ergo in statua materia aes fuit, causa opifex
tion to energy; metaphysics would speak of potency in asymmetrical relation Eadem condicio rerum omnium est; ex eo constant, quod fit, et ex eo, quod
to act; and Seneca does likewise, but of materia as inert in relation to the ac- facit” (Seneca, Ep. 65.3).
tivity of causa:7 Seneca begins to consider the meaning of the Stoic paradox that
6
Marcus Aurelius explains how Stoic physical and logical analysis is designed there is really only one type of cause, but he goes on to distinguish more
to achieve such clarity of vision: “Οἷον δὴ τὸ φαντασίαν λαμβάνειν ἐπὶ τῶν ὄψων than simply two types of causality in describing the Aristotelian doctrine of
καὶ τῶν τοιούτων ἐδωδίμων, ὅτι νεκρὸς οὗτος ἰχθύος, οὗτος δὲ νεκρὸς ὄρνιθος ἢ the four types of causes:9 “Stoicis placet unam causam esse, id, quod facit.
χοίρου: καὶ πάλιν, ὅτι ὁ Φάλερνος χυλάριόν ἐστι σταφυλίου καὶ ἡ περιπόρφυρος Aristoteles putat causam tribus modis dici” (Seneca, Ep. 65.4). The further
τριχία προβατίου αἱματίῳ κόγχης δεδευμένα: καὶ ἐπὶ τῶν κατὰ τὴν συνουσίαν types of causes can be seen as elaborations of the causa side of the initial
ἐντερίου παράτριψις καὶ μετά τινος σπασμοῦ μυξαρίου ἔκκρισις: οἷαι δὴ αὗταί bifurcation, making further distinctions about other active principles (which
εἰσιν αἱ φαντασίαι καθικνούμεναι αὐτῶν τῶν πραγμάτων καὶ διεξιοῦσαι δἰ αὐτῶν, are analogous to agent causality insofar as they are active and not passive).10
ὥστε ὁρᾶν οἷά τινά ποτέ ἐστιν: οὕτως δεῖ παῤ ὅλον τὸν βίον ποιεῖν καὶ ὅπου
λίαν ἀξιόπιστα τὰ πράγματα φαντάζεται, ἀπογυμνοῦν αὐτὰ καὶ τὴν εὐτέλειαν αἰτιῶδες καὶ ὑλικόν. ἐννόησον τὴν ἐσχάτην ὥραν. τὸ ἐκείνῳ ἁμαρτηθὲν ἐκεῖ
αὐτῶν καθορᾶν καὶ τὴν ἱστορίαν ἐφ̓ ᾗ σεμνύνεται περιαιρεῖν. δεινὸς γὰρ ὁ τῦφος κατάλιπε ὅπου ἡ ἁμαρτία ὑπέστη” (7.29); “Ἀλέξανδρος δὲ καὶ Γάιος καὶ Πομπήιος
παραλογιστὴς καὶ ὅτε δοκεῖς μάλιστα περὶ τὰ σπουδαῖα καταγίνεσθαι, τότε τί πρὸς Διογένη καὶ Ἡράκλειτον καὶ Σωκράτην; οἱ μὲν γὰρ εἶδον τὰ πράγματα καὶ
μάλιστα καταγοητεύῃ. ὅρα γοῦν ὁ Κράτης τί περὶ αὐτοῦ τοῦ Ξενοκράτους λέγει” τὰς αἰτίας καὶ τὰς ὕλας καὶ τὰ ἡγεμονικὰ ἦν αὐτῶν ταὐτά, ἐκεῖ δὲ ὅσων πρόνοια
(Meditations 6.13); “Διηνεκῶς καὶ ἐπὶ πάσης, εἰ οἶόν τε, φαντασίας φυσιολογεῖν, καὶ δουλεία πόσων” (8.3).
παθολογεῖν, διαλεκτικεύεσθαι” (Meditations 8.13 in M. Antoninus Imperator Ad Se 8
Edward Feser, The Last Superstition: A Refutation of the New Atheism (South
Ipsum, ed. Jan Hendrik Leopold, Scriptorum Classicorum Bibliotheca Oxoniensis Bend, IN: St. Augustine’s Press, 2008).
[Oxonii: E. Typographeo Clarendoniano, 1908]). 9
Marcus Aurelius seems to distinguish the four Aristotelian types of causality
7
Marcus Aurelius also repeatedly names this meditative bifurcation of vi- in this text: “Πόθεν ἐλήλυθεν ἕκαστον καὶ ἐκ τίνων ἕκαστον ὑποκειμένων καὶ εἰς
sion into causa (τὸ αἰτιῶδες) and materia (τὸ ὑλικὸν): “Τίς ἐπὶ τούτου ἡ ἱστορία τί μεταβάλλει καὶ οἷον ἔσται μεταβαλὸν καὶ ὡς οὐδὲν κακὸν πείσεται” (Meditations
τῆς ἀληθείας; διαίρεσις εἰς τὸ ὑλικὸν καὶ εἰς τὸ αἰτιῶδες” (Meditations 4.21.2); “Ἐξ 11.17). He seems to allude to the efficient cause “πόθεν ἐλήλυθεν ἕκαστον,” the
αἰτιώδους καὶ ὑλικοῦ συνέστηκα, οὐδέτερον δὲ τούτων εἰς τὸ μὴ ὂν φθαρήσεται, material cause “ἐκ τίνων ἕκαστον ὑποκειμένων,” the intrinsic formal cause “εἰς τί
ὥσπερ οὐδὲ ἐκ τοῦ μὴ ὄντος ὑπέστη. οὐκοῦν καταταχθήσεται πᾶν μέρος ἐμὸν μεταβάλλει,” and the intrinsic final cause “οἷον ἔσται μεταβαλὸν,” all of which is a
κατὰ μεταβολὴν εἰς μέρος τι τοῦ κόσμου καὶ πάλιν ἐκεῖνο εἰς ἕτερον μέρος τι τοῦ nexus of secondary causes subordinate to the action of the primary cause guarantee-
κόσμου μεταβαλεῖ καὶ ἤδη εἰς ἄπειρον. κατὰ τοιαύτην δὲ μεταβολὴν κἀγὼ ὑπέστην ing that “οὐδὲν κακὸν πείσεται.”
καὶ οἱ ἐμὲ γεννήσαντες καὶ ἐπανιόντι εἰς ἄλλο ἄπειρον. οὐδὲν γὰρ κωλύει οὕτως 10
The Scholastic distinction (Edward Feser, Scholastic Metaphysics: A Contempo-
φάναι, κἂν κατὰ περιόδους πεπερασμένας ὁ κόσμος διοικῆται” (5.13); “Ἐξάλειψον rary Introduction, Editiones Scholasticae 39 [Piscataway, NJ: Transaction Books, 2014],
τὴν φαντασίαν. στῆσον τὴν νευροσπαστίαν. περίγραψον τὸ ἐνεστὼς τοῦ χρόνου. 39) is made between active potencies (or “powers”) and passive potencies (or “po-
γνώρισον τὸ συμβαῖνον ἢ σοὶ ἢ ἄλλῳ. δίελε καὶ μέρισον τὸ ὑποκείμενον εἰς τὸ tentials”) in a way that seems indebted to the Stoics: cf. Christopher Gill, trans., Mar-
12 A Stoic Vision of Primary Causality Christopher S. Morrissey 13
sality from secondary physical causality. Stoicism thereby affords insight into Dicunt, ut scis, Stoici nostri duo esse in rerum natura, ex quibus
how meditations upon causes can, in turn, become visions of beauty. Let us omnia fiant, causam et materiam. Materia iacet iners, res ad om-
study this at work in the example already mentioned of Seneca. nia parata, cessatura, si nemo moveat. Causa autem, id est ratio,
materiam format et quocumque vult versat, ex illa varia opera
producit. Esse ergo debet, unde fiat aliquid, deinde a quo fiat.
Seneca’s Causal Meditation on the Divine Immanence Hoc causa est, illud materia. (Seneca, Ep. 65.2)
This way of thinking about causation within the universe focuses on
Seneca, in Letter 65, discusses the controverted question whether there is the extrinsic aspects of things, concerning which there is an external efficient
really only one type of cause, but does not really deny that many different cause acting upon and configuring the material cause. This focus upon mech-
types of causes may be distinguished. Instead, the point of the exercise is anistic extrinsic causality may be characteristic of the early modern scientific
to glimpse the way in which divine activity in the world must be seen as the worldview, which achieved success in mathematical modeling of efficient and
primary causal action, in relation to which all other causes are secondary.6 material causes.8 But is it the same as, or even prefigured in, the Stoic view?
The exercise begins with recognition of the asymmetrical structure Seneca, to be sure, immediately adduces the traditional Aristotelian example
of the world. Modern physics would speak of matter in asymmetrical rela- of the sculptor and his material: “Ergo in statua materia aes fuit, causa opifex
tion to energy; metaphysics would speak of potency in asymmetrical relation Eadem condicio rerum omnium est; ex eo constant, quod fit, et ex eo, quod
to act; and Seneca does likewise, but of materia as inert in relation to the ac- facit” (Seneca, Ep. 65.3).
tivity of causa:7 Seneca begins to consider the meaning of the Stoic paradox that
6
Marcus Aurelius explains how Stoic physical and logical analysis is designed there is really only one type of cause, but he goes on to distinguish more
to achieve such clarity of vision: “Οἷον δὴ τὸ φαντασίαν λαμβάνειν ἐπὶ τῶν ὄψων than simply two types of causality in describing the Aristotelian doctrine of
καὶ τῶν τοιούτων ἐδωδίμων, ὅτι νεκρὸς οὗτος ἰχθύος, οὗτος δὲ νεκρὸς ὄρνιθος ἢ the four types of causes:9 “Stoicis placet unam causam esse, id, quod facit.
χοίρου: καὶ πάλιν, ὅτι ὁ Φάλερνος χυλάριόν ἐστι σταφυλίου καὶ ἡ περιπόρφυρος Aristoteles putat causam tribus modis dici” (Seneca, Ep. 65.4). The further
τριχία προβατίου αἱματίῳ κόγχης δεδευμένα: καὶ ἐπὶ τῶν κατὰ τὴν συνουσίαν types of causes can be seen as elaborations of the causa side of the initial
ἐντερίου παράτριψις καὶ μετά τινος σπασμοῦ μυξαρίου ἔκκρισις: οἷαι δὴ αὗταί bifurcation, making further distinctions about other active principles (which
εἰσιν αἱ φαντασίαι καθικνούμεναι αὐτῶν τῶν πραγμάτων καὶ διεξιοῦσαι δἰ αὐτῶν, are analogous to agent causality insofar as they are active and not passive).10
ὥστε ὁρᾶν οἷά τινά ποτέ ἐστιν: οὕτως δεῖ παῤ ὅλον τὸν βίον ποιεῖν καὶ ὅπου
λίαν ἀξιόπιστα τὰ πράγματα φαντάζεται, ἀπογυμνοῦν αὐτὰ καὶ τὴν εὐτέλειαν αἰτιῶδες καὶ ὑλικόν. ἐννόησον τὴν ἐσχάτην ὥραν. τὸ ἐκείνῳ ἁμαρτηθὲν ἐκεῖ
αὐτῶν καθορᾶν καὶ τὴν ἱστορίαν ἐφ̓ ᾗ σεμνύνεται περιαιρεῖν. δεινὸς γὰρ ὁ τῦφος κατάλιπε ὅπου ἡ ἁμαρτία ὑπέστη” (7.29); “Ἀλέξανδρος δὲ καὶ Γάιος καὶ Πομπήιος
παραλογιστὴς καὶ ὅτε δοκεῖς μάλιστα περὶ τὰ σπουδαῖα καταγίνεσθαι, τότε τί πρὸς Διογένη καὶ Ἡράκλειτον καὶ Σωκράτην; οἱ μὲν γὰρ εἶδον τὰ πράγματα καὶ
μάλιστα καταγοητεύῃ. ὅρα γοῦν ὁ Κράτης τί περὶ αὐτοῦ τοῦ Ξενοκράτους λέγει” τὰς αἰτίας καὶ τὰς ὕλας καὶ τὰ ἡγεμονικὰ ἦν αὐτῶν ταὐτά, ἐκεῖ δὲ ὅσων πρόνοια
(Meditations 6.13); “Διηνεκῶς καὶ ἐπὶ πάσης, εἰ οἶόν τε, φαντασίας φυσιολογεῖν, καὶ δουλεία πόσων” (8.3).
παθολογεῖν, διαλεκτικεύεσθαι” (Meditations 8.13 in M. Antoninus Imperator Ad Se 8
Edward Feser, The Last Superstition: A Refutation of the New Atheism (South
Ipsum, ed. Jan Hendrik Leopold, Scriptorum Classicorum Bibliotheca Oxoniensis Bend, IN: St. Augustine’s Press, 2008).
[Oxonii: E. Typographeo Clarendoniano, 1908]). 9
Marcus Aurelius seems to distinguish the four Aristotelian types of causality
7
Marcus Aurelius also repeatedly names this meditative bifurcation of vi- in this text: “Πόθεν ἐλήλυθεν ἕκαστον καὶ ἐκ τίνων ἕκαστον ὑποκειμένων καὶ εἰς
sion into causa (τὸ αἰτιῶδες) and materia (τὸ ὑλικὸν): “Τίς ἐπὶ τούτου ἡ ἱστορία τί μεταβάλλει καὶ οἷον ἔσται μεταβαλὸν καὶ ὡς οὐδὲν κακὸν πείσεται” (Meditations
τῆς ἀληθείας; διαίρεσις εἰς τὸ ὑλικὸν καὶ εἰς τὸ αἰτιῶδες” (Meditations 4.21.2); “Ἐξ 11.17). He seems to allude to the efficient cause “πόθεν ἐλήλυθεν ἕκαστον,” the
αἰτιώδους καὶ ὑλικοῦ συνέστηκα, οὐδέτερον δὲ τούτων εἰς τὸ μὴ ὂν φθαρήσεται, material cause “ἐκ τίνων ἕκαστον ὑποκειμένων,” the intrinsic formal cause “εἰς τί
ὥσπερ οὐδὲ ἐκ τοῦ μὴ ὄντος ὑπέστη. οὐκοῦν καταταχθήσεται πᾶν μέρος ἐμὸν μεταβάλλει,” and the intrinsic final cause “οἷον ἔσται μεταβαλὸν,” all of which is a
κατὰ μεταβολὴν εἰς μέρος τι τοῦ κόσμου καὶ πάλιν ἐκεῖνο εἰς ἕτερον μέρος τι τοῦ nexus of secondary causes subordinate to the action of the primary cause guarantee-
κόσμου μεταβαλεῖ καὶ ἤδη εἰς ἄπειρον. κατὰ τοιαύτην δὲ μεταβολὴν κἀγὼ ὑπέστην ing that “οὐδὲν κακὸν πείσεται.”
καὶ οἱ ἐμὲ γεννήσαντες καὶ ἐπανιόντι εἰς ἄλλο ἄπειρον. οὐδὲν γὰρ κωλύει οὕτως 10
The Scholastic distinction (Edward Feser, Scholastic Metaphysics: A Contempo-
φάναι, κἂν κατὰ περιόδους πεπερασμένας ὁ κόσμος διοικῆται” (5.13); “Ἐξάλειψον rary Introduction, Editiones Scholasticae 39 [Piscataway, NJ: Transaction Books, 2014],
τὴν φαντασίαν. στῆσον τὴν νευροσπαστίαν. περίγραψον τὸ ἐνεστὼς τοῦ χρόνου. 39) is made between active potencies (or “powers”) and passive potencies (or “po-
γνώρισον τὸ συμβαῖνον ἢ σοὶ ἢ ἄλλῳ. δίελε καὶ μέρισον τὸ ὑποκείμενον εἰς τὸ tentials”) in a way that seems indebted to the Stoics: cf. Christopher Gill, trans., Mar-
14 A Stoic Vision of Primary Causality Christopher S. Morrissey 15
The bronze and the artist illustrate material and efficient causality, Artifacts may indeed bear the extrinsic stamp of accidental forms
respectively, the first two Aristotelian causal types. It is interesting to note imposed by artisans upon substrata unified with natural substantial forms,14
that Seneca’s description of formal causality may not in fact capture the na- but while the extrinsic final cause of a statue may be “money,” for example,
ture of Aristotle’s intrinsic formal causality—an intrinsic unfolding of that or “fame,” and so on, the intrinsic final cause is simply “statue,” once the
which pre-exists in the efficient cause and flows from the actual exercise of likeness imposed upon a natural substantial form is recognized for what it is,
the efficient cause.11 This may call into question my attempt to distance the namely, an aggregate of accidental forms that have been deliberately carved
Stoic view from the empiriometric causal focus of early modern science, at a certain way in order to achieve the statutory effect of recognition and com-
least if Seneca is only able to conceive of formal causality as an extrinsic con- memoration (i.e., to act as the formal cause that allows you to see this as a
figuration impressed upon matter, as the vividness of his examples might be likeness of “Pericles,” or “Napoleon,” or anything else). If you do not recog-
seen to suggest: “Tertia causa est forma. Neque enim statua ista doryphoros nize the figure carved by the sculptor, but still recognize it as a sculpture, then
aut diadumenos vocaretur, nisi haec illi esset inpressa facies” (Seneca, Ep. the intrinsic final cause has nonetheless achieved its effect on you—again,
65.5). But it seems to me that the emphasis upon the extrinsic that is to be assuming that, unlike the dog that also passes by the statue, you do recognize
found here stems simply from the fact that Seneca is reporting the standard that it is a statue—but its extrinsically-imposed accidental formal cause has
“textbook” example of artist and artifact.12 not achieved its effect. Further, if the statue was carved into some matter
His treatment of final causality, as the fourth Aristotelian cause, initially configured by the substantial form of ice instead of the substantial
unquestionably adduces many examples of purely extrinsic final causality: form of marble, then clearly you have a much more limited time for pointing
“Quid est propositum? Quod invitavit artificem, quod ille secutus fecit; vel to it and asking someone who or what it is meant to depict, since the intrinsic
pecunia est haec, si venditurus fabricavit, vel gloria, si laboravit in nomen, vel formal causality of ice is less stable at room temperature than that of marble.
religio, si donum templo paravit. Ergo et haec causa est, propter quam fit; The patterns extrinsically imposed upon matter by the agency of
an non putas inter causas facti operis esse numerandum, quo remoto factum artisans, whether as accidental forms or substantial forms (artifacts usually
non esset?” (Seneca, Ep. 65.6). But again, I believe this is a consequence of consist of the former, but Styrofoam seems to be a good example of the
the nature of the example, in which an artist externally acts as the asymmet- latter),15 are patterns that can be modeled after exemplars, whether those ex-
rical causa able to configure the inert bronze materia. Yet it must be noted emplars exist as external examples (as an artist who can either copy another
that, in its most profound sense, final causality is bound up with the inner artifact or follow a blueprint) or as ideas in the mind, as Seneca points out in
developmental trajectory of individual natural units, and such intrinsic final affirming that Plato has truly distinguished a fifth type of cause.16
causality is determined by the nature of the efficient causes which initiate that His quintam Plato adicit exemplar, quam ipse idean vocat; hoc est
developmental trajectory.13 enim, ad quod respiciens artifex id, quod destinabat, effecit. Ni-
cus Aurelius, Meditations, Books 1–6, Clarendon Later Ancient Philosophers (Oxford, hil autem ad rem pertinet, utrum foris habeat exemplar, ad quod
UK: Oxford University Press, 2013), 129, on “the standard Stoic distinction between referat oculos, an intus, quod ibi ipse concepit et posuit. Haec ex-
active and passive principles” (in Meditations 4.21). emplaria rerum omnium deus intra se habet numerosque univer-
11
Feser, Scholastic Metaphysics, 42–53. sorum, quae agenda sunt, et modos mente conplexus est; plenus
12
When Marcus Aurelius names only three causes, he names final causali- his figuris est, quas Plato ideas appellat, inmortales, inmutabiles,
ty third, after material and efficient causality, with no mention of formal causality: infatigabiles. Itaque homines quidem pereunt, ipsa autem huma-
“Τοιαῦτα τὰ πράγματα ὁρᾶν, διαιροῦντα εἰς ὕλην, αἴτιον, ἀναφοράν” (Meditations
12.10). This may be because these three causal factors can be viewed separately, on
their own, as extrinsic factors. Matter is only intrinsic to a unit insofar as it subor- 14
Feser, Scholastic Metaphysics, 164–71.
dinated to that purpose by the formal cause. Hylemorphism does not admit its ex- 15
Cf. Feser, Scholastic Metaphysics, 168.
istence apart from its correlative subordination to form, but in abstraction—which 16
The following text of Marcus Aurelius may be referring to agent causality
seems to be the point of the meditation here—it can be considered as something as paired with material causality, but it could also just as well be referring to for-
physically external, in contrast to the higher incorporeal meanings bestowed upon mal causality as operative in the production of anything, perhaps even in terms of
the corporeal world by God and by souls. ideal formal causality: “Ἴθι ἐπὶ τὴν ποιότητα τοῦ αἰτίου καὶ ἀπὸ τοῦ ὑλικοῦ αὐτὸ
13
Edward Feser, “Teleology: A Shopper’s Guide,” Philosophia Christi 12, no. 1 περιγράψας θέασαι: εἶτα καὶ τὸν χρόνον περιόρισον, ὅσον πλεῖστον ὑφίστασθαι
(2010): 142–59; Feser, Scholastic Metaphysics, 88–159. πέφυκε τοῦτο τὸ ἰδίως ποιόν” (Meditations 9.25).
14 A Stoic Vision of Primary Causality Christopher S. Morrissey 15
The bronze and the artist illustrate material and efficient causality, Artifacts may indeed bear the extrinsic stamp of accidental forms
respectively, the first two Aristotelian causal types. It is interesting to note imposed by artisans upon substrata unified with natural substantial forms,14
that Seneca’s description of formal causality may not in fact capture the na- but while the extrinsic final cause of a statue may be “money,” for example,
ture of Aristotle’s intrinsic formal causality—an intrinsic unfolding of that or “fame,” and so on, the intrinsic final cause is simply “statue,” once the
which pre-exists in the efficient cause and flows from the actual exercise of likeness imposed upon a natural substantial form is recognized for what it is,
the efficient cause.11 This may call into question my attempt to distance the namely, an aggregate of accidental forms that have been deliberately carved
Stoic view from the empiriometric causal focus of early modern science, at a certain way in order to achieve the statutory effect of recognition and com-
least if Seneca is only able to conceive of formal causality as an extrinsic con- memoration (i.e., to act as the formal cause that allows you to see this as a
figuration impressed upon matter, as the vividness of his examples might be likeness of “Pericles,” or “Napoleon,” or anything else). If you do not recog-
seen to suggest: “Tertia causa est forma. Neque enim statua ista doryphoros nize the figure carved by the sculptor, but still recognize it as a sculpture, then
aut diadumenos vocaretur, nisi haec illi esset inpressa facies” (Seneca, Ep. the intrinsic final cause has nonetheless achieved its effect on you—again,
65.5). But it seems to me that the emphasis upon the extrinsic that is to be assuming that, unlike the dog that also passes by the statue, you do recognize
found here stems simply from the fact that Seneca is reporting the standard that it is a statue—but its extrinsically-imposed accidental formal cause has
“textbook” example of artist and artifact.12 not achieved its effect. Further, if the statue was carved into some matter
His treatment of final causality, as the fourth Aristotelian cause, initially configured by the substantial form of ice instead of the substantial
unquestionably adduces many examples of purely extrinsic final causality: form of marble, then clearly you have a much more limited time for pointing
“Quid est propositum? Quod invitavit artificem, quod ille secutus fecit; vel to it and asking someone who or what it is meant to depict, since the intrinsic
pecunia est haec, si venditurus fabricavit, vel gloria, si laboravit in nomen, vel formal causality of ice is less stable at room temperature than that of marble.
religio, si donum templo paravit. Ergo et haec causa est, propter quam fit; The patterns extrinsically imposed upon matter by the agency of
an non putas inter causas facti operis esse numerandum, quo remoto factum artisans, whether as accidental forms or substantial forms (artifacts usually
non esset?” (Seneca, Ep. 65.6). But again, I believe this is a consequence of consist of the former, but Styrofoam seems to be a good example of the
the nature of the example, in which an artist externally acts as the asymmet- latter),15 are patterns that can be modeled after exemplars, whether those ex-
rical causa able to configure the inert bronze materia. Yet it must be noted emplars exist as external examples (as an artist who can either copy another
that, in its most profound sense, final causality is bound up with the inner artifact or follow a blueprint) or as ideas in the mind, as Seneca points out in
developmental trajectory of individual natural units, and such intrinsic final affirming that Plato has truly distinguished a fifth type of cause.16
causality is determined by the nature of the efficient causes which initiate that His quintam Plato adicit exemplar, quam ipse idean vocat; hoc est
developmental trajectory.13 enim, ad quod respiciens artifex id, quod destinabat, effecit. Ni-
cus Aurelius, Meditations, Books 1–6, Clarendon Later Ancient Philosophers (Oxford, hil autem ad rem pertinet, utrum foris habeat exemplar, ad quod
UK: Oxford University Press, 2013), 129, on “the standard Stoic distinction between referat oculos, an intus, quod ibi ipse concepit et posuit. Haec ex-
active and passive principles” (in Meditations 4.21). emplaria rerum omnium deus intra se habet numerosque univer-
11
Feser, Scholastic Metaphysics, 42–53. sorum, quae agenda sunt, et modos mente conplexus est; plenus
12
When Marcus Aurelius names only three causes, he names final causali- his figuris est, quas Plato ideas appellat, inmortales, inmutabiles,
ty third, after material and efficient causality, with no mention of formal causality: infatigabiles. Itaque homines quidem pereunt, ipsa autem huma-
“Τοιαῦτα τὰ πράγματα ὁρᾶν, διαιροῦντα εἰς ὕλην, αἴτιον, ἀναφοράν” (Meditations
12.10). This may be because these three causal factors can be viewed separately, on
their own, as extrinsic factors. Matter is only intrinsic to a unit insofar as it subor- 14
Feser, Scholastic Metaphysics, 164–71.
dinated to that purpose by the formal cause. Hylemorphism does not admit its ex- 15
Cf. Feser, Scholastic Metaphysics, 168.
istence apart from its correlative subordination to form, but in abstraction—which 16
The following text of Marcus Aurelius may be referring to agent causality
seems to be the point of the meditation here—it can be considered as something as paired with material causality, but it could also just as well be referring to for-
physically external, in contrast to the higher incorporeal meanings bestowed upon mal causality as operative in the production of anything, perhaps even in terms of
the corporeal world by God and by souls. ideal formal causality: “Ἴθι ἐπὶ τὴν ποιότητα τοῦ αἰτίου καὶ ἀπὸ τοῦ ὑλικοῦ αὐτὸ
13
Edward Feser, “Teleology: A Shopper’s Guide,” Philosophia Christi 12, no. 1 περιγράψας θέασαι: εἶτα καὶ τὸν χρόνον περιόρισον, ὅσον πλεῖστον ὑφίστασθαι
(2010): 142–59; Feser, Scholastic Metaphysics, 88–159. πέφυκε τοῦτο τὸ ἰδίως ποιόν” (Meditations 9.25).
16 A Stoic Vision of Primary Causality Christopher S. Morrissey 17
nitas, ad quam homo effingitur, permanet, et hominibus laboran- into our awareness as signifying something other than itself (e.g., “Pericles,”
tibus, intereuntibus illa nihil patitur. (Seneca, Ep. 65.7) or “Napoleon,” or whatever it is a statue of). This effect of signifying is
The Scholastic tradition likewise admits this fifth type of causality, a type of distinguished from the other types of causality because of the unavoidably
“extrinsic formal causality”—different from the intrinsic formal properties extrinsic manner in which a form interacts with other forms in the universe.
of the ice or marble onto which this external ideal pattern is imposed— An ice statue or a marble statue may impact your car by an accidental or even
which goes by the name of “ideal causality” or “extrinsic exemplary formal a deliberate agent cause; moreover, the statue itself may then be an efficient
causality.”17 cause of damage to your car. But the type of damage that your car sustains
Seneca counts five thus far, but we can see that the total number will depend on the intrinsic formal causality (i.e., of the substantial form of
of causes may be counted as six, once we take Aristotle’s four (material, ef- the material into which the sculptor inscribed the accidental forms of some-
ficient, formal, final) and distinguish two types within both formal and final body’s likeness) as it acts extrinsically upon the form of your car (i.e., an ice
causality—since both of those can be either extrinsic and intrinsic, whereas statue melting onto your car will do less damage than a marble statue putting
efficient causality is by its nature always extrinsic, and material causality is by a dent into it).19 Thus it is legitimate to distinguish the extrinsic signifying
its nature always intrinsic. But are there any more than these six types? Seneca action of a form from its intrinsic nature as a form that has configured a
in fact finishes up the traditional roster by adding a sixth cause (or seventh finite amount of matter.20 Clearly some forms of signification will be more
by our count)—“the statue itself ” (ipsa statua est)—and considers the Platonic enduring than others, as with the effects of a marble statue versus one that
view whether the universe itself can be considered similarly as such a cause, melts by tomorrow.21
if it is indeed similarly the artifact of God the artificer: 19
Marcus Aurelius seems acutely aware that the nature of the formal cause
Quinque ergo causae sunt, ut Plato dicit: id ex quo, id a quo, id will determine, by its interaction with other forms in the environment, the finite
in quo, id ad quod, id propter quod. Novissime id quod ex his lifespan of the formally constituted unit: “ἡ γὰρ ὁρμή σου ἔστω εἰς τὸ πᾶν ἀεὶ ὁρᾶν,
est. Tamquam in statua, quia de hac loqui coepimus, id ex quo τί ἐστιν αὐτὸ ἐκεῖνο τὸ τὴν φαντασίαν σοι ποιοῦν, καὶ ἀναπτύσσειν διαιροῦντα
aes est, id a quo artifex est, id in quo forma est, quae aptatur illi, εἰς τὸ αἴτιον, εἰς τὸ ὑλικόν, εἰς τὴν ἀναφοράν, εἰς τὸν χρόνον, ἐντὸς οὗ πεπαῦσθαι
id ad quod exemplar est, quod imitatur is, qui facit, id propter αὐτὸ δεήσει” (Meditations 12.18). The efficient cause is “τὸ αἴτιον,” the material cause
is “τὸ ὑλικόν,” the final cause is “τὴν ἀναφοράν,” and the intrinsic formal cause is
quod facientis propositum est, id quod ex istis est, ipsa statua est.
subject to the extrinsic formal causality which will be objectively specified by the
(Seneca, Ep. 65.8) environmental interactions of its active and passive potencies, thus determining “τὸν
Seneca distinguishes intrinsic formal causality (id in quo) from extrinsic formal χρόνον, ἐντὸς οὗ πεπαῦσθαι αὐτὸ δεήσει.”
causality (id ad quod), using Plato to expand the Aristotelian four to five caus- 20
Perhaps Marcus Aurelius speaks similarly of something like Seneca’s ipsa
es, but his sixth type names the entity that stands as the result of the entire statua est (“the statue itself ”) with the first and last items in this list: “Τοῦτο τί ἐστιν
nexus of causes: id quod ex istis est. αὐτὸ καθ̓ αὑτὸ τῇ ἰδίᾳ κατασκευῇ, τί μὲν τὸ οὐσιῶδες αὐτοῦ καὶ ὑλικόν, τί δὲ τὸ
The Scholastics distinguished a seventh type of cause by discern- αἰτιῶδες, τί δὲ ποιεῖ ἐν τῷ κόσμῳ, πόσον δὲ χρόνον ὑφίσταται” (Meditations 8.11).
Formal and material causality could be named with “τί μὲν τὸ οὐσιῶδες αὐτοῦ καὶ
ing two types within extrinsic formal causality: not just exemplary or ideal
ὑλικόν,” agent cause with “τί δὲ τὸ αἰτιῶδες,” final cause with “τί δὲ ποιεῖ ἐν τῷ
causality, but also “objective specificative causality.”18 This seventh type of κόσμῳ,” and space, time, and motion (as the finite actualization of potency as po-
causality is precisely the type of causality that is proper to the action of signs. tency) with “πόσον δὲ χρόνον ὑφίσταται.” But a concrete particular individual unit
What is remarkable is that it can be seen as the same type of cause intro- stands so constituted as able to exercise within the environment an objective speci-
duced by Seneca into his discussion—“the statue itself ” (ipsa statua est)—as ficative extrinsic formal causality peculiar to its own unity: “τί ἐστιν αὐτὸ καθ̓ αὑτὸ
the result of the nexus of the other causes (id quod ex istis est), which enters τῇ ἰδίᾳ κατασκευῇ.” It will also suffer from objective specificative extrinsic formal
causality within the environment (i.e., from those other forms that will determine
17
John Deely, New Beginnings: Early Modern Philosophy and Postmodern Thought, “πόσον δὲ χρόνον ὑφίσταται”).
Toronto Studies in Semiotics (Toronto, ON: University of Toronto Press, 1994), 21
Marcus Aurelius himself seems to name all seven causes in this remark-
151–82; John Deely, Four Ages of Understanding: The First Postmodern Survey of Philosophy able text: “πότε γὰρ ἁπλότητος ἀπολαύσεις; πότε δὲ σεμνότητος; πότε δὲ τῆς ἐφ̓
from Ancient Times to the Turn of the Twenty-First Century (Toronto: University of Toron- ἑκάστου γνωρίσεως, τί τε ἐστὶ κατ̓ οὐσίαν καὶ τίνα χώραν ἔχει ἐν τῷ κόσμῳ καὶ ἐπὶ
to Press, 2001), 632–33. πόσον πέφυκεν ὑφίστασθαι καὶ ἐκ τίνων συγκέκριται καὶ τίσι δύναται ὑπάρχειν
18
Deely, Four Ages of Understanding, 633n73. καὶ τίνες δύνανται αὐτὸ διδόναι τε καὶ ἀφαιρεῖσθαι” (Meditations 10.9). Intrinsic
16 A Stoic Vision of Primary Causality Christopher S. Morrissey 17
nitas, ad quam homo effingitur, permanet, et hominibus laboran- into our awareness as signifying something other than itself (e.g., “Pericles,”
tibus, intereuntibus illa nihil patitur. (Seneca, Ep. 65.7) or “Napoleon,” or whatever it is a statue of). This effect of signifying is
The Scholastic tradition likewise admits this fifth type of causality, a type of distinguished from the other types of causality because of the unavoidably
“extrinsic formal causality”—different from the intrinsic formal properties extrinsic manner in which a form interacts with other forms in the universe.
of the ice or marble onto which this external ideal pattern is imposed— An ice statue or a marble statue may impact your car by an accidental or even
which goes by the name of “ideal causality” or “extrinsic exemplary formal a deliberate agent cause; moreover, the statue itself may then be an efficient
causality.”17 cause of damage to your car. But the type of damage that your car sustains
Seneca counts five thus far, but we can see that the total number will depend on the intrinsic formal causality (i.e., of the substantial form of
of causes may be counted as six, once we take Aristotle’s four (material, ef- the material into which the sculptor inscribed the accidental forms of some-
ficient, formal, final) and distinguish two types within both formal and final body’s likeness) as it acts extrinsically upon the form of your car (i.e., an ice
causality—since both of those can be either extrinsic and intrinsic, whereas statue melting onto your car will do less damage than a marble statue putting
efficient causality is by its nature always extrinsic, and material causality is by a dent into it).19 Thus it is legitimate to distinguish the extrinsic signifying
its nature always intrinsic. But are there any more than these six types? Seneca action of a form from its intrinsic nature as a form that has configured a
in fact finishes up the traditional roster by adding a sixth cause (or seventh finite amount of matter.20 Clearly some forms of signification will be more
by our count)—“the statue itself ” (ipsa statua est)—and considers the Platonic enduring than others, as with the effects of a marble statue versus one that
view whether the universe itself can be considered similarly as such a cause, melts by tomorrow.21
if it is indeed similarly the artifact of God the artificer: 19
Marcus Aurelius seems acutely aware that the nature of the formal cause
Quinque ergo causae sunt, ut Plato dicit: id ex quo, id a quo, id will determine, by its interaction with other forms in the environment, the finite
in quo, id ad quod, id propter quod. Novissime id quod ex his lifespan of the formally constituted unit: “ἡ γὰρ ὁρμή σου ἔστω εἰς τὸ πᾶν ἀεὶ ὁρᾶν,
est. Tamquam in statua, quia de hac loqui coepimus, id ex quo τί ἐστιν αὐτὸ ἐκεῖνο τὸ τὴν φαντασίαν σοι ποιοῦν, καὶ ἀναπτύσσειν διαιροῦντα
aes est, id a quo artifex est, id in quo forma est, quae aptatur illi, εἰς τὸ αἴτιον, εἰς τὸ ὑλικόν, εἰς τὴν ἀναφοράν, εἰς τὸν χρόνον, ἐντὸς οὗ πεπαῦσθαι
id ad quod exemplar est, quod imitatur is, qui facit, id propter αὐτὸ δεήσει” (Meditations 12.18). The efficient cause is “τὸ αἴτιον,” the material cause
is “τὸ ὑλικόν,” the final cause is “τὴν ἀναφοράν,” and the intrinsic formal cause is
quod facientis propositum est, id quod ex istis est, ipsa statua est.
subject to the extrinsic formal causality which will be objectively specified by the
(Seneca, Ep. 65.8) environmental interactions of its active and passive potencies, thus determining “τὸν
Seneca distinguishes intrinsic formal causality (id in quo) from extrinsic formal χρόνον, ἐντὸς οὗ πεπαῦσθαι αὐτὸ δεήσει.”
causality (id ad quod), using Plato to expand the Aristotelian four to five caus- 20
Perhaps Marcus Aurelius speaks similarly of something like Seneca’s ipsa
es, but his sixth type names the entity that stands as the result of the entire statua est (“the statue itself ”) with the first and last items in this list: “Τοῦτο τί ἐστιν
nexus of causes: id quod ex istis est. αὐτὸ καθ̓ αὑτὸ τῇ ἰδίᾳ κατασκευῇ, τί μὲν τὸ οὐσιῶδες αὐτοῦ καὶ ὑλικόν, τί δὲ τὸ
The Scholastics distinguished a seventh type of cause by discern- αἰτιῶδες, τί δὲ ποιεῖ ἐν τῷ κόσμῳ, πόσον δὲ χρόνον ὑφίσταται” (Meditations 8.11).
Formal and material causality could be named with “τί μὲν τὸ οὐσιῶδες αὐτοῦ καὶ
ing two types within extrinsic formal causality: not just exemplary or ideal
ὑλικόν,” agent cause with “τί δὲ τὸ αἰτιῶδες,” final cause with “τί δὲ ποιεῖ ἐν τῷ
causality, but also “objective specificative causality.”18 This seventh type of κόσμῳ,” and space, time, and motion (as the finite actualization of potency as po-
causality is precisely the type of causality that is proper to the action of signs. tency) with “πόσον δὲ χρόνον ὑφίσταται.” But a concrete particular individual unit
What is remarkable is that it can be seen as the same type of cause intro- stands so constituted as able to exercise within the environment an objective speci-
duced by Seneca into his discussion—“the statue itself ” (ipsa statua est)—as ficative extrinsic formal causality peculiar to its own unity: “τί ἐστιν αὐτὸ καθ̓ αὑτὸ
the result of the nexus of the other causes (id quod ex istis est), which enters τῇ ἰδίᾳ κατασκευῇ.” It will also suffer from objective specificative extrinsic formal
causality within the environment (i.e., from those other forms that will determine
17
John Deely, New Beginnings: Early Modern Philosophy and Postmodern Thought, “πόσον δὲ χρόνον ὑφίσταται”).
Toronto Studies in Semiotics (Toronto, ON: University of Toronto Press, 1994), 21
Marcus Aurelius himself seems to name all seven causes in this remark-
151–82; John Deely, Four Ages of Understanding: The First Postmodern Survey of Philosophy able text: “πότε γὰρ ἁπλότητος ἀπολαύσεις; πότε δὲ σεμνότητος; πότε δὲ τῆς ἐφ̓
from Ancient Times to the Turn of the Twenty-First Century (Toronto: University of Toron- ἑκάστου γνωρίσεως, τί τε ἐστὶ κατ̓ οὐσίαν καὶ τίνα χώραν ἔχει ἐν τῷ κόσμῳ καὶ ἐπὶ
to Press, 2001), 632–33. πόσον πέφυκεν ὑφίστασθαι καὶ ἐκ τίνων συγκέκριται καὶ τίσι δύναται ὑπάρχειν
18
Deely, Four Ages of Understanding, 633n73. καὶ τίνες δύνανται αὐτὸ διδόναι τε καὶ ἀφαιρεῖσθαι” (Meditations 10.9). Intrinsic
18 A Stoic Vision of Primary Causality Christopher S. Morrissey 19
Further, the possibilities of signification that lie latent in matter can Therefore, we are now ready to approach, with Seneca, the question
be dormant for years and years, and enter into awareness only when extrinsic of the meaning of beauty, insofar as that question may be illuminated, given
formal causality as objective specificative causality achieves its effect. We dis- that we have made the preparatory causal distinctions. For the causal distinc-
tinguish the Statue of Liberty as such by formal causality, but the action of tions suggest the meaning of beauty as, above all, what is properly commu-
formal causality is not limited to simply that mere recognition of an intrinsic nicated by the shimmering significations of objective specificative causality.
form. We could multiply the actual effects of the Statue of Liberty’s intrinsic
accidental formal cause if we were to take it as an exemplar and produce
miniature copies of it as tourist souvenirs. But in addition to such ideal cau- Beauty as the Resolution to the “Only One Cause” Paradox
sality there is also the objective specificative causality that in principle has
an infinite range of effects beyond instantiation, recognition, or even multi- If we assume that Seneca’s philosophical convictions do not lead him to deny
plication of intrinsic form. This is the extrinsic formal causality that occurs that there is also a type of final causality that is intrinsic, in addition to his ex-
when we understand the significance of the last scene in the movie Planet amples of extrinsic final causality, then we can see that his six types of causes
of the Apes. Charlton Heston cries out not simply because he recognizes the are compatible with, and unproblematically map onto, the seven Scholastic
form of the Statue of Liberty (other people do that every day and do not cry types that we have just distinguished. But what is the meaning of the Stoic
out) but because he recognizes what it now means for him. And this precisely paradox that there is only really one type of cause? The example of the statue
illustrates the difference between (intrinsic) formal causality and (non-ideal) can help us to appreciate the problem raised, but only alluded to, by the text,
extrinsic formal causality, in which the object here and now specifies the namely, the very example of the universe that Seneca also invokes. Just as a
actualization of a certain effect of signification (as “objective specificative statue can be a sign of a person, or even signify the contextual meaning of a
causality”).22 state of affairs, what would it mean to take the world itself (i.e., the universe
as a whole) as a sign?
The Stoic view would seem to be that the universe itself cannot
formal causality would be “τί τε ἐστὶ κατ̓ οὐσίαν,” and intrinsic final causality “τίνα
χώραν ἔχει ἐν τῷ κόσμῳ,” but objective specificative extrinsic formal causality could function at all as a sign in the way that the statue itself can, and Seneca there-
be expressed, in terms of extrinsic environmental impact (e.g., the forms of ice fore insists upon the difficulty that this presents for the view of Plato and
or marble acting upon and being acted upon by the environment), as “ἐπὶ πόσον Aristotle that would multiply the number of causes beyond one: “Illud vero
πέφυκεν ὑφίστασθαι,” and while “ἐκ τίνων συγκέκριται” seems clearly to name non pro solita ipsis subtilitate dixerunt, totum mundum et consummatum
material causality, perhaps “τίσι δύναται ὑπάρχειν” obscurely names names ideal opus causam esse. Multum enim interest inter opus et causam operis” (Sen-
causality (extrinsic exemplary formal causality, e.g., either as conceptual intellectual eca, Ep. 65.14). To my ear, this objection from Seneca sounds like a highly
property, or in terms of masterworks possessed by someone else that are nonetheless perceptive affirmation of the absolute distinction between primary causali-
at least also able to be copied), and it also seems that “τίνες δύνανται αὐτὸ διδόναι ty and secondary causality, which later comes to be explicitly maintained in
τε καὶ ἀφαιρεῖσθαι” obscurely names extrinsic final causality. Scholastic philosophy. Yet I do think it is implicit in the authentically Stoic
22
Because this type of causality is “prior to the well-known Aristotelian four
objection presented here.
causes, the agent, the final, the formal, and the material cause,” it plays a unique role
in the universe: “It is precisely the function of extrinsic formal causality to displace Seneca clearly states the Platonic-Aristotelian approach to the prob-
the agent and final causes by a more elementary cause which is not committed to lem of the universe itself as a sign, which would have to be exercising a
explaining how interaction could be understood. Thus the solar system is explained non-ideal extrinsic formal causality. That approach must assume that causal
as a mechanism specified by extrinsic formal causes without needing any explanation analysis eventually yields a distinct recognition of the universe itself as the
by agent causes (let alone by final causes which have not been recognized by science objective specificative cause that signifies for our conscious awareness all the
since the seventeenth century). For Einstein’s general theory of relativity precisely causal effects of God’s goodness:
eliminated gravitational forces from explanation of the solar system, by substituting
the curvature of space-time for gravitational forces (Stephen Hawking, A Brief His- the earth and the other bodies of the solar system…plain cases of extrinsic formal
tory of Time, from the Big Bang to Black Holes [New York, NY: Bantam Books, 1988], causality” (Ralph A. Powell, “Epistemology’s Minimal Cause as Basis of Science,”
29–30). Now gravitational forces are agent causes, whereas the curved space-time in Terry Prewitt, John Deely, and Karen Haworth, ed., Semiotics 1988, Proceedings
that governs the path of the earth around the sun is an excellent example of extrinsic of the 13th Annual Conference of the Semiotic Society of America [Lanham, MD:
formal causality…because that path consists of specified temporal relations between University Press of America, 1989], 180, 186).
18 A Stoic Vision of Primary Causality Christopher S. Morrissey 19
Further, the possibilities of signification that lie latent in matter can Therefore, we are now ready to approach, with Seneca, the question
be dormant for years and years, and enter into awareness only when extrinsic of the meaning of beauty, insofar as that question may be illuminated, given
formal causality as objective specificative causality achieves its effect. We dis- that we have made the preparatory causal distinctions. For the causal distinc-
tinguish the Statue of Liberty as such by formal causality, but the action of tions suggest the meaning of beauty as, above all, what is properly commu-
formal causality is not limited to simply that mere recognition of an intrinsic nicated by the shimmering significations of objective specificative causality.
form. We could multiply the actual effects of the Statue of Liberty’s intrinsic
accidental formal cause if we were to take it as an exemplar and produce
miniature copies of it as tourist souvenirs. But in addition to such ideal cau- Beauty as the Resolution to the “Only One Cause” Paradox
sality there is also the objective specificative causality that in principle has
an infinite range of effects beyond instantiation, recognition, or even multi- If we assume that Seneca’s philosophical convictions do not lead him to deny
plication of intrinsic form. This is the extrinsic formal causality that occurs that there is also a type of final causality that is intrinsic, in addition to his ex-
when we understand the significance of the last scene in the movie Planet amples of extrinsic final causality, then we can see that his six types of causes
of the Apes. Charlton Heston cries out not simply because he recognizes the are compatible with, and unproblematically map onto, the seven Scholastic
form of the Statue of Liberty (other people do that every day and do not cry types that we have just distinguished. But what is the meaning of the Stoic
out) but because he recognizes what it now means for him. And this precisely paradox that there is only really one type of cause? The example of the statue
illustrates the difference between (intrinsic) formal causality and (non-ideal) can help us to appreciate the problem raised, but only alluded to, by the text,
extrinsic formal causality, in which the object here and now specifies the namely, the very example of the universe that Seneca also invokes. Just as a
actualization of a certain effect of signification (as “objective specificative statue can be a sign of a person, or even signify the contextual meaning of a
causality”).22 state of affairs, what would it mean to take the world itself (i.e., the universe
as a whole) as a sign?
The Stoic view would seem to be that the universe itself cannot
formal causality would be “τί τε ἐστὶ κατ̓ οὐσίαν,” and intrinsic final causality “τίνα
χώραν ἔχει ἐν τῷ κόσμῳ,” but objective specificative extrinsic formal causality could function at all as a sign in the way that the statue itself can, and Seneca there-
be expressed, in terms of extrinsic environmental impact (e.g., the forms of ice fore insists upon the difficulty that this presents for the view of Plato and
or marble acting upon and being acted upon by the environment), as “ἐπὶ πόσον Aristotle that would multiply the number of causes beyond one: “Illud vero
πέφυκεν ὑφίστασθαι,” and while “ἐκ τίνων συγκέκριται” seems clearly to name non pro solita ipsis subtilitate dixerunt, totum mundum et consummatum
material causality, perhaps “τίσι δύναται ὑπάρχειν” obscurely names names ideal opus causam esse. Multum enim interest inter opus et causam operis” (Sen-
causality (extrinsic exemplary formal causality, e.g., either as conceptual intellectual eca, Ep. 65.14). To my ear, this objection from Seneca sounds like a highly
property, or in terms of masterworks possessed by someone else that are nonetheless perceptive affirmation of the absolute distinction between primary causali-
at least also able to be copied), and it also seems that “τίνες δύνανται αὐτὸ διδόναι ty and secondary causality, which later comes to be explicitly maintained in
τε καὶ ἀφαιρεῖσθαι” obscurely names extrinsic final causality. Scholastic philosophy. Yet I do think it is implicit in the authentically Stoic
22
Because this type of causality is “prior to the well-known Aristotelian four
objection presented here.
causes, the agent, the final, the formal, and the material cause,” it plays a unique role
in the universe: “It is precisely the function of extrinsic formal causality to displace Seneca clearly states the Platonic-Aristotelian approach to the prob-
the agent and final causes by a more elementary cause which is not committed to lem of the universe itself as a sign, which would have to be exercising a
explaining how interaction could be understood. Thus the solar system is explained non-ideal extrinsic formal causality. That approach must assume that causal
as a mechanism specified by extrinsic formal causes without needing any explanation analysis eventually yields a distinct recognition of the universe itself as the
by agent causes (let alone by final causes which have not been recognized by science objective specificative cause that signifies for our conscious awareness all the
since the seventeenth century). For Einstein’s general theory of relativity precisely causal effects of God’s goodness:
eliminated gravitational forces from explanation of the solar system, by substituting
the curvature of space-time for gravitational forces (Stephen Hawking, A Brief His- the earth and the other bodies of the solar system…plain cases of extrinsic formal
tory of Time, from the Big Bang to Black Holes [New York, NY: Bantam Books, 1988], causality” (Ralph A. Powell, “Epistemology’s Minimal Cause as Basis of Science,”
29–30). Now gravitational forces are agent causes, whereas the curved space-time in Terry Prewitt, John Deely, and Karen Haworth, ed., Semiotics 1988, Proceedings
that governs the path of the earth around the sun is an excellent example of extrinsic of the 13th Annual Conference of the Semiotic Society of America [Lanham, MD:
formal causality…because that path consists of specified temporal relations between University Press of America, 1989], 180, 186).
20 A Stoic Vision of Primary Causality Christopher S. Morrissey 21
Haec omnia mundus quoque, ut ait Plato, habet: facientem: hic sion as evidence in favor of reducing the Stoic view to a simple equation of
deus est. Ex quo fit: haec materia est. Formam: haec est habi- God with the one and only substantial form of the universe, to seeing God
tus et ordo mundi, quem videmus. Exemplar, scilicet, ad quod simply as the rationality (ratio) within the universe itself “structuring” its mat-
deus hanc magnitudinem operis pulcherrimi fecit. Propositum, ter, as if this alone were what it means to understand God as “the soul of the
propter quod fecit. Quaeris, quod sit propositum deo? Bonitas world” (mundo animus):
Ita certe Plato ait: “Quae deo faciendi mundum fuit causa? Bonus Nempe universa ex materia et ex deo constant. Deus ista temper-
est; bono nulla cuiusquam boni invidia est. Fecit itaque quam op- at, quae circumfusa rectorem secuntur et ducem. Potentius autem
timum potuit.” (Seneca, Ep. 65.9–10) est ac pretiosius, quod facit, quod est deus, quam materia patiens
But Seneca proceeds to criticize this Platonic-Aristotelian approach dei. Quem in hoc mundo locum deus obtinet, hunc in homine an-
by objecting that the number of causes can be multiplied still further: imus. Quod est illic materia, id in nobis corpus est; serviant ergo
deteriora melioribus. Fortes simus adversus fortuita. Non con-
Haec, quae ab Aristotele et Platone ponitur, turba causarum aut
tremescamus iniurias, non vulnera, non vincula, non egestatem.
nimium multa aut nimium pauca conprendit. Nam si, quocumque
Mors quid est? Aut finis aut transitus. Nec desinere timeo, idem
remoto quid effici non potest, id causam iudicant esse faciendi,
est enim, quod non coepisse, nec transire, quia nusquam tam an-
pauca dixerunt. Ponant inter causas tempus; nihil sine tempore
potest fieri. Ponant locum; si non fuerit, ubi fiat aliquid, ne fiet guste ero. Vale. (Seneca, Ep. 65.23–24)
quidem. Ponant motum; nihil sine hoc nec fit nec perit. Nulla sine To my mind, the non-dogmatic character of Seneca’s reflection is
motu ars, nulla mutatio est. (Seneca, Ep. 65.11) evidence of a deeper insight into the immanent character of primary causality,
In other words, the point of the exercise for Seneca does not seem to be to for in order to distinguish it from secondary causality, a type of mystical (or
pursue the study of causality in the physical world by multiplying the number at least intuitive) grasp of its profound beauty is required in order to affirm the
of secondary causes.23 Rather, his purpose in studying causality has the spir- validity of the distinction.24 One must see it as shimmering on the surface of
itual aim of seeking consolation (65.15–24), not in secondary causes, but in secondary causality’s own beauty.
meditating on the one and only primary cause, God: For me, this beautiful vision of the peculiar action of primary cau-
sality at work everywhere in the universe is most rigorously and most con-
Sed nos nunc primam et generalem quaerimus causam. Haec sim- vincingly articulated in the Thomistic understanding of God as the source
plex esse debet; nam et materia simplex est. Quaerimus, quid sit (ipsum esse subsistens) of the actuality (esse) in all things.25 But it is capable of
causa? Ratio scilicet faciens, id est deus. Ista enim, quaecumque being grasped by human beings in a seemingly infinite variety of ways, and
rettulistis, non sunt multae et singulae causae, sed ex una pendent, many thinkers and cultures have attained and expressed this grasp of beauty.
ex ea, quae faciet. (Seneca, Ep. 65.12) Philosophical rigor is not mandatory, but an authentic spiritual experience of
What strikes me as most remarkable in Seneca’s discussion is the divine immanence is.
entirely open-minded, non-dogmatic character of his meditation. It invites Seneca (and Stoicism’s) “soul of the world” is therefore, just like
ongoing personal reflection and inquiry, and it does not insist upon a non-ne- Gerard Manley Hopkins’s apt poetic phrase for primary causality, “the dear-
gotiable Stoic view of causality to be opposed to an equally ossified Platon- est freshness deep down things,” best seen as a highly suggestive metaphor.
ic-Aristotelian view. Hence I believe it would be a mistake to take his conclu- What is glimpsed in this vision is never simply reducible to a univocal materi-

23
Similarly, in Marcus Aurelius the exhortation is to view the corporeal world 24
Marcus Aurelius is thus not at all a depressive melancholic in meditations
solely in terms of the physical world’s secondary causes, but only in order to strip like this one: “Τὸ σαπρὸν τῆς ἑκάστῳ ὑποκειμένης ὕλης: ὕδωρ, κόνις, ὀστάρια,
naked our usual corporeal interpretations of physical causality, and to thus prepare γράσος, ἢ πάλιν: πῶροι γῆς τὰ μάρμαρα καὶ ὑποστάθμαι ὁ χρυσός, ὁ ἄργυρος, καὶ
our minds to think about the world anew, with reference to the primary cause, rather τριχία ἡ ἐσθὴς καὶ αἷμα ἡ πορφύρα, καὶ τὰ ἄλλα πάντα τοιαῦτα. καὶ τὸ πνευμάτιον
than with reference to our habitually mistaken interpretations: “Γυμνὰ τῶν φλοιῶν δὲ ἄλλο τοιοῦτον καὶ ἐκ τούτων εἰς ταῦτα μεταβάλλον” (Meditations 9.36). Rather,
θεάσασθαι τὰ αἰτιώδη: τὰς ἀναφορὰς τῶν πράξεων: τί πόνος: τί ἡδονή: τί θάνατος: he is exercising his ability to see primary causality at work within—and condition-
τί δόξα: τίς ὁ ἑαυτῷ ἀσχολίας αἴτιος: πῶς οὐδεὶς ὑπ̓ ἄλλου ἐμποδίζεται: ὅτι πάντα ing—any level of secondary causality, no matter how low the level.
ὑπόληψις” (Meditations 12.8). 25
Deely, Four Ages of Understanding, 266–97.
20 A Stoic Vision of Primary Causality Christopher S. Morrissey 21
Haec omnia mundus quoque, ut ait Plato, habet: facientem: hic sion as evidence in favor of reducing the Stoic view to a simple equation of
deus est. Ex quo fit: haec materia est. Formam: haec est habi- God with the one and only substantial form of the universe, to seeing God
tus et ordo mundi, quem videmus. Exemplar, scilicet, ad quod simply as the rationality (ratio) within the universe itself “structuring” its mat-
deus hanc magnitudinem operis pulcherrimi fecit. Propositum, ter, as if this alone were what it means to understand God as “the soul of the
propter quod fecit. Quaeris, quod sit propositum deo? Bonitas world” (mundo animus):
Ita certe Plato ait: “Quae deo faciendi mundum fuit causa? Bonus Nempe universa ex materia et ex deo constant. Deus ista temper-
est; bono nulla cuiusquam boni invidia est. Fecit itaque quam op- at, quae circumfusa rectorem secuntur et ducem. Potentius autem
timum potuit.” (Seneca, Ep. 65.9–10) est ac pretiosius, quod facit, quod est deus, quam materia patiens
But Seneca proceeds to criticize this Platonic-Aristotelian approach dei. Quem in hoc mundo locum deus obtinet, hunc in homine an-
by objecting that the number of causes can be multiplied still further: imus. Quod est illic materia, id in nobis corpus est; serviant ergo
deteriora melioribus. Fortes simus adversus fortuita. Non con-
Haec, quae ab Aristotele et Platone ponitur, turba causarum aut
tremescamus iniurias, non vulnera, non vincula, non egestatem.
nimium multa aut nimium pauca conprendit. Nam si, quocumque
Mors quid est? Aut finis aut transitus. Nec desinere timeo, idem
remoto quid effici non potest, id causam iudicant esse faciendi,
est enim, quod non coepisse, nec transire, quia nusquam tam an-
pauca dixerunt. Ponant inter causas tempus; nihil sine tempore
potest fieri. Ponant locum; si non fuerit, ubi fiat aliquid, ne fiet guste ero. Vale. (Seneca, Ep. 65.23–24)
quidem. Ponant motum; nihil sine hoc nec fit nec perit. Nulla sine To my mind, the non-dogmatic character of Seneca’s reflection is
motu ars, nulla mutatio est. (Seneca, Ep. 65.11) evidence of a deeper insight into the immanent character of primary causality,
In other words, the point of the exercise for Seneca does not seem to be to for in order to distinguish it from secondary causality, a type of mystical (or
pursue the study of causality in the physical world by multiplying the number at least intuitive) grasp of its profound beauty is required in order to affirm the
of secondary causes.23 Rather, his purpose in studying causality has the spir- validity of the distinction.24 One must see it as shimmering on the surface of
itual aim of seeking consolation (65.15–24), not in secondary causes, but in secondary causality’s own beauty.
meditating on the one and only primary cause, God: For me, this beautiful vision of the peculiar action of primary cau-
sality at work everywhere in the universe is most rigorously and most con-
Sed nos nunc primam et generalem quaerimus causam. Haec sim- vincingly articulated in the Thomistic understanding of God as the source
plex esse debet; nam et materia simplex est. Quaerimus, quid sit (ipsum esse subsistens) of the actuality (esse) in all things.25 But it is capable of
causa? Ratio scilicet faciens, id est deus. Ista enim, quaecumque being grasped by human beings in a seemingly infinite variety of ways, and
rettulistis, non sunt multae et singulae causae, sed ex una pendent, many thinkers and cultures have attained and expressed this grasp of beauty.
ex ea, quae faciet. (Seneca, Ep. 65.12) Philosophical rigor is not mandatory, but an authentic spiritual experience of
What strikes me as most remarkable in Seneca’s discussion is the divine immanence is.
entirely open-minded, non-dogmatic character of his meditation. It invites Seneca (and Stoicism’s) “soul of the world” is therefore, just like
ongoing personal reflection and inquiry, and it does not insist upon a non-ne- Gerard Manley Hopkins’s apt poetic phrase for primary causality, “the dear-
gotiable Stoic view of causality to be opposed to an equally ossified Platon- est freshness deep down things,” best seen as a highly suggestive metaphor.
ic-Aristotelian view. Hence I believe it would be a mistake to take his conclu- What is glimpsed in this vision is never simply reducible to a univocal materi-

23
Similarly, in Marcus Aurelius the exhortation is to view the corporeal world 24
Marcus Aurelius is thus not at all a depressive melancholic in meditations
solely in terms of the physical world’s secondary causes, but only in order to strip like this one: “Τὸ σαπρὸν τῆς ἑκάστῳ ὑποκειμένης ὕλης: ὕδωρ, κόνις, ὀστάρια,
naked our usual corporeal interpretations of physical causality, and to thus prepare γράσος, ἢ πάλιν: πῶροι γῆς τὰ μάρμαρα καὶ ὑποστάθμαι ὁ χρυσός, ὁ ἄργυρος, καὶ
our minds to think about the world anew, with reference to the primary cause, rather τριχία ἡ ἐσθὴς καὶ αἷμα ἡ πορφύρα, καὶ τὰ ἄλλα πάντα τοιαῦτα. καὶ τὸ πνευμάτιον
than with reference to our habitually mistaken interpretations: “Γυμνὰ τῶν φλοιῶν δὲ ἄλλο τοιοῦτον καὶ ἐκ τούτων εἰς ταῦτα μεταβάλλον” (Meditations 9.36). Rather,
θεάσασθαι τὰ αἰτιώδη: τὰς ἀναφορὰς τῶν πράξεων: τί πόνος: τί ἡδονή: τί θάνατος: he is exercising his ability to see primary causality at work within—and condition-
τί δόξα: τίς ὁ ἑαυτῷ ἀσχολίας αἴτιος: πῶς οὐδεὶς ὑπ̓ ἄλλου ἐμποδίζεται: ὅτι πάντα ing—any level of secondary causality, no matter how low the level.
ὑπόληψις” (Meditations 12.8). 25
Deely, Four Ages of Understanding, 266–97.
22 A Stoic Vision of Primary Causality Christopher S. Morrissey 23
al part of an empiriometric physical schema (pace Christensen).26 Hence I am Seneca’s criticism here of the conventional Platonic-Aristotelian
inclined to accept this kind of perennial vision of the beauty of the divine view is, therefore, to my mind, an expression of authentic Stoic (and authen-
immanence, of which humans are ever capable,27 as expressive of authentic tic philosophical) insight into beauty,30 because it is meant to deny a vision
Stoicism.28 For it is nothing less than a spiritual vision of the beauty that per- of the world in relation to God that would take that relation merely as one
vades all things—“the dearest freshness deep down things.” of secondary causality, as with the sculpture in relation to the sculptor.31 The
On this vision, God may be understood as the efficient cause of special instance of the world in relation to God requires a special metaphor
the world, but not in the manner of secondary causality, like the artisan who that expresses the radically asymmetrical relationship of primary causality to
is a part (albeit a key part) of the process that makes the statue stand as the the world: “Quem in hoc mundo locum deus obtinet, hunc in homine ani-
statue itself. Rather, in contrast with the empiriometric picture familiar to mus” (Seneca, Ep. 65.24).
mathematical physics, the efficient causality characteristic of the divine agen- Moreover, the Stoic objection to understanding the world itself as
cy called “primary causality” is—because of its asymmetry in relation to the exercising objective specificative extrinsic formal causality in the same way
world—to be the “first cause” which makes actual anything that would stand that a statue can signify (i.e., it can formally impact the environment) is highly
as actual.29 pertinent. After all, what is there for the universe to exercise extrinsic for-
mal causality upon in this way, when there is, by definition, nothing outside
the universe? Surely its beauty cannot act upon God, for this would be to
26
Marcus Aurelius cautions us to exclude virtue from reductive causal analysis, misconceive the nature of God, and to fail to understand the radically asym-
so it seems certain to me that Stoicism cannot be identified with a purely empiriomet-
ric worldview in which God is simply the “structure” found in the equations of the 30
Marcus Aurelius unmistakably articulates this spiritual aim of Stoic med-
world’s multiple tensional sub-fields: “ὅλως οὖν, χωρὶς ἀρετῆς καὶ τῶν ἀπ̓ ἀρετῆς, itations upon physics: “Πῶς εἰς ἄλληλα πάντα μεταβάλλει, θεωρητικὴν μέθοδον
μέμνησο ἐπὶ τὰ κατὰ μέρος τρέχειν καὶ τῇ διαιρέσει αὐτῶν εἰς καταφρόνησιν ἰέναι, κτῆσαι καὶ διηνεκῶς πρόσεχε καὶ συγγυμνάσθητι περὶ τοῦτο τὸ μέρος: οὐδὲν
τὸ δ̓ αὐτὸ καὶ ἐπὶ τὸν βίον ὅλον μετάφερε” (Meditations, 11.2). Stephen Hawking γὰρ οὕτως μεγαλοφροσύνης ποιητικόν. ἐξεδύσατο τὸ σῶμα καὶ ἐννοήσας ὅτι
famously posed the question of what breathes the “fire” into the equations, and the ὅσον οὐδέπω πάντα ταῦτα καταλιπεῖν ἀπιόντα ἐξ ἀνθρώπων δεήσει, ἀνῆκεν
invocation of Heraclitus and the Stoics with this metaphor is suggestive to my mind ὅλον ἑαυτὸν δικαιοσύνῃ μὲν εἰς τὰ ὑφ̓ ἑαυτοῦ ἐνεργούμενα, ἐν δὲ τοῖς ἄλλοις
of the distinction between primary and secondary causality, even if Hawking himself συμβαίνουσι τῇ τῶν ὅλων φύσει. τί δ̓ ἐρεῖ τις ἢ ὑπολήψεται περὶ αὐτοῦ ἢ πράξει
dismisses any models of the universe not constructed purely in terms of secondary κατ̓ αὐτοῦ, οὐδ̓ εἰς νοῦν βάλλεται, δύο τούτοις ἀρκούμενος, εἰ αὐτὸς δικαιοπραγεῖ
causes (Hawking, A Brief History of Time, 174). τὸ νῦν πρασσόμενον καὶ φιλεῖ τὸ νῦν ἀπονεμόμενον ἑαυτῷ: ἀσχολίας δὲ πάσας
27
Cf. Aldous Huxley, The Perennial Philosophy, Harper Perennial Modern Clas- καὶ σπουδὰς ἀφῆκε καὶ οὐδὲν ἄλλο βούλεται ἢ εὐθεῖαν περαίνειν διὰ τοῦ νόμου
sics (New York: HarperCollins Publishers, 2009). καὶ εὐθεῖαν περαίνοντι ἕπεσθαι τῷ θεῷ” (Meditations 10.11).
28
Marcus Aurelius seems to achieve this, by a transposition of the reductive 31
Even so, there is an analogy to be made between the per se causality of the
physical bifurcation of causa and materia on the level of secondary causality, into the soul (versus any per accidens influences on the body) and the per se causality of the prima-
analogously asymmetrical bifurcation between primary and secondary causality (i.e., ry cause. (On this crucial Scholastic distinction between per se and per accidens causality,
as the fundamental insight which a sustained meditation on the asymmetry traceable cf. Feser, Aquinas, 69–72, 83–89; Feser, Scholastic Metaphysics, 148–54.) Marcus Aure-
within secondary causality will eventually yield): “Σωτηρία βίου ἕκαστον δἰ ὅλου lius suggests the analogy in this text, which again invokes the bifurcation meditation:
αὐτὸ τί ἐστιν ὁρᾶν, τί μὲν αὐτοῦ τὸ ὑλικόν, τί δὲ τὸ αἰτιῶδες: ἐξ ὅλης τῆς ψυχῆς “Μέμνησο ὅτι τὸ νευροσπαστοῦν ἐστιν ἐκεῖνο τὸ ἔνδον ἐγκεκρυμμένον: ἐκεῖνο
τὰ δίκαια ποιεῖν καὶ τἀληθῆ λέγειν. τί λοιπὸν ἢ ἀπολαύειν τοῦ ζῆν συνάπτοντα ῥητορεία, ἐκεῖνο ζωή, ἐκεῖνο, εἰ δεῖ εἰπεῖν, ἄνθρωπος. μηδέποτε συμπεριφαντάζου
ἄλλο ἐπ̓ ἄλλῳ ἀγαθόν, ὥστε μηδὲ τὸ βραχύτατον διάστημα ἀπολείπειν” (Medita- τὸ περικείμενον ἀγγειῶδες καὶ τὰ ὀργάνια ταῦτα τὰ περιπεπλασμένα: ὅμοια γάρ
tions 12.29). ἐστι σκεπάρνῳ, μόνον διαφέροντα, καθότι προσφυῆ ἐστιν. ἐπεί τοι οὐ μᾶλλόν τι
29
Deely, Four Ages of Understanding, 284–90; Feser, The Last Superstition, 49– τούτων ὄφελός ἐστι τῶν μορίων χωρὶς τῆς κινούσης καὶ ἰσχούσης αὐτὰ αἰτίας, ἢ
110; Edward Feser, Aquinas: A Beginner’s Guide (London, UK: Oneworld Publications, τῆς κερκίδος τῇ ὑφαντρίᾳ καὶ τοῦ καλάμου τῷ γράφοντι καὶ τοῦ μαστιγίου τῷ
2009), 8–81; Edward Feser, “Existential Inertia and the Five Ways,” American Catholic ἡνιόχῳ” (Meditations 10.38; LS 44). The affinity of the soul with God is also suggest-
Philosophical Quarterly 85, no. 2 (2011): 237–67; Edward Feser, “The Medieval Princi- ed in other texts: for example, “Πρὸς τί ποτε ἄρα νῦν χρῶμαι τῇ ἐμαυτοῦ ψυχῇ;
ple of Motion and the Modern Principle of Inertia,” Proceedings of the Society for Medie- παῤ ἕκαστα τοῦτο ἐπανερωτᾶν ἑαυτὸν καὶ ἐξετάζειν τί μοί ἐστι νῦν ἐν τούτῳ τῷ
val Logic and Metaphysics 10 (2012): 4–6; Edward Feser, “Motion in Aristotle, Newton, μορίῳ, ὃ δὴ ἡγεμονικὸν καλοῦσι, καὶ τίνος ἄρα νῦν ἔχω ψυχήν; μήτι παιδίου; μήτι
and Einstein,” in Edward Feser, ed., Aristotle on Method and Metaphysics, Philosophers μειρακίου; μήτι γυναικαρίου; μήτι τυράννου; μήτι κτήνους; μήτι θηρίου” (Medita-
in Depth (London, UK: Palgrave Macmillan, 2013), 236–58. tions 5.11).
22 A Stoic Vision of Primary Causality Christopher S. Morrissey 23
al part of an empiriometric physical schema (pace Christensen).26 Hence I am Seneca’s criticism here of the conventional Platonic-Aristotelian
inclined to accept this kind of perennial vision of the beauty of the divine view is, therefore, to my mind, an expression of authentic Stoic (and authen-
immanence, of which humans are ever capable,27 as expressive of authentic tic philosophical) insight into beauty,30 because it is meant to deny a vision
Stoicism.28 For it is nothing less than a spiritual vision of the beauty that per- of the world in relation to God that would take that relation merely as one
vades all things—“the dearest freshness deep down things.” of secondary causality, as with the sculpture in relation to the sculptor.31 The
On this vision, God may be understood as the efficient cause of special instance of the world in relation to God requires a special metaphor
the world, but not in the manner of secondary causality, like the artisan who that expresses the radically asymmetrical relationship of primary causality to
is a part (albeit a key part) of the process that makes the statue stand as the the world: “Quem in hoc mundo locum deus obtinet, hunc in homine ani-
statue itself. Rather, in contrast with the empiriometric picture familiar to mus” (Seneca, Ep. 65.24).
mathematical physics, the efficient causality characteristic of the divine agen- Moreover, the Stoic objection to understanding the world itself as
cy called “primary causality” is—because of its asymmetry in relation to the exercising objective specificative extrinsic formal causality in the same way
world—to be the “first cause” which makes actual anything that would stand that a statue can signify (i.e., it can formally impact the environment) is highly
as actual.29 pertinent. After all, what is there for the universe to exercise extrinsic for-
mal causality upon in this way, when there is, by definition, nothing outside
the universe? Surely its beauty cannot act upon God, for this would be to
26
Marcus Aurelius cautions us to exclude virtue from reductive causal analysis, misconceive the nature of God, and to fail to understand the radically asym-
so it seems certain to me that Stoicism cannot be identified with a purely empiriomet-
ric worldview in which God is simply the “structure” found in the equations of the 30
Marcus Aurelius unmistakably articulates this spiritual aim of Stoic med-
world’s multiple tensional sub-fields: “ὅλως οὖν, χωρὶς ἀρετῆς καὶ τῶν ἀπ̓ ἀρετῆς, itations upon physics: “Πῶς εἰς ἄλληλα πάντα μεταβάλλει, θεωρητικὴν μέθοδον
μέμνησο ἐπὶ τὰ κατὰ μέρος τρέχειν καὶ τῇ διαιρέσει αὐτῶν εἰς καταφρόνησιν ἰέναι, κτῆσαι καὶ διηνεκῶς πρόσεχε καὶ συγγυμνάσθητι περὶ τοῦτο τὸ μέρος: οὐδὲν
τὸ δ̓ αὐτὸ καὶ ἐπὶ τὸν βίον ὅλον μετάφερε” (Meditations, 11.2). Stephen Hawking γὰρ οὕτως μεγαλοφροσύνης ποιητικόν. ἐξεδύσατο τὸ σῶμα καὶ ἐννοήσας ὅτι
famously posed the question of what breathes the “fire” into the equations, and the ὅσον οὐδέπω πάντα ταῦτα καταλιπεῖν ἀπιόντα ἐξ ἀνθρώπων δεήσει, ἀνῆκεν
invocation of Heraclitus and the Stoics with this metaphor is suggestive to my mind ὅλον ἑαυτὸν δικαιοσύνῃ μὲν εἰς τὰ ὑφ̓ ἑαυτοῦ ἐνεργούμενα, ἐν δὲ τοῖς ἄλλοις
of the distinction between primary and secondary causality, even if Hawking himself συμβαίνουσι τῇ τῶν ὅλων φύσει. τί δ̓ ἐρεῖ τις ἢ ὑπολήψεται περὶ αὐτοῦ ἢ πράξει
dismisses any models of the universe not constructed purely in terms of secondary κατ̓ αὐτοῦ, οὐδ̓ εἰς νοῦν βάλλεται, δύο τούτοις ἀρκούμενος, εἰ αὐτὸς δικαιοπραγεῖ
causes (Hawking, A Brief History of Time, 174). τὸ νῦν πρασσόμενον καὶ φιλεῖ τὸ νῦν ἀπονεμόμενον ἑαυτῷ: ἀσχολίας δὲ πάσας
27
Cf. Aldous Huxley, The Perennial Philosophy, Harper Perennial Modern Clas- καὶ σπουδὰς ἀφῆκε καὶ οὐδὲν ἄλλο βούλεται ἢ εὐθεῖαν περαίνειν διὰ τοῦ νόμου
sics (New York: HarperCollins Publishers, 2009). καὶ εὐθεῖαν περαίνοντι ἕπεσθαι τῷ θεῷ” (Meditations 10.11).
28
Marcus Aurelius seems to achieve this, by a transposition of the reductive 31
Even so, there is an analogy to be made between the per se causality of the
physical bifurcation of causa and materia on the level of secondary causality, into the soul (versus any per accidens influences on the body) and the per se causality of the prima-
analogously asymmetrical bifurcation between primary and secondary causality (i.e., ry cause. (On this crucial Scholastic distinction between per se and per accidens causality,
as the fundamental insight which a sustained meditation on the asymmetry traceable cf. Feser, Aquinas, 69–72, 83–89; Feser, Scholastic Metaphysics, 148–54.) Marcus Aure-
within secondary causality will eventually yield): “Σωτηρία βίου ἕκαστον δἰ ὅλου lius suggests the analogy in this text, which again invokes the bifurcation meditation:
αὐτὸ τί ἐστιν ὁρᾶν, τί μὲν αὐτοῦ τὸ ὑλικόν, τί δὲ τὸ αἰτιῶδες: ἐξ ὅλης τῆς ψυχῆς “Μέμνησο ὅτι τὸ νευροσπαστοῦν ἐστιν ἐκεῖνο τὸ ἔνδον ἐγκεκρυμμένον: ἐκεῖνο
τὰ δίκαια ποιεῖν καὶ τἀληθῆ λέγειν. τί λοιπὸν ἢ ἀπολαύειν τοῦ ζῆν συνάπτοντα ῥητορεία, ἐκεῖνο ζωή, ἐκεῖνο, εἰ δεῖ εἰπεῖν, ἄνθρωπος. μηδέποτε συμπεριφαντάζου
ἄλλο ἐπ̓ ἄλλῳ ἀγαθόν, ὥστε μηδὲ τὸ βραχύτατον διάστημα ἀπολείπειν” (Medita- τὸ περικείμενον ἀγγειῶδες καὶ τὰ ὀργάνια ταῦτα τὰ περιπεπλασμένα: ὅμοια γάρ
tions 12.29). ἐστι σκεπάρνῳ, μόνον διαφέροντα, καθότι προσφυῆ ἐστιν. ἐπεί τοι οὐ μᾶλλόν τι
29
Deely, Four Ages of Understanding, 284–90; Feser, The Last Superstition, 49– τούτων ὄφελός ἐστι τῶν μορίων χωρὶς τῆς κινούσης καὶ ἰσχούσης αὐτὰ αἰτίας, ἢ
110; Edward Feser, Aquinas: A Beginner’s Guide (London, UK: Oneworld Publications, τῆς κερκίδος τῇ ὑφαντρίᾳ καὶ τοῦ καλάμου τῷ γράφοντι καὶ τοῦ μαστιγίου τῷ
2009), 8–81; Edward Feser, “Existential Inertia and the Five Ways,” American Catholic ἡνιόχῳ” (Meditations 10.38; LS 44). The affinity of the soul with God is also suggest-
Philosophical Quarterly 85, no. 2 (2011): 237–67; Edward Feser, “The Medieval Princi- ed in other texts: for example, “Πρὸς τί ποτε ἄρα νῦν χρῶμαι τῇ ἐμαυτοῦ ψυχῇ;
ple of Motion and the Modern Principle of Inertia,” Proceedings of the Society for Medie- παῤ ἕκαστα τοῦτο ἐπανερωτᾶν ἑαυτὸν καὶ ἐξετάζειν τί μοί ἐστι νῦν ἐν τούτῳ τῷ
val Logic and Metaphysics 10 (2012): 4–6; Edward Feser, “Motion in Aristotle, Newton, μορίῳ, ὃ δὴ ἡγεμονικὸν καλοῦσι, καὶ τίνος ἄρα νῦν ἔχω ψυχήν; μήτι παιδίου; μήτι
and Einstein,” in Edward Feser, ed., Aristotle on Method and Metaphysics, Philosophers μειρακίου; μήτι γυναικαρίου; μήτι τυράννου; μήτι κτήνους; μήτι θηρίου” (Medita-
in Depth (London, UK: Palgrave Macmillan, 2013), 236–58. tions 5.11).
24 A Stoic Vision of Primary Causality Christopher S. Morrissey 25
metrical action of primary causality. In other words, the Stoic vision stands in I have provided here some evidence that this meditative appreciation
defense of the radical transcendence of the divine actuality from all second- of beauty is, in fact, articulated in Stoic authors like Seneca and Marcus Aure-
ary causes, by seeing it as the radically immanent efficient primary causality lius, by quoting some relevant passages. I have tried to suggest the plausibility
that, by its very nature, can exist nowhere else but within the world as its most of my way of reading these authors by offering, as a paradigmatic example,
radical condition. the case of the spiritual exercise that attains a distinctive grasp of primary
The point of the Stoic paradox that the only true cause is God is there- causality. It does so by starting its meditation (as in Seneca’s Letter 65) with
fore not an expression of any kind of theological voluntarism. It is, rather, an an analysis of secondary causality within the world and proceeding to con-
attempt to avoid misunderstanding God as a cause like any other cause in the templation of what might be the meaning of the world itself (i.e., the world
physical world,32 which is what the contemporary analytic notion of form as considered as a sign). The graceful beauty of primary causality itself then
“structure” would lead us to, with its highly problematic empiriometric con- provides the answer.
strual of form.33 The point of the paradox, rather, is to prepare our vision for To be able to see God as primary cause means that one has glimpsed,
glimpsing the divine immanence of primary causality as radically beautiful. in a perennial vision (shared also by Plotinus), the grace that shimmers on the
surface of beauty’s secondary causality in the realm of the audible and the
visible. I have argued that this vision of grace shimmering on the surface of
Conclusion: A Stoic Vision of the Corporeal World as Beautiful beauty is the ultimate basis, both of the Scholastic distinction between pri-
mary and secondary causality, and also of the Stoic paradox that God alone
On my reading, the authentic Stoic understanding of God points, above all, is the only true cause. This latter thought is also sometimes expressed with
to an appreciation—attained via a meditative experience of beauty—of the a sublime, mystical observation about the divine immanence animating the
unique divine immanence found within all the actuality (esse) of the world’s world’s beauty: “tout est grâce.”35
beings. If the validity of this reading is granted, then it may also permit a pro-
found insight to come into focus, namely, that God stands in relation to the —TrinityWestern University
physical world such that its networks of secondary causality are radically depen-
dent on the divine primary causality. Meditation comes to appreciate vividly
God’s relation to the corporeal world, by contemplating the world accessible
by sense-perception (to which the physical world of mathematical physics is
entirely subordinate in actuality—since the quantum physical world possess-
es vastly more amounts of undetermined potency)34 in its radical beauty.

32
The paradox that “there is really only one true cause” (ratio scilicet faciens,
id est deus) can also be expressed as an affirmation that “there are really only two
types of causes” (ἔξω δὲ τούτων οὐδέν ἐστιν), as Marcus Aurelius does with the
meditative language of the causa/materia bifurcation that here considers the soul’s
relation before God (and note how similar this is to Seneca’s concluding reflections
on primary causality in the universe): “Ἅλις τοῦ ἀθλίου βίου καὶ γογγυσμοῦ καὶ
πιθηκισμοῦ.—τί ταράσσῃ; τί τούτων καινόν; τί σε ἐξίστησι; τὸ αἴτιον; ἴδε αὐτό.
ἀλλ̓ ἡ ὕλη; ἴδε αὐτήν. ἔξω δὲ τούτων οὐδέν ἐστιν, ἀλλὰ καὶ πρὸς τοὺς θεοὺς ἤδη
ποτὲ ἁπλούστερος καὶ χρηστότερος γενοῦ. Ἴσον τὸ ἑκατὸν ἔτεσι καὶ τὸ τρισὶ 35
“All is grace” — St. Therese of Lisieux; cf. Georges Bernanos, Diary of a
ταῦτα ἱστορῆσαι” (Meditations 9.37). Country Priest (New York, NY: Caroll & Graf Publishers, 2002). Initial versions of
33
David Oderberg, “Is Form Structure?,” in D.D. Novotný and L. Novák, some portions of this article were delivered as papers at the Northwest Ancient
eds., Neo-Aristotelian Perspectives in Metaphysics (London, UK: Routledge, 2014), 164– Philosophy Workshop at the University of British Columbia Campus, in Buchanan
80; Feser, Scholastic Metaphysics, 186–89. D324 on Saturday, September 27th, 2014, at 3:45pm, and also at The Power of Beau-
34
Cf. Wolfgang Smith, The Quantum Enigma: Finding the Hidden Key, 3rd ed. ty Conference at the Franciscan University of Steubenville, on Saturday, October 25,
(San Rafael, CA: Angelico Press, 2005). 2014, at 2:35pm.
24 A Stoic Vision of Primary Causality Christopher S. Morrissey 25
metrical action of primary causality. In other words, the Stoic vision stands in I have provided here some evidence that this meditative appreciation
defense of the radical transcendence of the divine actuality from all second- of beauty is, in fact, articulated in Stoic authors like Seneca and Marcus Aure-
ary causes, by seeing it as the radically immanent efficient primary causality lius, by quoting some relevant passages. I have tried to suggest the plausibility
that, by its very nature, can exist nowhere else but within the world as its most of my way of reading these authors by offering, as a paradigmatic example,
radical condition. the case of the spiritual exercise that attains a distinctive grasp of primary
The point of the Stoic paradox that the only true cause is God is there- causality. It does so by starting its meditation (as in Seneca’s Letter 65) with
fore not an expression of any kind of theological voluntarism. It is, rather, an an analysis of secondary causality within the world and proceeding to con-
attempt to avoid misunderstanding God as a cause like any other cause in the templation of what might be the meaning of the world itself (i.e., the world
physical world,32 which is what the contemporary analytic notion of form as considered as a sign). The graceful beauty of primary causality itself then
“structure” would lead us to, with its highly problematic empiriometric con- provides the answer.
strual of form.33 The point of the paradox, rather, is to prepare our vision for To be able to see God as primary cause means that one has glimpsed,
glimpsing the divine immanence of primary causality as radically beautiful. in a perennial vision (shared also by Plotinus), the grace that shimmers on the
surface of beauty’s secondary causality in the realm of the audible and the
visible. I have argued that this vision of grace shimmering on the surface of
Conclusion: A Stoic Vision of the Corporeal World as Beautiful beauty is the ultimate basis, both of the Scholastic distinction between pri-
mary and secondary causality, and also of the Stoic paradox that God alone
On my reading, the authentic Stoic understanding of God points, above all, is the only true cause. This latter thought is also sometimes expressed with
to an appreciation—attained via a meditative experience of beauty—of the a sublime, mystical observation about the divine immanence animating the
unique divine immanence found within all the actuality (esse) of the world’s world’s beauty: “tout est grâce.”35
beings. If the validity of this reading is granted, then it may also permit a pro-
found insight to come into focus, namely, that God stands in relation to the —TrinityWestern University
physical world such that its networks of secondary causality are radically depen-
dent on the divine primary causality. Meditation comes to appreciate vividly
God’s relation to the corporeal world, by contemplating the world accessible
by sense-perception (to which the physical world of mathematical physics is
entirely subordinate in actuality—since the quantum physical world possess-
es vastly more amounts of undetermined potency)34 in its radical beauty.

32
The paradox that “there is really only one true cause” (ratio scilicet faciens,
id est deus) can also be expressed as an affirmation that “there are really only two
types of causes” (ἔξω δὲ τούτων οὐδέν ἐστιν), as Marcus Aurelius does with the
meditative language of the causa/materia bifurcation that here considers the soul’s
relation before God (and note how similar this is to Seneca’s concluding reflections
on primary causality in the universe): “Ἅλις τοῦ ἀθλίου βίου καὶ γογγυσμοῦ καὶ
πιθηκισμοῦ.—τί ταράσσῃ; τί τούτων καινόν; τί σε ἐξίστησι; τὸ αἴτιον; ἴδε αὐτό.
ἀλλ̓ ἡ ὕλη; ἴδε αὐτήν. ἔξω δὲ τούτων οὐδέν ἐστιν, ἀλλὰ καὶ πρὸς τοὺς θεοὺς ἤδη
ποτὲ ἁπλούστερος καὶ χρηστότερος γενοῦ. Ἴσον τὸ ἑκατὸν ἔτεσι καὶ τὸ τρισὶ 35
“All is grace” — St. Therese of Lisieux; cf. Georges Bernanos, Diary of a
ταῦτα ἱστορῆσαι” (Meditations 9.37). Country Priest (New York, NY: Caroll & Graf Publishers, 2002). Initial versions of
33
David Oderberg, “Is Form Structure?,” in D.D. Novotný and L. Novák, some portions of this article were delivered as papers at the Northwest Ancient
eds., Neo-Aristotelian Perspectives in Metaphysics (London, UK: Routledge, 2014), 164– Philosophy Workshop at the University of British Columbia Campus, in Buchanan
80; Feser, Scholastic Metaphysics, 186–89. D324 on Saturday, September 27th, 2014, at 3:45pm, and also at The Power of Beau-
34
Cf. Wolfgang Smith, The Quantum Enigma: Finding the Hidden Key, 3rd ed. ty Conference at the Franciscan University of Steubenville, on Saturday, October 25,
(San Rafael, CA: Angelico Press, 2005). 2014, at 2:35pm.
Brian Donohue 27

Beauty and Motivation in Aristotle the range of possible translations is that the word shows up in a variety of
contexts. It appears at crucial junctures not only in his Ethics, but also in the
Topics, Rhetoric, Poetics, Politics, Metaphysics, and the Parts and Movement of Ani-
Brian Donohue mals. Aristotle seems to apply the word kalon to personal beauty, to features
of animals, to features of nature, to a thing’s proper functioning, to music, to
dramatic performances, to geometrical objects, and to contemplative activity.
Again, we are left wondering what such a word could mean, if indeed it has
I. Introduction a single meaning at all.
Unsurprisingly, then, there has been considerable scholarly debate
The concept of kalon appears at important places in Aristotle’s Ethics.1 For surrounding the interpretation of the concept of kalon in Aristotle’s thought.
instance, Aristotle claims that the virtuous agent acts for the sake of what is The debates here are manifold. The first and most prominent is whether
kalon; in his account of individual virtues of character, he describes many kalon should be regarded as an aesthetic concept.2 Here, it seems implausible
of them explicitly as dispositions oriented toward what is kalon; he also de- that the kalon the virtuous agent chooses is supposed to be the same as the
scribes many of the virtues themselves as kalon, and suggests that this has kalon in a work of art or in personal beauty. This is because it is implausible
something to do with the value and importance of the virtues. that what the virtuous agent appreciates about a virtuous action are its aes-
The Greek word kalon has been rendered variously in English as thetic features. This would have the consequence (it seems) of rendering the
“good,” “beautiful,” “noble,” “fine,” “admirable,” and “honorable.” Differ- virtuous agent as little different from a good art critic, and if this is Aristotle’s
ent translations have arisen not only among translators and commentators, view, then it’s probably incorrect. Similarly, with respect to our evaluations of
but also within single translations of the Ethics. This fact draws our attention agents, it’s consonant with Aristotle to advise that one vote for the most kalos
to two problems facing an investigation of the concept of kalon in Aristot- politician, but this certainly isn’t equivalent to advising someone to vote for
le’s ethics. First, it suggests that we have no English word that corresponds the most beautiful politician.
isomorphically with the term kalon. As English-readers of Aristotle, we need, Another debate is whether we should read the term kalon as equiv-
instead, an arsenal of terms to capture the nuanced features of its evidently ocal (or homonymous). There is some suggestion in the Topics that Aristotle
complex Greek connotation. Of course, this is a common problem facing thinks it is a homonym (Top. 106a20–22). And here, it is not clear what the
translators; isomorphic translations are perhaps more the exception than the implications of this would be for his Ethics (e.g., whether we could draw the
norm. However, a peculiar problem arises in this case because the concept it conclusion that he is using it equivocally between moral and aesthetic con-
is supposed to express is patently central to Aristotle’s Ethics, and yet we lack texts). This also raises the question of whether the term kalon is what some
not only a single word in English that corresponds to the Greek term, but it scholars call “pros hen equivocal”—that is, a term with several, but interrelated
might also very well be a native concept of the attribute kalon itself. From a senses. Still another debate concerns whether kalon is a parochial concept—
cursory survey of the above list of candidate translations, it isn’t at all clear that is, one that reflects only a particular view of beauty endemic to Aristotle
why the meanings associated with this list of English words should hang to- and his aristocratic ilk in ancient Athens. In that case, the concept of kalon
gether as expressing a single attribute familiar to English language users. would be of merely historical interest; it would have little or nothing to teach
The second problem facing translators is the diversity of contexts us about ethics today.
in which Aristotle employs the term kalon. As it turns out, one reason for In this paper, I have two goals. First, I wish to navigate some of the
above difficulties and present an interpretation of the meaning of kalon in
For general discussions, cf. Joseph Owens, “The Kalon in the Aristotelian
1
Aristotle, on which the term is not only relatively unified in its meaning, but
Ethics,” in Studies in Aristotle, ed. D.J. O’Meara (Washington, DC: Catholic University on which it also expresses nearly the same concept as our word beautiful
of America Press, 1981), 261–77; Kelly Rogers, “Aristotle’s Concept of To Kalon,” does. Second, on the basis of this characterization, I wish to show the im-
Ancient Philosophy 13 (1993): 355–71; Gabriel Richardson Lear, “Aristotle on Moral portance and application of this concept for three facets of Aristotle’s Ethics:
Virtue and the Fine,” in The Blackwell Guide to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, ed. Richard
Kraut (Oxford: Blackwell, 2006), 116–36.
2
Cf. Terence Irwin, “The Sense and Reference of Kalon in Aristotle,” Classical
© Brian Donohue, Quaestiones Disputatae, Vol. 6, No. 2 (Spring 2016)
Philology 105, no. 4 (2010): 381–96.
Brian Donohue 27

Beauty and Motivation in Aristotle the range of possible translations is that the word shows up in a variety of
contexts. It appears at crucial junctures not only in his Ethics, but also in the
Topics, Rhetoric, Poetics, Politics, Metaphysics, and the Parts and Movement of Ani-
Brian Donohue mals. Aristotle seems to apply the word kalon to personal beauty, to features
of animals, to features of nature, to a thing’s proper functioning, to music, to
dramatic performances, to geometrical objects, and to contemplative activity.
Again, we are left wondering what such a word could mean, if indeed it has
I. Introduction a single meaning at all.
Unsurprisingly, then, there has been considerable scholarly debate
The concept of kalon appears at important places in Aristotle’s Ethics.1 For surrounding the interpretation of the concept of kalon in Aristotle’s thought.
instance, Aristotle claims that the virtuous agent acts for the sake of what is The debates here are manifold. The first and most prominent is whether
kalon; in his account of individual virtues of character, he describes many kalon should be regarded as an aesthetic concept.2 Here, it seems implausible
of them explicitly as dispositions oriented toward what is kalon; he also de- that the kalon the virtuous agent chooses is supposed to be the same as the
scribes many of the virtues themselves as kalon, and suggests that this has kalon in a work of art or in personal beauty. This is because it is implausible
something to do with the value and importance of the virtues. that what the virtuous agent appreciates about a virtuous action are its aes-
The Greek word kalon has been rendered variously in English as thetic features. This would have the consequence (it seems) of rendering the
“good,” “beautiful,” “noble,” “fine,” “admirable,” and “honorable.” Differ- virtuous agent as little different from a good art critic, and if this is Aristotle’s
ent translations have arisen not only among translators and commentators, view, then it’s probably incorrect. Similarly, with respect to our evaluations of
but also within single translations of the Ethics. This fact draws our attention agents, it’s consonant with Aristotle to advise that one vote for the most kalos
to two problems facing an investigation of the concept of kalon in Aristot- politician, but this certainly isn’t equivalent to advising someone to vote for
le’s ethics. First, it suggests that we have no English word that corresponds the most beautiful politician.
isomorphically with the term kalon. As English-readers of Aristotle, we need, Another debate is whether we should read the term kalon as equiv-
instead, an arsenal of terms to capture the nuanced features of its evidently ocal (or homonymous). There is some suggestion in the Topics that Aristotle
complex Greek connotation. Of course, this is a common problem facing thinks it is a homonym (Top. 106a20–22). And here, it is not clear what the
translators; isomorphic translations are perhaps more the exception than the implications of this would be for his Ethics (e.g., whether we could draw the
norm. However, a peculiar problem arises in this case because the concept it conclusion that he is using it equivocally between moral and aesthetic con-
is supposed to express is patently central to Aristotle’s Ethics, and yet we lack texts). This also raises the question of whether the term kalon is what some
not only a single word in English that corresponds to the Greek term, but it scholars call “pros hen equivocal”—that is, a term with several, but interrelated
might also very well be a native concept of the attribute kalon itself. From a senses. Still another debate concerns whether kalon is a parochial concept—
cursory survey of the above list of candidate translations, it isn’t at all clear that is, one that reflects only a particular view of beauty endemic to Aristotle
why the meanings associated with this list of English words should hang to- and his aristocratic ilk in ancient Athens. In that case, the concept of kalon
gether as expressing a single attribute familiar to English language users. would be of merely historical interest; it would have little or nothing to teach
The second problem facing translators is the diversity of contexts us about ethics today.
in which Aristotle employs the term kalon. As it turns out, one reason for In this paper, I have two goals. First, I wish to navigate some of the
above difficulties and present an interpretation of the meaning of kalon in
For general discussions, cf. Joseph Owens, “The Kalon in the Aristotelian
1
Aristotle, on which the term is not only relatively unified in its meaning, but
Ethics,” in Studies in Aristotle, ed. D.J. O’Meara (Washington, DC: Catholic University on which it also expresses nearly the same concept as our word beautiful
of America Press, 1981), 261–77; Kelly Rogers, “Aristotle’s Concept of To Kalon,” does. Second, on the basis of this characterization, I wish to show the im-
Ancient Philosophy 13 (1993): 355–71; Gabriel Richardson Lear, “Aristotle on Moral portance and application of this concept for three facets of Aristotle’s Ethics:
Virtue and the Fine,” in The Blackwell Guide to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, ed. Richard
Kraut (Oxford: Blackwell, 2006), 116–36.
2
Cf. Terence Irwin, “The Sense and Reference of Kalon in Aristotle,” Classical
© Brian Donohue, Quaestiones Disputatae, Vol. 6, No. 2 (Spring 2016)
Philology 105, no. 4 (2010): 381–96.
28 Beauty and Motivation in Aristotle Brian Donohue 29
first, Aristotle’s claim that what is kalon is an object of choice for the virtuous “works” or “functions” of a thing (cf. NE 1097b22–31). The thought, then,
agent; second, how what is kalon in action is grounded in the ordered soul seems to be that what is kalon works like a formal cause (cf. Phys. 194b27–29)
(i.e., the soul that enjoys internal harmony among its components); third, that makes a thing to be ordered, proportionate, and definite. In that case,
Aristotle’s descriptions of God’s contemplative activity as kalon. I take each the passage from Metaphysics 13 would imply that the mathematical sciences
of these three aspects to highlight the significance of the kalon for Aristotle’s demonstrate things about order, proportion, and definiteness—all of which
Ethics, and in particular the sense in which a thing’s being kalon will serve to are characteristics that kalon instills in objects. This is the function or work of
motivate human beings to exercise the virtues, which (recall) is Aristotle’s kalon; it is what the kalon “does.”
very definition of happiness (NE 1098a15–17). In passages from Poetics (1450b34–37) and Politics (1326a33), Aristo-
tle suggests that an object’s magnitude or size might have something to do
with its being kalon. He explains at the same places, however, that this is a
II. Characterizing Kalon function of the properties of order, proportion, and definiteness. He writes:
to be kalon, a living creature, and every whole made up of parts,
My first task is to provide a characterization of Aristotle’s concept of kalon. must not only present a certain order in its arrangement of parts,
In this section, I consider five contexts in which the concept appears prom- but also be of a certain definite magnitude. Kalon is a matter of
inently. size and order, and therefore impossible either in a very minute
creature…or in a creature of vast size. (Poet. 1450b34–37, Bywa-
ter translation)
A. Order, proportion, and definiteness
There are two thoughts here. First, a thing’s being kalon depends upon some
In the latter books of the Metaphysics, Aristotle is investigating the nature degree of internal order and proportion of its parts with respect to the
of mathematical objects and mathematical sciences. In 13.3 (1078a31–b6), whole. To lack this order or proportion is to be somehow distorted, and thus
Aristotle offers a distinction between “good” (agathon) and kalon: whereas the not kalon. Second, there is a perceptual component to Aristotle’s account.
former appears only in action (en praxei), where action is understood as a spe- Obviously, the vastness or minuteness of a thing is relative to the perceiver.
cies of movement (kinesis), the latter can be found in things without move- But I think the point is that we perceivers cannot judge a thing to be kalon if
ment (en tois akinetois), such as numbers and geometrical figures. On the basis we cannot discern whether it bears the properties of order, proportion, or
of this distinction, Aristotle makes the argument that mathematical sciences definiteness, and this hinges on magnitude.
have something to say about what is kalon, because they offer proofs about To these two points, we can add a third. In Aristotle’s thought, the
the “attributes” that we also ascribe in a preeminent degree to the form or formal cause of a natural object seems inextricably tied to its final cause; for
idea (eide) of the kalon: order (taxis), proportion (summetria), and definiteness natural objects, the “what something is” is tied to “what it is for,” not only
(horismenon). In ascribing these to the form of kalon, we might take Aristotle because its form sets that thing upon a trajectory toward that goal, but more
as thinking of these as “essential properties” of kalon.3 However, Aristotle’s importantly because the goal itself is identified with the fully actualized form
discussion here implies that order, proportion, and definiteness are not only in question. For example, when a human being is generated, it is set upon a
attributes of these objects, essential or otherwise, but also causes or expla- trajectory to develop into a full human being. Thus, with respect to its nature, a
nations (aitia) of phenomena. Because mathematical sciences are concerned human being’s final cause is simply to mature into a fully actualized version
with order and definiteness, and order and definiteness are causes of many of the form it bears (see Meta. 1032a11–25).4 From this relationship between
things, these sciences must also treat of kalon as a cause “in some sense” (ai- formal and final causes, we can draw the lesson that the orientation of a
tian ten hos). Perhaps these two notions associated with kalon in this passage— thing’s parts toward composing the whole is both formal and teleological.
attribute and cause—can be brought closer together if we note that what
Ross translates as “attributes” is, in fact, the Greek word erga—that is, the
4
Two comments. First, this connection seems to some degree extricable in
the case of objects produced from human ingenuity rather than natural processes.
Second, a human being also has happiness as a goal, but this is a goal relative to
3
Gabriel Richardson Lear dubs them “formal properties” of kalon, see Lear, human actions and passions, not natural generative processes. This is why attaining
“Aristotle on Moral Virtue and the Fine.” happiness is a matter of “second nature” for Aristotle (NE 1103a14–25).
28 Beauty and Motivation in Aristotle Brian Donohue 29
first, Aristotle’s claim that what is kalon is an object of choice for the virtuous “works” or “functions” of a thing (cf. NE 1097b22–31). The thought, then,
agent; second, how what is kalon in action is grounded in the ordered soul seems to be that what is kalon works like a formal cause (cf. Phys. 194b27–29)
(i.e., the soul that enjoys internal harmony among its components); third, that makes a thing to be ordered, proportionate, and definite. In that case,
Aristotle’s descriptions of God’s contemplative activity as kalon. I take each the passage from Metaphysics 13 would imply that the mathematical sciences
of these three aspects to highlight the significance of the kalon for Aristotle’s demonstrate things about order, proportion, and definiteness—all of which
Ethics, and in particular the sense in which a thing’s being kalon will serve to are characteristics that kalon instills in objects. This is the function or work of
motivate human beings to exercise the virtues, which (recall) is Aristotle’s kalon; it is what the kalon “does.”
very definition of happiness (NE 1098a15–17). In passages from Poetics (1450b34–37) and Politics (1326a33), Aristo-
tle suggests that an object’s magnitude or size might have something to do
with its being kalon. He explains at the same places, however, that this is a
II. Characterizing Kalon function of the properties of order, proportion, and definiteness. He writes:
to be kalon, a living creature, and every whole made up of parts,
My first task is to provide a characterization of Aristotle’s concept of kalon. must not only present a certain order in its arrangement of parts,
In this section, I consider five contexts in which the concept appears prom- but also be of a certain definite magnitude. Kalon is a matter of
inently. size and order, and therefore impossible either in a very minute
creature…or in a creature of vast size. (Poet. 1450b34–37, Bywa-
ter translation)
A. Order, proportion, and definiteness
There are two thoughts here. First, a thing’s being kalon depends upon some
In the latter books of the Metaphysics, Aristotle is investigating the nature degree of internal order and proportion of its parts with respect to the
of mathematical objects and mathematical sciences. In 13.3 (1078a31–b6), whole. To lack this order or proportion is to be somehow distorted, and thus
Aristotle offers a distinction between “good” (agathon) and kalon: whereas the not kalon. Second, there is a perceptual component to Aristotle’s account.
former appears only in action (en praxei), where action is understood as a spe- Obviously, the vastness or minuteness of a thing is relative to the perceiver.
cies of movement (kinesis), the latter can be found in things without move- But I think the point is that we perceivers cannot judge a thing to be kalon if
ment (en tois akinetois), such as numbers and geometrical figures. On the basis we cannot discern whether it bears the properties of order, proportion, or
of this distinction, Aristotle makes the argument that mathematical sciences definiteness, and this hinges on magnitude.
have something to say about what is kalon, because they offer proofs about To these two points, we can add a third. In Aristotle’s thought, the
the “attributes” that we also ascribe in a preeminent degree to the form or formal cause of a natural object seems inextricably tied to its final cause; for
idea (eide) of the kalon: order (taxis), proportion (summetria), and definiteness natural objects, the “what something is” is tied to “what it is for,” not only
(horismenon). In ascribing these to the form of kalon, we might take Aristotle because its form sets that thing upon a trajectory toward that goal, but more
as thinking of these as “essential properties” of kalon.3 However, Aristotle’s importantly because the goal itself is identified with the fully actualized form
discussion here implies that order, proportion, and definiteness are not only in question. For example, when a human being is generated, it is set upon a
attributes of these objects, essential or otherwise, but also causes or expla- trajectory to develop into a full human being. Thus, with respect to its nature, a
nations (aitia) of phenomena. Because mathematical sciences are concerned human being’s final cause is simply to mature into a fully actualized version
with order and definiteness, and order and definiteness are causes of many of the form it bears (see Meta. 1032a11–25).4 From this relationship between
things, these sciences must also treat of kalon as a cause “in some sense” (ai- formal and final causes, we can draw the lesson that the orientation of a
tian ten hos). Perhaps these two notions associated with kalon in this passage— thing’s parts toward composing the whole is both formal and teleological.
attribute and cause—can be brought closer together if we note that what
Ross translates as “attributes” is, in fact, the Greek word erga—that is, the
4
Two comments. First, this connection seems to some degree extricable in
the case of objects produced from human ingenuity rather than natural processes.
Second, a human being also has happiness as a goal, but this is a goal relative to
3
Gabriel Richardson Lear dubs them “formal properties” of kalon, see Lear, human actions and passions, not natural generative processes. This is why attaining
“Aristotle on Moral Virtue and the Fine.” happiness is a matter of “second nature” for Aristotle (NE 1103a14–25).
30 Beauty and Motivation in Aristotle Brian Donohue 31
It seems plausible that this orientation of parts to whole is really just one • In 4.2 (1122a35–1123a18), Aristotle describes the magnif-
factor in a natural object’s orientation toward fully actualizing its form. Thus, icent person’s actions, which are characteristically manifest
it seems that one way a thing can be kalon is to the extent that it actualizes and open to view, as especially kalon. Connected with this
its form-telos.5 This would make sense of why Aristotle can claim in Parts of description is the further thought that these actions inspire
Animals 1.5 (645a4–25) that even the humblest creatures in nature can exhibit admiration and contemplation in those who witness them
kalon insofar as they are ordered to some goal (telos). (1122b16–17).
As I read Aristotle, then, our conceptual competency with (and intel-
ligent application of) the term kalon requires that we make a judgment about • In EN 10.8 (1178a9–1178b7), Aristotle reiterates the thought
a thing’s order or proportion or definiteness. As I hope to show more clearly that the liberal, or just, or courageous person needs external
below, what this order, proportion, or definiteness will look like will differ goods. His reason: “for how else is either he or any of the
from context to context—what makes an action kalon is not what makes others to be recognized?” (1178a34) This suggests that exter-
a person’s appearance kalon, though these attributes can be found in both nal goods are necessary as a means not only to performing
cases. Some authors have also linked these three properties of kalon with virtuous actions themselves, but also to having one’s virtue
other remarks of Aristotle’s that the kalon is linked closely with “the fitting” acknowledged.
(to prepon), although, as Aristotle remarks explicitly the two are not identical This thought that the kalon of a virtuous action has to be public
(Top. 135a12–14). I think this connection is unsurprising given the above ac- might strike us as counterintuitive, or perhaps flatly wrong, given its apparent
count. The judgment that some features of a thing are fitting (or proper, or endorsement of vainglory and egocentrism. Isn’t it true that if you do some-
appropriate) is plausibly linked with its order, proportion, and definiteness, thing virtuous you shouldn’t go blowing a trumpet before you? How could
just as one might judge that features are unfitting because they are disarrayed, that be an important part of virtue?
disproportionate, and ill-defined. But I have no more to say on this connec- This is a legitimate worry. But I think, properly understood, this is
tion in the confines of this discussion. not as objectionable a feature of kalon as it might sound at first hearing.
Consider a few simple cases. Suppose that, after the painting of the ceiling
of the Sistine Chapel, the chapel was closed off, such that no one was per-
B. Praiseworthiness and publicity mitted to contemplate, or even admire, Michelangelo’s work. Or suppose that
the heroism of Maximilian Kolbe, who laid down his life to save a stranger
Aristotle suggests in a few places that what is kalon must be open to public and fellow prisoner in Auschwitz, went forever unknown. What would we
view. In other words, there is a phenomenal, even “showy,” aspect to kalon. be inclined to judge in such cases? While undoubtedly Kolbe’s action was
We saw this point already in the passage from Poetics above. In Nicomachean heroic independently of its being acknowledged by anybody, there is also
Ethics also, Aristotle makes a few remarks to this same effect: some sense in judging that something would be lacking were the heroism of
Kolbe, or the ceiling of the Sistine Chapel, to go unnoticed. The common
• In 2.9 (1109b14–26), he claims that the difficulty of hitting the feature seems to be this, that what is kalon is such that it ought to receive the
intermediate in action is a reason (though not a sufficient rea- praise and admiration that is deserves; it is worthy of the praise it receives.
son) to count an action as kalon. Because this kind of action This is compatible with judging that an agent ought not to be motivated by
is difficult, one who achieves the action has accomplished the prospect of praise and admiration. If that is true, then Aristotle shouldn’t
something noteworthy—something that makes him the talk be read as claiming that the virtuous agent acts merely for the sake of receiving
of the town. praise; rather, he should be read as claiming that because a virtuous action is
kalon, it is the kind of action that comes into view, and which is and should be
acknowledged as praiseworthy. This is, in fact, very nearly the definition of
kalon Aristotle gives in Rhetoric 1.9 (1366a33–35): what is kalon is desirable for
5
Cf. Irwin, “Sense and Reference”; Lear, “Aristotle on Moral Virtue”; also,
its own sake (i.e., not for the sake of honor or praise or external recognition
Lear, Happy Lives and the Highest Good: An Essay on Aristotle’s “Nicomachean Ethics”
(Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press).
30 Beauty and Motivation in Aristotle Brian Donohue 31
It seems plausible that this orientation of parts to whole is really just one • In 4.2 (1122a35–1123a18), Aristotle describes the magnif-
factor in a natural object’s orientation toward fully actualizing its form. Thus, icent person’s actions, which are characteristically manifest
it seems that one way a thing can be kalon is to the extent that it actualizes and open to view, as especially kalon. Connected with this
its form-telos.5 This would make sense of why Aristotle can claim in Parts of description is the further thought that these actions inspire
Animals 1.5 (645a4–25) that even the humblest creatures in nature can exhibit admiration and contemplation in those who witness them
kalon insofar as they are ordered to some goal (telos). (1122b16–17).
As I read Aristotle, then, our conceptual competency with (and intel-
ligent application of) the term kalon requires that we make a judgment about • In EN 10.8 (1178a9–1178b7), Aristotle reiterates the thought
a thing’s order or proportion or definiteness. As I hope to show more clearly that the liberal, or just, or courageous person needs external
below, what this order, proportion, or definiteness will look like will differ goods. His reason: “for how else is either he or any of the
from context to context—what makes an action kalon is not what makes others to be recognized?” (1178a34) This suggests that exter-
a person’s appearance kalon, though these attributes can be found in both nal goods are necessary as a means not only to performing
cases. Some authors have also linked these three properties of kalon with virtuous actions themselves, but also to having one’s virtue
other remarks of Aristotle’s that the kalon is linked closely with “the fitting” acknowledged.
(to prepon), although, as Aristotle remarks explicitly the two are not identical This thought that the kalon of a virtuous action has to be public
(Top. 135a12–14). I think this connection is unsurprising given the above ac- might strike us as counterintuitive, or perhaps flatly wrong, given its apparent
count. The judgment that some features of a thing are fitting (or proper, or endorsement of vainglory and egocentrism. Isn’t it true that if you do some-
appropriate) is plausibly linked with its order, proportion, and definiteness, thing virtuous you shouldn’t go blowing a trumpet before you? How could
just as one might judge that features are unfitting because they are disarrayed, that be an important part of virtue?
disproportionate, and ill-defined. But I have no more to say on this connec- This is a legitimate worry. But I think, properly understood, this is
tion in the confines of this discussion. not as objectionable a feature of kalon as it might sound at first hearing.
Consider a few simple cases. Suppose that, after the painting of the ceiling
of the Sistine Chapel, the chapel was closed off, such that no one was per-
B. Praiseworthiness and publicity mitted to contemplate, or even admire, Michelangelo’s work. Or suppose that
the heroism of Maximilian Kolbe, who laid down his life to save a stranger
Aristotle suggests in a few places that what is kalon must be open to public and fellow prisoner in Auschwitz, went forever unknown. What would we
view. In other words, there is a phenomenal, even “showy,” aspect to kalon. be inclined to judge in such cases? While undoubtedly Kolbe’s action was
We saw this point already in the passage from Poetics above. In Nicomachean heroic independently of its being acknowledged by anybody, there is also
Ethics also, Aristotle makes a few remarks to this same effect: some sense in judging that something would be lacking were the heroism of
Kolbe, or the ceiling of the Sistine Chapel, to go unnoticed. The common
• In 2.9 (1109b14–26), he claims that the difficulty of hitting the feature seems to be this, that what is kalon is such that it ought to receive the
intermediate in action is a reason (though not a sufficient rea- praise and admiration that is deserves; it is worthy of the praise it receives.
son) to count an action as kalon. Because this kind of action This is compatible with judging that an agent ought not to be motivated by
is difficult, one who achieves the action has accomplished the prospect of praise and admiration. If that is true, then Aristotle shouldn’t
something noteworthy—something that makes him the talk be read as claiming that the virtuous agent acts merely for the sake of receiving
of the town. praise; rather, he should be read as claiming that because a virtuous action is
kalon, it is the kind of action that comes into view, and which is and should be
acknowledged as praiseworthy. This is, in fact, very nearly the definition of
kalon Aristotle gives in Rhetoric 1.9 (1366a33–35): what is kalon is desirable for
5
Cf. Irwin, “Sense and Reference”; Lear, “Aristotle on Moral Virtue”; also,
its own sake (i.e., not for the sake of honor or praise or external recognition
Lear, Happy Lives and the Highest Good: An Essay on Aristotle’s “Nicomachean Ethics”
(Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press).
32 Beauty and Motivation in Aristotle Brian Donohue 33
or any instrumental good), and worthy of praise, and pleasant because of its and quality of pleasure will correspond in these cases with the degree of
goodness.6 excellence (kratiston, kalliston) found in the object of cognition. This would
explain why Aristotle takes thinking and contemplation (dianoian kai theorian)
to be more pleasant and complete, namely, because the excellence found in
C. Pleasure the objects of thought and contemplation is greater than that found in the
objects of sense-perception.
This last point draws our attention to another feature of Aristotle’s concept I now wish to bring these considerations about pleasure together
of kalon: its connection with pleasure in the one who perceives kalon. Now with earlier considerations about which qualities are characteristic of kalon.
Aristotle is no hedonist. Early in Nicomachean Ethics (1095b14–22) he rejects Above, I argued that we should interpret Aristotle as holding that what is
hedonism, or acting for the sake of the pleasant experience one expects to kalon exemplifies some order, proportion, and definiteness. Thus, the quality
result from his action. He even remarks that the motive of pleasure is the of being kalon appears to be something discernible by our cognitive faculties:
principal cause of leading people astray from virtue (NE 1113a34–1113b1). some instances of these attributes we would apprehend through sense-per-
At the same time, Aristotle does not divorce pleasure or enjoyment from the ception; others through thought; still others through contemplation. But this
attainment of the highest good. While acting for the sake of pleasure is not would mean that our cognitive interaction with some kalon object would pre-
virtuous, pleasure will accompany virtuous activity. cede the kind of pleasure that, Aristotle claims, follows upon its heels. In fact,
How, then, is kalon tied to pleasure? I think there is an important I propose that this is what is being suggested in the final component in the
contemplative aspect to Aristotle’s answer. Pleasure and enjoyment arise in a above definition of kalon from Rhetoric: what is kalon is desirable for its own
perceiver from contemplating the well-ordered features of a person, or a sake, and worthy of praise, and pleasant because of its goodness. That is to say,
soul, or an action, or a drama, or a piece of music. if what is kalon has the properties we have supposed it to have (its exemplifi-
Where does Aristotle suggest that there is a contemplative dimen- cation of order, proportion, definiteness, and perhaps fittingness), and if all
sion to the pleasure that arises from kalon? In the first place, Aristotle seems these properties are connected with what is kalon being good (in some sense
to think that pleasure arises in conjunction with certain psychological states of “good”), then the pleasantness of kalon should arise immediately from
(what later his scholastic commentators would call apprehensio). In one of the apprehending those features in the object judged to be kalon.
clearest passages on this issue, Aristotle comments, “there is pleasure in all This schematic interpretation, if correct, would elucidate a puzzling
sense-perception, and likewise in thought and contemplation [dianoian kai passage linking kalon to pleasure from Nicomachean Ethics—namely, the de-
theorian] (which is most complete and pleasantest).… Pleasure completes the scription of the august agent’s self-sacrificial death as immensely pleasant
activity, not as a preexisting state [hexis] does, but as something complete [ti (NE 1169a20–25; cf. NE 1115a26–34; 1117a33–1117b13). However noble
telos] arising after the fact, as a season comes to full bloom. So long as the or beautiful his sacrifice may be, it’s far from obvious why the death should
object of thought [noeton] and sense-perception [aistheton] (together with the be intensely pleasant. One would think that if it were as pleasant as Aris-
judging and contemplative faculties) are as they should be, pleasure will be totle seems to think it is, then it would hardly count as a sacrifice. But if
found in the activity,” (NE 1174b14–1175a1, my translation). the above interpretation of the relationship between pleasure, kalon, and our
Aristotle’s point seems to be that pleasure will spontaneously ac- cognitive faculties is more or less correct, then we can resolve some of the
company the activation of a cognitive faculty, whether sense-perception or initial strangeness in the passage. What does the self-sacrificial agent expe-
thinking or contemplation. This is apparently a mere observation on his part; rience as pleasurable? Certainly not the death itself. Instead, I propose, he
he does not at this point offer an explanation of why pleasure should so arise apprehends ahead of time the grandness and beauty of the sacrificial action,
in tandem with activity. Further, he seems to be suggesting that the degree together with the course of actions leading up to it, and experiences pleasure
upon cognizing it. The passage implies that he considers this explicitly: upon
6
Anton Ford also discusses this issue, see Ford, “Response to Irwin,” Classical weighing a short life marked by the kalon against a long, mundane life, he
Philology 105, no. 4 (2010): 396–402. However, Ford (mistakenly, in my view) defines
praise as “speech expressing the greatness of someone else’s virtue,” and so arrives
at the conclusion that acting for the sake of the kalon is tantamount to “acting with
an eye to honor and esteem.”
32 Beauty and Motivation in Aristotle Brian Donohue 33
or any instrumental good), and worthy of praise, and pleasant because of its and quality of pleasure will correspond in these cases with the degree of
goodness.6 excellence (kratiston, kalliston) found in the object of cognition. This would
explain why Aristotle takes thinking and contemplation (dianoian kai theorian)
to be more pleasant and complete, namely, because the excellence found in
C. Pleasure the objects of thought and contemplation is greater than that found in the
objects of sense-perception.
This last point draws our attention to another feature of Aristotle’s concept I now wish to bring these considerations about pleasure together
of kalon: its connection with pleasure in the one who perceives kalon. Now with earlier considerations about which qualities are characteristic of kalon.
Aristotle is no hedonist. Early in Nicomachean Ethics (1095b14–22) he rejects Above, I argued that we should interpret Aristotle as holding that what is
hedonism, or acting for the sake of the pleasant experience one expects to kalon exemplifies some order, proportion, and definiteness. Thus, the quality
result from his action. He even remarks that the motive of pleasure is the of being kalon appears to be something discernible by our cognitive faculties:
principal cause of leading people astray from virtue (NE 1113a34–1113b1). some instances of these attributes we would apprehend through sense-per-
At the same time, Aristotle does not divorce pleasure or enjoyment from the ception; others through thought; still others through contemplation. But this
attainment of the highest good. While acting for the sake of pleasure is not would mean that our cognitive interaction with some kalon object would pre-
virtuous, pleasure will accompany virtuous activity. cede the kind of pleasure that, Aristotle claims, follows upon its heels. In fact,
How, then, is kalon tied to pleasure? I think there is an important I propose that this is what is being suggested in the final component in the
contemplative aspect to Aristotle’s answer. Pleasure and enjoyment arise in a above definition of kalon from Rhetoric: what is kalon is desirable for its own
perceiver from contemplating the well-ordered features of a person, or a sake, and worthy of praise, and pleasant because of its goodness. That is to say,
soul, or an action, or a drama, or a piece of music. if what is kalon has the properties we have supposed it to have (its exemplifi-
Where does Aristotle suggest that there is a contemplative dimen- cation of order, proportion, definiteness, and perhaps fittingness), and if all
sion to the pleasure that arises from kalon? In the first place, Aristotle seems these properties are connected with what is kalon being good (in some sense
to think that pleasure arises in conjunction with certain psychological states of “good”), then the pleasantness of kalon should arise immediately from
(what later his scholastic commentators would call apprehensio). In one of the apprehending those features in the object judged to be kalon.
clearest passages on this issue, Aristotle comments, “there is pleasure in all This schematic interpretation, if correct, would elucidate a puzzling
sense-perception, and likewise in thought and contemplation [dianoian kai passage linking kalon to pleasure from Nicomachean Ethics—namely, the de-
theorian] (which is most complete and pleasantest).… Pleasure completes the scription of the august agent’s self-sacrificial death as immensely pleasant
activity, not as a preexisting state [hexis] does, but as something complete [ti (NE 1169a20–25; cf. NE 1115a26–34; 1117a33–1117b13). However noble
telos] arising after the fact, as a season comes to full bloom. So long as the or beautiful his sacrifice may be, it’s far from obvious why the death should
object of thought [noeton] and sense-perception [aistheton] (together with the be intensely pleasant. One would think that if it were as pleasant as Aris-
judging and contemplative faculties) are as they should be, pleasure will be totle seems to think it is, then it would hardly count as a sacrifice. But if
found in the activity,” (NE 1174b14–1175a1, my translation). the above interpretation of the relationship between pleasure, kalon, and our
Aristotle’s point seems to be that pleasure will spontaneously ac- cognitive faculties is more or less correct, then we can resolve some of the
company the activation of a cognitive faculty, whether sense-perception or initial strangeness in the passage. What does the self-sacrificial agent expe-
thinking or contemplation. This is apparently a mere observation on his part; rience as pleasurable? Certainly not the death itself. Instead, I propose, he
he does not at this point offer an explanation of why pleasure should so arise apprehends ahead of time the grandness and beauty of the sacrificial action,
in tandem with activity. Further, he seems to be suggesting that the degree together with the course of actions leading up to it, and experiences pleasure
upon cognizing it. The passage implies that he considers this explicitly: upon
6
Anton Ford also discusses this issue, see Ford, “Response to Irwin,” Classical weighing a short life marked by the kalon against a long, mundane life, he
Philology 105, no. 4 (2010): 396–402. However, Ford (mistakenly, in my view) defines
praise as “speech expressing the greatness of someone else’s virtue,” and so arrives
at the conclusion that acting for the sake of the kalon is tantamount to “acting with
an eye to honor and esteem.”
34 Beauty and Motivation in Aristotle Brian Donohue 35
chooses the kalon—the cognition of which produces exorbitant pleasure in this paper, I will make two remarks upon it. First, there is little to suggest
him.7 that in ascribing kalon to an action, Aristotle means to ascribe a property in
Much more could be said about Aristotle’s account of pleasure, but virtue of which we have an obligation (moral or otherwise) to perform that
I will close this section with a final observation. In Nicomachean Ethics 3.4 action. Irwin’s main argument for identifying kalon in certain contexts with a
(1113a23–33), Aristotle suggests that not everyone discerns correctly what property of moral rightness or obligatoriness is that the kalon quality in such
is kalon in action. In fact, Aristotle tends to think that the majority of people contexts is deemed praiseworthy.11 But there are passages in which Aristotle
will not pursue what is genuinely good or beautiful (cf. NE 1095b14–16). suggests that a kalon thing is worthy of praise outside of specifically moral
Hence the need to measure the actions of most people against the conduct contexts, e.g., the passage from the Rhetoric mentioned above (1366a33–35).
of the august man, who serves as “norm and measure,” precisely because he Does kalon in moral contexts, then, merit a peculiarly moral kind of praise?
perceives correctly that which is beautiful and good. How does the august Perhaps, but Aristotle nowhere says this.
man come to see the truth? While there is some debate on this issue, Aris- Second, the relationship between kalon and goodness in general is
totle seems to suggest that prior habituation into virtue is what enables him not altogether clear. Throughout the Eudemian Ethics, Aristotle links goodness
to discern kalon with accuracy (NE 1103b20–26; 1144a20–36).8 The thought with kalon in the phrase: kalokagathia or “beauty-and-goodness.” This phrase
is that vicious habits blind an agent to what is genuinely good and beautiful, reflects Aristotle’s commitment that there are other non-kalon goods, but also
whereas virtuous habits attune an agent to the good and beautiful. In light of a kind of goodness that comes with being kalon. In other passages, howev-
these considerations, my final observation regarding pleasure is that Aristotle er, Aristotle draws some important distinctions between kalon and goodness
seems to hold the view that whether one will take pleasure in the kalon is (agathon). Recall that in Metaphysics 13.3 (1078a31–32), Aristotle suggests that
determined in large part by one’s moral education. good (agathon) is different from kalon, because goodness (in his sense) always
pertains to action (praxis), a species of movement (kinesis), whereas kalon can
exist in things that have no movement (akinetois)—for example, mathematical
D. Goodness and moral rightness objects. These considerations should give us pause in identifying kalon with
goodness, particularly with what we might today call “moral goodness” or
How does kalon stand with respect to what we might call an action’s “moral “moral value.” Presumably, Aristotle does not mean that triangles are morally
rightness”? The question is a sizable one. There are numerous commentators valuable, and yet they are kalon. Our task, then, is to explain how a thing’s
who insist that Aristotle does not have the concepts of moral obligation, or being kalon nonetheless carries great significance for his ethics.12
of a peculiarly moral sense of “ought,” or of peculiarly moral values.9 Ter-
ence Irwin has argued to the contrary that Aristotle both has a conception 11
In Irwin’s view, it makes sense to claim that we have a moral obligation to
of morality akin to ours and that, in ethical contexts, the word kalon picks develop or practice virtue. Thus, someone receives praise if he has fulfilled his moral
out the property of moral rightness or moral obligatoriness in an action.10 obligation to be virtuous. One should note, however, that he takes the fulfillment
While entering more fully into this debate would fall outside the scope of of moral obligation as sufficient (though not necessary) for praiseworthiness, thus
leaving room for praiseworthy supererogatory actions. By contrast, in my view, ap-
propriate praise is not a response to one having fulfilled a moral obligation, but a re-
7
For similar discussions, cf. Jonathan Sanford, “Are You Man Enough? Aris- sponse to a display of good human action (or of the kalon in action), and the notion
totle and Courage,” International Philosophical Quarterly 50, no. 4 (2010): 431–45. of obligation simply does not figure into his account.
8
Cf. Jessica Moss, “Virtue Makes the Goal Right: Virtue and Phronesis in Ar- 12
For another view on the relationship between goodness and kalon in Aristo-
istotle’s Ethics,” Phronesis 56, no. 3 (2011): 204–61. tle, cf. Aryeh Kosman, “Beauty and the Good: Situating the Kalon,” Classical Philology
9
Cf. G.E.M. Anscombe, “Modern Moral Philosophy,” Philosophy 33, no. 124 105, no. 4 (2010): 341–62. One should not conclude immediately from the above dis-
(1958): 1–19. tinction that the kalon has nothing to do with the agathon. Rather, Aristotle seems to
10
Cf. Julia Annas, The Morality of Happiness (New York: Oxford University think that all good actions are kalon, but not all kalon things are good (because not all
Press, 1993), 120–34; Irwin, “Sense and Reference”; Terence Irwin, From Socrates to kalon things are actions). This suggests that the kalon in action might nonetheless be
the Reformation, vol. 1 of The Development of Ethics: A Hsitorical and Critical Study (New intimately bound up with the moral life, if by “moral” or “ethical” one means (as Ar-
York: Oxford University Press, 2007); Terence Irwin, “Aristotle’s Conception of Mo- istotle does) “pertaining to one’s actions and passions, and thus to one’s habits (ethos)
rality,” in Proceedings from the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy, ed. John J. with a view to performing one’s function (ergon).” All that is not to say, however, that
Cleary (Langham, MD: University Press of America, 1986), 1:115–34. he thereby conceives of kalon actions as coextensive with morally obligatory actions,
34 Beauty and Motivation in Aristotle Brian Donohue 35
chooses the kalon—the cognition of which produces exorbitant pleasure in this paper, I will make two remarks upon it. First, there is little to suggest
him.7 that in ascribing kalon to an action, Aristotle means to ascribe a property in
Much more could be said about Aristotle’s account of pleasure, but virtue of which we have an obligation (moral or otherwise) to perform that
I will close this section with a final observation. In Nicomachean Ethics 3.4 action. Irwin’s main argument for identifying kalon in certain contexts with a
(1113a23–33), Aristotle suggests that not everyone discerns correctly what property of moral rightness or obligatoriness is that the kalon quality in such
is kalon in action. In fact, Aristotle tends to think that the majority of people contexts is deemed praiseworthy.11 But there are passages in which Aristotle
will not pursue what is genuinely good or beautiful (cf. NE 1095b14–16). suggests that a kalon thing is worthy of praise outside of specifically moral
Hence the need to measure the actions of most people against the conduct contexts, e.g., the passage from the Rhetoric mentioned above (1366a33–35).
of the august man, who serves as “norm and measure,” precisely because he Does kalon in moral contexts, then, merit a peculiarly moral kind of praise?
perceives correctly that which is beautiful and good. How does the august Perhaps, but Aristotle nowhere says this.
man come to see the truth? While there is some debate on this issue, Aris- Second, the relationship between kalon and goodness in general is
totle seems to suggest that prior habituation into virtue is what enables him not altogether clear. Throughout the Eudemian Ethics, Aristotle links goodness
to discern kalon with accuracy (NE 1103b20–26; 1144a20–36).8 The thought with kalon in the phrase: kalokagathia or “beauty-and-goodness.” This phrase
is that vicious habits blind an agent to what is genuinely good and beautiful, reflects Aristotle’s commitment that there are other non-kalon goods, but also
whereas virtuous habits attune an agent to the good and beautiful. In light of a kind of goodness that comes with being kalon. In other passages, howev-
these considerations, my final observation regarding pleasure is that Aristotle er, Aristotle draws some important distinctions between kalon and goodness
seems to hold the view that whether one will take pleasure in the kalon is (agathon). Recall that in Metaphysics 13.3 (1078a31–32), Aristotle suggests that
determined in large part by one’s moral education. good (agathon) is different from kalon, because goodness (in his sense) always
pertains to action (praxis), a species of movement (kinesis), whereas kalon can
exist in things that have no movement (akinetois)—for example, mathematical
D. Goodness and moral rightness objects. These considerations should give us pause in identifying kalon with
goodness, particularly with what we might today call “moral goodness” or
How does kalon stand with respect to what we might call an action’s “moral “moral value.” Presumably, Aristotle does not mean that triangles are morally
rightness”? The question is a sizable one. There are numerous commentators valuable, and yet they are kalon. Our task, then, is to explain how a thing’s
who insist that Aristotle does not have the concepts of moral obligation, or being kalon nonetheless carries great significance for his ethics.12
of a peculiarly moral sense of “ought,” or of peculiarly moral values.9 Ter-
ence Irwin has argued to the contrary that Aristotle both has a conception 11
In Irwin’s view, it makes sense to claim that we have a moral obligation to
of morality akin to ours and that, in ethical contexts, the word kalon picks develop or practice virtue. Thus, someone receives praise if he has fulfilled his moral
out the property of moral rightness or moral obligatoriness in an action.10 obligation to be virtuous. One should note, however, that he takes the fulfillment
While entering more fully into this debate would fall outside the scope of of moral obligation as sufficient (though not necessary) for praiseworthiness, thus
leaving room for praiseworthy supererogatory actions. By contrast, in my view, ap-
propriate praise is not a response to one having fulfilled a moral obligation, but a re-
7
For similar discussions, cf. Jonathan Sanford, “Are You Man Enough? Aris- sponse to a display of good human action (or of the kalon in action), and the notion
totle and Courage,” International Philosophical Quarterly 50, no. 4 (2010): 431–45. of obligation simply does not figure into his account.
8
Cf. Jessica Moss, “Virtue Makes the Goal Right: Virtue and Phronesis in Ar- 12
For another view on the relationship between goodness and kalon in Aristo-
istotle’s Ethics,” Phronesis 56, no. 3 (2011): 204–61. tle, cf. Aryeh Kosman, “Beauty and the Good: Situating the Kalon,” Classical Philology
9
Cf. G.E.M. Anscombe, “Modern Moral Philosophy,” Philosophy 33, no. 124 105, no. 4 (2010): 341–62. One should not conclude immediately from the above dis-
(1958): 1–19. tinction that the kalon has nothing to do with the agathon. Rather, Aristotle seems to
10
Cf. Julia Annas, The Morality of Happiness (New York: Oxford University think that all good actions are kalon, but not all kalon things are good (because not all
Press, 1993), 120–34; Irwin, “Sense and Reference”; Terence Irwin, From Socrates to kalon things are actions). This suggests that the kalon in action might nonetheless be
the Reformation, vol. 1 of The Development of Ethics: A Hsitorical and Critical Study (New intimately bound up with the moral life, if by “moral” or “ethical” one means (as Ar-
York: Oxford University Press, 2007); Terence Irwin, “Aristotle’s Conception of Mo- istotle does) “pertaining to one’s actions and passions, and thus to one’s habits (ethos)
rality,” in Proceedings from the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy, ed. John J. with a view to performing one’s function (ergon).” All that is not to say, however, that
Cleary (Langham, MD: University Press of America, 1986), 1:115–34. he thereby conceives of kalon actions as coextensive with morally obligatory actions,
36 Beauty and Motivation in Aristotle Brian Donohue 37

E. Beauty and the aesthetic of it. Does that imply that Aristotle did not regard beauty as of first-rate
importance to the development and exercise of virtue? I think not.
Finally, there is some question whether the term kalon overlaps with our En- To see why this is so, we should first reconsider the features of kalon
glish word beautiful. Again, it seems correct to say, on Aristotle’s view, that we encountered at the outset of our investigation: order, proportion, and
one should vote for the most kalos politician, but that is surely not to say definiteness. My suggestion is that if these are essential features of the kalon,
that one should vote for the most beautiful one. In a similar vein, there is then they will be found under some guise wherever the kalon is present. At
the worry that if kalon refers always to beauty, then a judgment that an act the same time, these need not be the same sort of order—or proportion or
of courage is kalon is apparently an aesthetic judgment. Considerations like definiteness—in each context wherein the kalon appears. One sort of order
these have led many scholars to two main conclusions: first, that the word or proportion might make a face beautiful, while another sort might make a
kalon, in most contexts, should not be understood as referring to the beauty soul beautiful. The beauty of a face seems to arise from an order, proportion,
of the thing that is kalon; and second, that kalon should not be translated and definiteness among the parts of that face, whereas the beauty of a soul
uniformly as beautiful. Of course, these two conclusions hang together. That would arise from an order, proportion, and definiteness among the parts of
kalon purportedly ought not to be thought in most contexts to refer to beauty that soul. For example, its order might consist in the ordering of rationali-
is the basis for the further claim that translators of kalon ought not to render ty and the passions within the soul; its proportion might consist in having
the word in English as beautiful, but instead by more neutral terms such as the right proportion of passion, which is reflected in one’s aiming at “the
fine, noble, or even the amorphous “good.”13 intermediate” in action; and its definiteness might consist in the fixity of its
Without a doubt, it seems utterly wrongheaded to suggest that the orientation toward the good. The presence of these features would be what
relevant value in an act of courage could be its beauty. As Aryeh Kosman makes a soul possess what Aristotle describes as “ethesin kalos,” or beautiful
puts it, “we do not expect the phronimos [the practically wise person], as a habits (NE 1095b5).
part of his virtue, to ‘walk down Piccadilly with a poppy or a lily’ in his eu- If that is essentially correct, then the critics who have resisted trans-
daimonic hand.”14 Kosman’s main thought seems to me obviously correct: lating kalon as “beautiful” have been relying upon an implicitly univocal
in describing the life of virtue, Aristotle decidedly did not have in mind an reading of the term. This reading is straightforwardly mistaken. In Topics
individual who fashions his life into an object of artistic appreciation. (106a9–21), Aristotle provides kalon as the case of a term that has multiple
However, the inference drawn from this fact is mistaken, namely, senses, and is thus equivocal. In particular, he remarks that although one
that the virtuous agent is not aiming to make his life beautiful. The reason is might apply kalon to both animals15 and houses, the contrary of kalon in each
that these commentators have construed beauty and the aesthetic too nar- case is different: “ugly” (aischron) and “mean” (mochtheron), respectively. At
rowly. They have begun with the paradigm of the art connoisseur, who has the same time, Aristotle cannot mean that the uses of kalon express strictly
an exceptional sensitivity to (modern) art, and concluded that because Ar- equivocal meanings (like the two meanings of our word “bank”). In Nicoma-
istotle does not intend to depict the virtuous agent as such a connoisseur, chean Ethics 4.2 (1122a34–1123a17), Aristotle draws a comparison between
kalon cannot refer to beauty. It is equally uncontroversial that Aristotle had the magnificent man (megaloprepes) and the expert (epistemos) on the basis that
no such concept of an art connoisseur or of art as we moderns might think both perform a work (ergon) that is “great and beautiful” (1122b16, mega kai
kalon). If kalon were strictly equivocal across contexts, this comparison would
be unintelligible. Similarly, in Nicomachean Ethics 9.9, Aristotle draws a close
which is a point of substantive debate between commentators such as Anscombe analogy between the virtuous agent’s relationship to virtuous actions and the
and Irwin. musician’s relationship to beautiful music: “for the august man (insofar as he
13
Some authors have simply embraced the conclusion that Aristotle is en- is august) rejoices in virtuous actions and disapproves of bad ones, just as
dorsing acting for broadly aesthetic reasons. In particular, Chappell argues that acting the musician is pleased with beautiful [kalois] melodies, but is pained by ugly
for the sake of beauty represents a distinct form of practical rationality, which is ones,” (1170a9–11, my translation). This suggests that Aristotle is fully cog-
irreducible to moral or prudential reasons. However, I think that this view both flirts nizant of, and makes use of, the parallel ways in which an action and a piece
with anachronism in ascribing to Aristotle a view about aesthetic value and unduly
of music might both be kalon. Thus, although Aristotle nowhere asserts this
narrows the meaning of kalon to application in contexts wherein roughly speaking an
aesthetic reading seems appropriate.
14
Kosman, “Beauty and the Good,” 342. 15
The Greek term zoon is ambiguous between “animal” and “picture.”
36 Beauty and Motivation in Aristotle Brian Donohue 37

E. Beauty and the aesthetic of it. Does that imply that Aristotle did not regard beauty as of first-rate
importance to the development and exercise of virtue? I think not.
Finally, there is some question whether the term kalon overlaps with our En- To see why this is so, we should first reconsider the features of kalon
glish word beautiful. Again, it seems correct to say, on Aristotle’s view, that we encountered at the outset of our investigation: order, proportion, and
one should vote for the most kalos politician, but that is surely not to say definiteness. My suggestion is that if these are essential features of the kalon,
that one should vote for the most beautiful one. In a similar vein, there is then they will be found under some guise wherever the kalon is present. At
the worry that if kalon refers always to beauty, then a judgment that an act the same time, these need not be the same sort of order—or proportion or
of courage is kalon is apparently an aesthetic judgment. Considerations like definiteness—in each context wherein the kalon appears. One sort of order
these have led many scholars to two main conclusions: first, that the word or proportion might make a face beautiful, while another sort might make a
kalon, in most contexts, should not be understood as referring to the beauty soul beautiful. The beauty of a face seems to arise from an order, proportion,
of the thing that is kalon; and second, that kalon should not be translated and definiteness among the parts of that face, whereas the beauty of a soul
uniformly as beautiful. Of course, these two conclusions hang together. That would arise from an order, proportion, and definiteness among the parts of
kalon purportedly ought not to be thought in most contexts to refer to beauty that soul. For example, its order might consist in the ordering of rationali-
is the basis for the further claim that translators of kalon ought not to render ty and the passions within the soul; its proportion might consist in having
the word in English as beautiful, but instead by more neutral terms such as the right proportion of passion, which is reflected in one’s aiming at “the
fine, noble, or even the amorphous “good.”13 intermediate” in action; and its definiteness might consist in the fixity of its
Without a doubt, it seems utterly wrongheaded to suggest that the orientation toward the good. The presence of these features would be what
relevant value in an act of courage could be its beauty. As Aryeh Kosman makes a soul possess what Aristotle describes as “ethesin kalos,” or beautiful
puts it, “we do not expect the phronimos [the practically wise person], as a habits (NE 1095b5).
part of his virtue, to ‘walk down Piccadilly with a poppy or a lily’ in his eu- If that is essentially correct, then the critics who have resisted trans-
daimonic hand.”14 Kosman’s main thought seems to me obviously correct: lating kalon as “beautiful” have been relying upon an implicitly univocal
in describing the life of virtue, Aristotle decidedly did not have in mind an reading of the term. This reading is straightforwardly mistaken. In Topics
individual who fashions his life into an object of artistic appreciation. (106a9–21), Aristotle provides kalon as the case of a term that has multiple
However, the inference drawn from this fact is mistaken, namely, senses, and is thus equivocal. In particular, he remarks that although one
that the virtuous agent is not aiming to make his life beautiful. The reason is might apply kalon to both animals15 and houses, the contrary of kalon in each
that these commentators have construed beauty and the aesthetic too nar- case is different: “ugly” (aischron) and “mean” (mochtheron), respectively. At
rowly. They have begun with the paradigm of the art connoisseur, who has the same time, Aristotle cannot mean that the uses of kalon express strictly
an exceptional sensitivity to (modern) art, and concluded that because Ar- equivocal meanings (like the two meanings of our word “bank”). In Nicoma-
istotle does not intend to depict the virtuous agent as such a connoisseur, chean Ethics 4.2 (1122a34–1123a17), Aristotle draws a comparison between
kalon cannot refer to beauty. It is equally uncontroversial that Aristotle had the magnificent man (megaloprepes) and the expert (epistemos) on the basis that
no such concept of an art connoisseur or of art as we moderns might think both perform a work (ergon) that is “great and beautiful” (1122b16, mega kai
kalon). If kalon were strictly equivocal across contexts, this comparison would
be unintelligible. Similarly, in Nicomachean Ethics 9.9, Aristotle draws a close
which is a point of substantive debate between commentators such as Anscombe analogy between the virtuous agent’s relationship to virtuous actions and the
and Irwin. musician’s relationship to beautiful music: “for the august man (insofar as he
13
Some authors have simply embraced the conclusion that Aristotle is en- is august) rejoices in virtuous actions and disapproves of bad ones, just as
dorsing acting for broadly aesthetic reasons. In particular, Chappell argues that acting the musician is pleased with beautiful [kalois] melodies, but is pained by ugly
for the sake of beauty represents a distinct form of practical rationality, which is ones,” (1170a9–11, my translation). This suggests that Aristotle is fully cog-
irreducible to moral or prudential reasons. However, I think that this view both flirts nizant of, and makes use of, the parallel ways in which an action and a piece
with anachronism in ascribing to Aristotle a view about aesthetic value and unduly
of music might both be kalon. Thus, although Aristotle nowhere asserts this
narrows the meaning of kalon to application in contexts wherein roughly speaking an
aesthetic reading seems appropriate.
14
Kosman, “Beauty and the Good,” 342. 15
The Greek term zoon is ambiguous between “animal” and “picture.”
38 Beauty and Motivation in Aristotle Brian Donohue 39
explicitly, kalon may count as what scholars have called a “pros hen equivo- III. Beauty and Motivation
cal”—that is, a word that has different, but interrelated senses, just like “being”
(Meta. 1003a32–35). If my above interpretation is correct, then we can easily I have belabored the problem of how to characterize kalon in Aristotle’s
identify a factor common to otherwise disparate uses of kalon: although the thought. Now I turn to the significance of kalon for Aristotle’s thought, in
set of properties that render a face beautiful are not the same that render a particular, for three aspects of his theory of ethics. This discussion will be
soul beautiful, both sets of properties exhibit order, proportion, and definite- necessarily succinct and cursory, but I hope informative nonetheless.
ness, and to that extent are kalon.
Perhaps, then, Aristotle’s word kalon is gesturing at the same phe-
nomenon as we are when we use the word beautiful. This would license, I A. Beauty as object of choice
think, a fairly uniform translation of kalon as beautiful. At the same time, his
remarks about the kalon obviously do not exhaust what we might say about First, consider beauty as an object of choice. In Nicomachean Ethics 2.3
the beautiful or the aesthetic. Likewise some claims we might make about the (1104b29–1105a1; cf. also Top. 102b14–20), Aristotle differentiates between
aesthetic will surely fall outside Aristotle’s purview. Where I think he’s got three types of object of choice: (1) the pleasant, (2) the advantageous, and (3)
something important to contribute is the role this concept of kalon plays in the beautiful. Aristotle suggests that these three neatly exhaust the range of
our pursuit and exercise of the virtues, which I’ll address in a moment.16 choices that might motivate us or otherwise appear desirable to us. Whether
or not he’s right about that, I think he is correct that these three are types
of object of choice. Pleasure motivates all by itself. Again, Aristotle is not
F. Summary a hedonist by any stretch; rather, he has in mind activities done just for the
pleasure or pleasantness they incur. Take some innocuous cases, like telling
To sum up so far: it is not too difficult, from what we have witnessed, to see jokes and playing games. That is not to say that one could not engage in these
kalon as fairly unified in meaning. The word designates the property or char- activities for the sake of the advantageous (e.g., telling someone a joke to
acteristic of a thing that marks it as possessing a certain order, proportion, win his or her approval), but rather that we often do choose them just for the
and definiteness. This is a property (or set of properties) that can supervene enjoyment we reap from them. The advantageous is likewise straightforward:
on radically different kinds of subvenient bases (e.g., relations among parts I choose to drive on I-79 south not because it is beautiful, and definitely
of a face, relations among parts of the soul, etc.). Further, it is a characteristic not because it is pleasant, but because it is the most practical way to travel
that must be open to view—to contemplation (NE 1122b17)—which merits to Steubenville. Further, Aristotle remarks that where most people err is in
praise, and which engenders pleasure in the (well-disposed) observer. I con- making pleasure the object of their choices. In choosing what is pleasant,
clude that it does not seem too strong to say that this just is Aristotle’s account easy, and agreeable, whenever one has the chance to choose it, one ends up
of beauty. It has many features commonly associated with beauty—not to habituating oneself to choose things are both pleasant and vicious.
mention the weightiness, the importance we might take beauty to have—as Significantly, then, Aristotle lists a third motive: acting for the sake
well as, I will argue, the motivational power of beauty, which we might hope of the beautiful, which is characteristic of the virtuous agent. Given how I
to discover in a philosophical account of beauty. have characterized kalon, how should we understand this? First, we need to
keep in mind that Aristotle thinks that the virtuous person chooses his ac-
tion not for some further end, but for the action itself. The virtuous action
terminates in itself—is an end in itself (NE 1105a30–1105b1). On Aristotle’s
16
One important set of issues I cannot address here is the relationship be- account, the efficient cause of action is the choice made, but the final end
tween this account of the kalon and Aristotle’s metaphysics generally. As a matter of action is simply to act well, to engage in “eupraxia” (NE 1139b3). Recall
of fact, I think there is a strong case to be made that the properties of kalon (order, that Aristotle defines happiness (eudaimonia) as an activity or activation of one’s
proportion, definiteness) should be read in light of Aristotle’s treatment of form virtuous character. In other words, the “flourishing” is in the “doing,” not a
(eidos, morphos). This interpretation, if correct, would also lend itself simultaneously product separate from the “doing.” From these considerations, I am led to
to teleological and efficient readings of the kalon, insofar as each thing’s telos involves think that the kalon that is pertinent to choice must be the kalon of the action
striving after the actualization of its form, and insofar as that form effects the actual-
in question—that is, the one that realizes an agent’s virtuous state.
ization of form. Cf. Metaphysics 1041a10 and following.
38 Beauty and Motivation in Aristotle Brian Donohue 39
explicitly, kalon may count as what scholars have called a “pros hen equivo- III. Beauty and Motivation
cal”—that is, a word that has different, but interrelated senses, just like “being”
(Meta. 1003a32–35). If my above interpretation is correct, then we can easily I have belabored the problem of how to characterize kalon in Aristotle’s
identify a factor common to otherwise disparate uses of kalon: although the thought. Now I turn to the significance of kalon for Aristotle’s thought, in
set of properties that render a face beautiful are not the same that render a particular, for three aspects of his theory of ethics. This discussion will be
soul beautiful, both sets of properties exhibit order, proportion, and definite- necessarily succinct and cursory, but I hope informative nonetheless.
ness, and to that extent are kalon.
Perhaps, then, Aristotle’s word kalon is gesturing at the same phe-
nomenon as we are when we use the word beautiful. This would license, I A. Beauty as object of choice
think, a fairly uniform translation of kalon as beautiful. At the same time, his
remarks about the kalon obviously do not exhaust what we might say about First, consider beauty as an object of choice. In Nicomachean Ethics 2.3
the beautiful or the aesthetic. Likewise some claims we might make about the (1104b29–1105a1; cf. also Top. 102b14–20), Aristotle differentiates between
aesthetic will surely fall outside Aristotle’s purview. Where I think he’s got three types of object of choice: (1) the pleasant, (2) the advantageous, and (3)
something important to contribute is the role this concept of kalon plays in the beautiful. Aristotle suggests that these three neatly exhaust the range of
our pursuit and exercise of the virtues, which I’ll address in a moment.16 choices that might motivate us or otherwise appear desirable to us. Whether
or not he’s right about that, I think he is correct that these three are types
of object of choice. Pleasure motivates all by itself. Again, Aristotle is not
F. Summary a hedonist by any stretch; rather, he has in mind activities done just for the
pleasure or pleasantness they incur. Take some innocuous cases, like telling
To sum up so far: it is not too difficult, from what we have witnessed, to see jokes and playing games. That is not to say that one could not engage in these
kalon as fairly unified in meaning. The word designates the property or char- activities for the sake of the advantageous (e.g., telling someone a joke to
acteristic of a thing that marks it as possessing a certain order, proportion, win his or her approval), but rather that we often do choose them just for the
and definiteness. This is a property (or set of properties) that can supervene enjoyment we reap from them. The advantageous is likewise straightforward:
on radically different kinds of subvenient bases (e.g., relations among parts I choose to drive on I-79 south not because it is beautiful, and definitely
of a face, relations among parts of the soul, etc.). Further, it is a characteristic not because it is pleasant, but because it is the most practical way to travel
that must be open to view—to contemplation (NE 1122b17)—which merits to Steubenville. Further, Aristotle remarks that where most people err is in
praise, and which engenders pleasure in the (well-disposed) observer. I con- making pleasure the object of their choices. In choosing what is pleasant,
clude that it does not seem too strong to say that this just is Aristotle’s account easy, and agreeable, whenever one has the chance to choose it, one ends up
of beauty. It has many features commonly associated with beauty—not to habituating oneself to choose things are both pleasant and vicious.
mention the weightiness, the importance we might take beauty to have—as Significantly, then, Aristotle lists a third motive: acting for the sake
well as, I will argue, the motivational power of beauty, which we might hope of the beautiful, which is characteristic of the virtuous agent. Given how I
to discover in a philosophical account of beauty. have characterized kalon, how should we understand this? First, we need to
keep in mind that Aristotle thinks that the virtuous person chooses his ac-
tion not for some further end, but for the action itself. The virtuous action
terminates in itself—is an end in itself (NE 1105a30–1105b1). On Aristotle’s
16
One important set of issues I cannot address here is the relationship be- account, the efficient cause of action is the choice made, but the final end
tween this account of the kalon and Aristotle’s metaphysics generally. As a matter of action is simply to act well, to engage in “eupraxia” (NE 1139b3). Recall
of fact, I think there is a strong case to be made that the properties of kalon (order, that Aristotle defines happiness (eudaimonia) as an activity or activation of one’s
proportion, definiteness) should be read in light of Aristotle’s treatment of form virtuous character. In other words, the “flourishing” is in the “doing,” not a
(eidos, morphos). This interpretation, if correct, would also lend itself simultaneously product separate from the “doing.” From these considerations, I am led to
to teleological and efficient readings of the kalon, insofar as each thing’s telos involves think that the kalon that is pertinent to choice must be the kalon of the action
striving after the actualization of its form, and insofar as that form effects the actual-
in question—that is, the one that realizes an agent’s virtuous state.
ization of form. Cf. Metaphysics 1041a10 and following.
40 Beauty and Motivation in Aristotle Brian Donohue 41
What, then, is a kalon action? We have caught a glimpse of Aristotle’s firm and acts following courage for the sake of something beautiful” (NE
answer already: it has to do with his famous doctrine that a virtuous action 1115b22–23, my translation). Aristotle is asserting here that what defines
is one that hits the intermediate. An analogy from music might help. A sing- courage (in part) is the end—that is, the beautiful at which the virtue aims
er’s goal is (usually) to hit the intermediate pitch (i.e., one that is neither too (cf. NE 1103b20; 1104b29–31;1105b9–11; 1122b6). This is also why the in-
sharp, nor too flat). Succeeding at this with any level of proficiency requires termediate is “relative to us”; in a virtuous action an agent aims at the inter-
practice and much of what Aristotle would place under the heading of ha- mediate with respect to his own passions and actions.
bituation. The beautiful pitch—the pitch that is kalon—is one that is produced My suggestion here is that the harmony among the parts of the soul
when a singer hits that intermediate, and to hit the beautiful pitch, the singer is what makes that soul beautiful. To be virtuous, it is not sufficient to hit the
must make this pitch his target. Moreover, the beautiful “product” of his intermediate in action between the excess and deficiency. It is, rather, nec-
activity is not separable from the activity itself; rather, the beauty manifests essary to have formed a character such that both one’s actions and passions
itself in the ordering and proportionality of pitch, tone, harmony, breathing, are ordered by reason, which discerns in each circumstance the appropriate
etc. Similarly, the virtuous agent is one habituated so as to be attuned to the degree of passion and action relative to one’s own state and circumstances.
kalon—the order and proportion characteristic of a virtuous action. To be so Thus, Aristotle identifies many vices as excesses or deficiencies of passion
ordered an action must bear the right relationship to one’s passions, to the in the soul of the agent. Cowardice exhibits an excess of fear and deficiency of
circumstances, and to one’s life as a whole. In Aristotle’s parlance, the action appropriate anger; and intemperance, gluttony, laziness, and lust exhibit an
must be done in the right way, at the right time, and to the right extent. Like- excessive and unordered desire. These tendencies say as much about the soul
wise, the virtuous agent’s “product” is not separable from the action itself, as they do about the action. And since the harmony of the soul’s elements is
but is rather manifest in the performance of the action. This is what it means bound up intimately with the beauty in action, the soul itself must come to
to choose an action for the sake of the beautiful; it is to choose the beauty bear the features of beauty that it brings about in action. It cannot actualize
that the action embodies and realizes. the kalon in individual actions unless it first has, interiorly, the order charac-
teristic of beauty.17 Put succinctly, the virtuous action is one that aims at the
virtue itself, which just is a state of the agent. Thus, there is reason to think
B. Beauty and harmony in the soul that, on Aristotle’s account, the virtuous soul becomes beautiful itself on
account of the harmony it achieves among its diverse elements in becoming
Next, I want to explain how beauty is also important for Aristotle’s evaluative virtuous.18
stance toward the states or habits (hexeis) of agents. In explaining the good
condition of a soul (i.e., moral virtue), Aristotle often employs an analogy
with health, the good condition of the body. He often describes health in C. Beauty and God
terms of a balance or harmony obtaining among various elements within a
biological system, and disease with the lack or loss of balance among those Finally, I think there is some suggestion that beauty is important for the role
elements. Hence, he writes, “it is the nature of such things to be destroyed by of God in Aristotle’s thought, and especially in his theory of ethics. There are
defect and excess, as we see in the case of strength and of health.… So too two observations I wish to make. The first is that contemplation of God (the-
is it, then, in the case of temperance and courage and the other excellences
[virtues]” (NE 1104a11–12, 19). This same view arises again in Aristotle’s 17
For similar discussions, cf. Rogers, “Aristotle’s Concept of To Kalon”; Rog-
discussion of particular virtues: the courageous man is the one who is neither ers, “Aristotle on the Motive of Courage,” Southern Journal of Philosophy 32, no. 3
deficient nor excessive in fearlessness, and so on. (1994): 303–13; and John Milliken, “Aristotle’s Aesthetic Ethics,” Southern Journal of
Now, at other places in the Ethics, Aristotle describes both virtu- Philosophy 44 (2006): 319–39.
ous habits generally (NE 1095b5) and particular virtues as beautiful (cf. NE
18
In this respect (among others), I think Plato and Aristotle stand in sub-
1115b22). He also suggests that the beauty of virtuous habits is linked in- stantive agreement. Although Aristotle does not follow Plato’s definition of justice
timately with taking beauty as an object of choice. For example, in the case as harmony obtaining among the soul’s various parts, the more general Platonic
point—that virtue is a matter of ordering and delimitation of the passions by rea-
of courage, he claims that “courage is beautiful, and as such its end it beau-
son, and that this brings about a balance to the soul—shines through in Aristotle’s
tiful; for each thing is defined by its end. Thus, the courageous man stands account.
40 Beauty and Motivation in Aristotle Brian Donohue 41
What, then, is a kalon action? We have caught a glimpse of Aristotle’s firm and acts following courage for the sake of something beautiful” (NE
answer already: it has to do with his famous doctrine that a virtuous action 1115b22–23, my translation). Aristotle is asserting here that what defines
is one that hits the intermediate. An analogy from music might help. A sing- courage (in part) is the end—that is, the beautiful at which the virtue aims
er’s goal is (usually) to hit the intermediate pitch (i.e., one that is neither too (cf. NE 1103b20; 1104b29–31;1105b9–11; 1122b6). This is also why the in-
sharp, nor too flat). Succeeding at this with any level of proficiency requires termediate is “relative to us”; in a virtuous action an agent aims at the inter-
practice and much of what Aristotle would place under the heading of ha- mediate with respect to his own passions and actions.
bituation. The beautiful pitch—the pitch that is kalon—is one that is produced My suggestion here is that the harmony among the parts of the soul
when a singer hits that intermediate, and to hit the beautiful pitch, the singer is what makes that soul beautiful. To be virtuous, it is not sufficient to hit the
must make this pitch his target. Moreover, the beautiful “product” of his intermediate in action between the excess and deficiency. It is, rather, nec-
activity is not separable from the activity itself; rather, the beauty manifests essary to have formed a character such that both one’s actions and passions
itself in the ordering and proportionality of pitch, tone, harmony, breathing, are ordered by reason, which discerns in each circumstance the appropriate
etc. Similarly, the virtuous agent is one habituated so as to be attuned to the degree of passion and action relative to one’s own state and circumstances.
kalon—the order and proportion characteristic of a virtuous action. To be so Thus, Aristotle identifies many vices as excesses or deficiencies of passion
ordered an action must bear the right relationship to one’s passions, to the in the soul of the agent. Cowardice exhibits an excess of fear and deficiency of
circumstances, and to one’s life as a whole. In Aristotle’s parlance, the action appropriate anger; and intemperance, gluttony, laziness, and lust exhibit an
must be done in the right way, at the right time, and to the right extent. Like- excessive and unordered desire. These tendencies say as much about the soul
wise, the virtuous agent’s “product” is not separable from the action itself, as they do about the action. And since the harmony of the soul’s elements is
but is rather manifest in the performance of the action. This is what it means bound up intimately with the beauty in action, the soul itself must come to
to choose an action for the sake of the beautiful; it is to choose the beauty bear the features of beauty that it brings about in action. It cannot actualize
that the action embodies and realizes. the kalon in individual actions unless it first has, interiorly, the order charac-
teristic of beauty.17 Put succinctly, the virtuous action is one that aims at the
virtue itself, which just is a state of the agent. Thus, there is reason to think
B. Beauty and harmony in the soul that, on Aristotle’s account, the virtuous soul becomes beautiful itself on
account of the harmony it achieves among its diverse elements in becoming
Next, I want to explain how beauty is also important for Aristotle’s evaluative virtuous.18
stance toward the states or habits (hexeis) of agents. In explaining the good
condition of a soul (i.e., moral virtue), Aristotle often employs an analogy
with health, the good condition of the body. He often describes health in C. Beauty and God
terms of a balance or harmony obtaining among various elements within a
biological system, and disease with the lack or loss of balance among those Finally, I think there is some suggestion that beauty is important for the role
elements. Hence, he writes, “it is the nature of such things to be destroyed by of God in Aristotle’s thought, and especially in his theory of ethics. There are
defect and excess, as we see in the case of strength and of health.… So too two observations I wish to make. The first is that contemplation of God (the-
is it, then, in the case of temperance and courage and the other excellences
[virtues]” (NE 1104a11–12, 19). This same view arises again in Aristotle’s 17
For similar discussions, cf. Rogers, “Aristotle’s Concept of To Kalon”; Rog-
discussion of particular virtues: the courageous man is the one who is neither ers, “Aristotle on the Motive of Courage,” Southern Journal of Philosophy 32, no. 3
deficient nor excessive in fearlessness, and so on. (1994): 303–13; and John Milliken, “Aristotle’s Aesthetic Ethics,” Southern Journal of
Now, at other places in the Ethics, Aristotle describes both virtu- Philosophy 44 (2006): 319–39.
ous habits generally (NE 1095b5) and particular virtues as beautiful (cf. NE
18
In this respect (among others), I think Plato and Aristotle stand in sub-
1115b22). He also suggests that the beauty of virtuous habits is linked in- stantive agreement. Although Aristotle does not follow Plato’s definition of justice
timately with taking beauty as an object of choice. For example, in the case as harmony obtaining among the soul’s various parts, the more general Platonic
point—that virtue is a matter of ordering and delimitation of the passions by rea-
of courage, he claims that “courage is beautiful, and as such its end it beau-
son, and that this brings about a balance to the soul—shines through in Aristotle’s
tiful; for each thing is defined by its end. Thus, the courageous man stands account.
42 Beauty and Motivation in Aristotle Brian Donohue 43
oria), which according to Aristotle is itself a divine activity (NE 1177b30–35; suggests strongly that God himself is considered supremely beautiful by our
1178b7–32), is the best and most beautiful standard for the soul’s activity thought and desire. There is corroborating evidence for this interpretation in
(houtos ho horos kallistos… kai houtos tes psuches horos aristos; EE 1249b13–22). the above passage from Eudemian Ethics, where Aristotle writes: “God is not
Now throughout the Ethics, Aristotle remarks upon the need for a “standard” a commanding ruler, but that for the sake of which practical wisdom issues
(horos) for the soul, since it is this standard that determines the intermediate commands,” (1249b13–14, my translation). Now Aristotle teaches unequiv-
between excess and deficiency (NE 1138b22–24). In this passage from the ocally that practical wisdom aims at what is beautiful (NE 1144a7–9), and
conclusion of the Eudemian Ethics, Aristotle is suggesting that the standard if practical wisdom aims ultimately at God, then God must be supremely
for our activity is, in one way, quite simple: whatever activity conduces to beautiful. This is, at least, what Aristotle’s discussion implies.
contemplation of God.19 This agrees with Aristotle’s remarks toward the end
of Nicomachean Ethics, that although even the most virtuous of agents will be
torn away from contemplation in order to look after his external needs (NE IV. Conclusion
1178b33–35), one should nonetheless “strain every nerve to live in accor-
dance with the best thing in us” (NE 1177b35)—namely, contemplation— This paper began with two questions: what is Aristotle’s concept of kalon,
for in this activity consists happiness in a preeminent way. In what sense, and what is the significance of kalon for certain aspects of his ethical theory?
then, should we understand contemplation of God as the “most beautiful” My conclusion is simple enough: the kalon, which I have argued just is Aris-
standard for the soul? The answer seems to be that it is the “most beautiful” totle’s concept of beauty, moves the soul that takes beauty into itself. The
standard insofar as it promotes an activity that is best.20 soul that becomes beautiful contemplates beauty and manifests beauty in its
The second observation is that there may be implications in Aristo- virtuous activities. This is the same beauty that moves an agent toward the
tle’s theory of ethics for the peculiar role he ascribes to God in the cosmos, greater harmonization of his own soul, moves him to act nobly and heroical-
namely, that of prime mover. By prime mover Aristotle does not mean the ly, and leads him to deny his passions when they run in excess. This beauty,
individual who flicks the first cosmic domino, which topples further dom- whose contemplation engenders supreme joy, awakens desire in the soul that
inoes—dominoes unto dominoes, all the way down to us. Rather, Aristo- is attuned to it. For these reasons I am pressed to read Aristotle as ascribing
tle means that God is the final cause of the cosmos, that for the sake of an indispensable role to the beautiful in his account of the virtuous life.21
which everything in the universe strives. In Metaphysics 12.7, Aristotle first
describes how final causes in general, and how the objects of thought and —University at Buffalo
desire in particular, “move [others] without being moved,” and then states
that thought and desire are both aimed at what is genuinely beautiful (to on
kalon, 1072a28). He goes on to describe the sense in which God is the prime
mover of the cosmos: he “moves [others] without being moved” insofar as
his life and activity are best and most desirable. This line of thought, then,

19
Of course, knowing which particular actions in our particular circumstanc-
es will achieve this will require practical wisdom (cf. NE 1144a6–9).
20
For related discussions, cf. D.J. Allan, “The Fine and the Good in the Eu-
demian Ethics,” in Untersuchungen zur Eudemischen Ethik, ed. P. Moraux and D. Harlfin-
ger (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter & Co., 1971), 64–71; Thomas Tuozzo, “Contempla-
tion, the Noble, and the Mean: The Standard for Moral Virtue in Aristotle’s Ethics,”
in Aristotle, Virtue, and the Mean, ed. John Bosley (Edmonton, AB: Academic Printing
and Publishing, 1996), 129–54; Michael Wiitala, “Contemplation and Action within
the Context of the Kalon: A Reading of the Nicomachean Ethics,” Proceedings of the
American Catholic Philosophical Association 83 (2009): 173–82; James L. Wood, “Con-
templating the Beautiful: The Practical Importance of Theoretical Excellence in Ar- I would like to thank Jonathan Sanford, Stephen Shortt, Nathan Cornwell,
21

istotle’s Ethics,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 49, no. 4 (2011): 391–412. and Theresa Farnan for helpful discussion of the issues in this paper.
42 Beauty and Motivation in Aristotle Brian Donohue 43
oria), which according to Aristotle is itself a divine activity (NE 1177b30–35; suggests strongly that God himself is considered supremely beautiful by our
1178b7–32), is the best and most beautiful standard for the soul’s activity thought and desire. There is corroborating evidence for this interpretation in
(houtos ho horos kallistos… kai houtos tes psuches horos aristos; EE 1249b13–22). the above passage from Eudemian Ethics, where Aristotle writes: “God is not
Now throughout the Ethics, Aristotle remarks upon the need for a “standard” a commanding ruler, but that for the sake of which practical wisdom issues
(horos) for the soul, since it is this standard that determines the intermediate commands,” (1249b13–14, my translation). Now Aristotle teaches unequiv-
between excess and deficiency (NE 1138b22–24). In this passage from the ocally that practical wisdom aims at what is beautiful (NE 1144a7–9), and
conclusion of the Eudemian Ethics, Aristotle is suggesting that the standard if practical wisdom aims ultimately at God, then God must be supremely
for our activity is, in one way, quite simple: whatever activity conduces to beautiful. This is, at least, what Aristotle’s discussion implies.
contemplation of God.19 This agrees with Aristotle’s remarks toward the end
of Nicomachean Ethics, that although even the most virtuous of agents will be
torn away from contemplation in order to look after his external needs (NE IV. Conclusion
1178b33–35), one should nonetheless “strain every nerve to live in accor-
dance with the best thing in us” (NE 1177b35)—namely, contemplation— This paper began with two questions: what is Aristotle’s concept of kalon,
for in this activity consists happiness in a preeminent way. In what sense, and what is the significance of kalon for certain aspects of his ethical theory?
then, should we understand contemplation of God as the “most beautiful” My conclusion is simple enough: the kalon, which I have argued just is Aris-
standard for the soul? The answer seems to be that it is the “most beautiful” totle’s concept of beauty, moves the soul that takes beauty into itself. The
standard insofar as it promotes an activity that is best.20 soul that becomes beautiful contemplates beauty and manifests beauty in its
The second observation is that there may be implications in Aristo- virtuous activities. This is the same beauty that moves an agent toward the
tle’s theory of ethics for the peculiar role he ascribes to God in the cosmos, greater harmonization of his own soul, moves him to act nobly and heroical-
namely, that of prime mover. By prime mover Aristotle does not mean the ly, and leads him to deny his passions when they run in excess. This beauty,
individual who flicks the first cosmic domino, which topples further dom- whose contemplation engenders supreme joy, awakens desire in the soul that
inoes—dominoes unto dominoes, all the way down to us. Rather, Aristo- is attuned to it. For these reasons I am pressed to read Aristotle as ascribing
tle means that God is the final cause of the cosmos, that for the sake of an indispensable role to the beautiful in his account of the virtuous life.21
which everything in the universe strives. In Metaphysics 12.7, Aristotle first
describes how final causes in general, and how the objects of thought and —University at Buffalo
desire in particular, “move [others] without being moved,” and then states
that thought and desire are both aimed at what is genuinely beautiful (to on
kalon, 1072a28). He goes on to describe the sense in which God is the prime
mover of the cosmos: he “moves [others] without being moved” insofar as
his life and activity are best and most desirable. This line of thought, then,

19
Of course, knowing which particular actions in our particular circumstanc-
es will achieve this will require practical wisdom (cf. NE 1144a6–9).
20
For related discussions, cf. D.J. Allan, “The Fine and the Good in the Eu-
demian Ethics,” in Untersuchungen zur Eudemischen Ethik, ed. P. Moraux and D. Harlfin-
ger (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter & Co., 1971), 64–71; Thomas Tuozzo, “Contempla-
tion, the Noble, and the Mean: The Standard for Moral Virtue in Aristotle’s Ethics,”
in Aristotle, Virtue, and the Mean, ed. John Bosley (Edmonton, AB: Academic Printing
and Publishing, 1996), 129–54; Michael Wiitala, “Contemplation and Action within
the Context of the Kalon: A Reading of the Nicomachean Ethics,” Proceedings of the
American Catholic Philosophical Association 83 (2009): 173–82; James L. Wood, “Con-
templating the Beautiful: The Practical Importance of Theoretical Excellence in Ar- I would like to thank Jonathan Sanford, Stephen Shortt, Nathan Cornwell,
21

istotle’s Ethics,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 49, no. 4 (2011): 391–412. and Theresa Farnan for helpful discussion of the issues in this paper.
Marcus Otte 45

The Metaphysics of Moral Values II. Characterizing Moral Values and Essences

and Moral Beauty In the tenth chapter of Christian Ethics, von Hildebrand offers perhaps his
most metaphysically potent account of moral values. These values each have
a distinct qualitative quiddity, or whatness. There are true distinctions between
Marcus Otte values such as honesty, purity, and reverence.
But what mode or modes of being do moral values possess? Von
Hildebrand contrasts his view with that of Aristotle, according to which all
goodness consists in the “immanent perfection of a being.”3 For von Hildeb-
I. Introduction rand, moral values, and other qualitative values, are somewhat akin to Plato’s
Ideas. Platonic goodness transcends each singular good thing. Similarly, the
The aim of this paper is twofold: to provide a more rigorous account of quiddity of a value has “independence” from any particular human act, as
the ontology of values and to suggest a means of merging von Hildebrand’s well as from types of human acts.4 In von Hildebrand’s understanding, this is
values with Scholastic metaphysics. At first glance, such a project might seem why the same value may be exhibited by multiple types of acts. Hence, purity
to make little sense. Von Hildebrandian values contrast in fundamental ways is present in resistance to any sexual sin, in chaste love, and in making vows
with Scholastic theories of the good and beautiful. For von Hildebrand, beau- of chastity.
ty and good are not transcendentals that are coextensive with being. Rather, Moral values, despite possessing this independence, are “embodied.”
being is rendered beautiful or good by values: properties that remain distinct They possess an essence of their own, but “shine forth” from acts of the
from “neutral” being as such.1 Nevertheless, there is ground for substantial will.5 There are no values in the created order that do not inhere in some-
movement towards synthesizing these traditions. Von Hildebrand’s descrip- thing.6 Additionally, to grasp the presence of values is only possible through
tion of values bears strong resemblance with a centerpiece of Scholastic phi- knowledge of the acts and attitudes that possess them.7 It is in understanding
losophy shared by many of its most influential figures, including Aquinas and the object, end, and content of an act of preaching, for example, that we
Duns Scotus: namely, the ontology of essences proposed by Avicenna. grasp the presence of its piety.
In order to limit the scope of the discussion, the focus here is placed upon Before establishing that moral values may be characterized as having
von Hildebrand’s first sphere of morally relevant values—that of actions. essences, it is necessary to briefly exposit the latter notion. St. Thomas’s On
Thus, I largely set aside “concrete responses” (i.e., immanent operations that Being and Essence is a paradigmatic expression of Avicenna’s theory of exis-
do not include exterior actions) and qualities of character.2 The thesis of tence and essence. This theory, or variations of it, was adopted by Giles of
this paper is as follows: considered in themselves, von Hildebrand’s values Rome, Henry of Ghent, and Bl. Duns Scotus, among others. For this reason,
are neither universal nor singular. Values, however, never exist simply as they I refer to the theory as “Scholastic,” despite its not being altogether uncon-
are in themselves. As the objects of rational thought, values are universal. As troversial for the Scholastics.8 In the Avicennean scheme, there are two ways
proper accidents that supervene on actions, they are singular. Von Hildeb- an essence may be considered: as it is in itself or as it exists. In considering
rand’s treatment of disvalues, however, cannot be successfully merged with an essence in itself, only that which is necessarily true of it can be attributed
Scholastic metaphysics: he regards disvalues as having positive being.
3
Ibid.,133.
4
Ibid.
5
Ibid.
6
The values of God, however, do not inhere in Him but are simply identical
1
Dietrich von Hildebrand, The Nature of Love (South Bend, IN: St. Augustine to him. See von Hildebrand, Christian Ethics, 123.
Press, 2009), 79. 7
Von Hildebrand, Christian Ethics, 133.
2
Dietrich von Hildebrand, Christian Ethics (New York, NY: David McKay 8
Dag Nikolaus Hasse, “Influence of Arabic and Islamic Philosophy on the
Company, 1953), 342–43. Latin West,” § 6.3, in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, first published September
19, 2008, substantive revision March 18, 2014, http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/
© Marcus Otte, Quaestiones Disputatae, Vol. 6, No. 2 (Spring 2016)
arabic-islamic-influence/
Marcus Otte 45

The Metaphysics of Moral Values II. Characterizing Moral Values and Essences

and Moral Beauty In the tenth chapter of Christian Ethics, von Hildebrand offers perhaps his
most metaphysically potent account of moral values. These values each have
a distinct qualitative quiddity, or whatness. There are true distinctions between
Marcus Otte values such as honesty, purity, and reverence.
But what mode or modes of being do moral values possess? Von
Hildebrand contrasts his view with that of Aristotle, according to which all
goodness consists in the “immanent perfection of a being.”3 For von Hildeb-
I. Introduction rand, moral values, and other qualitative values, are somewhat akin to Plato’s
Ideas. Platonic goodness transcends each singular good thing. Similarly, the
The aim of this paper is twofold: to provide a more rigorous account of quiddity of a value has “independence” from any particular human act, as
the ontology of values and to suggest a means of merging von Hildebrand’s well as from types of human acts.4 In von Hildebrand’s understanding, this is
values with Scholastic metaphysics. At first glance, such a project might seem why the same value may be exhibited by multiple types of acts. Hence, purity
to make little sense. Von Hildebrandian values contrast in fundamental ways is present in resistance to any sexual sin, in chaste love, and in making vows
with Scholastic theories of the good and beautiful. For von Hildebrand, beau- of chastity.
ty and good are not transcendentals that are coextensive with being. Rather, Moral values, despite possessing this independence, are “embodied.”
being is rendered beautiful or good by values: properties that remain distinct They possess an essence of their own, but “shine forth” from acts of the
from “neutral” being as such.1 Nevertheless, there is ground for substantial will.5 There are no values in the created order that do not inhere in some-
movement towards synthesizing these traditions. Von Hildebrand’s descrip- thing.6 Additionally, to grasp the presence of values is only possible through
tion of values bears strong resemblance with a centerpiece of Scholastic phi- knowledge of the acts and attitudes that possess them.7 It is in understanding
losophy shared by many of its most influential figures, including Aquinas and the object, end, and content of an act of preaching, for example, that we
Duns Scotus: namely, the ontology of essences proposed by Avicenna. grasp the presence of its piety.
In order to limit the scope of the discussion, the focus here is placed upon Before establishing that moral values may be characterized as having
von Hildebrand’s first sphere of morally relevant values—that of actions. essences, it is necessary to briefly exposit the latter notion. St. Thomas’s On
Thus, I largely set aside “concrete responses” (i.e., immanent operations that Being and Essence is a paradigmatic expression of Avicenna’s theory of exis-
do not include exterior actions) and qualities of character.2 The thesis of tence and essence. This theory, or variations of it, was adopted by Giles of
this paper is as follows: considered in themselves, von Hildebrand’s values Rome, Henry of Ghent, and Bl. Duns Scotus, among others. For this reason,
are neither universal nor singular. Values, however, never exist simply as they I refer to the theory as “Scholastic,” despite its not being altogether uncon-
are in themselves. As the objects of rational thought, values are universal. As troversial for the Scholastics.8 In the Avicennean scheme, there are two ways
proper accidents that supervene on actions, they are singular. Von Hildeb- an essence may be considered: as it is in itself or as it exists. In considering
rand’s treatment of disvalues, however, cannot be successfully merged with an essence in itself, only that which is necessarily true of it can be attributed
Scholastic metaphysics: he regards disvalues as having positive being.
3
Ibid.,133.
4
Ibid.
5
Ibid.
6
The values of God, however, do not inhere in Him but are simply identical
1
Dietrich von Hildebrand, The Nature of Love (South Bend, IN: St. Augustine to him. See von Hildebrand, Christian Ethics, 123.
Press, 2009), 79. 7
Von Hildebrand, Christian Ethics, 133.
2
Dietrich von Hildebrand, Christian Ethics (New York, NY: David McKay 8
Dag Nikolaus Hasse, “Influence of Arabic and Islamic Philosophy on the
Company, 1953), 342–43. Latin West,” § 6.3, in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, first published September
19, 2008, substantive revision March 18, 2014, http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/
© Marcus Otte, Quaestiones Disputatae, Vol. 6, No. 2 (Spring 2016)
arabic-islamic-influence/
46 The Metaphysics of Moral Values Marcus Otte 47
truly. So, for example, being rational and animal pertains to being man ab- independently of all realization.”13 Even if there were no instantiations of
solutely, and thus, is of the essence of man considered in itself, but being justice in the world, true propositions referring to justice could be formed.14
white or black does not belong to this essence. Of course, an essence never Let the above suffice as an account of moral values as they are in
exists simply as it is in itself. An essence may exist in two modes: singularly themselves. How do these values exist in the world of particular items? In
in particular things or universally “in the soul,” as an object of the intellect.9 von Hildebrand’s usage, a value is “a real property” of a being.15 The notion
Neither universality nor singularity is predicated of an essence in itself—the of being includes acts. Moral values are properties of acts as well as of char-
essence is indifferent to either determination. Horseness is just horseness, to acters and concrete responses.
use Avicenna’s expression. If we are to characterize such moral values in the Scholastic lexicon,
we must treat them as “proper accidents,” as will soon be clear. By describing
values as properties, von Hildebrand excludes, not only the notion that values
III. A Synthesis of Moral Values with Scholastic Metaphysics are relative or belong to the non-factual, but also the Platonic notion they are
substances. If values are properties, the Scholastic must treat them as acci-
Von Hildebrand asserts that qualitative values, as he describes them, are bet- dents. With regard to being that is outside the mind, the disjunction of sub-
ter characterized as Platonic than Aristotelian. But this is a confusing claim. stance and accident is exhaustive: accidents are predicated of other beings,
There are, for von Hildebrand, no values with strictly independent being, and substances are predicated of nothing. Therefore, values have accidental
existing in an ethereal realm. “Only real persons, their acts and attitudes, can being.
be morally good or bad.”10 Nevertheless, values can be considered purely The objection might be raised that I am departing from von Hildeb-
in themselves, in abstraction from their modes of existence. Just so, in the rand’s own description of values. There is a relevant passage worth quoting
Scholastic schemata, accidental properties can be abstracted from their in- at length:
stantiations, even if they cannot exist apart from them.
We understand and grasp there is an essential link between the
Von Hildebrand refers several times to the “quiddity” of value, or
value and the object [the value inheres in]. It is not only another
of types of values.11 Quiddity is, of course, a term for essence. St. Thomas,
and deeper relation than the one that exists between substance
following standard usage, distinguishes between “essence” and “quiddity”
and accident, the typical inherent relation, but it is moreover a
only inasmuch as the latter names the essence as “what is signified by the
necessary intelligible link, not a mere factual and accidental one.
definition [of the being].”12 Von Hildebrand does not signal an intention to
We understand that contrition is morally good and that it must
use this philosophical term of art in a non-standard way. He is inviting us to
be so.16
understand the ontology of values in a manner informed by Scholastic cate-
gories. Nevertheless, in treating moral values as accidents, we need not
When von Hildebrand refers, then, to a “world of values,” he does abandon von Hildebrand’s understanding of them. Here, we must draw a
not mean to signify a world of Platonic ideas. Rather, he means to empha- distinction between “proper accidents,” on one hand, and accidents that are
size that we may refer not only to existing values, but “to all possible future “accidentally in the subject,” on the other.17 The latter are accidents in the
realizations of values and indeed even to the mode of being that values have typical sense. Their being is not necessitated by the substance in which they
inhere. Tallness in Socrates, for example, is not consequent upon his essence
as man.

9
Thomas Aquinas, On Being and Essence, chap. 3, trans. Robert T. Miller, in
Fordham University Medieval Sourcebook, published October 2007, http://legacy.ford- 13
Von Hildebrand, The Nature of Love, 81.
ham.edu/halsall/basis/aquinas-esse.asp#f1e. This translation follows the Leonine 14
Ibid.
Edition of Aquinas’s works, vol. 43 Sancti Thomae De Aquino Opera Omnia 368– 15
Von Hildebrand, Christian Ethics, 89, 120.
81 (Rome 1976). 16
Ibid., 87.
10
Von Hildebrand, Christian Ethics, 170. 17
Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologica I-II q. 18, a. 3, ad. 2, trans. Fathers of
11
Ibid., 88, 102, 115, 133, 169. the English Dominican Province (Benzinger Bros., 1947), http://dhspriory.org/
12
Aquinas, On Being and Essence, chap. 1. thomas/summa/index.html.
46 The Metaphysics of Moral Values Marcus Otte 47
truly. So, for example, being rational and animal pertains to being man ab- independently of all realization.”13 Even if there were no instantiations of
solutely, and thus, is of the essence of man considered in itself, but being justice in the world, true propositions referring to justice could be formed.14
white or black does not belong to this essence. Of course, an essence never Let the above suffice as an account of moral values as they are in
exists simply as it is in itself. An essence may exist in two modes: singularly themselves. How do these values exist in the world of particular items? In
in particular things or universally “in the soul,” as an object of the intellect.9 von Hildebrand’s usage, a value is “a real property” of a being.15 The notion
Neither universality nor singularity is predicated of an essence in itself—the of being includes acts. Moral values are properties of acts as well as of char-
essence is indifferent to either determination. Horseness is just horseness, to acters and concrete responses.
use Avicenna’s expression. If we are to characterize such moral values in the Scholastic lexicon,
we must treat them as “proper accidents,” as will soon be clear. By describing
values as properties, von Hildebrand excludes, not only the notion that values
III. A Synthesis of Moral Values with Scholastic Metaphysics are relative or belong to the non-factual, but also the Platonic notion they are
substances. If values are properties, the Scholastic must treat them as acci-
Von Hildebrand asserts that qualitative values, as he describes them, are bet- dents. With regard to being that is outside the mind, the disjunction of sub-
ter characterized as Platonic than Aristotelian. But this is a confusing claim. stance and accident is exhaustive: accidents are predicated of other beings,
There are, for von Hildebrand, no values with strictly independent being, and substances are predicated of nothing. Therefore, values have accidental
existing in an ethereal realm. “Only real persons, their acts and attitudes, can being.
be morally good or bad.”10 Nevertheless, values can be considered purely The objection might be raised that I am departing from von Hildeb-
in themselves, in abstraction from their modes of existence. Just so, in the rand’s own description of values. There is a relevant passage worth quoting
Scholastic schemata, accidental properties can be abstracted from their in- at length:
stantiations, even if they cannot exist apart from them.
We understand and grasp there is an essential link between the
Von Hildebrand refers several times to the “quiddity” of value, or
value and the object [the value inheres in]. It is not only another
of types of values.11 Quiddity is, of course, a term for essence. St. Thomas,
and deeper relation than the one that exists between substance
following standard usage, distinguishes between “essence” and “quiddity”
and accident, the typical inherent relation, but it is moreover a
only inasmuch as the latter names the essence as “what is signified by the
necessary intelligible link, not a mere factual and accidental one.
definition [of the being].”12 Von Hildebrand does not signal an intention to
We understand that contrition is morally good and that it must
use this philosophical term of art in a non-standard way. He is inviting us to
be so.16
understand the ontology of values in a manner informed by Scholastic cate-
gories. Nevertheless, in treating moral values as accidents, we need not
When von Hildebrand refers, then, to a “world of values,” he does abandon von Hildebrand’s understanding of them. Here, we must draw a
not mean to signify a world of Platonic ideas. Rather, he means to empha- distinction between “proper accidents,” on one hand, and accidents that are
size that we may refer not only to existing values, but “to all possible future “accidentally in the subject,” on the other.17 The latter are accidents in the
realizations of values and indeed even to the mode of being that values have typical sense. Their being is not necessitated by the substance in which they
inhere. Tallness in Socrates, for example, is not consequent upon his essence
as man.

9
Thomas Aquinas, On Being and Essence, chap. 3, trans. Robert T. Miller, in
Fordham University Medieval Sourcebook, published October 2007, http://legacy.ford- 13
Von Hildebrand, The Nature of Love, 81.
ham.edu/halsall/basis/aquinas-esse.asp#f1e. This translation follows the Leonine 14
Ibid.
Edition of Aquinas’s works, vol. 43 Sancti Thomae De Aquino Opera Omnia 368– 15
Von Hildebrand, Christian Ethics, 89, 120.
81 (Rome 1976). 16
Ibid., 87.
10
Von Hildebrand, Christian Ethics, 170. 17
Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologica I-II q. 18, a. 3, ad. 2, trans. Fathers of
11
Ibid., 88, 102, 115, 133, 169. the English Dominican Province (Benzinger Bros., 1947), http://dhspriory.org/
12
Aquinas, On Being and Essence, chap. 1. thomas/summa/index.html.
48 The Metaphysics of Moral Values Marcus Otte 49
Proper accidents, on the other hand, are those that inhere in a sub- acts, they are proper accidents that inhere in the acts, and are not constitutive
stance in virtue of its essence, but are not included in the essence. The capac- of the essences of acts.19
ity to laugh is a typical example of an accident proper to man. This capacity is There is a second mode of existence to which an essence may be
a potentiality in every man, although circumstances, defect, or lack of devel- determined: namely, universality. Von Hildebrand does not overtly state that
opment might make it impossible to actualize. Despite such universality, this the quiddity of a value may exist as a universal concept. Nevertheless, there
characteristic does not belong to man’s essence. The ability to laugh is not is good reason to hold this was, in fact, his position. In Christian Ethics, he
part of the definition of man. Nevertheless, there is clearly an intelligible link makes references to knowledge as “the conforming of our intellect…to the
between man’s specific nature and his capacity for laughter. The potential to nature of a being.”20 This is the language of Scholasticism, in which the intel-
laugh does not inhere in man in the coincidental manner of height, color, etc. lect takes on the form of a contemplated object, albeit, according to the in-
When von Hildebrand denies that values have accidental being, his tellect’s mode of existence. To apply this account to the cognition of values:
depiction of accidents makes it clear he is referring to them in the typi- insofar as the intellect conforms to the nature of a contemplated value, the
cal sense: what Aquinas calls “accidents that are accidentally in the subject.” essence of that value is present to the intellect as a universal.
Such accidents do not have a necessary and intelligible link to the essences of
the beings they inhere in. But it is clear, to use a favorite example of von Hil-
debrand, that contrition cannot fail to exemplify goodness—positive value is IV. The Irradiation of Beauty
in contrition, and in a manner that is not merely accidental and factual.
Proper accidents, however, do possess such a necessary and intel- Von Hildebrand writes of a “metaphysical beauty” that irradiates from other
ligible link to their subjects. If values are properties, then they are proper values,21 and it is this beauty that will be discussed here. Moral values possess
accidents. It might be objected, however, that another alternative remains: an intrinsic beauty, not only goodness.22 This beauty is a value,23 and therefore
perhaps moral values are constitutive of the essences of acts. This would a real property. If our prior reasoning with respect to moral values is sound,
satisfy the conditions of necessity and intelligibility. Still, this latter option then it seems there are two possible ways moral beauty could exist in the
is not sensible, because it is possible to determinately refer to the species of world of singulars. First, such beauty might be a proper accident of a moral
acts without naming any value or disvalue. For example, adultery consists value, and thus, an accident of an accident. Second, moral beauty is possibly
in having relations with someone who is married and not one’s spouse, or an accident inhering in the act, but co-varying with values. There is a problem
having relations with someone who is not one’s spouse despite one being with this latter account, however. If moral beauty were merely a property of
married. Gluttony is indulgence in food in a manner either “too soon, too acts, and not of values, then we could contemplate the moral beauty of a
expensively, too much, too eagerly,” or “too daintily.”18 An act of contrition good act without any reference to a moral value. This is clearly not the case.
is sorrow for sin, together with the intent to confess and make satisfaction. Furthermore, von Hildebrand states explicitly that moral beauty is found
If, however, values and disvalues were constitutive of the essences of acts, it in moral values.24 It must be concluded then, that moral beauty inheres as a
would not be possible to determinately define an act according to its species proper accident in moral values.
without naming a value or disvalue. The very definition of adultery, for ex- It is important to note that moral beauty exists in varied forms. Each
ample, would need to name the disvalue of impurity. This is manifestly not moral value, such as purity or honesty, is beautiful in a specific manner. Like-
the case. The above definition provided for adultery successfully describes
all and only cases of adultery, and does so without naming a disvalue. The
same can be done for morally good acts and their values. Acts of feeding the 19
There are also values in characters and “concrete responses,” but in this
hungry, visiting the sick, burying the dead, instructing the ignorant, praying paper I am concerned only with characterizing the sphere of acts.
for the living and the dead, etc., can all be determinately defined according to
20
Von Hildebrand, Christian Ethics, 217.
species without naming a value. Thus, when values exist as singular things in
21
Alice von Hildebrand, “Debating Beauty: Jacques Maritain and Dietrich von
Hildebrand,” Crisis Magazine, July 1, 2004, http://www.crisismagazine.com/2004/
debating-beauty-jacques-maritain-and-dietrich-von-von Hildebrand-2.
22
Von Hildebrand, Christian Ethics, 450.
The Catholic Encyclopedia, s.v. “Gluttony,” by Joseph Delany (New York, NY:
18 23
Von Hildebrand, Nature of Love, 79.
Robert Appleton Company, 1909), http://www.newadvent.org/cathen/06590a.htm. 24
Von Hildebrand, Christian Ethics, 89, 417, 424.
48 The Metaphysics of Moral Values Marcus Otte 49
Proper accidents, on the other hand, are those that inhere in a sub- acts, they are proper accidents that inhere in the acts, and are not constitutive
stance in virtue of its essence, but are not included in the essence. The capac- of the essences of acts.19
ity to laugh is a typical example of an accident proper to man. This capacity is There is a second mode of existence to which an essence may be
a potentiality in every man, although circumstances, defect, or lack of devel- determined: namely, universality. Von Hildebrand does not overtly state that
opment might make it impossible to actualize. Despite such universality, this the quiddity of a value may exist as a universal concept. Nevertheless, there
characteristic does not belong to man’s essence. The ability to laugh is not is good reason to hold this was, in fact, his position. In Christian Ethics, he
part of the definition of man. Nevertheless, there is clearly an intelligible link makes references to knowledge as “the conforming of our intellect…to the
between man’s specific nature and his capacity for laughter. The potential to nature of a being.”20 This is the language of Scholasticism, in which the intel-
laugh does not inhere in man in the coincidental manner of height, color, etc. lect takes on the form of a contemplated object, albeit, according to the in-
When von Hildebrand denies that values have accidental being, his tellect’s mode of existence. To apply this account to the cognition of values:
depiction of accidents makes it clear he is referring to them in the typi- insofar as the intellect conforms to the nature of a contemplated value, the
cal sense: what Aquinas calls “accidents that are accidentally in the subject.” essence of that value is present to the intellect as a universal.
Such accidents do not have a necessary and intelligible link to the essences of
the beings they inhere in. But it is clear, to use a favorite example of von Hil-
debrand, that contrition cannot fail to exemplify goodness—positive value is IV. The Irradiation of Beauty
in contrition, and in a manner that is not merely accidental and factual.
Proper accidents, however, do possess such a necessary and intel- Von Hildebrand writes of a “metaphysical beauty” that irradiates from other
ligible link to their subjects. If values are properties, then they are proper values,21 and it is this beauty that will be discussed here. Moral values possess
accidents. It might be objected, however, that another alternative remains: an intrinsic beauty, not only goodness.22 This beauty is a value,23 and therefore
perhaps moral values are constitutive of the essences of acts. This would a real property. If our prior reasoning with respect to moral values is sound,
satisfy the conditions of necessity and intelligibility. Still, this latter option then it seems there are two possible ways moral beauty could exist in the
is not sensible, because it is possible to determinately refer to the species of world of singulars. First, such beauty might be a proper accident of a moral
acts without naming any value or disvalue. For example, adultery consists value, and thus, an accident of an accident. Second, moral beauty is possibly
in having relations with someone who is married and not one’s spouse, or an accident inhering in the act, but co-varying with values. There is a problem
having relations with someone who is not one’s spouse despite one being with this latter account, however. If moral beauty were merely a property of
married. Gluttony is indulgence in food in a manner either “too soon, too acts, and not of values, then we could contemplate the moral beauty of a
expensively, too much, too eagerly,” or “too daintily.”18 An act of contrition good act without any reference to a moral value. This is clearly not the case.
is sorrow for sin, together with the intent to confess and make satisfaction. Furthermore, von Hildebrand states explicitly that moral beauty is found
If, however, values and disvalues were constitutive of the essences of acts, it in moral values.24 It must be concluded then, that moral beauty inheres as a
would not be possible to determinately define an act according to its species proper accident in moral values.
without naming a value or disvalue. The very definition of adultery, for ex- It is important to note that moral beauty exists in varied forms. Each
ample, would need to name the disvalue of impurity. This is manifestly not moral value, such as purity or honesty, is beautiful in a specific manner. Like-
the case. The above definition provided for adultery successfully describes
all and only cases of adultery, and does so without naming a disvalue. The
same can be done for morally good acts and their values. Acts of feeding the 19
There are also values in characters and “concrete responses,” but in this
hungry, visiting the sick, burying the dead, instructing the ignorant, praying paper I am concerned only with characterizing the sphere of acts.
for the living and the dead, etc., can all be determinately defined according to
20
Von Hildebrand, Christian Ethics, 217.
species without naming a value. Thus, when values exist as singular things in
21
Alice von Hildebrand, “Debating Beauty: Jacques Maritain and Dietrich von
Hildebrand,” Crisis Magazine, July 1, 2004, http://www.crisismagazine.com/2004/
debating-beauty-jacques-maritain-and-dietrich-von-von Hildebrand-2.
22
Von Hildebrand, Christian Ethics, 450.
The Catholic Encyclopedia, s.v. “Gluttony,” by Joseph Delany (New York, NY:
18 23
Von Hildebrand, Nature of Love, 79.
Robert Appleton Company, 1909), http://www.newadvent.org/cathen/06590a.htm. 24
Von Hildebrand, Christian Ethics, 89, 417, 424.
50 The Metaphysics of Moral Values Marcus Otte 51
wise, moral disvalues possess a specific ugliness.25 This is congruous with intent. He does not treat the formal value of being as a property, but neither
moral beauty existing as a proper accident in diverse species of acts. The does he view it as simply identical and synonymous with being.
bundle of accidents each moral value possesses is congruous with the es- It is easy to see why the formal value of being cannot be a property,
sence of the value, since proper accidents have a necessary link with the though von Hildebrand does not say. Suppose this value is a property. If all
essence of the being they supervene upon. Indeed, for von Hildebrand the being has a formal value, then we need to ask if this value itself has being. If
metaphysical beauty, including the beauty of a moral value is an “expression the answer is yes, then the being of this value also has the property of having
of the essence” of the value.26 value, and so on infinitely. It would be necessary to posit an infinite number
of advening entities on any one entity. The only way to extricate ourselves
from this difficulty, while still upholding the value of being, is to erode the
V. Beauty and Good as Transcendentals difference between being and its value.
If the distinction between a being and its formal value is not real,
Von Hildebrand regards neither beauty nor good as coextensive with being. nor purely logical, then it is logical and virtual. The virtual distinction is the
Nevertheless, the rejection of these as transcendental is not essential to the product of the intellect but has a foundation in reality. A classic example is
theory of values in its entirety. One could very well accept the existence of in man’s essence. The essence is one thing. Still, it can be considered under
qualitative values (treating them as accidents, proper or otherwise) and main- the aspect of rationality or of animality, both of which can exist separately
tain virtually all of von Hildebrand’s treatment of value-responses, while also from each other, as they do in non-human creatures. The virtual distinction
holding that good and beauty transcend all genera. is further subdivided. In a major, or perfect, distinction, neither concept in
Not only is it possible to be deeply influenced by von Hildebrand question includes the other. The notion of rationality does not include that
while maintaining a Scholastic point of view on the transcendentals, it is also, of animality, nor vice versa, so these are virtually and perfectly distinct in
I will argue, advisable. Von Hildebrand’s rejection of the transcendental sta- man. In a minor, or imperfect virtual distinction, there is inclusion, as in the
tus of good and beauty poses a problem of coherence. This is so for a few case of “being” and “substance,” for instance.29 We can say that von Hildeb-
reasons. First, von Hildebrand posits a formal value of being. He refuses to rand’s notion of being includes its value because, whatever this value may be,
call this type of value a property. “We mean rather that, through philosophi- it is certainly not non-being. It ought to be concluded then, that if we are to
cal analysis, we can attain the insight that being as such possesses a distinctive formulate the relation between being and its value more precisely, the two are
value.”27 Von Hildebrand insists, “Every being possess a certain value insofar virtually and imperfectly distinct. For Thomists, being and the transcenden-
as it is something, as it is a being.”28 tals, such as good, are virtually and imperfectly distinct.30 At this point, we
But if this value is not a property, then what is it? Von Hildebrand can adduce that the formal value of being in von Hildebrandian philosophy,
is not clear. We can safely surmise that he holds no absolute, real distinction as well as that of good, ought to be considered a transcendental.
between a thing and its formal value as being. This level of distinction holds For von Hildebrand, to be a good is to have importance and to be
between, for example, a substance and its accidents. Is there, then, a real but able to motivate a value-response.31 We must say that the formal value of
modal distinction? This does not seem reasonable either. There is no sense in being is capable of eliciting such a response, since we see a response to this
treating the value of being as a mode of its existence. value in von Hildebrand himself. He writes of the “depth and grandeur” of
For a Thomist, this leaves only logical distinctions remaining. To say being, and of its “dignity and preciousness.”32 Since, then, the value of being
the distinction between a being and its formal value is purely logical would is a transcendental and is coextensive with being, all being must be good. But
be to say it is merely verbal: as in the difference between “human being” if all being is good, and necessarily so, then we have our conclusion: good is
and “rational animal.” This would be contrary to von Hildebrand’s obvious
29
Edward Feser, Scholastic Metaphysics: A Contemporary Introduction (Piscataway,
25
Ibid., 131–33. NJ: Transaction Books, 2014), 73.
26
Dietrich von Hildebrand, “Beauty in the Light of the Redemption,” Logos: 30
Reginald Garrigou-Lagrange, OP, The One God: A Commentary on the First
A Journal of Catholic Thought and Culture 4, no. 2 (2001): 78–92, accessed at https:// Part of St. Thomas’s Theological Summa, I.1–26, chap. 5, accessed at http://www.the-
novaearsvitae.org/the-necessity-of-beauty. summa.info/one/index.php.
27
Von Hildebrand, Christian Ethics, 146. 31
Von Hildebrand, Nature of Love, 79.
28
Ibid. 32
Von Hildebrand, Christian Ethics, 147–48.
50 The Metaphysics of Moral Values Marcus Otte 51
wise, moral disvalues possess a specific ugliness.25 This is congruous with intent. He does not treat the formal value of being as a property, but neither
moral beauty existing as a proper accident in diverse species of acts. The does he view it as simply identical and synonymous with being.
bundle of accidents each moral value possesses is congruous with the es- It is easy to see why the formal value of being cannot be a property,
sence of the value, since proper accidents have a necessary link with the though von Hildebrand does not say. Suppose this value is a property. If all
essence of the being they supervene upon. Indeed, for von Hildebrand the being has a formal value, then we need to ask if this value itself has being. If
metaphysical beauty, including the beauty of a moral value is an “expression the answer is yes, then the being of this value also has the property of having
of the essence” of the value.26 value, and so on infinitely. It would be necessary to posit an infinite number
of advening entities on any one entity. The only way to extricate ourselves
from this difficulty, while still upholding the value of being, is to erode the
V. Beauty and Good as Transcendentals difference between being and its value.
If the distinction between a being and its formal value is not real,
Von Hildebrand regards neither beauty nor good as coextensive with being. nor purely logical, then it is logical and virtual. The virtual distinction is the
Nevertheless, the rejection of these as transcendental is not essential to the product of the intellect but has a foundation in reality. A classic example is
theory of values in its entirety. One could very well accept the existence of in man’s essence. The essence is one thing. Still, it can be considered under
qualitative values (treating them as accidents, proper or otherwise) and main- the aspect of rationality or of animality, both of which can exist separately
tain virtually all of von Hildebrand’s treatment of value-responses, while also from each other, as they do in non-human creatures. The virtual distinction
holding that good and beauty transcend all genera. is further subdivided. In a major, or perfect, distinction, neither concept in
Not only is it possible to be deeply influenced by von Hildebrand question includes the other. The notion of rationality does not include that
while maintaining a Scholastic point of view on the transcendentals, it is also, of animality, nor vice versa, so these are virtually and perfectly distinct in
I will argue, advisable. Von Hildebrand’s rejection of the transcendental sta- man. In a minor, or imperfect virtual distinction, there is inclusion, as in the
tus of good and beauty poses a problem of coherence. This is so for a few case of “being” and “substance,” for instance.29 We can say that von Hildeb-
reasons. First, von Hildebrand posits a formal value of being. He refuses to rand’s notion of being includes its value because, whatever this value may be,
call this type of value a property. “We mean rather that, through philosophi- it is certainly not non-being. It ought to be concluded then, that if we are to
cal analysis, we can attain the insight that being as such possesses a distinctive formulate the relation between being and its value more precisely, the two are
value.”27 Von Hildebrand insists, “Every being possess a certain value insofar virtually and imperfectly distinct. For Thomists, being and the transcenden-
as it is something, as it is a being.”28 tals, such as good, are virtually and imperfectly distinct.30 At this point, we
But if this value is not a property, then what is it? Von Hildebrand can adduce that the formal value of being in von Hildebrandian philosophy,
is not clear. We can safely surmise that he holds no absolute, real distinction as well as that of good, ought to be considered a transcendental.
between a thing and its formal value as being. This level of distinction holds For von Hildebrand, to be a good is to have importance and to be
between, for example, a substance and its accidents. Is there, then, a real but able to motivate a value-response.31 We must say that the formal value of
modal distinction? This does not seem reasonable either. There is no sense in being is capable of eliciting such a response, since we see a response to this
treating the value of being as a mode of its existence. value in von Hildebrand himself. He writes of the “depth and grandeur” of
For a Thomist, this leaves only logical distinctions remaining. To say being, and of its “dignity and preciousness.”32 Since, then, the value of being
the distinction between a being and its formal value is purely logical would is a transcendental and is coextensive with being, all being must be good. But
be to say it is merely verbal: as in the difference between “human being” if all being is good, and necessarily so, then we have our conclusion: good is
and “rational animal.” This would be contrary to von Hildebrand’s obvious
29
Edward Feser, Scholastic Metaphysics: A Contemporary Introduction (Piscataway,
25
Ibid., 131–33. NJ: Transaction Books, 2014), 73.
26
Dietrich von Hildebrand, “Beauty in the Light of the Redemption,” Logos: 30
Reginald Garrigou-Lagrange, OP, The One God: A Commentary on the First
A Journal of Catholic Thought and Culture 4, no. 2 (2001): 78–92, accessed at https:// Part of St. Thomas’s Theological Summa, I.1–26, chap. 5, accessed at http://www.the-
novaearsvitae.org/the-necessity-of-beauty. summa.info/one/index.php.
27
Von Hildebrand, Christian Ethics, 146. 31
Von Hildebrand, Nature of Love, 79.
28
Ibid. 32
Von Hildebrand, Christian Ethics, 147–48.
52 The Metaphysics of Moral Values Marcus Otte 53
a transcendental. Good is not synonymous with, but is nevertheless coexten- possible objection, however: von Hildebrand asserts many different aesthetic
sive with being. values besides beauty, such as loveliness, gloriousness, or grandeur.45 If beau-
Granted, von Hildebrand downplays the value of being in compar- ty is a property and only one of many properties in the aesthetic sphere, then
ison to other values. The value of being as such is so formal, he points out, it is not transcendental.
that we are only made aware of it in philosophy33 and in a few moral situa- Von Hildebrand is not altogether clear on the relation between the
tions.34 Thus, apart from its ontological or qualitative values, any being is, “in values in the aesthetic sphere. He claims that the various aesthetic values
a certain way,” neutral, and we are justified in treating it as neutral.35 “center around the basic value of beauty.”46 But what is meant by “center
This belief in neutral being, however, is fraught with difficulty. If around”? He provides his clearest description as follows:
value is the important-in-itself, and all being has value, albeit of different Such [mutually] exclusive qualities therefore are both positive val-
kinds and degrees, then there is no neutral being. There is just analogical ues, in most cases even belonging to the same value domain. Ma-
importance. It is true that qualitative or ontological values will tend to over- jestic grandeur and delicate loveliness are both aesthetic values,
shadow the value of being in itself, but this is consistent with good being each a different dimension of a unitary beauty. Far from being
transcendental and predicated analogically across different categories. antagonistic to one another in the sense of qualitative incompat-
There is also good reason, given von Hildebrand’s theory of values, ibility or hostile contrast, both are, on the contrary, messengers
to regard beauty as transcendental. Beauty is manifested in differing ways of one and the same absolute beauty, completing instead of com-
across different kinds of being. It is present in art36 and music,37 as well as in bating each other.47
landscapes.38 Intelligence is also beautiful.39 There is a beauty that man has as
such40 and souls.41 Moral beauty is present in good actions.42 And Christ has

Beauty, then, embraces each of the aesthetic values in the sense that
divine beauty43 to which a devout person responds with supernatural charity. each one is a facet of beauty, or a way beauty may be manifested. The exis-
That beauty exists in each of these does not directly entail that beauty is a tence of multiple types of aesthetic values, then, could not form a basis for
transcendental. But if beauty is a transcendental, it should exist in all these rejecting beauty as a transcendental.
things.44 Moving on to the most serious consideration in favor of beauty as a
There are stronger considerations to be found in von Hildebrand’s transcendental, we need to refer to von Hildebrand’s description of the gen-
philosophy in favor of beauty as a transcendental. First we should note a eral value of being. He ascribes “grandeur”48 to being as such. This is else-
where treated as an aesthetic quality.49 He also writes of the “intrinsic beauty
33
Ibid., 146. and splendor” of value.50 It is completely congruous with his treatment of
34
Ibid., 148–49. the formal value of being to extend this description, “beauty and splendor,”
35
Ibid., 149. to such value, if even to an inferior degree. So, whether we are speaking of
36
Ibid., 124. being as such or the general value of being, beauty may be rightly ascribed to
37
Ibid. it. This entails that beauty is transcendental.
38
Ibid., 234. Why, then, does von Hildebrand not concede that either good or
39
Ibid., 105. beauty really is coextensive with being? The most important reason is be-
40
Ibid., 458. cause he holds there is, not merely neutral being, but positively existing dis-
41
Ibid., 235.
value. Good and beauty cannot be transcendental if there are things that owe
42
Ibid., 343.
43
Ibid., 234.
their evilness to evil being and not merely evil privation.51
44
The notion that beauty is a transcendental is, I acknowledge, a matter of
controversy among Thomists, as well as others of Scholastic persuasion. There is 45
Von Hildebrand, Christian Ethics, 130.
also dispute as to whether St. Thomas himself considered beauty a transcenden- 46
Ibid.
tal. Jacques Maritain argues he did (see Maritain, “Art and Beauty,” chap. 5 in Art 47
Ibid., 141–42.
and Scholasticism, trans. Joseph W. Evans, accessed at https://www3.nd.edu/De- 48
Ibid., 147.
partments/Maritain/etext/art5.htm); Jan Aastsen contends otherwise (see Aastsen, 49
Ibid., 141.
“Beauty in the Middle Ages: A Forgotten Transcendental?” Medieval Philosophy and 50
Ibid., 37.
Theology 1 [1991]: 68–91). 51
Ibid., 142–43.
52 The Metaphysics of Moral Values Marcus Otte 53
a transcendental. Good is not synonymous with, but is nevertheless coexten- possible objection, however: von Hildebrand asserts many different aesthetic
sive with being. values besides beauty, such as loveliness, gloriousness, or grandeur.45 If beau-
Granted, von Hildebrand downplays the value of being in compar- ty is a property and only one of many properties in the aesthetic sphere, then
ison to other values. The value of being as such is so formal, he points out, it is not transcendental.
that we are only made aware of it in philosophy33 and in a few moral situa- Von Hildebrand is not altogether clear on the relation between the
tions.34 Thus, apart from its ontological or qualitative values, any being is, “in values in the aesthetic sphere. He claims that the various aesthetic values
a certain way,” neutral, and we are justified in treating it as neutral.35 “center around the basic value of beauty.”46 But what is meant by “center
This belief in neutral being, however, is fraught with difficulty. If around”? He provides his clearest description as follows:
value is the important-in-itself, and all being has value, albeit of different Such [mutually] exclusive qualities therefore are both positive val-
kinds and degrees, then there is no neutral being. There is just analogical ues, in most cases even belonging to the same value domain. Ma-
importance. It is true that qualitative or ontological values will tend to over- jestic grandeur and delicate loveliness are both aesthetic values,
shadow the value of being in itself, but this is consistent with good being each a different dimension of a unitary beauty. Far from being
transcendental and predicated analogically across different categories. antagonistic to one another in the sense of qualitative incompat-
There is also good reason, given von Hildebrand’s theory of values, ibility or hostile contrast, both are, on the contrary, messengers
to regard beauty as transcendental. Beauty is manifested in differing ways of one and the same absolute beauty, completing instead of com-
across different kinds of being. It is present in art36 and music,37 as well as in bating each other.47
landscapes.38 Intelligence is also beautiful.39 There is a beauty that man has as
such40 and souls.41 Moral beauty is present in good actions.42 And Christ has

Beauty, then, embraces each of the aesthetic values in the sense that
divine beauty43 to which a devout person responds with supernatural charity. each one is a facet of beauty, or a way beauty may be manifested. The exis-
That beauty exists in each of these does not directly entail that beauty is a tence of multiple types of aesthetic values, then, could not form a basis for
transcendental. But if beauty is a transcendental, it should exist in all these rejecting beauty as a transcendental.
things.44 Moving on to the most serious consideration in favor of beauty as a
There are stronger considerations to be found in von Hildebrand’s transcendental, we need to refer to von Hildebrand’s description of the gen-
philosophy in favor of beauty as a transcendental. First we should note a eral value of being. He ascribes “grandeur”48 to being as such. This is else-
where treated as an aesthetic quality.49 He also writes of the “intrinsic beauty
33
Ibid., 146. and splendor” of value.50 It is completely congruous with his treatment of
34
Ibid., 148–49. the formal value of being to extend this description, “beauty and splendor,”
35
Ibid., 149. to such value, if even to an inferior degree. So, whether we are speaking of
36
Ibid., 124. being as such or the general value of being, beauty may be rightly ascribed to
37
Ibid. it. This entails that beauty is transcendental.
38
Ibid., 234. Why, then, does von Hildebrand not concede that either good or
39
Ibid., 105. beauty really is coextensive with being? The most important reason is be-
40
Ibid., 458. cause he holds there is, not merely neutral being, but positively existing dis-
41
Ibid., 235.
value. Good and beauty cannot be transcendental if there are things that owe
42
Ibid., 343.
43
Ibid., 234.
their evilness to evil being and not merely evil privation.51
44
The notion that beauty is a transcendental is, I acknowledge, a matter of
controversy among Thomists, as well as others of Scholastic persuasion. There is 45
Von Hildebrand, Christian Ethics, 130.
also dispute as to whether St. Thomas himself considered beauty a transcenden- 46
Ibid.
tal. Jacques Maritain argues he did (see Maritain, “Art and Beauty,” chap. 5 in Art 47
Ibid., 141–42.
and Scholasticism, trans. Joseph W. Evans, accessed at https://www3.nd.edu/De- 48
Ibid., 147.
partments/Maritain/etext/art5.htm); Jan Aastsen contends otherwise (see Aastsen, 49
Ibid., 141.
“Beauty in the Middle Ages: A Forgotten Transcendental?” Medieval Philosophy and 50
Ibid., 37.
Theology 1 [1991]: 68–91). 51
Ibid., 142–43.
54 The Metaphysics of Moral Values Marcus Otte 55
VI. Evil and Privation therefore such things admit of more or less according to the difference of
that which is said in a positive manner.”57
Von Hildebrand’s conception of disvalue is, indeed, not compatible with The reality of moral evil, then, includes both a privative and positive
good and beauty being transcendental. It may not be appreciated, however, aspect. An immoral act is marked by privation inasmuch as it lacks a due
just how close his understanding of evil is to that of the medieval Scholastics. ordination to the agent’s rightful end. While sin is not non-being, it may be
I wish to highlight these similarities now, again pointing to Aquinas. called non-being with respect to its being an act that is lacking in due excel-
With respect to moral evil, Aquinas does not regard evil as a mere lence, and also with respect to its depriving an agent of internal goods, both
lack. He, in fact, makes mention of ancient Stoics who held that moral evil is natural and supernatural. Viewed in its privative aspect, evil in human action
only a privation.52 These philosophers were misled because they defined the is caused by a defect in the act of the will: a deliberate inattention to a moral
turpitude of an evil act in terms of its merely falling outside the bounds of rule.58
reason. For example, adultery was condemned by them not because inter- The positive element of an immoral act’s evil consists in its oppo-
course with a woman besides one’s wife is blameworthy in itself, but solely sition to a moral rule. Privation alone cannot specify an act of wrongdoing
because such an act lacks the rectitude required by reason.53 “since only a positive principle can give content to actions.”59 It is in virtue of
Aquinas offers two considerations against the notion of pure pri- an act’s form that it is the kind of act it is. Furthermore, as has been noted,
vation in moral evil. First, privation need not consist in the total absence of only something positive can stand in a relation of contrariety. Therefore, the
something. There is, on one hand, such a thing as pure privation. Death is positive aspect of an act’s evil is prior to its privative aspect. It is because of
a complete absence of a life, for example. But there is also mixed privation, what an act is in itself that it is lacking in rightful order.
which coexists with positive being that is affected by the lack. Such privation St. Thomas’s morality, then, is not ultimately founded upon the “ob-
is not merely contradictory, but contrary.54 Notably, to be contrary to, and not jective good” of the agent in the way some modern Thomists understand.
merely contradict positive value is, for von Hildebrand, essential to negative Of the two aspects that constitute the evil of an immoral act, the positive
value.55 element “is more essential to the intelligibility (ratio) of moral evil.”60 The
Having made this distinction, Aquinas moves on to his second con- privative dimension is founded upon this positive aspect. An act is defective
sideration: that the Stoic understanding of evil runs roughshod over import- and turns an agent away from its natural end because it is contrary to a moral
ant knowledge we have that differentiates evil by degrees. If the Stoic were rule, not vice versa. Murder is malum in se and intrinsically opposed to reason.
correct, then an adulterer, for example, would sin only inasmuch as he ab- Thus, the murderer is cut off from his own flourishing.61
stains from acting reasonably. But if every sin were evil in this way, then sins For anyone familiar with von Hildebrand’s understanding of evil, the
could not be distinguished by degree, since each would be evil simply owing similarities should be obvious. First, and most importantly, von Hildebrand
to a privation. Aquinas draws an analogy with death, which is a pure lack: a emphasizes that positive value is prior to the natural end of a creature, and
man is equally dead whether his death is the result of being stabbed once or a likewise that an immoral act is immoral apart from any consideration of its
few times.56 If we are to distinguish between degrees of moral evil in various thwarting a creature from its end. If an act is wicked, it is for this reason that
acts, we can only do so by reference to their positive aspects. In mixed pri- it deprives a creature of its objective good.62
vations that include positive aspects “what is said of it [a thing] in a positive Both von Hildebrand and Aquinas hold that moral evil is contrary,
way pertains to the nature of that which is said of it in a privative way: and not merely contradictory, to the good.63 Both hold that evil is always willed
under the aspect of a good (if even not a moral good). Evil cannot be willed

52
Gregory M. Reichberg, “Beyond Privation: Moral Evil in Aquinas’s De 57
Ibid.
Malo,” The Review of Metaphysics 55, no. 4 (2002): 756. 58
Reichberg, “Beyond Privation,” 761.
53
Thomas Aquinas, On Evil, q. 2, a. 9, trans. John A. Oesterle and Jean T. 59
Ibid., 760.
Oesterle (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1995). 60
Ibid., 757
54
Reichberg, “Beyond Privation,” 756; Aquinas, On Evil, q. 2 a. 9. 61
Ibid.
55
Von Hildebrand, Christian Ethics, 142–43. 62
Von Hildebrand, Christian Ethics, 57.
56
Aquinas, On Evil, q. 2 a. 9. 63
Ibid., 26, 140; Aquinas, On Evil, q. 1, a. 1, ad. 4.
54 The Metaphysics of Moral Values Marcus Otte 55
VI. Evil and Privation therefore such things admit of more or less according to the difference of
that which is said in a positive manner.”57
Von Hildebrand’s conception of disvalue is, indeed, not compatible with The reality of moral evil, then, includes both a privative and positive
good and beauty being transcendental. It may not be appreciated, however, aspect. An immoral act is marked by privation inasmuch as it lacks a due
just how close his understanding of evil is to that of the medieval Scholastics. ordination to the agent’s rightful end. While sin is not non-being, it may be
I wish to highlight these similarities now, again pointing to Aquinas. called non-being with respect to its being an act that is lacking in due excel-
With respect to moral evil, Aquinas does not regard evil as a mere lence, and also with respect to its depriving an agent of internal goods, both
lack. He, in fact, makes mention of ancient Stoics who held that moral evil is natural and supernatural. Viewed in its privative aspect, evil in human action
only a privation.52 These philosophers were misled because they defined the is caused by a defect in the act of the will: a deliberate inattention to a moral
turpitude of an evil act in terms of its merely falling outside the bounds of rule.58
reason. For example, adultery was condemned by them not because inter- The positive element of an immoral act’s evil consists in its oppo-
course with a woman besides one’s wife is blameworthy in itself, but solely sition to a moral rule. Privation alone cannot specify an act of wrongdoing
because such an act lacks the rectitude required by reason.53 “since only a positive principle can give content to actions.”59 It is in virtue of
Aquinas offers two considerations against the notion of pure pri- an act’s form that it is the kind of act it is. Furthermore, as has been noted,
vation in moral evil. First, privation need not consist in the total absence of only something positive can stand in a relation of contrariety. Therefore, the
something. There is, on one hand, such a thing as pure privation. Death is positive aspect of an act’s evil is prior to its privative aspect. It is because of
a complete absence of a life, for example. But there is also mixed privation, what an act is in itself that it is lacking in rightful order.
which coexists with positive being that is affected by the lack. Such privation St. Thomas’s morality, then, is not ultimately founded upon the “ob-
is not merely contradictory, but contrary.54 Notably, to be contrary to, and not jective good” of the agent in the way some modern Thomists understand.
merely contradict positive value is, for von Hildebrand, essential to negative Of the two aspects that constitute the evil of an immoral act, the positive
value.55 element “is more essential to the intelligibility (ratio) of moral evil.”60 The
Having made this distinction, Aquinas moves on to his second con- privative dimension is founded upon this positive aspect. An act is defective
sideration: that the Stoic understanding of evil runs roughshod over import- and turns an agent away from its natural end because it is contrary to a moral
ant knowledge we have that differentiates evil by degrees. If the Stoic were rule, not vice versa. Murder is malum in se and intrinsically opposed to reason.
correct, then an adulterer, for example, would sin only inasmuch as he ab- Thus, the murderer is cut off from his own flourishing.61
stains from acting reasonably. But if every sin were evil in this way, then sins For anyone familiar with von Hildebrand’s understanding of evil, the
could not be distinguished by degree, since each would be evil simply owing similarities should be obvious. First, and most importantly, von Hildebrand
to a privation. Aquinas draws an analogy with death, which is a pure lack: a emphasizes that positive value is prior to the natural end of a creature, and
man is equally dead whether his death is the result of being stabbed once or a likewise that an immoral act is immoral apart from any consideration of its
few times.56 If we are to distinguish between degrees of moral evil in various thwarting a creature from its end. If an act is wicked, it is for this reason that
acts, we can only do so by reference to their positive aspects. In mixed pri- it deprives a creature of its objective good.62
vations that include positive aspects “what is said of it [a thing] in a positive Both von Hildebrand and Aquinas hold that moral evil is contrary,
way pertains to the nature of that which is said of it in a privative way: and not merely contradictory, to the good.63 Both hold that evil is always willed
under the aspect of a good (if even not a moral good). Evil cannot be willed

52
Gregory M. Reichberg, “Beyond Privation: Moral Evil in Aquinas’s De 57
Ibid.
Malo,” The Review of Metaphysics 55, no. 4 (2002): 756. 58
Reichberg, “Beyond Privation,” 761.
53
Thomas Aquinas, On Evil, q. 2, a. 9, trans. John A. Oesterle and Jean T. 59
Ibid., 760.
Oesterle (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1995). 60
Ibid., 757
54
Reichberg, “Beyond Privation,” 756; Aquinas, On Evil, q. 2 a. 9. 61
Ibid.
55
Von Hildebrand, Christian Ethics, 142–43. 62
Von Hildebrand, Christian Ethics, 57.
56
Aquinas, On Evil, q. 2 a. 9. 63
Ibid., 26, 140; Aquinas, On Evil, q. 1, a. 1, ad. 4.
56 The Metaphysics of Moral Values Marcus Otte 57
altogether for its own sake.64 Also, both characterize sin as the choice of a causality? Owing to the absence of formal and final causes of evil, there is
lower good rather than a higher, obligatory one (excepting some special con- not a per se efficient cause of evil either. Such a thing would be unintelligi-
siderations by which, von Hildebrand points out, a lower good may be oblig- ble.73 It follows, then, that evil must be caused per accidens. If we narrow the
atory rather than a higher one).65 Finally, von Hildebrand argues that, despite scope of the discussion from evil in general to moral evil to say it is caused
possessing the general value of being and even ontological values, qualitative per accidens, it follows that evil is never chosen purely for its own sake, but
disvalues can confer an overall negative importance upon beings.66 Consid- always under the aspect of at least an apparent good. If good is coextensive
ered in itself, a sinful deed is something that ought not exist, despite whatever with being, then evil can only be chosen per accidens. Aristotelian metaphysics
good might be derived from it. Similarly, Aquinas holds that, though possess- provides an account as to why it is strictly impossible to choose evil for itself,
ing the good of being, sinful acts must be accounted evils,67 even if they can but it is difficult to see how von Hildebrand’s theory of values, on its own,
possess a natural perfection as acts.68 could do the same.
Despite all this, the differences between Aquinas and von Hildeb-
rand on the nature of evil remain irreducible. From the point of view of
moral science evil has a positive element for St. Thomas, while ontologically VII. Ugliness and Privation
speaking it does not.69 There is no real evil being, except inasmuch as real
subjects are evil due to a privation of order. Von Hildebrand, on the other Aquinas writes little on ugliness directly. Von Hildebrand also seldom men-
hand, insists that evil possesses real being, both within and outside the moral tions ugliness, at least in his works that are available in English. It is clear,
sphere, owing to qualitative disvalues that are real and not privative.70 however, that von Hildebrand regards ugliness as an accident.74 He also, as
I will not attempt to offer a developed argument for the Thomist Alice von Hildebrand points out, insists that “ugliness isn’t just an absence of
position, since this takes us far afield from my principal thesis. Nevertheless, beauty but wages war on it.”75 This is true whether we consider the metaphys-
I do wish to make an observation in passing. The most serious dilemma von ical beauty that is the splendor of value or the beauty of form that visible
Hildebrand’s position faces is that it exacerbates the problem of evil and even and audible things may exhibit. Aquinas, not surprisingly, treats ugliness as
renders it fatal. If moral evil is a real property with positive being, and is not privative.76 He must do so, since he regards beauty as transcendental.77 How-
a lack, then how can it be said that God is not the author of evil?71 There is ever, to be ugly is not a pure privation but is a matter of degree.78 Recall that,
another difficulty. Von Hildebrand notes we cannot will anything that is ut- for Aquinas, mixed privations are contrary to and not merely contradictory
terly neutral or negative in importance.72 Precisely why this is impossible, he to their opposites. So Aquinas is in agreement with von Hildebrand that the
does not say. The claim appears to rest on phenomenological reflection. ugly is in opposition to beauty. Hence, whereas beauty delights,79 ugliness
Thomism, however, provides us the resources to metaphysically ac- repulses.80 Things may be physically81 or morally82 ugly.
count for why evil cannot be willed merely for evil. That this is so can be
explained according to the doctrine of the four causes. If evil consists in
73
Feser, Scholastic Metaphysics, 91–100; 148–54.
74
Von Hildebrand, Christian Ethics, 153–54.
disorder, that is, in a privation of form, then it does not have a formal cause. 75
Alice von Hildebrand, “Debating Beauty.”
Privation just is an absence of due form. Without form, neither can a thing 76
Thomas Aquinas, Commentary on Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, trans. C.J.
have a final cause. Evil must, however, have a material cause since, were there Litzinger, OP (Notre Dame, IN: Dumb Ox Books, 1993), n320; Aquinas, ST I, q. 39,
no substrate, there would be nothing to suffer privation. What of efficient a. 8.
77
Once again, I acknowledge there is controversy as to whether beauty is a
64
Von Hildebrand, Christian Ethics, 306; Aquinas, ST I-II, q. 8, a. 1. transcendental for St. Thomas. At the very least, he regards it as intrinsically related
65
Von Hildebrand, Christian Ethics, 380–83; Aquinas, ST I-II, q. 75, a. 1. to the good.
66
Von Hildebrand, Christian Ethics, 154–55. 78
Thomas Aquinas, Summa Contra Gentiles III.139.15, trans. Vernon J. Bourke
67
Aquinas, ST I-II, q. 18, a. 1; Aquinas, On Evil, q. 1, a. 3. (New York, NY: Hanover House, 1957), accessed at http://dhspriory.org/thomas/
68
Aquinas, ST I-II, q. 75, a. 4, ad. 2. ContraGentiles3b.htm#139.
69
Reichberg, “Beyond Privation,” 760–61. 79
Aquinas, ST I, q. 5, a. 4, ad. 1.
70
Von Hildebrand, Christian Ethics, 23. 80
Ibid., II-II, q. 158, a. 4, ad. 1.
71
Ibid., 18, 26. 81
Ibid., I-II, q. 81, a. 1.
72
Ibid., 306. 82
Ibid., II-II, q. 158, a. 4, arg. 1.
56 The Metaphysics of Moral Values Marcus Otte 57
altogether for its own sake.64 Also, both characterize sin as the choice of a causality? Owing to the absence of formal and final causes of evil, there is
lower good rather than a higher, obligatory one (excepting some special con- not a per se efficient cause of evil either. Such a thing would be unintelligi-
siderations by which, von Hildebrand points out, a lower good may be oblig- ble.73 It follows, then, that evil must be caused per accidens. If we narrow the
atory rather than a higher one).65 Finally, von Hildebrand argues that, despite scope of the discussion from evil in general to moral evil to say it is caused
possessing the general value of being and even ontological values, qualitative per accidens, it follows that evil is never chosen purely for its own sake, but
disvalues can confer an overall negative importance upon beings.66 Consid- always under the aspect of at least an apparent good. If good is coextensive
ered in itself, a sinful deed is something that ought not exist, despite whatever with being, then evil can only be chosen per accidens. Aristotelian metaphysics
good might be derived from it. Similarly, Aquinas holds that, though possess- provides an account as to why it is strictly impossible to choose evil for itself,
ing the good of being, sinful acts must be accounted evils,67 even if they can but it is difficult to see how von Hildebrand’s theory of values, on its own,
possess a natural perfection as acts.68 could do the same.
Despite all this, the differences between Aquinas and von Hildeb-
rand on the nature of evil remain irreducible. From the point of view of
moral science evil has a positive element for St. Thomas, while ontologically VII. Ugliness and Privation
speaking it does not.69 There is no real evil being, except inasmuch as real
subjects are evil due to a privation of order. Von Hildebrand, on the other Aquinas writes little on ugliness directly. Von Hildebrand also seldom men-
hand, insists that evil possesses real being, both within and outside the moral tions ugliness, at least in his works that are available in English. It is clear,
sphere, owing to qualitative disvalues that are real and not privative.70 however, that von Hildebrand regards ugliness as an accident.74 He also, as
I will not attempt to offer a developed argument for the Thomist Alice von Hildebrand points out, insists that “ugliness isn’t just an absence of
position, since this takes us far afield from my principal thesis. Nevertheless, beauty but wages war on it.”75 This is true whether we consider the metaphys-
I do wish to make an observation in passing. The most serious dilemma von ical beauty that is the splendor of value or the beauty of form that visible
Hildebrand’s position faces is that it exacerbates the problem of evil and even and audible things may exhibit. Aquinas, not surprisingly, treats ugliness as
renders it fatal. If moral evil is a real property with positive being, and is not privative.76 He must do so, since he regards beauty as transcendental.77 How-
a lack, then how can it be said that God is not the author of evil?71 There is ever, to be ugly is not a pure privation but is a matter of degree.78 Recall that,
another difficulty. Von Hildebrand notes we cannot will anything that is ut- for Aquinas, mixed privations are contrary to and not merely contradictory
terly neutral or negative in importance.72 Precisely why this is impossible, he to their opposites. So Aquinas is in agreement with von Hildebrand that the
does not say. The claim appears to rest on phenomenological reflection. ugly is in opposition to beauty. Hence, whereas beauty delights,79 ugliness
Thomism, however, provides us the resources to metaphysically ac- repulses.80 Things may be physically81 or morally82 ugly.
count for why evil cannot be willed merely for evil. That this is so can be
explained according to the doctrine of the four causes. If evil consists in
73
Feser, Scholastic Metaphysics, 91–100; 148–54.
74
Von Hildebrand, Christian Ethics, 153–54.
disorder, that is, in a privation of form, then it does not have a formal cause. 75
Alice von Hildebrand, “Debating Beauty.”
Privation just is an absence of due form. Without form, neither can a thing 76
Thomas Aquinas, Commentary on Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, trans. C.J.
have a final cause. Evil must, however, have a material cause since, were there Litzinger, OP (Notre Dame, IN: Dumb Ox Books, 1993), n320; Aquinas, ST I, q. 39,
no substrate, there would be nothing to suffer privation. What of efficient a. 8.
77
Once again, I acknowledge there is controversy as to whether beauty is a
64
Von Hildebrand, Christian Ethics, 306; Aquinas, ST I-II, q. 8, a. 1. transcendental for St. Thomas. At the very least, he regards it as intrinsically related
65
Von Hildebrand, Christian Ethics, 380–83; Aquinas, ST I-II, q. 75, a. 1. to the good.
66
Von Hildebrand, Christian Ethics, 154–55. 78
Thomas Aquinas, Summa Contra Gentiles III.139.15, trans. Vernon J. Bourke
67
Aquinas, ST I-II, q. 18, a. 1; Aquinas, On Evil, q. 1, a. 3. (New York, NY: Hanover House, 1957), accessed at http://dhspriory.org/thomas/
68
Aquinas, ST I-II, q. 75, a. 4, ad. 2. ContraGentiles3b.htm#139.
69
Reichberg, “Beyond Privation,” 760–61. 79
Aquinas, ST I, q. 5, a. 4, ad. 1.
70
Von Hildebrand, Christian Ethics, 23. 80
Ibid., II-II, q. 158, a. 4, ad. 1.
71
Ibid., 18, 26. 81
Ibid., I-II, q. 81, a. 1.
72
Ibid., 306. 82
Ibid., II-II, q. 158, a. 4, arg. 1.
58 The Metaphysics of Moral Values Marcus Otte 59
Von Hildebrand and Aquinas treat the relation between beauty and The existence of evil in a world created and ruled by an absolute-
good differently. For Aquinas, both are a matter of form. Beauty and good ly wise, absolutely powerful, and infinitely good God will always
differ logically and in aspect, but not really.83 Beauty is characterized by “in- remain an inscrutable mystery. Should we therefore deny the exis-
tegrity” or “perfection,” “proportion” or “harmony,” and “brightness” or tence of evil in order to escape from this dilemma? Or should we
“clarity.”84 In other words, a thing has beauty inasmuch as it is “in act,” in deny the existence of God, because of the indubitable existence
harmony with what it ought to be, and has the radiance of form.85 A thing is of evil? No, we must have the courage to say: I see something
ugly insofar as it lacks something it ought to have, and thus, is not integral; with absolute certitude, and I also see something else with abso-
or is disordered in a manner that will tend to thwart it from its good end; or lute certitude. I shall adhere to both even if I know not how they
does not shine forth in its nature, because it fails, in a manner of speaking, to can be reconciled.88
be what it is.
There is, of course, sense in this methodology. The rightful certitude
Von Hildebrand, on the other hand, regards a being as good inas- we have of two given facts ought to confer on us a certainty these facts are
much as it possesses value, and beauty is the chief aesthetic value. Ugliness compatible, even prior to us seeing how this might be. Nevertheless, this is
is not a defect, but a real property in itself with positive existence: it is an not enough to rebut the criticisms that have been offered against von Hil-
aesthetic disvalue. What considerations might help us decide between these debrand’s ontology of disvalue. It is evident there are ugly and evil things.
two accounts of the ugly? There are both methodological and metaphysical But how we ought to metaphysically characterize ugliness and evilness is not
points to consider. so immediately evident. Thomism and other standard Scholasticisms offer
One crucial argument in favor of the Thomistic position is that, descriptions of ugliness and evilness that are reconcilable with other accept-
first, since Aquinas treats ugliness as privative, he avoids giving it a per se cause ed truths (e.g., that God is Pure Act, that God is both good and sovereign,
and thus can account for why God ought not be called a cause of ugliness. that all beings except God are made and sustained by God, etc.). Unless a
Second, von Hildebrand’s ontology of ugliness can be charged with incoher- follower of von Hildebrand’s theory of disvalue can offer a similar account,
ence. If being has a splendor in itself—in its formal value, as von Hildebrand this weighs decisively in favor of a Scholastic understanding.
says—then it seems a privative account of ugliness is the only viable option.
If we simultaneously accept the formal value of being and the positive exis-
tence of aesthetic disvalue, then we are forced to speak of the splendor and VIII. Conclusion
majesty of a disvalue. In other words, we must attribute some measure of
beauty, not merely to ugly things, but to ugliness itself. But this is a contradic- Von Hildebrand’s value ontology remains in conflict with Scholasticism.
tion. As to whether beauty and good are transcendentals, there appears to be no
Von Hildebrand’s ontology of evilness and ugliness is motivated, reconciliation possible—only a fight to the finish. On some other matters,
in large part, by methodological concerns. Von Hildebrand emphasizes that however, there is much space for these conflicting outlooks to complement
“the nature of a datum which is given to us must take precedence over the ef- one another. Scholasticism provides time-tested concepts that are immensely
fort to bring the nature of this being into harmony with formerly discovered, helpful in building subtle and rigorous metaphysical theses. At the same time,
indubitable data.”86 Our primary worry should be to preserve knowledge of von Hildebrand offers keen insights into the moral and aesthetic dimensions
“the immediately given datum”87 and other indubitable truths. Harmonizing of life and the centrality of personhood, as well as, arguably, the most saga-
these is a secondary task. Thus, von Hildebrand writes: cious account of spiritual affectivity yet proposed.
The conflict between von Hildebrandian and Scholastic metaphysics
83
Ibid., I, q. 5, a. 4, ad. 1; ibid., I-II, q. 27, a. 1, ad. 3. is traceable, in part, to the differing concerns that motivate each ontology.
84
Jenna Henry, “It Is What It Is: Beauty, Act, and Perfection: A Thomistic The problems that arise from Parmenides’s axiom that “from nothing, noth-
Approach,” (Paper presented at the Annual Franciscan University Conference on
ing comes,” are very salient for St. Thomas as well as the Scholastics in gen-
Christian Philosophy, “The Power of Beauty,” co-sponsored with the Dietrich von
eral. Scholastic metaphysics is founded upon those aspects of reality that are
Hildebrand Legacy Project, Steubenville, OH, October 2014), 3–4.
85
Ibid., 4–5. needed to explain change and being, and to even provide an ultimate explana-
86
Von Hildebrand, Christian Ethics, 16.
87
Ibid. 88
Ibid., 18.
58 The Metaphysics of Moral Values Marcus Otte 59
Von Hildebrand and Aquinas treat the relation between beauty and The existence of evil in a world created and ruled by an absolute-
good differently. For Aquinas, both are a matter of form. Beauty and good ly wise, absolutely powerful, and infinitely good God will always
differ logically and in aspect, but not really.83 Beauty is characterized by “in- remain an inscrutable mystery. Should we therefore deny the exis-
tegrity” or “perfection,” “proportion” or “harmony,” and “brightness” or tence of evil in order to escape from this dilemma? Or should we
“clarity.”84 In other words, a thing has beauty inasmuch as it is “in act,” in deny the existence of God, because of the indubitable existence
harmony with what it ought to be, and has the radiance of form.85 A thing is of evil? No, we must have the courage to say: I see something
ugly insofar as it lacks something it ought to have, and thus, is not integral; with absolute certitude, and I also see something else with abso-
or is disordered in a manner that will tend to thwart it from its good end; or lute certitude. I shall adhere to both even if I know not how they
does not shine forth in its nature, because it fails, in a manner of speaking, to can be reconciled.88
be what it is.
There is, of course, sense in this methodology. The rightful certitude
Von Hildebrand, on the other hand, regards a being as good inas- we have of two given facts ought to confer on us a certainty these facts are
much as it possesses value, and beauty is the chief aesthetic value. Ugliness compatible, even prior to us seeing how this might be. Nevertheless, this is
is not a defect, but a real property in itself with positive existence: it is an not enough to rebut the criticisms that have been offered against von Hil-
aesthetic disvalue. What considerations might help us decide between these debrand’s ontology of disvalue. It is evident there are ugly and evil things.
two accounts of the ugly? There are both methodological and metaphysical But how we ought to metaphysically characterize ugliness and evilness is not
points to consider. so immediately evident. Thomism and other standard Scholasticisms offer
One crucial argument in favor of the Thomistic position is that, descriptions of ugliness and evilness that are reconcilable with other accept-
first, since Aquinas treats ugliness as privative, he avoids giving it a per se cause ed truths (e.g., that God is Pure Act, that God is both good and sovereign,
and thus can account for why God ought not be called a cause of ugliness. that all beings except God are made and sustained by God, etc.). Unless a
Second, von Hildebrand’s ontology of ugliness can be charged with incoher- follower of von Hildebrand’s theory of disvalue can offer a similar account,
ence. If being has a splendor in itself—in its formal value, as von Hildebrand this weighs decisively in favor of a Scholastic understanding.
says—then it seems a privative account of ugliness is the only viable option.
If we simultaneously accept the formal value of being and the positive exis-
tence of aesthetic disvalue, then we are forced to speak of the splendor and VIII. Conclusion
majesty of a disvalue. In other words, we must attribute some measure of
beauty, not merely to ugly things, but to ugliness itself. But this is a contradic- Von Hildebrand’s value ontology remains in conflict with Scholasticism.
tion. As to whether beauty and good are transcendentals, there appears to be no
Von Hildebrand’s ontology of evilness and ugliness is motivated, reconciliation possible—only a fight to the finish. On some other matters,
in large part, by methodological concerns. Von Hildebrand emphasizes that however, there is much space for these conflicting outlooks to complement
“the nature of a datum which is given to us must take precedence over the ef- one another. Scholasticism provides time-tested concepts that are immensely
fort to bring the nature of this being into harmony with formerly discovered, helpful in building subtle and rigorous metaphysical theses. At the same time,
indubitable data.”86 Our primary worry should be to preserve knowledge of von Hildebrand offers keen insights into the moral and aesthetic dimensions
“the immediately given datum”87 and other indubitable truths. Harmonizing of life and the centrality of personhood, as well as, arguably, the most saga-
these is a secondary task. Thus, von Hildebrand writes: cious account of spiritual affectivity yet proposed.
The conflict between von Hildebrandian and Scholastic metaphysics
83
Ibid., I, q. 5, a. 4, ad. 1; ibid., I-II, q. 27, a. 1, ad. 3. is traceable, in part, to the differing concerns that motivate each ontology.
84
Jenna Henry, “It Is What It Is: Beauty, Act, and Perfection: A Thomistic The problems that arise from Parmenides’s axiom that “from nothing, noth-
Approach,” (Paper presented at the Annual Franciscan University Conference on
ing comes,” are very salient for St. Thomas as well as the Scholastics in gen-
Christian Philosophy, “The Power of Beauty,” co-sponsored with the Dietrich von
eral. Scholastic metaphysics is founded upon those aspects of reality that are
Hildebrand Legacy Project, Steubenville, OH, October 2014), 3–4.
85
Ibid., 4–5. needed to explain change and being, and to even provide an ultimate explana-
86
Von Hildebrand, Christian Ethics, 16.
87
Ibid. 88
Ibid., 18.
60 The Metaphysics of Moral Values Marcus Otte 61
tion of being. Von Hildebrand’s philosophy is not indifferent to such matters. fundamentally and undermined the very possibility of natural or theological
Thus, he rebuts relativist views that deny objective being to the good and knowledge. The defense of the intelligibility of all reality was at the heart of
beautiful,89 and he locates the ultimate explanation of the good and beau- the great Scholastic syntheses.
tiful in God.90 Von Hildebrand’s principal focus, however, is to accentuate It would, of course, be an abject falsehood to reduce each of these
those features of persons that are marginalized by eudaemonistic accounts: ways of thinking to mere products of their times. They are products of ge-
in particular, self-transcendence and eigenleben, or subjectivity.91 The world of nius and piety, first and foremost. But they also have contexts that partly
values is the arena in which these traits of personhood are manifested—most account for them. If we had to summarize the distinction between von Hil-
importantly in the ethical and relational spheres. Von Hildebrand’s ontology debrand and, for instance, St. Thomas, with respect to their theories of good
of values is grounded in his exposition of value-responses. Most fundamen- and beauty, perhaps this is the most succinct way: von Hildebrand construed
tally, his philosophy begins with reflection on those aspects of reality that these qualities more Platonically (at least inasmuch as he rejected the notion
are presented to us in value-responses, as opposed to reflection on so-called that they are coextensive with being), emphasizing the transcendent in an age
“neutral” metaphysical facts. which often marginalized it, whereas Aquinas thought of good and beauty in
To push the point further, we could recall that, as Alasdair MacIntyre a more Aristotelian manner, securing the value of immanent realities that had
has said, a Catholic is not simply a Catholic, but is always a Catholic rather been de-emphasized or even demonized by others.
than something else.92 St. Augustine was a Catholic rather than a Pelagian or This essay has pointed out some routes to a partial fusion of these
a Manichean; St. Francis de Sales was a Catholic rather than a Calvinist; etc. traditions. If proponents of values wish to rescue von Hildebrand’s philoso-
The deposit of faith remains the same, but its articulation differs across the phy from its internal contradictions, their ontologies need to incorporate the
ages, in large part due to the diversity of errors it must confront. Dietrich transcendentals and a privative understanding of evil. Thus, the basic archi-
von Hildebrand lived in a time when the supernatural was derogated and the tecture of Scholastic metaphysics ought to be highly commended to them.
norms of morality were relativized. His response could hardly have contra- Although the doctrine of the transcendentals begins with Aristotle, and the
dicted these trends more directly; the theory of values makes moral goodness privative view of evil first explicitly emerges with Neoplatonism, nowhere
itself into an objective, non-natural property. Likewise, in a Europe where are these so well developed as within Scholastic thought.
totalitarian thinking lionized the state, von Hildebrand upheld the smaller Approaching this synthesis from the opposite direction, if the Scho-
communities of family and friendship. Where Nazism expounded on pride lastic is to refer to values, he must identify a place for them in his ontology, or
and the will-to-power, he wrote on love and beauty. His approach to moder- else build one. With respect to the values of actions we have identified such
nity, however, was not merely contrarian. This comes through most clearly a place—they are proper accidents supervening on acts. The key question for
in his adoption of a phenomenological method rather than Neo-Scholastic the Scholastic is whether von Hildebrand’s account of value-responses justi-
dialectic. fies belief in values. This itself is largely a question as to whether a phenom-
The princes of Scholasticism, on the other hand, lived in the after- enological method can provide insights into metaphysics (and meta-ethics)
math of Albigensianism. Hence, the doctrine of the goodness of creation that are not readily available through more traditional approaches.
was highly important for them. This was a factor in the ultimate acceptance
of Aristotelian modes of thought. The Scholastics also confronted Averro- —Boston College
ism, the occasionalism of some Muslim thinkers, and Maimonides’s theory
of equivocity. Each of these, in its own way, threatened truth or rationality
89
Von Hildebrand, Christian Ethics, 106–28.
90
Ibid., 187, 222.
91
Hildebrand, The Nature of Love, 200, 205–6.
92
Alasdair MacIntyre, “Catholic Instead of What?” YouTube video, Mac-
Intyre’s presentation from the Notre Dame Center for Ethics and Culture’s thirteenth
annual Fall Conference: “The Crowning Glory of the Virtues: Exploring the Many
Facets of Justice,” posted by “Notre Dame Center For Ethics and Culture - ( ndeth-
ics,” August 22, 2014, https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=TXpjzulHsuA.
60 The Metaphysics of Moral Values Marcus Otte 61
tion of being. Von Hildebrand’s philosophy is not indifferent to such matters. fundamentally and undermined the very possibility of natural or theological
Thus, he rebuts relativist views that deny objective being to the good and knowledge. The defense of the intelligibility of all reality was at the heart of
beautiful,89 and he locates the ultimate explanation of the good and beau- the great Scholastic syntheses.
tiful in God.90 Von Hildebrand’s principal focus, however, is to accentuate It would, of course, be an abject falsehood to reduce each of these
those features of persons that are marginalized by eudaemonistic accounts: ways of thinking to mere products of their times. They are products of ge-
in particular, self-transcendence and eigenleben, or subjectivity.91 The world of nius and piety, first and foremost. But they also have contexts that partly
values is the arena in which these traits of personhood are manifested—most account for them. If we had to summarize the distinction between von Hil-
importantly in the ethical and relational spheres. Von Hildebrand’s ontology debrand and, for instance, St. Thomas, with respect to their theories of good
of values is grounded in his exposition of value-responses. Most fundamen- and beauty, perhaps this is the most succinct way: von Hildebrand construed
tally, his philosophy begins with reflection on those aspects of reality that these qualities more Platonically (at least inasmuch as he rejected the notion
are presented to us in value-responses, as opposed to reflection on so-called that they are coextensive with being), emphasizing the transcendent in an age
“neutral” metaphysical facts. which often marginalized it, whereas Aquinas thought of good and beauty in
To push the point further, we could recall that, as Alasdair MacIntyre a more Aristotelian manner, securing the value of immanent realities that had
has said, a Catholic is not simply a Catholic, but is always a Catholic rather been de-emphasized or even demonized by others.
than something else.92 St. Augustine was a Catholic rather than a Pelagian or This essay has pointed out some routes to a partial fusion of these
a Manichean; St. Francis de Sales was a Catholic rather than a Calvinist; etc. traditions. If proponents of values wish to rescue von Hildebrand’s philoso-
The deposit of faith remains the same, but its articulation differs across the phy from its internal contradictions, their ontologies need to incorporate the
ages, in large part due to the diversity of errors it must confront. Dietrich transcendentals and a privative understanding of evil. Thus, the basic archi-
von Hildebrand lived in a time when the supernatural was derogated and the tecture of Scholastic metaphysics ought to be highly commended to them.
norms of morality were relativized. His response could hardly have contra- Although the doctrine of the transcendentals begins with Aristotle, and the
dicted these trends more directly; the theory of values makes moral goodness privative view of evil first explicitly emerges with Neoplatonism, nowhere
itself into an objective, non-natural property. Likewise, in a Europe where are these so well developed as within Scholastic thought.
totalitarian thinking lionized the state, von Hildebrand upheld the smaller Approaching this synthesis from the opposite direction, if the Scho-
communities of family and friendship. Where Nazism expounded on pride lastic is to refer to values, he must identify a place for them in his ontology, or
and the will-to-power, he wrote on love and beauty. His approach to moder- else build one. With respect to the values of actions we have identified such
nity, however, was not merely contrarian. This comes through most clearly a place—they are proper accidents supervening on acts. The key question for
in his adoption of a phenomenological method rather than Neo-Scholastic the Scholastic is whether von Hildebrand’s account of value-responses justi-
dialectic. fies belief in values. This itself is largely a question as to whether a phenom-
The princes of Scholasticism, on the other hand, lived in the after- enological method can provide insights into metaphysics (and meta-ethics)
math of Albigensianism. Hence, the doctrine of the goodness of creation that are not readily available through more traditional approaches.
was highly important for them. This was a factor in the ultimate acceptance
of Aristotelian modes of thought. The Scholastics also confronted Averro- —Boston College
ism, the occasionalism of some Muslim thinkers, and Maimonides’s theory
of equivocity. Each of these, in its own way, threatened truth or rationality
89
Von Hildebrand, Christian Ethics, 106–28.
90
Ibid., 187, 222.
91
Hildebrand, The Nature of Love, 200, 205–6.
92
Alasdair MacIntyre, “Catholic Instead of What?” YouTube video, Mac-
Intyre’s presentation from the Notre Dame Center for Ethics and Culture’s thirteenth
annual Fall Conference: “The Crowning Glory of the Virtues: Exploring the Many
Facets of Justice,” posted by “Notre Dame Center For Ethics and Culture - ( ndeth-
ics,” August 22, 2014, https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=TXpjzulHsuA.
Linus Meldrum 63

Beauty as Anomaly: in the beginning was the eye, not the word.”1 Postmodernism has been a
movement pre-occupied with deconstructing words, rejecting meta-narra-
Why Does the Bush Not Burn Up? tives, revising and reinventing history at will, ignoring traditions built from
scholarship and building “new traditions” of disparate bits of contemporary
distractive fascinations. The result, sadly, is that most of postmodern visual
Linus Meldrum art relies on many, many words to complete the “picture” for the viewer. This
condition demotes the visual to simply the visible; the literal now rules the
Meanwhile Moses was tending the flock of his father-in-law Je- realm of meaning.
thro, the priest of Midian. Leading the flock beyond the wilder- Can we renew the sense of a “visual contract” between artist and
ness, he came to the mountain of God, Horeb. There the angel viewer, to really know the mind of a truly visual artist? Can we regain what
of the LORD appeared to him as fire flaming out of a bush. has been lost, missed, or ignored in recent decades? If so, we must look—
When he looked, although the bush was on fire, it was not being and look hard. We must point ourselves to a seeing, not just a telling; we must
consumed. So Moses decided, “I must turn aside to look at this return to the primal act of knowing visual meaning by visual means. This vi-
remarkable sight. Why does the bush not burn up?” When the sual knowing is not a naming and cataloging of objects. This knowing desires
LORD saw that he had turned aside to look, God called out to identities for which there are no names. This kind of identity exists where
him from the bush: Moses! Moses! He answered, “Here I am.” nameable things gather and interact, but anomaly, a sparkling instrument of
the composer, lives between and among nameable objects and qualifies the
—Exod. 3:1–4 experience in a paradoxical way. Anomaly is something that cannot be, but
is—the bush that burns but is not consumed. Anomaly shakes the viewer
We are in a tenuous position. We desire a renewal of Beauty, but we struggle awake. Once the viewer is awakened, the artist has the opportunity to form
to get the party started. We are in disarray. We appear to have a willing cohort, the visual narrative as an experience of, not an illustration of, the subject—an
but there is no concise theory that guides us. Many of us have concise theo- incarnation as something you know with your eyes.
ries that contradict each other; are we Art Sedevacantists, believing that all of Let us consider visual examples that reorient our seeing. If the sur-
contemporary media is illicit, or are we Postmodern Pilgrims, walking a per- prise and mystery of anomaly is to be fruitful, let us return to tradition to
ilous path upon which Truth is obscured by layers of despair and disbelief ? see where Visual Art encountered the bridge to the Modern world. Visual
Most of us have grown up in a time when personal preference trumps formal modernism fully ripens at the end of the nineteenth century—a last gasp of
rules. In our culture, our aesthetic sensibilities cannot help but be affected energy that stamps all of art history with a seal of sorts. Apart from Monet
by a concept that began long ago as “Beauty is in the eye of the beholder” at Giverny, what came after 1900 began a certain process of dissipation.
and eventually morphed into a narcissistic motto for the art-makers of today: What makes this last fever of the old order so important is that the classi-
“That’s the way I roll.” cally trained minds of the artists found themselves encountering, or being
Vision, the sense by which we absorb much of the material world, hit on the forehead with, visual experiences that were largely dismissed by
is the necessary material pathway. However, the visible is not the same as the the artists of previous generations. It is not that previous artists did not see
visual. While the visible is taken in as data, the conveyance of meaning, partic- these contradictory new ideas as they looked at the world, manipulated their
ularly aesthetic meaning, means that the “stuff ” has been transformed by the materials, and looked at the images arriving from the work of their hands: it
mysterious action of the imagination. This transformation awakens the mind is impossible to believe that no artist before Cezanne ever experienced the
to visual narrative, an image-story that requires not words or names but re- time-enlarging wonderment of multiple viewpoints expressed in a single im-
lationships that precede the literal. A quote from Otto Pacht, twentieth cen-
tury Austrian art historian, helps to clarify: “[where] art history is concerned,
1
From Pächt’s series of lectures in 1970–1971, see Otto Pächt, Methodisches
zur kunsthistorischen Praxis (Als Vorlesung and der Universität Wien, gehalten im Win-
tersemester, 1970–1971), in Pächt, Methodisches zur kunsthistorischen Praxis, ed. Jorg
Oberhaidacher, Arthur Rosenauer, and Gertraut Schikola (Munich: Prestel-Verlag,
1997); published in English as Otto Pächt, The Practice of Art History: Reflections on
© Linus Meldrum, Quaestiones Disputatae, Vol. 6, No. 2 (Spring 2016)
Method, trans. David Britt (London: Harvey Miller, 1999).
Linus Meldrum 63

Beauty as Anomaly: in the beginning was the eye, not the word.”1 Postmodernism has been a
movement pre-occupied with deconstructing words, rejecting meta-narra-
Why Does the Bush Not Burn Up? tives, revising and reinventing history at will, ignoring traditions built from
scholarship and building “new traditions” of disparate bits of contemporary
distractive fascinations. The result, sadly, is that most of postmodern visual
Linus Meldrum art relies on many, many words to complete the “picture” for the viewer. This
condition demotes the visual to simply the visible; the literal now rules the
Meanwhile Moses was tending the flock of his father-in-law Je- realm of meaning.
thro, the priest of Midian. Leading the flock beyond the wilder- Can we renew the sense of a “visual contract” between artist and
ness, he came to the mountain of God, Horeb. There the angel viewer, to really know the mind of a truly visual artist? Can we regain what
of the LORD appeared to him as fire flaming out of a bush. has been lost, missed, or ignored in recent decades? If so, we must look—
When he looked, although the bush was on fire, it was not being and look hard. We must point ourselves to a seeing, not just a telling; we must
consumed. So Moses decided, “I must turn aside to look at this return to the primal act of knowing visual meaning by visual means. This vi-
remarkable sight. Why does the bush not burn up?” When the sual knowing is not a naming and cataloging of objects. This knowing desires
LORD saw that he had turned aside to look, God called out to identities for which there are no names. This kind of identity exists where
him from the bush: Moses! Moses! He answered, “Here I am.” nameable things gather and interact, but anomaly, a sparkling instrument of
the composer, lives between and among nameable objects and qualifies the
—Exod. 3:1–4 experience in a paradoxical way. Anomaly is something that cannot be, but
is—the bush that burns but is not consumed. Anomaly shakes the viewer
We are in a tenuous position. We desire a renewal of Beauty, but we struggle awake. Once the viewer is awakened, the artist has the opportunity to form
to get the party started. We are in disarray. We appear to have a willing cohort, the visual narrative as an experience of, not an illustration of, the subject—an
but there is no concise theory that guides us. Many of us have concise theo- incarnation as something you know with your eyes.
ries that contradict each other; are we Art Sedevacantists, believing that all of Let us consider visual examples that reorient our seeing. If the sur-
contemporary media is illicit, or are we Postmodern Pilgrims, walking a per- prise and mystery of anomaly is to be fruitful, let us return to tradition to
ilous path upon which Truth is obscured by layers of despair and disbelief ? see where Visual Art encountered the bridge to the Modern world. Visual
Most of us have grown up in a time when personal preference trumps formal modernism fully ripens at the end of the nineteenth century—a last gasp of
rules. In our culture, our aesthetic sensibilities cannot help but be affected energy that stamps all of art history with a seal of sorts. Apart from Monet
by a concept that began long ago as “Beauty is in the eye of the beholder” at Giverny, what came after 1900 began a certain process of dissipation.
and eventually morphed into a narcissistic motto for the art-makers of today: What makes this last fever of the old order so important is that the classi-
“That’s the way I roll.” cally trained minds of the artists found themselves encountering, or being
Vision, the sense by which we absorb much of the material world, hit on the forehead with, visual experiences that were largely dismissed by
is the necessary material pathway. However, the visible is not the same as the the artists of previous generations. It is not that previous artists did not see
visual. While the visible is taken in as data, the conveyance of meaning, partic- these contradictory new ideas as they looked at the world, manipulated their
ularly aesthetic meaning, means that the “stuff ” has been transformed by the materials, and looked at the images arriving from the work of their hands: it
mysterious action of the imagination. This transformation awakens the mind is impossible to believe that no artist before Cezanne ever experienced the
to visual narrative, an image-story that requires not words or names but re- time-enlarging wonderment of multiple viewpoints expressed in a single im-
lationships that precede the literal. A quote from Otto Pacht, twentieth cen-
tury Austrian art historian, helps to clarify: “[where] art history is concerned,
1
From Pächt’s series of lectures in 1970–1971, see Otto Pächt, Methodisches
zur kunsthistorischen Praxis (Als Vorlesung and der Universität Wien, gehalten im Win-
tersemester, 1970–1971), in Pächt, Methodisches zur kunsthistorischen Praxis, ed. Jorg
Oberhaidacher, Arthur Rosenauer, and Gertraut Schikola (Munich: Prestel-Verlag,
1997); published in English as Otto Pächt, The Practice of Art History: Reflections on
© Linus Meldrum, Quaestiones Disputatae, Vol. 6, No. 2 (Spring 2016)
Method, trans. David Britt (London: Harvey Miller, 1999).
64 Beauty as Anomaly Linus Meldrum 65
age. Actually knowing what is “going on” in Velazquez’s Las Meninas was, and it may be important to consumers of images and the visual philosophers who
is, as much of a challenge as following the narrative in Christopher Nolan’s are artists.
film Inception: both are conceptual—and visual—puzzles within puzzles. A
door was opening into a new frontier at the turn of the century, and some
artists kept inventing while continuing to work under the previous contract. Anomaly and Its Significance
In 1979, during a private conversation, New York School artist
George McNeil (1908–1995) described to several of us the understanding If we consider an anomaly not only as a peculiarity, but a “situated” pecu-
and manipulation of space by artists in the timeline of history. At first there liarity, we can understand it as something that requires—that is, demands—a
was no space, just a surface as in prehistoric cave painting. Then there was viewer’s attention. Like the Burning Bush, it magnetizes the air of the imagi-
the development of illusionistic space culminating in the highly specific Re- nation: visual identities begin to modify each other in striking combinations.
naissance conception of perspectival images that set the tone for generations The kind of anomaly I want you to consider is not a non sequitur, it is not a
to come. After centuries of artists manipulating one, two, and three point disturbance that simply interrupts the flow of expected reality by being ran-
perspective, Cezanne and a few others gave us the “New” Space—imag- dom and unexpected. It is not simply a surprise (or a simple “didn’t see that
es that combined different points of view in a single image. This thinking coming”). The phenomenon I am considering is a cultured (i.e., “cooked
gave us Cubism and eventually abstraction, including total abstraction, an up”) identity. It “comes from” something. Or, better yet, from someone. The
abandonment of the figure, the object, gravity, and the visual facts of the viewer’s interest is drawn along in a way that might compel the viewer to
material world. Needing a new tradition to revolt against, artists in the later feel comfortable only up to a point, after which questions begin to drive the
twentieth century pushed forward into what McNeil called the “New” New viewer’s imagination to desire to know something that might only be found
Space. These artists produced novel images that had no spatial rationale. In in the creator’s mind.
some cases, they negated space as a concept. They also pirated random visual To see this phenomenon in its environment, consider the following
ideas about space and used them aggressively, whimsically, and nonsensically. short list of examples of anomaly at work in painted images.
Often, artists chose to depict a literal or completely non-visual narrative, as in
painting words on a canvas. This made many of the images of contemporary
art subject-rich but visually poor. This poverty was not a lack of optical sen- Anomaly in the Renaissance World of Piero della Francesca
sations. While there may be pyrotechnical excitement, the narrative content
was better understood when talked about, rather than consumed, digested In the early twentieth century, artists became attracted to the strange and
and understood through the act of seeing. In other words, this kind of art- complex visual constructions of the Early Renaissance artist Piero della
work needed lots of explanation. Francesca. (fig. 1)
This challenge to visual narrative has persisted into the postmodern
era. As Visual Art status has been granted to non-visual meaning, the back-
ground for learning what Art is about has changed. While this heterodox
background can yield a teachable curriculum, it is also a distraction from
what Visual Art has always been good at: incarnating ineffable yet visually
concrete expressions of important subjects.
While there is much to ponder in the complexity of these conflicts,
we can cut through this Gordian knot by a return to seeing as the starting
point for understanding. As we look at an image, we can ask: how does it
“speak visually”? What makes the image visually distinctive? What makes it
“look back” at us? Let us examine visual anomaly as the “opening door” that
Fig. (1) Piero Della Francesca, The Finding and Proving of the True Cross
some artists have used, and can use, to invite us past the names of objects,
the names of colors, and the superficial literal references. Let us consider why Given that Piero was a math-driven perfectionist, and in light of the fact that
this image indicates an aspect of highly intentional poses and figure place-
64 Beauty as Anomaly Linus Meldrum 65
age. Actually knowing what is “going on” in Velazquez’s Las Meninas was, and it may be important to consumers of images and the visual philosophers who
is, as much of a challenge as following the narrative in Christopher Nolan’s are artists.
film Inception: both are conceptual—and visual—puzzles within puzzles. A
door was opening into a new frontier at the turn of the century, and some
artists kept inventing while continuing to work under the previous contract. Anomaly and Its Significance
In 1979, during a private conversation, New York School artist
George McNeil (1908–1995) described to several of us the understanding If we consider an anomaly not only as a peculiarity, but a “situated” pecu-
and manipulation of space by artists in the timeline of history. At first there liarity, we can understand it as something that requires—that is, demands—a
was no space, just a surface as in prehistoric cave painting. Then there was viewer’s attention. Like the Burning Bush, it magnetizes the air of the imagi-
the development of illusionistic space culminating in the highly specific Re- nation: visual identities begin to modify each other in striking combinations.
naissance conception of perspectival images that set the tone for generations The kind of anomaly I want you to consider is not a non sequitur, it is not a
to come. After centuries of artists manipulating one, two, and three point disturbance that simply interrupts the flow of expected reality by being ran-
perspective, Cezanne and a few others gave us the “New” Space—imag- dom and unexpected. It is not simply a surprise (or a simple “didn’t see that
es that combined different points of view in a single image. This thinking coming”). The phenomenon I am considering is a cultured (i.e., “cooked
gave us Cubism and eventually abstraction, including total abstraction, an up”) identity. It “comes from” something. Or, better yet, from someone. The
abandonment of the figure, the object, gravity, and the visual facts of the viewer’s interest is drawn along in a way that might compel the viewer to
material world. Needing a new tradition to revolt against, artists in the later feel comfortable only up to a point, after which questions begin to drive the
twentieth century pushed forward into what McNeil called the “New” New viewer’s imagination to desire to know something that might only be found
Space. These artists produced novel images that had no spatial rationale. In in the creator’s mind.
some cases, they negated space as a concept. They also pirated random visual To see this phenomenon in its environment, consider the following
ideas about space and used them aggressively, whimsically, and nonsensically. short list of examples of anomaly at work in painted images.
Often, artists chose to depict a literal or completely non-visual narrative, as in
painting words on a canvas. This made many of the images of contemporary
art subject-rich but visually poor. This poverty was not a lack of optical sen- Anomaly in the Renaissance World of Piero della Francesca
sations. While there may be pyrotechnical excitement, the narrative content
was better understood when talked about, rather than consumed, digested In the early twentieth century, artists became attracted to the strange and
and understood through the act of seeing. In other words, this kind of art- complex visual constructions of the Early Renaissance artist Piero della
work needed lots of explanation. Francesca. (fig. 1)
This challenge to visual narrative has persisted into the postmodern
era. As Visual Art status has been granted to non-visual meaning, the back-
ground for learning what Art is about has changed. While this heterodox
background can yield a teachable curriculum, it is also a distraction from
what Visual Art has always been good at: incarnating ineffable yet visually
concrete expressions of important subjects.
While there is much to ponder in the complexity of these conflicts,
we can cut through this Gordian knot by a return to seeing as the starting
point for understanding. As we look at an image, we can ask: how does it
“speak visually”? What makes the image visually distinctive? What makes it
“look back” at us? Let us examine visual anomaly as the “opening door” that
Fig. (1) Piero Della Francesca, The Finding and Proving of the True Cross
some artists have used, and can use, to invite us past the names of objects,
the names of colors, and the superficial literal references. Let us consider why Given that Piero was a math-driven perfectionist, and in light of the fact that
this image indicates an aspect of highly intentional poses and figure place-
66 Beauty as Anomaly Linus Meldrum 67
ment, we can assume that nothing is present in this image by accident. This in ways that are strange, right to the point of creating a sense of anomaly.
continuous narrative, playing across the stage of the image, is a story from The Finding and Proving of the True Cross is not a scene of a natural event.
the thirteenth century Golden Legend of Jacob de Voragine, which brings the Under the direction of Charles Blance, full-size facsimiles of Piero’s
viewer to the Holy Land with St. Helena searching for the True Cross. artwork in Arezzo were made by Charles Loyeux and brought to the Ecole
How does Piero tell us that the persistent St. Helena has the Cross des Beaux Arts in Paris in 1873 as teaching instruments in the Musee des Copies.
on her mind (fig. 2)? One of these images was the Finding and Proving of the True Cross.

The Image World of Georges Seurat

George Seurat (1859–1891) was a French painter and draughtsman of the


late nineteenth century. Along with Vincent Van Gogh, Paul Cezanne, and
others, he is part of the Art Historical group called the Neo-Impressionists.
Seurat is the artist who created the remarkable painting, Sunday After-
noon on the Isle of La Grande Jatte c1884 (fig. 3).

Fig. (2) St. Helena from The Finding and Proving of the True Cross

In Piero’s visual imagination, the Cross springs from her head. The narrative then
flows to the right and the True Cross is “proven” by resurrecting a dead
youth at the right side of the continuous narrative. The horizontal member
of the True Cross ends this visual journey by embedding itself into the face
of the man with the blue funnel hat, in a group of figures of authority who
Fig. (3) Georges Seurat, Sunday Afternoon on the Isle of La Grande Jatte
are “receiving” the news. At various stopping points across the image, visual
elements hook together by adjacencies (i.e., the crosses almost, but not quite,
touch), coincidental spatial layering (i.e., the joining of the left column of Famous enough to have a Broadway musical built from it, it is a unique and
the temple and the shoulder of the lady-in-waiting), and a sense of exacting, mysterious image hiding inside an almost cartoon-like look at the society of
and nearly abstract, geometry (i.e., the temple appears more as a concert of fin-de-siècle Paris. While there are many little visual puns, spatial leaps, and
shapes than as three-dimensional architecture). These examples (and a view- twists in this image (all very inventive, the relationship to Piero’s True Cross
er’s continued investigation will reveal more of them) are intended to accom- image is evident—the visual narrative is highly organized. Seurat, enrolled in
plish a satisfaction of Piero’s insistence on the unity of pictorial and literary the Ecole des Beaux Arts, had the opportunity to study Piero’s designs as early
narrative. The forms do more than fill the page. In comparison to the works as 1876 at the age of seventeen, absorbing some of Piero’s love of heraldic
of other artists of the Early Renaissance, Piero’s forms are fitted to the page parading and figuration layered over geometric formations.
66 Beauty as Anomaly Linus Meldrum 67
ment, we can assume that nothing is present in this image by accident. This in ways that are strange, right to the point of creating a sense of anomaly.
continuous narrative, playing across the stage of the image, is a story from The Finding and Proving of the True Cross is not a scene of a natural event.
the thirteenth century Golden Legend of Jacob de Voragine, which brings the Under the direction of Charles Blance, full-size facsimiles of Piero’s
viewer to the Holy Land with St. Helena searching for the True Cross. artwork in Arezzo were made by Charles Loyeux and brought to the Ecole
How does Piero tell us that the persistent St. Helena has the Cross des Beaux Arts in Paris in 1873 as teaching instruments in the Musee des Copies.
on her mind (fig. 2)? One of these images was the Finding and Proving of the True Cross.

The Image World of Georges Seurat

George Seurat (1859–1891) was a French painter and draughtsman of the


late nineteenth century. Along with Vincent Van Gogh, Paul Cezanne, and
others, he is part of the Art Historical group called the Neo-Impressionists.
Seurat is the artist who created the remarkable painting, Sunday After-
noon on the Isle of La Grande Jatte c1884 (fig. 3).

Fig. (2) St. Helena from The Finding and Proving of the True Cross

In Piero’s visual imagination, the Cross springs from her head. The narrative then
flows to the right and the True Cross is “proven” by resurrecting a dead
youth at the right side of the continuous narrative. The horizontal member
of the True Cross ends this visual journey by embedding itself into the face
of the man with the blue funnel hat, in a group of figures of authority who
Fig. (3) Georges Seurat, Sunday Afternoon on the Isle of La Grande Jatte
are “receiving” the news. At various stopping points across the image, visual
elements hook together by adjacencies (i.e., the crosses almost, but not quite,
touch), coincidental spatial layering (i.e., the joining of the left column of Famous enough to have a Broadway musical built from it, it is a unique and
the temple and the shoulder of the lady-in-waiting), and a sense of exacting, mysterious image hiding inside an almost cartoon-like look at the society of
and nearly abstract, geometry (i.e., the temple appears more as a concert of fin-de-siècle Paris. While there are many little visual puns, spatial leaps, and
shapes than as three-dimensional architecture). These examples (and a view- twists in this image (all very inventive, the relationship to Piero’s True Cross
er’s continued investigation will reveal more of them) are intended to accom- image is evident—the visual narrative is highly organized. Seurat, enrolled in
plish a satisfaction of Piero’s insistence on the unity of pictorial and literary the Ecole des Beaux Arts, had the opportunity to study Piero’s designs as early
narrative. The forms do more than fill the page. In comparison to the works as 1876 at the age of seventeen, absorbing some of Piero’s love of heraldic
of other artists of the Early Renaissance, Piero’s forms are fitted to the page parading and figuration layered over geometric formations.
68 Beauty as Anomaly Linus Meldrum 69
One then sees a visual inheritance residing in La Gande Jatte, in its still- we see that the upper tree trunk and the man are linked by their size, darkness
ness (even stiffness), its measured sense of exactitude and a calling to mind and proximity on the surface of the paper. The tree is part of nature, or “in
of Piero’s St. Helena. In fact, a specific and striking association to the True the ground,” and at the same time, it is “joined” to the distant man. What
Cross image is found within the image. (fig. 4) does the image visually cue? I suggest a form of dual nature, something akin
to hypostasis. The tree restlessly asserts and reasserts its inconceivability. Be-
cause of this, the drawing has no “end.” It recharges itself and perpetuates a
sense of an impossible visual narrative fitted to a scene that references nature
but poeticizes and transcends it—an anomaly.

Fig. (4) Seated Man (with Top Hat) and Tree from La Grande Jatte

In figure 4, we see a man with a tree springing from his head, itself an oddity,
if not an anomaly, which sets up a question: what was on that man’s mind?
Fig. (5) Georges Seurat, Tree and Man
Seurat is using something of the method of Piero here, guiding us toward
an encounter of something miraculous. To see the development of this con-
Seurat is a marvelous draughtsman who, in drawing with conté cray-
struction, we can look to one of the hundreds of drawings and oil sketches
on on rough paper, focused almost exclusively on finding the monochromatic
for the mural size Grande Jatte. The one to consider is the one that focuses
equivalent of the kind of color luminosity that he had developed in his poin-
on the tree that has “sprung” from the seated man (fig. 5). The conté crayon
tillist painting method in La Grande Jatte. Pointillism relies on small bits of
drawing is Seurat’s study and confirmation of a puzzle. What the tree does is
color laid side by side in a painting, sympathizing and antagonizing, optically
a distinct and startling anomaly.
mixing to produce a color experience in the eye of the viewer that more truly
The drawing is actually a refinement of something that plays only
matches the experience of color light in nature. Pointillism was a purposeful,
a minor part in the complete painting. The drawing is absolutely purposeful
sometimes systematic, extension of the Impressionist revolution of the pre-
and intended to “do something” to the mind of the viewer. This is not a
vious decades in France and elsewhere. But this drawing reveals something
picture. The drawing is carefully formed as a narrative spatial experience. Seurat
other than luminosity; the drawing reveals Seurat’s encounter with something
likely experienced a fleeting moment of seeing a man standing on the bank
in nature and his design response. His drawing proposes an anomaly—the
of the island who happened to be, in the view of the artist, almost behind the
impossible tree is living in two places at once. While this is a precursory
tree. The tree that starts its upward journey in “our space” ends its journey
example of the upcoming modernist concern with space and form on the
“paired” with the man on the distant bank. As the tree diminishes in diameter
two-dimensional surface, it is also, in one complete moment, a recapitulation
68 Beauty as Anomaly Linus Meldrum 69
One then sees a visual inheritance residing in La Gande Jatte, in its still- we see that the upper tree trunk and the man are linked by their size, darkness
ness (even stiffness), its measured sense of exactitude and a calling to mind and proximity on the surface of the paper. The tree is part of nature, or “in
of Piero’s St. Helena. In fact, a specific and striking association to the True the ground,” and at the same time, it is “joined” to the distant man. What
Cross image is found within the image. (fig. 4) does the image visually cue? I suggest a form of dual nature, something akin
to hypostasis. The tree restlessly asserts and reasserts its inconceivability. Be-
cause of this, the drawing has no “end.” It recharges itself and perpetuates a
sense of an impossible visual narrative fitted to a scene that references nature
but poeticizes and transcends it—an anomaly.

Fig. (4) Seated Man (with Top Hat) and Tree from La Grande Jatte

In figure 4, we see a man with a tree springing from his head, itself an oddity,
if not an anomaly, which sets up a question: what was on that man’s mind?
Fig. (5) Georges Seurat, Tree and Man
Seurat is using something of the method of Piero here, guiding us toward
an encounter of something miraculous. To see the development of this con-
Seurat is a marvelous draughtsman who, in drawing with conté cray-
struction, we can look to one of the hundreds of drawings and oil sketches
on on rough paper, focused almost exclusively on finding the monochromatic
for the mural size Grande Jatte. The one to consider is the one that focuses
equivalent of the kind of color luminosity that he had developed in his poin-
on the tree that has “sprung” from the seated man (fig. 5). The conté crayon
tillist painting method in La Grande Jatte. Pointillism relies on small bits of
drawing is Seurat’s study and confirmation of a puzzle. What the tree does is
color laid side by side in a painting, sympathizing and antagonizing, optically
a distinct and startling anomaly.
mixing to produce a color experience in the eye of the viewer that more truly
The drawing is actually a refinement of something that plays only
matches the experience of color light in nature. Pointillism was a purposeful,
a minor part in the complete painting. The drawing is absolutely purposeful
sometimes systematic, extension of the Impressionist revolution of the pre-
and intended to “do something” to the mind of the viewer. This is not a
vious decades in France and elsewhere. But this drawing reveals something
picture. The drawing is carefully formed as a narrative spatial experience. Seurat
other than luminosity; the drawing reveals Seurat’s encounter with something
likely experienced a fleeting moment of seeing a man standing on the bank
in nature and his design response. His drawing proposes an anomaly—the
of the island who happened to be, in the view of the artist, almost behind the
impossible tree is living in two places at once. While this is a precursory
tree. The tree that starts its upward journey in “our space” ends its journey
example of the upcoming modernist concern with space and form on the
“paired” with the man on the distant bank. As the tree diminishes in diameter
two-dimensional surface, it is also, in one complete moment, a recapitulation
70 Beauty as Anomaly Linus Meldrum 71
of the many mysteries of Piero as well as many, often anonymous, authors Contemporary abstractionist painter Sean Scully wrote of Morandi’s power
of medieval and early Renaissance images that contain time-busting and to subversively corrupt a visit to a modern art show. Hung on the “small
space-warping, continuous narratives. This is the disjunctive realm of the walls” of a gallery, Morandi’s paintings acted as “conscientious objectors”
peculiar, but not accidental, anomaly. that drew attention away from the large-scale abstract paintings that filled the
If we look again at La Grande Jatte (fig. 3), we can see the man with larger walls.2 His “simple,” still-life characters seem to say “we know who we
the tree coming out of his head and the small man at the bank of the river— are, but why are we here?” Almost every one of his images is an anomaly—
this is how the idea found its eventual place in the whole image. Did Seurat they are not composed to be attractive, colorful or pleasant. They are objects
intend to convey a specific meaning for this anomaly? Does the man with the and a tabletop and at the same time they corrupt pictorial space. The objects,
top hat, from which springs the impossible tree, have a particular thought? simple as they are, take on personalities that demand to be known anthropo-
Do we need an exact explanation? No. We can dream along with Seurat with- morphically and narratively.
out constricting his narrative. An exact explanation would stop the melody In a way, they are puzzling and distinctly anomalous. The viewer is
and awaken the sleeper. I am content to know that the unity composed here prompted to call them still-life images but at the same time they are not; you
is a visual consolation—a certain confirmation of the wholeness of vision in are forced to ignore their object-ness and accept them as characters acting in
this made-up world of Seurat. a work of fiction, whose shared actions deny the stillness of still-life. While
For this unusual masterpiece, there are over one hundred works, we never can be sure of the genre of fiction (Morandi himself was tight-
drawings, and painted sketches that preceded it. This large composition is lipped) his work can be called anything from magical realism, to tall-tales,
filled with “unusual” moments of narration. The man and tree drawing alone to suspense stories. Sometimes they are conspiracies, and the conspirators
has more to see. Notice how the tree casts two shadows; Seurat is teasing our are the harmless inhabitants of your china cabinet. They are encamped in
perception to find the second tree. I would ignore the postmodern analysis Morandi’s tabletop landscape and they are signaling to us that they intend
that the woman with the monkey on a chain and the woman who is fishing to be known as a particular unity in spite of what is expected of a natura
are intended to give figurative reference to Parisian prostitution. After all, morta picture. They are naively respectful of tradition and, at the same time,
sometimes a fishing pole is just a fishing pole. unrepentantly modern. It is no surprise that Piero was also one of Morandi’s
favorite artists.

Giorgio Morandi
William Bailey
In the middle of the twentieth century, the artist Giorgio Morandi accom-
plished something of a miracle. In the face of Matisse and Picasso launching Later in the twentieth century, an artist bucking the trend of sensationalist
abstraction onto center stage of the art world (and nearly every artist follow- Pop Art in the 60s, also found his way into still life as a stage for narration
ing along), Morandi had the quiet audacity to paint still life images (fig. 6). (fig.  7). Described as a “realist” by some, accepted as a “conservative” by
many, his sense of “reality” is far from real. A deeply traditional thinker, his
images continually ripened in the 1970s and 80s to eventually contain no
apparent traditional perspective. There is volume but no “real” space. No
ellipses at bases and tops of volumetric objects. No diminution to create a
foreground and background. The cast shadows mystify; they appear to make
sense. But how deep is this tabletop that holds so many objects stacked from
front to back? Is that really the way the shadows could fall? Knowing that
Bailey does not work from a factually observed still life gives a clue: this is all
made-up and he is the inventor of realist “anomalies” that branch out from a

Fig. (6) Giorgio Morandi, Natura Morta (Still Life)


Sean Scully, Resistance and Persistence: Selected Writings, ed. Florence Ingleby
2

(London/New York: Merrel, 2006).


70 Beauty as Anomaly Linus Meldrum 71
of the many mysteries of Piero as well as many, often anonymous, authors Contemporary abstractionist painter Sean Scully wrote of Morandi’s power
of medieval and early Renaissance images that contain time-busting and to subversively corrupt a visit to a modern art show. Hung on the “small
space-warping, continuous narratives. This is the disjunctive realm of the walls” of a gallery, Morandi’s paintings acted as “conscientious objectors”
peculiar, but not accidental, anomaly. that drew attention away from the large-scale abstract paintings that filled the
If we look again at La Grande Jatte (fig. 3), we can see the man with larger walls.2 His “simple,” still-life characters seem to say “we know who we
the tree coming out of his head and the small man at the bank of the river— are, but why are we here?” Almost every one of his images is an anomaly—
this is how the idea found its eventual place in the whole image. Did Seurat they are not composed to be attractive, colorful or pleasant. They are objects
intend to convey a specific meaning for this anomaly? Does the man with the and a tabletop and at the same time they corrupt pictorial space. The objects,
top hat, from which springs the impossible tree, have a particular thought? simple as they are, take on personalities that demand to be known anthropo-
Do we need an exact explanation? No. We can dream along with Seurat with- morphically and narratively.
out constricting his narrative. An exact explanation would stop the melody In a way, they are puzzling and distinctly anomalous. The viewer is
and awaken the sleeper. I am content to know that the unity composed here prompted to call them still-life images but at the same time they are not; you
is a visual consolation—a certain confirmation of the wholeness of vision in are forced to ignore their object-ness and accept them as characters acting in
this made-up world of Seurat. a work of fiction, whose shared actions deny the stillness of still-life. While
For this unusual masterpiece, there are over one hundred works, we never can be sure of the genre of fiction (Morandi himself was tight-
drawings, and painted sketches that preceded it. This large composition is lipped) his work can be called anything from magical realism, to tall-tales,
filled with “unusual” moments of narration. The man and tree drawing alone to suspense stories. Sometimes they are conspiracies, and the conspirators
has more to see. Notice how the tree casts two shadows; Seurat is teasing our are the harmless inhabitants of your china cabinet. They are encamped in
perception to find the second tree. I would ignore the postmodern analysis Morandi’s tabletop landscape and they are signaling to us that they intend
that the woman with the monkey on a chain and the woman who is fishing to be known as a particular unity in spite of what is expected of a natura
are intended to give figurative reference to Parisian prostitution. After all, morta picture. They are naively respectful of tradition and, at the same time,
sometimes a fishing pole is just a fishing pole. unrepentantly modern. It is no surprise that Piero was also one of Morandi’s
favorite artists.

Giorgio Morandi
William Bailey
In the middle of the twentieth century, the artist Giorgio Morandi accom-
plished something of a miracle. In the face of Matisse and Picasso launching Later in the twentieth century, an artist bucking the trend of sensationalist
abstraction onto center stage of the art world (and nearly every artist follow- Pop Art in the 60s, also found his way into still life as a stage for narration
ing along), Morandi had the quiet audacity to paint still life images (fig. 6). (fig.  7). Described as a “realist” by some, accepted as a “conservative” by
many, his sense of “reality” is far from real. A deeply traditional thinker, his
images continually ripened in the 1970s and 80s to eventually contain no
apparent traditional perspective. There is volume but no “real” space. No
ellipses at bases and tops of volumetric objects. No diminution to create a
foreground and background. The cast shadows mystify; they appear to make
sense. But how deep is this tabletop that holds so many objects stacked from
front to back? Is that really the way the shadows could fall? Knowing that
Bailey does not work from a factually observed still life gives a clue: this is all
made-up and he is the inventor of realist “anomalies” that branch out from a

Fig. (6) Giorgio Morandi, Natura Morta (Still Life)


Sean Scully, Resistance and Persistence: Selected Writings, ed. Florence Ingleby
2

(London/New York: Merrel, 2006).


72 Beauty as Anomaly Linus Meldrum 73
perhaps conventional base to become familiar yet impossible—an opening door Stepping back from this to the viewpoint of the Creator of this nar-
to a narrative experience that stops time and expands time all at once. rative event—He who calls from the Bush—we see that the Divine Artist
needed something more than a thunderstorm, or colorful sunset, or some
other radiance of nature to draw the mind of Moses. He needed to take a
piece of common nature and embed it in a supernatural impossibility.
And it worked. Moses drew aside. Moses “heard” this visual call.
Moses met and heard God speak from the bush. God could have simply
talked to Moses in a dream—or as he watered his flock, or as he gazed at
the stars—but He chose to use this crack in natural reality to awaken the
visual imagination of Moses. And Moses was ready (perceptive, alert, close
to nature) and aware of, indeed actively participating in, everyday marvels like
birth, death, and love. He leapt at the chance to know this newfound, mar-
velous experience. And he became, with God’s grace, on fire himself.
An anomaly, if it is to persist in its mystery, is never completely
“owned.” Gregory of Nyssa, in The Life of Moses, directs us to consider God’s
eternal incomprehensibility. Like Plotinus, Gregory sees the progress toward
Fig. (7) William Bailey, Mercatale Still Life the Divine Beauty as a perpetual turning-toward. Gregory teaches that as
much as Moses wanted to see God, it was impossible to complete his desire
We can see in these images, characterizations that could be found in Piero, in any human way.
Seurat, and Morandi. These characters are far, far away—strangely flattened
like a distant cityscape. However, when seen in person, the painted objects in
the image are slightly larger than life-sized—they are closer than close. That is an The Sacred Wood
anomaly that breaks the convention of “realism” and places us in a sublime
encounter with the tabletop narrative. If any of this is to make sense for visual art and artists, there remains this
So, what has this to do with the Burning Bush? And what does an question: to what does anomaly point? Or as viewers of and participants
anomaly have to do with reaching from our everyday natural world to some- in the artist’s work, from whence does the anomaly come? The “effect” of
thing beyond the everyday, to Beauty? anomaly is not enough to be artful—hot pepper is not flavor and explosions
Gregory of Nyssa, the fourth century theologian and Cappadocian are not fireworks. Something in the surprise that is initiated by the creator
Father of the Church, alluded to anomaly in his theological writings. His The must transform our understanding of the creator’s desire and purpose. The
Life of Moses is a theologically perceptive biography, placing our imagination creator must start in a world we know well, and then lead us to a place we can-
onto the path of experiences that Moses walked. The quote from Exodus at not get to on our own. We must not be frustrated if the destination remains
the beginning of this paper is a narrative focal point in the life of Moses. Af- mysterious. Cataloging and rational description will not explain our awe and
ter losing his Hebrew family birthright, Moses gains an Egyptian princedom, wonder without dropping back to the world of defined figures, objects, and
kills a man, loses his royal inheritance, runs away, and finds love in the desert places. Explaining a paradox, or even a concise joke, undoes the meaningful
with Zipporah, the daughter of Jethro. A life of adventure, yet nothing like experience intended by the author. This is the challenge of knowing visual
what was to come. His personal encounter with the Living God begins with art; the viewer must, in some way, explain the art to the mind with language
his attention being grabbed by an anomaly, or inconceivability—the bush constructions that live in two worlds—the invented world of the creator and
that, although on fire, just keeps burning.3 the everyday world of the viewer.
In the essays of T. S. Eliot compiled as The Sacred Wood, an important
clarification is found. He tries to fit together the efforts of creative writers
and the longstanding tradition of literature forms. (I insert below in brackets
Gregory of Nyssa, The Life of Moses, trans. Abraham J. Malherbe and Everett
3

Ferguson (New York: Paulist Press, 1978). my extension of the idea into the realm of the visual.)
72 Beauty as Anomaly Linus Meldrum 73
perhaps conventional base to become familiar yet impossible—an opening door Stepping back from this to the viewpoint of the Creator of this nar-
to a narrative experience that stops time and expands time all at once. rative event—He who calls from the Bush—we see that the Divine Artist
needed something more than a thunderstorm, or colorful sunset, or some
other radiance of nature to draw the mind of Moses. He needed to take a
piece of common nature and embed it in a supernatural impossibility.
And it worked. Moses drew aside. Moses “heard” this visual call.
Moses met and heard God speak from the bush. God could have simply
talked to Moses in a dream—or as he watered his flock, or as he gazed at
the stars—but He chose to use this crack in natural reality to awaken the
visual imagination of Moses. And Moses was ready (perceptive, alert, close
to nature) and aware of, indeed actively participating in, everyday marvels like
birth, death, and love. He leapt at the chance to know this newfound, mar-
velous experience. And he became, with God’s grace, on fire himself.
An anomaly, if it is to persist in its mystery, is never completely
“owned.” Gregory of Nyssa, in The Life of Moses, directs us to consider God’s
eternal incomprehensibility. Like Plotinus, Gregory sees the progress toward
Fig. (7) William Bailey, Mercatale Still Life the Divine Beauty as a perpetual turning-toward. Gregory teaches that as
much as Moses wanted to see God, it was impossible to complete his desire
We can see in these images, characterizations that could be found in Piero, in any human way.
Seurat, and Morandi. These characters are far, far away—strangely flattened
like a distant cityscape. However, when seen in person, the painted objects in
the image are slightly larger than life-sized—they are closer than close. That is an The Sacred Wood
anomaly that breaks the convention of “realism” and places us in a sublime
encounter with the tabletop narrative. If any of this is to make sense for visual art and artists, there remains this
So, what has this to do with the Burning Bush? And what does an question: to what does anomaly point? Or as viewers of and participants
anomaly have to do with reaching from our everyday natural world to some- in the artist’s work, from whence does the anomaly come? The “effect” of
thing beyond the everyday, to Beauty? anomaly is not enough to be artful—hot pepper is not flavor and explosions
Gregory of Nyssa, the fourth century theologian and Cappadocian are not fireworks. Something in the surprise that is initiated by the creator
Father of the Church, alluded to anomaly in his theological writings. His The must transform our understanding of the creator’s desire and purpose. The
Life of Moses is a theologically perceptive biography, placing our imagination creator must start in a world we know well, and then lead us to a place we can-
onto the path of experiences that Moses walked. The quote from Exodus at not get to on our own. We must not be frustrated if the destination remains
the beginning of this paper is a narrative focal point in the life of Moses. Af- mysterious. Cataloging and rational description will not explain our awe and
ter losing his Hebrew family birthright, Moses gains an Egyptian princedom, wonder without dropping back to the world of defined figures, objects, and
kills a man, loses his royal inheritance, runs away, and finds love in the desert places. Explaining a paradox, or even a concise joke, undoes the meaningful
with Zipporah, the daughter of Jethro. A life of adventure, yet nothing like experience intended by the author. This is the challenge of knowing visual
what was to come. His personal encounter with the Living God begins with art; the viewer must, in some way, explain the art to the mind with language
his attention being grabbed by an anomaly, or inconceivability—the bush constructions that live in two worlds—the invented world of the creator and
that, although on fire, just keeps burning.3 the everyday world of the viewer.
In the essays of T. S. Eliot compiled as The Sacred Wood, an important
clarification is found. He tries to fit together the efforts of creative writers
and the longstanding tradition of literature forms. (I insert below in brackets
Gregory of Nyssa, The Life of Moses, trans. Abraham J. Malherbe and Everett
3

Ferguson (New York: Paulist Press, 1978). my extension of the idea into the realm of the visual.)
74 Beauty as Anomaly Linus Meldrum 75
What exactly is this abyss? And if something “has gone amiss at work—an act and an image that was Beautiful. What follows such an en-
with our standards,” is it wholly the fault of the younger genera- counter is an immersion in narrative. For Moses, that would be the narrative
tion that it is aware of no authority that it must respect? It is part of Salvation, the Burning Bush and Moses’s awakening was situated in the
of the business of the critic to preserve tradition—where a good tradition to which Moses belonged. He was granted deep familiarity with the
tradition exists. It is part of his business to see literature [images] Person of God, who is Pure Truth, Pure Goodness, and (importantly for the
steadily and to see it [the realm of images] whole; and this is em- visual sense) Pure Beauty. What Moses saw was as much as any human could
inently to see it [image-making] not as consecrated by time, but hope for before the seeing of the human face of Christ.
to see it beyond time; to see the best work of our time and the A visual artist might define anomaly: something that is familiar or
best work of twenty-five hundred years ago with the same eyes.”4 should be familiar (that is, respecting and building on a tradition) made to
This broadcasts the necessity of hinging the visual inventions of the visual be peculiar in order to convey an understanding of the invisible and super-
artist to the vast river of ideas that forms tradition. Without this, the artist is natural realm that is beyond “mere vision.” And continuing: the intention of
simply “creating novelties.” doing such a thing is to confirm with particular inventiveness something that,
For Moses, as recounted by Gregory of Nyssa in The Life of Moses, while factually obscure, is actually already known because it is a “permanent
thing”—we recognize in an image the substance of narrative that glues to-
The bold request which goes up the mountains of desire asks gether the everyday world. Sometimes that pang of recognition is from see-
this: to enjoy the Beauty not in mirrors and reflections, but face ing expressed tenderness, complementary affection, impending malevolence,
to face. The divine voice granted what was requested in what or other human-relational experiences. And sometimes it all takes place on a
was denied, showing in a few words an immeasurable depth of tabletop in an image. While we may clearly recount the dramatic actions with-
thought. The munificence of God assented to the fulfillment of in a parable, the actions are never the subject. For visual artists, who are also
his desire, but did not promise any cessation or satiety of the de- parable-tellers, the subject of the work lies beyond practical vision. Crack
sire. He would not have shown himself to his servant if the sight open the visual story at the anomalous seam and look inside. The place for
were such as to bring the desire of the beholder to an end, since us to “rest” is in the mind of the artist who, through image-making, signals
the true sight of God consists in this: that the one who looks up to us the presence of something both human and supernatural.
to God never ceases in that desire.5 In a work of Christian art, or in secular art from the hands of a
So what would Gregory suggest to an artist trying to reach the Divine? Do Christian artist, for instance, the work can narrate the experience of God.
not create images intended to convey the supernatural by using “factualism,” When that occurs, we are given the opportunity to see a distant land through
“pure naturalism,” “pure realism,” or “pure rationalism” that come to a con- the telescope of the artist’s mind. It is also true community: the artist and
clusion, to a summation that is an “end.” Something in the image—namely, viewer “being” together, mind joined to mind.
in the design of the image—must keep open the channel of ongoing progress The anomaly is just the beacon. The essential goal is to know the
toward the Divine. If an image “resolves,” the experience is over, the image mind of a creating human, or in sacred art, to know the mind of the ultimate
is “done.” Creator. This is the primordial bowl of content into which we dip our daily
Gregory of Nyssa might say that the Seurat drawing (fig. 5) is not bread.
“done,” but he would also say that it does not need more drawing so that it There are non-Christian artists, and I must say, even anti-Christian
can be done; rather, it is a “leading to.” Leading to where? I would contend: artists who know these ideas well. I specifically selected some artwork with-
right into the mind of Seurat, or in the other works as examples, into the out a Christian message in order to highlight this. However, the artworks I
minds of Piero, Morandi, or Bailey. By seeing the anomalous beacon we can have selected are more than anomaly-rich; the artists are also part of a tradi-
make our way to a significant destination: the living mind of another person. tion. Not coincidentally, they all can be grouped as dramatists or constructors
What Moses saw in the anomaly of the Burning Bush was “God’s Mind” of visual parables. None of these artists ignored the past; they entered the
goldmine of tradition and explored with great care. They each found a way
to renew tradition without destroying tradition. Christian artists today often
4
T. S. Eliot, The Sacred Wood, Essays on Poetry and Criticism (New York: Alfred
A. Knopf, 1921). spend time in obvious parts of the goldmine of tradition rather than trust
5
Gregory of Nyssa, The Life of Moses. that there are rich veins yet to be uncovered by more digging. Many of these
74 Beauty as Anomaly Linus Meldrum 75
What exactly is this abyss? And if something “has gone amiss at work—an act and an image that was Beautiful. What follows such an en-
with our standards,” is it wholly the fault of the younger genera- counter is an immersion in narrative. For Moses, that would be the narrative
tion that it is aware of no authority that it must respect? It is part of Salvation, the Burning Bush and Moses’s awakening was situated in the
of the business of the critic to preserve tradition—where a good tradition to which Moses belonged. He was granted deep familiarity with the
tradition exists. It is part of his business to see literature [images] Person of God, who is Pure Truth, Pure Goodness, and (importantly for the
steadily and to see it [the realm of images] whole; and this is em- visual sense) Pure Beauty. What Moses saw was as much as any human could
inently to see it [image-making] not as consecrated by time, but hope for before the seeing of the human face of Christ.
to see it beyond time; to see the best work of our time and the A visual artist might define anomaly: something that is familiar or
best work of twenty-five hundred years ago with the same eyes.”4 should be familiar (that is, respecting and building on a tradition) made to
This broadcasts the necessity of hinging the visual inventions of the visual be peculiar in order to convey an understanding of the invisible and super-
artist to the vast river of ideas that forms tradition. Without this, the artist is natural realm that is beyond “mere vision.” And continuing: the intention of
simply “creating novelties.” doing such a thing is to confirm with particular inventiveness something that,
For Moses, as recounted by Gregory of Nyssa in The Life of Moses, while factually obscure, is actually already known because it is a “permanent
thing”—we recognize in an image the substance of narrative that glues to-
The bold request which goes up the mountains of desire asks gether the everyday world. Sometimes that pang of recognition is from see-
this: to enjoy the Beauty not in mirrors and reflections, but face ing expressed tenderness, complementary affection, impending malevolence,
to face. The divine voice granted what was requested in what or other human-relational experiences. And sometimes it all takes place on a
was denied, showing in a few words an immeasurable depth of tabletop in an image. While we may clearly recount the dramatic actions with-
thought. The munificence of God assented to the fulfillment of in a parable, the actions are never the subject. For visual artists, who are also
his desire, but did not promise any cessation or satiety of the de- parable-tellers, the subject of the work lies beyond practical vision. Crack
sire. He would not have shown himself to his servant if the sight open the visual story at the anomalous seam and look inside. The place for
were such as to bring the desire of the beholder to an end, since us to “rest” is in the mind of the artist who, through image-making, signals
the true sight of God consists in this: that the one who looks up to us the presence of something both human and supernatural.
to God never ceases in that desire.5 In a work of Christian art, or in secular art from the hands of a
So what would Gregory suggest to an artist trying to reach the Divine? Do Christian artist, for instance, the work can narrate the experience of God.
not create images intended to convey the supernatural by using “factualism,” When that occurs, we are given the opportunity to see a distant land through
“pure naturalism,” “pure realism,” or “pure rationalism” that come to a con- the telescope of the artist’s mind. It is also true community: the artist and
clusion, to a summation that is an “end.” Something in the image—namely, viewer “being” together, mind joined to mind.
in the design of the image—must keep open the channel of ongoing progress The anomaly is just the beacon. The essential goal is to know the
toward the Divine. If an image “resolves,” the experience is over, the image mind of a creating human, or in sacred art, to know the mind of the ultimate
is “done.” Creator. This is the primordial bowl of content into which we dip our daily
Gregory of Nyssa might say that the Seurat drawing (fig. 5) is not bread.
“done,” but he would also say that it does not need more drawing so that it There are non-Christian artists, and I must say, even anti-Christian
can be done; rather, it is a “leading to.” Leading to where? I would contend: artists who know these ideas well. I specifically selected some artwork with-
right into the mind of Seurat, or in the other works as examples, into the out a Christian message in order to highlight this. However, the artworks I
minds of Piero, Morandi, or Bailey. By seeing the anomalous beacon we can have selected are more than anomaly-rich; the artists are also part of a tradi-
make our way to a significant destination: the living mind of another person. tion. Not coincidentally, they all can be grouped as dramatists or constructors
What Moses saw in the anomaly of the Burning Bush was “God’s Mind” of visual parables. None of these artists ignored the past; they entered the
goldmine of tradition and explored with great care. They each found a way
to renew tradition without destroying tradition. Christian artists today often
4
T. S. Eliot, The Sacred Wood, Essays on Poetry and Criticism (New York: Alfred
A. Knopf, 1921). spend time in obvious parts of the goldmine of tradition rather than trust
5
Gregory of Nyssa, The Life of Moses. that there are rich veins yet to be uncovered by more digging. Many of these
76 Beauty as Anomaly Alessandro Rovati 77
contemporary Christian artists are consumed with the study of technique. In
the goldmine, technique is the practical craft of using pick and shovel. Tech-
The Beauty that Pierces the Heart:
nique is important for artists, but it is not Art. Technique helps to clarify ideas Joseph Ratzinger’s Christological
but it is not an idea in itself. Good spelling is not literature. A good image
is a good parable—a visual story with an embedded truth. For Piero, it was Understanding of Beauty
turning St. Helena’s desire to find the relic of the Cross (and his understand-
ing of dynamic geometric perfection) into a story that pulls the eye along.
Alessandro Rovati
Christian artists, especially Catholic artists who seek the deepest themes and
strongest traditions, have a wealth of mentor-artists in the historical timeline.
Study will reveal that when an anomaly is present, the image jumps to life.
This visual refreshment helps to renew tradition and elevate traditional art. It Art, Beauty, and the Magisterium1
also keeps technical expertise from succumbing to simple archaism. It is a sad
but clarifying moment when a Christian artist realizes that technical expertise The Pope is your friend.… We need you. We need your collabo-
is the actual subject-matter of his images. It is one thing to honor tradition; ration in order to carry out our ministry, which consists, as you
it is another thing to simply love being a traditionalist. know, in preaching and rendering accessible and comprehensible
If the incarnate soul who is the art-maker is seeking a Divine truth, to the minds and hearts of our people the things of the spirit, the
or trying to part the veil to glimpse, however partially, the beatific vision, invisible, the ineffable, the things of God Himself. And in this
and if he or she calls us with an anomaly, we should pay attention; in this activity of transposing the invisible world into accessible and in-
image-soaked, image-driven culture we share, it may be the narrow path to telligible forms you are masters. It is your task, your mission; and
finding Beauty. your art consists in grasping treasures from the heavenly realm
of the spirit and clothing them in words, colors, forms—making
—Franciscan University them accessible.2
The words that Blessed Paul VI addressed to artists during the Second Vat-
ican Council is just one of many instances of the fruitful dialogue between
1
A work-in-progress version of this scholarly article was presented at the
Franciscan University of Steubenville conference on Christian Philosophy, “The
Power of Beauty,” on October 24–25, 2014. I thank Dr. John F. Crosby and the
Program Committee for their kind invitation to present at the conference, Catherine
F. O’Camb for her logistical help, and the Philosophy Department at Franciscan
University for its financial support. I also need to thank Stephen and Suzanne Lewis
for their hospitality. Mary Burazer and Susan Mayes of Belmont Abbey College and
Francesco Tosi of Università Cattolica di Milano have given me an invaluable help in
collecting the research materials I needed, and I want to thank Sr. Mary Eucharista,
SMMC and Matteo Bergamaschi for their comments on earlier versions of this arti-
cle. Dr. Theresa Farnan, whose work has made this journal issue possible, has given
me important suggestions, and I know that my article is better because of them.
Finally, for her edits and companionship, my heartfelt gratitude goes to my wife,
Rachelle Ramirez.
2
Paul VI, “Mass with Artists,” May 7, 1964, accessed August 30, 2015,
http://w2.vatican.va/content/paul-vi/it/homilies/1964/documents/hf_p-vi_
hom_19640507_messa-artisti.html.
© Alessandro Rovati, Quaestiones Disputatae, Vol. 6, No. 2 (Spring 2016)
76 Beauty as Anomaly Alessandro Rovati 77
contemporary Christian artists are consumed with the study of technique. In
the goldmine, technique is the practical craft of using pick and shovel. Tech-
The Beauty that Pierces the Heart:
nique is important for artists, but it is not Art. Technique helps to clarify ideas Joseph Ratzinger’s Christological
but it is not an idea in itself. Good spelling is not literature. A good image
is a good parable—a visual story with an embedded truth. For Piero, it was Understanding of Beauty
turning St. Helena’s desire to find the relic of the Cross (and his understand-
ing of dynamic geometric perfection) into a story that pulls the eye along.
Alessandro Rovati
Christian artists, especially Catholic artists who seek the deepest themes and
strongest traditions, have a wealth of mentor-artists in the historical timeline.
Study will reveal that when an anomaly is present, the image jumps to life.
This visual refreshment helps to renew tradition and elevate traditional art. It Art, Beauty, and the Magisterium1
also keeps technical expertise from succumbing to simple archaism. It is a sad
but clarifying moment when a Christian artist realizes that technical expertise The Pope is your friend.… We need you. We need your collabo-
is the actual subject-matter of his images. It is one thing to honor tradition; ration in order to carry out our ministry, which consists, as you
it is another thing to simply love being a traditionalist. know, in preaching and rendering accessible and comprehensible
If the incarnate soul who is the art-maker is seeking a Divine truth, to the minds and hearts of our people the things of the spirit, the
or trying to part the veil to glimpse, however partially, the beatific vision, invisible, the ineffable, the things of God Himself. And in this
and if he or she calls us with an anomaly, we should pay attention; in this activity of transposing the invisible world into accessible and in-
image-soaked, image-driven culture we share, it may be the narrow path to telligible forms you are masters. It is your task, your mission; and
finding Beauty. your art consists in grasping treasures from the heavenly realm
of the spirit and clothing them in words, colors, forms—making
—Franciscan University them accessible.2
The words that Blessed Paul VI addressed to artists during the Second Vat-
ican Council is just one of many instances of the fruitful dialogue between
1
A work-in-progress version of this scholarly article was presented at the
Franciscan University of Steubenville conference on Christian Philosophy, “The
Power of Beauty,” on October 24–25, 2014. I thank Dr. John F. Crosby and the
Program Committee for their kind invitation to present at the conference, Catherine
F. O’Camb for her logistical help, and the Philosophy Department at Franciscan
University for its financial support. I also need to thank Stephen and Suzanne Lewis
for their hospitality. Mary Burazer and Susan Mayes of Belmont Abbey College and
Francesco Tosi of Università Cattolica di Milano have given me an invaluable help in
collecting the research materials I needed, and I want to thank Sr. Mary Eucharista,
SMMC and Matteo Bergamaschi for their comments on earlier versions of this arti-
cle. Dr. Theresa Farnan, whose work has made this journal issue possible, has given
me important suggestions, and I know that my article is better because of them.
Finally, for her edits and companionship, my heartfelt gratitude goes to my wife,
Rachelle Ramirez.
2
Paul VI, “Mass with Artists,” May 7, 1964, accessed August 30, 2015,
http://w2.vatican.va/content/paul-vi/it/homilies/1964/documents/hf_p-vi_
hom_19640507_messa-artisti.html.
© Alessandro Rovati, Quaestiones Disputatae, Vol. 6, No. 2 (Spring 2016)
78 The Beauty that Pierces the Heart Alessandro Rovati 79
the Church and the world of art that has left so many astonishing traces in ator.”5 Certainly the two are distinguished, for while the former, the crafts-
our history. From the beginning of Christianity, we can witness an alliance man, gives form and meaning to something that already exists, the latter,
between the Gospel and art, a relationship that encompasses the first pa- God, brings something into being out of nothing, creating ex nihilo. But, at
leo-Christian symbols, medieval art, the Eastern Orthodox icon tradition, the same time, while the infinite difference between the Creator and the crea-
the great works of the Renaissance, and all the other artistic expressions ture is evident, human beings’ artistic creativity expresses in a distinctive way
that followed up to today. From where does such an enduring and fruitful the likeness between them and God.
relationship come? Why is it that the Church and artists have engaged in this A second element that justifies the substantive relationship between
unbroken dialogue for centuries?3 art and the Church is the link between the former and the mystery of the
There are many historical reasons that can justify this privileged re- Word made flesh. While the Old Testament forbade the representation of
lationship. The prominent role that Christianity had in Western culture, the God in images, the Incarnation, where the invisible becomes visible, intro-
generous patronage of many Christian leaders, the work of the various re- duced into the history of the world “a new dimension of beauty, of which
ligious orders, and widespread popular piety are just a few of the causes of the Gospel message is filled to the brim.”6 Accordingly, artists who are con-
this multifaceted phenomenon. Following St. John Paul II, I want to suggest stantly searching for the meaning of things and who are striving to make
that besides these contingent factors, the dialogue between the Church and present the spiritual reality that their souls intuit, could not but find in Reve-
artists “is rooted in the very essence of both religious experience and artistic lation a never-ending and engaging source of inspiration. That is why the Sa-
creativity.”4 cred Scripture has become an “immense vocabulary”7 (to use an expression
In a letter he addressed to artists on the occasion of the Jubilee, of the playwright Paul Claudel that was dear to St. John Paul II) which artists,
in fact, St. John Paul II—himself an artist—meditated on the connections both Christians and not, have used to produce their beautiful works, be they
between God’s creative activity as described in Genesis and the artist’s own pictorial, architectural, or musical. These artistic expressions of the biblical
work. “The human craftsman,” he wrote, “mirrors the image of God as Cre- word, in turn, have greatly benefitted the Church and her children, for whom
art has become a nourishing source of education and help in their journey of
faith.8
3
While I recognize that there have been many instances in which such a Finally, there is another element that represents the culmination of
dialogue has in fact been broken and that its very possibility or necessity has been ex- the close relationship between artists and the Church. Even when its sub-
plicitly denied by some, in what follows I want to emphasize the positive relationship ject is not explicitly religious, art has the power to point in a special way to
that exists or can exist between the Church and various artistic expressions. While
both Ratzinger and the magisterial documents reflect on the problematic state of 5
Ibid.
some contemporary artistic expressions, they focus more on the fruitful relationship 6
Ibid., § 5, par. 2.
between art and faith than on its denial. Moreover, I do not possess the necessary 7
Ibid., § 5, par. 3.
expertise in art history to discuss specific challenges to the relationship between art 8
To say it with Ratzinger: “some artistic expressions are real highways to
and faith. For Ratzinger’s description of what he calls “the crisis of art,” see his The God, the supreme Beauty; indeed, they help us to grow in our relationship with him,
Spirit of the Liturgy (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 2000), 130–31. And Benedict XVI, in prayer. These are works that were born from faith and express faith. We can see an
Message to the President of the Pontifical Council for Culture on the Occasion example of this when we visit a Gothic cathedral: we are enraptured by the vertical
of the 13th Public Conference of the Pontifical Academies on the Theme: “The lines that soar skywards and uplift our gaze and our spirit, while at the same time
Universality of Beauty: A Comparison between Aesthetics and Ethics,” November we feel small yet long for fullness. Or when we enter a Romanesque church we are
24, 2008, accessed August 30, 2015, http://w2.vatican.va/content/benedict-xvi/ spontaneously prompted to meditate and to pray. We perceive that these splendid
en/messages/pont-messages/2008/documents/hf_ben-xvi_mes_20081124_ravasi. buildings contain, as it were, the faith of generations. Or when we listen to a piece of
html. Interestingly enough, when Paul VI met with artists during the Second Vat- sacred music that plucks at our heartstrings, our mind, as it were, expands and turns
ican Council he acknowledged that both the Church and artists had their share of naturally to God” (Benedict XVI, “General Audience,” par. 5–6, August 31, 2011,
responsibility in creating a distance between art and faith, thus recognizing the need accessed August 30, 2015, http://w2.vatican.va/content/benedict-xvi/en/audienc-
of mutual forgiveness (Paul VI, “Mass with Artists). es/2011/documents/hf_ben-xvi_aud_20110831.html). The examples could contin-
4
John Paul II, Letter to Artists, § 1, par. 3, April 4, 1999, accessed August ue to include the medieval paintings that taught the tenets of the faith to illiterate
30, 2015, https://w2.vatican.va/content/john-paul-ii/en/letters/1999/documents/ faithful and the contemporary use of technological media to catechize people within
hf_jp-ii_let_23041999_artists.html. and outside the Church.
78 The Beauty that Pierces the Heart Alessandro Rovati 79
the Church and the world of art that has left so many astonishing traces in ator.”5 Certainly the two are distinguished, for while the former, the crafts-
our history. From the beginning of Christianity, we can witness an alliance man, gives form and meaning to something that already exists, the latter,
between the Gospel and art, a relationship that encompasses the first pa- God, brings something into being out of nothing, creating ex nihilo. But, at
leo-Christian symbols, medieval art, the Eastern Orthodox icon tradition, the same time, while the infinite difference between the Creator and the crea-
the great works of the Renaissance, and all the other artistic expressions ture is evident, human beings’ artistic creativity expresses in a distinctive way
that followed up to today. From where does such an enduring and fruitful the likeness between them and God.
relationship come? Why is it that the Church and artists have engaged in this A second element that justifies the substantive relationship between
unbroken dialogue for centuries?3 art and the Church is the link between the former and the mystery of the
There are many historical reasons that can justify this privileged re- Word made flesh. While the Old Testament forbade the representation of
lationship. The prominent role that Christianity had in Western culture, the God in images, the Incarnation, where the invisible becomes visible, intro-
generous patronage of many Christian leaders, the work of the various re- duced into the history of the world “a new dimension of beauty, of which
ligious orders, and widespread popular piety are just a few of the causes of the Gospel message is filled to the brim.”6 Accordingly, artists who are con-
this multifaceted phenomenon. Following St. John Paul II, I want to suggest stantly searching for the meaning of things and who are striving to make
that besides these contingent factors, the dialogue between the Church and present the spiritual reality that their souls intuit, could not but find in Reve-
artists “is rooted in the very essence of both religious experience and artistic lation a never-ending and engaging source of inspiration. That is why the Sa-
creativity.”4 cred Scripture has become an “immense vocabulary”7 (to use an expression
In a letter he addressed to artists on the occasion of the Jubilee, of the playwright Paul Claudel that was dear to St. John Paul II) which artists,
in fact, St. John Paul II—himself an artist—meditated on the connections both Christians and not, have used to produce their beautiful works, be they
between God’s creative activity as described in Genesis and the artist’s own pictorial, architectural, or musical. These artistic expressions of the biblical
work. “The human craftsman,” he wrote, “mirrors the image of God as Cre- word, in turn, have greatly benefitted the Church and her children, for whom
art has become a nourishing source of education and help in their journey of
faith.8
3
While I recognize that there have been many instances in which such a Finally, there is another element that represents the culmination of
dialogue has in fact been broken and that its very possibility or necessity has been ex- the close relationship between artists and the Church. Even when its sub-
plicitly denied by some, in what follows I want to emphasize the positive relationship ject is not explicitly religious, art has the power to point in a special way to
that exists or can exist between the Church and various artistic expressions. While
both Ratzinger and the magisterial documents reflect on the problematic state of 5
Ibid.
some contemporary artistic expressions, they focus more on the fruitful relationship 6
Ibid., § 5, par. 2.
between art and faith than on its denial. Moreover, I do not possess the necessary 7
Ibid., § 5, par. 3.
expertise in art history to discuss specific challenges to the relationship between art 8
To say it with Ratzinger: “some artistic expressions are real highways to
and faith. For Ratzinger’s description of what he calls “the crisis of art,” see his The God, the supreme Beauty; indeed, they help us to grow in our relationship with him,
Spirit of the Liturgy (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 2000), 130–31. And Benedict XVI, in prayer. These are works that were born from faith and express faith. We can see an
Message to the President of the Pontifical Council for Culture on the Occasion example of this when we visit a Gothic cathedral: we are enraptured by the vertical
of the 13th Public Conference of the Pontifical Academies on the Theme: “The lines that soar skywards and uplift our gaze and our spirit, while at the same time
Universality of Beauty: A Comparison between Aesthetics and Ethics,” November we feel small yet long for fullness. Or when we enter a Romanesque church we are
24, 2008, accessed August 30, 2015, http://w2.vatican.va/content/benedict-xvi/ spontaneously prompted to meditate and to pray. We perceive that these splendid
en/messages/pont-messages/2008/documents/hf_ben-xvi_mes_20081124_ravasi. buildings contain, as it were, the faith of generations. Or when we listen to a piece of
html. Interestingly enough, when Paul VI met with artists during the Second Vat- sacred music that plucks at our heartstrings, our mind, as it were, expands and turns
ican Council he acknowledged that both the Church and artists had their share of naturally to God” (Benedict XVI, “General Audience,” par. 5–6, August 31, 2011,
responsibility in creating a distance between art and faith, thus recognizing the need accessed August 30, 2015, http://w2.vatican.va/content/benedict-xvi/en/audienc-
of mutual forgiveness (Paul VI, “Mass with Artists). es/2011/documents/hf_ben-xvi_aud_20110831.html). The examples could contin-
4
John Paul II, Letter to Artists, § 1, par. 3, April 4, 1999, accessed August ue to include the medieval paintings that taught the tenets of the faith to illiterate
30, 2015, https://w2.vatican.va/content/john-paul-ii/en/letters/1999/documents/ faithful and the contemporary use of technological media to catechize people within
hf_jp-ii_let_23041999_artists.html. and outside the Church.
80 The Beauty that Pierces the Heart Alessandro Rovati 81
religious experience. For instance, St. John Paul II noticed that “in so far Christological understanding of beauty.13
as it seeks the beautiful, …art is by its nature a kind of appeal to the mys- Beauty has such an important role in the Christian life, first and fore-
tery. Even when they explore the darkest depths of the soul or the most most, because the experience of beauty “is by no means a supplementary or
unsettling aspects of evil, artists give voice in a way to the universal desire secondary factor in our search for meaning and happiness.”14 The experience
for redemption.”9 It is no mistake, consequently, that the Church has found of beauty does not imply an escape from reality into the realm of irrational or
herself especially concerned with art and artists. God reconciles the world pure aesthetics. Quite the contrary, beauty is usually something that facilitates
in Christ by making Himself known to all human beings. At the same time, and deepens the encounter with reality. We experience this fact every time
Jesus “fully reveals man to man,” as we read in Gaudium et Spes,10 so that the we see a beautiful natural scene, or when we observe an astonishing work of
Church becomes a special companion for those who, like most artists, seek art, or even when we meet a person that strikes us with his or her beauty. In
to truly understand the depths of reality and the mystery of humanity. all these instances the attraction we feel for the beauty we confront makes
For all these reasons, it does not come as a surprise that the Church us more attentive and engaged, thus introducing us to a deeper knowledge
and artists experience a special closeness. We see clear traces of this special of the object before us. These rather simplistic examples actually point to a
relationship in the message that Bl. Paul VI addressed to artists at the conclu- topic that has been discussed at length in the Catholic tradition—namely, the
sion of the Second Vatican Council. “If you are friends of the true art, you fundamental connection between truth and beauty. “Truth, the aim or goal
are our friends! …This world in which we live needs beauty in order not to of reason,” says Ratzinger, “is expressed in beauty and in beauty becomes
sink into despair. Beauty, like truth, brings joy to the human heart.… Remem- itself, is proven to be truth. Therefore, wherever there is truth beauty must
ber that you are the custodians of beauty in the world.”11 be born, wherever human beings are fulfilled in a correct and good way, they
express themselves in beauty. The relationship between truth and beauty is
inseparable and therefore we need beauty.”15
The Promise of Beauty
Emery de Gaàl, The Theology of Pope Benedict XVI: The Christocentric Shift (New York,
I have just shown the extent to which both Bl. Paul VI and St. John Paul II NY: Palgrave MacMillan, 2010), and Aidan Nichols, The Thought of Pope Benedict XVI:
emphasize the relationship between art, beauty, and faith. Why is this so? An Introduction to the Theology of Joseph Ratzinger (New York, NY: Burns & Oates, 2007).
What is it that makes beauty such an important concept for the Christian 13
In what follows I will show the key role that beauty plays in Ratzinger’s
life? To answer these questions I now turn to a discussion12 of Ratzinger’s theological vision, and I will give an account of the way he builds an aesthetics that
is rooted in Christ. While I will use multiple texts written by Ratzinger himself, the
9
John Paul II, Letter to Artists, § 10, par. 2. cursory nature of some of his statements on the connection between beauty and
10
Paul VI, Gaudium et Spes, § 22, par. 1, December 7, 1965, accessed August Christ has forced me to rely also on other sources. The choice of such sources is not
30, 2015, http://www.vatican.va/archive/hist_councils/ii_vatican_council/docu- arbitrary, though, as I have simply gone back to those authors that Ratzinger himself
ments/vat-ii_const_19651207_gaudium-et-spes_en.html. identifies as foundational for his own thinking. In particular, in his essay “Wounded
11
Paul VI, Messages of the Council: to the Artists, par. 1, 3, December 8, 1965, ac- by the Arrow of Beauty: The Cross and the New ‘Aesthetics’ of Faith,” which rep-
cessed August 30, 2015, https://w2.vatican.va/content/paul-vi/en/speeches/1965/ resents the most articulate statement of Ratzinger’s Christological understanding of
documents/hf_p-vi_spe_19651208_epilogo-concilio-artisti.html. beauty, he identifies two figures who have been important for him: Joseph Pieper and
12
Given the scope of this article, I have not had a chance to expand on the Hans Urs von Balthasar. Accordingly, I will develop an account of Ratzinger’s theol-
place that the liturgy and the sacraments have in Ratzinger’s reflection on beauty. On ogy that draws on the connections between him and these two authors. “Wounded
this topic, see Joseph Ratzinger, Theology of the Liturgy: The Sacramental Foundation of by the Arrow of Beauty” has been published in the collection of Ratzinger’s essays
Christian Existence, trans. Kenneth Baker, SJ, and Michael J. Miller, vol. 11, Collected called On the Way to Jesus Christ (San Francisco, CA: Ignatius Press, 2005), 32–41.
Works (San Francisco, CA: Ignatius Press, 2008); Ratzinger, The Spirit of the Liturgy, 14
Benedict XVI, “Meeting with Artists,” par. 5, November 21, 2009, accessed
trans. John Saward (San Francisco, CA: Ignatius Press, 2000); Ratzinger, A New Song August 30, 2015, http://w2.vatican.va/content/benedict-xvi/en/speeches/2009/
for the Lord: Faith in Christ and Liturgy Today, trans. Martha M. Matesich (New York: november/documents/hf_ben-xvi_spe_20091121_artisti.html.
Crossroad Publishing Company, 1996); Ratzinger, The Feast of Faith: Approaches to a 15
Benedict XVI, “Interview with the Journalists during the Flight to
Theology of the Liturgy (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1986). The most comprehensive Spain,” par. 10, November 6, 2010, accessed August 30, 2015, http://w2.vatican.
account of Ratzinger’s theology can be found in Tracy Rowland, Ratzinger’s Faith: The va/content/benedict-xvi/en/speeches/2010/november/documents/hf_ben-xvi_
Theology of Pope Benedict XVI (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 2008); see also, spe_20101106_intervista-spagna.html.
80 The Beauty that Pierces the Heart Alessandro Rovati 81
religious experience. For instance, St. John Paul II noticed that “in so far Christological understanding of beauty.13
as it seeks the beautiful, …art is by its nature a kind of appeal to the mys- Beauty has such an important role in the Christian life, first and fore-
tery. Even when they explore the darkest depths of the soul or the most most, because the experience of beauty “is by no means a supplementary or
unsettling aspects of evil, artists give voice in a way to the universal desire secondary factor in our search for meaning and happiness.”14 The experience
for redemption.”9 It is no mistake, consequently, that the Church has found of beauty does not imply an escape from reality into the realm of irrational or
herself especially concerned with art and artists. God reconciles the world pure aesthetics. Quite the contrary, beauty is usually something that facilitates
in Christ by making Himself known to all human beings. At the same time, and deepens the encounter with reality. We experience this fact every time
Jesus “fully reveals man to man,” as we read in Gaudium et Spes,10 so that the we see a beautiful natural scene, or when we observe an astonishing work of
Church becomes a special companion for those who, like most artists, seek art, or even when we meet a person that strikes us with his or her beauty. In
to truly understand the depths of reality and the mystery of humanity. all these instances the attraction we feel for the beauty we confront makes
For all these reasons, it does not come as a surprise that the Church us more attentive and engaged, thus introducing us to a deeper knowledge
and artists experience a special closeness. We see clear traces of this special of the object before us. These rather simplistic examples actually point to a
relationship in the message that Bl. Paul VI addressed to artists at the conclu- topic that has been discussed at length in the Catholic tradition—namely, the
sion of the Second Vatican Council. “If you are friends of the true art, you fundamental connection between truth and beauty. “Truth, the aim or goal
are our friends! …This world in which we live needs beauty in order not to of reason,” says Ratzinger, “is expressed in beauty and in beauty becomes
sink into despair. Beauty, like truth, brings joy to the human heart.… Remem- itself, is proven to be truth. Therefore, wherever there is truth beauty must
ber that you are the custodians of beauty in the world.”11 be born, wherever human beings are fulfilled in a correct and good way, they
express themselves in beauty. The relationship between truth and beauty is
inseparable and therefore we need beauty.”15
The Promise of Beauty
Emery de Gaàl, The Theology of Pope Benedict XVI: The Christocentric Shift (New York,
I have just shown the extent to which both Bl. Paul VI and St. John Paul II NY: Palgrave MacMillan, 2010), and Aidan Nichols, The Thought of Pope Benedict XVI:
emphasize the relationship between art, beauty, and faith. Why is this so? An Introduction to the Theology of Joseph Ratzinger (New York, NY: Burns & Oates, 2007).
What is it that makes beauty such an important concept for the Christian 13
In what follows I will show the key role that beauty plays in Ratzinger’s
life? To answer these questions I now turn to a discussion12 of Ratzinger’s theological vision, and I will give an account of the way he builds an aesthetics that
is rooted in Christ. While I will use multiple texts written by Ratzinger himself, the
9
John Paul II, Letter to Artists, § 10, par. 2. cursory nature of some of his statements on the connection between beauty and
10
Paul VI, Gaudium et Spes, § 22, par. 1, December 7, 1965, accessed August Christ has forced me to rely also on other sources. The choice of such sources is not
30, 2015, http://www.vatican.va/archive/hist_councils/ii_vatican_council/docu- arbitrary, though, as I have simply gone back to those authors that Ratzinger himself
ments/vat-ii_const_19651207_gaudium-et-spes_en.html. identifies as foundational for his own thinking. In particular, in his essay “Wounded
11
Paul VI, Messages of the Council: to the Artists, par. 1, 3, December 8, 1965, ac- by the Arrow of Beauty: The Cross and the New ‘Aesthetics’ of Faith,” which rep-
cessed August 30, 2015, https://w2.vatican.va/content/paul-vi/en/speeches/1965/ resents the most articulate statement of Ratzinger’s Christological understanding of
documents/hf_p-vi_spe_19651208_epilogo-concilio-artisti.html. beauty, he identifies two figures who have been important for him: Joseph Pieper and
12
Given the scope of this article, I have not had a chance to expand on the Hans Urs von Balthasar. Accordingly, I will develop an account of Ratzinger’s theol-
place that the liturgy and the sacraments have in Ratzinger’s reflection on beauty. On ogy that draws on the connections between him and these two authors. “Wounded
this topic, see Joseph Ratzinger, Theology of the Liturgy: The Sacramental Foundation of by the Arrow of Beauty” has been published in the collection of Ratzinger’s essays
Christian Existence, trans. Kenneth Baker, SJ, and Michael J. Miller, vol. 11, Collected called On the Way to Jesus Christ (San Francisco, CA: Ignatius Press, 2005), 32–41.
Works (San Francisco, CA: Ignatius Press, 2008); Ratzinger, The Spirit of the Liturgy, 14
Benedict XVI, “Meeting with Artists,” par. 5, November 21, 2009, accessed
trans. John Saward (San Francisco, CA: Ignatius Press, 2000); Ratzinger, A New Song August 30, 2015, http://w2.vatican.va/content/benedict-xvi/en/speeches/2009/
for the Lord: Faith in Christ and Liturgy Today, trans. Martha M. Matesich (New York: november/documents/hf_ben-xvi_spe_20091121_artisti.html.
Crossroad Publishing Company, 1996); Ratzinger, The Feast of Faith: Approaches to a 15
Benedict XVI, “Interview with the Journalists during the Flight to
Theology of the Liturgy (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1986). The most comprehensive Spain,” par. 10, November 6, 2010, accessed August 30, 2015, http://w2.vatican.
account of Ratzinger’s theology can be found in Tracy Rowland, Ratzinger’s Faith: The va/content/benedict-xvi/en/speeches/2010/november/documents/hf_ben-xvi_
Theology of Pope Benedict XVI (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 2008); see also, spe_20101106_intervista-spagna.html.
82 The Beauty that Pierces the Heart Alessandro Rovati 83
Some Catholic thinkers have further described this connection be- the splendor of the truth,19 which means, in turn, that beauty is an authentic
tween truth and beauty by regarding the latter as a transcendental—that is, as source of knowledge and not a simple distraction. Similarly, there is a special
one of the fundamental properties of being, together with unity, truth, and relationship between beauty and goodness. As Saint John Paul II said, while
goodness. Tracy Rowland explains that “although Ratzinger has not directly meditating on the beginning of Genesis: “in perceiving that all he had created
addressed the issue as an academic question,16 implicit within everything he was good, God saw that it was beautiful as well.… In a certain sense, beauty
writes on beauty is a preference for the line that follows St. Augustine, John is the visible form of the good, just as the good is the metaphysical condition
of La Rochelle, St. Bonaventure, and, in contemporary times, Hans Urs von of beauty.”20 If it were not for this fundamental connection with beauty, the
Balthasar.”17 These qualities are present in varying degrees and appearances good would lose its attractiveness and human beings would lack the evidence
in all that exists and, as Balthasar explains, “since the transcendentals pen- they need to choose it above evil. Balthasar helps us to see that “in a world
etrate all being, it follows that they are not delimited from each other but that no longer has enough confidence in itself to affirm the beautiful, the
penetrate each other.”18 Accordingly, beauty can be rightfully described as proofs of the truth have lost their cogency.… Syllogisms may still dutifully
clatter away, …but the logic of these answers is itself a mechanism which no
16
Ratzinger has on multiple occasions reflected on the connection between longer captivates anyone. The very conclusions are no longer conclusive.”21
beauty, truth, and goodness in the context of talking about the new evangelization. To better explain the connection between truth and beauty, Ratzing-
“The need and urgency for a renewed dialogue between aesthetics and ethics, be- er refers to Plato’s Phaedrus.22 In it beauty is described as a spear that wounds
tween beauty, truth and goodness, is once again proposed to us not only by the the human heart and reawakens the person so as to thrust her into the search
current cultural and artistic debate but also by daily reality. In fact, the split emerges for meaning and happiness. “The indubitably earthly, physical lover is shaken
dramatically at different levels and at times there is a glaring contrast between the two
to his depths by the encounter with beauty, which is to say, once again with
dimensions.… I have often emphasized the need for and commitment to widening
the horizons of reason, and in this perspective it is also necessary to again under-
something earthly, physical, apparent to the senses. But in that overpowering
stand the close connection that binds the search for beauty with the search for truth emotion he is carried out of the dimension of the here and now, becomes
and goodness” (Benedict XVI, “The Universality of Beauty,” par. 3–4). Cf. Ratzing- unborn and imperishable, and his emotion cannot be satisfied with anything
er, “Meeting with Clergy of the Diocese of Bolzano-Bressanone,” August 6, 2008, less than the Whole, the Totality of being, truth, goodness, beauty.”23 Human
accessed August 30, 2015, http://w2.vatican.va/content/benedict-xvi/en/speech- beings do not feel at home in the world; their soul thirsts for an unknown
es/2008/august/documents/hf_ben-xvi_spe_20080806_clero-bressanone.html,
and the “Message to the Participants Of the Second World Congress
on Ecclesial Theological Aesthetic, vol. 1, Seeing the Form (San Francisco, CA: Ignatius Press, 1982),
Movements and New Communities,” May 22, 2006, accessed on August 30, 2015, 33–41. For a neat description of the role of transcendentals in Balthasar’s theolo-
http://w2.vatican.va/content/benedict-xvi/en/messages/pont-messages/2006/ gy, see Matteo Bergamaschi, “Teologia Della Belleza?: Sul Ruolo Dei Trascendentali
documents/hf_ben-xvi_mes_20060522_ecclesial-movements.html. Nell’ermeneutica Teologica Di H. U. Von Balthasar,” Archivio Teologico Torinese 21, no.
17
Rowland, Ratzinger’s Faith, 8. The relationship with Balthasar—Benedict 1 (2015): 83–105.
called Balthasar “one of the greatest theologians of the 20th century” (Benedict XVI, 19
See Joseph Ratzinger, “Is the Catechism Up-to-Date?,” in On the Way to
“General Audience,” June 25, 2008, accessed August 30, 2015, http://w2.vatican.va/ Jesus Christ (San Francisco, CA: Ignatius Press, 2005), 165. See also Benedict XVI,
content/benedict-xvi/en/audiences/2008/documents/hf_ben-xvi_aud_20080625. Sacramentum Caritatis, § 35, February 22, 2007, accessed August 30, 2015, http://
html)—is particularly important to make sense of Ratzinger’s theological proposal. w2.vatican.va/content/benedict-xvi/en/apost_exhortations/documents/hf_ben-
Ratzinger describes his friendship with Balthasar and the debt he owes to Balthasar’s xvi_exh_20070222_sacramentum-caritatis.html.
theology in his autobiography Milestones: Memoirs, 1927–1977 (San Francisco, CA: 20
John Paul II, Letter to Artists, § 3, par. 2.
Ignatius Press, 1998), 143. All the monographic works cited in note 7 above further 21
Balthasar, Seeing the Form, 19.
articulate and describe the relationhip between these two great theologians. In what 22
Ratzinger, “Wounded by the Arrow of Beauty,” 34; in the same text
follows I will expand Ratzinger’s arguments by using Balthasar’s work, for Ratzinger Ratzinger discloses that his own interpretation of Phaedrus is “based on the magnifi-
himself has on multiple occasions recognized his debt towards Balthasar’s theolog- cent interpretation of Platonic Eros in Joseph Pieper’s ‘Begeisterung und Göttlicher
ical aesthetics. In particular, see his “Wounded by the Arrow of Beauty,” 36. And Wahnsinn.’” Pieper’s interpretation of Phaedrus has been published in English with
Benedict XVI, “Meeting with Artists.” the title Enthusiasm and Divine Madness: On the Platonic Dialogue Phaedrus (New York,
18
Hans Urs von Balthasar, “Earthly Beauty and Divine Glory,” Communio NY: Harcourt, Brace & World, Inc., 1964). Given the importance of Pieper’s contri-
International Catholic Review 10, no. 3 (1983): 203. Balthasar provides an articulate de- bution for Ratzinger’s argument, I have referred extensively to this text.
fense of the opinion that beauty is a transcendental in his The Glory of the Lord: A 23
Pieper, Enthusiasm and Divine Madness, 75–76.
82 The Beauty that Pierces the Heart Alessandro Rovati 83
Some Catholic thinkers have further described this connection be- the splendor of the truth,19 which means, in turn, that beauty is an authentic
tween truth and beauty by regarding the latter as a transcendental—that is, as source of knowledge and not a simple distraction. Similarly, there is a special
one of the fundamental properties of being, together with unity, truth, and relationship between beauty and goodness. As Saint John Paul II said, while
goodness. Tracy Rowland explains that “although Ratzinger has not directly meditating on the beginning of Genesis: “in perceiving that all he had created
addressed the issue as an academic question,16 implicit within everything he was good, God saw that it was beautiful as well.… In a certain sense, beauty
writes on beauty is a preference for the line that follows St. Augustine, John is the visible form of the good, just as the good is the metaphysical condition
of La Rochelle, St. Bonaventure, and, in contemporary times, Hans Urs von of beauty.”20 If it were not for this fundamental connection with beauty, the
Balthasar.”17 These qualities are present in varying degrees and appearances good would lose its attractiveness and human beings would lack the evidence
in all that exists and, as Balthasar explains, “since the transcendentals pen- they need to choose it above evil. Balthasar helps us to see that “in a world
etrate all being, it follows that they are not delimited from each other but that no longer has enough confidence in itself to affirm the beautiful, the
penetrate each other.”18 Accordingly, beauty can be rightfully described as proofs of the truth have lost their cogency.… Syllogisms may still dutifully
clatter away, …but the logic of these answers is itself a mechanism which no
16
Ratzinger has on multiple occasions reflected on the connection between longer captivates anyone. The very conclusions are no longer conclusive.”21
beauty, truth, and goodness in the context of talking about the new evangelization. To better explain the connection between truth and beauty, Ratzing-
“The need and urgency for a renewed dialogue between aesthetics and ethics, be- er refers to Plato’s Phaedrus.22 In it beauty is described as a spear that wounds
tween beauty, truth and goodness, is once again proposed to us not only by the the human heart and reawakens the person so as to thrust her into the search
current cultural and artistic debate but also by daily reality. In fact, the split emerges for meaning and happiness. “The indubitably earthly, physical lover is shaken
dramatically at different levels and at times there is a glaring contrast between the two
to his depths by the encounter with beauty, which is to say, once again with
dimensions.… I have often emphasized the need for and commitment to widening
the horizons of reason, and in this perspective it is also necessary to again under-
something earthly, physical, apparent to the senses. But in that overpowering
stand the close connection that binds the search for beauty with the search for truth emotion he is carried out of the dimension of the here and now, becomes
and goodness” (Benedict XVI, “The Universality of Beauty,” par. 3–4). Cf. Ratzing- unborn and imperishable, and his emotion cannot be satisfied with anything
er, “Meeting with Clergy of the Diocese of Bolzano-Bressanone,” August 6, 2008, less than the Whole, the Totality of being, truth, goodness, beauty.”23 Human
accessed August 30, 2015, http://w2.vatican.va/content/benedict-xvi/en/speech- beings do not feel at home in the world; their soul thirsts for an unknown
es/2008/august/documents/hf_ben-xvi_spe_20080806_clero-bressanone.html,
and the “Message to the Participants Of the Second World Congress
on Ecclesial Theological Aesthetic, vol. 1, Seeing the Form (San Francisco, CA: Ignatius Press, 1982),
Movements and New Communities,” May 22, 2006, accessed on August 30, 2015, 33–41. For a neat description of the role of transcendentals in Balthasar’s theolo-
http://w2.vatican.va/content/benedict-xvi/en/messages/pont-messages/2006/ gy, see Matteo Bergamaschi, “Teologia Della Belleza?: Sul Ruolo Dei Trascendentali
documents/hf_ben-xvi_mes_20060522_ecclesial-movements.html. Nell’ermeneutica Teologica Di H. U. Von Balthasar,” Archivio Teologico Torinese 21, no.
17
Rowland, Ratzinger’s Faith, 8. The relationship with Balthasar—Benedict 1 (2015): 83–105.
called Balthasar “one of the greatest theologians of the 20th century” (Benedict XVI, 19
See Joseph Ratzinger, “Is the Catechism Up-to-Date?,” in On the Way to
“General Audience,” June 25, 2008, accessed August 30, 2015, http://w2.vatican.va/ Jesus Christ (San Francisco, CA: Ignatius Press, 2005), 165. See also Benedict XVI,
content/benedict-xvi/en/audiences/2008/documents/hf_ben-xvi_aud_20080625. Sacramentum Caritatis, § 35, February 22, 2007, accessed August 30, 2015, http://
html)—is particularly important to make sense of Ratzinger’s theological proposal. w2.vatican.va/content/benedict-xvi/en/apost_exhortations/documents/hf_ben-
Ratzinger describes his friendship with Balthasar and the debt he owes to Balthasar’s xvi_exh_20070222_sacramentum-caritatis.html.
theology in his autobiography Milestones: Memoirs, 1927–1977 (San Francisco, CA: 20
John Paul II, Letter to Artists, § 3, par. 2.
Ignatius Press, 1998), 143. All the monographic works cited in note 7 above further 21
Balthasar, Seeing the Form, 19.
articulate and describe the relationhip between these two great theologians. In what 22
Ratzinger, “Wounded by the Arrow of Beauty,” 34; in the same text
follows I will expand Ratzinger’s arguments by using Balthasar’s work, for Ratzinger Ratzinger discloses that his own interpretation of Phaedrus is “based on the magnifi-
himself has on multiple occasions recognized his debt towards Balthasar’s theolog- cent interpretation of Platonic Eros in Joseph Pieper’s ‘Begeisterung und Göttlicher
ical aesthetics. In particular, see his “Wounded by the Arrow of Beauty,” 36. And Wahnsinn.’” Pieper’s interpretation of Phaedrus has been published in English with
Benedict XVI, “Meeting with Artists.” the title Enthusiasm and Divine Madness: On the Platonic Dialogue Phaedrus (New York,
18
Hans Urs von Balthasar, “Earthly Beauty and Divine Glory,” Communio NY: Harcourt, Brace & World, Inc., 1964). Given the importance of Pieper’s contri-
International Catholic Review 10, no. 3 (1983): 203. Balthasar provides an articulate de- bution for Ratzinger’s argument, I have referred extensively to this text.
fense of the opinion that beauty is a transcendental in his The Glory of the Lord: A 23
Pieper, Enthusiasm and Divine Madness, 75–76.
84 The Beauty that Pierces the Heart Alessandro Rovati 85
good and is restless, for it perceives that its original perfection is lost, and it and, instead, content themselves with the small pleasures and achievements
is not clear how to reach it again. As Plato puts it in the Symposium: “we used that life makes available to them. Furthermore, today the world is full of
to be complete wholes in our original nature, and now ‘Love’ is the name beauty that is “deceptive and false,” that “does not awaken a longing for the
for our pursuit of wholeness, for our desire to be complete.”24 And yet, con- ineffable, a willingness to sacrifice and to lose oneself, but instead stirs up the
tinues Plato, human beings are not sure what this completeness might look desire, the will for power, possession, and pleasure.”31 However, even in the
like, so much so that even when people are joined in love they “still cannot midst of the confusion and the many reductions that are present in contem-
say what it is that they want from one another. No one would think it is the porary culture, “there remains in the depths of [people’s] being an ultimate
intimacy of sex.… It is obvious that the soul of every lover longs for some- interior openness to truth, to love, to God.”32 Despite all their shortcomings,
thing else; his soul cannot say what it is, but like an oracle it has a sense of mistakes, and narrow-mindedness, human beings cannot completely forget
what it wants, and like an oracle it hides behind a riddle.”25 To describe this and extirpate from their hearts the yearning for the lost origin described by
human state Pieper speaks of “yearning,” “remembrance,” and “recollection Plato. Benedict XVI expressed this reality beautifully in his encyclical Spe
of origin,”26 while the theologian Pedro Escobar refers to the “poverty and Salvi: “Day by day, man experiences many greater or lesser hopes; …when
beggarliness of the human spirit.”27 The encounter with the “beauty we have these hopes are fulfilled, however, it becomes clear that they were not, in
down here” awakens the soul and directs it to the “true beauty,” yet such an reality, the whole. It becomes evident that man has need of a hope that goes
experience remains “beyond comprehension because they [those who en- further. It becomes clear that only something infinite will suffice for him,
counter beauty] cannot fully grasp what it is that they are seeing.”28 Beauty is something that will always be more than he can ever attain.”33 Accordingly,
a promise: “when we receive beauty in the proper way, we experience not so when touched by authentic beauty, the person is freed from the usual torpor
much a quenching of our thirst, satisfaction, and pleasure, as evocation of and distraction, for such an encounter “unlocks the yearning of the human
an expectancy; we are referred to something that is not-already-present.”29 heart, the profound desire to know, to love, to go towards the Other, to
Granting that such a description of the encounter with beauty might reach for Beyond.”34 Christianity is essentially open to and interested in the
sound too idealistic to the contemporary readers, Ratzinger argues that this experience of beauty, for beauty represents a call to transcendence, it stirs the
is more a sign of the culture in which we live, rather than a problem with the nostalgia for the Infinite that constitutes the human heart and thus becomes
Platonic description. We live “in the technological world, which is a self-made a path towards the ultimate Mystery—that is, God.
world of man.… [In it] it is only himself that man always encounters. The
fundamental structure of this world is feasibility.… Even the question of
salvation…is geared to the ability of man, who wants to become the engineer The Beauty Became Flesh
of himself and of history.… Creation is silent; …it speaks only the language
of mathematics, of technological utility.”30 Caught up in the routine of daily If in Plato the object of the ultimate human yearning for meaning and ful-
concerns and imbued with the rationalistic and materialistic prejudices of the fillment is unknown, in Christ the answer to our thirst and hunger for truth,
modern age, human beings seem to have lost their ability to appreciate the beauty, and justice is revealed to us,35 so that we now can say with Saint
glimpses of beauty that are present in the world and they let themselves be Augustine: “you have made us for yourself, and our heart is restless until it
lifted up beyond reality’s appearances. Many have simply given up the search rests in you.”36 That the Word became flesh (John 1:14) means that Beauty
for that “something” that might constitute the real fulfillment of their desires
31
Joseph Ratzinger, “Wounded by the Power of Beauty,” 40.
24
Plato, Symposium 192e. 32
Benedict XVI, Spe Salvi, § 46, November 30, 2007, accessed August 30,
25
Ibid., 192d. 2015, http://w2.vatican.va/content/benedict-xvi/en/encyclicals/documents/hf_
26
Pieper, Enthusiasm and Divine Madness, 79. ben-xvi_enc_20071130_spe-salvi.html.
27
Pedro Escobar, “Hans Urs Von Balthasar: Christo-Logian,” Communio Inter- 33
Benedict XVI, Spe Salvi, § 30, par. 1.
national Catholic Review 2, no. 3 (1975): 307. 34
Benedict XVI, “Meeting with Artists.”
28
Plato, Phaedrus 249d–250b. 35
A brief, but powerful statement of Ratzinger’s Christology can be found in
29
Pieper, Enthusiasm and Divine Madness, 85. his essay “Taking Bearings in Christology” in Joseph Ratzinger, Behold the Pierced One:
30
Joseph Ratzinger, Handing on the Faith in an Age of Disbelief (San Francisco, An Approach to a Spiritual Christology (San Francisco, CA: Ignatius Press, 1986), 13–46.
CA: Ignatius Press, 2006), 14–15. 36
Augustine, Confessions, I, 1.
84 The Beauty that Pierces the Heart Alessandro Rovati 85
good and is restless, for it perceives that its original perfection is lost, and it and, instead, content themselves with the small pleasures and achievements
is not clear how to reach it again. As Plato puts it in the Symposium: “we used that life makes available to them. Furthermore, today the world is full of
to be complete wholes in our original nature, and now ‘Love’ is the name beauty that is “deceptive and false,” that “does not awaken a longing for the
for our pursuit of wholeness, for our desire to be complete.”24 And yet, con- ineffable, a willingness to sacrifice and to lose oneself, but instead stirs up the
tinues Plato, human beings are not sure what this completeness might look desire, the will for power, possession, and pleasure.”31 However, even in the
like, so much so that even when people are joined in love they “still cannot midst of the confusion and the many reductions that are present in contem-
say what it is that they want from one another. No one would think it is the porary culture, “there remains in the depths of [people’s] being an ultimate
intimacy of sex.… It is obvious that the soul of every lover longs for some- interior openness to truth, to love, to God.”32 Despite all their shortcomings,
thing else; his soul cannot say what it is, but like an oracle it has a sense of mistakes, and narrow-mindedness, human beings cannot completely forget
what it wants, and like an oracle it hides behind a riddle.”25 To describe this and extirpate from their hearts the yearning for the lost origin described by
human state Pieper speaks of “yearning,” “remembrance,” and “recollection Plato. Benedict XVI expressed this reality beautifully in his encyclical Spe
of origin,”26 while the theologian Pedro Escobar refers to the “poverty and Salvi: “Day by day, man experiences many greater or lesser hopes; …when
beggarliness of the human spirit.”27 The encounter with the “beauty we have these hopes are fulfilled, however, it becomes clear that they were not, in
down here” awakens the soul and directs it to the “true beauty,” yet such an reality, the whole. It becomes evident that man has need of a hope that goes
experience remains “beyond comprehension because they [those who en- further. It becomes clear that only something infinite will suffice for him,
counter beauty] cannot fully grasp what it is that they are seeing.”28 Beauty is something that will always be more than he can ever attain.”33 Accordingly,
a promise: “when we receive beauty in the proper way, we experience not so when touched by authentic beauty, the person is freed from the usual torpor
much a quenching of our thirst, satisfaction, and pleasure, as evocation of and distraction, for such an encounter “unlocks the yearning of the human
an expectancy; we are referred to something that is not-already-present.”29 heart, the profound desire to know, to love, to go towards the Other, to
Granting that such a description of the encounter with beauty might reach for Beyond.”34 Christianity is essentially open to and interested in the
sound too idealistic to the contemporary readers, Ratzinger argues that this experience of beauty, for beauty represents a call to transcendence, it stirs the
is more a sign of the culture in which we live, rather than a problem with the nostalgia for the Infinite that constitutes the human heart and thus becomes
Platonic description. We live “in the technological world, which is a self-made a path towards the ultimate Mystery—that is, God.
world of man.… [In it] it is only himself that man always encounters. The
fundamental structure of this world is feasibility.… Even the question of
salvation…is geared to the ability of man, who wants to become the engineer The Beauty Became Flesh
of himself and of history.… Creation is silent; …it speaks only the language
of mathematics, of technological utility.”30 Caught up in the routine of daily If in Plato the object of the ultimate human yearning for meaning and ful-
concerns and imbued with the rationalistic and materialistic prejudices of the fillment is unknown, in Christ the answer to our thirst and hunger for truth,
modern age, human beings seem to have lost their ability to appreciate the beauty, and justice is revealed to us,35 so that we now can say with Saint
glimpses of beauty that are present in the world and they let themselves be Augustine: “you have made us for yourself, and our heart is restless until it
lifted up beyond reality’s appearances. Many have simply given up the search rests in you.”36 That the Word became flesh (John 1:14) means that Beauty
for that “something” that might constitute the real fulfillment of their desires
31
Joseph Ratzinger, “Wounded by the Power of Beauty,” 40.
24
Plato, Symposium 192e. 32
Benedict XVI, Spe Salvi, § 46, November 30, 2007, accessed August 30,
25
Ibid., 192d. 2015, http://w2.vatican.va/content/benedict-xvi/en/encyclicals/documents/hf_
26
Pieper, Enthusiasm and Divine Madness, 79. ben-xvi_enc_20071130_spe-salvi.html.
27
Pedro Escobar, “Hans Urs Von Balthasar: Christo-Logian,” Communio Inter- 33
Benedict XVI, Spe Salvi, § 30, par. 1.
national Catholic Review 2, no. 3 (1975): 307. 34
Benedict XVI, “Meeting with Artists.”
28
Plato, Phaedrus 249d–250b. 35
A brief, but powerful statement of Ratzinger’s Christology can be found in
29
Pieper, Enthusiasm and Divine Madness, 85. his essay “Taking Bearings in Christology” in Joseph Ratzinger, Behold the Pierced One:
30
Joseph Ratzinger, Handing on the Faith in an Age of Disbelief (San Francisco, An Approach to a Spiritual Christology (San Francisco, CA: Ignatius Press, 1986), 13–46.
CA: Ignatius Press, 2006), 14–15. 36
Augustine, Confessions, I, 1.
86 The Beauty that Pierces the Heart Alessandro Rovati 87
became flesh, so that the Church, making hers the words of Psalm 45, refers matter, can know him.”41 Accordingly, after the coming of Christ the prohi-
to Christ as “the most handsome among all men,” (Ps. 45:3) or, in the words bition to represent God with images falls, for the Lord has entered history
of the Eastern Orthodox tradition, as “the supremely Beautiful, possessed and started to act in our sensible world.42 Now “images of beauty, in which
of a beauty above all the children of earth.”37 The beauty that the Church the mystery of the invisible God becomes visible, are an essential part of
venerates in Christ is not first and foremost the external one, but rather, Christian worship”43 so much so that Ratzinger claims that Iconoclasm—the
as Ratzinger explains, “the beauty of Truth [that] appears in Him, the very absolute prohibition of artistic representation of God—is not “a Christian
beauty of God who draws us to Himself [by eliciting in us a] holy passion option.”44 The biblical prohibition of depicting the Lord is grounded in the
(eros), that enables us to go forth…to meet the Love who calls us.”38 will to avoid incarcerating the divine glory in a finite form—something that
In the Old Testament Moses, the true prophet, is described as the would inevitably lead to idolatry. God claims the right to choose the proper
one “whom the Lord knew face to face” (Deut. 34:10). More than all the form in which to appear, and Jesus is the image that God chose. In Him “God
miraculous deeds he accomplished and the inspired words he pronounced, has given himself an ‘image’: in Christ who was made man. In him who was
what made Moses unique was that he spoke with God. He was given a famil- crucified, the denial of false images of God is taken to an extreme. God now
iarity with the Lord that no one else in Israel ever imagined possible, for he reveals his true face in the figure of the sufferer who shares man’s God-for-
“spoke with God as with a friend.”39 Still, despite the gift of standing in the saken condition by taking it upon himself. This innocent sufferer has attained
presence of the Lord that Moses received, Scripture tells us that his relation- the certitude of hope: there is a God, and God can create justice in a way that
ship with God had limits. In Exodus the Lord tells Moses: “You shall see my we cannot conceive, yet we can begin to grasp it through faith.”45 The radical
back; but my face shall not be seen” (Exod. 33:23). Only in Jesus is what was novelty of Revelation is that in it “God has acted in history and entered into
imperfectly given to Moses finally fulfilled. “No one has ever seen God; it is our sensible world, so that it may become transparent to him.”46
the only Son, who is nearest to the Father’s heart who has made him known” Jesus is the Word, the expression of God that with his human exis-
(John 1:18). The glory of God is manifested in Jesus, for he is the form of tence bears witness to the Lord. The first disciples were captivated and trans-
God’s revelation to the world. To enter in communion with Jesus is to enter ported not by a message or a theory, but by a Person who so stood out in his
in communion with God, for “God becomes accessible to us through the encounters and conversations that, as Balthasar poetically explains, “as the
one he sent, Jesus Christ: it is in the encounter with him that we experience contours of his uniqueness emerge, suddenly and in an indescribable manner
the recognition of God that leads to communion and thus to ‘life.’”40
Earlier I mentioned the connection between the allegiance between
41
Joseph Ratzinger, “The Spirit of the Liturgy,” in Theology of the Liturgy: The
Sacramental Foundation of Christian Existence, vol. 1, Collected Works (San Francisco, CA:
Christianity and art with the mystery of the Incarnation. We can now ap-
Ignatius Press, 2008), 75.
preciate it even more. “The Incarnation means, in the first place, that the 42
While according to the modern spirit God’s place is the spiritual world,
invisible God enters into the visible world, so that we, who are bound to Ratzinger emphasizes that the God who made himself manifest in Jesus cannot be
pushed outside the course of history, for he has intervened directly in the material
world by becoming part of it. As a matter of fact, “God is God and he does not
merely operate at the level of ideas” (Benedict XVI, Jesus of Nazareth: The Infancy
37
Enkomia of the Orthós of the Holy and Great Saturday, quoted in John Paul II, Narratives [New York, NY: Image Books, 2012], 56). Ratzinger reflects on the re-
Letter to Artists, § 6, par. 4. lationship between faith and sensible experience in his Principles of Catholic Theology:
38
Joseph Ratzinger, “Wounded by the Power of Beauty,” 33. The use of the Building Stones for a Fundamental Theology (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1987), 343–55.
word eros is significant; “what is at stake here is the movement affected by seeing 43
Ratzinger, The Sacramental Foundation of Christian Existence, 81.
what God has shown. This is a movement of the entire person, leading away from 44
Ibid.
himself through the vision towards the invisible God” (Balthasar, Seeing the Form, 45
Benedict XVI, Spe Salvi, § 43.
118). The encounter with Jesus engages the whole human person, thus eliciting a 46
Ratzinger, The Spirit of the Liturgy, 131. Similarly Balthasar identifies Chris-
response to God’s initiative that involves the whole self. tianity in the fact that “man is not merely addressed in a total mystery, as if he were
39
Benedict XVI, Jesus of Nazareth: From the Baptism in the Jordan to the Transfigu- compelled to accept obediently in blind and naked faith something hidden from him,
ration (New York, NY: Doubleday, 2007), 4. but that something is ‘offered’ to man by God, …in such a way that man can see it,
40
Benedict XVI, Jesus of Nazareth. Part Two: Holy Week, from the Entrance into understand it, make it his own, and live from it in keeping with his human nature”
Jerusalem to the Resurrection (San Francisco, CA: Ignatius Press, 2011), 84. (Balthasar, Seeing the Form, 118).
86 The Beauty that Pierces the Heart Alessandro Rovati 87
became flesh, so that the Church, making hers the words of Psalm 45, refers matter, can know him.”41 Accordingly, after the coming of Christ the prohi-
to Christ as “the most handsome among all men,” (Ps. 45:3) or, in the words bition to represent God with images falls, for the Lord has entered history
of the Eastern Orthodox tradition, as “the supremely Beautiful, possessed and started to act in our sensible world.42 Now “images of beauty, in which
of a beauty above all the children of earth.”37 The beauty that the Church the mystery of the invisible God becomes visible, are an essential part of
venerates in Christ is not first and foremost the external one, but rather, Christian worship”43 so much so that Ratzinger claims that Iconoclasm—the
as Ratzinger explains, “the beauty of Truth [that] appears in Him, the very absolute prohibition of artistic representation of God—is not “a Christian
beauty of God who draws us to Himself [by eliciting in us a] holy passion option.”44 The biblical prohibition of depicting the Lord is grounded in the
(eros), that enables us to go forth…to meet the Love who calls us.”38 will to avoid incarcerating the divine glory in a finite form—something that
In the Old Testament Moses, the true prophet, is described as the would inevitably lead to idolatry. God claims the right to choose the proper
one “whom the Lord knew face to face” (Deut. 34:10). More than all the form in which to appear, and Jesus is the image that God chose. In Him “God
miraculous deeds he accomplished and the inspired words he pronounced, has given himself an ‘image’: in Christ who was made man. In him who was
what made Moses unique was that he spoke with God. He was given a famil- crucified, the denial of false images of God is taken to an extreme. God now
iarity with the Lord that no one else in Israel ever imagined possible, for he reveals his true face in the figure of the sufferer who shares man’s God-for-
“spoke with God as with a friend.”39 Still, despite the gift of standing in the saken condition by taking it upon himself. This innocent sufferer has attained
presence of the Lord that Moses received, Scripture tells us that his relation- the certitude of hope: there is a God, and God can create justice in a way that
ship with God had limits. In Exodus the Lord tells Moses: “You shall see my we cannot conceive, yet we can begin to grasp it through faith.”45 The radical
back; but my face shall not be seen” (Exod. 33:23). Only in Jesus is what was novelty of Revelation is that in it “God has acted in history and entered into
imperfectly given to Moses finally fulfilled. “No one has ever seen God; it is our sensible world, so that it may become transparent to him.”46
the only Son, who is nearest to the Father’s heart who has made him known” Jesus is the Word, the expression of God that with his human exis-
(John 1:18). The glory of God is manifested in Jesus, for he is the form of tence bears witness to the Lord. The first disciples were captivated and trans-
God’s revelation to the world. To enter in communion with Jesus is to enter ported not by a message or a theory, but by a Person who so stood out in his
in communion with God, for “God becomes accessible to us through the encounters and conversations that, as Balthasar poetically explains, “as the
one he sent, Jesus Christ: it is in the encounter with him that we experience contours of his uniqueness emerge, suddenly and in an indescribable manner
the recognition of God that leads to communion and thus to ‘life.’”40
Earlier I mentioned the connection between the allegiance between
41
Joseph Ratzinger, “The Spirit of the Liturgy,” in Theology of the Liturgy: The
Sacramental Foundation of Christian Existence, vol. 1, Collected Works (San Francisco, CA:
Christianity and art with the mystery of the Incarnation. We can now ap-
Ignatius Press, 2008), 75.
preciate it even more. “The Incarnation means, in the first place, that the 42
While according to the modern spirit God’s place is the spiritual world,
invisible God enters into the visible world, so that we, who are bound to Ratzinger emphasizes that the God who made himself manifest in Jesus cannot be
pushed outside the course of history, for he has intervened directly in the material
world by becoming part of it. As a matter of fact, “God is God and he does not
merely operate at the level of ideas” (Benedict XVI, Jesus of Nazareth: The Infancy
37
Enkomia of the Orthós of the Holy and Great Saturday, quoted in John Paul II, Narratives [New York, NY: Image Books, 2012], 56). Ratzinger reflects on the re-
Letter to Artists, § 6, par. 4. lationship between faith and sensible experience in his Principles of Catholic Theology:
38
Joseph Ratzinger, “Wounded by the Power of Beauty,” 33. The use of the Building Stones for a Fundamental Theology (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1987), 343–55.
word eros is significant; “what is at stake here is the movement affected by seeing 43
Ratzinger, The Sacramental Foundation of Christian Existence, 81.
what God has shown. This is a movement of the entire person, leading away from 44
Ibid.
himself through the vision towards the invisible God” (Balthasar, Seeing the Form, 45
Benedict XVI, Spe Salvi, § 43.
118). The encounter with Jesus engages the whole human person, thus eliciting a 46
Ratzinger, The Spirit of the Liturgy, 131. Similarly Balthasar identifies Chris-
response to God’s initiative that involves the whole self. tianity in the fact that “man is not merely addressed in a total mystery, as if he were
39
Benedict XVI, Jesus of Nazareth: From the Baptism in the Jordan to the Transfigu- compelled to accept obediently in blind and naked faith something hidden from him,
ration (New York, NY: Doubleday, 2007), 4. but that something is ‘offered’ to man by God, …in such a way that man can see it,
40
Benedict XVI, Jesus of Nazareth. Part Two: Holy Week, from the Entrance into understand it, make it his own, and live from it in keeping with his human nature”
Jerusalem to the Resurrection (San Francisco, CA: Ignatius Press, 2011), 84. (Balthasar, Seeing the Form, 118).
88 The Beauty that Pierces the Heart Alessandro Rovati 89
the ray of the Unconditional breaks through, casting a person down to ado- “Impassibilis est Deus, sed non incompassibilis”51 (God cannot suffer, but he
ration and transforming him into a believer and a follower.”47 By listening to can suffer with). “Man is worth so much to God that he himself became man
him, living with him, and following him, the disciples came to the astonishing in order to suffer with man in an utterly real way—in flesh and blood—as is
realization that Jesus is God himself. “They are privileged to see him as the revealed to us in the account of Jesus’s Passion.”52 In Jesus’s suffering God’s
one…who speaks face-to-face with the Father, person to person. They are glory is revealed, for the splendor of God’s love shines forth and draws all
privileged to see him in his utterly unique filial being.… They are privileged creatures to him. Christians do not turn to the Cross because of a morose
to see what the ‘people’ do not see, and this seeing gives rise to a recognition love of suffering, but because in it God manifested who he really is: “the
that goes beyond the ‘opinion’ of the people. This seeing is the wellspring of God who, in the unfathomable depth of his self-giving love, sets the true
their faith, their confession; it provides the foundation for the Church.”48 power of good against all the powers of evil,”53 thus donating us a new life
At this point a question needs to be asked. With all this talk about that not even death can defeat.
beauty, are we not forgetting that the world seems actually dominated by the
will to possess, to dominate others, and to be in power? Isn’t reality more
determined by the ugliness of violence and hatred, rather than by beauty? Beauty as a Source of Knowledge
Ratzinger is no stranger to this objection and he notes that even in the Scrip-
ture we can spot a similar tension. The “most handsome among all men” Let me use a passage from Benedict XVI’s Apostolic Exhortation Sacramen-
is also described in a radically different way by the prophet Isaiah: “He had tum Caritatis to offer a brief summary of his Christological understanding of
neither beauty, nor majesty, nothing to attract our eyes, no grace to make beauty. “In Jesus we contemplate beauty and splendor at their source. This is
us delight in him.” (Isa. 53:2) Clearly the Scripture suggests that we need to no mere aestheticism, but the concrete way in which the truth of God’s love
overcome the classical ideal of beauty as perfect harmony, so as to reach a in Christ encounters us, attracts us, and delights us, enabling us to emerge
more comprehensive understanding of beauty and truth. A new realism is from ourselves and drawing us towards our true vocation, which is love.”54
required, one that is able to embrace the reality of the suffering and struggle Once again, we see how, for Ratzinger, the category of beauty is fundamental.
that characterize our world, without succumbing to the temptation of taking The way to know Christ is to be touched by his beauty. Without undervaluing
refuge in an abstract idea of beauty that ignores the actual state of things. the importance of theological reflection, Ratzinger wants to emphasize how
The reality of the Cross witnesses to this new and more profound in this time dominated by confusion and divisions, even within the Church,
understanding of beauty, for the One who is the Word incarnate, the authen- abstract arguments about the faith are not able to effectively persuade us
tic Beauty, has accepted to be hit, tortured, and crowned with thorns. “In and our fellow human beings. What we need, instead, is to encounter again
this Face that is so disfigured, there appears the genuine, extreme beauty: the the beauty of faith—that is, to experience how the encounter with the per-
beauty of love that goes ‘to the very end’; (John 13:1) thus showing itself as sonal presence of Christ himself answers and corresponds to the deepest
greater than falsehood and violence.”49 The God who has manifested Him- yearnings of our heart. The beauty of Christ impresses itself on the soul
self as supreme love in the cross-shattered Christ50 shows us that the beauty and kindles desire, and, in so doing, it marks the beginning of a journey. We
of truth embraces pain, even the obscure mystery of death, so that hope may are not merely speaking of an emotional journey; 55 Ratzinger insists that the
determine our lives more than fear and hate. renewed encounter with the beauty of Christ allows us to reach a true and
Ratzinger reports an expression of Bernard of Clairvaux to further deep knowledge. In the process of being touched by Christ, in fact, our eyes
meditate on the mystery of the Cross. The medieval monk used to say that
51
This is a quote from one of Saint Bernard’s sermons (Sermones in Cant.,
Sermo 26, 5: PL 183, 906) used in Benedict XVI, Spe Salvi, § 39.
52
Benedict XVI, Spe Salvi, § 39
47
Ibid., 32. 53
Benedict XVI, Jesus of Nazareth. Part Two: Holy Week, from the Entrance into
48
Benedict XVI, Jesus of Nazareth: From the Baptism in the Jordan to the Transfig- Jerusalem to the Resurrection, 157.
uration, 291. 54
Benedict XVI, Sacramentum Caritatis, § 35, par. 1.
49
Ibid., 39. 55
Ratzinger warns us against the reduction of faith to sentimentalism in his
50
I owe this expression to Stanley Hauerwas’s book Cross-Shattered Christ: Med- Truth and Tolerance: Christian Belief and World Religions (San Francisco, CA: Ignatius
itations on the Seven Last Words (Grand Rapids, MI: Brazos Press, 2004). Press, 2004), 138–61.
88 The Beauty that Pierces the Heart Alessandro Rovati 89
the ray of the Unconditional breaks through, casting a person down to ado- “Impassibilis est Deus, sed non incompassibilis”51 (God cannot suffer, but he
ration and transforming him into a believer and a follower.”47 By listening to can suffer with). “Man is worth so much to God that he himself became man
him, living with him, and following him, the disciples came to the astonishing in order to suffer with man in an utterly real way—in flesh and blood—as is
realization that Jesus is God himself. “They are privileged to see him as the revealed to us in the account of Jesus’s Passion.”52 In Jesus’s suffering God’s
one…who speaks face-to-face with the Father, person to person. They are glory is revealed, for the splendor of God’s love shines forth and draws all
privileged to see him in his utterly unique filial being.… They are privileged creatures to him. Christians do not turn to the Cross because of a morose
to see what the ‘people’ do not see, and this seeing gives rise to a recognition love of suffering, but because in it God manifested who he really is: “the
that goes beyond the ‘opinion’ of the people. This seeing is the wellspring of God who, in the unfathomable depth of his self-giving love, sets the true
their faith, their confession; it provides the foundation for the Church.”48 power of good against all the powers of evil,”53 thus donating us a new life
At this point a question needs to be asked. With all this talk about that not even death can defeat.
beauty, are we not forgetting that the world seems actually dominated by the
will to possess, to dominate others, and to be in power? Isn’t reality more
determined by the ugliness of violence and hatred, rather than by beauty? Beauty as a Source of Knowledge
Ratzinger is no stranger to this objection and he notes that even in the Scrip-
ture we can spot a similar tension. The “most handsome among all men” Let me use a passage from Benedict XVI’s Apostolic Exhortation Sacramen-
is also described in a radically different way by the prophet Isaiah: “He had tum Caritatis to offer a brief summary of his Christological understanding of
neither beauty, nor majesty, nothing to attract our eyes, no grace to make beauty. “In Jesus we contemplate beauty and splendor at their source. This is
us delight in him.” (Isa. 53:2) Clearly the Scripture suggests that we need to no mere aestheticism, but the concrete way in which the truth of God’s love
overcome the classical ideal of beauty as perfect harmony, so as to reach a in Christ encounters us, attracts us, and delights us, enabling us to emerge
more comprehensive understanding of beauty and truth. A new realism is from ourselves and drawing us towards our true vocation, which is love.”54
required, one that is able to embrace the reality of the suffering and struggle Once again, we see how, for Ratzinger, the category of beauty is fundamental.
that characterize our world, without succumbing to the temptation of taking The way to know Christ is to be touched by his beauty. Without undervaluing
refuge in an abstract idea of beauty that ignores the actual state of things. the importance of theological reflection, Ratzinger wants to emphasize how
The reality of the Cross witnesses to this new and more profound in this time dominated by confusion and divisions, even within the Church,
understanding of beauty, for the One who is the Word incarnate, the authen- abstract arguments about the faith are not able to effectively persuade us
tic Beauty, has accepted to be hit, tortured, and crowned with thorns. “In and our fellow human beings. What we need, instead, is to encounter again
this Face that is so disfigured, there appears the genuine, extreme beauty: the the beauty of faith—that is, to experience how the encounter with the per-
beauty of love that goes ‘to the very end’; (John 13:1) thus showing itself as sonal presence of Christ himself answers and corresponds to the deepest
greater than falsehood and violence.”49 The God who has manifested Him- yearnings of our heart. The beauty of Christ impresses itself on the soul
self as supreme love in the cross-shattered Christ50 shows us that the beauty and kindles desire, and, in so doing, it marks the beginning of a journey. We
of truth embraces pain, even the obscure mystery of death, so that hope may are not merely speaking of an emotional journey; 55 Ratzinger insists that the
determine our lives more than fear and hate. renewed encounter with the beauty of Christ allows us to reach a true and
Ratzinger reports an expression of Bernard of Clairvaux to further deep knowledge. In the process of being touched by Christ, in fact, our eyes
meditate on the mystery of the Cross. The medieval monk used to say that
51
This is a quote from one of Saint Bernard’s sermons (Sermones in Cant.,
Sermo 26, 5: PL 183, 906) used in Benedict XVI, Spe Salvi, § 39.
52
Benedict XVI, Spe Salvi, § 39
47
Ibid., 32. 53
Benedict XVI, Jesus of Nazareth. Part Two: Holy Week, from the Entrance into
48
Benedict XVI, Jesus of Nazareth: From the Baptism in the Jordan to the Transfig- Jerusalem to the Resurrection, 157.
uration, 291. 54
Benedict XVI, Sacramentum Caritatis, § 35, par. 1.
49
Ibid., 39. 55
Ratzinger warns us against the reduction of faith to sentimentalism in his
50
I owe this expression to Stanley Hauerwas’s book Cross-Shattered Christ: Med- Truth and Tolerance: Christian Belief and World Religions (San Francisco, CA: Ignatius
itations on the Seven Last Words (Grand Rapids, MI: Brazos Press, 2004). Press, 2004), 138–61.
90 The Beauty that Pierces the Heart Alessandro Rovati 91
are open, our soul is reawakened, and we become able to judge starting from a present event,62 for, to use a powerful expression of Pope Francis, Jesus
experience what truly corresponds to our nature. “impacts us, shocks us, and renews us”63 today just as he did with his first
After becoming Pope, Ratzinger wonderfully expressed these in- disciples two thousand years ago.
sights in the beginning of his first encyclical Deus Caritas Est. “Being Chris- On multiple occasions Ratzinger has reflected on the fact that “the
tian is not the result of an ethical choice or a lofty idea, but the encounter only effective apologia for Christianity comes down to two arguments, name-
with an event, a person, which gives life a new horizon and a decisive direc- ly, the saints the Church has produced and the art which has grown in her
tion.”56 A philosophical abstraction or an ethical ideal would not have needed womb. Better witness is borne to the Lord by the splendor of holiness and
a mother. God, instead, is recognizable because He is a “You” that comes art which have arisen in the community of believers than by the clever ex-
forward and enters into a relationship with us. cuses which apologetics has come up with.”64 Faith is not maintained auto-
Faith presupposes a personal “encounter with the living God,”57 but matically; “it is not a ‘finished business’ that can be simply taken for granted.
can we participate today in Christ’s victory over death? How does Christ The life of faith needs to be constantly renewed.”65 The great service that the
remain present and continue to take initiative to befriend us? I quote again Church can and must offer to humanity is “to be an icon of divine beauty,
from one of Benedict XVI’s meditations: “The Event of Christ goes on in a burning flame of charity, a path so that the world may believe in the One
history through the companionship of the believers.… The companionship whom God has sent (cf. John 6:29).”66 This is why now, more than ever, the
of the believers is the effective sign of Christ’s salvation for human beings; it Church needs to be a place where beauty is cherished67 and where people
is the sacrament of the world’s salvation. This is how the risen Christ holds
encounter with the true God, a light which touches us at the core of our being and
us in His embrace; this companionship is Christ himself present.”58 The engages our minds, wills and emotions, opening us to relationships lived in commu-
Church is the presence of Christ; it is the way God remains contemporane- nion” (Francis, Lumen Fidei, § 40, par. 2, June 29, 2013, accessed August 30, 2015,
ous with us, which means that the Church is Christ’s “simultaneousness with https://w2.vatican.va/content/francesco/en/encyclicals/documents/papa-fran-
us.”59 Christianity is neither a fact of the past nor a hope for the future.60 It cesco_20130629_enciclica-lumen-fidei.html). The way Ratzinger’s Christological
is neither a list of dogmas nor a system of moral precepts.61 Christianity is focus is shaping Francis’s moral vision is, I think, one of the most fruitful lines of
enquiry for future theological research.
56
Benedict XVI, Deus Caritas Est, § 1, par. 2, December 25, 2005, accessed 62
My insistence on the “present” of the faith, which I draw from Ratzinger’s
August 30, 2015, http://w2.vatican.va/content/benedict-xvi/en/encyclicals/docu- theology, should not in any way be taken as a rejection or denial of the essentially es-
ments/hf_ben-xvi_enc_20051225_deus-caritas-est.html. chatological meaning of the Christian existence. On the topic, see Joseph Ratzinger,
57
Ibid., § 28, par. 4. Eschatology: Death and Eternal Life (Washington, D.C.: Catholic University of America
58
Benedict XVI, “Meditation during the First General Congregation of the Press, 1988). See also the meditations on Advent contained in What It Means to Be a
13th General Assembly of the Synod of Bishops,” October 8, 2012, accessed on Christian: Three Sermons (San Francisco, CA: Ignatius Press, 2006).
August 30, 2015, http://w2.vatican.va/content/benedict-xvi/en/speeches/2012/ 63
Francis, “Letter to a Non-Believer” in L’Osservatore Romano, Weekly Edition
october/documents/hf_ben-xvi_spe_20121008_meditazione-sinodo.html. in English, September 18, 2013, 9.
59
Joseph Ratzinger, Church, Ecumenism and Politics: New Essays in Ecclesiology 64
Joseph Ratzinger and Vittorio Messori, The Ratzinger Report: An Exclusive In-
(San Francisco, CA: Ignatius Press, 2008), p. 14. terview on the State of the Church (San Francisco, CA: Ignatius Press, 1985), pp. 129–30.
60
Benedict XVI, Jesus of Nazareth. Part Two: Holy Week, from the Entrance into 65
Joseph Ratzinger, Gospel, Catechesis, Catechism: Sidelights on the Catechism of the
Jerusalem to the Resurrection, 289: “Christian prayer for the Lord’s return always includes Catholic Church (San Francisco, CA: Ignatius Press, 1997), 23.
the experience of his presence. It is never purely focused on the future. The words 66
Benedict XVI, “Holy Mass with Dedication of the Church of the Sagra-
of the risen Lord make the point: ‘I am with you always to the close of the age’ (Matt. da Familia and of the Altar,” par. 9, November 7, 2010, accessed on August 30,
28:20).” 2015, http://w2.vatican.va/content/benedict-xvi/en/homilies/2010/documents/
61
I want to briefly emphasize the fundamental continuity that exists on this hf_ben-xvi_hom_20101107_barcelona.html.
point between Benedict XVI and Pope Francis. Among the many signs of the unity 67
This is why Ratzinger has always emphasized the need to cultivate the beau-
among the two is the fact that Francis decided to publish the encyclical Lumen Fidei ty of the liturgy, not for a mere antiquarianism or aestheticism, but because the
that, as he acknowledges in the Introduction, had been completed by Ratzinger be- Church “is to transform, improve, ‘humanize’ the world—but how can she do that if
fore his resignation. In it the Popes argue that “for transmitting a purely doctrinal at the same time she turns her back on beauty, which is so closely allied to love? For
content, an idea might suffice, or perhaps a book, or the repetition of a spoken together, beauty and love form the true consolation in this world, bringing it as near
message. But what is communicated in the Church…is the new light born of an as possible to the world of the resurrection. The Church must maintain high stan-
90 The Beauty that Pierces the Heart Alessandro Rovati 91
are open, our soul is reawakened, and we become able to judge starting from a present event,62 for, to use a powerful expression of Pope Francis, Jesus
experience what truly corresponds to our nature. “impacts us, shocks us, and renews us”63 today just as he did with his first
After becoming Pope, Ratzinger wonderfully expressed these in- disciples two thousand years ago.
sights in the beginning of his first encyclical Deus Caritas Est. “Being Chris- On multiple occasions Ratzinger has reflected on the fact that “the
tian is not the result of an ethical choice or a lofty idea, but the encounter only effective apologia for Christianity comes down to two arguments, name-
with an event, a person, which gives life a new horizon and a decisive direc- ly, the saints the Church has produced and the art which has grown in her
tion.”56 A philosophical abstraction or an ethical ideal would not have needed womb. Better witness is borne to the Lord by the splendor of holiness and
a mother. God, instead, is recognizable because He is a “You” that comes art which have arisen in the community of believers than by the clever ex-
forward and enters into a relationship with us. cuses which apologetics has come up with.”64 Faith is not maintained auto-
Faith presupposes a personal “encounter with the living God,”57 but matically; “it is not a ‘finished business’ that can be simply taken for granted.
can we participate today in Christ’s victory over death? How does Christ The life of faith needs to be constantly renewed.”65 The great service that the
remain present and continue to take initiative to befriend us? I quote again Church can and must offer to humanity is “to be an icon of divine beauty,
from one of Benedict XVI’s meditations: “The Event of Christ goes on in a burning flame of charity, a path so that the world may believe in the One
history through the companionship of the believers.… The companionship whom God has sent (cf. John 6:29).”66 This is why now, more than ever, the
of the believers is the effective sign of Christ’s salvation for human beings; it Church needs to be a place where beauty is cherished67 and where people
is the sacrament of the world’s salvation. This is how the risen Christ holds
encounter with the true God, a light which touches us at the core of our being and
us in His embrace; this companionship is Christ himself present.”58 The engages our minds, wills and emotions, opening us to relationships lived in commu-
Church is the presence of Christ; it is the way God remains contemporane- nion” (Francis, Lumen Fidei, § 40, par. 2, June 29, 2013, accessed August 30, 2015,
ous with us, which means that the Church is Christ’s “simultaneousness with https://w2.vatican.va/content/francesco/en/encyclicals/documents/papa-fran-
us.”59 Christianity is neither a fact of the past nor a hope for the future.60 It cesco_20130629_enciclica-lumen-fidei.html). The way Ratzinger’s Christological
is neither a list of dogmas nor a system of moral precepts.61 Christianity is focus is shaping Francis’s moral vision is, I think, one of the most fruitful lines of
enquiry for future theological research.
56
Benedict XVI, Deus Caritas Est, § 1, par. 2, December 25, 2005, accessed 62
My insistence on the “present” of the faith, which I draw from Ratzinger’s
August 30, 2015, http://w2.vatican.va/content/benedict-xvi/en/encyclicals/docu- theology, should not in any way be taken as a rejection or denial of the essentially es-
ments/hf_ben-xvi_enc_20051225_deus-caritas-est.html. chatological meaning of the Christian existence. On the topic, see Joseph Ratzinger,
57
Ibid., § 28, par. 4. Eschatology: Death and Eternal Life (Washington, D.C.: Catholic University of America
58
Benedict XVI, “Meditation during the First General Congregation of the Press, 1988). See also the meditations on Advent contained in What It Means to Be a
13th General Assembly of the Synod of Bishops,” October 8, 2012, accessed on Christian: Three Sermons (San Francisco, CA: Ignatius Press, 2006).
August 30, 2015, http://w2.vatican.va/content/benedict-xvi/en/speeches/2012/ 63
Francis, “Letter to a Non-Believer” in L’Osservatore Romano, Weekly Edition
october/documents/hf_ben-xvi_spe_20121008_meditazione-sinodo.html. in English, September 18, 2013, 9.
59
Joseph Ratzinger, Church, Ecumenism and Politics: New Essays in Ecclesiology 64
Joseph Ratzinger and Vittorio Messori, The Ratzinger Report: An Exclusive In-
(San Francisco, CA: Ignatius Press, 2008), p. 14. terview on the State of the Church (San Francisco, CA: Ignatius Press, 1985), pp. 129–30.
60
Benedict XVI, Jesus of Nazareth. Part Two: Holy Week, from the Entrance into 65
Joseph Ratzinger, Gospel, Catechesis, Catechism: Sidelights on the Catechism of the
Jerusalem to the Resurrection, 289: “Christian prayer for the Lord’s return always includes Catholic Church (San Francisco, CA: Ignatius Press, 1997), 23.
the experience of his presence. It is never purely focused on the future. The words 66
Benedict XVI, “Holy Mass with Dedication of the Church of the Sagra-
of the risen Lord make the point: ‘I am with you always to the close of the age’ (Matt. da Familia and of the Altar,” par. 9, November 7, 2010, accessed on August 30,
28:20).” 2015, http://w2.vatican.va/content/benedict-xvi/en/homilies/2010/documents/
61
I want to briefly emphasize the fundamental continuity that exists on this hf_ben-xvi_hom_20101107_barcelona.html.
point between Benedict XVI and Pope Francis. Among the many signs of the unity 67
This is why Ratzinger has always emphasized the need to cultivate the beau-
among the two is the fact that Francis decided to publish the encyclical Lumen Fidei ty of the liturgy, not for a mere antiquarianism or aestheticism, but because the
that, as he acknowledges in the Introduction, had been completed by Ratzinger be- Church “is to transform, improve, ‘humanize’ the world—but how can she do that if
fore his resignation. In it the Popes argue that “for transmitting a purely doctrinal at the same time she turns her back on beauty, which is so closely allied to love? For
content, an idea might suffice, or perhaps a book, or the repetition of a spoken together, beauty and love form the true consolation in this world, bringing it as near
message. But what is communicated in the Church…is the new light born of an as possible to the world of the resurrection. The Church must maintain high stan-
92 The Beauty that Pierces the Heart Alessandro Rovati 93
are encouraged to encounter the saints, “the true bearers of light within his- ceive that their lives bear witness to something better, Someone greater than
tory, for they are men and women of faith, hope and love.”68 Faith is not a them. Think, for example, of the many sisters and brothers who in these days
purely inward truth, for the truth that faith discloses is a truth centered on are shedding their blood for the faith, a sign that Christ’s love “till the end” is
an encounter with Christ who meets us “ever anew in the men and women real, and that not even death and suffering can defeat it.
who reflect his presence, in his word, in the sacraments, and especially in the Ratzinger certainly agrees with Dostoyevsky’s famous statement in
Eucharist. In the Church’s Liturgy, in her prayer, in the living community of his novel The Idiot that “the beautiful will save us;”74 what the Russian writer
believers, we experience the love of God, we perceive his presence and we is referring to, though, is not just any beauty, but the redemptive beauty of
thus learn to recognize that presence in our daily lives.”69 Christ. That is why Ratzinger insists that a renewed conversion is possible; it
The beauty of Christ is now living in the human reality of the is possible to be signs of hope in a world of despair, provided that we learn
Church,70 his body, and, especially, in the lives of the saints, that is, those to see Christ in our midst. There are two conditions necessary for that to
whose lives would not make sense if God did not exist. The truth of Chris- happen. First, that we let ourselves be educated by the light of faith so that
tian claims depends on the truthfulness of the lives of those who confess we may have our eyes open and our hearts ready to recognize and welcome
Jesus Christ as their Lord, so that witness, rather than argument, is the real God’s gratuitous initiative.75 Second, that we participate in the life where God
apology of Christianity. Even today faith can be born in us, if our hearts are has decided to make himself present, namely, the life of the Church, the
pierced by the lives of those whom Christ has called and in whom the new- Body of Christ, with its saints and sacraments.76 Only “if we know Him, not
ness of life that is made possible by the encounter with him shines forth. only in words, but if we are struck by the arrow of his paradoxical beauty,
Ratzinger is not referring exclusively to the great figures of saints then we will truly know him, and know him not only because we have heard
who were recognized officially by the Church, for “holiness does not consist others speak about him. Then we will have found the beauty of Truth, of the
in adventurous achievements of virtue, but in joining him [Christ] loving. Truth that redeems.”77
Hence the real saints are also the quite human, quite natural people in whom
through the Easter transformation and purification what is human appears —Belmont Abbey College
afresh in its total originality and beauty.”71 In them we see what a life trans-
formed by the Gospel looks like and we have a glimpse of what eternal life
is.
Eternal life is not primarily the life that will come after death, as
opposed to our current existence on earth. Instead, “‘eternal life’ is life itself,
real life, which can also be lived in the present age and is no longer challenged
by physical death. This is the point: to seize ‘life’ here and now, real life that
can no longer be destroyed by anything or anyone.”72 When one meets the
“living”—as the first Christians called themselves73—one cannot but per-

dards; she must be a place where beauty can be at home; she must lead the struggle
for that ‘spiritualization’ without which the world becomes the ‘Worst circle of hell’”
(Ratzinger, The Feast of Faith: Approaches to a Theology of the Liturgy, 124–25).
68
Benedict XVI, Deus Caritas Est, § 40.
69
Ibid., 17.
70
For a good exposition of Ratzinger’s ecclesiology, see his Called to Commu- 74
Ratzinger refers to this quote in his “Wounded by the Power of Beauty,” 41.
nion: Understanding the Church Today (San Francisco, CA: Ignatius Press, 1996). 75
See Benedict XVI, Deus Caritas Est, § 31.
71
Benedict XVI, The Yes of Jesus Christ: Exercises in Faith, Hope, and Love (New 76
For Ratzinger’s contribution on the Eucharistic nature of the Church and
York, NY: Crossroad Publishing Company, 1991), 105. the importance of the Eucharist for the Christian life, see the essays, addresses, and
72
Benedict XVI, Jesus of Nazareth. Part Two: Holy Week, from the Entrance into homilies collected in, “The Celebration of the Eucharist: Source and Summit of
Jerusalem to the Resurrection, 83. Christian Life,” part C of The Sacramental Foundation of Christian Existence, 187–417.
73
Ibid. 77
Joseph Ratzinger, “Wounded by the Power of Beauty,” 41.
92 The Beauty that Pierces the Heart Alessandro Rovati 93
are encouraged to encounter the saints, “the true bearers of light within his- ceive that their lives bear witness to something better, Someone greater than
tory, for they are men and women of faith, hope and love.”68 Faith is not a them. Think, for example, of the many sisters and brothers who in these days
purely inward truth, for the truth that faith discloses is a truth centered on are shedding their blood for the faith, a sign that Christ’s love “till the end” is
an encounter with Christ who meets us “ever anew in the men and women real, and that not even death and suffering can defeat it.
who reflect his presence, in his word, in the sacraments, and especially in the Ratzinger certainly agrees with Dostoyevsky’s famous statement in
Eucharist. In the Church’s Liturgy, in her prayer, in the living community of his novel The Idiot that “the beautiful will save us;”74 what the Russian writer
believers, we experience the love of God, we perceive his presence and we is referring to, though, is not just any beauty, but the redemptive beauty of
thus learn to recognize that presence in our daily lives.”69 Christ. That is why Ratzinger insists that a renewed conversion is possible; it
The beauty of Christ is now living in the human reality of the is possible to be signs of hope in a world of despair, provided that we learn
Church,70 his body, and, especially, in the lives of the saints, that is, those to see Christ in our midst. There are two conditions necessary for that to
whose lives would not make sense if God did not exist. The truth of Chris- happen. First, that we let ourselves be educated by the light of faith so that
tian claims depends on the truthfulness of the lives of those who confess we may have our eyes open and our hearts ready to recognize and welcome
Jesus Christ as their Lord, so that witness, rather than argument, is the real God’s gratuitous initiative.75 Second, that we participate in the life where God
apology of Christianity. Even today faith can be born in us, if our hearts are has decided to make himself present, namely, the life of the Church, the
pierced by the lives of those whom Christ has called and in whom the new- Body of Christ, with its saints and sacraments.76 Only “if we know Him, not
ness of life that is made possible by the encounter with him shines forth. only in words, but if we are struck by the arrow of his paradoxical beauty,
Ratzinger is not referring exclusively to the great figures of saints then we will truly know him, and know him not only because we have heard
who were recognized officially by the Church, for “holiness does not consist others speak about him. Then we will have found the beauty of Truth, of the
in adventurous achievements of virtue, but in joining him [Christ] loving. Truth that redeems.”77
Hence the real saints are also the quite human, quite natural people in whom
through the Easter transformation and purification what is human appears —Belmont Abbey College
afresh in its total originality and beauty.”71 In them we see what a life trans-
formed by the Gospel looks like and we have a glimpse of what eternal life
is.
Eternal life is not primarily the life that will come after death, as
opposed to our current existence on earth. Instead, “‘eternal life’ is life itself,
real life, which can also be lived in the present age and is no longer challenged
by physical death. This is the point: to seize ‘life’ here and now, real life that
can no longer be destroyed by anything or anyone.”72 When one meets the
“living”—as the first Christians called themselves73—one cannot but per-

dards; she must be a place where beauty can be at home; she must lead the struggle
for that ‘spiritualization’ without which the world becomes the ‘Worst circle of hell’”
(Ratzinger, The Feast of Faith: Approaches to a Theology of the Liturgy, 124–25).
68
Benedict XVI, Deus Caritas Est, § 40.
69
Ibid., 17.
70
For a good exposition of Ratzinger’s ecclesiology, see his Called to Commu- 74
Ratzinger refers to this quote in his “Wounded by the Power of Beauty,” 41.
nion: Understanding the Church Today (San Francisco, CA: Ignatius Press, 1996). 75
See Benedict XVI, Deus Caritas Est, § 31.
71
Benedict XVI, The Yes of Jesus Christ: Exercises in Faith, Hope, and Love (New 76
For Ratzinger’s contribution on the Eucharistic nature of the Church and
York, NY: Crossroad Publishing Company, 1991), 105. the importance of the Eucharist for the Christian life, see the essays, addresses, and
72
Benedict XVI, Jesus of Nazareth. Part Two: Holy Week, from the Entrance into homilies collected in, “The Celebration of the Eucharist: Source and Summit of
Jerusalem to the Resurrection, 83. Christian Life,” part C of The Sacramental Foundation of Christian Existence, 187–417.
73
Ibid. 77
Joseph Ratzinger, “Wounded by the Power of Beauty,” 41.
Sister Mary Eucharista, SMMC 95

Beauty and Hermeneutic Identity tradition exercises over us.” In “reading” and recognizing tradition, we begin
to take it upon ourselves to generate a “shared community of meaning,” the
in Consecrated Life: Gadamer and the fulfillment of festival or celebration, where tradition is transmitted rather
than conserved, where we learn “to grasp and express the past anew,” finally
“Icon of the Transfigured Christ” encountering it. Festival unites everyone, reminding us that in our quest for
understanding, beauty and truth, we have hope in ultimate fulfillment. Since
human life on earth is a preparation for the eschatological2 fulfillment of
Sister Mary Eucharista, SMMC
Eternity, this festival, signified by the Eternal Banquet or “Supper of the
Lamb,”3 is at the heart of the dialogue with the “Icon of the Transfigured
“Thank you, Sister, for wearing your habit!” “Mom, a blue fairy!” “Sister,
Christ,” the religious, and this is a reminder of the transcendent destiny of
would you and your sisters pray for my special request?” Comments that
spring spontaneously from the lips of persons who encounter religious the human person.
demonstrate that those in consecrated life keep up a consistent dialogue with
those who observe them, oftentimes without words. Consecrated life serves
as a sign to those who live it, and for those who view it from without. The
The Icon of the Transfigured Christ
variety of reactions and responses to the sight of a religious sister, brother,
John Paul II writes that consecrated life, profoundly established in the model
or priest in habit show that this sign is significant enough to comment upon,
of Jesus Christ in His life and teaching, is “a gift of God the Father to His
creating wonder at a kind of beauty discerned by the observer and reminding
Church through the Holy Spirit” whereby the religious—in the profession
him or her of the transcendence of human existence. In 1996, Saint Pope
of the evangelical counsels of poverty, chastity, and obedience—continu-
John Paul II wrote an Apostolic Exhortation in honor of Consecrated life
ally reveals the “characteristic features of Jesus.”4 These features “are made
called Vita Consecrata (On Consecrated Life), where he calls the religious the
constantly ‘visible’ in the midst of the world,” and those who view this “icon of
“Icon of the Transfigured Christ,” linking those living the evangelical coun-
the transfigured Christ,” are guided towards the “mystery of the Kingdom
sels with “Christ’s radiant face in the mystery of the Transfiguration.”1
of God already at work in history, even as it awaits its full realization in
In his essay, The Relevance of the Beautiful, Hans-Georg Gadamer ac-
heaven.”5 The “universal presence and the evangelical nature of its witness”
knowledges hermeneutic identity, and therein, symbol and festival, or cel-
clearly indicate that the life of consecration is “a reality which affects the
ebration, in art. Every art piece is a tradition or history that addresses the
whole Church…‘which concerns us all’…[and] is at the very heart of the Church
viewer, according to Gadamer, and the viewer responds according to his or
as a decisive element for her mission, since it ‘manifests the inner nature of
her tradition. Art can reveal and also conceals the yet-to-be revealed. In view-
the Christian calling’ and the striving of the whole Church as Bride towards
ing the “icon” of consecrated life through Gadamer’s aesthetics, this paper
union with her one Spouse.”6
will discuss several of his keys to understanding any art, including the uni-
Consecrated life was not only an assistance to the Church in former
versal, the ontological function, the connection between beauty and truth,
years, but is also “a precious and necessary gift for the present and the future
and philosophical aesthetics—with some aspects of Kant’s Third Critique.
of the People of God, since it is an intimate part of her life, her holiness
Gadamer addresses hermeneutic identity whereby a challenge is issued by the
and her mission.”7 Though the call is individual to those who receive it (the
work and is accepted by the viewer. In this “dialogue,” Gadamer’s process of
religious accepting his or her personal vocation), the universal sign of those
recognition discussed in his analysis of symbol “elicits the permanent from
the transient” and assists us in becoming more aware of the “power that 2
Eschatology refers to a branch of theology that deals with the end of ma-
terial existence and death, judgment, heaven and hell, the “four last things,” and
1
John Paul II, Vita Consecrata, § 14, par. 2, March 25, 1996, accessed August reunion with the Divine.
29, 2014, http://w2.vatican.va/content/john-paul-ii/en/apost_exhortations/doc- 3
Rev. 19:9, New American Bible Revised Edition.
uments/hf_jp-ii_exh_25031996_vita-consecrata.html. (Hereafter Vita Consecrata is 4
John Paul II, VC, § 1, par. 1.
referred to as VC.) 5
Ibid.
6
Ibid., § 3.
© Sister Mary Eucharista, SMMC, Quaestiones Disputatae, Vol. 6, No. 2 (Spring 2016) 7
Ibid.
Sister Mary Eucharista, SMMC 95

Beauty and Hermeneutic Identity tradition exercises over us.” In “reading” and recognizing tradition, we begin
to take it upon ourselves to generate a “shared community of meaning,” the
in Consecrated Life: Gadamer and the fulfillment of festival or celebration, where tradition is transmitted rather
than conserved, where we learn “to grasp and express the past anew,” finally
“Icon of the Transfigured Christ” encountering it. Festival unites everyone, reminding us that in our quest for
understanding, beauty and truth, we have hope in ultimate fulfillment. Since
human life on earth is a preparation for the eschatological2 fulfillment of
Sister Mary Eucharista, SMMC
Eternity, this festival, signified by the Eternal Banquet or “Supper of the
Lamb,”3 is at the heart of the dialogue with the “Icon of the Transfigured
“Thank you, Sister, for wearing your habit!” “Mom, a blue fairy!” “Sister,
Christ,” the religious, and this is a reminder of the transcendent destiny of
would you and your sisters pray for my special request?” Comments that
spring spontaneously from the lips of persons who encounter religious the human person.
demonstrate that those in consecrated life keep up a consistent dialogue with
those who observe them, oftentimes without words. Consecrated life serves
as a sign to those who live it, and for those who view it from without. The
The Icon of the Transfigured Christ
variety of reactions and responses to the sight of a religious sister, brother,
John Paul II writes that consecrated life, profoundly established in the model
or priest in habit show that this sign is significant enough to comment upon,
of Jesus Christ in His life and teaching, is “a gift of God the Father to His
creating wonder at a kind of beauty discerned by the observer and reminding
Church through the Holy Spirit” whereby the religious—in the profession
him or her of the transcendence of human existence. In 1996, Saint Pope
of the evangelical counsels of poverty, chastity, and obedience—continu-
John Paul II wrote an Apostolic Exhortation in honor of Consecrated life
ally reveals the “characteristic features of Jesus.”4 These features “are made
called Vita Consecrata (On Consecrated Life), where he calls the religious the
constantly ‘visible’ in the midst of the world,” and those who view this “icon of
“Icon of the Transfigured Christ,” linking those living the evangelical coun-
the transfigured Christ,” are guided towards the “mystery of the Kingdom
sels with “Christ’s radiant face in the mystery of the Transfiguration.”1
of God already at work in history, even as it awaits its full realization in
In his essay, The Relevance of the Beautiful, Hans-Georg Gadamer ac-
heaven.”5 The “universal presence and the evangelical nature of its witness”
knowledges hermeneutic identity, and therein, symbol and festival, or cel-
clearly indicate that the life of consecration is “a reality which affects the
ebration, in art. Every art piece is a tradition or history that addresses the
whole Church…‘which concerns us all’…[and] is at the very heart of the Church
viewer, according to Gadamer, and the viewer responds according to his or
as a decisive element for her mission, since it ‘manifests the inner nature of
her tradition. Art can reveal and also conceals the yet-to-be revealed. In view-
the Christian calling’ and the striving of the whole Church as Bride towards
ing the “icon” of consecrated life through Gadamer’s aesthetics, this paper
union with her one Spouse.”6
will discuss several of his keys to understanding any art, including the uni-
Consecrated life was not only an assistance to the Church in former
versal, the ontological function, the connection between beauty and truth,
years, but is also “a precious and necessary gift for the present and the future
and philosophical aesthetics—with some aspects of Kant’s Third Critique.
of the People of God, since it is an intimate part of her life, her holiness
Gadamer addresses hermeneutic identity whereby a challenge is issued by the
and her mission.”7 Though the call is individual to those who receive it (the
work and is accepted by the viewer. In this “dialogue,” Gadamer’s process of
religious accepting his or her personal vocation), the universal sign of those
recognition discussed in his analysis of symbol “elicits the permanent from
the transient” and assists us in becoming more aware of the “power that 2
Eschatology refers to a branch of theology that deals with the end of ma-
terial existence and death, judgment, heaven and hell, the “four last things,” and
1
John Paul II, Vita Consecrata, § 14, par. 2, March 25, 1996, accessed August reunion with the Divine.
29, 2014, http://w2.vatican.va/content/john-paul-ii/en/apost_exhortations/doc- 3
Rev. 19:9, New American Bible Revised Edition.
uments/hf_jp-ii_exh_25031996_vita-consecrata.html. (Hereafter Vita Consecrata is 4
John Paul II, VC, § 1, par. 1.
referred to as VC.) 5
Ibid.
6
Ibid., § 3.
© Sister Mary Eucharista, SMMC, Quaestiones Disputatae, Vol. 6, No. 2 (Spring 2016) 7
Ibid.
96 Beauty and Hermeneutic Identity Sister Mary Eucharista, SMMC 97
who receive their vocation, and have it confirmed through acceptance to a of Jesus to come and follow Him. In leaving their ordinary lives to surround
community, alerts all those who encounter the religious that “the profession Him as His chosen followers and closest companions, learning from the Pro-
of the evangelical counsels is an integral part of the Church’s life and a much tagonist and Author of the Gospel Himself how to live authentic Gospel
needed incentive towards ever greater fidelity to the Gospel.”8 The substance values, they had entered into a special relationship with Him. Now they were
of the choice to gift one’s life in a profound and deep-rooted demonstration invited by His Father to listen to Him, who was now radiant of face and
of love for Jesus Christ—and in Him, for each person on earth—encourages brighter than lightning, conversing with two of the greatest champions of
and supports the Christian people en route to the Eschaton (Eternal Life), Jewish leadership, prophesy, story, and tradition. This realization settled deep
since they can draw from religious powerful support even by the ministry of into their souls enabling them to contemplate the mystery before their eyes,
their presence.9 not understanding it immediately, but in time perhaps more able to compre-
In the mystery of the Transfiguration, the Apostles that accompanied hend the reality, not only of the event of the Transfiguration, but also of
Jesus were brought to a high mountain, Tabor, where they were introduced to Jesus’s divine Kingship.
a ground-shaking experience in beholding their Friend and Master, Jesus, in All are called to contemplate this mystery; however, those called to
unexpected glory. This was an event quite reminiscent of Moses’s close com- that unique vocation, where all is given over to Christ by their profession of
munication with the Divine over forty days in the cloud of the Glory of God vows, are made a “kind of sign and prophetic statement for the community of
(Shekinah) on Mount Sinai, as related in Exodus, 24:16–18 and 34:29. During the brethren and for the world.”12 As a result, Peter’s words, “Lord, it is well
the Transfiguration, the radiance of Moses and the radiance of Jesus were that we are here,”13 not only indicate the thrust of the Christian life—making
akin in their connection with the Glory of God—and of course Moses being Christ the ultimate focus—but also express the profundity of the vocation
present with Elijah—showed the unbroken connection of the tradition that of consecrated life. It is indeed good to be where He is the center of one’s
was being passed on. This was to Christianity a tradition of promise, living life; where nothing distracts from Him, even those goods that one has forsak-
faith and fulfillment in the coming of the promised Messiah who would go en for the Kingdom; where all is connected to Him, to contribute all powers
forth to save not only the Chosen People, but all those who would choose to and energies to His service, and to be absorbed in His splendor.
engage with His mission and to follow through on that engagement. At the According to John Paul II, those in consecrated life, like the Apos-
Transfiguration, the Apostles were in awe of what Jesus was doing and how tles, have received their invitation from the Father to follow His Son. Accept-
He appeared; they were overwhelmed and amazed by Moses and Elijah, the ing this invitation brings unexpected gifts to the consecrated. The religious
two Old Testament heroes who were alive, conversing with Jesus. The won- has given up the natural happiness of having material goods, spouse, chil-
der of Peter, James, and John could only be balanced later by the temptation dren, home, personal money, and the right to direct one’s personal wishes
to be scandalized, seeing Jesus in His weakness presented to the same three in the manner one wishes (rather than following the will of a superior). The
whom Christ requested to accompany Him in His agony in the garden before consecrated life demands this commitment and is the unique intimacy with
His passion and death. “This mystery is constantly relived by the Church, the Christ and the living of the evangelical counsels, the vows of poverty, chas-
people on its way to the eschatological encounter with its Lord. Like the three tity and obedience, that is “a specific acceptance of the mystery of Christ,
chosen disciples, the Church contemplates the transfigured face of Christ in lived within the Church.”14 It is the “response to this call and the interior
order to be confirmed in faith and to avoid being dismayed at His disfigured attraction which accompanies it” that, according to St. Thomas, gives the
face on the Cross. In both cases, she is the Bride before her Spouse, shar- consecrated person the identity of “being comparable to a genuine holo-
ing in his mystery and surrounded by his light. This light shines on all the caust” because of “his or her complete self-offering.”15 “It is the duty of the
Church’s children.”10 consecrated life to show that the Incarnate Son of God is the eschatological goal
The Apostles were caught off guard by Jesus in His new, glorified towards which all things tend, the splendour before which every other light pales,
appearance, but when the voice of the Father was heard, “This is My beloved and the infinite beauty which alone can fully satisfy the human heart.”16 This
Son: listen to Him,”11 they were given a deeper penetration into the invitation 12
John Paul II, VC, § 15, par. 2.
8
Ibid. 13
Matt. 17:4.
9
Ibid. 14
John Paul II, VC, § 16, par. 1.
10
Ibid., § 15, par. 2. 15
Ibid., § 17, par. 2.
11
Matt. 17:5. 16
Ibid., § 16, par. 2.
96 Beauty and Hermeneutic Identity Sister Mary Eucharista, SMMC 97
who receive their vocation, and have it confirmed through acceptance to a of Jesus to come and follow Him. In leaving their ordinary lives to surround
community, alerts all those who encounter the religious that “the profession Him as His chosen followers and closest companions, learning from the Pro-
of the evangelical counsels is an integral part of the Church’s life and a much tagonist and Author of the Gospel Himself how to live authentic Gospel
needed incentive towards ever greater fidelity to the Gospel.”8 The substance values, they had entered into a special relationship with Him. Now they were
of the choice to gift one’s life in a profound and deep-rooted demonstration invited by His Father to listen to Him, who was now radiant of face and
of love for Jesus Christ—and in Him, for each person on earth—encourages brighter than lightning, conversing with two of the greatest champions of
and supports the Christian people en route to the Eschaton (Eternal Life), Jewish leadership, prophesy, story, and tradition. This realization settled deep
since they can draw from religious powerful support even by the ministry of into their souls enabling them to contemplate the mystery before their eyes,
their presence.9 not understanding it immediately, but in time perhaps more able to compre-
In the mystery of the Transfiguration, the Apostles that accompanied hend the reality, not only of the event of the Transfiguration, but also of
Jesus were brought to a high mountain, Tabor, where they were introduced to Jesus’s divine Kingship.
a ground-shaking experience in beholding their Friend and Master, Jesus, in All are called to contemplate this mystery; however, those called to
unexpected glory. This was an event quite reminiscent of Moses’s close com- that unique vocation, where all is given over to Christ by their profession of
munication with the Divine over forty days in the cloud of the Glory of God vows, are made a “kind of sign and prophetic statement for the community of
(Shekinah) on Mount Sinai, as related in Exodus, 24:16–18 and 34:29. During the brethren and for the world.”12 As a result, Peter’s words, “Lord, it is well
the Transfiguration, the radiance of Moses and the radiance of Jesus were that we are here,”13 not only indicate the thrust of the Christian life—making
akin in their connection with the Glory of God—and of course Moses being Christ the ultimate focus—but also express the profundity of the vocation
present with Elijah—showed the unbroken connection of the tradition that of consecrated life. It is indeed good to be where He is the center of one’s
was being passed on. This was to Christianity a tradition of promise, living life; where nothing distracts from Him, even those goods that one has forsak-
faith and fulfillment in the coming of the promised Messiah who would go en for the Kingdom; where all is connected to Him, to contribute all powers
forth to save not only the Chosen People, but all those who would choose to and energies to His service, and to be absorbed in His splendor.
engage with His mission and to follow through on that engagement. At the According to John Paul II, those in consecrated life, like the Apos-
Transfiguration, the Apostles were in awe of what Jesus was doing and how tles, have received their invitation from the Father to follow His Son. Accept-
He appeared; they were overwhelmed and amazed by Moses and Elijah, the ing this invitation brings unexpected gifts to the consecrated. The religious
two Old Testament heroes who were alive, conversing with Jesus. The won- has given up the natural happiness of having material goods, spouse, chil-
der of Peter, James, and John could only be balanced later by the temptation dren, home, personal money, and the right to direct one’s personal wishes
to be scandalized, seeing Jesus in His weakness presented to the same three in the manner one wishes (rather than following the will of a superior). The
whom Christ requested to accompany Him in His agony in the garden before consecrated life demands this commitment and is the unique intimacy with
His passion and death. “This mystery is constantly relived by the Church, the Christ and the living of the evangelical counsels, the vows of poverty, chas-
people on its way to the eschatological encounter with its Lord. Like the three tity and obedience, that is “a specific acceptance of the mystery of Christ,
chosen disciples, the Church contemplates the transfigured face of Christ in lived within the Church.”14 It is the “response to this call and the interior
order to be confirmed in faith and to avoid being dismayed at His disfigured attraction which accompanies it” that, according to St. Thomas, gives the
face on the Cross. In both cases, she is the Bride before her Spouse, shar- consecrated person the identity of “being comparable to a genuine holo-
ing in his mystery and surrounded by his light. This light shines on all the caust” because of “his or her complete self-offering.”15 “It is the duty of the
Church’s children.”10 consecrated life to show that the Incarnate Son of God is the eschatological goal
The Apostles were caught off guard by Jesus in His new, glorified towards which all things tend, the splendour before which every other light pales,
appearance, but when the voice of the Father was heard, “This is My beloved and the infinite beauty which alone can fully satisfy the human heart.”16 This
Son: listen to Him,”11 they were given a deeper penetration into the invitation 12
John Paul II, VC, § 15, par. 2.
8
Ibid. 13
Matt. 17:4.
9
Ibid. 14
John Paul II, VC, § 16, par. 1.
10
Ibid., § 15, par. 2. 15
Ibid., § 17, par. 2.
11
Matt. 17:5. 16
Ibid., § 16, par. 2.
98 Beauty and Hermeneutic Identity Sister Mary Eucharista, SMMC 99
differs from the total commitment of the lay person, by virtue of the secular manifest…an explicit desire to be totally conformed to Him” by living “in
character of their vocation, which is to “reflect the mystery of the Incarnate obedience, with nothing of one’s own and in chastity.”27 Consecrated persons
Word, particularly insofar as He is the Alpha and Omega of the world, the find in Jesus the model of divine living on earth, and follow it in their own
foundation and measure of the value of all created things.”17 lives—“for it was embraced by Him.”28
The religious, or “Icon of the Transfigured Christ,” communicates The mystery of the Transfiguration included the Holy Spirit29 in the
the “Trinitarian nature of the Christian life and…anticipates in a certain way “bright cloud”30 that overshadowed Jesus and his three Apostles on Mount
that eschatological fulfillment”18 for which humans long, where goodness, Tabor. The call of consecrated persons “is closely linked to the working of
truth, and beauty flourish. Contemplative, consecrated living is reflected in the Holy Spirit,”31 allowing them to “recognize the appeal of such a demand-
Christ’s deep prayer on Mount Tabor, whereas the active life is reflected in ing choice”32 by planting a seed of a longing for it, directing its development,
the “revelation of Christ’s glory” and the “preparation for facing Christ’s and assisting it to grow and ripen into a positive response, until it is trans-
Cross.”19 Christ’s close communion with his Apostles is replicated in His as- formed into action. The Holy Spirit “configures” into Christ those called to
sociation with those who are called to climb Tabor in order to “[strengthen] consecration, “prompting them to make His mission their own.”33 With open
the faith in the disciples’ hearts, [prepare] them for the tragedy of the Cross hearts, religious allow the Holy Spirit to purify them until they become “con-
and [prefigure] the glory of the Resurrection.”20 Those called to consecrat- formed to Christ.” This is what is understood as “the prolongation in history of
ed life have “a special experience of the light which shines forth from the Incarnate a special presence of the Risen Lord.”
Word.”21 Jesus, the Son of the Father, calls all to follow Him since He is the Church History records the Fathers of the Church calling religious
way to the Father; but of “those called to the consecrated life, He asks a total life “philokalia, or love of the divine beauty, which is the reflection of the
commitment,”22 namely, that of leaving all behind them “in order to live at divine goodness.”34 Those who are led by the Holy Spirit to live in full con-
His side and to follow Him wherever He goes.”23 Jesus’s face, which is “the formity to Christ have within them “a ray of the unapproachable light”
image of the invisible God”24 and the “reflection of the Father’s glory,”25 lets and, through this earthly journey, they are drawn “towards the inexhaustible
those who view it see “the depths of an eternal and infinite love which is at Source of light,” representing the Church as Bride.35 “The consecrated life
the very root of our being.”26 In the hearts of those called to consecrated thus becomes a particularly profound expression of the Church as Bride
life, it inspires the impulse to cast away all that is not Christ, and to “make who, prompted by the Spirit to imitate her Spouse, stands before Him ‘in
splendor, without spot or wrinkle or any such thing, that she might be holy
17
Ibid. and without blemish’ (Eph. 5:27).”36
18
Ibid., § 14, par. 2. As religious pray at home or walk among their brothers and sisters
19
Ibid. in the human family, they are called to witness and to be witnessed. What is it
20
Ibid., § 15, par. 2. that “viewers” see in the lives of celibates who are called to give all to follow
21
Ibid. Christ? What is the hermeneutic identity of “The Icon of the Transfigured
22
The laity is called to the total commitment of the Universal Call to Holiness
Christ,” and how does it address those who “view” it? Does a “viewer” feel a
(Lumen Gentium), where the family is the Domestic Church, and the secular world
is the mission field where they are to minister (Christifidelis Laici). Religious have a
unique deepening of their baptismal call whereby, at the invitation of Christ, they
vow additionally to give up the legitimate goods sacrificed by the vows of chastity, 27
Ibid.
poverty, obedience, and living in community under a superior, etc. Bishops, priests 28
Ibid.
in the West, and religious (those in consecrated life) take the commitment to which 29
Ibid., § 19: “A significant spiritual interpretation of the Transfiguration sees
Christ referred in Matt. 19:12 that requires a setting aside all for the Kingdom of this cloud as an image of the Holy Spirit.”
God to make Christ “the one focus of [their] lives” (John Paul II, VC, § 15, par. 2). 30
Matt. 17:5.
This exclusive commitment, in addition to professing the other vows, is not particu- 31
John Paul II, VC, § 19.
larly included in the call of the laity. 32
Ibid.
23
John Paul II, VC, § 18, par. 1. 33
Ibid.
24
Col. 1:15. 34
Ibid.
25
Heb. 1:3. 35
Ibid.
26
John Paul II, VC, § 18, par. 2. 36
Ibid.
98 Beauty and Hermeneutic Identity Sister Mary Eucharista, SMMC 99
differs from the total commitment of the lay person, by virtue of the secular manifest…an explicit desire to be totally conformed to Him” by living “in
character of their vocation, which is to “reflect the mystery of the Incarnate obedience, with nothing of one’s own and in chastity.”27 Consecrated persons
Word, particularly insofar as He is the Alpha and Omega of the world, the find in Jesus the model of divine living on earth, and follow it in their own
foundation and measure of the value of all created things.”17 lives—“for it was embraced by Him.”28
The religious, or “Icon of the Transfigured Christ,” communicates The mystery of the Transfiguration included the Holy Spirit29 in the
the “Trinitarian nature of the Christian life and…anticipates in a certain way “bright cloud”30 that overshadowed Jesus and his three Apostles on Mount
that eschatological fulfillment”18 for which humans long, where goodness, Tabor. The call of consecrated persons “is closely linked to the working of
truth, and beauty flourish. Contemplative, consecrated living is reflected in the Holy Spirit,”31 allowing them to “recognize the appeal of such a demand-
Christ’s deep prayer on Mount Tabor, whereas the active life is reflected in ing choice”32 by planting a seed of a longing for it, directing its development,
the “revelation of Christ’s glory” and the “preparation for facing Christ’s and assisting it to grow and ripen into a positive response, until it is trans-
Cross.”19 Christ’s close communion with his Apostles is replicated in His as- formed into action. The Holy Spirit “configures” into Christ those called to
sociation with those who are called to climb Tabor in order to “[strengthen] consecration, “prompting them to make His mission their own.”33 With open
the faith in the disciples’ hearts, [prepare] them for the tragedy of the Cross hearts, religious allow the Holy Spirit to purify them until they become “con-
and [prefigure] the glory of the Resurrection.”20 Those called to consecrat- formed to Christ.” This is what is understood as “the prolongation in history of
ed life have “a special experience of the light which shines forth from the Incarnate a special presence of the Risen Lord.”
Word.”21 Jesus, the Son of the Father, calls all to follow Him since He is the Church History records the Fathers of the Church calling religious
way to the Father; but of “those called to the consecrated life, He asks a total life “philokalia, or love of the divine beauty, which is the reflection of the
commitment,”22 namely, that of leaving all behind them “in order to live at divine goodness.”34 Those who are led by the Holy Spirit to live in full con-
His side and to follow Him wherever He goes.”23 Jesus’s face, which is “the formity to Christ have within them “a ray of the unapproachable light”
image of the invisible God”24 and the “reflection of the Father’s glory,”25 lets and, through this earthly journey, they are drawn “towards the inexhaustible
those who view it see “the depths of an eternal and infinite love which is at Source of light,” representing the Church as Bride.35 “The consecrated life
the very root of our being.”26 In the hearts of those called to consecrated thus becomes a particularly profound expression of the Church as Bride
life, it inspires the impulse to cast away all that is not Christ, and to “make who, prompted by the Spirit to imitate her Spouse, stands before Him ‘in
splendor, without spot or wrinkle or any such thing, that she might be holy
17
Ibid. and without blemish’ (Eph. 5:27).”36
18
Ibid., § 14, par. 2. As religious pray at home or walk among their brothers and sisters
19
Ibid. in the human family, they are called to witness and to be witnessed. What is it
20
Ibid., § 15, par. 2. that “viewers” see in the lives of celibates who are called to give all to follow
21
Ibid. Christ? What is the hermeneutic identity of “The Icon of the Transfigured
22
The laity is called to the total commitment of the Universal Call to Holiness
Christ,” and how does it address those who “view” it? Does a “viewer” feel a
(Lumen Gentium), where the family is the Domestic Church, and the secular world
is the mission field where they are to minister (Christifidelis Laici). Religious have a
unique deepening of their baptismal call whereby, at the invitation of Christ, they
vow additionally to give up the legitimate goods sacrificed by the vows of chastity, 27
Ibid.
poverty, obedience, and living in community under a superior, etc. Bishops, priests 28
Ibid.
in the West, and religious (those in consecrated life) take the commitment to which 29
Ibid., § 19: “A significant spiritual interpretation of the Transfiguration sees
Christ referred in Matt. 19:12 that requires a setting aside all for the Kingdom of this cloud as an image of the Holy Spirit.”
God to make Christ “the one focus of [their] lives” (John Paul II, VC, § 15, par. 2). 30
Matt. 17:5.
This exclusive commitment, in addition to professing the other vows, is not particu- 31
John Paul II, VC, § 19.
larly included in the call of the laity. 32
Ibid.
23
John Paul II, VC, § 18, par. 1. 33
Ibid.
24
Col. 1:15. 34
Ibid.
25
Heb. 1:3. 35
Ibid.
26
John Paul II, VC, § 18, par. 2. 36
Ibid.
100 Beauty and Hermeneutic Identity Sister Mary Eucharista, SMMC 101
connection with beauty and the transcendent when observing this “icon,” or own in the “great artistic revolution of modern times.” Is this still art? Kant
even perhaps feel opposition, and if so, what difference does it make? notes that humans take in beauty with “disinterested delight.”45 This entails
no question of practical use, since beauty is not practical. “We cannot ask,
‘What purpose is served by enjoyment?’”46 Kant describes aesthetic taste as
Gadamer and Art: Universal, Beauty, Symbol, Festival sensus communis, or common sense.47 About this, Gadamer states, “Taste is
communicative”; everyone has it to some measure, and there is no excessive
Gadamer, in expressing his philosophical aesthetics about works of art,37 conceptualizing about what we are seeing.48 We know we have been struck to
points out that, as Aristotle explains in his Poetics, “Poetry is more philosoph- the heart by what is beautiful, and as a result we are attracted to it.
ical than history,” because “the one describes the thing that has been, and the The hermeneutic identity of the work, “establishes the unity of the
other a kind of thing that might be.”38 The statements of history are of the work,” and “even the most fleeting and unique of experiences is intended
same nature as singulars, while the statements of poetry (art) are of the same in its self-identity when it appears or is valued as an aesthetic experience.”49
nature as universals.39 History reports what has actually happened, while “po- Gadamer believes that one must be able to identify something in order to un-
etry tells us how things may happen and teaches us to recognize the universal derstand it: “for there was something there that I passed judgment upon and
in all human action and suffering.”40 understood. I identify something as it was or as it is, and this identity alone
Gadamer adds a second point about art, in that “art leads us be- constitutes the meaning of the work.”50 He claims that artistic productions
yond the limits of contemporary aesthetics.”41 The Greek ethico-political intend what they produce to be what they are. They are works in terms of
world held that the “beautiful ethical life” was the virtuous life of the people their hermeneutic identity. “If the identity of the work is as we have said,
finding communication “in all forms of communal life, giving shape to the then the genuine reception and experience of a work of art can exist only for
whole, and so allowing men to recognize themselves in their own world.”42 one who ‘plays along,’ that is, one who performs in an active way himself.”51
In noting the beautiful, one is compelled to acknowledge that it is truth. This The hermeneutic identity of the art piece resides specifically in
truth of beauty is not inaccessible in the here and now, but lies amid the “dis- “there being something to ‘understand,’ that it asks to be understood in what
order of reality with all its imperfections, evils, errors, extremes, and fateful it ‘says’ or ‘intends.’ The work issues a challenge that expects to be met. It re-
confusions.”43 The beautiful connects the ideal and the real, and this is its quires an answer—an answer that can only be given by someone who accepts
ontological function.44 the challenge. And that answer must be his or her own, and given actively.”52
The third point that Gadamer identifies in art is discovered in phil- This assent from the viewer produces meaning and understanding. When
osophical aesthetics and partly in Kant’s Third Critique (The Critique of Judg- one views art, he or she is involved in “profound intellectual and spiritual
ment). The advent of aesthetics corresponded with the age of rationalism activity.” If the experience has been genuine, “then the world has become
when art was considered part of religious or secular embellishment. Art both brighter and less burdensome.”53 The art becomes “the focal point of
was not autonomous then, but formed part of the “life-world”—making it recognition and understanding…bound up with variation and difference.”
beautiful with expressions of religious worship or the coronation of a ruler, The viewer, in meeting the challenge issued by the work of art, “fills out” and
perhaps. Art became emancipated from conventional topics, standing on its completes the work for him or herself.54 Gadamer utilizes Kant’s comments

37
Hans-Georg Gadamer, The Relevance of the Beautiful and Other Essays, trans. Emmanuel Kant, Critique of Judgment, trans. J. H. Bernard. (Hafner Press:
45

Nicholas Walker, ed. Robert Bernasconi (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, New York, 1951), 44–45.
1986). 46
Gadamer, The Relevance of the Beautiful, 19.
38
Aristotle, Poetics 9.1452b4 in The Basic Works of Aristotle, ed. Richard McKe- 47
Kant, Critique of Judgment, 76–77, 135–38.
on (Random House, Inc.: New York, 2001), 1462. 48
Gadamer, The Relevance of the Beautiful, 19–20.
39
Ibid. 49
Ibid., 25.
40
Gadamer, The Relevance of the Beautiful, 13. 50
Ibid.
41
Ibid. 51
Ibid., 25–26.
42
Ibid., 14. 52
Ibid., 26.
43
Ibid. 53
Ibid.
44
Ibid. 54
Ibid.
100 Beauty and Hermeneutic Identity Sister Mary Eucharista, SMMC 101
connection with beauty and the transcendent when observing this “icon,” or own in the “great artistic revolution of modern times.” Is this still art? Kant
even perhaps feel opposition, and if so, what difference does it make? notes that humans take in beauty with “disinterested delight.”45 This entails
no question of practical use, since beauty is not practical. “We cannot ask,
‘What purpose is served by enjoyment?’”46 Kant describes aesthetic taste as
Gadamer and Art: Universal, Beauty, Symbol, Festival sensus communis, or common sense.47 About this, Gadamer states, “Taste is
communicative”; everyone has it to some measure, and there is no excessive
Gadamer, in expressing his philosophical aesthetics about works of art,37 conceptualizing about what we are seeing.48 We know we have been struck to
points out that, as Aristotle explains in his Poetics, “Poetry is more philosoph- the heart by what is beautiful, and as a result we are attracted to it.
ical than history,” because “the one describes the thing that has been, and the The hermeneutic identity of the work, “establishes the unity of the
other a kind of thing that might be.”38 The statements of history are of the work,” and “even the most fleeting and unique of experiences is intended
same nature as singulars, while the statements of poetry (art) are of the same in its self-identity when it appears or is valued as an aesthetic experience.”49
nature as universals.39 History reports what has actually happened, while “po- Gadamer believes that one must be able to identify something in order to un-
etry tells us how things may happen and teaches us to recognize the universal derstand it: “for there was something there that I passed judgment upon and
in all human action and suffering.”40 understood. I identify something as it was or as it is, and this identity alone
Gadamer adds a second point about art, in that “art leads us be- constitutes the meaning of the work.”50 He claims that artistic productions
yond the limits of contemporary aesthetics.”41 The Greek ethico-political intend what they produce to be what they are. They are works in terms of
world held that the “beautiful ethical life” was the virtuous life of the people their hermeneutic identity. “If the identity of the work is as we have said,
finding communication “in all forms of communal life, giving shape to the then the genuine reception and experience of a work of art can exist only for
whole, and so allowing men to recognize themselves in their own world.”42 one who ‘plays along,’ that is, one who performs in an active way himself.”51
In noting the beautiful, one is compelled to acknowledge that it is truth. This The hermeneutic identity of the art piece resides specifically in
truth of beauty is not inaccessible in the here and now, but lies amid the “dis- “there being something to ‘understand,’ that it asks to be understood in what
order of reality with all its imperfections, evils, errors, extremes, and fateful it ‘says’ or ‘intends.’ The work issues a challenge that expects to be met. It re-
confusions.”43 The beautiful connects the ideal and the real, and this is its quires an answer—an answer that can only be given by someone who accepts
ontological function.44 the challenge. And that answer must be his or her own, and given actively.”52
The third point that Gadamer identifies in art is discovered in phil- This assent from the viewer produces meaning and understanding. When
osophical aesthetics and partly in Kant’s Third Critique (The Critique of Judg- one views art, he or she is involved in “profound intellectual and spiritual
ment). The advent of aesthetics corresponded with the age of rationalism activity.” If the experience has been genuine, “then the world has become
when art was considered part of religious or secular embellishment. Art both brighter and less burdensome.”53 The art becomes “the focal point of
was not autonomous then, but formed part of the “life-world”—making it recognition and understanding…bound up with variation and difference.”
beautiful with expressions of religious worship or the coronation of a ruler, The viewer, in meeting the challenge issued by the work of art, “fills out” and
perhaps. Art became emancipated from conventional topics, standing on its completes the work for him or herself.54 Gadamer utilizes Kant’s comments

37
Hans-Georg Gadamer, The Relevance of the Beautiful and Other Essays, trans. Emmanuel Kant, Critique of Judgment, trans. J. H. Bernard. (Hafner Press:
45

Nicholas Walker, ed. Robert Bernasconi (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, New York, 1951), 44–45.
1986). 46
Gadamer, The Relevance of the Beautiful, 19.
38
Aristotle, Poetics 9.1452b4 in The Basic Works of Aristotle, ed. Richard McKe- 47
Kant, Critique of Judgment, 76–77, 135–38.
on (Random House, Inc.: New York, 2001), 1462. 48
Gadamer, The Relevance of the Beautiful, 19–20.
39
Ibid. 49
Ibid., 25.
40
Gadamer, The Relevance of the Beautiful, 13. 50
Ibid.
41
Ibid. 51
Ibid., 25–26.
42
Ibid., 14. 52
Ibid., 26.
43
Ibid. 53
Ibid.
44
Ibid. 54
Ibid.
102 Beauty and Hermeneutic Identity Sister Mary Eucharista, SMMC 103
on other aspects of beauty in art, such as form being the vehicle of beauty, what Gadamer calls “fulfilled time.”64 Humans make a transition from life,
in order to support the idea that the viewer is in the position to actively con- experienced in normal time, to a work of art, where time becomes a cele-
struct the form. The identity of the work invites the viewer into a “constant bration. He also writes that “in the experience of art, we must learn to dwell
cooperative activity,”55 into the dialogue. upon the work in a specific way,” with no tedium in our tarrying as we absorb
Gadamer believes that the symbolic in general and in art rests on the its riches, and in this way we can relate to eternity.65
“intricate interplay of showing and concealing.” Art is not a bearer of mean- “The Icon of the Transfigured Christ” is an eschatological sign to
ing but carries it in itself: “the meaning of the work of art lies in the fact that the viewer of the place of Eternal Life in the sense that he or she lives not
it is there.”56 Once it is “there,” it is ready to be “encountered” by whoever for this world, but for the next, and in that living, gives witness to a light, a life
meets it, and to be perceived. The symbolic does not point to a meaning, but and a future that is outside of materiality. When this icon is viewed, a mes-
allows the meaning to present itself. The symbol preserves that meaning in sage is received by the viewer, thereby creating a bridge from Eternity to that
itself: is a repraesentatio, not in the sense of a replacement, but as something moment in time. The living icon stands out by giving testimony to the reality
that gains meaning by being represented.57 It demands constructive activity of the Eternal Wedding Banquet. In this Nuptial Feast of the Lamb, where
on the part of the viewer.58 all are invited (though some do not choose to attend), a great, expectant and
Recognition is another aspect of symbol. This is understood with joyous assembly gathers in the greatest community celebration ever known:
the tesserae hospitalis (the Roman custom of a host breaking an object in hospi- the Festival of Festivals!
tality, so it can be refitted for recognition when he and his guest meet again).
“Recognition means knowing something as that with which we are already
acquainted…[implying] that we have come to know something more authen- The “Icon” and the Dialogue
tically than we were able to do when caught up in our first encounter with it.
Recognition elicits the permanent from the transient.”59 Tradition present in The viewer of “the Icon of the Transfigured Christ” encounters the vowed
a work is not intended to conserve but to transmit: “learning how to grasp religious who is in the process of constantly revealing the “characteristic fea-
and express the past anew,” and in this sense this transmission corresponds tures of Jesus,”66 and without perhaps consciously realizing it, is struck by the
with translation. In addition, we do not repeat the past, but encounter it.60 A “mystery of the Kingdom of God already at work in history, even as it awaits
work of art “transforms our fleeting experience into the stable and lasting its full realization in heaven.”67 How does the dialogue actually take place
form of an independent and internally coherent creation…in such a way that between “the Icon of the Transfigured Christ” and the viewer? Perhaps it
we go beyond ourselves by penetrating deeper into the work.”61 would be helpful to note Gadamer’s ideas on the matter and then to propose
A final element of Gadamer’s commentary on art is the notion of how the dialogue occurs with the art piece that is the religious.
festival. Festival is an experience of community, represents community in Gadamer compares dialogue with the model of the Platonic dialec-
its most perfect form, and builds community because no one is excluded or tic as a method by which humans come to understanding; one cannot attain
separated.62 Work separates and divides, while festival includes and gathers understanding without logical structures of openness and questioning. “We
everyone together.63 Festivals are celebrated intentionally, and are meant for cannot have experiences without asking questions.”68 The heart of question-
everyone. In contrast to boredom and bustle, which are both time-fillers, the ing is to make sense, which also comprises a sense of direction. Gadamer
former with empty time, and the latter with filling time, festival and art are states that when a question develops in authentic dialogue (to gain insight
rather than to prove oneself right), “it breaks open the being of the object,
55
Ibid., 27. as it were. Hence the logos that explicates this opened-up being is an answer.
56
Ibid., 33.
57
Ibid., 37.
58
Ibid. 64
Ibid., 42.
59
Ibid., 47. 65
Ibid., 45.
60
Ibid., 49. 66
John Paul II, VC, § 1, par. 1.
61
Ibid., 53. 67
Ibid.
62
Ibid., 39. 68
Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, 2nd rev. ed. (London: The Contin-
63
Ibid., 40. uum International Publishing Group Ltd., 2004), 362.
102 Beauty and Hermeneutic Identity Sister Mary Eucharista, SMMC 103
on other aspects of beauty in art, such as form being the vehicle of beauty, what Gadamer calls “fulfilled time.”64 Humans make a transition from life,
in order to support the idea that the viewer is in the position to actively con- experienced in normal time, to a work of art, where time becomes a cele-
struct the form. The identity of the work invites the viewer into a “constant bration. He also writes that “in the experience of art, we must learn to dwell
cooperative activity,”55 into the dialogue. upon the work in a specific way,” with no tedium in our tarrying as we absorb
Gadamer believes that the symbolic in general and in art rests on the its riches, and in this way we can relate to eternity.65
“intricate interplay of showing and concealing.” Art is not a bearer of mean- “The Icon of the Transfigured Christ” is an eschatological sign to
ing but carries it in itself: “the meaning of the work of art lies in the fact that the viewer of the place of Eternal Life in the sense that he or she lives not
it is there.”56 Once it is “there,” it is ready to be “encountered” by whoever for this world, but for the next, and in that living, gives witness to a light, a life
meets it, and to be perceived. The symbolic does not point to a meaning, but and a future that is outside of materiality. When this icon is viewed, a mes-
allows the meaning to present itself. The symbol preserves that meaning in sage is received by the viewer, thereby creating a bridge from Eternity to that
itself: is a repraesentatio, not in the sense of a replacement, but as something moment in time. The living icon stands out by giving testimony to the reality
that gains meaning by being represented.57 It demands constructive activity of the Eternal Wedding Banquet. In this Nuptial Feast of the Lamb, where
on the part of the viewer.58 all are invited (though some do not choose to attend), a great, expectant and
Recognition is another aspect of symbol. This is understood with joyous assembly gathers in the greatest community celebration ever known:
the tesserae hospitalis (the Roman custom of a host breaking an object in hospi- the Festival of Festivals!
tality, so it can be refitted for recognition when he and his guest meet again).
“Recognition means knowing something as that with which we are already
acquainted…[implying] that we have come to know something more authen- The “Icon” and the Dialogue
tically than we were able to do when caught up in our first encounter with it.
Recognition elicits the permanent from the transient.”59 Tradition present in The viewer of “the Icon of the Transfigured Christ” encounters the vowed
a work is not intended to conserve but to transmit: “learning how to grasp religious who is in the process of constantly revealing the “characteristic fea-
and express the past anew,” and in this sense this transmission corresponds tures of Jesus,”66 and without perhaps consciously realizing it, is struck by the
with translation. In addition, we do not repeat the past, but encounter it.60 A “mystery of the Kingdom of God already at work in history, even as it awaits
work of art “transforms our fleeting experience into the stable and lasting its full realization in heaven.”67 How does the dialogue actually take place
form of an independent and internally coherent creation…in such a way that between “the Icon of the Transfigured Christ” and the viewer? Perhaps it
we go beyond ourselves by penetrating deeper into the work.”61 would be helpful to note Gadamer’s ideas on the matter and then to propose
A final element of Gadamer’s commentary on art is the notion of how the dialogue occurs with the art piece that is the religious.
festival. Festival is an experience of community, represents community in Gadamer compares dialogue with the model of the Platonic dialec-
its most perfect form, and builds community because no one is excluded or tic as a method by which humans come to understanding; one cannot attain
separated.62 Work separates and divides, while festival includes and gathers understanding without logical structures of openness and questioning. “We
everyone together.63 Festivals are celebrated intentionally, and are meant for cannot have experiences without asking questions.”68 The heart of question-
everyone. In contrast to boredom and bustle, which are both time-fillers, the ing is to make sense, which also comprises a sense of direction. Gadamer
former with empty time, and the latter with filling time, festival and art are states that when a question develops in authentic dialogue (to gain insight
rather than to prove oneself right), “it breaks open the being of the object,
55
Ibid., 27. as it were. Hence the logos that explicates this opened-up being is an answer.
56
Ibid., 33.
57
Ibid., 37.
58
Ibid. 64
Ibid., 42.
59
Ibid., 47. 65
Ibid., 45.
60
Ibid., 49. 66
John Paul II, VC, § 1, par. 1.
61
Ibid., 53. 67
Ibid.
62
Ibid., 39. 68
Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, 2nd rev. ed. (London: The Contin-
63
Ibid., 40. uum International Publishing Group Ltd., 2004), 362.
104 Beauty and Hermeneutic Identity Sister Mary Eucharista, SMMC 105
Its sense lies in the sense of the question.”69 In Socratic dialogue, “there is a Recognition distinguishes the permanent from the transient,76 trans-
profound recognition of the priority of the question in all knowledge and dis- mitting (or translating) the past in a new way, thus creating an encounter.
course that really reveals something of an object. Discourse that is intended Since the Holy Spirit works within the “icon” the continuation in history of
to reveal something requires that that thing be broken open by the ques- a special presence of the Risen Lord, the “icon” produces an attraction for
tion.”70 Gadamer writes that dialectic advances through the questions and those who “recognize” the symbol and the reality of the Eschaton that is
answers; “the path of all knowledge leads through the question,” which is to strong but gentle, unconcealed yet somehow elusive. For the person who has
bring into the open, since “the openness of what is in question consists in the never seen a religious sister, brother, or priest, this recognition might be: in
fact that the answer is not settled.” This is the condition of every true ques- the memory of, or connection to, a story he or she has heard, in a conversa-
tion.71 Knowledge is the consideration of opposites; it is dialectical “from tion with an older relative, in one’s dreams of giving one’s own life to a wor-
the ground up” and “only a person who has questions can have knowledge, thy cause; or even in wondering about what the life of such a person could
but questions include the antithesis of yes and no, of being like this and like entail. On the part of one who has no Catholic or Christian background, the
that.72 With some of these ideas in mind, let us proceed to the dialogue of sight of a religious can affect even the young viewer with stunning manifesta-
the “Icon of the Transfigured Christ” (the person in consecrated life) and tion.77 A question is asked by the sight of the icon, since the art is addressing
the “viewer.” the viewer, and the viewer responds with the answer that is right for that time
The dialogue that occurs upon the viewing of the “Icon of the in his or her life. Sometimes the answer is another question. Sometimes the
Transfigured Christ” is a dialogue that opens from the icon itself. The art conversation goes on in the head of the person after leaving the icon, with
addresses the viewer, and the questions begin. That pause and glance on the the memory of the icon carrying the dialogue.
part of a viewer of the “icon,” perhaps an exclamation or comment, or the Viewers are drawn to the work the Holy Spirit has accomplished in
continued gaze, begins the dialogue initiated by the sight of the religious, the icon: they perceive that “ray of the unapproachable light,” and, through
which is the art addressing the viewer. The wide variety of responses to the the icon, they are drawn “towards the inexhaustible Source of light,” repre-
sight of a religious in the public eye, perhaps at the store or on the street, is a senting the Church as Bride.78 The reception and experience of the icon can
strong indication of the hermeneutic identity of the icon—the “reality which exist, though, only for those who engage in the dialogue. The viewer’s assent
affects” those who observe it.73 In communicating the “Trinitarian nature of to engage in the dialogue produces meaning and understanding in the con-
the Christian life,” and “[anticipating] in a certain way that eschatological ful- versation, filling in a better comprehension for him or herself. If the experi-
filment”74 for which humans long—where goodness, truth and beauty flour- ence has been genuine, the viewer is left with the knowledge that the world
ish—the icon intends what it produces to be what it is: a sign or reminder is a brighter and less burdensome place. Those who find themselves in an
that humans have an eternal destiny. The divine One has invited persons to understanding of the “icon” create a community of comprehending beauty
dedicate their whole lives to the end of creating the identity of the complete found in the connection of the ideal and the real, thus fulfilling its ontolog-
holocaust in imitation of the divine Original, without many religious even 76
Gadamer, The Relevance of the Beautiful, 47.
realizing that this is what others see when viewing them. The viewer may ob- 77
In the case of a particular “viewer,” I (the author of this paper) met a young
serve, as in a mirror, “the depths of an eternal and infinite love which is at the woman with two children at a post office in Spokane. The mother was friendly and
very root of our being”75—love that is accessible to the viewer. The subject the older child, about aged seven, glanced over for a moment and seemed mildly
matter, as it were, of the icon, is brought to light, and the dialogue continues. curious, then went back to play with her toy. The younger child, aged about three
or four, stopped in mid-step and stood riveted, staring at me. I thought at first that
she believed I was a Disney character come to life, or some other creature. As she
gazed at me, I was touched by her wonder and peace as her mother took her hand to
69
Ibid., 362, 363. lead her away. She couldn’t look away and allowed herself to be led backwards, still
70
Ibid., 363. watching me standing in line. Finally she lisped, pointing at me, “P’etty, mom. SOOO
71
Ibid. p’etty! Oh, mom, p’etty!” Her gaze took everything in, and finally her mother picked
72
Ibid., 365. her up and took her back out to the car. I believe it was not a physical prettiness she
73
John Paul II, VC, § 3. was commenting upon, but something deeper that spoke to her soul. This event
74
Gadamer, Truth and Method, 363. convinced me to write this paper.
75
John Paul II, VC, § 18, par. 2. 78
John Paul II, VC, § 19.
104 Beauty and Hermeneutic Identity Sister Mary Eucharista, SMMC 105
Its sense lies in the sense of the question.”69 In Socratic dialogue, “there is a Recognition distinguishes the permanent from the transient,76 trans-
profound recognition of the priority of the question in all knowledge and dis- mitting (or translating) the past in a new way, thus creating an encounter.
course that really reveals something of an object. Discourse that is intended Since the Holy Spirit works within the “icon” the continuation in history of
to reveal something requires that that thing be broken open by the ques- a special presence of the Risen Lord, the “icon” produces an attraction for
tion.”70 Gadamer writes that dialectic advances through the questions and those who “recognize” the symbol and the reality of the Eschaton that is
answers; “the path of all knowledge leads through the question,” which is to strong but gentle, unconcealed yet somehow elusive. For the person who has
bring into the open, since “the openness of what is in question consists in the never seen a religious sister, brother, or priest, this recognition might be: in
fact that the answer is not settled.” This is the condition of every true ques- the memory of, or connection to, a story he or she has heard, in a conversa-
tion.71 Knowledge is the consideration of opposites; it is dialectical “from tion with an older relative, in one’s dreams of giving one’s own life to a wor-
the ground up” and “only a person who has questions can have knowledge, thy cause; or even in wondering about what the life of such a person could
but questions include the antithesis of yes and no, of being like this and like entail. On the part of one who has no Catholic or Christian background, the
that.72 With some of these ideas in mind, let us proceed to the dialogue of sight of a religious can affect even the young viewer with stunning manifesta-
the “Icon of the Transfigured Christ” (the person in consecrated life) and tion.77 A question is asked by the sight of the icon, since the art is addressing
the “viewer.” the viewer, and the viewer responds with the answer that is right for that time
The dialogue that occurs upon the viewing of the “Icon of the in his or her life. Sometimes the answer is another question. Sometimes the
Transfigured Christ” is a dialogue that opens from the icon itself. The art conversation goes on in the head of the person after leaving the icon, with
addresses the viewer, and the questions begin. That pause and glance on the the memory of the icon carrying the dialogue.
part of a viewer of the “icon,” perhaps an exclamation or comment, or the Viewers are drawn to the work the Holy Spirit has accomplished in
continued gaze, begins the dialogue initiated by the sight of the religious, the icon: they perceive that “ray of the unapproachable light,” and, through
which is the art addressing the viewer. The wide variety of responses to the the icon, they are drawn “towards the inexhaustible Source of light,” repre-
sight of a religious in the public eye, perhaps at the store or on the street, is a senting the Church as Bride.78 The reception and experience of the icon can
strong indication of the hermeneutic identity of the icon—the “reality which exist, though, only for those who engage in the dialogue. The viewer’s assent
affects” those who observe it.73 In communicating the “Trinitarian nature of to engage in the dialogue produces meaning and understanding in the con-
the Christian life,” and “[anticipating] in a certain way that eschatological ful- versation, filling in a better comprehension for him or herself. If the experi-
filment”74 for which humans long—where goodness, truth and beauty flour- ence has been genuine, the viewer is left with the knowledge that the world
ish—the icon intends what it produces to be what it is: a sign or reminder is a brighter and less burdensome place. Those who find themselves in an
that humans have an eternal destiny. The divine One has invited persons to understanding of the “icon” create a community of comprehending beauty
dedicate their whole lives to the end of creating the identity of the complete found in the connection of the ideal and the real, thus fulfilling its ontolog-
holocaust in imitation of the divine Original, without many religious even 76
Gadamer, The Relevance of the Beautiful, 47.
realizing that this is what others see when viewing them. The viewer may ob- 77
In the case of a particular “viewer,” I (the author of this paper) met a young
serve, as in a mirror, “the depths of an eternal and infinite love which is at the woman with two children at a post office in Spokane. The mother was friendly and
very root of our being”75—love that is accessible to the viewer. The subject the older child, about aged seven, glanced over for a moment and seemed mildly
matter, as it were, of the icon, is brought to light, and the dialogue continues. curious, then went back to play with her toy. The younger child, aged about three
or four, stopped in mid-step and stood riveted, staring at me. I thought at first that
she believed I was a Disney character come to life, or some other creature. As she
gazed at me, I was touched by her wonder and peace as her mother took her hand to
69
Ibid., 362, 363. lead her away. She couldn’t look away and allowed herself to be led backwards, still
70
Ibid., 363. watching me standing in line. Finally she lisped, pointing at me, “P’etty, mom. SOOO
71
Ibid. p’etty! Oh, mom, p’etty!” Her gaze took everything in, and finally her mother picked
72
Ibid., 365. her up and took her back out to the car. I believe it was not a physical prettiness she
73
John Paul II, VC, § 3. was commenting upon, but something deeper that spoke to her soul. This event
74
Gadamer, Truth and Method, 363. convinced me to write this paper.
75
John Paul II, VC, § 18, par. 2. 78
John Paul II, VC, § 19.
106 Beauty and Hermeneutic Identity Sister Mary Eucharista, SMMC 107
ical function, bringing into being a richness actualizing a deeper reality. The into thinking about meeting God in Eternity and the “Last things”—death,
beauty found is a presence, an encounter with the truth present in the work judgment, heaven, and hell—is frightening for many. It is not characteristi-
itself. As a result of this encounter, the truth within the other is awakened cally pleasant to think about these things, unless one is curious, or until one
through the beauty discovered, and the dialogue continues. prepares for the end of life, although, even then, thoughts of the end of life
The variety in the dialogue runs the spectrum of human emotion, are frightening for many. As with any good piece of art, the icon speaks a
stimulating, affecting, impressing, or connecting on some deeper level for the truth with which some are challenged and deeply uncomfortable, and, as a
most part. In a sense, this discovery is a calling back to the truths that may be result, a struggle ensues, leaving the viewer to grapple with those elements
dormant, or may be on the surface of the individual’s consciousness, or per- “spoken about” in the dialogue.
haps buried deeply, awaiting confirmation. Issues of love or questions long Regardless, the encounter occurs and the dialogue may continue
unanswered awaken deep aspirations of the human heart, possibly leading long after the parting. As any art piece can contribute to arousing, piquing,
the “viewer(s)” to question themselves, or to comment to others what they or achieving understanding in the viewer, so the “Icon of the Transfigured
have noticed. Children note a range of ideas that spring forth in exclamations Christ” challenges and disrupts conventional expectations, deepening a view-
like “Mary!” “Jesus!” “Look, a church lady!” or the communication of a gaze er’s experience of art, addressing their tradition, perhaps bringing them to a
of deep introspection, not seeming able to tear themselves away. Other chil- more profound realization that they are in touch with the transcendent and
dren make observations like “Madeleine, Mom, Madeleine!” or “Barney!” that in recognizing this, they become more attentive to the beautiful and
Some non-Catholics look quizzical or make comments, sometimes coming more aware of wonder. It may be suggested that this dialogue, this encounter,
over for autographs, as though the religious were a celebrity, or with ques- this connection of love, and this truth, will form part of that great Encoun-
tions, wondering why a person would be a celibate—sometimes shaking their ter at the end of time where reigns Eternal Festival: the Wedding Feast of the
heads in disbelief or amazement. Catholic adults surreptitiously comment Lamb, where community, recognition, and joy are resolved into that place of
and converse with those near them, reminiscing about their school days with Beauty in which the ideal and the real become one.
sisters. Oftentimes they will come over to the religious to ask for prayers,
thank the religious for his or her vocation, or remark how they themselves —Gonzaga University
had had a vocation to religious life, but had chosen another path, either to
their own delight, for example, in a good marriage, or to their chagrin, there-
by inviting consolation and encouragement from the religious. Frequently a
young person who is dealing with questions about becoming a religious will
approach, sometimes nervously and hesitatingly, or sometimes confidently
and with excitement. Above all, and perhaps most common in the topic of
the dialogue, is a response on the part of more reflective observers, of the
incongruity of the presence of religious in the midst of a material world that
typically would be absorbed in material things.
Viewers may be struck by joy in the icon, which is a contrast to what
might be noticeable in the faces of others who have all they need. Since the
icon communicates the prophetic element of a life lived for eternal values,
the dialogue may sometimes be a negative one. Viewers may be menacing,
avoidant, or even take violent action, such as shouting insults, gesturing vul-
garly, or even spitting upon the “icon,” infuriated beyond any kind of con-
nection with a person they have never met.79 Being reminded or surprised
79
One event that comes to mind is a meeting between two sisters (the au-
thor of this paper and her religious superior) and a bicyclist in a market square in he conjured up a mouthful of saliva, expelling it all over the sister nearest him as he
Salzburg, Austria in the summer of 2005. The cyclist caught sight of the religious passed by, shouting profanities. (He was afterwards dubbed by the two sisters, “The
from the distant part of the square, and then began to accelerate towards the two as Salzburg Spitter.”)
106 Beauty and Hermeneutic Identity Sister Mary Eucharista, SMMC 107
ical function, bringing into being a richness actualizing a deeper reality. The into thinking about meeting God in Eternity and the “Last things”—death,
beauty found is a presence, an encounter with the truth present in the work judgment, heaven, and hell—is frightening for many. It is not characteristi-
itself. As a result of this encounter, the truth within the other is awakened cally pleasant to think about these things, unless one is curious, or until one
through the beauty discovered, and the dialogue continues. prepares for the end of life, although, even then, thoughts of the end of life
The variety in the dialogue runs the spectrum of human emotion, are frightening for many. As with any good piece of art, the icon speaks a
stimulating, affecting, impressing, or connecting on some deeper level for the truth with which some are challenged and deeply uncomfortable, and, as a
most part. In a sense, this discovery is a calling back to the truths that may be result, a struggle ensues, leaving the viewer to grapple with those elements
dormant, or may be on the surface of the individual’s consciousness, or per- “spoken about” in the dialogue.
haps buried deeply, awaiting confirmation. Issues of love or questions long Regardless, the encounter occurs and the dialogue may continue
unanswered awaken deep aspirations of the human heart, possibly leading long after the parting. As any art piece can contribute to arousing, piquing,
the “viewer(s)” to question themselves, or to comment to others what they or achieving understanding in the viewer, so the “Icon of the Transfigured
have noticed. Children note a range of ideas that spring forth in exclamations Christ” challenges and disrupts conventional expectations, deepening a view-
like “Mary!” “Jesus!” “Look, a church lady!” or the communication of a gaze er’s experience of art, addressing their tradition, perhaps bringing them to a
of deep introspection, not seeming able to tear themselves away. Other chil- more profound realization that they are in touch with the transcendent and
dren make observations like “Madeleine, Mom, Madeleine!” or “Barney!” that in recognizing this, they become more attentive to the beautiful and
Some non-Catholics look quizzical or make comments, sometimes coming more aware of wonder. It may be suggested that this dialogue, this encounter,
over for autographs, as though the religious were a celebrity, or with ques- this connection of love, and this truth, will form part of that great Encoun-
tions, wondering why a person would be a celibate—sometimes shaking their ter at the end of time where reigns Eternal Festival: the Wedding Feast of the
heads in disbelief or amazement. Catholic adults surreptitiously comment Lamb, where community, recognition, and joy are resolved into that place of
and converse with those near them, reminiscing about their school days with Beauty in which the ideal and the real become one.
sisters. Oftentimes they will come over to the religious to ask for prayers,
thank the religious for his or her vocation, or remark how they themselves —Gonzaga University
had had a vocation to religious life, but had chosen another path, either to
their own delight, for example, in a good marriage, or to their chagrin, there-
by inviting consolation and encouragement from the religious. Frequently a
young person who is dealing with questions about becoming a religious will
approach, sometimes nervously and hesitatingly, or sometimes confidently
and with excitement. Above all, and perhaps most common in the topic of
the dialogue, is a response on the part of more reflective observers, of the
incongruity of the presence of religious in the midst of a material world that
typically would be absorbed in material things.
Viewers may be struck by joy in the icon, which is a contrast to what
might be noticeable in the faces of others who have all they need. Since the
icon communicates the prophetic element of a life lived for eternal values,
the dialogue may sometimes be a negative one. Viewers may be menacing,
avoidant, or even take violent action, such as shouting insults, gesturing vul-
garly, or even spitting upon the “icon,” infuriated beyond any kind of con-
nection with a person they have never met.79 Being reminded or surprised
79
One event that comes to mind is a meeting between two sisters (the au-
thor of this paper and her religious superior) and a bicyclist in a market square in he conjured up a mouthful of saliva, expelling it all over the sister nearest him as he
Salzburg, Austria in the summer of 2005. The cyclist caught sight of the religious passed by, shouting profanities. (He was afterwards dubbed by the two sisters, “The
from the distant part of the square, and then began to accelerate towards the two as Salzburg Spitter.”)
Daniel VanderKolk 109

Dietrich von Hildebrand as Ambassador And yet Dostoevsky was himself quite savage in his hatred of the
Catholic Church. Why was this?4
to the East: A Philokalic Reading of Hollis reasons that Dostoyevsky lacked the “final grace of recognition” and
His Writings on Beauty that his unconscious intense love for the Roman Catholic Church, coupled
with his inability to enter it, led to an equal degree of hatred for the Roman
Catholic Church. Hollis—like Dostoyevsky—wrote at a time when the dif-
DanielVanderKolk ferences between the two great Christian groups were seen as much more
pronounced than they seem to many today.
The arguments that Dostoyevsky espouses against Roman Cathol-
icism are simplistic and uncharitable. In this essay, there is neither the need
Introduction nor the space to refute his jejune estimation of Roman Catholicism. Fur-
thermore, Dostoyevsky’s harsh judgment of Roman Catholicism forms part
The famous quote by Dostoyevsky, “Beauty will save the world,”1 encapsu- of a thread of criticism aimed at the West as a whole. His criticisms of Ca-
lates the theme of the current volume, The Power of Beauty. For many of us tholicism are not so much a singling out as a constituent of a larger excoria-
in the West, these words inspire hope in the renewing power of beauty. The tion. Dostoyevsky does not greatly distinguish between Roman Catholicism,
statement’s meaning, however, is opaque. Either aesthetic beauty elevates hu- Europe, and the West, but treats them as a whole. Dostoyevsky’s opinions
man desires, or metaphysical beauty inspires mimicry. That is to say, either an do not come from a sheltered, uncouth soul. He was worldly and sensitive,
aesthetically pleasing creation ennobles those who behold it, or the beauty of intelligent, well-read, and talented. He spent much time abroad, and succes-
moral conduct incites imitation in those who behold it. sively gave himself to different competing ideologies.
Roman Catholic intellectuals often use this phrase to promote their Where did such vehement anti-Western, anti-Roman Catholic no-
theology in the context of modernity.2 This phenomenon occurs despite tions originate? My argument in this paper is that Dostoyevsky’s hyper-ratio-
the fact that Dostoyevsky, in the same work, The Idiot, gives his protagonist nal, hypo-spiritual branding of the West in general—and Roman Catholicism
Prince Myshkin the following lines: “Roman Catholicism is, in my opinion, in particular—traces back, in large part, to a Modern Greek compiling of
worse than Atheism itself.”3 Dostoyevsky himself did hold such stark views mainly Byzantine ascetic texts, known as The Philokalia.
of the Roman Catholic Church. Writing for The Tablet in 1947, Christopher In fact, a growing number of Eastern Orthodox scholars familiar
Hollis recognized this: with both traditions have rejected this simplistic Eastern view of the West.
Dostoevsky is not only a Christian novelist, but his Christianity For example, Thomas Aquinas was often criticized in twentieth century East-
has about it a recognition of the necessary primacy of the spir- ern Orthodox circles for his lack of apophatic nuance. Recently, however,
itual, a repudiation of what one may call “soup-kitchen” Chris- scholars such as Marcus Plested have shown this bias to be lacking to a con-
tianity, which makes him much more sympathetic to the Catho- siderable degree.5 George Demacopoulos and Aristotle Papanikolaou have
lic reader than all but a very few of modern Western writers…. edited volumes of a similar nature that touch on other controversial Eastern
Orthodox-Roman Catholic topics such as the filioque, the prominence of St.
1
See Fyodor Dostoevsky, The Idiot, trans. Constance Garnett (New York: Augustine, and episcopal authority.6 David Bentley Hart has followed suit
Bantam, 1981), 370. Ippolit attributes this quote to the prince.
2
See Donald Demarco, “Can Beauty Save the World?,” CERC (2009), ac- 4
Christopher Hollis, “Dostoevsky and the Catholic Church: A Clue to the
cessed August 7, 2015, http://www.catholiceducation.org/en/religion-and-philoso- Russian Mind,” The Tablet, August 30, 1947, http://archive.thetablet.co.uk/arti-
phy/philosophy/can-beauty-save-the-world.html; R. Jared Staudt, “Beauty Will Save cle/30th-august-1947/5/dostoevsky-and-the-catholic-church-a-clue-to-the-r/.
the World: From the Mouth of an Idiot to the Pen of a Pope,” Crisis Magazine, July 5
Marcus Plested, Orthodox Readings of Aquinas (Oxford: Oxford University
10, 2013, accessed August 7, 2015, http://www.crisismagazine.com/2013/beauty- Press, 2012).
will-save-the-world-from-the-mouth-of-an-idiot-to-the-pen-of-a-pope. 6
George Demacopoulos and Aristotle Papanikolaou, Orthodox Constructions
3
Dostoevsky, The Idiot, part 4, chap. 7. of the West (New York: Fordham University Press, 2013); George Demacopoulos
and Aristotle Papanikolaou, Orthodox Readings of Augustine (Yonkers: St. Vladimir’s
© Daniel VanderKolk, Quaestiones Disputatae, Vol. 6, No. 2 (Spring 2016)
Seminary Press, 2008).
Daniel VanderKolk 109

Dietrich von Hildebrand as Ambassador And yet Dostoevsky was himself quite savage in his hatred of the
Catholic Church. Why was this?4
to the East: A Philokalic Reading of Hollis reasons that Dostoyevsky lacked the “final grace of recognition” and
His Writings on Beauty that his unconscious intense love for the Roman Catholic Church, coupled
with his inability to enter it, led to an equal degree of hatred for the Roman
Catholic Church. Hollis—like Dostoyevsky—wrote at a time when the dif-
DanielVanderKolk ferences between the two great Christian groups were seen as much more
pronounced than they seem to many today.
The arguments that Dostoyevsky espouses against Roman Cathol-
icism are simplistic and uncharitable. In this essay, there is neither the need
Introduction nor the space to refute his jejune estimation of Roman Catholicism. Fur-
thermore, Dostoyevsky’s harsh judgment of Roman Catholicism forms part
The famous quote by Dostoyevsky, “Beauty will save the world,”1 encapsu- of a thread of criticism aimed at the West as a whole. His criticisms of Ca-
lates the theme of the current volume, The Power of Beauty. For many of us tholicism are not so much a singling out as a constituent of a larger excoria-
in the West, these words inspire hope in the renewing power of beauty. The tion. Dostoyevsky does not greatly distinguish between Roman Catholicism,
statement’s meaning, however, is opaque. Either aesthetic beauty elevates hu- Europe, and the West, but treats them as a whole. Dostoyevsky’s opinions
man desires, or metaphysical beauty inspires mimicry. That is to say, either an do not come from a sheltered, uncouth soul. He was worldly and sensitive,
aesthetically pleasing creation ennobles those who behold it, or the beauty of intelligent, well-read, and talented. He spent much time abroad, and succes-
moral conduct incites imitation in those who behold it. sively gave himself to different competing ideologies.
Roman Catholic intellectuals often use this phrase to promote their Where did such vehement anti-Western, anti-Roman Catholic no-
theology in the context of modernity.2 This phenomenon occurs despite tions originate? My argument in this paper is that Dostoyevsky’s hyper-ratio-
the fact that Dostoyevsky, in the same work, The Idiot, gives his protagonist nal, hypo-spiritual branding of the West in general—and Roman Catholicism
Prince Myshkin the following lines: “Roman Catholicism is, in my opinion, in particular—traces back, in large part, to a Modern Greek compiling of
worse than Atheism itself.”3 Dostoyevsky himself did hold such stark views mainly Byzantine ascetic texts, known as The Philokalia.
of the Roman Catholic Church. Writing for The Tablet in 1947, Christopher In fact, a growing number of Eastern Orthodox scholars familiar
Hollis recognized this: with both traditions have rejected this simplistic Eastern view of the West.
Dostoevsky is not only a Christian novelist, but his Christianity For example, Thomas Aquinas was often criticized in twentieth century East-
has about it a recognition of the necessary primacy of the spir- ern Orthodox circles for his lack of apophatic nuance. Recently, however,
itual, a repudiation of what one may call “soup-kitchen” Chris- scholars such as Marcus Plested have shown this bias to be lacking to a con-
tianity, which makes him much more sympathetic to the Catho- siderable degree.5 George Demacopoulos and Aristotle Papanikolaou have
lic reader than all but a very few of modern Western writers…. edited volumes of a similar nature that touch on other controversial Eastern
Orthodox-Roman Catholic topics such as the filioque, the prominence of St.
1
See Fyodor Dostoevsky, The Idiot, trans. Constance Garnett (New York: Augustine, and episcopal authority.6 David Bentley Hart has followed suit
Bantam, 1981), 370. Ippolit attributes this quote to the prince.
2
See Donald Demarco, “Can Beauty Save the World?,” CERC (2009), ac- 4
Christopher Hollis, “Dostoevsky and the Catholic Church: A Clue to the
cessed August 7, 2015, http://www.catholiceducation.org/en/religion-and-philoso- Russian Mind,” The Tablet, August 30, 1947, http://archive.thetablet.co.uk/arti-
phy/philosophy/can-beauty-save-the-world.html; R. Jared Staudt, “Beauty Will Save cle/30th-august-1947/5/dostoevsky-and-the-catholic-church-a-clue-to-the-r/.
the World: From the Mouth of an Idiot to the Pen of a Pope,” Crisis Magazine, July 5
Marcus Plested, Orthodox Readings of Aquinas (Oxford: Oxford University
10, 2013, accessed August 7, 2015, http://www.crisismagazine.com/2013/beauty- Press, 2012).
will-save-the-world-from-the-mouth-of-an-idiot-to-the-pen-of-a-pope. 6
George Demacopoulos and Aristotle Papanikolaou, Orthodox Constructions
3
Dostoevsky, The Idiot, part 4, chap. 7. of the West (New York: Fordham University Press, 2013); George Demacopoulos
and Aristotle Papanikolaou, Orthodox Readings of Augustine (Yonkers: St. Vladimir’s
© Daniel VanderKolk, Quaestiones Disputatae, Vol. 6, No. 2 (Spring 2016)
Seminary Press, 2008).
110 Dietrich von Hildebrand as Ambassador Daniel VanderKolk 111
with more aggressive, yet equally apt insights.7 Dostoyevsky was no doubt familiar with their writings.11 Conservative in na-
Following on this trend in twenty-first century Eastern Orthodox ture, the Slavophile movement sought a return to “authentic” Russian tra-
theological scholarship, I submit that Dietrich von Hildebrand’s writings on dition, and viewed Russia’s monasteries as a manifestation of the essence of
beauty represent both a broad spectrum of Roman Catholic thought and a Russian culture.
Philokalic, Eastern Orthodox view of the world. Perhaps greater recognition The greatest monastery of nineteenth century Russia was Optina,
of the Eastern character of Dietrich von Hildebrand’s writings will nurture whose monks deeply influenced the Slavophiles—especially the Kireyevskys
East-West dialogue by adding some subtlety to balance common mispercep- and Dostoyevsky.12 This famous male monastic community, situated south-
tions. west of Moscow, is widely recognized by modern Russian Orthodox scholars
as having exerted—arguably—more influence on the conservative spiritual
movements within Russia during the nineteenth century and the beginning
Dostoyevsky, the Slavophiles, and Optina Monastery: of the twentieth century than any other contemporaneous Russian institu-
Dostoyevsky’s Link to The Philokalia tion. Why was Optina so popular? The monastery was undergoing a spiritual
revival. The life of the male monastic community had been rejuvenated by
Fyodor Dostoyevsky composed The Idiot in Europe from 1867–1869, during the rediscovery of their spiritual tradition, recorded in The Philokalia. Paert
a somewhat self-imposed yet undesired absence from Russia.8 The experi- writes:
ences of this period of his life polarized his developing philosophical posi- In the 1840s, the [Optina] hermitage began its publishing ac-
tions and justified his future ones. Gocsik writes: “He [Dostoyevsky] began tivities with the assistance of educated novices Leonid Kavelin,
to believe more vehemently in the superiority of the Russian soul over the Amvrosii Grenkov, and Iuvelian Polovtsev, and with the active
European intellect.”9 It appears that much of Dostoyevsky’s disdain for the support of the Slavophile Ivan Kireevskii and Bishop Filaret
West came from personal experience and personal rumination. (Drozdov). The aim of the publishers was to introduce the leg-
Yet, external agents, such as Slavophilism, a nineteenth century Rus- acy of Paisii Velichkovskii and other works of monastic spiritu-
sian-Nationalist ideology, influenced the novelist greatly.10 The Kireyevsky ality to the reading public in Russia. By the turn of the century
brothers—Pyotr and Ivan—were two of the most influential Slavophiles; Optina had published 125 titles (225,000 total print copies), the
majority of which were by hesychast authors. The monastery sent
their published books to all Russian communal monasteries and
7
David Bentley Hart, “The Myth of Schism,” in Ecumenism Today: The Uni-
versal Church in the 21st Century, ed. Francesca Aran Murphy and Christopher Asprey 11
See Joseph Frank, Dostoyevsky: The Mantle of the Prophet, 1871–1881 (Princ-
(Burlington, VT: Ashgate Publishing, 2008). eton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2003); Sarah Hudspith, Dostoevsky and the Idea
8
See Karen Gocsik, “The Man and His Times: Biography,” The Brothers Kara- of Russianness: A New Perspective on Unity and Brotherhood (New York, NY: Routledge,
mazov Resource, Dartmouth Rhetoric and Writing Department, accessed February 24, 2015, 2004), 5. David Denby, “Can Dostoyevsky Still Kick You in the Gut?,” The New York-
http://www.dartmouth.edu/~karamazov/resources/?page_id=513. Fleeing to Eu- er, June 11, 2012, http://www.newyorker.com/books/page-turner/can-dostoevsky-
rope from creditors in Russia, he increasingly loathed his surroundings the longer he still-kick-you-in-the-gut, dates the beginning of the Slavophile influence on Dosto-
remained abroad. yevsky to his Notes From the Underground. Janko Lavrin, Tolstoy: An Approach Bound with
9
Ibid.; see also Liza Knapp, ed., Dostoyevsky’s The Idiot: A Critical Companion Dostoyevsky (New York, NY: Routledge, 2015), 23, disagrees, seeing the influence of
(Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 1998), 143. Slavophilism on Dostoyevsky in his later works such as The Idiot and The Possessed.
10
Slavophilism is complex and is not exhausted by Russian Nationalism or 12
See Sergius Chetverikov, Elder Ambrose of Optina (Platina, California: St.
Russian Anti-Westernism. Robert Bird writes: “the Slavophiles were as likely to dis- Herman of Alaska Brotherhood, 1997), 65, 123–33, for the Kireyevsky brothers’
agree as to agree with each other…if they were united in a single movement, it was connection to Optina. For Optina’s effect on Dostoyevsky, see Leonard J Stanton,
not by any partiality for the Slavic race, but rather by a shared commitment to the The Optina Pustyn Monastery in the Russian Literary Imagination: Iconic Vision in Works
religious and universal calling of Russia” in Aleksei Khomiakov and Ivan Kireevsky, by Dostoevsky, Gogol, Tolstoy, and Others, Middlebury Studies in Russian Language and
On Spiritual Unity: A Slavophile Reader, trans. Boris Jakim and Robert Bird (Hudson, Literature 3 (New York, NY: Peter Lang, 1995). Optina Monastery is Optina Pustyn
NY: Lindisfarne Books, 1998), 7. See Leonid Kavelin, Elder Macarius of Optina (Pla- in Russian. “Pustyn” literally means “desert” but by convention has attained the
tina, California: St. Herman of Alaska Brotherhood, 1995), 290–307, for insights on meaning “monastery” in reference to the Egyptian and Palestinian deserts that first
the Slavophile rebellion from European culture. inspired Christian monasticism.
110 Dietrich von Hildebrand as Ambassador Daniel VanderKolk 111
with more aggressive, yet equally apt insights.7 Dostoyevsky was no doubt familiar with their writings.11 Conservative in na-
Following on this trend in twenty-first century Eastern Orthodox ture, the Slavophile movement sought a return to “authentic” Russian tra-
theological scholarship, I submit that Dietrich von Hildebrand’s writings on dition, and viewed Russia’s monasteries as a manifestation of the essence of
beauty represent both a broad spectrum of Roman Catholic thought and a Russian culture.
Philokalic, Eastern Orthodox view of the world. Perhaps greater recognition The greatest monastery of nineteenth century Russia was Optina,
of the Eastern character of Dietrich von Hildebrand’s writings will nurture whose monks deeply influenced the Slavophiles—especially the Kireyevskys
East-West dialogue by adding some subtlety to balance common mispercep- and Dostoyevsky.12 This famous male monastic community, situated south-
tions. west of Moscow, is widely recognized by modern Russian Orthodox scholars
as having exerted—arguably—more influence on the conservative spiritual
movements within Russia during the nineteenth century and the beginning
Dostoyevsky, the Slavophiles, and Optina Monastery: of the twentieth century than any other contemporaneous Russian institu-
Dostoyevsky’s Link to The Philokalia tion. Why was Optina so popular? The monastery was undergoing a spiritual
revival. The life of the male monastic community had been rejuvenated by
Fyodor Dostoyevsky composed The Idiot in Europe from 1867–1869, during the rediscovery of their spiritual tradition, recorded in The Philokalia. Paert
a somewhat self-imposed yet undesired absence from Russia.8 The experi- writes:
ences of this period of his life polarized his developing philosophical posi- In the 1840s, the [Optina] hermitage began its publishing ac-
tions and justified his future ones. Gocsik writes: “He [Dostoyevsky] began tivities with the assistance of educated novices Leonid Kavelin,
to believe more vehemently in the superiority of the Russian soul over the Amvrosii Grenkov, and Iuvelian Polovtsev, and with the active
European intellect.”9 It appears that much of Dostoyevsky’s disdain for the support of the Slavophile Ivan Kireevskii and Bishop Filaret
West came from personal experience and personal rumination. (Drozdov). The aim of the publishers was to introduce the leg-
Yet, external agents, such as Slavophilism, a nineteenth century Rus- acy of Paisii Velichkovskii and other works of monastic spiritu-
sian-Nationalist ideology, influenced the novelist greatly.10 The Kireyevsky ality to the reading public in Russia. By the turn of the century
brothers—Pyotr and Ivan—were two of the most influential Slavophiles; Optina had published 125 titles (225,000 total print copies), the
majority of which were by hesychast authors. The monastery sent
their published books to all Russian communal monasteries and
7
David Bentley Hart, “The Myth of Schism,” in Ecumenism Today: The Uni-
versal Church in the 21st Century, ed. Francesca Aran Murphy and Christopher Asprey 11
See Joseph Frank, Dostoyevsky: The Mantle of the Prophet, 1871–1881 (Princ-
(Burlington, VT: Ashgate Publishing, 2008). eton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2003); Sarah Hudspith, Dostoevsky and the Idea
8
See Karen Gocsik, “The Man and His Times: Biography,” The Brothers Kara- of Russianness: A New Perspective on Unity and Brotherhood (New York, NY: Routledge,
mazov Resource, Dartmouth Rhetoric and Writing Department, accessed February 24, 2015, 2004), 5. David Denby, “Can Dostoyevsky Still Kick You in the Gut?,” The New York-
http://www.dartmouth.edu/~karamazov/resources/?page_id=513. Fleeing to Eu- er, June 11, 2012, http://www.newyorker.com/books/page-turner/can-dostoevsky-
rope from creditors in Russia, he increasingly loathed his surroundings the longer he still-kick-you-in-the-gut, dates the beginning of the Slavophile influence on Dosto-
remained abroad. yevsky to his Notes From the Underground. Janko Lavrin, Tolstoy: An Approach Bound with
9
Ibid.; see also Liza Knapp, ed., Dostoyevsky’s The Idiot: A Critical Companion Dostoyevsky (New York, NY: Routledge, 2015), 23, disagrees, seeing the influence of
(Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 1998), 143. Slavophilism on Dostoyevsky in his later works such as The Idiot and The Possessed.
10
Slavophilism is complex and is not exhausted by Russian Nationalism or 12
See Sergius Chetverikov, Elder Ambrose of Optina (Platina, California: St.
Russian Anti-Westernism. Robert Bird writes: “the Slavophiles were as likely to dis- Herman of Alaska Brotherhood, 1997), 65, 123–33, for the Kireyevsky brothers’
agree as to agree with each other…if they were united in a single movement, it was connection to Optina. For Optina’s effect on Dostoyevsky, see Leonard J Stanton,
not by any partiality for the Slavic race, but rather by a shared commitment to the The Optina Pustyn Monastery in the Russian Literary Imagination: Iconic Vision in Works
religious and universal calling of Russia” in Aleksei Khomiakov and Ivan Kireevsky, by Dostoevsky, Gogol, Tolstoy, and Others, Middlebury Studies in Russian Language and
On Spiritual Unity: A Slavophile Reader, trans. Boris Jakim and Robert Bird (Hudson, Literature 3 (New York, NY: Peter Lang, 1995). Optina Monastery is Optina Pustyn
NY: Lindisfarne Books, 1998), 7. See Leonid Kavelin, Elder Macarius of Optina (Pla- in Russian. “Pustyn” literally means “desert” but by convention has attained the
tina, California: St. Herman of Alaska Brotherhood, 1995), 290–307, for insights on meaning “monastery” in reference to the Egyptian and Palestinian deserts that first
the Slavophile rebellion from European culture. inspired Christian monasticism.
112 Dietrich von Hildebrand as Ambassador Daniel VanderKolk 113
to the Russian and Bulgarian monasteries in Athos, as well as to The writings, credited with reviving monastic life in the Balkans and
seminary and academic libraries. The Optina eldership was quite Russia, focus on subduing bodily desires, purifying inner sins through prayer,
unique in that it forged a link with a section of Russian educated and contemplating theological truths. The monks who studied these writings
society, which Stanton described as the “Optina intelligentsia.”13 left a deep impression on Dostoyevsky. In fact, Elder Ambrose of Opti-
The reforming character of The Philokalia rested in its emphasis on sincere na is often thought of as the inspiration for the character Fr. Zosima from
piety, an aspect of religious devotion that was often lost in the externals The Brothers Karamazov.15 In some ways the spiritual effects of The Philokalia
of Russian Orthodox Christianity. The monks and elders of Optina were and the spiritual revival it sparked in Russia are felt in the West through
known throughout nineteenth century Russia for their authentic faith. Be- the writings of Dostoyevsky, which are often heralded for their spiritual and
cause their monastic lifestyle was directed by the reading of The Philokalia, the psychological insights. For this reason, The Philokalia deserves a more thor-
Slavophiles— including Dostoyevsky—also read The Philokalia. ough treatment in the West, where the anthology has been relegated to the
realm of Eastern Orthodox Christians, Early Christianity scholars, and Byz-
antinists.
Compiling The Philokalia

The Philokalia is a collection of Christian monastic treatises, akin to the Say- The Philokalia, Noesis, and Apophaticism
ings of the Desert Fathers and the Rule of Benedict. The five-volume anthology
comprised treatises by Byzantine authors ranging from the fourth century The title “Philokalia” literally means “love of the beautiful things”; “kalia”
to the fifteenth century. The compilers of the anthology gathered popu- could also translate as “good.” It is a uniquely multi-faceted word, fitting for
lar Eastern Christian monastic texts long forgotten in the monasteries of a study of the transcendentals. Kallistos Ware, the foremost expert on The
Greece and Romania. These texts had become unintelligible to believers due Philokalia, includes the following footnote in his English translation of the
to linguistic changes in both the Hellenistic and Slavic language groups. In text:
addition, the utility of the printing press had not yet been applied to these The Greek word used here is not agathos (good) but kalos, a term
disparate monastic manuscripts. The compilers of The Philokalia knew that that in the Septuagint, and in the Greek patristic tradition as a
this technology would greatly aid the dissemination of the teachings found in whole, denotes the beautiful no less and sometimes more than
these precious manuscripts. Three initial translations of the Byzantine Greek the good. To speak of creation and created things as beautiful
texts into modern Eastern Orthodox languages were made. The volumes does not of course mean only that they are pleasing to look at.
of The Philokalia were initially published in Modern Greek by Nikodemos What is implicit in this context is the understanding that physical
of the Holy Mountain in 1782. 1793 saw the publishing of The Philokalia in beauty is an epiphany of divine beauty: physical beauty is related
Old Church Slavonic by Paisii Velichkovsky. Ignatii Brianchaninov published to moral beauty, and both are related to their origin in the world
them in 1857 in Modern Russian.14 of incorporeal essences (the logoi) and its principle, the Good it-
self, or God. It is with these connotations in mind that the term
13
Irina Paert, Spiritual Elders: Charisma and Tradition in Russian Orthodoxy
(Dekalb, IL: Northern Illinois University Press, 2010), 76. “Hesychast” is an Eastern
Orthodox term for one who cultivates interior silence, calm, and quiet through con-
tinual prayer. The term derives from the Ancient Greek word hesychia (ἡσυχία), which ed. Brock Bingaman and Bradley Nassif (New York, NY: Oxford University Press,
translates as “still, quiet, rest.” 2012), 36–49; Nicholas Groves, “Optina Pustyn as a Center of Desert Spirituality in
14
For the history of the compiling of The Philokalia, see: Starets Macarius of Nineteenth-Century Russia: In Search of the Prayer of the Heart,” Romanian Medi-
Optina, “Introduction,” Russian Letters of Spiritual Direction: 1834–1860, trans. Iulia evalia 2 (2004); and Schemamonk Metrophanes, Blessed Paisius Velichkovsky: The Man
de Beausobre (Yonkers: St. Vladimir’s Seminary Press, 1975); Nikodemos of the Behind the Philokalia, trans. Fr. Seraphim Rose (Platina, CA: St. Herman of Alaska
Holy Mountain and Makarios of Corinth, The Philokalia: The Complete Text, trans. Brotherhood, 1976).
G.E.H. Palmer, Philip Sherrard, and Kallistos Ware (London: Faber and Faber, 15
See George Andrew Panichas, Dostoevsky’s Spiritual Art: The Burden of Vision
1979), 1:11–13; John Anthony McGuckin, “The Making of the Philokalia: A Tale (New Jersey: Transaction Publishers, 2005), 159, and Jacques Catteau, Dostoevsky and
of Monks and Manuscripts,” in The Philokalia: A Classic Text of Orthodox Spirituality, the Process of Literary Creation (New York, NY: Cambridge University Press, 1989), 87.
112 Dietrich von Hildebrand as Ambassador Daniel VanderKolk 113
to the Russian and Bulgarian monasteries in Athos, as well as to The writings, credited with reviving monastic life in the Balkans and
seminary and academic libraries. The Optina eldership was quite Russia, focus on subduing bodily desires, purifying inner sins through prayer,
unique in that it forged a link with a section of Russian educated and contemplating theological truths. The monks who studied these writings
society, which Stanton described as the “Optina intelligentsia.”13 left a deep impression on Dostoyevsky. In fact, Elder Ambrose of Opti-
The reforming character of The Philokalia rested in its emphasis on sincere na is often thought of as the inspiration for the character Fr. Zosima from
piety, an aspect of religious devotion that was often lost in the externals The Brothers Karamazov.15 In some ways the spiritual effects of The Philokalia
of Russian Orthodox Christianity. The monks and elders of Optina were and the spiritual revival it sparked in Russia are felt in the West through
known throughout nineteenth century Russia for their authentic faith. Be- the writings of Dostoyevsky, which are often heralded for their spiritual and
cause their monastic lifestyle was directed by the reading of The Philokalia, the psychological insights. For this reason, The Philokalia deserves a more thor-
Slavophiles— including Dostoyevsky—also read The Philokalia. ough treatment in the West, where the anthology has been relegated to the
realm of Eastern Orthodox Christians, Early Christianity scholars, and Byz-
antinists.
Compiling The Philokalia

The Philokalia is a collection of Christian monastic treatises, akin to the Say- The Philokalia, Noesis, and Apophaticism
ings of the Desert Fathers and the Rule of Benedict. The five-volume anthology
comprised treatises by Byzantine authors ranging from the fourth century The title “Philokalia” literally means “love of the beautiful things”; “kalia”
to the fifteenth century. The compilers of the anthology gathered popu- could also translate as “good.” It is a uniquely multi-faceted word, fitting for
lar Eastern Christian monastic texts long forgotten in the monasteries of a study of the transcendentals. Kallistos Ware, the foremost expert on The
Greece and Romania. These texts had become unintelligible to believers due Philokalia, includes the following footnote in his English translation of the
to linguistic changes in both the Hellenistic and Slavic language groups. In text:
addition, the utility of the printing press had not yet been applied to these The Greek word used here is not agathos (good) but kalos, a term
disparate monastic manuscripts. The compilers of The Philokalia knew that that in the Septuagint, and in the Greek patristic tradition as a
this technology would greatly aid the dissemination of the teachings found in whole, denotes the beautiful no less and sometimes more than
these precious manuscripts. Three initial translations of the Byzantine Greek the good. To speak of creation and created things as beautiful
texts into modern Eastern Orthodox languages were made. The volumes does not of course mean only that they are pleasing to look at.
of The Philokalia were initially published in Modern Greek by Nikodemos What is implicit in this context is the understanding that physical
of the Holy Mountain in 1782. 1793 saw the publishing of The Philokalia in beauty is an epiphany of divine beauty: physical beauty is related
Old Church Slavonic by Paisii Velichkovsky. Ignatii Brianchaninov published to moral beauty, and both are related to their origin in the world
them in 1857 in Modern Russian.14 of incorporeal essences (the logoi) and its principle, the Good it-
self, or God. It is with these connotations in mind that the term
13
Irina Paert, Spiritual Elders: Charisma and Tradition in Russian Orthodoxy
(Dekalb, IL: Northern Illinois University Press, 2010), 76. “Hesychast” is an Eastern
Orthodox term for one who cultivates interior silence, calm, and quiet through con-
tinual prayer. The term derives from the Ancient Greek word hesychia (ἡσυχία), which ed. Brock Bingaman and Bradley Nassif (New York, NY: Oxford University Press,
translates as “still, quiet, rest.” 2012), 36–49; Nicholas Groves, “Optina Pustyn as a Center of Desert Spirituality in
14
For the history of the compiling of The Philokalia, see: Starets Macarius of Nineteenth-Century Russia: In Search of the Prayer of the Heart,” Romanian Medi-
Optina, “Introduction,” Russian Letters of Spiritual Direction: 1834–1860, trans. Iulia evalia 2 (2004); and Schemamonk Metrophanes, Blessed Paisius Velichkovsky: The Man
de Beausobre (Yonkers: St. Vladimir’s Seminary Press, 1975); Nikodemos of the Behind the Philokalia, trans. Fr. Seraphim Rose (Platina, CA: St. Herman of Alaska
Holy Mountain and Makarios of Corinth, The Philokalia: The Complete Text, trans. Brotherhood, 1976).
G.E.H. Palmer, Philip Sherrard, and Kallistos Ware (London: Faber and Faber, 15
See George Andrew Panichas, Dostoevsky’s Spiritual Art: The Burden of Vision
1979), 1:11–13; John Anthony McGuckin, “The Making of the Philokalia: A Tale (New Jersey: Transaction Publishers, 2005), 159, and Jacques Catteau, Dostoevsky and
of Monks and Manuscripts,” in The Philokalia: A Classic Text of Orthodox Spirituality, the Process of Literary Creation (New York, NY: Cambridge University Press, 1989), 87.
114 Dietrich von Hildebrand as Ambassador Daniel VanderKolk 115
should be read, as indeed it should be read in the actual title of ence, intuition or “simple cognition” (the term used by St. Isaac
The Philokalia.16 the Syrian). The intellect dwells in the “depths of the soul”; it con-
A central motif in The Philokalia is an Eastern Orthodox notion of three stitutes the innermost aspect of the heart (St. Diadochos). The
general stages of spiritual life: purification, illumination, and deification.17 intellect is the organ of contemplation. “Intellection” (νόησις -
The first stage, purification, refers to the most outwardly active step in this noīsis): not an abstract concept or a visual image, but the act or
process. At this point the ascetic labors in fasting, keeping vigil, manual la- function of the intellect whereby it apprehends spiritual realities
bor, attentive prayer, confession, and spiritual reading in order to subdue in a direct manner.19
his or her bodily desires and wash away his or her inward sins. The second The Philokalia here states that Christians contemplate God by first contem-
stage, illumination, is when the ascetic accumulates grace and contemplates plating created things with an intuitive faculty of their heart, above rational
the theological implications of God’s creation. The third step, deification,18 thought.
involves the ascetic contemplating God Himself. This strict emphasis on the spiritual faculty of man being the pri-
For this study, the important point is how The Philokalia describes mary mode of theological apprehension found in these Byzantine texts has
the Eastern Orthodox interaction with divine creation—and by extension— deeply affected the Eastern Orthodox sense of mysticism. Mystical apophat-
manmade creations and beauty. Kallistos Ware writes: ic theology, not discursive cataphatic theology, has become the self-defining
“Intellect” (νοῦς - nous): the highest faculty in man, through characteristic of Eastern Orthodoxy in recent centuries. Theologians such
which—provided it is purified—he knows God or the inner es- as Lossky and Romanides have particularly used this quality to delimit the
sences or principles of created things by means of direct appre- boundary between Eastern Orthodoxy and other Christian groups.20 Howev-
hension or spiritual perception. Unlike the dianoia or reason, from er, recently, efforts have begun to rethink this self-identity as the Eastern Or-
which it must be carefully distinguished, the intellect does not thodox being the most-apophatic or most-mystical Christian group. McGu-
function by formulating abstract concepts and then arguing on ckin, a renowned Eastern Orthodox theologian and a Romanian Orthodox
this basis to a conclusion reached through deductive reasoning, priest, specifically responded to Lossky’s legacy in a recent commencement
but it understands divine truth by means of immediate experi- speech:
If one did make a global review (which Lossky does not) of the
16
Nikodemos of the Holy Mountain and Makarios of Corinth, The Philokalia:
mystical tradition of the West, would it be all that divergent in
The Complete Text, trans. G.E.H. Palmer, Philip Sherrard, and Kallistos Ware (London: spiritual ethos? Were the Western mystics (distinctive personalities
Faber and Faber, 1984), 3:390. though they surely were) all that individualistic and un-ecclesial?
17
Nikodemos of the Holy Mountain, The Philokalia, 1:358–59: “Contempla- In setting out this thesis has not Lossky unconsciously fallen into
tion (θεωρία): the perception or vision of the intellect through which one attains that very type of Bergsonian polarization that he attacks in his
spiritual knowledge. It may be contrasted with the practice of the virtues which opening pages? For surely the Western church was able enough
designates the more external aspect of the ascetic life–purification and the keeping to receive or dismiss any theological voice from its larger sense
of the commandments–but which is an indispensable prerequisite of contemplation. of the Tradition: knowing well enough the significant differentiae
Depending on the level of personal spiritual growth, contemplation has two main between a St. John of the Cross and a Nicholas of Cusa.
stages: it may be either of the inner essences [principles] of created beings or, at a
higher stage, of God Himself.” Lossky argues that the Western mystical tradition is almost ex-
18
See Norman Russell, The Doctrine of Deification in the Greek Patristic Tradition, clusively Christocentric and neglectful of the Trinitarian reality
Oxford Early Christian Studies (New York, NY: Oxford University Press, 2004); of God. But the mystics of the West, so it seems to me, are a
Michael J. Christensen and Jeffrey A. Wittung, eds., Partakers of the Divine Nature: The
History and Development of Deification in the Christian Traditions (Madison, NJ: Fairleigh
Dickinson University Press, 2007); for studies in theosis, see Stephen Finlan and 19
Nikodemos of the Holy Mountain, The Philokalia, 1:362.
Vladimir Kharmalov, eds., Theosis: Deification in Christian Theology, vol. 1, Princeton 20
See Vladimir Lossky, The Mystical Theology of the Eastern Church, (Crestwood,
Theological Monograph Series (Eugene, OR: Pickwick, 2006) and Stephen Finlan NY: St. Vladimir’s Seminary Press, 1976), 26; and John Romanides, Patristic Theology:
and Vladimir Kharmalov, eds., Theosis: Deification in Christian Theology, vol. 2, Princeton The University Lectures of Fr. John Romanides (The Dalles, OR: Uncut Mountain Press,
Theological Monograph Series (Eugene, OR: Pickwick, 2011). 2008), 286–87.
114 Dietrich von Hildebrand as Ambassador Daniel VanderKolk 115
should be read, as indeed it should be read in the actual title of ence, intuition or “simple cognition” (the term used by St. Isaac
The Philokalia.16 the Syrian). The intellect dwells in the “depths of the soul”; it con-
A central motif in The Philokalia is an Eastern Orthodox notion of three stitutes the innermost aspect of the heart (St. Diadochos). The
general stages of spiritual life: purification, illumination, and deification.17 intellect is the organ of contemplation. “Intellection” (νόησις -
The first stage, purification, refers to the most outwardly active step in this noīsis): not an abstract concept or a visual image, but the act or
process. At this point the ascetic labors in fasting, keeping vigil, manual la- function of the intellect whereby it apprehends spiritual realities
bor, attentive prayer, confession, and spiritual reading in order to subdue in a direct manner.19
his or her bodily desires and wash away his or her inward sins. The second The Philokalia here states that Christians contemplate God by first contem-
stage, illumination, is when the ascetic accumulates grace and contemplates plating created things with an intuitive faculty of their heart, above rational
the theological implications of God’s creation. The third step, deification,18 thought.
involves the ascetic contemplating God Himself. This strict emphasis on the spiritual faculty of man being the pri-
For this study, the important point is how The Philokalia describes mary mode of theological apprehension found in these Byzantine texts has
the Eastern Orthodox interaction with divine creation—and by extension— deeply affected the Eastern Orthodox sense of mysticism. Mystical apophat-
manmade creations and beauty. Kallistos Ware writes: ic theology, not discursive cataphatic theology, has become the self-defining
“Intellect” (νοῦς - nous): the highest faculty in man, through characteristic of Eastern Orthodoxy in recent centuries. Theologians such
which—provided it is purified—he knows God or the inner es- as Lossky and Romanides have particularly used this quality to delimit the
sences or principles of created things by means of direct appre- boundary between Eastern Orthodoxy and other Christian groups.20 Howev-
hension or spiritual perception. Unlike the dianoia or reason, from er, recently, efforts have begun to rethink this self-identity as the Eastern Or-
which it must be carefully distinguished, the intellect does not thodox being the most-apophatic or most-mystical Christian group. McGu-
function by formulating abstract concepts and then arguing on ckin, a renowned Eastern Orthodox theologian and a Romanian Orthodox
this basis to a conclusion reached through deductive reasoning, priest, specifically responded to Lossky’s legacy in a recent commencement
but it understands divine truth by means of immediate experi- speech:
If one did make a global review (which Lossky does not) of the
16
Nikodemos of the Holy Mountain and Makarios of Corinth, The Philokalia:
mystical tradition of the West, would it be all that divergent in
The Complete Text, trans. G.E.H. Palmer, Philip Sherrard, and Kallistos Ware (London: spiritual ethos? Were the Western mystics (distinctive personalities
Faber and Faber, 1984), 3:390. though they surely were) all that individualistic and un-ecclesial?
17
Nikodemos of the Holy Mountain, The Philokalia, 1:358–59: “Contempla- In setting out this thesis has not Lossky unconsciously fallen into
tion (θεωρία): the perception or vision of the intellect through which one attains that very type of Bergsonian polarization that he attacks in his
spiritual knowledge. It may be contrasted with the practice of the virtues which opening pages? For surely the Western church was able enough
designates the more external aspect of the ascetic life–purification and the keeping to receive or dismiss any theological voice from its larger sense
of the commandments–but which is an indispensable prerequisite of contemplation. of the Tradition: knowing well enough the significant differentiae
Depending on the level of personal spiritual growth, contemplation has two main between a St. John of the Cross and a Nicholas of Cusa.
stages: it may be either of the inner essences [principles] of created beings or, at a
higher stage, of God Himself.” Lossky argues that the Western mystical tradition is almost ex-
18
See Norman Russell, The Doctrine of Deification in the Greek Patristic Tradition, clusively Christocentric and neglectful of the Trinitarian reality
Oxford Early Christian Studies (New York, NY: Oxford University Press, 2004); of God. But the mystics of the West, so it seems to me, are a
Michael J. Christensen and Jeffrey A. Wittung, eds., Partakers of the Divine Nature: The
History and Development of Deification in the Christian Traditions (Madison, NJ: Fairleigh
Dickinson University Press, 2007); for studies in theosis, see Stephen Finlan and 19
Nikodemos of the Holy Mountain, The Philokalia, 1:362.
Vladimir Kharmalov, eds., Theosis: Deification in Christian Theology, vol. 1, Princeton 20
See Vladimir Lossky, The Mystical Theology of the Eastern Church, (Crestwood,
Theological Monograph Series (Eugene, OR: Pickwick, 2006) and Stephen Finlan NY: St. Vladimir’s Seminary Press, 1976), 26; and John Romanides, Patristic Theology:
and Vladimir Kharmalov, eds., Theosis: Deification in Christian Theology, vol. 2, Princeton The University Lectures of Fr. John Romanides (The Dalles, OR: Uncut Mountain Press,
Theological Monograph Series (Eugene, OR: Pickwick, 2011). 2008), 286–87.
116 Dietrich von Hildebrand as Ambassador Daniel VanderKolk 117
long way removed from solipsism in their spirituality. There are is entirely attending to a non-aesthetic concern, we are nevertheless acted
undoubtedly different foci and stresses to the Orthodox ascet- upon by the aesthetics of our environment. He reiterates that even a person
ical fathers: but throughout the spirituality of the West runs a who cannot reason well is the recipient of spiritual nourishment from an
profound focus on the Cross and its redemptive power: and that aesthetically beautiful environment. Therefore, in von Hildebrand’s thought,
cannot be simply reduced to a Christological focus deprived of one does not need to discursively connect a series of conceptions for the
Trinitarian perspective.21 drawing of a conclusion in order to benefit from aesthetic beauty. The ap-
Lossky was an educated Russian living in Paris from 1927–1958, as a mem- preciation of beautiful aesthetics does not require conscious, active effort of
ber of the Russian diaspora. Dostoyevsky was not far-removed from Lossky will.23
with regards to intellectual milieu and theology. Although sincere, both men The concept elucidated here by von Hildebrand is similar to the
reacted to the Catholics they encountered by assuming that they accurately activity of noesis, or intellectualization as articulated in The Philokalia. Spe-
represented Catholicism. To balance their characterization of Catholicism, I cifically, the non-rational and subconscious aspects of the activity here de-
offer up the aesthetics of Dietrich von Hildebrand as a bridge between East scribed by von Hildebrand mimic the supra-rational and intuitive properties
and West in the realm of mystical theology. of Philokalic noesis. One difference is that the authors of The Philokalia refer
mainly to divine creation, while von Hildebrand refers to both divine and
man-made creations. In keeping with the boundaries of The Philokalia’s genre,
Dietrich von Hildebrand as Noetic Aesthete a philosophical treatment of aesthetics would be out of place. Nevertheless,
it is reasonable to assume the authors of The Philokalia would apply what they
One vibrant characteristic of von Hildebrand’s treatment of beauty is his say about God’s creation to man-made creation.
concern for emphasizing the intuitiveness of the manner through which hu- Von Hildebrand elaborates his conception of the experience of
mans experience beauty. His work Aesthetics especially bears out this claim. beauty as relying primarily on our non-rational faculties in his monograph
While elaborating on the function of beauty as a central source of human “Beauty in the Light of the Redemption.” In this monograph, von Hildeb-
happiness, von Hildebrand turns to Arcadian scenes for elucidation of his rand first distinguishes beauty of form from metaphysical beauty. Second,
argument: he defends beauty of form from a utilitarian devaluation. He then refutes
an attack on beauty of form which contends that the sensory faculties are
The role of beauty for human happiness is not restricted to those
unspiritual powers used by those less advanced in virtue. At this juncture he
moments in which one is consciously looking at beautiful things.
criticizes philosophical endeavors to salvage the noble intangibility of beauty
Beauty is active even at those times when one’s attention is wholly
of form by severing the connection between beauty of form and the senses
directed to other things. The beauty of the environment in which
of seeing and hearing:
one lives—one’s house, even if it is very simple, like the farm-
houses of Tuscany; the view from one’s house, both near and far; If, for example, we view a lofty mountain range bathed in gleam-
the architectural beauty of the neighboring houses; the beauty ing sunlight, it is not that which we see directly before us to which
of the sun that shines into the house, and of the shadow cast beauty is attached, but the thought of God’s creative power is
by a tree—all this nourishes the soul even of the simplest man, the real beauty. In a word, the real bearer of beauty is something
entering into his pores even when he is not concentrating on it.22 incorporeal which we connect intellectually with the visible and
audible by means of analogies…. This attempt at rescuing the
The phrase “consciously looking” and the clause “one’s attention is wholly
incorporeality of beauty is well-meant, to be sure, but it is false,
directed to other things” should be read as descriptions of the use of the
for the beauty of the Campagna Romana or that of the Seventh
rational faculty. This passage places the experience of beauty beyond our rea-
Symphony by Bruckner is intuitive, linked directly with that which
soning faculty. Von Hildebrand points out that even when our consciousness
21
John McGuckin, “On the Mystical Theology of the Eastern Church,” St.
Vladimir’s Theological Quarterly 59, no. 1, (2015): 392–93.
22
Dietrich von Hildebrand, “The Place of Beauty in Human Existence,” in
Aesthetics (Dietrich von Hildebrand Legacy Project, forthcoming). 23
Ibid.
116 Dietrich von Hildebrand as Ambassador Daniel VanderKolk 117
long way removed from solipsism in their spirituality. There are is entirely attending to a non-aesthetic concern, we are nevertheless acted
undoubtedly different foci and stresses to the Orthodox ascet- upon by the aesthetics of our environment. He reiterates that even a person
ical fathers: but throughout the spirituality of the West runs a who cannot reason well is the recipient of spiritual nourishment from an
profound focus on the Cross and its redemptive power: and that aesthetically beautiful environment. Therefore, in von Hildebrand’s thought,
cannot be simply reduced to a Christological focus deprived of one does not need to discursively connect a series of conceptions for the
Trinitarian perspective.21 drawing of a conclusion in order to benefit from aesthetic beauty. The ap-
Lossky was an educated Russian living in Paris from 1927–1958, as a mem- preciation of beautiful aesthetics does not require conscious, active effort of
ber of the Russian diaspora. Dostoyevsky was not far-removed from Lossky will.23
with regards to intellectual milieu and theology. Although sincere, both men The concept elucidated here by von Hildebrand is similar to the
reacted to the Catholics they encountered by assuming that they accurately activity of noesis, or intellectualization as articulated in The Philokalia. Spe-
represented Catholicism. To balance their characterization of Catholicism, I cifically, the non-rational and subconscious aspects of the activity here de-
offer up the aesthetics of Dietrich von Hildebrand as a bridge between East scribed by von Hildebrand mimic the supra-rational and intuitive properties
and West in the realm of mystical theology. of Philokalic noesis. One difference is that the authors of The Philokalia refer
mainly to divine creation, while von Hildebrand refers to both divine and
man-made creations. In keeping with the boundaries of The Philokalia’s genre,
Dietrich von Hildebrand as Noetic Aesthete a philosophical treatment of aesthetics would be out of place. Nevertheless,
it is reasonable to assume the authors of The Philokalia would apply what they
One vibrant characteristic of von Hildebrand’s treatment of beauty is his say about God’s creation to man-made creation.
concern for emphasizing the intuitiveness of the manner through which hu- Von Hildebrand elaborates his conception of the experience of
mans experience beauty. His work Aesthetics especially bears out this claim. beauty as relying primarily on our non-rational faculties in his monograph
While elaborating on the function of beauty as a central source of human “Beauty in the Light of the Redemption.” In this monograph, von Hildeb-
happiness, von Hildebrand turns to Arcadian scenes for elucidation of his rand first distinguishes beauty of form from metaphysical beauty. Second,
argument: he defends beauty of form from a utilitarian devaluation. He then refutes
an attack on beauty of form which contends that the sensory faculties are
The role of beauty for human happiness is not restricted to those
unspiritual powers used by those less advanced in virtue. At this juncture he
moments in which one is consciously looking at beautiful things.
criticizes philosophical endeavors to salvage the noble intangibility of beauty
Beauty is active even at those times when one’s attention is wholly
of form by severing the connection between beauty of form and the senses
directed to other things. The beauty of the environment in which
of seeing and hearing:
one lives—one’s house, even if it is very simple, like the farm-
houses of Tuscany; the view from one’s house, both near and far; If, for example, we view a lofty mountain range bathed in gleam-
the architectural beauty of the neighboring houses; the beauty ing sunlight, it is not that which we see directly before us to which
of the sun that shines into the house, and of the shadow cast beauty is attached, but the thought of God’s creative power is
by a tree—all this nourishes the soul even of the simplest man, the real beauty. In a word, the real bearer of beauty is something
entering into his pores even when he is not concentrating on it.22 incorporeal which we connect intellectually with the visible and
audible by means of analogies…. This attempt at rescuing the
The phrase “consciously looking” and the clause “one’s attention is wholly
incorporeality of beauty is well-meant, to be sure, but it is false,
directed to other things” should be read as descriptions of the use of the
for the beauty of the Campagna Romana or that of the Seventh
rational faculty. This passage places the experience of beauty beyond our rea-
Symphony by Bruckner is intuitive, linked directly with that which
soning faculty. Von Hildebrand points out that even when our consciousness
21
John McGuckin, “On the Mystical Theology of the Eastern Church,” St.
Vladimir’s Theological Quarterly 59, no. 1, (2015): 392–93.
22
Dietrich von Hildebrand, “The Place of Beauty in Human Existence,” in
Aesthetics (Dietrich von Hildebrand Legacy Project, forthcoming). 23
Ibid.
118 Dietrich von Hildebrand as Ambassador Daniel VanderKolk 119
is seen and heard, and no intellectual ascent to something else is of form is somehow both reliant upon our sense of seeing and our sense
necessary to grasp this beauty.24 of hearing, yet entirely transcends our sensory life. Von Hildebrand, inso-
This passage reveals von Hildebrand’s intense conviction that the theological far as he theologizes about aesthetics in these passages, does not fit the old
contemplation of beauty of form is a non-discursive action with a strong stereotype, often propagated in contemporary Eastern Orthodox circles, of
quality of immediacy. In contemporary Eastern Orthodox theological termi- the overly rational Roman Catholic Scholastic. On the contrary, the Eastern
nology, von Hildebrand’s allusion to an intuitive faculty would closely match Orthodox find a kindred soul.
the term nous (the spiritual intellect), not for the divine communicatory prop-
erty of the nous so much as its immediate, intuitive property. Many Eastern
Orthodox theologians present Roman Catholic theology in an overly-rational Conclusion
light; they might expect von Hildebrand to ascribe theological contemplation
of beauty to the discursive intellect. Yet von Hildebrand holds what might be The real differences separating Eastern Orthodoxy from Roman Catholicism
called an “Eastern Orthodox” or “noetic” reading of this contemplative act. should not be underestimated. Nevertheless, each Christian body must speak
He ascribes carrying out a contemplative act to an intuitive part of the soul. truthfully of the other with a spirit of charity. All too often intra-Christian
His statement may even be described as Philokalic and apophatic: philokalic dialogue halts at the level of traditional biases and unexamined generaliza-
in the sense that it is noetic, and apophatic in the sense that it shuns discur- tions. This paper has endeavored to unpack one such misconception. Fyodor
siveness for intuitiveness. Dostoyevsky, and many other recent Eastern Orthodox intellectuals, held
A profound sense of mystery also occupies von Hildebrand’s eval- the West, in general, and the Roman Catholic Church, in particular, to be in
uation of beauty of form. Continuing where the previous quotation left off, captivity to reason, with little sense of mystery. Dietrich von Hildebrand, in
von Hildebrand writes: at least one significant portion of his thought, breaks this stale stereotype.
He displays, in keeping with the theology of The Philokalia (the work so trea-
We must not try to evade the mysteries in reality, but in a com- sured by Dostoyevsky’s beloved elders), an apophatic, noetic conception of
plete thaumazein at the mystery, we must try to understand it by the encounter with beauty. Beauty will indeed save the world, provided that
means of a deeper penetration. This higher beauty of form is also it is bound to truth, goodness, and love. The words of Macarius, Elder of
bestowed directly and intuitively by means of the visible and the Optina Monastery, written in the middle of the nineteenth century, directed
audible, and in spite of its connection with the senses, it is of a to an anonymous Russian who had converted back to the Eastern Orthodoxy
spiritual sublimity which qualitatively completely transcends the of his or her youth after many years as a Lutheran, are appropriate to all
sphere of the senses.25 Christians regardless of their confession. Macarius, counseling Anonymous’s
The phrase “evade the mysteries of reality” should be read as “misperceive disturbance when contemplating the fate of those outside of his or her con-
an enigma in our attempt to rationally define it.” This ready admission of the fession, writes:
presence of supra-rational qualities in reality is entirely in line with the East- We cannot and must not judge them. The ways of the Lord are
ern Orthodox emphasis on negative theology, on apophaticism. Noteworthy inscrutable; let us leave these good people entirely to His judg-
too is von Hildebrand’s phrase “by means of a deeper penetration” after the ment and to the grace of His Providence. He alone knows how
conjunction “but”; it implies that this intuitive faculty which understands the and why He has built the argosy of humanity, and the small boat
mystery of beauty is, because it fathoms more completely, a higher power of each one of us, such as it is.26
of the soul. Again, in Eastern manner, von Hildebrand locates the intuitive
faculty above the rational. Furthermore, in keeping with the modern East-
ern Orthodox emphasis on the deep paradoxes inherent within Christianity —St.Vladimir’s Orthodox Theological Seminary
(which can be interpreted as an extension of their apophatic tendency), von
Hildebrand states a paradox at the end of this passage. He claims that beauty
Dietrich von Hildebrand, “Reconsiderations: Beauty in the Light of the
24

Redemption,” Logos 4, no. 2 (2001): 86. 26


Starets Macarius of Optina, Russian Letters of Spiritual Direction, 1834–1860,
25
Ibid., 86–87. trans. Iulia de Beausobre (Yonkers: St. Vladimir’s Seminary Press, 1975), 54.
118 Dietrich von Hildebrand as Ambassador Daniel VanderKolk 119
is seen and heard, and no intellectual ascent to something else is of form is somehow both reliant upon our sense of seeing and our sense
necessary to grasp this beauty.24 of hearing, yet entirely transcends our sensory life. Von Hildebrand, inso-
This passage reveals von Hildebrand’s intense conviction that the theological far as he theologizes about aesthetics in these passages, does not fit the old
contemplation of beauty of form is a non-discursive action with a strong stereotype, often propagated in contemporary Eastern Orthodox circles, of
quality of immediacy. In contemporary Eastern Orthodox theological termi- the overly rational Roman Catholic Scholastic. On the contrary, the Eastern
nology, von Hildebrand’s allusion to an intuitive faculty would closely match Orthodox find a kindred soul.
the term nous (the spiritual intellect), not for the divine communicatory prop-
erty of the nous so much as its immediate, intuitive property. Many Eastern
Orthodox theologians present Roman Catholic theology in an overly-rational Conclusion
light; they might expect von Hildebrand to ascribe theological contemplation
of beauty to the discursive intellect. Yet von Hildebrand holds what might be The real differences separating Eastern Orthodoxy from Roman Catholicism
called an “Eastern Orthodox” or “noetic” reading of this contemplative act. should not be underestimated. Nevertheless, each Christian body must speak
He ascribes carrying out a contemplative act to an intuitive part of the soul. truthfully of the other with a spirit of charity. All too often intra-Christian
His statement may even be described as Philokalic and apophatic: philokalic dialogue halts at the level of traditional biases and unexamined generaliza-
in the sense that it is noetic, and apophatic in the sense that it shuns discur- tions. This paper has endeavored to unpack one such misconception. Fyodor
siveness for intuitiveness. Dostoyevsky, and many other recent Eastern Orthodox intellectuals, held
A profound sense of mystery also occupies von Hildebrand’s eval- the West, in general, and the Roman Catholic Church, in particular, to be in
uation of beauty of form. Continuing where the previous quotation left off, captivity to reason, with little sense of mystery. Dietrich von Hildebrand, in
von Hildebrand writes: at least one significant portion of his thought, breaks this stale stereotype.
He displays, in keeping with the theology of The Philokalia (the work so trea-
We must not try to evade the mysteries in reality, but in a com- sured by Dostoyevsky’s beloved elders), an apophatic, noetic conception of
plete thaumazein at the mystery, we must try to understand it by the encounter with beauty. Beauty will indeed save the world, provided that
means of a deeper penetration. This higher beauty of form is also it is bound to truth, goodness, and love. The words of Macarius, Elder of
bestowed directly and intuitively by means of the visible and the Optina Monastery, written in the middle of the nineteenth century, directed
audible, and in spite of its connection with the senses, it is of a to an anonymous Russian who had converted back to the Eastern Orthodoxy
spiritual sublimity which qualitatively completely transcends the of his or her youth after many years as a Lutheran, are appropriate to all
sphere of the senses.25 Christians regardless of their confession. Macarius, counseling Anonymous’s
The phrase “evade the mysteries of reality” should be read as “misperceive disturbance when contemplating the fate of those outside of his or her con-
an enigma in our attempt to rationally define it.” This ready admission of the fession, writes:
presence of supra-rational qualities in reality is entirely in line with the East- We cannot and must not judge them. The ways of the Lord are
ern Orthodox emphasis on negative theology, on apophaticism. Noteworthy inscrutable; let us leave these good people entirely to His judg-
too is von Hildebrand’s phrase “by means of a deeper penetration” after the ment and to the grace of His Providence. He alone knows how
conjunction “but”; it implies that this intuitive faculty which understands the and why He has built the argosy of humanity, and the small boat
mystery of beauty is, because it fathoms more completely, a higher power of each one of us, such as it is.26
of the soul. Again, in Eastern manner, von Hildebrand locates the intuitive
faculty above the rational. Furthermore, in keeping with the modern East-
ern Orthodox emphasis on the deep paradoxes inherent within Christianity —St.Vladimir’s Orthodox Theological Seminary
(which can be interpreted as an extension of their apophatic tendency), von
Hildebrand states a paradox at the end of this passage. He claims that beauty
Dietrich von Hildebrand, “Reconsiderations: Beauty in the Light of the
24

Redemption,” Logos 4, no. 2 (2001): 86. 26


Starets Macarius of Optina, Russian Letters of Spiritual Direction, 1834–1860,
25
Ibid., 86–87. trans. Iulia de Beausobre (Yonkers: St. Vladimir’s Seminary Press, 1975), 54.
Richard Sherlock 121

The Beauty of Marital Love have a contradiction. In this very phrase, we are said to behold beauty. That
is, beauty is something outside of the person who beholds the beautiful. The
in the Thought of Saint John Paul II observer “beholds” the majesty of redwoods, the intricate design of the Taj
Mahal, or the complex structure of Mahler’s Third Symphony. These are
instances of beauty in nature, architecture, and music that we “behold” as
Richard Sherlock outside of ourselves.
Thus, even on a first “look,” we do not define beauty. We behold it.
Saint John Paul II is one of the two greatest Catholic realist phenomenol- Beauty appears to us, it is not in us. In the words of Roger Scruton, beauty
ogists of the twentieth century. While we rightly revere his papacy and its “demands an active attention.” When we recognize someone or something
magisterial works (e.g., Fides et Ratio, Veritatis Splendor, Theology of the Body and as beautiful we are recognizing a quality or qualities of the object of our at-
above all the new Catechism), we should remember that his pre-papal years tention. We are pointing to what we experience.4
were spent as a professor of philosophy at the Catholic University of Lu- Beauty can and should be distinguished both from what it definitely
blin. His important works of this period—Love and Responsibility,1 The Acting is not (e.g., kitsch or titillation) and from what it may potentially be (e.g., the
Person,2 and many powerful essays—are realist phenomenology at its best. enjoyable, the interesting, and the pleasurable). That which is beautiful may
One of his most important contributions is his rich understanding of marital be enjoyable, pleasurable, or interesting. But, for example, things that are
love. Like Dietrich von Hildebrand, the other phenomenological thinker of enjoyable, such as a roller coaster ride, are not always regarded as beautiful.
his stature, Saint John Paul II employs the tools of a realist and personalist I attend to something that is beautiful because it has the quality of
phenomenology of the marital embrace to reach the traditional moral con- beauty. My attentiveness is focused on its beauty. Beauty has an attraction
clusions—for instance, about the nature of the human person, the problem that is different than being charming, pretty, or intricate.
of contraception, and the meaning of marriage—in a more attractive and A person is beautiful not because he or she is “good looking”; rath-
powerful manner than the sometimes sterile manuals of the past. In what er, a person is recognized as beautiful because of who he or she is in the
follows I shall use sections of Theology of the Body3 as well as his pre-papal fullest sense. Beauty draws us toward a whole person, who is more than a
work since these sections contain philosophy as such, rather than theology, look. We behold a whole person, not just his or her appearance. We are also
and can therefore stand on their own. In this paper, I present Saint John Paul drawn to this person as beautiful, as who he or she is. A beautiful person is
II’s understanding of the beauty of marital love and suggest some fruitful not merely a representative of a group, or what we might call a token (e.g.,
avenues for further research. Miss America or Mr. Universe). Provisionally, as a first step, we might say that
beauty represents the completeness of the object, person, relation, or scene
that is beheld as beautiful. The completeness comes from the way in which
Elements of Beauty parts fit together in harmony to create a whole greater than the sum of the
parts.
It is often said that beauty is in the eye of the beholder. This is often under- In my view this fittingness is not reducible to a tidy definition. Ex-
stood in a way that denies the language of the statement itself. Of course we perience never is. This is why phenomenological inquiry is such a fruitful
apprehend beauty, so beauty must be in our “eyes,” broadly construed. If it way to examine human experience. It is a method of showing, as distinguished
is further claimed that beauty is defined by the look of the looker, then we from telling. At the beginning of Western philosophy, Plato used this show-
ing method to make this point. His main character, Socrates, never makes a
1
Karol Wojtyla, Love and Responsibility (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1981). discursive argument as modern philosophers, with the exception of Witt-
This is the first English translation of a work originally published in Polish in 1960. genstein, are wont to do. It is also found in philosophers who sometimes
2
Karol Wojtyla, The Acting Person, trans. Andrzei Potocki (Dordrecht, Hol- use a showing method (e.g., Augustine’s dialogue with Evodius on free will;
land: D. Reidel, 1979). Anselm’s dialogue with Boso, Cur Deus Homo; Machiavelli’s Florentine Histo-
3
Saint John Paul II, Man and Woman He Created Them: A Theology Of The Body,
ry, Berkeley’s Three Dialogues; and Hume’s History of England). For example,
trans. Michael Waldstein (Boston: Pauline Books, 2006).
© Richard Sherlock, Quaestiones Disputatae, Vol. 6, No. 2 (Spring 2016) 4
Roger Scruton, Beauty (London: Oxford University Press, 2009).
Richard Sherlock 121

The Beauty of Marital Love have a contradiction. In this very phrase, we are said to behold beauty. That
is, beauty is something outside of the person who beholds the beautiful. The
in the Thought of Saint John Paul II observer “beholds” the majesty of redwoods, the intricate design of the Taj
Mahal, or the complex structure of Mahler’s Third Symphony. These are
instances of beauty in nature, architecture, and music that we “behold” as
Richard Sherlock outside of ourselves.
Thus, even on a first “look,” we do not define beauty. We behold it.
Saint John Paul II is one of the two greatest Catholic realist phenomenol- Beauty appears to us, it is not in us. In the words of Roger Scruton, beauty
ogists of the twentieth century. While we rightly revere his papacy and its “demands an active attention.” When we recognize someone or something
magisterial works (e.g., Fides et Ratio, Veritatis Splendor, Theology of the Body and as beautiful we are recognizing a quality or qualities of the object of our at-
above all the new Catechism), we should remember that his pre-papal years tention. We are pointing to what we experience.4
were spent as a professor of philosophy at the Catholic University of Lu- Beauty can and should be distinguished both from what it definitely
blin. His important works of this period—Love and Responsibility,1 The Acting is not (e.g., kitsch or titillation) and from what it may potentially be (e.g., the
Person,2 and many powerful essays—are realist phenomenology at its best. enjoyable, the interesting, and the pleasurable). That which is beautiful may
One of his most important contributions is his rich understanding of marital be enjoyable, pleasurable, or interesting. But, for example, things that are
love. Like Dietrich von Hildebrand, the other phenomenological thinker of enjoyable, such as a roller coaster ride, are not always regarded as beautiful.
his stature, Saint John Paul II employs the tools of a realist and personalist I attend to something that is beautiful because it has the quality of
phenomenology of the marital embrace to reach the traditional moral con- beauty. My attentiveness is focused on its beauty. Beauty has an attraction
clusions—for instance, about the nature of the human person, the problem that is different than being charming, pretty, or intricate.
of contraception, and the meaning of marriage—in a more attractive and A person is beautiful not because he or she is “good looking”; rath-
powerful manner than the sometimes sterile manuals of the past. In what er, a person is recognized as beautiful because of who he or she is in the
follows I shall use sections of Theology of the Body3 as well as his pre-papal fullest sense. Beauty draws us toward a whole person, who is more than a
work since these sections contain philosophy as such, rather than theology, look. We behold a whole person, not just his or her appearance. We are also
and can therefore stand on their own. In this paper, I present Saint John Paul drawn to this person as beautiful, as who he or she is. A beautiful person is
II’s understanding of the beauty of marital love and suggest some fruitful not merely a representative of a group, or what we might call a token (e.g.,
avenues for further research. Miss America or Mr. Universe). Provisionally, as a first step, we might say that
beauty represents the completeness of the object, person, relation, or scene
that is beheld as beautiful. The completeness comes from the way in which
Elements of Beauty parts fit together in harmony to create a whole greater than the sum of the
parts.
It is often said that beauty is in the eye of the beholder. This is often under- In my view this fittingness is not reducible to a tidy definition. Ex-
stood in a way that denies the language of the statement itself. Of course we perience never is. This is why phenomenological inquiry is such a fruitful
apprehend beauty, so beauty must be in our “eyes,” broadly construed. If it way to examine human experience. It is a method of showing, as distinguished
is further claimed that beauty is defined by the look of the looker, then we from telling. At the beginning of Western philosophy, Plato used this show-
ing method to make this point. His main character, Socrates, never makes a
1
Karol Wojtyla, Love and Responsibility (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1981). discursive argument as modern philosophers, with the exception of Witt-
This is the first English translation of a work originally published in Polish in 1960. genstein, are wont to do. It is also found in philosophers who sometimes
2
Karol Wojtyla, The Acting Person, trans. Andrzei Potocki (Dordrecht, Hol- use a showing method (e.g., Augustine’s dialogue with Evodius on free will;
land: D. Reidel, 1979). Anselm’s dialogue with Boso, Cur Deus Homo; Machiavelli’s Florentine Histo-
3
Saint John Paul II, Man and Woman He Created Them: A Theology Of The Body,
ry, Berkeley’s Three Dialogues; and Hume’s History of England). For example,
trans. Michael Waldstein (Boston: Pauline Books, 2006).
© Richard Sherlock, Quaestiones Disputatae, Vol. 6, No. 2 (Spring 2016) 4
Roger Scruton, Beauty (London: Oxford University Press, 2009).
122 The Beauty of Marital Love Richard Sherlock 123
Socrates did not tell Glaucon how unnatural a perfect community would be. beauty of Shakespeare is not in the memorable passages from Hamlet, Mac-
He simply shows him the community of wives. In the Symposium, when it is beth, Puck, or Mark Anthony, rather the beauty is beheld in the fullness of
Socrates turn to speak, he does not make his own argument. Rather, he gives the play Hamlet, Macbeth, Midsummer Night’s Dream, or Julius Caesar, respective-
the teaching he has heard from the semi­divine source, Diotima. This teaching ly. Notice that the fitting and thus beautiful soliloquy or operatic aria (e.g., by
is complicated by the fact that it is “delivered,” if we may use this phrase, by Don Giovanni) does not need to have a particularly good intent (e.g., Mark
analogies that direct the attention of the reader or hearer. Anthony’s “praise”). The play as a whole does and should point to the good.
What we can then do is show how the fitting works together with Yet there is something different in the beauty of music, opera, and
its context, analogically like the parts of a motor or the gears of a watch. If, Shakespeare from the beauty of Botticelli’s The Birth of Venus, The Pieta, Del-
instead of the chorus at the end of Beethoven’s Ninth Symphony, we heard icate Arch, or Rembrandt’s Isaac Blessing Jacob and Esau. Painting or sculpture
a couple of minutes of Errol Garner, the disjoint would be jarring. Simi- does not change. Nature changes very slowly. One could have seen a Rem-
larly, a dead animal hanging from a rope in the middle of Rainbow Arch in brandt two hundred years ago or yesterday and it would present the same
Southern Utah would not fit. In Picasso’s les Demoiselles D’Avignon, the women beauty. Delicate Arch is almost the same as it was a century ago. Only an
are presented in a jarring fashion and they appear unhappy. They should be. expert could mark the differences. Music, drama, and opera, however, are
They are prostitutes. This quality of the women is fitting for where they are different. Every time they are performed, the notes or the dialogue are the
and what they are doing. If the women were in business suits it would not same but the music and the performance is different. In a wonderful passage,
fit. When we see a frail eighty-year-old man holding the car door open for Saint Francis de Sales notes the complexity of music:
his equally aged wife we behold the beauty of marital love. The fittingness is For music to be beautiful the voices not only must be true, clear,
obvious. and distinct from one another but also united together in such a
Secondly, the beautiful draws us out of ourselves towards that which way that there may arise a just consonance and harmony which is
is beautiful. We behold or attend to that which is beautiful. Beauty pulls us not unfairly termed a discordant harmony or rather a harmonious
out of ourselves and beyond our materiality. The beautiful brings us an inti- discord.5
mation of transcendence which, following Saint Bonaventure’s Itinerarium, we
can recognize as a beginning of a journey to God. Music is a wonderful example of the unity and complexity of the beautiful.
Thus, we can say that the truly beautiful is in relation to that which Brunhilde’s aria before she throws herself on the pyre is sung differently
surrounds it. Brunhilde’s aria at the end of Gotterdamerung is set within the by Kirsten Flagstad and Fiorenza Cossotto—to name two great twentieth
opera itself, which opera is set within the context of Wagner’s ring cycle. century mezzo-sopranos. Beethoven’s “Eroica” is different when conducted
Delicate Arch fits its place in the world. It also draws us toward a source of by Solti, von Karajan, or Bernstein. A Chopin polonaise is played differently
beauty outside of us. Its beauty would be surely diminished if the arch were by Horowitz or Rubenstein. The notes are the same but the work is played
removed to a museum like a wall of an Egyptian tomb has been removed to differently.
a Metropolitan Museum in New York. This diversity in unity is seen even more in the case of human per-
Suppose, for example, in the middle of a manuscript of Purcell’s sons and their relationships. In a rich study from 1975, Saint John Paul II
Dido and Aeneas there was a saxophone solo reminiscent of the early John writes that the “action of persons reveals the wholeness, originality, and un-
Coltrane. We would doubt the authenticity of the manuscript for two rea- repeatability of each human being and discloses our own acting I, or self in
sons. First the discordance would be jarring. Secondly, the saxophone was a way different than self consciousness, in what might be called a more pro-
not created for another two centuries. found or ultimate way.”6 This action diverges with each person—as a subject
Thus, beauty is relational in two ways. First, the beautiful object—
the “out-there” person, natural object, art, or relation—is always related to
that context in which it is beheld as beautiful. Secondly, beauty is relational to
5
Saint Francis de Sales, Treatise on the Love of God, trans. Henry Mackey (New
those who behold it. York: Tan Books, 1997).
6
Karol Wojtyla, “Uczestnictwo Czy Aliencaja,” Summarium 7, no. 27 (1978):
Hearing just the second movement of Dvorak’s New World Symphony
7–16; Karol Wojtyla, “Participation or Alienation” Analecta Husserliana 6 (1977):
is hiding the light of the whole under a bushel. However beautiful “Nessun 61–73. This paper was sent in French translation to the Fourth International Phe-
Dorma” is alone, it loses part of its beauty when removed from Turandot. The nomenology Conference in Fribourg (January 24–28, 1975), and also presented by
122 The Beauty of Marital Love Richard Sherlock 123
Socrates did not tell Glaucon how unnatural a perfect community would be. beauty of Shakespeare is not in the memorable passages from Hamlet, Mac-
He simply shows him the community of wives. In the Symposium, when it is beth, Puck, or Mark Anthony, rather the beauty is beheld in the fullness of
Socrates turn to speak, he does not make his own argument. Rather, he gives the play Hamlet, Macbeth, Midsummer Night’s Dream, or Julius Caesar, respective-
the teaching he has heard from the semi­divine source, Diotima. This teaching ly. Notice that the fitting and thus beautiful soliloquy or operatic aria (e.g., by
is complicated by the fact that it is “delivered,” if we may use this phrase, by Don Giovanni) does not need to have a particularly good intent (e.g., Mark
analogies that direct the attention of the reader or hearer. Anthony’s “praise”). The play as a whole does and should point to the good.
What we can then do is show how the fitting works together with Yet there is something different in the beauty of music, opera, and
its context, analogically like the parts of a motor or the gears of a watch. If, Shakespeare from the beauty of Botticelli’s The Birth of Venus, The Pieta, Del-
instead of the chorus at the end of Beethoven’s Ninth Symphony, we heard icate Arch, or Rembrandt’s Isaac Blessing Jacob and Esau. Painting or sculpture
a couple of minutes of Errol Garner, the disjoint would be jarring. Simi- does not change. Nature changes very slowly. One could have seen a Rem-
larly, a dead animal hanging from a rope in the middle of Rainbow Arch in brandt two hundred years ago or yesterday and it would present the same
Southern Utah would not fit. In Picasso’s les Demoiselles D’Avignon, the women beauty. Delicate Arch is almost the same as it was a century ago. Only an
are presented in a jarring fashion and they appear unhappy. They should be. expert could mark the differences. Music, drama, and opera, however, are
They are prostitutes. This quality of the women is fitting for where they are different. Every time they are performed, the notes or the dialogue are the
and what they are doing. If the women were in business suits it would not same but the music and the performance is different. In a wonderful passage,
fit. When we see a frail eighty-year-old man holding the car door open for Saint Francis de Sales notes the complexity of music:
his equally aged wife we behold the beauty of marital love. The fittingness is For music to be beautiful the voices not only must be true, clear,
obvious. and distinct from one another but also united together in such a
Secondly, the beautiful draws us out of ourselves towards that which way that there may arise a just consonance and harmony which is
is beautiful. We behold or attend to that which is beautiful. Beauty pulls us not unfairly termed a discordant harmony or rather a harmonious
out of ourselves and beyond our materiality. The beautiful brings us an inti- discord.5
mation of transcendence which, following Saint Bonaventure’s Itinerarium, we
can recognize as a beginning of a journey to God. Music is a wonderful example of the unity and complexity of the beautiful.
Thus, we can say that the truly beautiful is in relation to that which Brunhilde’s aria before she throws herself on the pyre is sung differently
surrounds it. Brunhilde’s aria at the end of Gotterdamerung is set within the by Kirsten Flagstad and Fiorenza Cossotto—to name two great twentieth
opera itself, which opera is set within the context of Wagner’s ring cycle. century mezzo-sopranos. Beethoven’s “Eroica” is different when conducted
Delicate Arch fits its place in the world. It also draws us toward a source of by Solti, von Karajan, or Bernstein. A Chopin polonaise is played differently
beauty outside of us. Its beauty would be surely diminished if the arch were by Horowitz or Rubenstein. The notes are the same but the work is played
removed to a museum like a wall of an Egyptian tomb has been removed to differently.
a Metropolitan Museum in New York. This diversity in unity is seen even more in the case of human per-
Suppose, for example, in the middle of a manuscript of Purcell’s sons and their relationships. In a rich study from 1975, Saint John Paul II
Dido and Aeneas there was a saxophone solo reminiscent of the early John writes that the “action of persons reveals the wholeness, originality, and un-
Coltrane. We would doubt the authenticity of the manuscript for two rea- repeatability of each human being and discloses our own acting I, or self in
sons. First the discordance would be jarring. Secondly, the saxophone was a way different than self consciousness, in what might be called a more pro-
not created for another two centuries. found or ultimate way.”6 This action diverges with each person—as a subject
Thus, beauty is relational in two ways. First, the beautiful object—
the “out-there” person, natural object, art, or relation—is always related to
that context in which it is beheld as beautiful. Secondly, beauty is relational to
5
Saint Francis de Sales, Treatise on the Love of God, trans. Henry Mackey (New
those who behold it. York: Tan Books, 1997).
6
Karol Wojtyla, “Uczestnictwo Czy Aliencaja,” Summarium 7, no. 27 (1978):
Hearing just the second movement of Dvorak’s New World Symphony
7–16; Karol Wojtyla, “Participation or Alienation” Analecta Husserliana 6 (1977):
is hiding the light of the whole under a bushel. However beautiful “Nessun 61–73. This paper was sent in French translation to the Fourth International Phe-
Dorma” is alone, it loses part of its beauty when removed from Turandot. The nomenology Conference in Fribourg (January 24–28, 1975), and also presented by
124 The Beauty of Marital Love Richard Sherlock 125
with reason, will, and appetite—yet there is a common thread in each acting however, sufficient. For example, Hitler’s actions were perfectly suited to the
being. From The Acting Person we capture the same point: sort of person he was. Yet no one would refer to Hitler or his actions as
Although the disparity in the experience of man that we have beautiful.
been stressing here is an obstacle to the arrival at an interpreta- Beauty attracts us. The beautiful directs our gaze in every sense to
tion and conception of man, it does open new possibilities and that which is beyond us or, shall we say, that which transcends us. Beauty’s
wide vistas for investigation. On the ground of the integrated ex- attraction is found both in its fittingness and in its participation in the good.
perience of man…the person is revealed though action because That which is truly beautiful is both fitting and good. The structure and
in this experience man is given us from the inside and not only songs of West Side Story are fitting and good. They are not fitting in the mid-
outwardly. Just because he has given not as the man-subject but dle of Aida. Alfredo’s aria “un di felice eterea” is beautiful set in the first act
in his entire experiential subjectiveness as the ego, new possibil- of La Traviata. It would not be fitting in Guys and Dolls.
ities are opened for such an interpretation of man, which will at In the music of Palestrina we hear the fittingness of the parts as
the same time allow us to reproduce at the right proportions the in a Rolex watch. But in the words and music we are led or directed to the
subjectiveness of man.7 ultimate good, God. Seeing a painting of the crucifixion by, for example,
Giotto, Tintoretto, or Gruenwald we can see how all parts fit together: pro-
The final element of complexity comes from the fact—which Ar- portion, color, balance, artistic medium, etc. This fittingness is important.
istotle so memorably notes—that human beings are by nature social beings. What makes these paintings truly good is the manner in which they lead us
We act with and for or against others. As Saint John Paul II writes: “acting to think about the true good. A Turner watercolor or an Ansel Adams pho-
together with others is not only frequent and usual but indeed a universal oc- tograph of Yosemite likewise directs us to the good of nature and ultimately
currence.”8 In spite of this obvious fact, however, he is correct when he notes to the creator of this good, God.
that this relational nature of human persons “has not received the attention Thus we come to the third element of the beautiful. As Roger Scru-
it deserves.”9 Anglo-American philosophers tend to focus on those named A ton has so eloquently argued, beauty appears to the person who beholds it
and B, Smith and Jones, or John Doe and Jane Roe. These are abstractions, not as a product but as a gift. Of course the painter, architect, or composer
straw men and women stripped of the complexity of actual persons, not real created a specific instance of beauty. Though beauty is experienced in in-
persons. stances, it is not fully grasped in any one instance or collection of instances.
It is universally known that persons act in community as family As such, beauty transcends any specific instantiation. Instances or examples
members, friends, employees, teachers, and students. However, as Saint John point us to transcendence as such, to that which is pure beauty. These are the
Paul II notes, there is a normative element to the acts of a person. Persons “traces” left by the creator in creation.
act in company with others for that which they regard as good. That persons This is even true of art that, at first glance, only displays pain or evil.
are often wrong is granted. But persons do not willingly act for what they As we recognize pain and suffering, we can be repelled from the evil, which
regard as evil. As Aristotle argues at the beginning of his Nichomachean Ethics, may, in turn, be the first step toward the ultimate good. The rakishness of
all persons desire the good and act for what they believe is good. Mozart’s Don Giovanni repels us as a warning against sexual license. Wag-
The other, with whom we are related, is a good that we recognize ner’s Tristan and Isolde is a tragedy that we cannot fail to recognize as such.
that partially completes us. We desire this other person because this other fits But it also points to a love that is not itself tragic, even when found in tragic
together with what we are as a unique person, with many other relationships circumstances. Michelangelo’s The Last Judgment in the Sistine Chapel displays
to persons, objects, nature, and God. the worst evil that can befall a person, but also shows the ultimate good of
This observation, as old as Plato and Aristotle, directs us to the sec- those who are saved.
ond fundamental element of the beautiful. Fittingness is necessary. It is not, Thus we can see three elements of beauty that we can bring to bear
on the beauty of marital love with the help of Saint John Paul II. The first
invitation to the Philosophy Department at the University of Fribourg (February 27, element is that the beautiful is that which is fitting in two ways. The beautiful
1975).
fits together as whole, not an assemblage of parts. Further, this whole fits in
7
Wojtyla, The Acting Person, 18.
8
Wojtyla, The Acting Person, 261 its context or background. Secondly, the beautiful that we apprehend either
9
Ibid. should point itself to the good that it embodies, or point us toward the good
124 The Beauty of Marital Love Richard Sherlock 125
with reason, will, and appetite—yet there is a common thread in each acting however, sufficient. For example, Hitler’s actions were perfectly suited to the
being. From The Acting Person we capture the same point: sort of person he was. Yet no one would refer to Hitler or his actions as
Although the disparity in the experience of man that we have beautiful.
been stressing here is an obstacle to the arrival at an interpreta- Beauty attracts us. The beautiful directs our gaze in every sense to
tion and conception of man, it does open new possibilities and that which is beyond us or, shall we say, that which transcends us. Beauty’s
wide vistas for investigation. On the ground of the integrated ex- attraction is found both in its fittingness and in its participation in the good.
perience of man…the person is revealed though action because That which is truly beautiful is both fitting and good. The structure and
in this experience man is given us from the inside and not only songs of West Side Story are fitting and good. They are not fitting in the mid-
outwardly. Just because he has given not as the man-subject but dle of Aida. Alfredo’s aria “un di felice eterea” is beautiful set in the first act
in his entire experiential subjectiveness as the ego, new possibil- of La Traviata. It would not be fitting in Guys and Dolls.
ities are opened for such an interpretation of man, which will at In the music of Palestrina we hear the fittingness of the parts as
the same time allow us to reproduce at the right proportions the in a Rolex watch. But in the words and music we are led or directed to the
subjectiveness of man.7 ultimate good, God. Seeing a painting of the crucifixion by, for example,
Giotto, Tintoretto, or Gruenwald we can see how all parts fit together: pro-
The final element of complexity comes from the fact—which Ar- portion, color, balance, artistic medium, etc. This fittingness is important.
istotle so memorably notes—that human beings are by nature social beings. What makes these paintings truly good is the manner in which they lead us
We act with and for or against others. As Saint John Paul II writes: “acting to think about the true good. A Turner watercolor or an Ansel Adams pho-
together with others is not only frequent and usual but indeed a universal oc- tograph of Yosemite likewise directs us to the good of nature and ultimately
currence.”8 In spite of this obvious fact, however, he is correct when he notes to the creator of this good, God.
that this relational nature of human persons “has not received the attention Thus we come to the third element of the beautiful. As Roger Scru-
it deserves.”9 Anglo-American philosophers tend to focus on those named A ton has so eloquently argued, beauty appears to the person who beholds it
and B, Smith and Jones, or John Doe and Jane Roe. These are abstractions, not as a product but as a gift. Of course the painter, architect, or composer
straw men and women stripped of the complexity of actual persons, not real created a specific instance of beauty. Though beauty is experienced in in-
persons. stances, it is not fully grasped in any one instance or collection of instances.
It is universally known that persons act in community as family As such, beauty transcends any specific instantiation. Instances or examples
members, friends, employees, teachers, and students. However, as Saint John point us to transcendence as such, to that which is pure beauty. These are the
Paul II notes, there is a normative element to the acts of a person. Persons “traces” left by the creator in creation.
act in company with others for that which they regard as good. That persons This is even true of art that, at first glance, only displays pain or evil.
are often wrong is granted. But persons do not willingly act for what they As we recognize pain and suffering, we can be repelled from the evil, which
regard as evil. As Aristotle argues at the beginning of his Nichomachean Ethics, may, in turn, be the first step toward the ultimate good. The rakishness of
all persons desire the good and act for what they believe is good. Mozart’s Don Giovanni repels us as a warning against sexual license. Wag-
The other, with whom we are related, is a good that we recognize ner’s Tristan and Isolde is a tragedy that we cannot fail to recognize as such.
that partially completes us. We desire this other person because this other fits But it also points to a love that is not itself tragic, even when found in tragic
together with what we are as a unique person, with many other relationships circumstances. Michelangelo’s The Last Judgment in the Sistine Chapel displays
to persons, objects, nature, and God. the worst evil that can befall a person, but also shows the ultimate good of
This observation, as old as Plato and Aristotle, directs us to the sec- those who are saved.
ond fundamental element of the beautiful. Fittingness is necessary. It is not, Thus we can see three elements of beauty that we can bring to bear
on the beauty of marital love with the help of Saint John Paul II. The first
invitation to the Philosophy Department at the University of Fribourg (February 27, element is that the beautiful is that which is fitting in two ways. The beautiful
1975).
fits together as whole, not an assemblage of parts. Further, this whole fits in
7
Wojtyla, The Acting Person, 18.
8
Wojtyla, The Acting Person, 261 its context or background. Secondly, the beautiful that we apprehend either
9
Ibid. should point itself to the good that it embodies, or point us toward the good
126 The Beauty of Marital Love Richard Sherlock 127
by repelling us from evil. The grim reality of Manet’s The Execution of Emperor organizations (e.g., Rotary Club or a bowling league). Marriage, however, is
Maximillian repels us by its depiction of the brutality of the event and points more than an associational relationship; rather it is a complete giving of two
to the permanent truth of the impermanence of the goods of this world. selves to each other, not as Rotarians or golfers, but as full persons.
Finally, the beautiful, in leading us to experience the eternal in the instance, Saint John Paul II notes that this call to the married life is rooted in a
imperfectly illuminates the transcendence that is found in instances yet is prior fact of creation: “marriage is possible because God created them male
more than any instance. This is what Roger Scruton calls “the sense of the and female.”12 From this standpoint, sexual ethics is not just about marriage,
sacred” found in the beautiful.10 but concerns the whole range of relations between persons of the opposite
sex with different material bodies, psychological make-up, and spiritual tem-
peraments.13
The Beauty of Marriage To begin with, Saint John Paul II teaches that marriage is a special
relationship, a participation that is unique to human persons. God created us
Finally, we come to marriage, in a unique manner, as an exemplar of beauty. to be together as male and female, not alone. In marriage the male and the
Further, we will see how Saint John Paul II helps us understand this beauty. female unite in such a profound way that “the two become one flesh.” The
At the beginning of The Acting Person Saint John Paul II makes a fun- fittingness of marriage is both universal and unique. Marriage as an institu-
damental distinction between “associational relationships” and true “partici- tion is found in every known society. This is a truth of phenomenological
pation” with others. At work a person has an associational relationship with reason, historical reason, and revelation. Though taught in revelation, it does
a boss, coworkers and those he oversees. Friendliness is fitting. Demeaning not need revelation to justify it.
jokes are not. Actions that are fitting at work are not fitting when watching A true marriage, one whose beauty we can behold, is at first a bio-
and listening to a concert. In every associational relationship, some actions logical fittingness. Our bodies are created such that we physically fit together
are fitting and some are not. At a neighborhood party, getting to know your in intimacy. Furthermore, this fitting together is necessary for the continued
new neighbors is fitting; getting drunk is not. Associational relationships in- biological existence of humanity.
volve a person, to be sure, but they are focused on only one part of the This fitting together is a complementarity that is at first biological
person. Accordingly, only some actions are fitting. The nature of the associ- but is more than biological. It is an essential feature of human nature that is
ational relationship sets out the boundaries of the fitting. As Saint John Paul more than biological. On this point the social science data is overwhelming
notes, “we may live and act in common with others in various societies and and conclusive. Men and women are different in so many ways that it is diffi-
social groups,” yet participation “arises before us as a task.”11 cult to number them. This fact is reflected in two Biblical teachings. First, in
Participation involves a relation of the person as a subject that ful- Genesis, we read that God created human beings as men and women, “male
fills his or her humanity in the way that it was meant to be. As finite, em- and female he created them” (Gen. 1:27). Secondly, in Romans, we read that
bodied beings, our true completion as persons awaits eternity. Participation, God’s plan has been made evident in creation. “God’s invisible qualities…
however, points us in the right direction and starts us on the journey to full have been clearly seen, being understood from what has been made” (Rom.
completeness, not as workers, students, homeowners, or car drivers etc., but 1:20). Coming together in marriage, men and women complement each other
as persons who transcend any of our partial roles. Participation is a relation- in profound and lasting ways.
ship of the whole person, who is fuller and richer than merely the sum of the Again, music is our best analogy in another area universally admitted
associational roles he or she has. to be an exemplar of beauty. Consider Bach’s The Passion of Our Lord Accord-
Monastic life, for example, is a call to a special form of participation. ing to the Gospel of St. John. Each of the vocal parts, even each voice, must fit
This life involves a unique form of total self-giving. The more universal call with each the others and with the orchestra. Each instrument in the orchestra
to a full participatory relationship is the call to true married life. Marriage is must complement the others to produce the majestic beauty of the whole.
as complete and total a relationship as most human persons can have. We
have many associations as employers, employees, or members of clubs or
Saint John Paul II, A Theology of the Body, 136–40.
12

10
Roger Scruton, The Soul of the World (New York: Princeton University Press, Larry Arnhart, Darwinian Natural Right: The Biological Ethics of Human Nature,
13

2014). SUNY Series in Philosophy and Biology (New York: SUNY Press, 1998); Steven
11
Wojtyla, The Acting Person, 279. Rhoades, Taking Sex Differences Seriously (New York: Encounter Books, 2005).
126 The Beauty of Marital Love Richard Sherlock 127
by repelling us from evil. The grim reality of Manet’s The Execution of Emperor organizations (e.g., Rotary Club or a bowling league). Marriage, however, is
Maximillian repels us by its depiction of the brutality of the event and points more than an associational relationship; rather it is a complete giving of two
to the permanent truth of the impermanence of the goods of this world. selves to each other, not as Rotarians or golfers, but as full persons.
Finally, the beautiful, in leading us to experience the eternal in the instance, Saint John Paul II notes that this call to the married life is rooted in a
imperfectly illuminates the transcendence that is found in instances yet is prior fact of creation: “marriage is possible because God created them male
more than any instance. This is what Roger Scruton calls “the sense of the and female.”12 From this standpoint, sexual ethics is not just about marriage,
sacred” found in the beautiful.10 but concerns the whole range of relations between persons of the opposite
sex with different material bodies, psychological make-up, and spiritual tem-
peraments.13
The Beauty of Marriage To begin with, Saint John Paul II teaches that marriage is a special
relationship, a participation that is unique to human persons. God created us
Finally, we come to marriage, in a unique manner, as an exemplar of beauty. to be together as male and female, not alone. In marriage the male and the
Further, we will see how Saint John Paul II helps us understand this beauty. female unite in such a profound way that “the two become one flesh.” The
At the beginning of The Acting Person Saint John Paul II makes a fun- fittingness of marriage is both universal and unique. Marriage as an institu-
damental distinction between “associational relationships” and true “partici- tion is found in every known society. This is a truth of phenomenological
pation” with others. At work a person has an associational relationship with reason, historical reason, and revelation. Though taught in revelation, it does
a boss, coworkers and those he oversees. Friendliness is fitting. Demeaning not need revelation to justify it.
jokes are not. Actions that are fitting at work are not fitting when watching A true marriage, one whose beauty we can behold, is at first a bio-
and listening to a concert. In every associational relationship, some actions logical fittingness. Our bodies are created such that we physically fit together
are fitting and some are not. At a neighborhood party, getting to know your in intimacy. Furthermore, this fitting together is necessary for the continued
new neighbors is fitting; getting drunk is not. Associational relationships in- biological existence of humanity.
volve a person, to be sure, but they are focused on only one part of the This fitting together is a complementarity that is at first biological
person. Accordingly, only some actions are fitting. The nature of the associ- but is more than biological. It is an essential feature of human nature that is
ational relationship sets out the boundaries of the fitting. As Saint John Paul more than biological. On this point the social science data is overwhelming
notes, “we may live and act in common with others in various societies and and conclusive. Men and women are different in so many ways that it is diffi-
social groups,” yet participation “arises before us as a task.”11 cult to number them. This fact is reflected in two Biblical teachings. First, in
Participation involves a relation of the person as a subject that ful- Genesis, we read that God created human beings as men and women, “male
fills his or her humanity in the way that it was meant to be. As finite, em- and female he created them” (Gen. 1:27). Secondly, in Romans, we read that
bodied beings, our true completion as persons awaits eternity. Participation, God’s plan has been made evident in creation. “God’s invisible qualities…
however, points us in the right direction and starts us on the journey to full have been clearly seen, being understood from what has been made” (Rom.
completeness, not as workers, students, homeowners, or car drivers etc., but 1:20). Coming together in marriage, men and women complement each other
as persons who transcend any of our partial roles. Participation is a relation- in profound and lasting ways.
ship of the whole person, who is fuller and richer than merely the sum of the Again, music is our best analogy in another area universally admitted
associational roles he or she has. to be an exemplar of beauty. Consider Bach’s The Passion of Our Lord Accord-
Monastic life, for example, is a call to a special form of participation. ing to the Gospel of St. John. Each of the vocal parts, even each voice, must fit
This life involves a unique form of total self-giving. The more universal call with each the others and with the orchestra. Each instrument in the orchestra
to a full participatory relationship is the call to true married life. Marriage is must complement the others to produce the majestic beauty of the whole.
as complete and total a relationship as most human persons can have. We
have many associations as employers, employees, or members of clubs or
Saint John Paul II, A Theology of the Body, 136–40.
12

10
Roger Scruton, The Soul of the World (New York: Princeton University Press, Larry Arnhart, Darwinian Natural Right: The Biological Ethics of Human Nature,
13

2014). SUNY Series in Philosophy and Biology (New York: SUNY Press, 1998); Steven
11
Wojtyla, The Acting Person, 279. Rhoades, Taking Sex Differences Seriously (New York: Encounter Books, 2005).
128 The Beauty of Marital Love Richard Sherlock 129
School teachers of music used to emphasize this point by playing cannot involve a biological family; such a marriage, however, can still exem-
recordings of well-known songs with one small part missing (e.g., the oboe). plify beauty.
Though beginning music students did not realize how important that part The second stage of universal fittingness is again a fact that social
was, they immediately recognized that it was missing. Similarly in marriage: scientists can demonstrate and a phenomenology of the human person can
the beauty of the whole only appears when each part plays its complementa- more fully reveal. Men and women are psychologically different yet comple-
ry role. mentary. Men and women are morally, politically, and spiritually equal but
A second element of marriage is a core element of its beauty, name- they are not interchangeable. There is a psychological and social complemen-
ly, its permanence. Other forms of human male-female relationships are tarity that point to the truth that only male and female persons can become
not permanent, nor are most of them meant to be. Dating may lead to the “one flesh.”14
permanence of marriage. But as dating it is impermanent—the “one night Finally, there is a spiritual unity in diversity in marriage. Men and
stand” or “living together” is designed to be impermanent. Same-gendered women differ in the way they come to God. They can and do come to the
relationships may be termed “marriage” in civil society. Social science, how- same point, although their ways are different. This too is well documented,
ever, has shown that these relationships are far less permanent than male-fe- both empirically and phenomenologically.15
male marriages. Not every such “marriage” dissolves, but most do. At this In a universal sense then, marriage involves a complete giving of one
point the supposed divorce rate of fifty percent or more is typically advanced person to another in the threefold manner just noted. These are the fitting
as a critique of the idea that marriage is, or is thought to be, permanent by and complimentary ways in which we are created. Somewhat like the Trinity
those who get married. This is an instance of statistics being used in a very there is a threefold unity of persons who remain distinct.
misleading fashion. About two-thirds of first marriages remain “until death Yet in each beautiful marriage there is that which is uniquely fitting
do us part”; the fifty percnt or more figure comes from the fact that some for that marriage. The notes of every beautiful marriage may be broadly the
people get married several times. same. Each marriage, however, plays the notes differently. Of course, there is
Permanence is also a crucial feature of other forms of beauty. The a total giving of one person to another in intimacy, work, play, and faith. The
natural beauty of Bryce Canyon or Niagara Falls is as permanent as anything persons do not dissolve their individuality. They complete it. As a lifelong
can be in an ultimately impermanent world. El Greco’s The Trinity and da commitment, the beauty of marital love is renewed constantly. Like The Pieta,
Vinci’s The Virgin and Child With St. Anne are also permanent exemplars of it is permanent. Like Bach’s The Passion of our Lord According to the Gospel of St.
beauty. John, it changes each time it is played.
This same permanence is also found in music. Mozart’s Requiem Every true marriage is unique. This is a point that Saint John Paul II
Mass in D will be conducted differently by Szell or Ozawa. Mahler’s Third makes repeatedly. In The Theology of the Body, for instance, he writes:
Symphony will sound slightly differently with Zubin Mehta or Maurice They reveal themselves to one another with that specific depth
Abravanel at the helm. Palestrina’s Pope Marcellus Mass will also be heard of their own human “I” which precisely reveals through their
differently with different singers. Nevertheless, the beauty is rooted in the sex, their masculinity and their femininity. And thus in a singu-
composition that remains, no matter who is singing, playing or conducting. lar way the woman “is given” in the mode of knowledge to the
Friendship, a relationship that is extolled in ancient thought (e.g., Aristotle’s man and he to her.16
Nichomachean Ethics) and by medieval thinkers (e.g., Saint Aelred of Riveaux’s
On Spiritual Friendship—a restatement of Aristotle for Christian theology Marital love thus embodies the three elements of beauty we noted
which holds that in every true friendship there is a third, Christ) is at its best earlier. First, the married couple fits together as a unique whole that is greater
permanent. It is not, however, complementary. As Aristotle says, the friend is than the sum of the parts. The persons are still unique individuals. In the
a “second self.” self-giving love of the marital union the persons become a fuller and larger
Parenthood is, of course, a crucial telos of marriage. Parenthood, couple than they would be if they were only friends at work or play. As Saint
however, is more than merely being a sperm or egg donor. Parenthood 14
Saint John Paul II, A Theology of the Body, 479–80.
comes from marriage but does not define marriage. Married couples come 15
Marta Trzebiatowska and Steve Bruce, Why are Women More Religious than
before families. In some cases, because of age, illness or infertility, marriage Men (London: Oxford University, 2012).
16
Saint John Paul II, A Theology of the Body, 189.
128 The Beauty of Marital Love Richard Sherlock 129
School teachers of music used to emphasize this point by playing cannot involve a biological family; such a marriage, however, can still exem-
recordings of well-known songs with one small part missing (e.g., the oboe). plify beauty.
Though beginning music students did not realize how important that part The second stage of universal fittingness is again a fact that social
was, they immediately recognized that it was missing. Similarly in marriage: scientists can demonstrate and a phenomenology of the human person can
the beauty of the whole only appears when each part plays its complementa- more fully reveal. Men and women are psychologically different yet comple-
ry role. mentary. Men and women are morally, politically, and spiritually equal but
A second element of marriage is a core element of its beauty, name- they are not interchangeable. There is a psychological and social complemen-
ly, its permanence. Other forms of human male-female relationships are tarity that point to the truth that only male and female persons can become
not permanent, nor are most of them meant to be. Dating may lead to the “one flesh.”14
permanence of marriage. But as dating it is impermanent—the “one night Finally, there is a spiritual unity in diversity in marriage. Men and
stand” or “living together” is designed to be impermanent. Same-gendered women differ in the way they come to God. They can and do come to the
relationships may be termed “marriage” in civil society. Social science, how- same point, although their ways are different. This too is well documented,
ever, has shown that these relationships are far less permanent than male-fe- both empirically and phenomenologically.15
male marriages. Not every such “marriage” dissolves, but most do. At this In a universal sense then, marriage involves a complete giving of one
point the supposed divorce rate of fifty percent or more is typically advanced person to another in the threefold manner just noted. These are the fitting
as a critique of the idea that marriage is, or is thought to be, permanent by and complimentary ways in which we are created. Somewhat like the Trinity
those who get married. This is an instance of statistics being used in a very there is a threefold unity of persons who remain distinct.
misleading fashion. About two-thirds of first marriages remain “until death Yet in each beautiful marriage there is that which is uniquely fitting
do us part”; the fifty percnt or more figure comes from the fact that some for that marriage. The notes of every beautiful marriage may be broadly the
people get married several times. same. Each marriage, however, plays the notes differently. Of course, there is
Permanence is also a crucial feature of other forms of beauty. The a total giving of one person to another in intimacy, work, play, and faith. The
natural beauty of Bryce Canyon or Niagara Falls is as permanent as anything persons do not dissolve their individuality. They complete it. As a lifelong
can be in an ultimately impermanent world. El Greco’s The Trinity and da commitment, the beauty of marital love is renewed constantly. Like The Pieta,
Vinci’s The Virgin and Child With St. Anne are also permanent exemplars of it is permanent. Like Bach’s The Passion of our Lord According to the Gospel of St.
beauty. John, it changes each time it is played.
This same permanence is also found in music. Mozart’s Requiem Every true marriage is unique. This is a point that Saint John Paul II
Mass in D will be conducted differently by Szell or Ozawa. Mahler’s Third makes repeatedly. In The Theology of the Body, for instance, he writes:
Symphony will sound slightly differently with Zubin Mehta or Maurice They reveal themselves to one another with that specific depth
Abravanel at the helm. Palestrina’s Pope Marcellus Mass will also be heard of their own human “I” which precisely reveals through their
differently with different singers. Nevertheless, the beauty is rooted in the sex, their masculinity and their femininity. And thus in a singu-
composition that remains, no matter who is singing, playing or conducting. lar way the woman “is given” in the mode of knowledge to the
Friendship, a relationship that is extolled in ancient thought (e.g., Aristotle’s man and he to her.16
Nichomachean Ethics) and by medieval thinkers (e.g., Saint Aelred of Riveaux’s
On Spiritual Friendship—a restatement of Aristotle for Christian theology Marital love thus embodies the three elements of beauty we noted
which holds that in every true friendship there is a third, Christ) is at its best earlier. First, the married couple fits together as a unique whole that is greater
permanent. It is not, however, complementary. As Aristotle says, the friend is than the sum of the parts. The persons are still unique individuals. In the
a “second self.” self-giving love of the marital union the persons become a fuller and larger
Parenthood is, of course, a crucial telos of marriage. Parenthood, couple than they would be if they were only friends at work or play. As Saint
however, is more than merely being a sperm or egg donor. Parenthood 14
Saint John Paul II, A Theology of the Body, 479–80.
comes from marriage but does not define marriage. Married couples come 15
Marta Trzebiatowska and Steve Bruce, Why are Women More Religious than
before families. In some cases, because of age, illness or infertility, marriage Men (London: Oxford University, 2012).
16
Saint John Paul II, A Theology of the Body, 189.
130 The Beauty of Marital Love Richard Sherlock 131
John Paul II writes: “One can understand this ‘spousal’ meaning of the hu- transcendent” should be developed as another path from the temporal to
man body only in the context of the person. The body has a spousal meaning the transcendent, a natural theology of beauty. Finally, how might art that
because the human person…is a creature that God willed for his own sake presents a violent scene or a corrupt character (e.g., Iago in Verdi’s Othello)
and that, at the same time, cannot fully find himself, except through the gift nevertheless point us to the good?
of self.” Of course, he notes, that some may give themselves in celibacy for Much more work needs to be done on all of these questions. If
God. Yet this giving also shows that human persons find themselves most my argument has merit, I have shown that core elements of beauty taken
fully in a complete gift of self.17 from what are universally acknowledged as forms of beauty, nature, visual
Secondly, this unity of two persons points beyond itself to the good arts, music, and sculpture, can be analogically found in male-female marriage.
of human unity. It exemplifies the unity in difference that should be the goal Questions unique to marriage also follow. How does the beauty of marriage
of all human beings. Though more deeply than other relationships, marriage in its complementarity and permanence reflect an image of the complemen-
directs our attention to the broader truth of harmony and care for others tarity and permanence of the Trinity? Saint John Paul II has made this point
that we intuitively recognize as human goods. A wonderful example is Leon- explicitly in his Familiaris Consortio, but much more should be done to explore
ardo da Vinci’s 1510 masterpiece Virgin and Child With St. Anne. We recognize this. How do bad marriages, divorce, and imperfect non-marital relationships
immediately a relationship of love that is fully human yet profound. None of nevertheless point us to the truth, even in their untruth? These analyses of
the three have halos marking the divine. But the depth of a truly human good beauty itself and of marital beauty will take time and care in the future.
is obvious.
Finally, marital love is an intimation of the greatest of all possible —Utah State University
loves: God’s love for us. The sanctity of marriage can bring to us the “sense
of the sacred” that Scruton holds is part of the telos of art.
This beauty of marital love directs us to the eternal beauty, of the re-
lation between both God and persons and God and the Church. The Song of
Songs and Ephesians are central texts in this regard. The beauty of marital love
is found at its deepest level when the “two become one flesh.” In a similar
manner, God comes to us as one person, both fully divine and fully human.
This essay has only been a first sketch of bringing together a phil-
osophical understanding of beauty with the thought of Saint John Paul II
on marriage. Much more detailed studies need to be done. Theologically,
three questions are evident. First, how does the threefold structure of beauty
that we have suggested connect with the Trinity, perhaps as an image of the
Trinity in the world? Second, how might the unity in diversity of the married
couple be an image of God’s relation to the world as suggested in Ephesians?
Third, how might this same reality point to the unity and difference in the
Incarnation? Finally, how is this understanding of beauty connected with, or
distinct from, the work of Hans Urs von Balthasar, in whose work beauty is
a central concept?
Philosophically, in order to come to a richer understanding of beau-
ty in general, much more needs to be done in three areas. First, more needs
to be explored about the difference between the beauty found in music,
which changes every time it is played, and other arts, like painting, that do
not change. Secondly, the idea that true beauty embodies a “trace of the

17
Ibid.
130 The Beauty of Marital Love Richard Sherlock 131
John Paul II writes: “One can understand this ‘spousal’ meaning of the hu- transcendent” should be developed as another path from the temporal to
man body only in the context of the person. The body has a spousal meaning the transcendent, a natural theology of beauty. Finally, how might art that
because the human person…is a creature that God willed for his own sake presents a violent scene or a corrupt character (e.g., Iago in Verdi’s Othello)
and that, at the same time, cannot fully find himself, except through the gift nevertheless point us to the good?
of self.” Of course, he notes, that some may give themselves in celibacy for Much more work needs to be done on all of these questions. If
God. Yet this giving also shows that human persons find themselves most my argument has merit, I have shown that core elements of beauty taken
fully in a complete gift of self.17 from what are universally acknowledged as forms of beauty, nature, visual
Secondly, this unity of two persons points beyond itself to the good arts, music, and sculpture, can be analogically found in male-female marriage.
of human unity. It exemplifies the unity in difference that should be the goal Questions unique to marriage also follow. How does the beauty of marriage
of all human beings. Though more deeply than other relationships, marriage in its complementarity and permanence reflect an image of the complemen-
directs our attention to the broader truth of harmony and care for others tarity and permanence of the Trinity? Saint John Paul II has made this point
that we intuitively recognize as human goods. A wonderful example is Leon- explicitly in his Familiaris Consortio, but much more should be done to explore
ardo da Vinci’s 1510 masterpiece Virgin and Child With St. Anne. We recognize this. How do bad marriages, divorce, and imperfect non-marital relationships
immediately a relationship of love that is fully human yet profound. None of nevertheless point us to the truth, even in their untruth? These analyses of
the three have halos marking the divine. But the depth of a truly human good beauty itself and of marital beauty will take time and care in the future.
is obvious.
Finally, marital love is an intimation of the greatest of all possible —Utah State University
loves: God’s love for us. The sanctity of marriage can bring to us the “sense
of the sacred” that Scruton holds is part of the telos of art.
This beauty of marital love directs us to the eternal beauty, of the re-
lation between both God and persons and God and the Church. The Song of
Songs and Ephesians are central texts in this regard. The beauty of marital love
is found at its deepest level when the “two become one flesh.” In a similar
manner, God comes to us as one person, both fully divine and fully human.
This essay has only been a first sketch of bringing together a phil-
osophical understanding of beauty with the thought of Saint John Paul II
on marriage. Much more detailed studies need to be done. Theologically,
three questions are evident. First, how does the threefold structure of beauty
that we have suggested connect with the Trinity, perhaps as an image of the
Trinity in the world? Second, how might the unity in diversity of the married
couple be an image of God’s relation to the world as suggested in Ephesians?
Third, how might this same reality point to the unity and difference in the
Incarnation? Finally, how is this understanding of beauty connected with, or
distinct from, the work of Hans Urs von Balthasar, in whose work beauty is
a central concept?
Philosophically, in order to come to a richer understanding of beau-
ty in general, much more needs to be done in three areas. First, more needs
to be explored about the difference between the beauty found in music,
which changes every time it is played, and other arts, like painting, that do
not change. Secondly, the idea that true beauty embodies a “trace of the

17
Ibid.
Theresa Farnan 133

Beauty, the Person, and Disability: argument. Giubilini and Minerva argue specifically that killing is acceptable,
even justifiable, in the case of two particular disabilities involving distinctive,
Understanding (and Defending) sometimes disfiguring, physical and facial characteristics. While Giubilini and
Minerva avoid discussing whether an infant’s present or predicted appearance
the Intrinsic Beauty and Value may influence parents’ perception of the child’s value, the authors’ choice of
of the Person with Disabilities visible, distinctive disabilities seems designed to create the mental image of a
human being who is “other” and “less than” as a way to reinforce their claim
that these infants lack the moral status of personhood.3
Theresa Farnan I have two goals in this paper. First, I will follow the logic of Gi-
ubilini and Minerva’s argument and demonstrate that it leads to the absolute
In February 2012, the British Journal of Medical Ethics published a paper that affirmation of parent preference over the rights of the child, even after birth,
garnered notoriety for its central premise. In “After birth abortion: why regardless of the presence or absence of disability, and potentially on the
should the baby live?” authors Alberto Giubilini and Francesca Minerva ar- basis of appearance alone. Second, I will reflect on the way that disability
gue that infanticide as well as abortion should be legal in cases of babies born in human persons presents difficulties for our attempts to understand and
with disabilities.1 They focus on two disabilities—Treacher Collins syndrome define beauty. If we accept as given that beauty is related in a meaningful way
and Down syndrome—as instances where infanticide should be permitted. to goodness, and therefore perfection, then the visible, sometimes shocking,
Let me state at the outset that I absolutely reject their claim that physical imperfections that can be present in the disabled person would seem
unborn and newborn human beings lack the moral status of personhood, automatically to exclude him or her from being considered beautiful. And
as well as their abhorrent conclusion that it is acceptable to kill them.2 In yet, if beauty were related in a meaningful way to goodness, it would seem
this paper, however, I would like to focus on a more subtle aspect of their that persons with disabilities like Down syndrome, many of whom are cog-
nitively incapable of malice, should be considered among the most beautiful
1
Alberto Giubilini and Francesca Minerva, “After-birth abortion: why should human beings. The exclusion of these persons from the beautiful undercuts
the baby live?” Journal of Medical Ethics 39, no. 5 (2013): 261–63; first published Feb- the relationship of the beautiful with the good. Accordingly, in this paper, I
ruary 23, 2012, doi: 10.1136/medethics-2011-100411, accessed August 22, 2015, will argue that persons with disabilities challenge us to look more carefully at
http://jme.bmj.com/content/early/2012/03/01/medethics-2011-100411.full. the meaning of beauty in the human person.
2
A quick survey of responses to their paper reveals that many commenta- Moreover, the arguments by Giubilini and Minerva, as well as ar-
tors reject this argument. See for example, Jacqueline A. Laing, “Infanticide: A reply guments previously made by Peter Singer, are not merely academic; there
to Giubilini and Minerva” Journal of Medical Ethics 39, no. 5 (2013): 336–40, doi: are real consequences for persons with disabilities as well as for the rest of
10.1136/medethics-2012-100664; M. Beard and S. Lynch, “Personhood, harm, and
interest: A reply to Alberto Giubilini and Francesca Minerva,” Journal of Medical Eth- 3
Giubilini and Minerva echo Peter Singer’s argument that “the preference
ics 39, no. 5 (2013): e1–e4, doi: 10.1136/medethics-2012-100692, accessed August utilitarian reason for respecting the life of a person cannot apply to a newborn baby.
22, 2015, http://researchonline.nd.edu.au/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1023&con- Newborn babies cannot see themselves as beings that might or might not have a
text=phil_article. Some of the short responses to the article are quite compelling, future, and so they cannot have a desire to continue living. For the same reason, if a
including this reply by Josephine M. Treloar, a physician and mother of a child with right to life must be based on the capacity to want to go on living, or on the ability
trisomy 13, who observed “Professionals caring for mothers of babies with disabil- to see oneself as a continuing mental subject, a newborn baby cannot have a right to
ities must accept that there is another view, even if they do not understand it: that life. Finally a newborn baby is not an autonomous being, capable of making choices,
these babies can give and receive love. Your article reads like a court proceeding in and to kill a newborn baby cannot violate the principle of respect for autonomy. In
which all possible evidence against the baby living was taken into account, but there all this, the newborn baby is on the same footing as the fetus, and hence fewer rea-
was no advocate for the baby” (Josephine M. Treloar, “Where there is no love…,” sons exist against killing both babies and fetuses than exist against killing those who
response to Giubilini and Minerva, “After-birth abortion: why should the baby live?” are capable of seeing themselves as distinct entities existing over time” (Peter Singer,
published March 14, 2012, accessed August 22, 2015, http://jme.bmj.com/content/ Practical Ethics, 3rd ed. [New York: Cambridge University Press, 2011], 152). Singer
early/2012/03/01/medethics-2011-100411.short/reply#medethics_el_3870). concludes that the preference of the parents has sole weight in whether or not they
may be killed, even in cases where the disability is not life threatening and the infant
© Theresa Farnan, Quaestiones Disputatae, Vol. 6, No. 2 (Spring 2016)
probably will grow up to enjoy a happy life (Singer, Practical Ethics, 159–67).
Theresa Farnan 133

Beauty, the Person, and Disability: argument. Giubilini and Minerva argue specifically that killing is acceptable,
even justifiable, in the case of two particular disabilities involving distinctive,
Understanding (and Defending) sometimes disfiguring, physical and facial characteristics. While Giubilini and
Minerva avoid discussing whether an infant’s present or predicted appearance
the Intrinsic Beauty and Value may influence parents’ perception of the child’s value, the authors’ choice of
of the Person with Disabilities visible, distinctive disabilities seems designed to create the mental image of a
human being who is “other” and “less than” as a way to reinforce their claim
that these infants lack the moral status of personhood.3
Theresa Farnan I have two goals in this paper. First, I will follow the logic of Gi-
ubilini and Minerva’s argument and demonstrate that it leads to the absolute
In February 2012, the British Journal of Medical Ethics published a paper that affirmation of parent preference over the rights of the child, even after birth,
garnered notoriety for its central premise. In “After birth abortion: why regardless of the presence or absence of disability, and potentially on the
should the baby live?” authors Alberto Giubilini and Francesca Minerva ar- basis of appearance alone. Second, I will reflect on the way that disability
gue that infanticide as well as abortion should be legal in cases of babies born in human persons presents difficulties for our attempts to understand and
with disabilities.1 They focus on two disabilities—Treacher Collins syndrome define beauty. If we accept as given that beauty is related in a meaningful way
and Down syndrome—as instances where infanticide should be permitted. to goodness, and therefore perfection, then the visible, sometimes shocking,
Let me state at the outset that I absolutely reject their claim that physical imperfections that can be present in the disabled person would seem
unborn and newborn human beings lack the moral status of personhood, automatically to exclude him or her from being considered beautiful. And
as well as their abhorrent conclusion that it is acceptable to kill them.2 In yet, if beauty were related in a meaningful way to goodness, it would seem
this paper, however, I would like to focus on a more subtle aspect of their that persons with disabilities like Down syndrome, many of whom are cog-
nitively incapable of malice, should be considered among the most beautiful
1
Alberto Giubilini and Francesca Minerva, “After-birth abortion: why should human beings. The exclusion of these persons from the beautiful undercuts
the baby live?” Journal of Medical Ethics 39, no. 5 (2013): 261–63; first published Feb- the relationship of the beautiful with the good. Accordingly, in this paper, I
ruary 23, 2012, doi: 10.1136/medethics-2011-100411, accessed August 22, 2015, will argue that persons with disabilities challenge us to look more carefully at
http://jme.bmj.com/content/early/2012/03/01/medethics-2011-100411.full. the meaning of beauty in the human person.
2
A quick survey of responses to their paper reveals that many commenta- Moreover, the arguments by Giubilini and Minerva, as well as ar-
tors reject this argument. See for example, Jacqueline A. Laing, “Infanticide: A reply guments previously made by Peter Singer, are not merely academic; there
to Giubilini and Minerva” Journal of Medical Ethics 39, no. 5 (2013): 336–40, doi: are real consequences for persons with disabilities as well as for the rest of
10.1136/medethics-2012-100664; M. Beard and S. Lynch, “Personhood, harm, and
interest: A reply to Alberto Giubilini and Francesca Minerva,” Journal of Medical Eth- 3
Giubilini and Minerva echo Peter Singer’s argument that “the preference
ics 39, no. 5 (2013): e1–e4, doi: 10.1136/medethics-2012-100692, accessed August utilitarian reason for respecting the life of a person cannot apply to a newborn baby.
22, 2015, http://researchonline.nd.edu.au/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1023&con- Newborn babies cannot see themselves as beings that might or might not have a
text=phil_article. Some of the short responses to the article are quite compelling, future, and so they cannot have a desire to continue living. For the same reason, if a
including this reply by Josephine M. Treloar, a physician and mother of a child with right to life must be based on the capacity to want to go on living, or on the ability
trisomy 13, who observed “Professionals caring for mothers of babies with disabil- to see oneself as a continuing mental subject, a newborn baby cannot have a right to
ities must accept that there is another view, even if they do not understand it: that life. Finally a newborn baby is not an autonomous being, capable of making choices,
these babies can give and receive love. Your article reads like a court proceeding in and to kill a newborn baby cannot violate the principle of respect for autonomy. In
which all possible evidence against the baby living was taken into account, but there all this, the newborn baby is on the same footing as the fetus, and hence fewer rea-
was no advocate for the baby” (Josephine M. Treloar, “Where there is no love…,” sons exist against killing both babies and fetuses than exist against killing those who
response to Giubilini and Minerva, “After-birth abortion: why should the baby live?” are capable of seeing themselves as distinct entities existing over time” (Peter Singer,
published March 14, 2012, accessed August 22, 2015, http://jme.bmj.com/content/ Practical Ethics, 3rd ed. [New York: Cambridge University Press, 2011], 152). Singer
early/2012/03/01/medethics-2011-100411.short/reply#medethics_el_3870). concludes that the preference of the parents has sole weight in whether or not they
may be killed, even in cases where the disability is not life threatening and the infant
© Theresa Farnan, Quaestiones Disputatae, Vol. 6, No. 2 (Spring 2016)
probably will grow up to enjoy a happy life (Singer, Practical Ethics, 159–67).
134 Beauty, the Person, and Disability Theresa Farnan 135
society, since the premises these authors advance influence policy discussions Beauty as a stumbling block for acceptance
and the actual practice of medicine.4 With the advent of genetic testing, both
before and after birth, a person diagnosed with a disability, especially one that Imagine that you are an expectant or new mother or father who receives this
is disfiguring or aesthetically unappealing, is vulnerable to eugenic abortion description of your unborn child (Down syndrome): Your child will have “a
or infanticide in order to accommodate the parents’ desire for an attractive distinct facial appearance”—a small head with “flattened facial features,” a
or at least “normal looking” child. This is not, as it is so often presented, a protruding tongue, small, low-set ears and eyes slanting upward, to a degree
private choice. The acceptance of eugenic abortion and infanticide has grave that is “unusual for the child’s ethnic group.” He or she will have a shortened
implications for the society that tolerates or encourages such intentional kill- neck, “broad short hands with a single crease in the palm,” “relatively short
ing of innocent life.5 fingers and small hands and feet,” and “poor muscle tone.”6 He or she may
have “excess skin at the nape of the neck” and “separated joints between the
bones of the skull,” and his or her head may be “abnormally shaped.” “No
matter the severity of the condition,” your child will have this distinctive
4
In his justification for publishing this article, editor Julian Savulescu ac- appearance.7
knowledged that these arguments have already influenced medical protocols for in- Or suppose you are handed this description (Treacher Collins syn-
fanticide such as the Groningen Protocol in the Netherlands, and confirmed that the drome): Your child may “have underdeveloped facial bones, particularly
publication of “After Birth Abortion” marked the “extension of the existing debate the cheek bones, and a very small jaw and chin.” Your child may have “an
around infanticide from medical indications to social indications” (Savulescu,“Why opening in the roof of the mouth called a cleft palate” and “eyes that slant
Did the Journal Publish an Article Defending Infanticide?,” editorial justification to downward, sparse eyelashes, and a notch in the lower eyelids called an eyelid
publish Giubilini and Minerva, “After-birth abortion: why should the baby live?,” coloboma.” He or she may “have additional eye abnormalities that can lead
accessed August 30, 2015, http://jme.bmj.com/content/suppl/2012/03/01/mede-
to vision loss…and absent, small, or unusually formed ears.”8
thics-2011-100411.DC2/Savulescu_JME_defence_editorial.pdf).
In both of these cases, the expectant parents can readily access pic-
5
A recent article about preimplantation genetic diagnosis (PGD) noted some
of the ethical problems this causes, even for those who accept eugenic abortion tures of other children and adults with these syndromes. It is worth noting
as a means to eliminate genetic illnesses. “But the procedure also raises unsettling that published pictures and descriptions often highlight the distinctive fea-
ethical questions that trouble advocates for the disabled and have left some doctors tures that persons with these disabilities usually have, leading parents to focus
struggling with what they should tell their patients. When are prospective parents on how different their unborn baby’s appearance will be from typical babies.9
justified in discarding embryos? Is it acceptable, for example, for diseases like GSS Descriptions and pictures of these and other disabilities are so at odds with
(Gerstmann-Straussler-Scheinker disease), that develop in adulthood? What if a gene
only increases the risk of a disease? And should people be able to use it to pick
whether they have a boy or girl? A recent international survey found that 2 percent 6
Mayo clinic, Diseases and Conditions, s.v. “Down Syndrome,” accessed Novem-
of more than 27,000 uses of [PGD] were made to choose a child’s sex. In the United ber 22, 2014, http://www.mayoclinic.org/diseases-conditions/down-syndrome/ba-
States, there are no regulations that limit the method’s use. The Society for Assisted sics/symptoms/con-20020948.
Reproductive Technology, whose members provide [PGD], says it is ‘ethically jus- 7
ADAM Medical Encyclopedia (Medline Plus), s.v. “Down Syndrome,” accessed
tified’ to prevent serious adult diseases for which ‘no safe, effective interventions November 22, 2014, http://www.nlm.nih.gov/medlineplus/ency/article/000997.
are available.’ The method is ‘ethically allowed’ for conditions ‘of lesser severity’ htm.
or for which the gene increases risk but does not guarantee a disease” (Gina Ko- 8
Genetics Home Reference, s.v. “Treacher Collins Syndrome,” accessed Novem-
lata, “Ethics Questions Arise as Genetic Testing of Embryos Increases,” New York ber 22, 2014, http://ghr.nlm.nih.gov/condition/treacher-collins-syndrome.
Times, February 3, 2014, http://www.nytimes.com/2014/02/04/health/ethics-ques- 9
In the case of these two disabilities, the parents will also be told that there
tions-arise-as-genetic-testing-of-embryos-increases.html?_r=0). Even more trou- may be accompanying health difficulties. In the first case, Down syndrome, there will
bling, in this same article, some bioethicists argue that this kind of genetic screening be some degree of cognitive impairment, ranging from mild to severe, and there may
should be obligatory. “Janet Malek, a bioethicist at the Brody School of Medicine at be other health issues, most notably cardiac anomalies. In the second case, Treacher
East Carolina University, said that people who carry a gene like GSS have a moral Collins syndrome, there is likely no cognitive impairment, and the accompanying
duty to use [PGD]—if they can afford it—to spare the next generation. ‘If there is health issues, mild to severe, are directly related to the facial structure. However, at
a paradigm example in which a parent can have an obligation to use this technology, the time of the initial diagnosis, there is often no way to ascertain how severe these
this is it,’ she said” (ibid.). conditions will be. See articles referenced in footnotes 3, 4, and 5 above.
134 Beauty, the Person, and Disability Theresa Farnan 135
society, since the premises these authors advance influence policy discussions Beauty as a stumbling block for acceptance
and the actual practice of medicine.4 With the advent of genetic testing, both
before and after birth, a person diagnosed with a disability, especially one that Imagine that you are an expectant or new mother or father who receives this
is disfiguring or aesthetically unappealing, is vulnerable to eugenic abortion description of your unborn child (Down syndrome): Your child will have “a
or infanticide in order to accommodate the parents’ desire for an attractive distinct facial appearance”—a small head with “flattened facial features,” a
or at least “normal looking” child. This is not, as it is so often presented, a protruding tongue, small, low-set ears and eyes slanting upward, to a degree
private choice. The acceptance of eugenic abortion and infanticide has grave that is “unusual for the child’s ethnic group.” He or she will have a shortened
implications for the society that tolerates or encourages such intentional kill- neck, “broad short hands with a single crease in the palm,” “relatively short
ing of innocent life.5 fingers and small hands and feet,” and “poor muscle tone.”6 He or she may
have “excess skin at the nape of the neck” and “separated joints between the
bones of the skull,” and his or her head may be “abnormally shaped.” “No
matter the severity of the condition,” your child will have this distinctive
4
In his justification for publishing this article, editor Julian Savulescu ac- appearance.7
knowledged that these arguments have already influenced medical protocols for in- Or suppose you are handed this description (Treacher Collins syn-
fanticide such as the Groningen Protocol in the Netherlands, and confirmed that the drome): Your child may “have underdeveloped facial bones, particularly
publication of “After Birth Abortion” marked the “extension of the existing debate the cheek bones, and a very small jaw and chin.” Your child may have “an
around infanticide from medical indications to social indications” (Savulescu,“Why opening in the roof of the mouth called a cleft palate” and “eyes that slant
Did the Journal Publish an Article Defending Infanticide?,” editorial justification to downward, sparse eyelashes, and a notch in the lower eyelids called an eyelid
publish Giubilini and Minerva, “After-birth abortion: why should the baby live?,” coloboma.” He or she may “have additional eye abnormalities that can lead
accessed August 30, 2015, http://jme.bmj.com/content/suppl/2012/03/01/mede-
to vision loss…and absent, small, or unusually formed ears.”8
thics-2011-100411.DC2/Savulescu_JME_defence_editorial.pdf).
In both of these cases, the expectant parents can readily access pic-
5
A recent article about preimplantation genetic diagnosis (PGD) noted some
of the ethical problems this causes, even for those who accept eugenic abortion tures of other children and adults with these syndromes. It is worth noting
as a means to eliminate genetic illnesses. “But the procedure also raises unsettling that published pictures and descriptions often highlight the distinctive fea-
ethical questions that trouble advocates for the disabled and have left some doctors tures that persons with these disabilities usually have, leading parents to focus
struggling with what they should tell their patients. When are prospective parents on how different their unborn baby’s appearance will be from typical babies.9
justified in discarding embryos? Is it acceptable, for example, for diseases like GSS Descriptions and pictures of these and other disabilities are so at odds with
(Gerstmann-Straussler-Scheinker disease), that develop in adulthood? What if a gene
only increases the risk of a disease? And should people be able to use it to pick
whether they have a boy or girl? A recent international survey found that 2 percent 6
Mayo clinic, Diseases and Conditions, s.v. “Down Syndrome,” accessed Novem-
of more than 27,000 uses of [PGD] were made to choose a child’s sex. In the United ber 22, 2014, http://www.mayoclinic.org/diseases-conditions/down-syndrome/ba-
States, there are no regulations that limit the method’s use. The Society for Assisted sics/symptoms/con-20020948.
Reproductive Technology, whose members provide [PGD], says it is ‘ethically jus- 7
ADAM Medical Encyclopedia (Medline Plus), s.v. “Down Syndrome,” accessed
tified’ to prevent serious adult diseases for which ‘no safe, effective interventions November 22, 2014, http://www.nlm.nih.gov/medlineplus/ency/article/000997.
are available.’ The method is ‘ethically allowed’ for conditions ‘of lesser severity’ htm.
or for which the gene increases risk but does not guarantee a disease” (Gina Ko- 8
Genetics Home Reference, s.v. “Treacher Collins Syndrome,” accessed Novem-
lata, “Ethics Questions Arise as Genetic Testing of Embryos Increases,” New York ber 22, 2014, http://ghr.nlm.nih.gov/condition/treacher-collins-syndrome.
Times, February 3, 2014, http://www.nytimes.com/2014/02/04/health/ethics-ques- 9
In the case of these two disabilities, the parents will also be told that there
tions-arise-as-genetic-testing-of-embryos-increases.html?_r=0). Even more trou- may be accompanying health difficulties. In the first case, Down syndrome, there will
bling, in this same article, some bioethicists argue that this kind of genetic screening be some degree of cognitive impairment, ranging from mild to severe, and there may
should be obligatory. “Janet Malek, a bioethicist at the Brody School of Medicine at be other health issues, most notably cardiac anomalies. In the second case, Treacher
East Carolina University, said that people who carry a gene like GSS have a moral Collins syndrome, there is likely no cognitive impairment, and the accompanying
duty to use [PGD]—if they can afford it—to spare the next generation. ‘If there is health issues, mild to severe, are directly related to the facial structure. However, at
a paradigm example in which a parent can have an obligation to use this technology, the time of the initial diagnosis, there is often no way to ascertain how severe these
this is it,’ she said” (ibid.). conditions will be. See articles referenced in footnotes 3, 4, and 5 above.
136 Beauty, the Person, and Disability Theresa Farnan 137
cultural expectations and classical conceptions of beauty that they form a two philosophies are thoroughly intertwined in our culture’s approach to dis-
genuine psychological barrier to accepting the child’s humanity. ability.
Materialism leads to seeing the person only in terms of his or her
physical, material limitations, including physical and cognitive limitations. A
Political and Philosophical Context for “After-birth Abortion” materialist who encounters physical limitations in a person may assume the
presence of cognitive limitations even when none are present. For those who
At the time Giubilini and Minerva published this article in the Journal of believe that there is nothing more to a person than the material body, who
Medical Ethics, the British Parliament was conducting an inquiry into the eth- reject any ability of the person to transcend his or her body, and who believe
ics of abortion in cases of disability, focusing on section one of the 1967 that all cognitive and emotional activity is circumscribed by the confines of
Abortion Act, which permits abortion in cases of disabilities.10 The inquiry the body, the appearance of disability signals a life not worth living.
focused especially on the troubling aspects of aborting babies with cleft pal- The ethical theory of utilitarianism, then, is a comfortable fit for the
ate or Down syndrome and noted the connection between appearance and materialist, especially when considering issues relating to disability. From the
abortions performed for eugenic reasons. According to one of the written time Jeremy Bentham articulated pleasure and pain as decisive factors in eval-
responses, entered as evidence in the report, “Ground E reflects to me the uating the morality of an action, utilitarian philosophers have grappled with
spectre of eugenics and the worrying trend in society to only value the per- ways to account for intangible values like beauty.13 But even if the utilitarian
fect and beautiful, the ‘useful’ and productive.”11 adopts a perspective that allows for beauty as an intangible good that gives
This comment implicitly identifies the philosophies that are most in- pleasure, it is difficult to see how he would accommodate the person with
fluential in marginalizing and rejecting disabled persons based on appearance: visible physical defects, or whether he would see any value in this project.
materialism and utilitarianism.12 While it is true that a number of different This raises an important question for utilitarian philosophers: How
philosophical ideas influence attitudes toward disabled persons, materialism would they respond to parents who claim that their child’s appearance con-
and utilitarianism uniquely cause typically-abled, typically-appearing persons stitutes an intolerable burden, an insurmountable obstacle to their happiness?
to question the value of others based on surface impressions. In fact, these Suppose for instance, that a child is born with a moderate case of Treacher
Collins syndrome, able to breathe and eat without difficulty, with a correct-
ible hearing impairment, and no cognitive impairment. However, his appear-
10
Section one of the 1967 Abortion Act of the United Kingdom stipulates ance is distinctively different. If parents view the psychological burden of
that abortion is allowed if “there is a substantial risk that if the child were born it caring for an unattractive, disfigured child as an extreme hardship, should
would suffer from such physical or mental abnormalities as to be seriously handi- they be permitted to kill the child and try again? Moreover, should we accept
capped” (Abortion Act 1967, 15 Eliz. 2, c. 87, § 1[1][b], http://www.legislation.gov. that how others regard a person’s appearance constitutes such suffering on
uk/ukpga/1967/87/pdfs/ukpga_19670087_en.pdf). The Law is notable for allow- the part of the parents or the child that it is better for that person not to live?
ing abortion up to and at birth in cases of disability as well as for its vagueness as to
Utilitarian philosopher Peter Singer skirts this issue in in his article
what constitutes a serious handicap. See also Human Fertilisation and Embryology
Act 1990, 38 Eliz. 2, c. 37, http://www.legislation.gov.uk/ukpga/1990/37/pdfs/ “Ethics and Disability” by protesting that, unlike differences of appearance,
ukpga_19900037_en.pdf. For a brief history of the Abortion Act and subsequent disability causes suffering. While dismissive of the rights and value of dis-
amendments, see “Inquiry into Abortion on the Grounds of Disability,” accessed abled infants, he becomes noticeably squeamish at the thought of abortion
April 16, 2016, http://scotscatholic.org/upload/Abortion%20and%20Disabili-
ty%20Report%2017%207%2013.pdf. 13
See for example, “Value of a Lot of Pleasure or Pain, How to be Measured”
11
Bruce, et al., Parliamentary Inquiry into Abortion on the Grounds of Disability. and “Pleasures and Pains, Their Kinds,” chap. 4 and 5 in Bentham’s Introduction to the
12
In this section, I am considering the particular form of preference utili- Principles of Morals and Legislation ([Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1907], accessed Octo-
tarianism exemplified by Peter Singer and by Giubilini and Minerva. This particular ber 21, 2014, http://www.econlib.org/library/Bentham/bnthPML.html), in which
approach to utilitarian ethics has had the greatest influence on the debate about he describes the felicific calculus and how to use it. His first three pains, pains of
abortion and euthanasia of infants. Proponents of abortion and euthanasia combine privation, the senses and awkwardness especially apply to the suffering of various
arguments about the suffering of the child with deference to the preferences of the kinds of disability. See also G.E. Moore’s discussion of beauty in “The Ideal,” chap.
parents, pivoting off the definition of personhood set forth by Singer in Practical 6 in Principia Ethica (Buffalo: Prometheus, 1988), accessed October 21, 2014, http://
Ethics. fair-use.org/g-e-moore/principia-ethica.
136 Beauty, the Person, and Disability Theresa Farnan 137
cultural expectations and classical conceptions of beauty that they form a two philosophies are thoroughly intertwined in our culture’s approach to dis-
genuine psychological barrier to accepting the child’s humanity. ability.
Materialism leads to seeing the person only in terms of his or her
physical, material limitations, including physical and cognitive limitations. A
Political and Philosophical Context for “After-birth Abortion” materialist who encounters physical limitations in a person may assume the
presence of cognitive limitations even when none are present. For those who
At the time Giubilini and Minerva published this article in the Journal of believe that there is nothing more to a person than the material body, who
Medical Ethics, the British Parliament was conducting an inquiry into the eth- reject any ability of the person to transcend his or her body, and who believe
ics of abortion in cases of disability, focusing on section one of the 1967 that all cognitive and emotional activity is circumscribed by the confines of
Abortion Act, which permits abortion in cases of disabilities.10 The inquiry the body, the appearance of disability signals a life not worth living.
focused especially on the troubling aspects of aborting babies with cleft pal- The ethical theory of utilitarianism, then, is a comfortable fit for the
ate or Down syndrome and noted the connection between appearance and materialist, especially when considering issues relating to disability. From the
abortions performed for eugenic reasons. According to one of the written time Jeremy Bentham articulated pleasure and pain as decisive factors in eval-
responses, entered as evidence in the report, “Ground E reflects to me the uating the morality of an action, utilitarian philosophers have grappled with
spectre of eugenics and the worrying trend in society to only value the per- ways to account for intangible values like beauty.13 But even if the utilitarian
fect and beautiful, the ‘useful’ and productive.”11 adopts a perspective that allows for beauty as an intangible good that gives
This comment implicitly identifies the philosophies that are most in- pleasure, it is difficult to see how he would accommodate the person with
fluential in marginalizing and rejecting disabled persons based on appearance: visible physical defects, or whether he would see any value in this project.
materialism and utilitarianism.12 While it is true that a number of different This raises an important question for utilitarian philosophers: How
philosophical ideas influence attitudes toward disabled persons, materialism would they respond to parents who claim that their child’s appearance con-
and utilitarianism uniquely cause typically-abled, typically-appearing persons stitutes an intolerable burden, an insurmountable obstacle to their happiness?
to question the value of others based on surface impressions. In fact, these Suppose for instance, that a child is born with a moderate case of Treacher
Collins syndrome, able to breathe and eat without difficulty, with a correct-
ible hearing impairment, and no cognitive impairment. However, his appear-
10
Section one of the 1967 Abortion Act of the United Kingdom stipulates ance is distinctively different. If parents view the psychological burden of
that abortion is allowed if “there is a substantial risk that if the child were born it caring for an unattractive, disfigured child as an extreme hardship, should
would suffer from such physical or mental abnormalities as to be seriously handi- they be permitted to kill the child and try again? Moreover, should we accept
capped” (Abortion Act 1967, 15 Eliz. 2, c. 87, § 1[1][b], http://www.legislation.gov. that how others regard a person’s appearance constitutes such suffering on
uk/ukpga/1967/87/pdfs/ukpga_19670087_en.pdf). The Law is notable for allow- the part of the parents or the child that it is better for that person not to live?
ing abortion up to and at birth in cases of disability as well as for its vagueness as to
Utilitarian philosopher Peter Singer skirts this issue in in his article
what constitutes a serious handicap. See also Human Fertilisation and Embryology
Act 1990, 38 Eliz. 2, c. 37, http://www.legislation.gov.uk/ukpga/1990/37/pdfs/ “Ethics and Disability” by protesting that, unlike differences of appearance,
ukpga_19900037_en.pdf. For a brief history of the Abortion Act and subsequent disability causes suffering. While dismissive of the rights and value of dis-
amendments, see “Inquiry into Abortion on the Grounds of Disability,” accessed abled infants, he becomes noticeably squeamish at the thought of abortion
April 16, 2016, http://scotscatholic.org/upload/Abortion%20and%20Disabili-
ty%20Report%2017%207%2013.pdf. 13
See for example, “Value of a Lot of Pleasure or Pain, How to be Measured”
11
Bruce, et al., Parliamentary Inquiry into Abortion on the Grounds of Disability. and “Pleasures and Pains, Their Kinds,” chap. 4 and 5 in Bentham’s Introduction to the
12
In this section, I am considering the particular form of preference utili- Principles of Morals and Legislation ([Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1907], accessed Octo-
tarianism exemplified by Peter Singer and by Giubilini and Minerva. This particular ber 21, 2014, http://www.econlib.org/library/Bentham/bnthPML.html), in which
approach to utilitarian ethics has had the greatest influence on the debate about he describes the felicific calculus and how to use it. His first three pains, pains of
abortion and euthanasia of infants. Proponents of abortion and euthanasia combine privation, the senses and awkwardness especially apply to the suffering of various
arguments about the suffering of the child with deference to the preferences of the kinds of disability. See also G.E. Moore’s discussion of beauty in “The Ideal,” chap.
parents, pivoting off the definition of personhood set forth by Singer in Practical 6 in Principia Ethica (Buffalo: Prometheus, 1988), accessed October 21, 2014, http://
Ethics. fair-use.org/g-e-moore/principia-ethica.
138 Beauty, the Person, and Disability Theresa Farnan 139
or infanticide in the case of difference, including differences of appearance: In addition, Singer’s dismissive response is inadequate in his choice
I wish Koch and other disability advocates would abandon the and characterization of differences. For many persons with Down syndrome,
use of the term “difference” when referring to disability. “Dif- for example, aside from physical characteristics that do not cause suffering
ference” is a much broader term. Presumably, Koch doesn’t really (such as low set ears or a small head), the chief manifestation of their disabili-
think that I believe that suffering necessarily results from, say, ty is a lower level of cognitive functioning.17 In these instances, the diagnosed
having red hair, or perfect pitch, or being able to play 20 games disability actually causes differences, rather than suffering. Perhaps a more
of chess simultaneously while blindfolded, but these characteris- appropriate example of the kind of difference that is linked to abortion/
tics certainly make one “different” from the norm. The fact that infanticide would be a person’s inability to master chess, rather than Singer’s
Koch knows, and you, the reader, know, that these differences are fantasy of the blindfolded chess virtuoso playing twenty games simultane-
not what he is referring to, shows that we all know that disabilities ously. Does a person’s inability to master chess rise to the level of suffering?
are not simply “differences.” Why pretend that they are?14 Is Singer honest enough to admit that in these cases he would allow infanti-
cide or abortion based on potential IQ levels and other criteria, criteria that
While Singer criticizes disability advocates for using the broad term are differences that do not constitute physical suffering?
“difference” instead of disability, he too is guilty of broad-brush generaliza- Singer’s conflation of disability and suffering provides an emotion-
tions. Not every disability causes suffering; in fact, suffering is not an inevi- al argument in support of his belief that ultimately parents should be able
table result of the disabilities cited by Giubilini and Minerva. Ultimately, the to end a child’s life based on their preferences and interests rather than the
preference of the parents is the decisive factor for Singer, Giubilini, and Min- baby’s. Holding him to his own premises, namely his elevation of the par-
erva, since the happiness of parents—who are capable of imagining their ents’ right to the kind of baby they prefer, and his denial of personhood to
own futures, desiring happiness, and making choices—outweighs the happi- infants and the unborn, Singer ends up affirming the right to abortion and
ness of the baby, before and after birth. Singer avoids the obvious conclusion infanticide based on difference as well as disability. For Singer, as well as for
that if parent preference is the deciding factor, there is nothing to stop the Giubilini and Minerva, nothing other than the subjective feelings and desires
parents of a child with a difference like red hair from opting for infanticide of parents prevents the killing of any unborn or newborn baby. Therefore,
as a result of their fear that the child may suffer socially or emotionally from the distinction between difference and disability carries no weight in protect-
his or her difference (in this case red hair), or due to the parents’ own be- ing babies from the preferences of their parents. Why pretend otherwise?18
lief that they may suffer emotionally, socially, or financially because of their
child’s difference. (Singer’s choice of red hair as a value neutral difference bearable suffering…this group includes patients who are not dependent on intensive
is ironic, considering the fact that in 2011 one of the world’s largest sperm medical treatment but for whom a very poor quality of life, associated with sustained
banks stopped accepting donations from red-headed men, reflecting social suffering, is predicted.” This group includes babies with spina bifida. See Eduard
preferences against red hair.)15 Moreover, Singer’s radical stance of denying Verhagen and Pieter J.J. Sauer, “The Groningen Protocol—Euthanasia in Severely Ill
personhood to babies, newborn as well as unborn, ensures that in cases of Newborns,” N Engl J Med 352 (2005): 959–62, doi: 10.1056/NEJMp058026, accessed
physical suffering due to congenital birth defects, pressure is brought to bear November 22, 2014, http://www.nejm.org/doi/full/10.1056/NEJMp058026.
to end suffering by ending life, rather than by ameliorating suffering, even
17
“Disability” is not as clear-cut as Singer portrays it. Chromosomal abnor-
when the diagnosis is not terminal.16 malities like trisomy 21 can occur in Mosaic forms, resulting in a more ambiguous
presentation. Moreover, the manifestation of Down syndrome can vary according
to individual. Some persons with Down syndrome have IQs in the normal range, for
14
Peter Singer, “Ethics and Disability: A Response to Koch,” Journal of Dis- example. See for instance, this study in which 2/35 children with Down syndrome
ability Policy Studies 16, no. 2 (2005): 130–33, accessed November 22, 2014, http:// had IQs in the normal range (E. Pastore, B. Marino, A. Calzolari, et al., “Clinical
www.utilitarian.net/singer/by/2005----.pdf. and cardiorespiratory assessment in children with Down syndrome….,” Arch Pediatr
15
Kimberly Hayes Taylor, “Sperm Bank: Redheads Not Wanted,” NBC News, Adolesc Med 154, no. 4 [2000]: 408–10). At birth, and even in the first three years—
September 22, 2011, http://www.nbcnews.com/id/44579757/ns/health-mens_ Singer’s window for infanticide—parents cannot predict the potential of any child,
health/t/sperm-bank-redheads-not-wanted/#.VDbRIEu0aO0. not even one with a diagnosed disability.
16
This is chillingly demonstrated by the application of the Groningen Pro- 18
Singer himself argues in “Ethics and Disability,” 132: “For the reason I
tocol in the Netherlands. Newborn victims of infanticide include “infants with a have just quickly sketched, I do not think that killing any fetus or newborn infant
hopeless prognosis who experience what parents and medical experts deem to be un- is morally equivalent to killing a rational and self-conscious being. This does not
138 Beauty, the Person, and Disability Theresa Farnan 139
or infanticide in the case of difference, including differences of appearance: In addition, Singer’s dismissive response is inadequate in his choice
I wish Koch and other disability advocates would abandon the and characterization of differences. For many persons with Down syndrome,
use of the term “difference” when referring to disability. “Dif- for example, aside from physical characteristics that do not cause suffering
ference” is a much broader term. Presumably, Koch doesn’t really (such as low set ears or a small head), the chief manifestation of their disabili-
think that I believe that suffering necessarily results from, say, ty is a lower level of cognitive functioning.17 In these instances, the diagnosed
having red hair, or perfect pitch, or being able to play 20 games disability actually causes differences, rather than suffering. Perhaps a more
of chess simultaneously while blindfolded, but these characteris- appropriate example of the kind of difference that is linked to abortion/
tics certainly make one “different” from the norm. The fact that infanticide would be a person’s inability to master chess, rather than Singer’s
Koch knows, and you, the reader, know, that these differences are fantasy of the blindfolded chess virtuoso playing twenty games simultane-
not what he is referring to, shows that we all know that disabilities ously. Does a person’s inability to master chess rise to the level of suffering?
are not simply “differences.” Why pretend that they are?14 Is Singer honest enough to admit that in these cases he would allow infanti-
cide or abortion based on potential IQ levels and other criteria, criteria that
While Singer criticizes disability advocates for using the broad term are differences that do not constitute physical suffering?
“difference” instead of disability, he too is guilty of broad-brush generaliza- Singer’s conflation of disability and suffering provides an emotion-
tions. Not every disability causes suffering; in fact, suffering is not an inevi- al argument in support of his belief that ultimately parents should be able
table result of the disabilities cited by Giubilini and Minerva. Ultimately, the to end a child’s life based on their preferences and interests rather than the
preference of the parents is the decisive factor for Singer, Giubilini, and Min- baby’s. Holding him to his own premises, namely his elevation of the par-
erva, since the happiness of parents—who are capable of imagining their ents’ right to the kind of baby they prefer, and his denial of personhood to
own futures, desiring happiness, and making choices—outweighs the happi- infants and the unborn, Singer ends up affirming the right to abortion and
ness of the baby, before and after birth. Singer avoids the obvious conclusion infanticide based on difference as well as disability. For Singer, as well as for
that if parent preference is the deciding factor, there is nothing to stop the Giubilini and Minerva, nothing other than the subjective feelings and desires
parents of a child with a difference like red hair from opting for infanticide of parents prevents the killing of any unborn or newborn baby. Therefore,
as a result of their fear that the child may suffer socially or emotionally from the distinction between difference and disability carries no weight in protect-
his or her difference (in this case red hair), or due to the parents’ own be- ing babies from the preferences of their parents. Why pretend otherwise?18
lief that they may suffer emotionally, socially, or financially because of their
child’s difference. (Singer’s choice of red hair as a value neutral difference bearable suffering…this group includes patients who are not dependent on intensive
is ironic, considering the fact that in 2011 one of the world’s largest sperm medical treatment but for whom a very poor quality of life, associated with sustained
banks stopped accepting donations from red-headed men, reflecting social suffering, is predicted.” This group includes babies with spina bifida. See Eduard
preferences against red hair.)15 Moreover, Singer’s radical stance of denying Verhagen and Pieter J.J. Sauer, “The Groningen Protocol—Euthanasia in Severely Ill
personhood to babies, newborn as well as unborn, ensures that in cases of Newborns,” N Engl J Med 352 (2005): 959–62, doi: 10.1056/NEJMp058026, accessed
physical suffering due to congenital birth defects, pressure is brought to bear November 22, 2014, http://www.nejm.org/doi/full/10.1056/NEJMp058026.
to end suffering by ending life, rather than by ameliorating suffering, even
17
“Disability” is not as clear-cut as Singer portrays it. Chromosomal abnor-
when the diagnosis is not terminal.16 malities like trisomy 21 can occur in Mosaic forms, resulting in a more ambiguous
presentation. Moreover, the manifestation of Down syndrome can vary according
to individual. Some persons with Down syndrome have IQs in the normal range, for
14
Peter Singer, “Ethics and Disability: A Response to Koch,” Journal of Dis- example. See for instance, this study in which 2/35 children with Down syndrome
ability Policy Studies 16, no. 2 (2005): 130–33, accessed November 22, 2014, http:// had IQs in the normal range (E. Pastore, B. Marino, A. Calzolari, et al., “Clinical
www.utilitarian.net/singer/by/2005----.pdf. and cardiorespiratory assessment in children with Down syndrome….,” Arch Pediatr
15
Kimberly Hayes Taylor, “Sperm Bank: Redheads Not Wanted,” NBC News, Adolesc Med 154, no. 4 [2000]: 408–10). At birth, and even in the first three years—
September 22, 2011, http://www.nbcnews.com/id/44579757/ns/health-mens_ Singer’s window for infanticide—parents cannot predict the potential of any child,
health/t/sperm-bank-redheads-not-wanted/#.VDbRIEu0aO0. not even one with a diagnosed disability.
16
This is chillingly demonstrated by the application of the Groningen Pro- 18
Singer himself argues in “Ethics and Disability,” 132: “For the reason I
tocol in the Netherlands. Newborn victims of infanticide include “infants with a have just quickly sketched, I do not think that killing any fetus or newborn infant
hopeless prognosis who experience what parents and medical experts deem to be un- is morally equivalent to killing a rational and self-conscious being. This does not
140 Beauty, the Person, and Disability Theresa Farnan 141
It seems that a more reasonable response would be that the parents with their lives, like who they are, and like how they look.21 In a stunning dis-
should not be able to claim to know the potential for happiness of another play of the callousness of utilitarianism, Minerva and Giubilini then assert,
person, no matter how he or she looks or on the possibility of future lim- “Nonetheless, to bring up such children might be an unbearable burden on
itations. The parents’ own subjective responses to the fear of their child’s the family, and on society as a whole, when the state economically provides
disability, including the fear of potential suffering, should not be considered for their care.”22 Although their argument specifically invokes economic con-
adequate grounds for denying the child the opportunity to live and make of cerns, nothing prevents the same argument from being made for aesthetic
his or her own life what he or she wills. In fact, while they encounter chal- concerns.23 In fact, because their argument explicitly denies the personhood
lenges, many disabled persons view their disabilities as crucial to their own of an infant with disabilities, it offers nothing to counteract prejudice against
development as unique individuals.19 disabled babies based on the appearance of disability or any other factor.
However, Giubilini and Minerva consider this and reach the opposite Granted, utilitarianism and materialism are not the only philosophies
conclusion. They grudgingly acknowledge research that shows that persons that influence society in assessing the value of the unborn and newborn child
with Down syndrome are “often reported to be happy”20—although they fail with disabilities. However, given the high rate of abortion of children diag-
to reference a recent study published in the American Journal of Medical Genetics nosed prenatally with Down syndrome (as high as 90 percent), at a time when
that documented persons with Down syndrome are overwhelmingly happy improvements in medical care and social opportunities are removing many
of the obstacles persons with Down syndrome might experience, the impar-
tial observer is reluctantly forced to conclude that Singer’s utilitarianism is
mean, of course, that killing fetuses or infants is a matter of moral indifference. carrying the day. A final sobering statistic from the UK Parliamentary Inquiry
On the contrary, to kill a fetus or an infant is normally very wrong indeed. The starkly illustrates this: In the United Kingdom, the cost of prenatal screening
wrong, however, consists primarily in the harm it does to the pregnant woman, or for Down syndrome ranges from 29 to 31 million pounds per year, whereas
the parents, who have conceived the child and already love it and wish to nurture it.
during the fiscal year 2012–2013, the amount of money spent on research to
The death of a fetus or a newborn infant is generally a tragedy for the parents, not
for the fetus or infant, who has not yet even glimpsed the prospects of the life that alleviate the effects of Down syndrome was only 1.8 million pounds.24
might have been in store for it. Or, we could put it this way: To the extent that the
death of a fetus or newborn infant is a tragedy for that being, it would also have been
a tragedy if the fetus or infant had never been conceived. It is an impersonal loss, Changing our utilitarian culture
because the fetus or infant is not yet a person.” In his 1980 review of Practical Ethics,
H.L.A. Hart points out “In principle, only the arguments from side effects would The issue at hand, then, is how to respond to utilitarian efforts to “weed out”
count against the killing of a normal baby in order to replace it with a child whose persons with disabilities. Ultimately, the only certain way to protect disabled
prospects of happiness were greater. Moreover, on the Total View the secret killing children is to assert and defend the personhood of each and every human
of a normal happy child without replacement by parents unwilling to be burdened being with disabilities. At the same time, recognizing that utilitarianism dom-
with its upbringing would be no greater moral wrong than that done by parents who
abstain from conceiving a child for the same reasons” (H.L.A. Hart, “Death and 21
One study found that 99% of persons with Down syndrome are over-
Utility,” The New York Review of Books, May 15, 1980, http://www.nybooks.com/ whelmingly happy with their lives, 97% like who they are, and 96% like how they look
articles/1980/05/15/death-and-utility/). (BG Skotko, SP Levine, and R. Goldstein, “Self-perceptions from people with Down
19
Dr. Amie Stringfellow, a physician who was born with a severe case of syndrome,” Am J Med Genet 155a, no. 10 [2011]: 2360–69, doi: 10.1002/ajmg.a.34235,
Treacher-Collins Syndrome, wrote “given the chance to live my life over again with- accessed August 22, 2015, http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/21910246).
out Treacher Collins, I would have to politely decline. I believe that the experiences in 22
Giubilini and Minerva, “After-birth abortion”; Giving Giubilini and Miner-
my life as a result of Treacher Collins have molded me into the person that I am to- va the benefit of the doubt, they must not have considered that these same economic
day.… Having Treacher Collins syndrome, or any other medical condition, does not arguments could be invoked to justify gender selection abortion and infanticide in
make someone ‘abnormal,’ it only makes him human” (Amie Stringfellow, “About cultures that do not value girls.
Me,” in Reflections on Treacher Collins Syndrome, accessed November 22, 2014, http:// 23
It is surprising that in the end they ground their argument on the economic
www.treachercollins.org/tcs/About_Me.html). impact of these disabilities in light of the fact that persons with these syndromes
20
The study referenced in Giubilini and Minerva, “After-birth abortion,” is can be mildly affected, needing no more extraordinary care than typical children with
P. Alderson, “Down’s Syndrome: cost, quality, and the value of life,” Soc Sci Med 5 learning disabilities.
(2001): 627–38. 24
Bruce, et al., Parliamentary Inquiry into Abortion on the Grounds of Disability.
140 Beauty, the Person, and Disability Theresa Farnan 141
It seems that a more reasonable response would be that the parents with their lives, like who they are, and like how they look.21 In a stunning dis-
should not be able to claim to know the potential for happiness of another play of the callousness of utilitarianism, Minerva and Giubilini then assert,
person, no matter how he or she looks or on the possibility of future lim- “Nonetheless, to bring up such children might be an unbearable burden on
itations. The parents’ own subjective responses to the fear of their child’s the family, and on society as a whole, when the state economically provides
disability, including the fear of potential suffering, should not be considered for their care.”22 Although their argument specifically invokes economic con-
adequate grounds for denying the child the opportunity to live and make of cerns, nothing prevents the same argument from being made for aesthetic
his or her own life what he or she wills. In fact, while they encounter chal- concerns.23 In fact, because their argument explicitly denies the personhood
lenges, many disabled persons view their disabilities as crucial to their own of an infant with disabilities, it offers nothing to counteract prejudice against
development as unique individuals.19 disabled babies based on the appearance of disability or any other factor.
However, Giubilini and Minerva consider this and reach the opposite Granted, utilitarianism and materialism are not the only philosophies
conclusion. They grudgingly acknowledge research that shows that persons that influence society in assessing the value of the unborn and newborn child
with Down syndrome are “often reported to be happy”20—although they fail with disabilities. However, given the high rate of abortion of children diag-
to reference a recent study published in the American Journal of Medical Genetics nosed prenatally with Down syndrome (as high as 90 percent), at a time when
that documented persons with Down syndrome are overwhelmingly happy improvements in medical care and social opportunities are removing many
of the obstacles persons with Down syndrome might experience, the impar-
tial observer is reluctantly forced to conclude that Singer’s utilitarianism is
mean, of course, that killing fetuses or infants is a matter of moral indifference. carrying the day. A final sobering statistic from the UK Parliamentary Inquiry
On the contrary, to kill a fetus or an infant is normally very wrong indeed. The starkly illustrates this: In the United Kingdom, the cost of prenatal screening
wrong, however, consists primarily in the harm it does to the pregnant woman, or for Down syndrome ranges from 29 to 31 million pounds per year, whereas
the parents, who have conceived the child and already love it and wish to nurture it.
during the fiscal year 2012–2013, the amount of money spent on research to
The death of a fetus or a newborn infant is generally a tragedy for the parents, not
for the fetus or infant, who has not yet even glimpsed the prospects of the life that alleviate the effects of Down syndrome was only 1.8 million pounds.24
might have been in store for it. Or, we could put it this way: To the extent that the
death of a fetus or newborn infant is a tragedy for that being, it would also have been
a tragedy if the fetus or infant had never been conceived. It is an impersonal loss, Changing our utilitarian culture
because the fetus or infant is not yet a person.” In his 1980 review of Practical Ethics,
H.L.A. Hart points out “In principle, only the arguments from side effects would The issue at hand, then, is how to respond to utilitarian efforts to “weed out”
count against the killing of a normal baby in order to replace it with a child whose persons with disabilities. Ultimately, the only certain way to protect disabled
prospects of happiness were greater. Moreover, on the Total View the secret killing children is to assert and defend the personhood of each and every human
of a normal happy child without replacement by parents unwilling to be burdened being with disabilities. At the same time, recognizing that utilitarianism dom-
with its upbringing would be no greater moral wrong than that done by parents who
abstain from conceiving a child for the same reasons” (H.L.A. Hart, “Death and 21
One study found that 99% of persons with Down syndrome are over-
Utility,” The New York Review of Books, May 15, 1980, http://www.nybooks.com/ whelmingly happy with their lives, 97% like who they are, and 96% like how they look
articles/1980/05/15/death-and-utility/). (BG Skotko, SP Levine, and R. Goldstein, “Self-perceptions from people with Down
19
Dr. Amie Stringfellow, a physician who was born with a severe case of syndrome,” Am J Med Genet 155a, no. 10 [2011]: 2360–69, doi: 10.1002/ajmg.a.34235,
Treacher-Collins Syndrome, wrote “given the chance to live my life over again with- accessed August 22, 2015, http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/21910246).
out Treacher Collins, I would have to politely decline. I believe that the experiences in 22
Giubilini and Minerva, “After-birth abortion”; Giving Giubilini and Miner-
my life as a result of Treacher Collins have molded me into the person that I am to- va the benefit of the doubt, they must not have considered that these same economic
day.… Having Treacher Collins syndrome, or any other medical condition, does not arguments could be invoked to justify gender selection abortion and infanticide in
make someone ‘abnormal,’ it only makes him human” (Amie Stringfellow, “About cultures that do not value girls.
Me,” in Reflections on Treacher Collins Syndrome, accessed November 22, 2014, http:// 23
It is surprising that in the end they ground their argument on the economic
www.treachercollins.org/tcs/About_Me.html). impact of these disabilities in light of the fact that persons with these syndromes
20
The study referenced in Giubilini and Minerva, “After-birth abortion,” is can be mildly affected, needing no more extraordinary care than typical children with
P. Alderson, “Down’s Syndrome: cost, quality, and the value of life,” Soc Sci Med 5 learning disabilities.
(2001): 627–38. 24
Bruce, et al., Parliamentary Inquiry into Abortion on the Grounds of Disability.
142 Beauty, the Person, and Disability Theresa Farnan 143
inates the practice of ethics, especially bioethics, it is important to broaden difference or medical problem. Sometimes, in a person we can identify a
society’s understanding of the value of disabled persons by emphasizing the specific problem—a defect (i.e., something missing, atypical or extra that can
potential of each disabled person, rather than the limitations. Finally, it is es- affect how the body works). Often there are situations where the whole per-
sential to reconcile beauty and disability, in order to avoid the marginalization son is affected—“syndromes” (i.e., the result of genetic anomalies that affect
of disabled persons based on appearance alone. the whole person). In this case, the “syndrome” can give rise to a number
In general, disability challenges Christian philosophers to arrive at of specific defects. Defect then is a term that indicates that a specific body
deeper insights about the person, the relationship of body and soul, and part or function that is compromised in some way and that we can evaluate
the existence and meaning of suffering.25 For example, disabilities that cause clinically on a scale of integrity or function. Applying the criteria for defect
dementia pose difficulties that mirror the concerns about infanticide raised implies considering the person solely as an object, rather than a subject with
earlier in this paper. Christian ethicists must counter the impression that as inherent dignity.
cognitive abilities diminish, so does the personhood of the Alzheimer’s suf- Focusing on the defect—viewing the person as an object that can
ferer; this misconception is often used to justify passive euthanasia of Alzhei- be coldly evaluated for visible imperfections that reduce his or her moral
mer’s patients. status—allows those whose imperfections are trivial to view the disabled as
For Christian philosophers though, there is a deeper philosophical “other,” putting emotional distance between the typical person and the dis-
issue here. Given that beauty and goodness are related in a meaningful way, abled person. However, barring a sudden death, every person faces the pros-
and given the goodness and unity of the human person, how do we reconcile pect of disability in his or her life due to normal processes of aging, human
beauty with disability in the person? When family members assert that their susceptibility to illness, injury, and imperfection of human judgment. Part of
disabled son or daughter, brother or sister, husband or wife, is beautiful, they emotional and spiritual maturity is coming to terms with our own imperfec-
really mean it, not in a subjective or metaphorical way, but as an objective tion and mortality, and developing a sense of solidarity with and compassion
statement that deserves to be taken seriously. In the context of this particular for those who suffer from disabilities.26 A necessary first step, then, is recog-
discussion of the power of beauty, then, I would like to offer some initial nizing our tendency to see only the visible defect rather than the person.
considerations of areas in need of further exploration in order to understand
this relationship between beauty and disability.

Beauty and the disabled person

With this distinction in mind, is it possible for the Christian philosopher to


The disabled person as “other” reconcile beauty with different kinds of disability? In considering this prob-
lem, the Christian philosopher is guided by the following premises: first, that
The distinction between disability and defect is important for understanding beauty and goodness are related in some way; second, that every human be-
the basis for the marginalization of the person with disabilities based on ap-
pearance. Disability is a term that refers to the specific physical or intellectual 26
In Dependent Rational Animals, Alasdair MacIntyre argues that it is important
challenges that a person faces, usually resulting from a physical or genetic not only that communities care for vulnerable persons like the disabled, but that
members of the community have solidarity with them, based on recognizing the
25
It is important to realize as well that to family members of disabled persons, possibility that at some time they might be, have been, or will be similarly depen-
especially those with severe disabilities, the question of why their loved one suffers dent and vulnerable (Macintyre, “The political and social structures of the common
looms large. As Christians, we can point to the Crucified Christ, understanding that good,” chap. 11 in Dependent Rational Animals [Chicago: Open Court, 1999]). Unfor-
we unite our suffering with him. Even then, suffering is still a mystery. Without the tunately, movements like the assisted suicide movement have successfully turned this
context of Christianity, however, the suffering of the innocent, including children recognition of future dependence into a rationale for euthanasia, based on the fear
and those born with child-like cognitive abilities, seems overwhelming. See Fyodor of potentially being dependent and therefore a burden on others. Without a culture
Dostoyevsky, “Rebellion,” bk. 5, chap. 4, in The Brothers Karamazov, for the classic being informed not only by virtue ethics, but also by the conviction of the dignity
exposition of this difficulty (Dostoyevsky, The Brothers Karamazov, trans. Constance and worth of each human being, it is not clear how successful Macintyre’s argument
Garnett, ed. Manuel Komroff [New York: New American Library, 1980]). would be.
142 Beauty, the Person, and Disability Theresa Farnan 143
inates the practice of ethics, especially bioethics, it is important to broaden difference or medical problem. Sometimes, in a person we can identify a
society’s understanding of the value of disabled persons by emphasizing the specific problem—a defect (i.e., something missing, atypical or extra that can
potential of each disabled person, rather than the limitations. Finally, it is es- affect how the body works). Often there are situations where the whole per-
sential to reconcile beauty and disability, in order to avoid the marginalization son is affected—“syndromes” (i.e., the result of genetic anomalies that affect
of disabled persons based on appearance alone. the whole person). In this case, the “syndrome” can give rise to a number
In general, disability challenges Christian philosophers to arrive at of specific defects. Defect then is a term that indicates that a specific body
deeper insights about the person, the relationship of body and soul, and part or function that is compromised in some way and that we can evaluate
the existence and meaning of suffering.25 For example, disabilities that cause clinically on a scale of integrity or function. Applying the criteria for defect
dementia pose difficulties that mirror the concerns about infanticide raised implies considering the person solely as an object, rather than a subject with
earlier in this paper. Christian ethicists must counter the impression that as inherent dignity.
cognitive abilities diminish, so does the personhood of the Alzheimer’s suf- Focusing on the defect—viewing the person as an object that can
ferer; this misconception is often used to justify passive euthanasia of Alzhei- be coldly evaluated for visible imperfections that reduce his or her moral
mer’s patients. status—allows those whose imperfections are trivial to view the disabled as
For Christian philosophers though, there is a deeper philosophical “other,” putting emotional distance between the typical person and the dis-
issue here. Given that beauty and goodness are related in a meaningful way, abled person. However, barring a sudden death, every person faces the pros-
and given the goodness and unity of the human person, how do we reconcile pect of disability in his or her life due to normal processes of aging, human
beauty with disability in the person? When family members assert that their susceptibility to illness, injury, and imperfection of human judgment. Part of
disabled son or daughter, brother or sister, husband or wife, is beautiful, they emotional and spiritual maturity is coming to terms with our own imperfec-
really mean it, not in a subjective or metaphorical way, but as an objective tion and mortality, and developing a sense of solidarity with and compassion
statement that deserves to be taken seriously. In the context of this particular for those who suffer from disabilities.26 A necessary first step, then, is recog-
discussion of the power of beauty, then, I would like to offer some initial nizing our tendency to see only the visible defect rather than the person.
considerations of areas in need of further exploration in order to understand
this relationship between beauty and disability.

Beauty and the disabled person

With this distinction in mind, is it possible for the Christian philosopher to


The disabled person as “other” reconcile beauty with different kinds of disability? In considering this prob-
lem, the Christian philosopher is guided by the following premises: first, that
The distinction between disability and defect is important for understanding beauty and goodness are related in some way; second, that every human be-
the basis for the marginalization of the person with disabilities based on ap-
pearance. Disability is a term that refers to the specific physical or intellectual 26
In Dependent Rational Animals, Alasdair MacIntyre argues that it is important
challenges that a person faces, usually resulting from a physical or genetic not only that communities care for vulnerable persons like the disabled, but that
members of the community have solidarity with them, based on recognizing the
25
It is important to realize as well that to family members of disabled persons, possibility that at some time they might be, have been, or will be similarly depen-
especially those with severe disabilities, the question of why their loved one suffers dent and vulnerable (Macintyre, “The political and social structures of the common
looms large. As Christians, we can point to the Crucified Christ, understanding that good,” chap. 11 in Dependent Rational Animals [Chicago: Open Court, 1999]). Unfor-
we unite our suffering with him. Even then, suffering is still a mystery. Without the tunately, movements like the assisted suicide movement have successfully turned this
context of Christianity, however, the suffering of the innocent, including children recognition of future dependence into a rationale for euthanasia, based on the fear
and those born with child-like cognitive abilities, seems overwhelming. See Fyodor of potentially being dependent and therefore a burden on others. Without a culture
Dostoyevsky, “Rebellion,” bk. 5, chap. 4, in The Brothers Karamazov, for the classic being informed not only by virtue ethics, but also by the conviction of the dignity
exposition of this difficulty (Dostoyevsky, The Brothers Karamazov, trans. Constance and worth of each human being, it is not clear how successful Macintyre’s argument
Garnett, ed. Manuel Komroff [New York: New American Library, 1980]). would be.
144 Beauty, the Person, and Disability Theresa Farnan 145
ing has dignity and value by virtue of his or her personhood, and accordingly In fact, any attempt to describe the beauty of Divine or angelic per-
should not be treated merely as an object; and finally, that there is a profound sons requires us to move past a default physical norm of beauty. For this
unity of body and soul that points to and reveals the mystery of the person. reason, it is important to insist on the fundamental relationship between
Culturally, we tend to illuminate what beauty is by viewing the goodness and beauty, a relationship that anchors evaluations of beauty.28 In
non-disabled as the norm of beauty and the disabled as the exceptional sub- this paper, I have taken as given that beauty is related in a meaningful way to
set, to be accommodated separately. According to this way of understanding goodness, based on the common sense observation that human beings are
beauty and the person, we look at physical perfection as a manifestation of attracted by beauty, and see it as good, pleasurable or valuable in some way.29
goodness and what a person physically should be as the most exemplary Pope John Paul II goes further, describing the relationship this way:
characteristic. We look past imperfections and try to find instances of beauty The link between good and beautiful stirs fruitful reflection. In a
in the disabled person.27 certain sense, beauty is the visible form of the good, just as the
However, this approach is problematic for a number of reasons. At good is the metaphysical condition of beauty. This was well un-
heart, it objectifies the person, approaching the person as an object to be derstood by the Greeks who, by fusing the two concepts, coined a
evaluated in a clinical, impartial way. Persons with disabilities become their term which embraces both: kalokagathía, or beauty-goodness. On
own subset, which reinforces the perception of them as other. Viewing per- this point Plato writes: “The power of the Good has taken refuge
sons according to these categories focuses inordinately on the body, implic- in the nature of the Beautiful.”30
itly undercutting the unity of the body and soul. Moreover, it ignores the
goodness of the whole person as significant for understanding and revealing But John Paul II’s words suggest additional difficulties. Aquinas de-
beauty. Persons with disabilities are not the only ones who would be excluded fines the beautiful as that which pleases when seen “quae visa placet,” and
by this approach; as each person ages, he or she would become less beautiful describes conditions that are required for something to be considered beauti-
according to this definition. In addition, this kind of definition is susceptible ful: integritas or perfectio (integrity or completeness); debita proportio or consonantia
to relativism, according to cultural and social norms. For these reasons, in (due proportion or harmony); and claritas (clarity, brightness, or splendor).31
light of the unity of the person and the relationship between beauty and With material objects, the more perfect they are, the more goodness they
goodness, any understanding of beauty and the person that accepts a default
physical norm of beauty is ultimately dissatisfying. 28
No discussion of the relationship between goodness and beauty would be
Perhaps a better approach to understanding the relationship between complete without acknowledging the controversy over whether or not beauty is a
beauty and disability would be to refine our understanding of beauty in the transcendental, a metaphysical property of every existing thing. Such a determination
person in such a way that it is not limited to the body, taking into account that a would mean that beauty is identical with the true and the good while differing from
human person is not limited to or defined by his or her body, which is imper- them conceptually. A deeper consideration of that question is beyond the scope of
fect and susceptible to age, illness, or injury. This approach also poses other this paper; however, persons with disabilities can illuminate some important issues
surrounding the relationship of the beautiful with the good, especially the difficulty
challenges that should not be underestimated. In particular, it leads to the
of applying standards of beauty to a person. See Jan Aertsen, “Beauty in the Middle
possibility of diluting what beauty means so that it is rendered wholly sub- Ages: A Forgotten Transcendental?,” Medieval Philosophy and Theology 1 (1991): 68–97,
jective and, as a result, meaningless. Moreover, it runs the risk of minimizing and Jacques Maritain, “Art and Beauty,” chap. 5 in Art and Scholasticism (Notre Dame,
the ugliness of the suffering that often accompanies disability, sickness and IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1974).
aging. Nevertheless, if the beauty of the person is to be evaluated, we cannot 29
By goodness, I mean more than just personal preference—an object is not
limit ourselves to consideration of beauty on the basis of physical norms or good because we prefer it, but it is good because in some way it contributes to our
criteria, but instead need to ask ourselves how beauty is instantiated in the flourishing. Preference for a good arises from recognition of its goodness; similarly,
person. we recognize an object’s beauty, rather than confer beauty upon it. Recognition of its
beauty arises from something intrinsic and good in the object itself.
30
St. John Paul II, Letter to Artists § 3, par. 2, April 4, 1999, accessed November
27
To a certain extent, use of words like “special” and token inclusions of 22, 2014, https://w2.vatican.va/content/john-paul-ii/en/letters/1999/documents/
persons with disabilities in advertising campaigns, although intended to affirm the hf_jp-ii_let_23041999_artists.html.
value of persons with disabilities, reinforce this sense of persons with disabilities as 31
Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologica I, q. 5., art. 4, ad 1(Hereafter, ST); Aqui-
the exceptional subset. nas, ST I, q. 39, art. 8.
144 Beauty, the Person, and Disability Theresa Farnan 145
ing has dignity and value by virtue of his or her personhood, and accordingly In fact, any attempt to describe the beauty of Divine or angelic per-
should not be treated merely as an object; and finally, that there is a profound sons requires us to move past a default physical norm of beauty. For this
unity of body and soul that points to and reveals the mystery of the person. reason, it is important to insist on the fundamental relationship between
Culturally, we tend to illuminate what beauty is by viewing the goodness and beauty, a relationship that anchors evaluations of beauty.28 In
non-disabled as the norm of beauty and the disabled as the exceptional sub- this paper, I have taken as given that beauty is related in a meaningful way to
set, to be accommodated separately. According to this way of understanding goodness, based on the common sense observation that human beings are
beauty and the person, we look at physical perfection as a manifestation of attracted by beauty, and see it as good, pleasurable or valuable in some way.29
goodness and what a person physically should be as the most exemplary Pope John Paul II goes further, describing the relationship this way:
characteristic. We look past imperfections and try to find instances of beauty The link between good and beautiful stirs fruitful reflection. In a
in the disabled person.27 certain sense, beauty is the visible form of the good, just as the
However, this approach is problematic for a number of reasons. At good is the metaphysical condition of beauty. This was well un-
heart, it objectifies the person, approaching the person as an object to be derstood by the Greeks who, by fusing the two concepts, coined a
evaluated in a clinical, impartial way. Persons with disabilities become their term which embraces both: kalokagathía, or beauty-goodness. On
own subset, which reinforces the perception of them as other. Viewing per- this point Plato writes: “The power of the Good has taken refuge
sons according to these categories focuses inordinately on the body, implic- in the nature of the Beautiful.”30
itly undercutting the unity of the body and soul. Moreover, it ignores the
goodness of the whole person as significant for understanding and revealing But John Paul II’s words suggest additional difficulties. Aquinas de-
beauty. Persons with disabilities are not the only ones who would be excluded fines the beautiful as that which pleases when seen “quae visa placet,” and
by this approach; as each person ages, he or she would become less beautiful describes conditions that are required for something to be considered beauti-
according to this definition. In addition, this kind of definition is susceptible ful: integritas or perfectio (integrity or completeness); debita proportio or consonantia
to relativism, according to cultural and social norms. For these reasons, in (due proportion or harmony); and claritas (clarity, brightness, or splendor).31
light of the unity of the person and the relationship between beauty and With material objects, the more perfect they are, the more goodness they
goodness, any understanding of beauty and the person that accepts a default
physical norm of beauty is ultimately dissatisfying. 28
No discussion of the relationship between goodness and beauty would be
Perhaps a better approach to understanding the relationship between complete without acknowledging the controversy over whether or not beauty is a
beauty and disability would be to refine our understanding of beauty in the transcendental, a metaphysical property of every existing thing. Such a determination
person in such a way that it is not limited to the body, taking into account that a would mean that beauty is identical with the true and the good while differing from
human person is not limited to or defined by his or her body, which is imper- them conceptually. A deeper consideration of that question is beyond the scope of
fect and susceptible to age, illness, or injury. This approach also poses other this paper; however, persons with disabilities can illuminate some important issues
surrounding the relationship of the beautiful with the good, especially the difficulty
challenges that should not be underestimated. In particular, it leads to the
of applying standards of beauty to a person. See Jan Aertsen, “Beauty in the Middle
possibility of diluting what beauty means so that it is rendered wholly sub- Ages: A Forgotten Transcendental?,” Medieval Philosophy and Theology 1 (1991): 68–97,
jective and, as a result, meaningless. Moreover, it runs the risk of minimizing and Jacques Maritain, “Art and Beauty,” chap. 5 in Art and Scholasticism (Notre Dame,
the ugliness of the suffering that often accompanies disability, sickness and IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1974).
aging. Nevertheless, if the beauty of the person is to be evaluated, we cannot 29
By goodness, I mean more than just personal preference—an object is not
limit ourselves to consideration of beauty on the basis of physical norms or good because we prefer it, but it is good because in some way it contributes to our
criteria, but instead need to ask ourselves how beauty is instantiated in the flourishing. Preference for a good arises from recognition of its goodness; similarly,
person. we recognize an object’s beauty, rather than confer beauty upon it. Recognition of its
beauty arises from something intrinsic and good in the object itself.
30
St. John Paul II, Letter to Artists § 3, par. 2, April 4, 1999, accessed November
27
To a certain extent, use of words like “special” and token inclusions of 22, 2014, https://w2.vatican.va/content/john-paul-ii/en/letters/1999/documents/
persons with disabilities in advertising campaigns, although intended to affirm the hf_jp-ii_let_23041999_artists.html.
value of persons with disabilities, reinforce this sense of persons with disabilities as 31
Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologica I, q. 5., art. 4, ad 1(Hereafter, ST); Aqui-
the exceptional subset. nas, ST I, q. 39, art. 8.
146 Beauty, the Person, and Disability Theresa Farnan 147
possess and the more beautiful they are; we can evaluate the qualities that considered the person as a beautiful thing, passively displaying beauty. But as
Aquinas identifies as necessary for beauty in an objective way. But it is not agent, the person actively engages with the beautiful, not only by being beau-
at all clear how we could apply the same standards to a human person, who tiful, but also by desiring it and creating beautiful things. Here the words of
is an integral unity of body and soul; or to a divine or angelic person who is Saint John Paul II, describing the relationship of the artist to beauty, as one
immaterial.32 To limit beauty to material perfection views the person in a shal- who creates something beautiful, offer an important insight, “It is in living
low and superficial way that is neither born out by experience, nor consonant and acting that man establishes his relationship with being, with the truth
with an understanding of the person as possessing an immaterial soul. And and with the good.”34 Perhaps this insight can illuminate the relationship of
yet, we also cannot deny that we know human persons through their bod- the person to beauty as one who not only is beautiful but also creates some-
ies—and our first impression of beauty in the human person occurs through thing beautiful; “it is in living and acting that man established his relationship
the appearance of the body. Compounding the difficulty, we find many in- with” beauty as well as “with the truth and with the good.”35 A full account
stances of morally good and virtuous persons in bodies that at first glance of person and beauty must include this active dimension as well, not just for
seem far from beautiful; this seems to be the rule rather than the exception artists but for every person. But it is difficult to understand how to fit the
among persons with disabilities. person with disabilities into our account of the active dimension of the rela-
It is tempting to integrate disability into a Thomistic account of tionship between person and beauty. How exactly would a person with severe
beauty by pointing out that visa may refer to “seeing” with the intellect, rather disabilities create beauty? Is he or she limited to appreciating beauty? If so, it
than seeing with the eye. However, I would argue that even this reading poses would seem that he or she suffers not only from his disability, but also from
difficulties for evaluating beauty in the person with disabilities, or any per- an impoverished relationship with beauty.36
son for that matter, as intellectually seeing a person is still inferior to knowing
the person. Intellectually seeing the person enables you to see actions, or in
the case of the person with disabilities, inability to perform certain actions; Beauty and the person: future considerations
knowing the person reveals virtues and moral beauty. In fact, the evaluation
of a disabled person using intellectual criteria (or “seeing” them with the These issues merely scratch the surface of the complexity involved in giving
intellect) is precisely the approach taken by Giubilini and Minerva, as well as an account of beauty that does justice to persons with disabilities. Although
Peter Singer and others who devalue the person with disabilities. According this involves looking at beauty from an unusual perspective, it is an important
to their calculations, various aspects of disabilities are obvious, immediate, and pressing task, especially in light of our culture’s acceptance of eugenic
and inadequately mitigated by something as nebulous as “spiritual beauty”; abortion and, if Giubilini and Minerva have their way, infanticide. Moreover,
one gets the sense that to Singer and other utilitarians any assertion that a considering whether and how a person with disabilities might be described
disabled person is beautiful can only indicate wishful thinking and pretending as beautiful pushes us toward a richer and more profound understanding of
that the disability does not exist. In this instance, it certainly seems that the beauty, especially with respect to persons, human, divine, and angelic.
Thomistic account of beauty is in need of additional clarification in order to In light of this, I would like to suggest further avenues of inquiry
apply to the person.33 that may illuminate how beauty and disability can be reconciled. First and
Saint John Paul II’s Letter to Artists also encourages us to expand our foremost, any account of beauty in the person should illuminate how beauty
consideration of the relationship between person and beauty. So far, we have in a person differs from beauty in an object. That requires examining the re-
lationship of the body both to the soul and to the person, focusing on the ex-
32
In ST I, q. 39, art. 8, Aquinas describes various properties of beauty as a
property of the Son as perfectly the nature and express image of the Father, but 34
St. John Paul II, Letter to Artists, § 3, par. 3.
does not explain how this occurs. However, his characterization of the property of 35
Ibid.
integritas or perfectio is especially problematic for attempts to understand how persons 36
Research on the musical abilities of children with Down syndrome reveals
with disabilities can be beautiful; he proposes that insofar as things lack perfection or that their sense of rhythm is not impaired at all. They not only famously love music
integrity, they are ugly (turpia). but also are good at reproducing rhythms. This suggests that perhaps we underes-
33
Additional discussion of the distinction between seeing and knowing the timate the artistic capabilities of persons with disabilities; see B. Stratford and EY
person is beyond the scope of this paper, but is an important area for future consid- Ching, “Rhythm and time in the perception of Down’s syndrome children,” J Ment
eration of disability in the person. Defic Res 27 (1983): 23–38.
146 Beauty, the Person, and Disability Theresa Farnan 147
possess and the more beautiful they are; we can evaluate the qualities that considered the person as a beautiful thing, passively displaying beauty. But as
Aquinas identifies as necessary for beauty in an objective way. But it is not agent, the person actively engages with the beautiful, not only by being beau-
at all clear how we could apply the same standards to a human person, who tiful, but also by desiring it and creating beautiful things. Here the words of
is an integral unity of body and soul; or to a divine or angelic person who is Saint John Paul II, describing the relationship of the artist to beauty, as one
immaterial.32 To limit beauty to material perfection views the person in a shal- who creates something beautiful, offer an important insight, “It is in living
low and superficial way that is neither born out by experience, nor consonant and acting that man establishes his relationship with being, with the truth
with an understanding of the person as possessing an immaterial soul. And and with the good.”34 Perhaps this insight can illuminate the relationship of
yet, we also cannot deny that we know human persons through their bod- the person to beauty as one who not only is beautiful but also creates some-
ies—and our first impression of beauty in the human person occurs through thing beautiful; “it is in living and acting that man established his relationship
the appearance of the body. Compounding the difficulty, we find many in- with” beauty as well as “with the truth and with the good.”35 A full account
stances of morally good and virtuous persons in bodies that at first glance of person and beauty must include this active dimension as well, not just for
seem far from beautiful; this seems to be the rule rather than the exception artists but for every person. But it is difficult to understand how to fit the
among persons with disabilities. person with disabilities into our account of the active dimension of the rela-
It is tempting to integrate disability into a Thomistic account of tionship between person and beauty. How exactly would a person with severe
beauty by pointing out that visa may refer to “seeing” with the intellect, rather disabilities create beauty? Is he or she limited to appreciating beauty? If so, it
than seeing with the eye. However, I would argue that even this reading poses would seem that he or she suffers not only from his disability, but also from
difficulties for evaluating beauty in the person with disabilities, or any per- an impoverished relationship with beauty.36
son for that matter, as intellectually seeing a person is still inferior to knowing
the person. Intellectually seeing the person enables you to see actions, or in
the case of the person with disabilities, inability to perform certain actions; Beauty and the person: future considerations
knowing the person reveals virtues and moral beauty. In fact, the evaluation
of a disabled person using intellectual criteria (or “seeing” them with the These issues merely scratch the surface of the complexity involved in giving
intellect) is precisely the approach taken by Giubilini and Minerva, as well as an account of beauty that does justice to persons with disabilities. Although
Peter Singer and others who devalue the person with disabilities. According this involves looking at beauty from an unusual perspective, it is an important
to their calculations, various aspects of disabilities are obvious, immediate, and pressing task, especially in light of our culture’s acceptance of eugenic
and inadequately mitigated by something as nebulous as “spiritual beauty”; abortion and, if Giubilini and Minerva have their way, infanticide. Moreover,
one gets the sense that to Singer and other utilitarians any assertion that a considering whether and how a person with disabilities might be described
disabled person is beautiful can only indicate wishful thinking and pretending as beautiful pushes us toward a richer and more profound understanding of
that the disability does not exist. In this instance, it certainly seems that the beauty, especially with respect to persons, human, divine, and angelic.
Thomistic account of beauty is in need of additional clarification in order to In light of this, I would like to suggest further avenues of inquiry
apply to the person.33 that may illuminate how beauty and disability can be reconciled. First and
Saint John Paul II’s Letter to Artists also encourages us to expand our foremost, any account of beauty in the person should illuminate how beauty
consideration of the relationship between person and beauty. So far, we have in a person differs from beauty in an object. That requires examining the re-
lationship of the body both to the soul and to the person, focusing on the ex-
32
In ST I, q. 39, art. 8, Aquinas describes various properties of beauty as a
property of the Son as perfectly the nature and express image of the Father, but 34
St. John Paul II, Letter to Artists, § 3, par. 3.
does not explain how this occurs. However, his characterization of the property of 35
Ibid.
integritas or perfectio is especially problematic for attempts to understand how persons 36
Research on the musical abilities of children with Down syndrome reveals
with disabilities can be beautiful; he proposes that insofar as things lack perfection or that their sense of rhythm is not impaired at all. They not only famously love music
integrity, they are ugly (turpia). but also are good at reproducing rhythms. This suggests that perhaps we underes-
33
Additional discussion of the distinction between seeing and knowing the timate the artistic capabilities of persons with disabilities; see B. Stratford and EY
person is beyond the scope of this paper, but is an important area for future consid- Ching, “Rhythm and time in the perception of Down’s syndrome children,” J Ment
eration of disability in the person. Defic Res 27 (1983): 23–38.
148 Beauty, the Person, and Disability Theresa Farnan 149
tent to which the body reveals the person.37 It should consider how we apply the person enables us to transcend the physical limitations of the body and
ideals of beauty to the human person—imperfect and changing—without recognize the beauty of the person.
treating him or her as an object. One of the most insidious aspects of Giubilini and Minerva’s pro-
Assuming that there is a relationship between beauty and goodness, posal is that it allows killing at the moment when the parents are about to
we must consider how we describe the disabled person whose physical ap- experience the privilege of knowing their child. It magnifies their fears both
pearance does not conform to norms of beauty. If beauty is known intellec- of and for their child, playing on their belief that their child will look and
tually through sight, as Aquinas suggests, is it possible for others to look past be defective. Denying the personhood of the baby and offering abortion or
the obvious physical defects that can accompany disability? As you come to infanticide as an escape from disability deprives parents of the opportunity
know the person with visible physical disabilities, do the obvious disabilities to appreciate the beauty of and fall in love with their baby as a person. In
recede in importance or do they become part of the person’s beauty? How recognizing the power of beauty to shape attitudes and actions, our response
is it possible that the body, so often the source of limitation for the disabled, must be a loving and unequivocal affirmation of the goodness and beauty of
can become the medium through which even the severely disabled person is every person, regardless of appearance or ability.
revealed in artistic representations as beautiful? In a 1995 letter to women,
Pope John Paul II referred to the spiritual beauty with which all of us are —Franciscan University
created.38 Exactly what does spiritual beauty mean, and how do we know it
in others? Is it known intellectually or through a more profound relational
perception of the person?
These are just a few of the challenging questions about beauty that
in the end lead us to a deeper consideration of personhood. The person is
increasingly defined in a Cartesian sense, as a thinking substance or as per-
sons who are “able to make aims and appreciate their own life.”39 But know-
ing a person with disabilities reveals the inadequacy of equating personhood
with the superficial and obvious exercise of intellect and will. Knowing the
disabled person leads us instead to focus on the more profound ability of
the person to be in relationship with others, which draws on the intellect
and the will in subtle, mysterious ways.40 In the end, this relational aspect of
37
This is not intended to imply some kind of separateness of the soul from
the person; rather the relationship of the body to the soul is a question that is distinct
from the relationship of the body to the person. Both questions must be considered.
38
“Perhaps more than men, women acknowledge the person, because they
see persons with their hearts. They see them independently of various ideological or
political systems. They see others in their greatness and limitations; they try to go out
to them and help them. In this way the basic plan of the Creator takes flesh in the infants as poverty, arguing that childlike receptivity is a perfection, imaging as it does
history of humanity and there is constantly revealed, in the variety of vocations, that the receptivity of Christ. This offers an avenue for future exploration of the recep-
beauty-not merely physical, but above all spiritual-which God bestowed from the tive relationality of persons with disability, who profoundly image the neediness of
very beginning on all, and in a particular way on women” (St. John Paul II, “Letter childhood relationality. Schindler makes the case that relationality must be anchored
to Women,” § 12, par. 1, June 29, 1995, accessed August 30, 2015, http://w2.vat- in esse rather than agere, another important insight for understanding the relationality
ican.va/content/john-paul-ii/en/letters/1995/documents/hf_jp-ii_let_29061995_ of persons with disabilities; see David Schindler, “Norris Clark on Person, Being,
women.html). and St. Thomas,” Communio 20, no. 3 (1993): 580–92, http://www.communio-icr.
39
Giubilini and Minerva, “After-birth abortion.” com/files/schindler20-3.pdf. See also Aquinas, ST I, q. 40, art. 2, for his discussion
40
Particular attention is paid to the receptive relationality of infants in the dis- of distinction of the persons of the Blessed Trinity according to relation, which
cussion about receptivity and relationality in David Schindler’s review of Fr. Norris proves crucial for understanding the relationality of persons as an aspect of imaging
Clark’s Person and Being. Schindler rejects Clark’s characterization of the receptivity of God.
148 Beauty, the Person, and Disability Theresa Farnan 149
tent to which the body reveals the person.37 It should consider how we apply the person enables us to transcend the physical limitations of the body and
ideals of beauty to the human person—imperfect and changing—without recognize the beauty of the person.
treating him or her as an object. One of the most insidious aspects of Giubilini and Minerva’s pro-
Assuming that there is a relationship between beauty and goodness, posal is that it allows killing at the moment when the parents are about to
we must consider how we describe the disabled person whose physical ap- experience the privilege of knowing their child. It magnifies their fears both
pearance does not conform to norms of beauty. If beauty is known intellec- of and for their child, playing on their belief that their child will look and
tually through sight, as Aquinas suggests, is it possible for others to look past be defective. Denying the personhood of the baby and offering abortion or
the obvious physical defects that can accompany disability? As you come to infanticide as an escape from disability deprives parents of the opportunity
know the person with visible physical disabilities, do the obvious disabilities to appreciate the beauty of and fall in love with their baby as a person. In
recede in importance or do they become part of the person’s beauty? How recognizing the power of beauty to shape attitudes and actions, our response
is it possible that the body, so often the source of limitation for the disabled, must be a loving and unequivocal affirmation of the goodness and beauty of
can become the medium through which even the severely disabled person is every person, regardless of appearance or ability.
revealed in artistic representations as beautiful? In a 1995 letter to women,
Pope John Paul II referred to the spiritual beauty with which all of us are —Franciscan University
created.38 Exactly what does spiritual beauty mean, and how do we know it
in others? Is it known intellectually or through a more profound relational
perception of the person?
These are just a few of the challenging questions about beauty that
in the end lead us to a deeper consideration of personhood. The person is
increasingly defined in a Cartesian sense, as a thinking substance or as per-
sons who are “able to make aims and appreciate their own life.”39 But know-
ing a person with disabilities reveals the inadequacy of equating personhood
with the superficial and obvious exercise of intellect and will. Knowing the
disabled person leads us instead to focus on the more profound ability of
the person to be in relationship with others, which draws on the intellect
and the will in subtle, mysterious ways.40 In the end, this relational aspect of
37
This is not intended to imply some kind of separateness of the soul from
the person; rather the relationship of the body to the soul is a question that is distinct
from the relationship of the body to the person. Both questions must be considered.
38
“Perhaps more than men, women acknowledge the person, because they
see persons with their hearts. They see them independently of various ideological or
political systems. They see others in their greatness and limitations; they try to go out
to them and help them. In this way the basic plan of the Creator takes flesh in the infants as poverty, arguing that childlike receptivity is a perfection, imaging as it does
history of humanity and there is constantly revealed, in the variety of vocations, that the receptivity of Christ. This offers an avenue for future exploration of the recep-
beauty-not merely physical, but above all spiritual-which God bestowed from the tive relationality of persons with disability, who profoundly image the neediness of
very beginning on all, and in a particular way on women” (St. John Paul II, “Letter childhood relationality. Schindler makes the case that relationality must be anchored
to Women,” § 12, par. 1, June 29, 1995, accessed August 30, 2015, http://w2.vat- in esse rather than agere, another important insight for understanding the relationality
ican.va/content/john-paul-ii/en/letters/1995/documents/hf_jp-ii_let_29061995_ of persons with disabilities; see David Schindler, “Norris Clark on Person, Being,
women.html). and St. Thomas,” Communio 20, no. 3 (1993): 580–92, http://www.communio-icr.
39
Giubilini and Minerva, “After-birth abortion.” com/files/schindler20-3.pdf. See also Aquinas, ST I, q. 40, art. 2, for his discussion
40
Particular attention is paid to the receptive relationality of infants in the dis- of distinction of the persons of the Blessed Trinity according to relation, which
cussion about receptivity and relationality in David Schindler’s review of Fr. Norris proves crucial for understanding the relationality of persons as an aspect of imaging
Clark’s Person and Being. Schindler rejects Clark’s characterization of the receptivity of God.
Roger Scruton 151

Beauty and Desecration to the present, so that you sense its being, as it were, with you in the moment
where you are. It is the role of beauty and aesthetic judgment to do that. By
seeking beauty we are also seeking long-term companionship, rather than
Roger Scruton short-term function.
We also argue about our ends from a religious point of view. We
The following is about beauty, and the questions that worry us today: just know that people have a conception of the meaning of life as lying in some
what is the role of beauty in the life that is growing around us?1 How do we way beyond life, either in the transcendental or in the afterlife. This meaning
distinguish it from its fake versions? And how do we defend it against the is sometimes revealed in the present moment: the moment which people are
surrounding culture? apt to describe as sacred, such as the moment of liturgy and worship, the
I wish to say a few philosophical things before we begin about why moment of revelation or reading a sacred text. And perhaps being blessed
beauty matters. We live in a world in which utilitarian values are not just with that experience is what St. Paul describes (in the words of the prayer
triumphant, but for many people the only values that there are. For such book) as “the peace that passeth understanding”: such a thing involves very
people there seems to be no sense that things can have a value that is not a powerful emotion and a powerful experience—if you can attain it. But we
form of use. This means that all of us are engaged all the time in what some live in a world where not everyone does obtain it or even seek for it. Increas-
philosophers call “instrumental reasoning.” Whenever we are asked to justify ingly the surrounding culture either ignores the sacred or denigrates it. So it
something we try to find a purpose for it. For example, when someone says is very difficult to explain to people who are immersed in the secular culture
“Justify the shape of a particular room at a particular University,” we do so how you would justify the ends of existence and not just the means. I think
in terms of its purpose, which is to gather people together to listen to a lec- this is our situation today.
ture. If it is not very efficient at that, then the room has not actually achieved Take as an example a landscape by Renoir. Whatever is happening
what it set out to achieve. In all our activities we are familiar with this kind in that landscape, it is imbued with a sense of peace and order, and takes
of reasoning. But the question is, why is that the only kind of reasoning? We from the surrounding colors the vitality that brings it to life. But Renoir, like
know perfectly well that it cannot be the only kind because if something is other impressionists, painted a world to which we belong. Belonging is an
a means to an end, there has to be an end that it is a means to, and that too all-important aspect of human experience. Not everybody has it; and our jails
needs a justification. So we do reason with each other about the ends of our are filled with the people who do not. But most of the people reading this,
activity; what our goals are and whether we should be pursuing them. And I imagine, are where they are without having committed a criminal offense
this is especially true in activities such as building or setting out on a career, in and feel that they do instinctively belong in the world and are in the business
which there is a long term project involved and an end point that you cannot of making that belonging more rooted, more permanent, and more wound
very clearly envisage. You know when you set out to build something, you together with the belonging of their fellows; indeed, that is part of what edu-
cannot clearly envisage the endpoint just from a ground plan. You need some cation is about. And that is what you see in a beautiful landscape by a painter
conception of not just what it will look like, but what will it be like to live like Renoir. These are ordinary trees—fruit trees—with an ordinary moun-
with it. And only if you know what it will be like to live with it, will you be tain in the distance, and so on; but the painter shows them as part of a world
justified in building it. to which we belong. And for him—for Renoir and his contemporaries—it is
One reason why modern architecture is such a failure is because a post-religious world. The impressionists were very much a people of their
people do not try to envisage what it will be like to live with the product time, who were skeptical about religion, and in any case, they regarded it as
that they are building. Rather, they think only about its present function and their duty as painters to show that it is this world, not the next that matters.
whether it fulfills it according to the requirements. Reasoning about what it is It is quite hard to paint the next world. It has been done in words by Dan-
like to live with something means bringing the end of your activity forward te, and a few painters have tried to follow him, but for the most part their
efforts have been failures. But nevertheless, our world is not that bad. It is
This essay is based on a transcript of Roger Scruton’s plenary lecture, given
1
imbued with its own tranquility and that tranquility can reside in perception
on September 19th, 2014. A video of the talk can be found at: http://www.faithan-
itself. That is what Renoir is telling us. He says, “ “Stop, stand still, and look.”
dreason.com/2014/12/dr-roger-scruton-beauty-desecration/.
And in that perception, you will see that this thing right in front of you has
© Roger Scruton, Quaestiones Disputatae, Vol. 6, No. 2 (Spring 2016) a meaning all of its own, a meaning that justifies you being in it and reminds
Roger Scruton 151

Beauty and Desecration to the present, so that you sense its being, as it were, with you in the moment
where you are. It is the role of beauty and aesthetic judgment to do that. By
seeking beauty we are also seeking long-term companionship, rather than
Roger Scruton short-term function.
We also argue about our ends from a religious point of view. We
The following is about beauty, and the questions that worry us today: just know that people have a conception of the meaning of life as lying in some
what is the role of beauty in the life that is growing around us?1 How do we way beyond life, either in the transcendental or in the afterlife. This meaning
distinguish it from its fake versions? And how do we defend it against the is sometimes revealed in the present moment: the moment which people are
surrounding culture? apt to describe as sacred, such as the moment of liturgy and worship, the
I wish to say a few philosophical things before we begin about why moment of revelation or reading a sacred text. And perhaps being blessed
beauty matters. We live in a world in which utilitarian values are not just with that experience is what St. Paul describes (in the words of the prayer
triumphant, but for many people the only values that there are. For such book) as “the peace that passeth understanding”: such a thing involves very
people there seems to be no sense that things can have a value that is not a powerful emotion and a powerful experience—if you can attain it. But we
form of use. This means that all of us are engaged all the time in what some live in a world where not everyone does obtain it or even seek for it. Increas-
philosophers call “instrumental reasoning.” Whenever we are asked to justify ingly the surrounding culture either ignores the sacred or denigrates it. So it
something we try to find a purpose for it. For example, when someone says is very difficult to explain to people who are immersed in the secular culture
“Justify the shape of a particular room at a particular University,” we do so how you would justify the ends of existence and not just the means. I think
in terms of its purpose, which is to gather people together to listen to a lec- this is our situation today.
ture. If it is not very efficient at that, then the room has not actually achieved Take as an example a landscape by Renoir. Whatever is happening
what it set out to achieve. In all our activities we are familiar with this kind in that landscape, it is imbued with a sense of peace and order, and takes
of reasoning. But the question is, why is that the only kind of reasoning? We from the surrounding colors the vitality that brings it to life. But Renoir, like
know perfectly well that it cannot be the only kind because if something is other impressionists, painted a world to which we belong. Belonging is an
a means to an end, there has to be an end that it is a means to, and that too all-important aspect of human experience. Not everybody has it; and our jails
needs a justification. So we do reason with each other about the ends of our are filled with the people who do not. But most of the people reading this,
activity; what our goals are and whether we should be pursuing them. And I imagine, are where they are without having committed a criminal offense
this is especially true in activities such as building or setting out on a career, in and feel that they do instinctively belong in the world and are in the business
which there is a long term project involved and an end point that you cannot of making that belonging more rooted, more permanent, and more wound
very clearly envisage. You know when you set out to build something, you together with the belonging of their fellows; indeed, that is part of what edu-
cannot clearly envisage the endpoint just from a ground plan. You need some cation is about. And that is what you see in a beautiful landscape by a painter
conception of not just what it will look like, but what will it be like to live like Renoir. These are ordinary trees—fruit trees—with an ordinary moun-
with it. And only if you know what it will be like to live with it, will you be tain in the distance, and so on; but the painter shows them as part of a world
justified in building it. to which we belong. And for him—for Renoir and his contemporaries—it is
One reason why modern architecture is such a failure is because a post-religious world. The impressionists were very much a people of their
people do not try to envisage what it will be like to live with the product time, who were skeptical about religion, and in any case, they regarded it as
that they are building. Rather, they think only about its present function and their duty as painters to show that it is this world, not the next that matters.
whether it fulfills it according to the requirements. Reasoning about what it is It is quite hard to paint the next world. It has been done in words by Dan-
like to live with something means bringing the end of your activity forward te, and a few painters have tried to follow him, but for the most part their
efforts have been failures. But nevertheless, our world is not that bad. It is
This essay is based on a transcript of Roger Scruton’s plenary lecture, given
1
imbued with its own tranquility and that tranquility can reside in perception
on September 19th, 2014. A video of the talk can be found at: http://www.faithan-
itself. That is what Renoir is telling us. He says, “ “Stop, stand still, and look.”
dreason.com/2014/12/dr-roger-scruton-beauty-desecration/.
And in that perception, you will see that this thing right in front of you has
© Roger Scruton, Quaestiones Disputatae, Vol. 6, No. 2 (Spring 2016) a meaning all of its own, a meaning that justifies you being in it and reminds
152 Beauty and Desecration Roger Scruton 153
you that you belong to it. So there is a moment of standing still that we all the love aspect. Yet, all our loves create powers, and in all the things that
can achieve and which involves letting the otherness of the world dawn on matter to us most, there is the element of power.
us. The world is other than me—not just imagined by me—but there in front Furthermore, regarding the tranquility that Renoir is trying to put
of me and including me nevertheless. across to us in his painting, many of the literary and artistic critics of today
When painters do this—painters of modern life as Baudelaire calls would ask the questions, “What does this tranquility conceal? Who is using
them—they do not behave as photographers behave. This is something it? Who is gaining? Who is losing?” And you can imagine the text in Modern
which is very difficult to explain to people these days because everybody Language Review which will analyze that painting and try to persuade you that
goes around with a smart phone or some such technological apparatus, im- it is there as part of the hegemony of the bourgeois class, representing nature
mortalizing the ephemera of their existence, and as a result desecrating it as in such a way as to endorse comfortable bourgeois attitudes, excluding
with their own trivial perceptions. Renoir was not doing that at all. He was the truth about labor that went into those fruit trees and to clearing the
not pointing a camera at that landscape; maybe the landscape did not entirely ground in which they were planted; in other words, legitimizing the power
look like that. He was trying to extract from it what it means; and what it of the French Bourgeoisie over the French peasant. In that way, Renoir be-
means not just from the perceptual point of view but spiritually. Now we live comes part of the ideology of western culture, and we need to liberate the
in a time when there is much ugliness and much desecration—in many ways a oppressed victims that this ideology is designed to keep in subjection. When
deliberate making ugly of things, or carelessness as to whether things should you start thinking in this way, nothing is as it seems. Everything dissolves, giv-
be ugly or beautiful. And many things that we regard as beautiful we discover ing way to the reality behind it, which is the power that people exercise over
to be desecrated. Not just by the way we treat them, but also by the works of each other. And that is why beauty is thought to be a kind of deception; it
art that are supposed to celebrate them. We know this from our experience conceals the real relations between people, in which one class, or one person,
of the human form. The human form is all-important to us because it is the or one group, has dominion over another.
primary locus of meaning. It is the thing that means most to us in the world. For the impressionist painters, such thinking is all nonsense. For
The human face and the human body come before us imbued with the life of them, seeming is everything. What Renoir was trying to do with such a paint-
the spirit, but we can also desecrate them as they are desecrated by pornog- ing is to remind you of something which you would otherwise not notice,
raphy, which wipes away the human face from the animal body. And to be in namely, that the world is not concealed by its appearance but revealed in it.
that way turned into an object is essentially to lose one’s spiritual value. The real world, the human world, the world of our moral life and emotional
Now part of what lies behind this is a growing obsession with pow- relations, is the world that comes across to us in our immediate perception,
er. Power is the great commodity that is, as it were, transferred from person when we stop all the instrumental reasoning and forget all the powers and
to person in the world that we are creating. And many people would say, the projects and just look. But because of the obsession with power, people
Look, here is old Scruton communicating his ideas to an audience, cease to look; they wipe away the face of the world so that the way things
enjoying his power. You as my readers are transferring to me that seem is no longer available to them. Their work becomes an assault on beau-
power—the power to hold your attention and to infect you with ty, because it is an assault on the way we represent each other. An example is
my reactionary attitudes. This power is something that I have not a work of art (if you can call it that) called Zygotic acceleration, Biogenetic de-sub-
yet justified and many scholars influenced by people like Foucault limated libidinal model, created by the two brothers Jake and Dinos Chapman.2
would say that I could not justify it. The institution is structured It is quite normal now in British art schools for people to do joint works of
by domination, and I am enjoying that domination—triumphing art like this because that way you get rid of the romantic idea of the artistic
genius who has got something special to say. Instead artists are doing it to-
over you, the victims who are reading this essay.
gether, the purpose in this case being to make the human body into a kind
Now you do not actually believe this because you know that you are sitting of liquid, standing in those childish Mary Jane shoes with all the body parts
and reading willingly—but nevertheless one can re-describe the whole of the deformed (for example, having a penis instead of a nose). These artists were
world in that way; you can take the most innocent thing—for example, the
love of a mother for a child or the child for the mother—and you know that
2
Jake and Dinos Chapman, Zygotic acceleration, Biogentic de-sublimated libidinal
there is power in that too, for if there were not, the mother could not protect model (Enlarged x 1000), 1995, mannequin, mixed media, wigs and trainers, http://
jakeanddinoschapman.com/works/zygotic-acceleration-biogenetic-de-sublimat-
the child, and yet it is not the power aspect of it that is important but rather
ed-libidinal-model-enlarged-x-1000/. (Warning: some graphic content.)
152 Beauty and Desecration Roger Scruton 153
you that you belong to it. So there is a moment of standing still that we all the love aspect. Yet, all our loves create powers, and in all the things that
can achieve and which involves letting the otherness of the world dawn on matter to us most, there is the element of power.
us. The world is other than me—not just imagined by me—but there in front Furthermore, regarding the tranquility that Renoir is trying to put
of me and including me nevertheless. across to us in his painting, many of the literary and artistic critics of today
When painters do this—painters of modern life as Baudelaire calls would ask the questions, “What does this tranquility conceal? Who is using
them—they do not behave as photographers behave. This is something it? Who is gaining? Who is losing?” And you can imagine the text in Modern
which is very difficult to explain to people these days because everybody Language Review which will analyze that painting and try to persuade you that
goes around with a smart phone or some such technological apparatus, im- it is there as part of the hegemony of the bourgeois class, representing nature
mortalizing the ephemera of their existence, and as a result desecrating it as in such a way as to endorse comfortable bourgeois attitudes, excluding
with their own trivial perceptions. Renoir was not doing that at all. He was the truth about labor that went into those fruit trees and to clearing the
not pointing a camera at that landscape; maybe the landscape did not entirely ground in which they were planted; in other words, legitimizing the power
look like that. He was trying to extract from it what it means; and what it of the French Bourgeoisie over the French peasant. In that way, Renoir be-
means not just from the perceptual point of view but spiritually. Now we live comes part of the ideology of western culture, and we need to liberate the
in a time when there is much ugliness and much desecration—in many ways a oppressed victims that this ideology is designed to keep in subjection. When
deliberate making ugly of things, or carelessness as to whether things should you start thinking in this way, nothing is as it seems. Everything dissolves, giv-
be ugly or beautiful. And many things that we regard as beautiful we discover ing way to the reality behind it, which is the power that people exercise over
to be desecrated. Not just by the way we treat them, but also by the works of each other. And that is why beauty is thought to be a kind of deception; it
art that are supposed to celebrate them. We know this from our experience conceals the real relations between people, in which one class, or one person,
of the human form. The human form is all-important to us because it is the or one group, has dominion over another.
primary locus of meaning. It is the thing that means most to us in the world. For the impressionist painters, such thinking is all nonsense. For
The human face and the human body come before us imbued with the life of them, seeming is everything. What Renoir was trying to do with such a paint-
the spirit, but we can also desecrate them as they are desecrated by pornog- ing is to remind you of something which you would otherwise not notice,
raphy, which wipes away the human face from the animal body. And to be in namely, that the world is not concealed by its appearance but revealed in it.
that way turned into an object is essentially to lose one’s spiritual value. The real world, the human world, the world of our moral life and emotional
Now part of what lies behind this is a growing obsession with pow- relations, is the world that comes across to us in our immediate perception,
er. Power is the great commodity that is, as it were, transferred from person when we stop all the instrumental reasoning and forget all the powers and
to person in the world that we are creating. And many people would say, the projects and just look. But because of the obsession with power, people
Look, here is old Scruton communicating his ideas to an audience, cease to look; they wipe away the face of the world so that the way things
enjoying his power. You as my readers are transferring to me that seem is no longer available to them. Their work becomes an assault on beau-
power—the power to hold your attention and to infect you with ty, because it is an assault on the way we represent each other. An example is
my reactionary attitudes. This power is something that I have not a work of art (if you can call it that) called Zygotic acceleration, Biogenetic de-sub-
yet justified and many scholars influenced by people like Foucault limated libidinal model, created by the two brothers Jake and Dinos Chapman.2
would say that I could not justify it. The institution is structured It is quite normal now in British art schools for people to do joint works of
by domination, and I am enjoying that domination—triumphing art like this because that way you get rid of the romantic idea of the artistic
genius who has got something special to say. Instead artists are doing it to-
over you, the victims who are reading this essay.
gether, the purpose in this case being to make the human body into a kind
Now you do not actually believe this because you know that you are sitting of liquid, standing in those childish Mary Jane shoes with all the body parts
and reading willingly—but nevertheless one can re-describe the whole of the deformed (for example, having a penis instead of a nose). These artists were
world in that way; you can take the most innocent thing—for example, the
love of a mother for a child or the child for the mother—and you know that
2
Jake and Dinos Chapman, Zygotic acceleration, Biogentic de-sublimated libidinal
there is power in that too, for if there were not, the mother could not protect model (Enlarged x 1000), 1995, mannequin, mixed media, wigs and trainers, http://
jakeanddinoschapman.com/works/zygotic-acceleration-biogenetic-de-sublimat-
the child, and yet it is not the power aspect of it that is important but rather
ed-libidinal-model-enlarged-x-1000/. (Warning: some graphic content.)
154 Beauty and Desecration Roger Scruton 155
brought up in an art school which told them that the purpose of art is not to spiritual wrestling which we know from Delacroix’s life and from his other
beautify life, or to replace the sacred moment that religion might have given paintings. Delacroix’s Unmade Bed is the record of a battle with fabric—a
us. In no way is art to give us a sense of the meaningfulness of things; on the wrestling with the flexibility of this world and an attempt to impose upon it a
contrary it is there to deconstruct those things, to show that life is essentially meaningful human form.4 It is a testimony to the spiritual life with which we
meaningless. You can best show this by taking the human body and making invest all the objects with which we are in touch. He was looking for a kind of
it repulsive. harmony or order— even a kind of redemption in the shape of those sheets:
We all know of Tracy Emin’s My Bed, which last changed hands at the trace left in them by the spirit, which will include meaning beyond the
two million pounds, in which she presented…well, her bed. After she had present moment. This illustrates the difference between the representation
got out of it of course, with all the debris of her nights dissipation lying on of life—which is also a transfiguration of life into a permanent record of the
the carpet round about. It is in the Tate Modern Gallery now; its permanent spirit—and the mere debris of life. Once you see it, you realize that only the
resting place.3 (Although those sheets are going to rot away quicker than most first of those is a genuine artistic activity.
sheets do.) I want to contrast it with another bed which I mentioned in the However we have entered a period in our history when ugliness
film I made about this: Delacroix’s bed. Delacroix was a great French paint- has become a kind of cult— not ugliness as such but transgressive ugliness,
er from the romantic period who was also a highly learned and interesting like those melted together human figures of the Chapman brothers. It is an
cultural figure—perhaps one of the greatest of nineteenth century cultural ugliness that pollutes or negates some familiar ideal or value. Now trans-
figures in France. Here is his bed (fig. 1). gression has a certain appeal. It is an act of self-affirmation that frees itself
from judgment. The transgressive gesture says “I don’t care if you actually
judge me or not, I’m going to do it, and I’m going to affirm myself against
your judgment.” That is in itself a liberation. I think I have seen this in every
sphere of human endeavor since the 1960s: the assumption of a freedom to
offend. It is the freedom to annihilate other people’s vision of what matters
and to show that the values by which other people live do not count for you.
That is a stage which all of us have to go through at some point in our lives.
We have to fight against our parents, fight against institutions, fight against
the people who seem to be preventing us from being what we truly are and
going out into the world so as to claim it as our own. And in the normal run
of things that is not a particularly bad thing to do, because after all, once you
are out there in the big world feeling the winds of opposition all around, you
realize that you are actually on your own, and it was a terrible mistake to be so
offensive to the people you need. Gradually you work your way back to them,
Fig. (1) Delacroix, An Unmade Bed and reassume possession of them as they do of you; you are reconciled and
forgiven, as in the famous parable of the prodigal son.
It is not an actual bed like Emin’s, but a painting of a bed. In painting it, he So there is a paradox in this position of assuming the freedom to
has tried to transfer into the bed some of his sense of the value of lying offend. It is only because other people’s values count for you that you can
in it and being the thing that wrestled with those sheets. A comparison of be exhilarated by defying them. Nevertheless, this is certainly what artists
these two works helps you to understand what has gone wrong in art today. at a certain stage did. De Kooning was, I guess, a paradigm of this. He is
Tracy Emin’s bed presents itself but offers nothing beyond itself: it is just an artist who has largely been “seen through” now, except in America. And
there. Delacroix’s bed presents something other than itself. The painter’s life the reason why he has not been “seen through” in America is that a lot of
has been translated into those fabrics; a perpetuation in another form of a
Fig. 1: Eugene Delacroix, An Unmade Bed, 1828, watercolor, 18.5 x 29.9
4

Tracy Emin, My Bed, 1998, Mattress, linens, pillows, objects, 79 x 211 x 234
3
cm, New York: Art Resource, http://www.artres.com/C.aspx?VP3=ViewBox_
cm, Staachi Gallery, http://www.saatchigallery.com/artists/artpages/tracey_emin_ VPage&VBID=2UN365NZT2PJC&IT=ZoomImageTemplate01_VForm&I-
my_bed.htm. ID=2UNTWACVPDMF&PN=1&CT=Search&SF=0.
154 Beauty and Desecration Roger Scruton 155
brought up in an art school which told them that the purpose of art is not to spiritual wrestling which we know from Delacroix’s life and from his other
beautify life, or to replace the sacred moment that religion might have given paintings. Delacroix’s Unmade Bed is the record of a battle with fabric—a
us. In no way is art to give us a sense of the meaningfulness of things; on the wrestling with the flexibility of this world and an attempt to impose upon it a
contrary it is there to deconstruct those things, to show that life is essentially meaningful human form.4 It is a testimony to the spiritual life with which we
meaningless. You can best show this by taking the human body and making invest all the objects with which we are in touch. He was looking for a kind of
it repulsive. harmony or order— even a kind of redemption in the shape of those sheets:
We all know of Tracy Emin’s My Bed, which last changed hands at the trace left in them by the spirit, which will include meaning beyond the
two million pounds, in which she presented…well, her bed. After she had present moment. This illustrates the difference between the representation
got out of it of course, with all the debris of her nights dissipation lying on of life—which is also a transfiguration of life into a permanent record of the
the carpet round about. It is in the Tate Modern Gallery now; its permanent spirit—and the mere debris of life. Once you see it, you realize that only the
resting place.3 (Although those sheets are going to rot away quicker than most first of those is a genuine artistic activity.
sheets do.) I want to contrast it with another bed which I mentioned in the However we have entered a period in our history when ugliness
film I made about this: Delacroix’s bed. Delacroix was a great French paint- has become a kind of cult— not ugliness as such but transgressive ugliness,
er from the romantic period who was also a highly learned and interesting like those melted together human figures of the Chapman brothers. It is an
cultural figure—perhaps one of the greatest of nineteenth century cultural ugliness that pollutes or negates some familiar ideal or value. Now trans-
figures in France. Here is his bed (fig. 1). gression has a certain appeal. It is an act of self-affirmation that frees itself
from judgment. The transgressive gesture says “I don’t care if you actually
judge me or not, I’m going to do it, and I’m going to affirm myself against
your judgment.” That is in itself a liberation. I think I have seen this in every
sphere of human endeavor since the 1960s: the assumption of a freedom to
offend. It is the freedom to annihilate other people’s vision of what matters
and to show that the values by which other people live do not count for you.
That is a stage which all of us have to go through at some point in our lives.
We have to fight against our parents, fight against institutions, fight against
the people who seem to be preventing us from being what we truly are and
going out into the world so as to claim it as our own. And in the normal run
of things that is not a particularly bad thing to do, because after all, once you
are out there in the big world feeling the winds of opposition all around, you
realize that you are actually on your own, and it was a terrible mistake to be so
offensive to the people you need. Gradually you work your way back to them,
Fig. (1) Delacroix, An Unmade Bed and reassume possession of them as they do of you; you are reconciled and
forgiven, as in the famous parable of the prodigal son.
It is not an actual bed like Emin’s, but a painting of a bed. In painting it, he So there is a paradox in this position of assuming the freedom to
has tried to transfer into the bed some of his sense of the value of lying offend. It is only because other people’s values count for you that you can
in it and being the thing that wrestled with those sheets. A comparison of be exhilarated by defying them. Nevertheless, this is certainly what artists
these two works helps you to understand what has gone wrong in art today. at a certain stage did. De Kooning was, I guess, a paradigm of this. He is
Tracy Emin’s bed presents itself but offers nothing beyond itself: it is just an artist who has largely been “seen through” now, except in America. And
there. Delacroix’s bed presents something other than itself. The painter’s life the reason why he has not been “seen through” in America is that a lot of
has been translated into those fabrics; a perpetuation in another form of a
Fig. 1: Eugene Delacroix, An Unmade Bed, 1828, watercolor, 18.5 x 29.9
4

Tracy Emin, My Bed, 1998, Mattress, linens, pillows, objects, 79 x 211 x 234
3
cm, New York: Art Resource, http://www.artres.com/C.aspx?VP3=ViewBox_
cm, Staachi Gallery, http://www.saatchigallery.com/artists/artpages/tracey_emin_ VPage&VBID=2UN365NZT2PJC&IT=ZoomImageTemplate01_VForm&I-
my_bed.htm. ID=2UNTWACVPDMF&PN=1&CT=Search&SF=0.
156 Beauty and Desecration Roger Scruton 157
money has been spent on his pictures, so that museum art critics and private culty of emerging from a life of oppression, etc. We have many great works
owners conspire to make sure that they are not going to lose the two million of Romantic art which focus on these very negative aspects of the human
dollars that they spent on whatever masterpiece had been palmed off on condition but which try to find beauty in them nevertheless. All of this is
them. If you can keep the values up, then your museum is still worth what epitomized in Baudelaire’s famous poem Beauty that I recommend you to
you have invested in it. Take De Kooning’s painting entitled Woman.5 It is his read. There was a movement away from the beautiful, and at the same time a
representation of what a woman fundamentally is. All those ideals of wom- fear of the sweetness that beauty can bring into our lives. Is there not a kind
anhood that you might have entertained in your self-deceiving moments are, of deception involved in that? If life really is as bad as we all know it to be,
De Kooning tells you, as nothing beside his representation. His painting gives is art not deceiving us by trying to make us find sweetness and consolation
you the truth of woman. And of course it is a lie. in it? Maybe there is no sweetness and consolation. Maybe art should have
Another instance of this approach to ideals is to be found in modern another role: that of showing the truth to people who would not otherwise
opera productions. Some of you may know the great opera Rusalka by Dvor- be able to perceive it. And if art concentrates on beauty, is it not just going to
ak, which tells the famous story of Undine the water nymph—Rusalka in degenerate into faking things?
the Czech version—who falls in love with a mortal. It is a beautiful romantic I give you a contrast here between two Venuses. Everybody knows
story not only about the mystery of woman but about the traditional demand Botticelli’s The Birth of Venus,6 which I should like to contrast with The Birth
for chastity and purity in preparing a woman for love and the danger in which of Venus by Bouguereau;7 Bouguereau being the famous salon painter of the
she is put by this demand. The demand is symbolized by the fact that she ac- nineteenth century in France who was a wonderfully accomplished painter in
tually is living in the water; if she comes out of it, will that be the end of her? the style of Ingres. A question mark is inevitably placed over him because of
If she tempts the mortal into the water, will that be the end of him, etc? So the sweetness, gentleness and also the perfection of everything he did, which
this story is told many, many times, but never as well as by Dvorak. Recently seemed to many people to be a kind of lying. Baudelaire expressly defended
there has been a production of this opera by Covent Garden (London’s Op- Manet against Bouguereau because Manet was showing us life as it is without
era) in which Rusalka the water nymph—the pure water nymph who dreams any of this cloying sweetness.
of an erotic relation which no water nymph is allowed—is turned into a You all know Botticelli’s Venus (fig. 2).
prostitute and the water is the bath in which she is lying while expecting a
stream of lovers and in which, for reasons that cannot be explained, she sings
an aria to the moon. This kind of desecration is a very ordinary occurrence in
opera productions today. The idea in the minds of so many opera producers
when asked to produce a romantic fairy tale is to bring in sex and violence in
order that the audience of ordinary middle class people, who spent a couple
hundred dollars for their tickets, can be given a hard time. They came there
for this beautiful romantic legend—and they will not come again—but you
have got them for a couple of hours. So insult them while you can.
Why did all this come about? I think that we cannot understand the
great movement to desecrate works of art if we do not attend a little bit to
the phenomenon of kitsch, and the distrust of beauty that arose because of
kitsch. In the Romantic Movement—which dominated all of art through the
nineteenth century—there grew a certain suspicion of beauty; the homely Fig. (2) Botticelli, Venus
sort of beauty that appeals to ordinary people and does not seem to threat-
en them. There was a movement toward the sublime: great tragedies rather
6
Fig. 3: Sandro Botticelli, The Birth of Venus, c1486, tempera on panel, 172.5
than sweet fairy tales, emphasizing the difficulties of human life, the diffi- x 278.5 cm, Uffizi Gallery, http://www.uffizi.org/artworks/the-birth-of-venus-by-
sandro-botticelli/.
7
Fig. 4: William-Adolphe Bouguereau, The Birth of Venus, 1879, oil on canvas,
William De Kooning, Woman, I, 1950–52, oil on canvas, 192.7 x 147.3 cm,
5
300 x 218 cm, Musée D’Orsay, http://www.musee-orsay.fr/en/collections/index-
MoMA, http://www.moma.org/collection/works/79810. of-works/notice.html?nnumid=016649%7C.
156 Beauty and Desecration Roger Scruton 157
money has been spent on his pictures, so that museum art critics and private culty of emerging from a life of oppression, etc. We have many great works
owners conspire to make sure that they are not going to lose the two million of Romantic art which focus on these very negative aspects of the human
dollars that they spent on whatever masterpiece had been palmed off on condition but which try to find beauty in them nevertheless. All of this is
them. If you can keep the values up, then your museum is still worth what epitomized in Baudelaire’s famous poem Beauty that I recommend you to
you have invested in it. Take De Kooning’s painting entitled Woman.5 It is his read. There was a movement away from the beautiful, and at the same time a
representation of what a woman fundamentally is. All those ideals of wom- fear of the sweetness that beauty can bring into our lives. Is there not a kind
anhood that you might have entertained in your self-deceiving moments are, of deception involved in that? If life really is as bad as we all know it to be,
De Kooning tells you, as nothing beside his representation. His painting gives is art not deceiving us by trying to make us find sweetness and consolation
you the truth of woman. And of course it is a lie. in it? Maybe there is no sweetness and consolation. Maybe art should have
Another instance of this approach to ideals is to be found in modern another role: that of showing the truth to people who would not otherwise
opera productions. Some of you may know the great opera Rusalka by Dvor- be able to perceive it. And if art concentrates on beauty, is it not just going to
ak, which tells the famous story of Undine the water nymph—Rusalka in degenerate into faking things?
the Czech version—who falls in love with a mortal. It is a beautiful romantic I give you a contrast here between two Venuses. Everybody knows
story not only about the mystery of woman but about the traditional demand Botticelli’s The Birth of Venus,6 which I should like to contrast with The Birth
for chastity and purity in preparing a woman for love and the danger in which of Venus by Bouguereau;7 Bouguereau being the famous salon painter of the
she is put by this demand. The demand is symbolized by the fact that she ac- nineteenth century in France who was a wonderfully accomplished painter in
tually is living in the water; if she comes out of it, will that be the end of her? the style of Ingres. A question mark is inevitably placed over him because of
If she tempts the mortal into the water, will that be the end of him, etc? So the sweetness, gentleness and also the perfection of everything he did, which
this story is told many, many times, but never as well as by Dvorak. Recently seemed to many people to be a kind of lying. Baudelaire expressly defended
there has been a production of this opera by Covent Garden (London’s Op- Manet against Bouguereau because Manet was showing us life as it is without
era) in which Rusalka the water nymph—the pure water nymph who dreams any of this cloying sweetness.
of an erotic relation which no water nymph is allowed—is turned into a You all know Botticelli’s Venus (fig. 2).
prostitute and the water is the bath in which she is lying while expecting a
stream of lovers and in which, for reasons that cannot be explained, she sings
an aria to the moon. This kind of desecration is a very ordinary occurrence in
opera productions today. The idea in the minds of so many opera producers
when asked to produce a romantic fairy tale is to bring in sex and violence in
order that the audience of ordinary middle class people, who spent a couple
hundred dollars for their tickets, can be given a hard time. They came there
for this beautiful romantic legend—and they will not come again—but you
have got them for a couple of hours. So insult them while you can.
Why did all this come about? I think that we cannot understand the
great movement to desecrate works of art if we do not attend a little bit to
the phenomenon of kitsch, and the distrust of beauty that arose because of
kitsch. In the Romantic Movement—which dominated all of art through the
nineteenth century—there grew a certain suspicion of beauty; the homely Fig. (2) Botticelli, Venus
sort of beauty that appeals to ordinary people and does not seem to threat-
en them. There was a movement toward the sublime: great tragedies rather
6
Fig. 3: Sandro Botticelli, The Birth of Venus, c1486, tempera on panel, 172.5
than sweet fairy tales, emphasizing the difficulties of human life, the diffi- x 278.5 cm, Uffizi Gallery, http://www.uffizi.org/artworks/the-birth-of-venus-by-
sandro-botticelli/.
7
Fig. 4: William-Adolphe Bouguereau, The Birth of Venus, 1879, oil on canvas,
William De Kooning, Woman, I, 1950–52, oil on canvas, 192.7 x 147.3 cm,
5
300 x 218 cm, Musée D’Orsay, http://www.musee-orsay.fr/en/collections/index-
MoMA, http://www.moma.org/collection/works/79810. of-works/notice.html?nnumid=016649%7C.
158 Beauty and Desecration Roger Scruton 159
First is to try and find a way to produce real art that is not kitsch. That is a re-
In that face, you see a particular conception of the erotic. Botticelli was a ally hard thing to do; producing art that does not have this fake character, that
Platonist who believed as Plato did that beauty is an object of desire, but also is not just childish, that is not a Christmas decoration. Or you can do what
a gateway to the transcendental. You understand what beauty really is if you Jeff Koons does, which is to produce something which is so obviously kitsch
follow through that gateway, leave behind your earthly desires, and unite with that nobody could ever accuse you of being taken in by it. For example, his
the spiritual condition from which they originally spring. This face for him Balloon Dog8 sculpture is such obvious kitsch that we feel he must be making
was not an object of sexual interest, but a stimulus to transcending all such a deeper point by producing it. Nobody has ever discovered what that deeper
sensual emotions. The model for his Venus was Simonetta Vespucci, who point is, but there it is, desecrating a beautiful classical façade, probably for
was the mistress of his prince and therefore unobtainable anyway. But she many years to come.
was for Botticelli a symbol of the erotic as Plato conceived it, as an impulse The causes of the situation in which we find ourselves go deep.
rooted in the flesh that must be transcended into the spiritual. We have acquired a distrust of beauty (or many people have). Many artists
Bouguereau’s birth of Venus, as you see (fig. 3), is all perfection of have acquired this distrust because beauty is an invitation into realms that
form but with no such transcendental meaning. have been mined. There are traps there. You might fall into the trap of Bou-
guereau. However beautiful your human figures may be, they turn out in the
end just to be your standard “Christmas card porn”. The reality slips away
from you and you are left with a fake. There is an attempt to show that you
are a genuine artist by producing something that nobody could possibly like,
because that will prove that you must be serious. And there are consolations
also in ugliness, when it is used to show that life does not matter anyway.
That is the meaning of the Chapman brothers’ sculpture: “life is simply a
nothingness. We happen to have been born and will die, decay, and disappear
and so what?” There is a charm in that view; a charm which I call the ‘charm
of disenchantment.’ Being disenchanted with things gives you a kind of
glamour. You know if you go around a room of people who are exclaiming
“oooh!” and “ahhh!” in the face of kitsch, then being disenchanted gives you
a kind of distinction. You are the one who is not saying “oooh!” or “ahhh!”.
I think that many artists aspire to the distinction of “not being taken in” so
to speak—of not being duped by the surrounding culture of fakes, while
producing indecipheable fakes of their own.
Added to this is a desire to desecrate the old values by putting graf-
fiti on things, such as a moustache on the Mona Lisa.9 When that moustache
was first put on the Mona Lisa by Marcel Duchamp he was saying “We’ve
Fig. (3) Bouguereau, Birth of Venus gone beyond that. That’s all nonsense. You might be taken in by that but I’m
not.” But ever since that gesture about a hundred years ago, much of the art
She is sniffing her freshly shaven armpit, waiting for the lover who is going to that we have come across (at least from the art schools) amounts to putting
come through the bathroom door, and obviously she will have to get rid of another moustache on the Mona Lisa. The question automatically arises as
the company meanwhile. Bougereau was a great master of color and form,
but somehow the sentiment is fake. This is not a real Venus. This is sexuality
8
Jeff Koons, Balloon Dog, 1994–2004, mirror-polished stainless steel with
in its ordinary vulgar form without any of Boticelli’s attempt to show the transparent coating, 307.3 x 363.2 x 114.3 cm, http://www.jeffkoons.com/artwork/
celebration/balloon-dog-0.
meaning of it or of its reflection in the transcendental. 9
Marcel Duchamp, L.H.O.O.Q., 1919, rectified readymade: pencil on repro-
Desecration takes many forms. If we worry about kitsch, which all duction of Leonardo Davinci’s Mona Lisa, 19.7 x 12.4 cm, Musée National d’Art
painters today do, what do we do about it? There are roughly two responses. Moderne (on loan), https://www.nga.gov/images/decor/dadainfo_fs.shtm.
158 Beauty and Desecration Roger Scruton 159
First is to try and find a way to produce real art that is not kitsch. That is a re-
In that face, you see a particular conception of the erotic. Botticelli was a ally hard thing to do; producing art that does not have this fake character, that
Platonist who believed as Plato did that beauty is an object of desire, but also is not just childish, that is not a Christmas decoration. Or you can do what
a gateway to the transcendental. You understand what beauty really is if you Jeff Koons does, which is to produce something which is so obviously kitsch
follow through that gateway, leave behind your earthly desires, and unite with that nobody could ever accuse you of being taken in by it. For example, his
the spiritual condition from which they originally spring. This face for him Balloon Dog8 sculpture is such obvious kitsch that we feel he must be making
was not an object of sexual interest, but a stimulus to transcending all such a deeper point by producing it. Nobody has ever discovered what that deeper
sensual emotions. The model for his Venus was Simonetta Vespucci, who point is, but there it is, desecrating a beautiful classical façade, probably for
was the mistress of his prince and therefore unobtainable anyway. But she many years to come.
was for Botticelli a symbol of the erotic as Plato conceived it, as an impulse The causes of the situation in which we find ourselves go deep.
rooted in the flesh that must be transcended into the spiritual. We have acquired a distrust of beauty (or many people have). Many artists
Bouguereau’s birth of Venus, as you see (fig. 3), is all perfection of have acquired this distrust because beauty is an invitation into realms that
form but with no such transcendental meaning. have been mined. There are traps there. You might fall into the trap of Bou-
guereau. However beautiful your human figures may be, they turn out in the
end just to be your standard “Christmas card porn”. The reality slips away
from you and you are left with a fake. There is an attempt to show that you
are a genuine artist by producing something that nobody could possibly like,
because that will prove that you must be serious. And there are consolations
also in ugliness, when it is used to show that life does not matter anyway.
That is the meaning of the Chapman brothers’ sculpture: “life is simply a
nothingness. We happen to have been born and will die, decay, and disappear
and so what?” There is a charm in that view; a charm which I call the ‘charm
of disenchantment.’ Being disenchanted with things gives you a kind of
glamour. You know if you go around a room of people who are exclaiming
“oooh!” and “ahhh!” in the face of kitsch, then being disenchanted gives you
a kind of distinction. You are the one who is not saying “oooh!” or “ahhh!”.
I think that many artists aspire to the distinction of “not being taken in” so
to speak—of not being duped by the surrounding culture of fakes, while
producing indecipheable fakes of their own.
Added to this is a desire to desecrate the old values by putting graf-
fiti on things, such as a moustache on the Mona Lisa.9 When that moustache
was first put on the Mona Lisa by Marcel Duchamp he was saying “We’ve
Fig. (3) Bouguereau, Birth of Venus gone beyond that. That’s all nonsense. You might be taken in by that but I’m
not.” But ever since that gesture about a hundred years ago, much of the art
She is sniffing her freshly shaven armpit, waiting for the lover who is going to that we have come across (at least from the art schools) amounts to putting
come through the bathroom door, and obviously she will have to get rid of another moustache on the Mona Lisa. The question automatically arises as
the company meanwhile. Bougereau was a great master of color and form,
but somehow the sentiment is fake. This is not a real Venus. This is sexuality
8
Jeff Koons, Balloon Dog, 1994–2004, mirror-polished stainless steel with
in its ordinary vulgar form without any of Boticelli’s attempt to show the transparent coating, 307.3 x 363.2 x 114.3 cm, http://www.jeffkoons.com/artwork/
celebration/balloon-dog-0.
meaning of it or of its reflection in the transcendental. 9
Marcel Duchamp, L.H.O.O.Q., 1919, rectified readymade: pencil on repro-
Desecration takes many forms. If we worry about kitsch, which all duction of Leonardo Davinci’s Mona Lisa, 19.7 x 12.4 cm, Musée National d’Art
painters today do, what do we do about it? There are roughly two responses. Moderne (on loan), https://www.nga.gov/images/decor/dadainfo_fs.shtm.
160 Beauty and Desecration Roger Scruton 161
to whether there is any point in doing it twice, let alone a thousand times. this color fit with that color?” and so on. And I think people take revenge
The thought behind all this is that we have asked too much of art. We have on beauty because they do not see that there is something more important
asked it to be a substitute for religion; to be the light from, and the window without which there can be no revenge. That more important thing is just the
on to, the transcendental. If it disappoints us in accomplishing this, then we instinct to get things right, to make things fit in and harmonize. And this is
become in a certain way angry with it. Disappointment turns to repudiation. where aesthetic judgment is a fundamental part of our everyday lives. We are
So what is the mission of art? Is there a mission that we can still engaged in it all the time. Now I am not a natty dresser, but even I have the
maintain? I do believe that we all have a need for redemption, and I do not question whether this tie goes with that jacket; it occupies me for a certain
mean that necessarily in the religious sense. I mean that we need actions, amount of time, and it is a part of my attempt to fit in and harmonize, and
gestures, plans, and projects to have a fulfillment of some kind, to lift us out to fit into a given occasion.
of the day-to-day appetites that otherwise swallow us. All of our actions aim You could put it, however, in a much more pretentious philosophical
towards this. They aim beyond themselves to a point of rest in which we can way by saying that when we do this we are trying to realize ourselves as sub-
look back and endorse what we have done. This is so obviously the case with jects in the realm of objects. That is the language that Hegel and his followers
human relations—especially love relations. It is there in all of our lives. A life would use. The point is this. We are free beings. We are subjects who have
without this and without ideals gets tired of itself. When people are set on an inner life; but that inner life is not meaningful to us if we cannot in some
the path of transgression it is partly because they have become disappointed way make it into an outward reality among other outward realities. In all our
with the possibility of actually achieving this sort of redemption. So, where gestures we are trying to become a real part of things; to belong, in other
then does beauty fit into this and what can it actually do by way of satisfying words. This process of ‘realization’ is something that goes on all the time and
our desire to be rescued from the world of appetite? all rational beings are engaged in it. Children know about it already, and we
I have argued that the search for beauty is the search for a home, see this when children are doing simple social and domestic things, like set-
for a place where you can be at home with yourself and with others, a place ting the table for dinner. On such occasions you see what Wittgenstein would
where you belong. This is going back to the Renoir landscape; a landscape call ‘the natural expression of aesthetic judgment.’ There they are trying to
as a thing that we belong to. Being at home means being at home with your- fit things into the right place on the table. They are not saying to themselves
self, and that means seeing yourself in some way as another, as another per- “Is this beautiful? Is this ugly?” or anything like that. Those words are not
son. Seeing yourself from outside, not just as this selfish self-involved thing part of their vocabulary probably; but they are asking themselves the ques-
that you are familiar with when you wake up in the morning, but that other tion “Is this right? Am I getting it right? Should it be a little bit more to the
thing that you were when you went to bed— the thing that has spent a day left?” You see in the intent expression something only human beings mani-
with other people. And you want to be at home with what you find. And I fest. No animals manifest this sense of the rightness and the wrongness of
think this search for being at home does not start with high art, nor does it things, because if they reason at all they reason instrumentally. The children
end there. One of the reasons why people have become so confused about have gone completely beyond the whole idea of the instrumental function
beauty is because they have constantly taken their examples from the realm of these things. They have tried to fit things together so that they look right,
of high art: those great and difficult things like Botticelli’s Venus, which you and so the guests will find that they look right too. That is the beginnings of
have to think about for a long time before you know what they mean. High the aesthetic attitude.
art challenges us in the deepest parts of our being, and maybe we feel turned We do not accept our world as simply a thing that is there, an assem-
off by it since we cannot live up to it, so we seek to live in another way. But bly of objects. We try to adorn it and to fit it to ourselves and us to it. We are
that is not where the search for beauty begins, nor is it where it ends. always aware of the distinction between things standing out and things fitting
I think it begins, and ends, with everyday life. People misconceive in. Sometimes it is right for them to stand out, and sometimes it is wrong.
aesthetics when they see it merely as the realm of beauty, as though that is all Fitting in is one of the most important aspects of our life in every sphere
we were ever really thinking about. When we go around the world, making of human endeavor. We all have a need to be a part of something greater
aesthetic judgments, it is not all “Oh yes! That’s beautiful…. No that’s ugly, than ourselves. In many areas there is a distinction between looking right
etc.” That’s not the way we behave at all. We actually make completely dif- and being right; but one of the important features of the aesthetic is that the
ferent kinds of judgments. We talk about whether something fits in, whether distinction between looking and being gets collapsed. For the children setting
it is graceful, whether that would be the right way to go forward, “Does the table there is not a distinction between the plate being in the right place
160 Beauty and Desecration Roger Scruton 161
to whether there is any point in doing it twice, let alone a thousand times. this color fit with that color?” and so on. And I think people take revenge
The thought behind all this is that we have asked too much of art. We have on beauty because they do not see that there is something more important
asked it to be a substitute for religion; to be the light from, and the window without which there can be no revenge. That more important thing is just the
on to, the transcendental. If it disappoints us in accomplishing this, then we instinct to get things right, to make things fit in and harmonize. And this is
become in a certain way angry with it. Disappointment turns to repudiation. where aesthetic judgment is a fundamental part of our everyday lives. We are
So what is the mission of art? Is there a mission that we can still engaged in it all the time. Now I am not a natty dresser, but even I have the
maintain? I do believe that we all have a need for redemption, and I do not question whether this tie goes with that jacket; it occupies me for a certain
mean that necessarily in the religious sense. I mean that we need actions, amount of time, and it is a part of my attempt to fit in and harmonize, and
gestures, plans, and projects to have a fulfillment of some kind, to lift us out to fit into a given occasion.
of the day-to-day appetites that otherwise swallow us. All of our actions aim You could put it, however, in a much more pretentious philosophical
towards this. They aim beyond themselves to a point of rest in which we can way by saying that when we do this we are trying to realize ourselves as sub-
look back and endorse what we have done. This is so obviously the case with jects in the realm of objects. That is the language that Hegel and his followers
human relations—especially love relations. It is there in all of our lives. A life would use. The point is this. We are free beings. We are subjects who have
without this and without ideals gets tired of itself. When people are set on an inner life; but that inner life is not meaningful to us if we cannot in some
the path of transgression it is partly because they have become disappointed way make it into an outward reality among other outward realities. In all our
with the possibility of actually achieving this sort of redemption. So, where gestures we are trying to become a real part of things; to belong, in other
then does beauty fit into this and what can it actually do by way of satisfying words. This process of ‘realization’ is something that goes on all the time and
our desire to be rescued from the world of appetite? all rational beings are engaged in it. Children know about it already, and we
I have argued that the search for beauty is the search for a home, see this when children are doing simple social and domestic things, like set-
for a place where you can be at home with yourself and with others, a place ting the table for dinner. On such occasions you see what Wittgenstein would
where you belong. This is going back to the Renoir landscape; a landscape call ‘the natural expression of aesthetic judgment.’ There they are trying to
as a thing that we belong to. Being at home means being at home with your- fit things into the right place on the table. They are not saying to themselves
self, and that means seeing yourself in some way as another, as another per- “Is this beautiful? Is this ugly?” or anything like that. Those words are not
son. Seeing yourself from outside, not just as this selfish self-involved thing part of their vocabulary probably; but they are asking themselves the ques-
that you are familiar with when you wake up in the morning, but that other tion “Is this right? Am I getting it right? Should it be a little bit more to the
thing that you were when you went to bed— the thing that has spent a day left?” You see in the intent expression something only human beings mani-
with other people. And you want to be at home with what you find. And I fest. No animals manifest this sense of the rightness and the wrongness of
think this search for being at home does not start with high art, nor does it things, because if they reason at all they reason instrumentally. The children
end there. One of the reasons why people have become so confused about have gone completely beyond the whole idea of the instrumental function
beauty is because they have constantly taken their examples from the realm of these things. They have tried to fit things together so that they look right,
of high art: those great and difficult things like Botticelli’s Venus, which you and so the guests will find that they look right too. That is the beginnings of
have to think about for a long time before you know what they mean. High the aesthetic attitude.
art challenges us in the deepest parts of our being, and maybe we feel turned We do not accept our world as simply a thing that is there, an assem-
off by it since we cannot live up to it, so we seek to live in another way. But bly of objects. We try to adorn it and to fit it to ourselves and us to it. We are
that is not where the search for beauty begins, nor is it where it ends. always aware of the distinction between things standing out and things fitting
I think it begins, and ends, with everyday life. People misconceive in. Sometimes it is right for them to stand out, and sometimes it is wrong.
aesthetics when they see it merely as the realm of beauty, as though that is all Fitting in is one of the most important aspects of our life in every sphere
we were ever really thinking about. When we go around the world, making of human endeavor. We all have a need to be a part of something greater
aesthetic judgments, it is not all “Oh yes! That’s beautiful…. No that’s ugly, than ourselves. In many areas there is a distinction between looking right
etc.” That’s not the way we behave at all. We actually make completely dif- and being right; but one of the important features of the aesthetic is that the
ferent kinds of judgments. We talk about whether something fits in, whether distinction between looking and being gets collapsed. For the children setting
it is graceful, whether that would be the right way to go forward, “Does the table there is not a distinction between the plate being in the right place
162 Beauty and Desecration Roger Scruton 163
and looking to be in the right place. Rather, being and seeming have come we are free beings, but we also know that freedom demands recognition.
together. And that is something that is really important for us: to live in world This is something that Hegel emphasized and it is something that has to be
where every now and then being and seeming coincide, so that nothing, as it re-expressed in every generation. We are not truly free until others recognize
were, deceives us anymore. This is the great social significance of the aesthet- that we are free and grant us the space to be free, and that means that we are
ic. We live in a world which has been in many ways uglified and it is a world in relations of mutuality with each other. My freedom is always, as it were,
that we want to redeem, so that we are part of it once again. Our fulfillment rubbing up against the edge of your freedom and that boundary between us
is, as it were, reflected back to us from all the things that we encounter. That is the public world where we both belong, and it is in shaping that boundary
is part of what I mean by redemption, and why I say that redemption is one between us that the aesthetic sense is so important. That is where in our
function of the aesthetic. search for recognition from each other we attempt to be graceful towards
No matter what circumstances you are in, even if you are living in a each other and to bring each other to our side. I bring you to my side and
trailer park, you can do things right. You go to your local timber merchant, you bring me to your side so that the boundary where we coincide is mutu-
and you buy the Georgian windows to replace the rubbish that would other- ally acceptable. This practice, which might reasonably be called “grace”, is a
wise be there—you build a little cornice, and so on. Even when there is a lot matter of harmony and fitting in. Of course it cannot be achieved without
of money involved you can get things totally wrong, and there are plenty of the habit of giving and receiving. I give way to you and you give way to me.
examples to illustrate this. I offer you things and you receive them, and so on. This is what the public
In the town center of Reading in England there is a development world ideally should be, and that kind of giving and receiving things is what
that is built entirely out of horizontals, and nobody wants to live there. The should be embodied in our ideal forms of architecture. And it is in this search
center of Reading was destroyed completely by this development and it is to- for a mutual boundary, where we can stand and face each other and recognize
day standing totally empty, vandalized and covered in graffiti. This emphasis each other’s freedom, that is the true goal of aesthetic judgment, the source
on the horizontal was originally a very aesthetic thing, which came in with the of its redemptive power, and the reason why beauty matters.
architectural modernists, and in particular with the writings of Le Corbusier.
But even the modernists recognized, in the end, that vertical lines are the
frame that every building needs. Here is an example of a perfected modernist
interior, which is Wittgenstein’s house in Vienna which he designed for his
sister.10 And Wittgenstein, like me, had the sense that architecture ultimately
must get the vertical emphasis right; must make verticals stand parallel to
each other. And it is this sense of detail that matters. This is not my preferred
form of architecture really, but you can see the aesthetic instinct at work in
everything in this building. He designed it for his sister, who never lived in
it, and it ended up as the embassy of a communist country for which it is
wonderfully suited. An example of what architects really can do can be found
in the church of S Maria della Pace in Rome, by Pietro da Cortona, where
you see the desire to fit things together, and how a building comes alive and
captures the light of the sun so as to incorporate that light into itself, making
it part of its own spirit, so to speak.
The previous few examples are just taken from the air, but they are
meant to emphasize the place of aesthetic judgment—of our desire to get
things right—in our ordinary everyday life and in the life of our enterprisers,
builders, and dwellers; in the lives of people who settle down. We know that

10
An image can be found at: http://www.arch.virginia.edu/files/uploads/
Wittgst_freilerwithname.jpg
162 Beauty and Desecration Roger Scruton 163
and looking to be in the right place. Rather, being and seeming have come we are free beings, but we also know that freedom demands recognition.
together. And that is something that is really important for us: to live in world This is something that Hegel emphasized and it is something that has to be
where every now and then being and seeming coincide, so that nothing, as it re-expressed in every generation. We are not truly free until others recognize
were, deceives us anymore. This is the great social significance of the aesthet- that we are free and grant us the space to be free, and that means that we are
ic. We live in a world which has been in many ways uglified and it is a world in relations of mutuality with each other. My freedom is always, as it were,
that we want to redeem, so that we are part of it once again. Our fulfillment rubbing up against the edge of your freedom and that boundary between us
is, as it were, reflected back to us from all the things that we encounter. That is the public world where we both belong, and it is in shaping that boundary
is part of what I mean by redemption, and why I say that redemption is one between us that the aesthetic sense is so important. That is where in our
function of the aesthetic. search for recognition from each other we attempt to be graceful towards
No matter what circumstances you are in, even if you are living in a each other and to bring each other to our side. I bring you to my side and
trailer park, you can do things right. You go to your local timber merchant, you bring me to your side so that the boundary where we coincide is mutu-
and you buy the Georgian windows to replace the rubbish that would other- ally acceptable. This practice, which might reasonably be called “grace”, is a
wise be there—you build a little cornice, and so on. Even when there is a lot matter of harmony and fitting in. Of course it cannot be achieved without
of money involved you can get things totally wrong, and there are plenty of the habit of giving and receiving. I give way to you and you give way to me.
examples to illustrate this. I offer you things and you receive them, and so on. This is what the public
In the town center of Reading in England there is a development world ideally should be, and that kind of giving and receiving things is what
that is built entirely out of horizontals, and nobody wants to live there. The should be embodied in our ideal forms of architecture. And it is in this search
center of Reading was destroyed completely by this development and it is to- for a mutual boundary, where we can stand and face each other and recognize
day standing totally empty, vandalized and covered in graffiti. This emphasis each other’s freedom, that is the true goal of aesthetic judgment, the source
on the horizontal was originally a very aesthetic thing, which came in with the of its redemptive power, and the reason why beauty matters.
architectural modernists, and in particular with the writings of Le Corbusier.
But even the modernists recognized, in the end, that vertical lines are the
frame that every building needs. Here is an example of a perfected modernist
interior, which is Wittgenstein’s house in Vienna which he designed for his
sister.10 And Wittgenstein, like me, had the sense that architecture ultimately
must get the vertical emphasis right; must make verticals stand parallel to
each other. And it is this sense of detail that matters. This is not my preferred
form of architecture really, but you can see the aesthetic instinct at work in
everything in this building. He designed it for his sister, who never lived in
it, and it ended up as the embassy of a communist country for which it is
wonderfully suited. An example of what architects really can do can be found
in the church of S Maria della Pace in Rome, by Pietro da Cortona, where
you see the desire to fit things together, and how a building comes alive and
captures the light of the sun so as to incorporate that light into itself, making
it part of its own spirit, so to speak.
The previous few examples are just taken from the air, but they are
meant to emphasize the place of aesthetic judgment—of our desire to get
things right—in our ordinary everyday life and in the life of our enterprisers,
builders, and dwellers; in the lives of people who settle down. We know that

10
An image can be found at: http://www.arch.virginia.edu/files/uploads/
Wittgst_freilerwithname.jpg
Illustrations

Meldrum, Beauty as Anomoly

Fig. 1–2 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
Piero della Francesca, Finding and Prooving of the True Cross, c. 1460, fresco, 356
x 747 cm, Arezzo, San Francesco.

Fig. 3–4 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
Georges Seurat, A Sunday Afternoon on the Island of La Grande Jatte, 1884–1886,
oil on canvas, 207.6 × 308 cm, Art Institute of Chicago.

Fig. 5 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
Georges Seurat, Man standing next to a tree; study on La Grande Jatte, 1884–1885,
pencil on paper, Von Der Heydt-Museum, Wuppertal, Photo © DeAgostini/
Getty Images.

Fig. 6 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
Georgio Morandi, Still Life, 1953, oil on canvas, 20.32 x 40.3225 cm, acquired
1954, The Phillips Collection, Washington, D.C. © 2015 Artists Rights Soci-
ety (ARS), New York / SIAE, Rome.

Fig. 7 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
William Bailey, Mercatile Still Life, 1981, oil and wax on canvas, 76.2 x 101.6
cm, MoMA, New York © 2016 William Bailey.

Scruton, Beauty and Desecration

Fig. 1 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
Eugene Delacroix, An Unmade Bed, 1828, watercolor, 18.5 x 29.9 cm, Musée
Eugene Delacroix, Paris, France © RMN-Grand Palais / Art Resource, NY.

Fig. 2 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
Sandro Botticelli, Birth of Venus, 1482–1485, tempera on panel, 172.5 x 278.9
cm, Uffizi Gallery, Florence.

Fig. 3 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
William-Adolphe Bouguereau, Birth of Venus, 1879, oil on canvas, 300 x 218
cm, Musée d’Orsay, Paris, France.
Quaestiones Disputatae Quaestiones Disputatae is a journal of philosophy inspired by the medieval
dialectical form of the “disputed question”: a method of philosophical dis-
Editor: cussion aimed at addressing the relevant issues of the time. In the spirit of
Alex Plato, Franciscan University of Steubenville the medieval quaestiones disputatae, this journal addresses significant questions
and topics of contemporary philosophic interest. Recognizing that signifi-
Assistant Editor: cant philosophical contributions are found among philosophers of various
Kevin F. Kwasnik, Franciscan University of Steubenville backgrounds and outlooks, the journal is, therefore, not limited to a particu-
lar period of philosophy, nor is it representative of a specific philosophic
Editorial Assistant: school or point of view.
Jacob Smith, Franciscan University of Steubenville
Each issue has a special theme. An issue may focus on a topic in a particular
Board of Advisors: area of philosophy, such as logic, philosophy of science, political philosophy,
or aesthetics; on the work of a significant philosopher such as Proclus, Duns
Joseph M. Boyle, University of Toronto Scotus, or Husserl; on the examination and study of an important text of
John Deely, University of St. Thomas, Houston philosophy such as the Enneads of Plotinus, or Formalism in Ethics and Non-
Alfred Fredosso, University of Notre Dame Formal Ethics of Values by Max Scheler; or on the valuable contributions of a
Robert P. George, Princeton University particular philosophical school or movement such as Cambridge Platonism,
Stephen Gersh, University of Notre Dame Scottish Realism, or Paduan Aristotelianism.
Christina M. Gschwandtner, University of Scranton
Siobhan Nash-Marshall, Manhattanville College Quaestiones Disputatae aims at a genuine philosophia perennis that respects the
Timothy Noone, Catholic University of America tradition of philosophy but also recognizes philosophy to be a dynamic and
Giorgio E. Pini, Fordham University progressive discipline, one that is more than its history. In this way, it can be
Nicholas Rescher, University of Pittsburgh a forum for philosophers to discuss and share their work, and to participate
Linda Zagzebski, University of Oklahoma in a meaningful dialogue with others.

Subscription Information:

We are pleased to announce that The Catholic University of America Press will Contact Information:
be managing subscriptions to Quaestiones Disputatae beginning this fall (2014). All correspondence concerning Quaestiones Disputatae, submissions, or the
Those interested in subscribing may inquire at http://cuapress.cua.edu/ Annual Conference in Christian Philosophy hosted by Franciscan University
journals/quaestionesdisputatae.cfm, via email at jrnlcirc@press.jhu.edu, or of Steubenville should be directed to:
by calling 1-800-548-1784. Individual subscriptions are $40 per year and
institutional subscriptions are $100 per year. Single issues are $20 for
individuals and $60 per issue for institutions. No additional shipping and Alex Plato, Editor
handling costs for U.S. purchases, but please add $15 for international shipping. Quaestiones Disputatae
Discover, MasterCard, Visa or American Express are accepted. Residents of Franciscan University of Steubenville
MD, VA, and DC should add applicable taxes. Quaestiones Disputatae is also 1235 University Blvd
available electronically through The Philosophy Documentation Center at Steubenville, OH 43952
http://www.pdcnet.org/qd. Checks may be made out to “The Catholic qdphilosophyjournal@gmail.com
University of America Press” and sent to:
Quaestiones Disputatae
P.O. Box 19966 Copyright © 2016 Quaestiones Disputatae
Baltimore, MD 21211-0966 ISSN: 2150-5756
Quaestiones
Quaestiones Disputatae
Franciscan University of Steubenville

Quaestiones
Disputatae
1235 University Blvd

Disputatae
Steubenville, OH 43952

www.quaestionesdisputatae.com

The Power of Beauty


Selected Papers on
A Journal of
Philosophical Inquiry the Power of Beauty
and Discussion

Issue Edited by
Theresa Farnan
Volume 6
N o. 2

ISSN: 2150-5756 Volume 6, No. 2 Spring 2016

You might also like