You are on page 1of 18

The Propaganda of the Deed: Terrorism,

Counterterrorism, and Mobilization


Ethan Bueno de Mesquita Washington University
Eric S. Dickson New York University

Many terrorist factions care about the level of popular support they enjoy within a population they claim to represent.
Empirically, this level of support can either rise or fall in the aftermath of a campaign of terrorist violence. Under what
circumstances is the use of terror an effective tactic for mobilizing political support for an extremist group? This article
models a scenario in which an extremist faction considers attacking a government in the hopes of provoking a counterterror
response that will radicalize the population, increasing the extremists’ support at the expense of a more moderate faction.
In our scenario, such radicalization can result either from the economic damage caused by counterterror operations or by
the way in which such operations change the population’s assessment of the government’s motivations. We demonstrate that
such attempts at mobilizing public support can be, but need not be, successful, discuss factors that make both the initiation
of a terror campaign and successful mobilization more or less likely, and relate our results to several empirical cases.

I t is often argued, by scholars and “practitioners” alike,


that terrorism is a powerful tool for generating sup-
port for a violent extremist movement.1 A central
intuition underlying this idea is that terrorists use vio-
the British repression . . . Although the Easter Re-
public of 1916 had been apparently buried in
the smoking ruins of central Dublin, by 1918
the idea had been resurrected as 75 of the 103
lence to provoke governments into harsh and indiscrimi- newly elected members of the Westminster par-
nate counterterrorism responses in order to radicalize and liament pronounced themselves in Dublin the
mobilize a population whose interests the terrorists claim new Dáil of an independent Irish Republic.”
to represent. Examples abound both from history and the (1971, 64)
current day.
Bell (1971) argues that the first successful use of guer- Early Basque separatist members of ETA adopted
rilla tactics in the twentieth century was by Irish Catholics similar tactics in the 1960s, attacking Spanish targets with
during the “Rising” in Dublin in 1916. The British the goal of provoking government repression. Zirakzadeh
responded with harsh countermeasures. Several schol- describes this strategy:
ars, however, argue that the British response ultimately
strengthened the republican cause. English writes, “The The militants reasoned that selective attacks
British response to republican subversion frequently in- against government bullies would provoke the
volved punishing the wider population for IRA activities: government into excessive and nondiscrimina-
this had the unintended—indeed, counterproductive— tory retaliation against all Basque residents . . . the
effect of strengthening the IRA that it was intended to escalating spiral of government repression and
undermine” (2003, 17). And Bell notes, civilian resistance would culminate with a Span-
ish government no longer able to afford an exten-
The Irish people, as the rebels had planned, sive, expensive and permanent occupation of the
were vitalized by the Rising and angered by Basque country.” (2002, 73)

Ethan Bueno de Mesquita is assistant professor of political science, CB 1063, Washington University, 1 Brookings Drive, St. Louis, MO
63130 (ebuenode@artsci.wustl.edu). Eric S. Dickson is assistant professor of politics, New York University, 19 West 4th Street, New York,
NY 10012 (eric.dickson@nyu.edu).
We have received valuable comments from Macartan Humphreys, Stathis Kalyvas, David Laitin, and several anonymous referees.
1
Pape (2003) provides a detailed discussion of the strategic uses of terrorism.
American Journal of Political Science, Vol. 51, No. 2, April 2007, Pp. 364–381

C 2007, Midwest Political Science Association ISSN 0092-5853

364
THE PROPAGANDA OF THE DEED 365

In the 1940s, the militant Zionist Irgun engaged in on two causal mechanisms that contribute to this dy-
a campaign of violence with the explicit goal of forcing namic. First, the aggrieved public learns about the nature
the British into a level of repression they would find un- of the government by observing whether the govern-
palatable. Menachem Begin, the Irgun’s leader, believed ment, when confronted with terror, responds in a way
inflicting sufficient casualties would compel the British that imposes suffering not only on the terrorists but on
to either withdraw or adopt repressive counterterrorism the aggrieved population as a whole. Second, armed con-
measures that would radicalize the Jewish population in flict imposes economic externalities that make the ag-
Mandate Palestine, with either response constituting a vic- grieved public more inclined toward extremism because
tory for the Irgun (Bell 1977). In the event, the British were the opportunity costs of violence are lower in a crippled
unwilling to engage in the sort of repression that would economy.
have been necessary to put down the Zionist revolt. As The possibility that government counterterror in-
Bell reports, “The British could wound but not kill, in- creases support for terrorists raises the question of why
sult but not eliminate” (1971, 71–72). Instead, the British governments engage in repressive crackdowns in the first
adopted a rather conciliatory stance, negotiating with the place. We argue that governments face trade-offs that
more moderate Labor Zionists, and eventually withdraw- inform their counterterror choices. On the one hand,
ing from Palestine. governments need to engage in some form of counter-
Current events in the Middle East reveal related dy- terrorism to preserve their security. Doing so in a non-
namics. Hamas and other Islamic groups have been locked repressive way may simply be technologically infeasible
in competition with the PLO for leadership of the Pales- or too costly from the government’s perspective. On the
tinian people (Bloom 2004). Part of the motivation for other hand, governments also bear costs for repressive
terrorist attacks is to provoke repressive Israeli responses, counterterror. When counterterror imposes hardship on
radicalizing the population and bolstering support for ex- an aggrieved population, support for continued violence
tremists (Mishal and Sela 2000). And, indeed, this strat- is likely to increase both because the opportunity costs of
egy, along with the corruption of the Fatah leadership, violence decrease and because the people conclude that
seems to have worked. In the recent 2006 elections for the government is not concerned with their welfare.
the Palestinian Legislative Council, Hamas won an ab- The model we propose generates a number of find-
solute majority of the seats and therefore leadership of ings. It demonstrates how, in equilibrium, terrorist vio-
the Palestinian Authority. Similarly, the recent kidnapping lence can provoke government counterterror responses
of Israeli soldiers by Hezbollah provoked Israeli military that increase support for the terrorist movement. How-
reprisals against Lebanon. The effects of these attacks on ever, it is also consistent with the empirical fact that,
Lebanese public opinion remain uncertain as of this writ- sometimes, government counterterrorism does not radi-
ing in July 2006. calize support for the terrorists. Further, we demonstrate
The United States faces the same dilemma in Iraq. how concerns over public responses shape government
U.S. forces fear that military countermeasures against ter- counterterror policies. Finally, the article has implications
rorists may be the spark that ignites mass mobilization, for when terrorist conflict is likely to occur, the condi-
rather than quelling violence. This trade-off between se- tions under which conflict between the terrorists and the
curity and mobilization was perhaps most evident in the government increases or decreases radicalism among the
debate over tactics leading up to the assault on Fallujah in aggrieved population, and when governments are likely
November 2004. either to show restraint or to react particularly harshly
Cases like these raise important puzzles. By what when confronting terrorism.
mechanisms do government crackdowns radicalize
populations and increase mobilization? If government
counterterrorism is likely to backfire in this way, why are
terrorists able to provoke governments into pursuing re- The Extant Literature
pressive strategies? When will governments, faced with
a campaign of violence, engage in repression? Is it ever Our work builds on a variety of models in the game the-
possible for a government to engage in military counter- oretic literature on the relationship between government
terrorism without mobilizing the opposition? counterterrorism policy and militant response. Perhaps
In this article we present a formal model to explore the most closely related paper is Siqueira and Sandler
the intuition that terrorists sometimes perpetrate acts of (2007), which models a conflict between terrorists and
political violence with the goal of mobilizing an aggrieved governments where a major concern of both parties
population that they claim to represent. We concentrate is public opinion. In that model, governments face a
366 ETHAN BUENO DE MESQUITA AND ERIC S. DICKSON

trade-off between counterterror spending, which in- Sandler (2007) consider differs from ours. In their model,
creases security, and the provision of public goods, which public opinion becomes more moderate (i.e., support for
bolsters moderation in public opinion. the government increases) when the government spends
Both de Figueiredo and Weingast (2001) and more on public goods. Hence, terrorist attacks can in-
Rosendorff and Sandler (2004) suggest that government crease radicalism by diverting government money toward
crackdowns radicalize moderates, leading to an increase counterterrorism and away from public goods. In our
in violence. Ginkel and Smith (1999) demonstrate that a model, the causal mechanisms by which terror and coun-
revolutionary vanguard that has private information re- terterror alter public opinion are through the level of
garding the strength of the government can, under certain economic damage inflicted on the aggrieved population
conditions, engage in costly violence that will signal to the through counterterror and what this may reveal about the
population that the government is likely to be weak and, government’s motivations and, thus, expected future ac-
therefore, susceptible to revolution. DeNardo (1985) ar- tions. The two articles, then, explore related phenomena
gues that one of the three purposes of terrorism is to serve from different, but complementary, perspectives.
as a “spur to mobilization,” either by directly reducing the A key difference from de Figueiredo and Weingast
state’s repressive capacity or by demeaning the forces of (2001) and Rosendorff and Sandler (2004) is that they
repression. Lichbach (1987) focuses on the consistency of argue that moderates will always respond to government
government policies over time to explain variance in mo- crackdowns by becoming more radical. We treat the pop-
bilization responses. When government policies are in- ulation members’ decisions of whether to radicalize en-
consistent, he claims, government counterterror increases dogenously and find that government crackdowns can
violence. Bueno de Mesquita (2005a) argues that govern- lead to an increase or a decrease in extremism depend-
ment crackdowns can lead to an increase or decrease in ing on the level of damage inflicted and the inferences
support for terrorism, depending on the relative effect the aggrieved population draws from the government’s
of counterterror on economic opportunity, ideology, and behavior. In this sense, our results are similar to those in
the success of the terrorist organization. Bueno de Mesquita (2005a). However, in that model there
Other papers examine the role of signaling and learn- is no signaling and so the population does not learn about
ing in terrorist conflict without focusing on mobilization. the government’s type. As such, while counterterror pol-
Kydd and Walter (2002) and Bueno de Mesquita (2005b) icy can increase or decrease mobilization, the terrorists
suggest that governments may conclude, as a result of are not engaged in terrorism for the purpose of mobiliz-
extremist violence, that moderates with whom the gov- ing the population. Thus, these two models address fun-
ernment is negotiating are unable or unwilling to pre- damentally different aspects of the dynamics of terrorist
vent future terrorism. In a related study, Arce and Sandler conflict.
(2007) analyze the choice of concessions versus counter- Ginkel and Smith (1999) model the use of violence
terrorism when a government is uncertain about the ex- as a device to signal information about the government’s
tremism of the terrorist enemy. Lapan and Sandler (1988) type and, thereby, affect mobilization. However, Ginkel
show that government actions other than counterterror, and Smith are concerned with private information that
such as granting concessions, can signal lack of resolve a revolutionary vanguard has regarding the ability of the
on the government’s part. Lapan and Sandler (1993) and government to withstand a campaign of violence. We con-
Overgaard (1994) argue that terrorist violence may signal centrate, instead, on the government’s private information
the strength of the terrorist organization to the govern- regarding the extent to which it is willing to trade off
ment. Blomberg, Hess, and Weerapana (2004) model a the welfare of the aggrieved population in exchange for
situation in which terrorists employ differing degrees of greater security from terrorism.
violence as a strategic response to information about the Clearly a complete model of the relationship between
government’s willingness to expand economic or political terrorism and mobilization would incorporate all of the
freedom. dynamics discussed above and many others. We have cho-
This article differs from these earlier works in a variety sen, however, to focus on two factors that we believe are
of ways. Siqueira and Sandler (2007) also focus on pub- important and have received relatively little attention in
lic opinion. However, they model competition between the literature—externalities associated with counterter-
the terrorists and the government for public support. ror and signaling about the government’s level of concern
We, alternatively, model competition between moderate for the welfare of the aggrieved public. Restricting our
and extreme factions, both of whom want to represent attention in this way allows us to generate insights into
the aggrieved population in opposition to the govern- the behavior of governments, terrorists, and mass publics
ment. Moreover, the causal mechanism that Siqueira and within a tractable theoretical framework. Throughout,
THE PROPAGANDA OF THE DEED 367

we discuss examples and illustrations from the empiri- campaign. If they do so, the government decides how to
cal literature. respond. In particular, the government chooses whether
to invest in developing a counterterror campaign that in-
flicts as little damage as possible on the aggrieved popula-
tion or whether to engage in a less discriminating form of
The Model counterterror that causes more damage. Finally, whether
or not there has been a terrorist conflict, each member of
Consider a model with three kinds of strategic actors: a the aggrieved population decides whether to support the
government (G), a population of individuals who are in moderates or extremists. If the moderates gain control,
some way at odds with the government (we will refer to they will pursue a strategy of negotiation and compro-
this population as the aggrieved),2 and an extremist fac- mise. If the extremists gain control, they will pursue a
tion (E). We will also make reference to a moderate faction strategy of violent conflict.
(M) with whom the extremists compete for leadership of The extremist faction’s objective is to maximize the
the aggrieved population, although the moderates are not probability that it becomes the leader of the aggrieved
strategic actors in our model. population. Different government types have different
In referring to terrorism in the Basque country, preferences over the relative value of negotiation versus
for example, we would take the Spanish government to an ongoing conflict. The government also bears costs for
be the government in question, the Basque people to be resources spent on counterterrorism, and it may, or may
the aggrieved population, moderate Basque parties to be not, also be concerned with the welfare of the aggrieved
the moderate faction, and ETA to be the extremist faction. population. Finally, the reaction of each member of the ag-
In the dispute between Israel and the Palestinians, the Is- grieved population to events reflects that member’s con-
raeli government is the government in question, the Pales- cerns about her political and economic welfare.
tinian people are the aggrieved population, Fatah is the With this general framework in place, we now turn
moderate faction, and Hamas, Islamic Jihad, or other mili- to the detailed structure and assumptions of the model.
tants represent the extremist faction. In Northern Ireland,
the British are the government, the Irish Catholics are
the aggrieved, various moderate Republican political or- Extremist Faction
ganizations are the moderate faction, and the Irish Re-
publican Army (and various splinter groups) constitute The extremist faction seeks to become the leader of the
the extremist faction. In British Mandate Palestine, the aggrieved population. The extremists face a binary choice:
British colonials were the relevant government, Jews liv- to engage in terrorism (t) or to decide not to engage
ing in Palestine were an aggrieved population, the Labor in terrorism (nt). Thus, a strategy for the extremists is
Zionists and Haganah were the moderate faction, and the ␴E ∈ {t, nt}. We have assumed that if the extremists gain
Irgun represented an extremist faction. In each of these control, they will pursue armed conflict. Thus, this initial
cases, the conflict involved the aggrieved population’s na- decision ought not be viewed as a choice over whether
tional aspirations.3 or not to embrace violence. Rather, it is a decision about
The game is played as follows. In the beginning the ex- whether it is instrumentally useful, in the cause of armed
tremists decide whether or not to launch a violent terrorist struggle, to serve as a terrorist vanguard.
The probability that the extremists win enough sup-
2
port in the population to gain control is denoted Pr(E ).
We want to be clear that we intend no normative judgement, ei-
ther in the abstract or in the specific motivating examples discussed Without loss of generality, we normalize the benefit of
below, by referring to the population in question as “aggrieved.” gaining control to one. Thus, the extremists’ expected util-
Aggrieved is meant to represent the population’s subjective assess- ity for strategy ␴E is4
ment of itself. Moreover, there may be more than one aggrieved
population in any given context. For instance, while we discuss the EUE (␴E ) = Pr (E | ␴E ).
Jewish population in British Mandate Palestine, there was also an
Arab aggrieved population in conflict with the British colonials.
3
We do not model the behavior of or public opinion among any
other population that is represented by the government (e.g., the
4
Spanish people in the Basque conflict, the Israeli people in the Note that terrorism is taken to be costless for the extremists. How-
Israeli-Palestinian case, or the Arabs living in British Mandate Pales- ever, the equilibria of the model that we describe later remain intact
tine). As such, whenever we refer to “the aggrieved population” in if terrorism becomes costly. After we demonstrate the equilibria of
the course of the article, it is the aggrieved population that the ter- our model, another footnote below describes how a cost to ter-
rorists claim to represent (e.g., the Basque people, the Palestinian rorism affects the details of the conditions under which different
people, the Irish Catholics) to which we refer. equilibria exist.
368 ETHAN BUENO DE MESQUITA AND ERIC S. DICKSON

Government we will refer to such a campaign as discriminating. Or the


government can choose a counterterror campaign that is
We model two possible types of government. The govern- less costly, but which does not concern itself with the wel-
ment’s type is labeled . With (commonly held) prior fare of the population; we will refer to such a campaign
probability p, the government is of type  = ␪ > 0, as undiscriminating.6 The idea is that a given security ob-
and with complementary probability 1 − p the govern- jective can be achieved through different means; different
ment is of type  = 0. The government knows its own government types may experience different tradeoffs be-
type, but this is private information; the extremists and tween the costs of a campaign and the collateral damage
the aggrieved population know only the common prior it may inflict.7
probabilities. Thus, the government’s strategy comes down to one
We use type to parameterize how much governments of two choices. The government can engage in discrim-
are concerned with the welfare of the aggrieved popula- inating counterterror (dc) or undiscriminating counter-
tion. In particular, the welfare of the population factors terror (uc). Call the government’s strategy ␴G ∈ {dc , uc }.
positively into the preferences only of governments of As discussed above, this choice implies a level of costs the
type  = ␪. Governments of type  = 0 are indiffer- government bears (K ) and a level of damage inflicted on
ent to the welfare of the population. Because of this dis- the population (D). The levels of cost and damage im-
tinction, we will frequently refer to governments of type plied by the different counterterror possibilities are given
 = 0 as “hard-line” and governments of type  = ␪ as as follows:
“soft-line.”5 
k̄ if ␴G = dc
A government of type  receives a payoff u (E ) if K =
the extremists win control and pursue a campaign of vi- k if ␴G = uc
¯
olence. It receives a payoff of u (M) if the moderates
where k̄ > k > 0.
gain control and pursue a strategy of negotiation. We ¯ 
assume that all governments prefer to face an aggrieved d¯ if ␴G = uc
population led by moderates rather than extremists D=
d if ␴G = dc
(i.e., u (M) > u (E ) for  ∈ {0, ␪}). Moreover, ¯
all else equal, negotiation is weakly more palat- where d¯ > d > 0.
¯
able to the soft-line government than the hard- That is, a discriminating counterterror campaign
line government (i.e., u␪ (M) − u␪ (E ) ≥ u0 (M) − costs the government more than an undiscriminating
u0 (E )). campaign, but it inflicts less damage on the aggrieved
We allow the government to choose alternative coun- population.
terterror campaign strategies that differ in their cost and The overall expected utility of the government is
the degree of collateral damage they inflict on the ag- EU G (␴G , )
grieved population. The government can choose a coun-
terterror campaign that goes out of its way to minimize the = Pr(E )[u (E ) + (1 − ␤) f (D(␴G ))]
amount of damage inflicted on the aggrieved population; + Pr(M)[u (M) + f (D(␴G ))] − K (␴G ),
5
Some readers may find it strange that the government’s type is where f (D(␴G )) represents the economic opportunities
taken to be uncertain here, particularly given that many of the gov- for the aggrieved population, and f  (D) < 0—damage
ernments targeted by terrorists have been democratically elected from government counterterror diminishes economic op-
and that debate over the appropriate posture towards terrorism was
an important component of the campaigns resulting in the elec- portunity. The parameter ␤ represents the portion of the
tion of those governments. Indeed, in democracies which have been economy that is expected to be destroyed should the ex-
confronted by terrorists over a long time period, such as Israel and tremists gain control and engage in further violence. This
Spain, different political parties can develop differentiated reputa-
tions when it comes to their likely bargaining and counterterrorism is described in more detail below. Sometimes we will
strategies. However, such reputations are only partial reputations,
and it is not uncommon for governments to take actions that were 6
We have in mind that a discriminating campaign might involve in-
not widely anticipated in advance or at the time of their election, telligence work to infiltrate cells, targeted assassinations that do not
such as Likud Prime Minister Ariel Sharon’s initiative to withdraw kill innocent bystanders, or other such tactics, while undiscriminat-
Israeli settlers from Gaza in 2005 or the talks with ETA held by the ing counterterror would involve border closings, bombings which
administration of Popular Party Prime Minister Jose Maria Aznar cause collateral damage and destroy infrastructure, or imposition
in 1999. Uncertainty about the government’s type is likely to be of curfews.
even greater in situations where the conflict is not long-standing
7
and the ruling authority is a geographically distant power—witness We therefore do not model a government’s choice between differ-
the uncertainty of the Iraqi population about the intentions of the ent security objectives; such a model of optimal counterterrorism
U.S. occupation that began in 2003. policy can be found in Powell (forthcoming).
THE PROPAGANDA OF THE DEED 369

write the expected utility of a government of type  as Putting these together, the payoff to a member of the
EU  (␴G ). aggrieved population if the extremist faction gains control
are

The Aggrieved Population Ui (E ) = ␲w + ␾i + (1 − ␤) f (D).


If the moderate faction gains control, they pursue a
The members of the aggrieved population must choose strategy of negotiation. The government’s type affects the
whom to support to represent their interests in the on- expected outcome of negotiation. The expected payoff
going dispute with the government: the extremists or the to a member of the aggrieved population from negoti-
moderates. For instance, each Palestinian must choose ation with a government of type  is v(M | ), where
whether to support the Palestinian Authority or a faction v(M | ␪) > v(M | 0). That is, it is better to negotiate with
such as Hamas or Islamic Jihad. Competition between a soft-line government than a hard-line government. Ne-
the moderates and the extremists does not necessarily in- gotiation, unlike terrorist conflict, does not inflict eco-
volve democratic elections in which the faction that wins nomic externalities. Thus, the payoffs associated with the
a majority gains power; it might, for instance, also take moderates gaining control are
the form of direct conflict between the factions. As such,
we leave the level of support needed by the extremists Ui (M) = Pr( = ␪)v(M | ␪)
(conversely, the moderates) general. In particular, the ex- + Pr( = 0)v(M | 0) + f (D).
tremists gain power if they achieve the support of a share
Finally, we assume that there is some uncertainty
x ∈ (0, 1) of the population. If x = 12 the extremists sim-
about the distribution of ideological preferences in the
ply need majority control, if x < 12 the extremists can gain
population. In particular, prior to deciding whether to
control with less than majority support, and if x > 12 the
support the extremist or moderate faction, the ideologi-
extremists need more than a majority to gain power. We
cal preferences (␾i ) of all population members experience
refer to the group that achieves leadership as the aggrieved
a random shock ⑀, with distribution G. This represents
regime or sometimes, just the regime.
the idea that the government cannot be perfectly certain
Several factors affect the population members’
of the public opinion outcomes associated with its coun-
choices: the state of the economy, the expected outcome
terterrorism policies.
of the conflict with the government under each regime,
and heterogeneous individual ideological views.
If the extremists gain control, they pursue armed con-
flict, which they win with probability ␲. Such a victory Equilibria
confers a benefit w on the population. However, violence
is also costly, causing significant damage to the econ- Having described the model in the previous section, we
omy. Thus, should the extremists win control, the level now proceed to analyze the equilibrium behavior of ac-
of economic opportunity is diminished by a factor of tors, and the way in which that behavior can be expected
␤ ∈ (0, 1).8 to change as features of the strategic situation vary. As
Finally, members of the aggrieved population also our solution concept, we employ Perfect Bayesian Equi-
have idiosyncratic preferences over whether they support librium, along with two refinements. First, we assume that
the extremists or the moderates, given by ␾i , where i is a actors do not play weakly dominated strategies.9 And sec-
generic member of the aggrieved population. These can ond, we assume that off-the-equilibrium path beliefs are
be thought of as ideological in nature. Some individuals, “intuitive,” in the sense that an unexpected observation
based on their personal ideals or temperament, may be of discriminating (undiscriminating) counterterror leads
naturally inclined toward supporting the goals of those the aggrieved population to believe that the government
who are engaged in armed conflict against a government is soft-line (hard-line).10
perceived as repressive. Others, however, may have an op-
posite inclination because they personally abhor the use of 9
This assumption is relevant only to the equilibrium analysis of the
violence. We assume that the ␾i s are distributed according aggrieved population and is meant to eliminate counterintuitive
equilibria in which actors support the faction which would leave
to some continuous, increasing distribution . them strictly worse off were it to be in power. In strategic terms,
our assumption is that members of the aggrieved population will
support their most preferred faction regardless of whether or not
8 they are pivotal in determining who comes to power.
See Abadie and Gardeazabal (2003), Enders and Sandler (1996),
10
and Sandler and Enders (2005) for empirical estimates of the eco- By unexpected, we mean a government behavior that is not chosen
nomic costs of terrorism. by either government type in a pooling equilibrium of the game.
370 ETHAN BUENO DE MESQUITA AND ERIC S. DICKSON

We first consider the incentives faced by members of costs of conflict. That is, the population reasons that the
the aggrieved population as they decide whom to support; amount they sacrifice economically by supporting the ex-
then proceed to the strategic incentives faced by a govern- tremists and, consequently, further violence, is smaller
ment who must decide how to respond to a campaign of when counterterror has already significantly damaged the
violence by the extremist faction; and finally classify the economy. Thus, the greater the level of damage, the more
types of equilibrium which can be observed in the game support there is for the extremists. This fact will also influ-
as a whole. We then derive comparative statics describ- ence governments’ trade-offs between alternative coun-
ing the way in which changes in particular features of the terterror tactics.
interaction affect the likelihood that different equilibria These two endogenous determinants of support for
will be observed. violence suggest reasons that an extremist faction might
expect to gain support from launching an attack: by pro-
voking a counterterror response, damage will be inflicted
The Aggrieved Population on the aggrieved population, and information about the
government’s type may also be revealed. The first of these
When deciding whether to support the moderate or ex-
factors will always tend to increase support for the ex-
tremist faction, members of the aggrieved population
tremists; sometimes the second will as well, depending on
simply compare the expected outcomes associated with
the nature of the information revealed.
each faction, given their beliefs about the type of the gov-
Of course, we have not yet discussed how the popu-
ernment against which they have a grievance. Suppose
lation’s posterior beliefs about the government’s type are
that the population’s posterior probability that the gov-
formed. In any equilibrium, these beliefs will depend on
ernment is soft-line (once any campaign of violence has
the strategies played by different government types. To
been launched or not launched, and any counterterror re-
address this, we must turn to the consideration of the
sponse has been observed) is represented by p̄. Then the
different equilibria of the model.
following Lemma indicates that the level of support for
the extremist faction is decreasing in p̄.
The Government
Lemma 1. The level of support for the extremist faction
When attention is restricted to the subgame following
(Pr(E)) is decreasing in p̄.
the initiation of a campaign of extremist violence, three
The proofs of this and all other results are in the different configurations of government behavior can be
appendix. sustained in equilibrium.
The intuition behind this result is simple. Because
the aggrieved population is more confident that a soft- Lemma 3. In the subgame in which governments must
line government will strike a favorable deal with the more choose how to respond to a campaign of violence by the
moderate faction, a heightened belief that the government extremist faction, there are three types of equilibrium in
is soft-line (higher p̄) reduces the attractiveness of vio- pure strategies. Either (1) both government types choose
lent conflict and, therefore, of the extremist faction. This discriminating counterterror; (2) both government types
plays a key role in governments’ strategic incentives. In choose undiscriminating counterterror; or (3) soft-line gov-
particular, a government can, at least partially, determine ernments choose discriminating counterterror but hard-line
who it faces at the bargaining table or in a conflict by governments choose undiscriminating counterterror.
attempting to manipulate the aggrieved populations’ per- In the next subsection, when we describe the equi-
ceptions of the government. As such, governments may libria of the overall game, we provide a discussion of the
have incentives to attempt to conceal, or to make clear, intuitions underlying governments’ incentives in each of
their underlying type. these cases. However, it is important to note here that
The next Lemma examines how the level of support the Lemma rules out any equilibria in which government
for the extremist faction is affected by economic damage types behave differently from one another in counter-
caused by government counterterror operations. stereotypical ways. That is, there are no equilibria in which
soft-line governments choose an undiscriminating coun-
Lemma 2. The level of support for the extremist faction
terterror strategy while hard-line governments choose a
(Pr(E)) is increasing in the level of damage inflicted on the
discriminating one. The intuition is simple. If conditions
aggrieved population by counterterrorism (D).
were such that a soft-line government wished to play
As damage increases, overall economic opportunity an undiscriminating counterterror strategy, it would cer-
is reduced. This diminishes the marginal opportunity tainly be the case that a hard-line government would wish
THE PROPAGANDA OF THE DEED 371

to do so as well. This is true for two reasons. First, hard- initial strike worth their while.11 In the third of these equi-
line governments bear a lower relative cost for pursuing an libria with violence, the aggrieved population will learn
undiscriminating counterterror strategy because, unlike the government’s type, but the risk to the extremist fac-
soft-line governments, they do not care about the dam- tion that this new knowledge will increase the population’s
age caused by such operations. Second, a hard-line gov- appetite for peaceful negotiations and a moderate leader-
ernment would prefer, if possible, not to reveal its type; ship is outweighed by the economic damage that ensues
as demonstrated in Lemma 1, an increased belief that the and the alternative possibility that the government will be
government is hard-line increases support for the extrem- revealed to be hard-line and an unappealing negotiating
ist faction. As such, when a soft-line government would partner.
choose undiscriminating counterterror, a hard-line gov- It is interesting to note how public opinion changes
ernment would prefer to match it, thereby concealing its in the equilibria with violence. Whereas in the first two
type while choosing its genuinely preferred tactic. equilibria, public support for the extremist faction al-
ways increases, the popularity of the extremists may ei-
ther increase or decrease in the third equilibrium. Ex ante,
Perfect Bayesian Equilibria the expected gain in support for the extremist faction is
of the Overall Game positive—making it willing to launch the attack in the first
place—but ex post, the level of support may increase or
The following Proposition describes the pure strategy Per- decrease, depending on the way in which the government
fect Bayesian equilibria of our overall game, in which an chooses to respond to terrorism (and the information
extremist faction decides whether or not to launch a cam- about its type that this reveals). This intuition underlines
paign of violence; the government must decide how to the fact that a soft-line government’s greater inherent will-
respond to any campaign that is launched; and members ingness to bear the costs of discriminating counterterror
of the aggrieved population must decide which potential operations can, in certain circumstances, be a strategic as-
leadership faction they wish to support. set. In the context of a separating equilibrium, it can lead
to a decrease in support for the extremist faction.
Proposition 1. The game has four types of Perfect
Finally, there is a fourth equilibrium in which the
Bayesian equilibrium in pure strategies. On the equilibrium
extremist faction chooses not to launch a campaign of vi-
path, either (1) the extremist faction mounts a campaign of
olence because the expected effect on its popularity would
violence and both government types choose discriminating
be negative. This is the case when governments’ expected
counterterror; (2) the extremist faction mounts a campaign
counterterror responses are informative about their type,
of violence and both government types choose undiscrim-
but the balance of considerations for the extremists runs in
inating counterterror; (3) the extremist faction mounts a
the opposite direction to that described for the third equi-
campaign of violence and soft-line governments choose dis-
librium above. That is, ex ante, support for the extremists
criminating counterterror but hard-line governments choose
is expected to diminish if they engage in terrorism.
undiscriminating counterterror; or (4) the extremist fac-
In order to build intuition, it is useful to devise a
tion does not mount a terror campaign, but had it done so
graphical depiction of the circumstances under which dif-
the soft-line government would have chosen discriminat-
ferent equilibria exist. While the model has many param-
ing counterterror and the hard-line government would have
eters, we organize the following discussion around a series
chosen undiscriminating counterterror.
of graphs along which the relative cost of different coun-
The model predicts that several distinct configura- terterror strategies, k̄ − k, varies while other parameters
¯
tions of behavior may be observed, depending on the cir- of the model are held fixed.12 The graphs contained in
cumstances. Perhaps the most fundamental thing to note Figure 1 present a schematic diagram describing the three
is that the extremist faction may or may not choose to different ways in which equilibrium regions can be related
launch a campaign of violence in equilibrium. In three
of the four types of Perfect Bayesian equilibrium, the ex-
tremist faction does choose to resort to terrorist tactics.
11
In the first two of these equilibria (i.e., the pooling equi- If we added to the model a cost to extremists for engaging in
libria), the expected government counterterror practices violence, and the cost were sufficiently high, pooling equilibria
with no terrorism would also be possible.
will cause damage but not inform members of the ag-
12
grieved population about the government’s type. Consis- Similar intuitions could be obtained if another quantity were
varied instead. We choose this one because the differing costs of
tent with the intuitions in Lemmata 1 and 2, this will lead different counterterror strategies are fundamental to governments’
to increased support for the extremist faction, making the incentives in the model, as well as for analytical convenience.
372 ETHAN BUENO DE MESQUITA AND ERIC S. DICKSON

FIGURE 1 Equilibrium Ranges

Notes: There are three possible configurations (the three figures) of ranges (in k¯ − k
space) for the existence of the three types of pure strategy equilibria (shown as different¯
shaded bars in each figure). Which configuration holds is a function of underlying pa-
rameter values and distributional assumptions. The values of the ␥ s and cs are defined in
Appendix A.5.

to one another as k̄ − k varies, depending on the specific Implications of the Equilibria


¯
details of the situation.13
While the details vary, certain regularities are evident. Having shown the intuition for the existence of a variety
First, for the lowest values of k̄ − k, there is a unique equi- of equilibria of the model, we now wish to discuss some
¯
librium, in which the extremist faction acts violently and substantive implications of particular equilibria. We begin
both government types respond in a discriminating way. by focusing on the separating equilibrium in which both
Second, for the highest values of k̄ − k, there is also a types of governments engage in counterterror, but where
¯
unique equilibrium, in which the extremists again resort hard-line governments do so in a way that inflicts greater
to terrorism but both government types now respond in damage on the population than do soft-line governments.
an undiscriminating fashion. And third, for intermediate We then proceed to the pooling equilibria.
values of k̄ − k, a separating equilibrium exists—either
¯
one with or one without violence. Further details of equi-
librium existence or uniqueness vary depending on the
precise form of the ideological distribution  of the ag-
grieved population and on other factors; for example,
Separating Equilibria
there may or may not be a range in which the separat- In the model, soft-line and hard-line governments differ
ing equilibrium is unique (although it is never the case in the extent to which they internalize damage inflicted on
that both separating equilibria and equilibria pooling on the aggrieved population. This difference implies that the
discriminating counterterror simultaneously exist), and two government types face different trade-offs between
there may or may not be a range in which no pure strat- the two possible counterterror strategies. Specifically, it is
egy equilibria exist.14 relatively less costly for soft-line governments to engage
in a discriminating counterterror campaign because they
13
Readers interested in the technical details of how these graphs internalize benefits from reducing damage to the popula-
were devised can consult section A.5 of the appendix. tion that are not internalized by hard-line governments.
14
It can be shown that mixed-strategy equilibria exist when this is As a result, the population is sometimes able to learn about
true. Note also that if we added a cost to extremists for engaging in the government’s type by observing its behavior.
violence, the cutpoint for when the extremists engage in violence In the separating equilibria, if the population ob-
in a separating equilibrium would shift (terrorism would be less
likely as the cost of terrorism increased), but the existence of the serves a heavy level of damage, more of them will support
equilibria we discuss remains unchanged. the extremist faction. Two factors drive this result. First,
THE PROPAGANDA OF THE DEED 373

the high level of damage reduces the opportunity costs and high levels of damage make an extremist leadership
of ongoing conflict, bolstering support for the extremists. relatively more attractive, as shown in Lemmata 1 and 2.
Second, in this separating equilibrium, the observed high If the government reacts in a particularly harsh way, the
level of damage allows the members of the population to population is certain to radicalize, increasing support for
infer that the government is hard-line, which makes them the extremists.15
more inclined to support violence. The situation is not as immediately clear if the pop-
These features of mobilization behavior have impli- ulation observes a low level of damage (d), thereby learn-
¯
cations for the incentives facing the two types of gov- ing that the government is soft-line. On the one hand,
ernments. Both types know that if they engage in an an increased belief in the soft-line nature of the govern-
undiscriminating campaign, they will face a higher level of ment makes a moderate regime relatively more attrac-
mobilization. However, two other factors enter into their tive because moderates negotiate more effectively with
calculations: the costs of a discriminating campaign and soft-line governments. On the other hand, the damage
the damage inflicted on the aggrieved population. Because inflicted, though less severe than would have been the
the hard-liners are indifferent to damage inflicted on the case under a hard-line government, does decrease the op-
population, they are less inclined to bear the costs of run- portunity costs of continued conflict, relative to when
ning a discriminating campaign. Thus, if those costs are the government is not forced to engage in any countert-
sufficiently high, the hard-liners are willing to face greater error because the extremists do not attack. As such, the
mobilization to avoid them, while soft-liners will pursue two effects cut in opposite directions, and a more explicit
a discriminating campaign in order to avoid imposing comparison between potential levels of support for the
damage on the aggrieved population. extremists is necessary to determine the overall effect on
Of course, the extremists, in choosing whether or not mobilization.
to attack, are uncertain whether they are facing a hard- Suppose the aggrieved population believes that the
line or a soft-line government. Depending on a variety government is soft-line with probability p . Then by com-
of factors, which we explore below, the extremists might paring the expected payoff from supporting the extrem-
or might not want to initiate a terrorist conflict. Thus, ists versus the moderates, we find that a member of the
there are two kinds of separating equilibria—one where aggrieved population supports the extremists if and only
the extremists attack and the government’s type is actually if
revealed and another in which the extremists do not attack
␾i ≥ p  v(M | ␪) + (1 − p  )v(M | 0) + ␤ f (D) − ␲w.
and the government’s type is not revealed.
Thus, in the absence of conflict, the expected level of sup-
port for the extremists is given by
Conflict and Radicalism N nt = 1 − ( pv(M | ␪) + (1 − p)v(M | 0)

An important question in the study of terrorism, and + ␤ f (0) − ␲w),


one which we can address in the context of our sepa- where p is the prior belief.
rating equilibria, concerns how the aggrieved population If there is conflict, and the government reveals itself
responds to violent conflict between terrorists and the to be soft-line by choosing a discriminating counterterror
government. The empirical record contains examples of strategy, then support for the extremists is
different types of reactions. Israeli crackdowns in the West
Bank and Gaza Strip have, by and large, increased Pales- Nduc,dc = 1 − (v(M | ␪) + ␤ f (d) − ␲w).
¯ ¯
tinian support for violence in general and the extremist Because  is monotone increasing in its argument, the
militant groups in particular (Bloom 2004). Palestinians condition for decreased radicalization in the aggrieved
blame Israel for its counterterror activities. Conversely, population following conflict can be expressed as
counterterror efforts against Basque separatists in the
␤[ f (0) − f (d)] < (1 − p)(v(M | ␪) − v(M | 0)). (1)
1980s by the French and Spanish governments were ac- ¯
companied by a decline in support for ETA (Funes 1998). The left-hand side of equation (1) represents the impact
Note that in a separating equilibrium in which the on the opportunity costs of ongoing violence from dis-
extremists initiate a terrorist campaign, if the population criminating counterterror relative to no counterterror. All
observes a high level of damage (d), ¯ then it learns that
the government is hard-line. This will, for certain, lead to 15
See Abadie (2006) and Krueger and Laitin (2004) for evidence
an increase in support for the extremists because both an linking terrorism to measures of how hard-line the government is,
increased belief in the hard-line nature of the government such as level of political repression and absence of civil rights.
374 ETHAN BUENO DE MESQUITA AND ERIC S. DICKSON

else equal, the marginal increase in support for the ex- The problem of even discriminating counterterror-
tremists associated with initiating a terrorist campaign ism causing significant damage might arise, for instance,
will be smaller when the damage from a discriminating when the aggrieved population lives in enclaves, such that,
campaign is relatively low. in order to pursue the terrorists, the government is forced
The right-hand side of equation (1) represents the to target the entire enclave. This is consistent with the
relative benefit of negotiating with a soft-line rather than frequent use of terrorism as a tool by ethnic minorities
a hard-line government. When soft-line governments engaged in separatist conflicts (e.g., Basques in Spain,
are much more amenable to negotiation than are hard-line Palestinians, Tamils in Sri Lanka, Kurds in Turkey, etc.).
governments, learning that the government is soft-line All types of governments might share similar posi-
significantly decreases support for the extremists. Thus, tions vis-á-vis negotiation in situations where domestic
the expected level of extremist support, given conflict, is pressure has hardened against negotiation. In such situ-
decreasing in the difference in attitude toward negotiation ations, the aggrieved population will perceive that there
between the hard-line and soft-line governments. is little advantage to dealing with a soft-line government
These results have several implications for the pat- over a hard-line government and will, thus, be more in-
terns of mobilization and radicalization we expect to see clined to support extremist violence.
empirically. First, counterterror campaigns in which a
government appears insensitive to the suffering of the Proposition 2. Conditional on being in the separating
aggrieved population will result in increased mobiliza- equilibrium, the extremists are more likely to initiate a ter-
tion in support of the extremists. Second, governments rorist conflict when conditions make it difficult to engage
that are concerned with the welfare of the population, in discriminating counterterrorism without imposing neg-
but which either lack the technology, or find themselves ative externalities on the aggrieved population (high d) and
¯
in situations where it is impossible, to engage in even dis- when the value of negotiating with hard-line and soft-line
criminating counterterror without nonetheless imposing governments is similar (small v(M | ␪) − v(M | 0)).
serious damage on the population (high d) are also likely
¯ Proof. The result follows from the argument in the text
to face an increasingly radical aggrieved population. Con-
and inspection of equation (1).
versely, when governments are concerned with the welfare
of the aggrieved population and can engage in counter- The predictions regarding the effect of negative ex-
terror that imposes relatively low levels of damage, then ternalities discussed above seem consistent with the two
conflict can backfire on an extremist terrorist vanguard, examples with which we began this discussion. In the case
decreasing radicalization and increasing support for the of the Israeli/Palestinian conflict, the damage from Israeli
moderates. crackdowns has been large. And this has had a significant
Finally, when both hard-line and soft-line govern- impact on the state of the Palestinian economy. Thus,
ments find negotiation unpalatable, learning that the within the context of our model, it is not surprising that
government is soft-line does not particularly sway the the Palestinians have mobilized and increased support for
aggrieved population. Consequently, the negative effects extremist groups such as Islamic Jihad and Hamas. The
on the economy of counterterror are likely to outweigh level of damage has both increased the Palestinians’ be-
the positive effects of learning that the government is soft- liefs that the Israeli government is relatively hard-line and
line, leading to an increase in support for the extremists. eroded economic opportunities for Palestinians. Both of
these effects mitigate in favor of support for Hamas and
The Likelihood of Terrorism other extremist groups.
The case of the Spanish and French crackdowns on
From the above results, one can also gain some insight into Basque separatists in the 1980s provides a counterexam-
the kinds of societies that are likely to experience terrorist ple. In this case, Basque public opinion turned sharply
conflict. If terrorism is likely to backfire, all other things against the ETA during the counterterror campaign (Clark
being equal, failing to increase support for the extremists, 1990; Funes 1998). And, consistent with the model, this
then the extremists will be less likely to initiate a campaign was a counterterror campaign that inflicted very low ex-
of violence in the first place. Thus, the model predicts that ternalities on the population at large. Indeed, the height
terrorist conflicts will be most common in places where of the counterterror campaign in 1987 coincided with the
even soft-line governments are unable to engage in coun- fastest growth in Basque GDP in modern Spanish history.
terterror without imposing heavy negative externalities The second prediction of the proposition has impli-
and in societies where all types of governments more or cations for how public opinion within a society affects the
less agree on the value of negotiated settlements. likelihood of terrorism occurring. In particular, societies
THE PROPAGANDA OF THE DEED 375

that are unified in their view of how to deal with radicals, in undiscriminating counterterror or both government
so there is relatively little difference between negotiating types can engage in discriminating counterterror. Because
with a hard- and a soft-line government, are more likely to the government types play the same strategies in either of
experience terrorism. Highly polarized societies, alterna- these equilibria, in some sense they do not lend themselves
tively, are less likely to be victims of terrorism. The reason as well to the kind of analysis done for the separating equi-
is that, in polarized societies, terrorism carries significant libria. However, there are several facts worth noting.
risk for the extremists—if the population learns that the First, in either pooling equilibrium, terrorism always
government is soft-line, the extremists will lose a signifi- increases support for the extremists. The reason is as
cant amount of support. follows. In either type of pooling equilibrium, the gov-
Finally, it is worth discussing the effect of the prior ernment engages in some counterterrorism, which does
beliefs that the government is soft- or hard-line on the some damage to the economy. This, as we have already
likelihood of the extremists initiating a conflict. Recall seen, increases support for the extremists by decreasing
that when the government is hard-line, terrorism is sure the opportunity costs of conflict. Further, since it is a pool-
to help the extremists. Hence, one might have expected ing equilibrium, the aggrieved population learns nothing
that an increased belief that the government is hard-line about the government’s type. Thus, the aggrieved pop-
would unequivocally increase the likelihood of a terrorist ulation’s beliefs about the government are the same re-
campaign beginning. Surprisingly, this turns out not to gardless of whether or not there is conflict. Consequently,
be the case. in a pooling equilibrium, the overall effect of terror-
There are two effects of an increased belief in the gov- ism on support for the extremists is positive, regardless
ernment being hard-line on the extremists’ decision of of whether the government pools on discriminating or
whether to engage in terrorism. On the one hand, when undiscriminating counterterrorism. This is true despite
it is likely that the government is hard-line, it is likely the fact that these equilibria have poor welfare conse-
that terrorism will provoke undiscriminating counterter- quences from the aggrieved population’s point of view—
ror and a consequent increase in support for the extrem- the terrorist violence has made their living conditions
ists. This effect makes the extremists more likely to engage worse while bringing no informational benefit.
in terrorism. On the other hand, when it is likely the gov-
Remark 2. Terrorism always increases support for the ex-
ernment is hard-line, support for the extremists in the
tremists in a pooling equilibrium.
absence of a terrorist conflict is already likely to be high.
This is because, independent of the state of the economy, From a particular point of view, this result may seem
members of the aggrieved population prefer an extremist counterintuitive. By engaging in terrorism, the extremists
regime that will pursue a militant strategy if they believe have taken actions which leave the aggrieved population
they are facing a hard-line government. Since this implies strictly worse off (due to the economic damage), and yet
that the extremists will have strong support even with- the extremists’ popularity increases within that popula-
out a terrorist campaign (i.e., the people will support ex- tion. Why should members of the population put up with
tremism without a “terrorist vanguard” leading the way), this state of affairs rather than blaming the extremists
they are less inclined to engage in terrorism, which car- and bolstering support for the moderate faction instead?
ries the risk that the government will surprise everyone The answer lies in a commitment problem that the pop-
and turn out to be soft-line, reducing support for the ulation faces. It would be in the population’s interest if
extremists. Thus, whether the extremists are more likely individuals could commit to punishing the extremists for
to attack when they believe the government is hard-line sparking a cycle of violence that had a deleterious im-
or soft-line is ambiguous. It depends on a complicated pact on the population’s welfare. But they lack the means
relationship of parameter values and the shape of the dis- to make such a commitment. Consequently, when the
tribution of preferences in the aggrieved population. time comes to decide whom to support, the diminished
economic opportunities caused by the counterterrorism
Remark 1. Within the separating equilibria, an increased
response make the members of the population inclined
belief that the government is hard-line can increase or de-
toward direct struggle against the government, leading
crease the probability that the extremists engage in terrorism.
them to support the extremist faction, even though this
faction’s earlier actions diminished the aggrieved popu-
Pooling Equilibria lation’s welfare. Thus, the model is consistent with the
sort of perverse outcomes we may sometimes see in the
As stated in Proposition 1, two kinds of pooling equi- world whereby a people support a violent faction that is
libria are possible—both government types can engage continuously diminishing their quality of life.
376 ETHAN BUENO DE MESQUITA AND ERIC S. DICKSON

Comparative Statics they do not want to risk the government revealing itself
to be soft-line. As the costs of discriminating counter-
Now that we have seen what equilibria exist, and what terror diminish even further, there will once again be
the implications of those equilibria are, it is informative terrorism.
to consider how changes in some of the relevant features This is the surprising part of the nonmonotonic-
of the situation affect which equilibria are likely to be ity. Because the cost of discriminating counterterror is
observed in practice. The first comparative statics result low, both government types are willing to minimize the
is intuitive given the discussion surrounding Figure 1. economic damage their counterterror inflicts on the ag-
grieved population. However, the very fact that they are
Proposition 3. As discriminating counterterror opera-
both willing to do this can trigger a terror attack. The ter-
tions become more costly relative to undiscriminating ones
rorists cease to be concerned that the population will learn
(the quantity k̄ − k increases), the set of pure strategy equi-
¯ any information about the government from its counter-
libria changes in the following way. Initially, it is a unique
terror strategy. As a result, they are once again tempted
pure strategy Perfect Bayesian equilibrium for the extrem-
to provoke the government through counterterrorism.
ist faction to strike and for the government types to pool
Thus, an increase in the willingness of governments to
on discriminating counterterror; ultimately, it is a unique
engage in discriminating counterterror that protects the
pure strategy Perfect Bayesian equilibrium for the extremist
interests of the aggrieved population can, ironically, some-
faction to strike and for the government types to pool on
times increase the risk of terrorism occurring.
undiscriminating counterterror. An equilibrium in which
As a final comparative static, we consider the impact
government types separate exists for intermediate values of
of variation in the prior belief p that the government is
k̄ − k.
¯ soft-line.
At one level, the basic thrust of Proposition 3 is fairly
Proposition 4. As the prior belief p that the government
obvious. As discriminating counterterror becomes rela-
is of the soft-line type increases, both of the pooling equilibria
tively more expensive, behavior shifts in the direction of
become more likely.
undiscriminating counterterror. At the extremes, only the
relevant pooling equilibria are possible, while a mix of be- Consider the equilibrium in which the extremist fac-
haviors takes place in the intermediate ranges. tion launches a terror campaign and the government types
However, what is more interesting is to consider the pool on undiscriminating counterterror. The soft-line
interaction between the incentives of the government type is less comfortable with this equilibrium than its
types and the incentives of the extremist faction. As we hard-line counterpart; as p increases, the pooling equi-
saw earlier, in the range of parameter values for which a librium becomes more palatable to nearly indifferent
separating equilibrium exists, the extremists may or may soft-line types because the posterior level of support for
not choose to engage in violence. In situations where the the extremist faction will be lower. The incentive to switch
extremists do not wish to resort to terrorism when gov- to a discriminating campaign therefore decreases. Simi-
ernments separate, there is the potential for an important larly, consider the equilibrium in which the extremist fac-
nonmonotonicity in extremist strategies. Because it is, as tion launches a terror campaign and the government types
discussed above, always in the interests of the extremist pool on discriminating counterterror. It is the hard-line
faction to launch a terror campaign when governments type that is less comfortable with this equilibrium. As p in-
pool, it may be the case that terror campaigns will be creases, the pooling equilibrium becomes more palatable
launched for high and low, but not for some intermedi- to nearly indifferent hard-line types, because the poste-
ate, values of k̄ − k. rior level of support for the extremist faction will again be
¯
The idea is as follows. When the additional cost of lower in the equilibrium. Switching to an undiscriminat-
discriminating counterterror is very high, there will be ing campaign becomes less appealing because the relative
a pooling equilibrium on nondiscriminating counter- increase in mobilization for the extremists is larger.
terror. The extremists always want to engage in violence While an increase in p increases the likelihood of the
when there is a pooling equilibrium, thus costly dis- pooling equilibria (in which there is always terrorism), we
crimination will lead to a terrorist conflict. If the sep- cannot conclude from that that an increase in p increases
arating equilibrium is of the sort where the extremists the overall risk of terrorism. The range over which a sep-
choose not to attack, then as the cost of discriminating arating equilibrium exists is unchanged as p varies. And,
counterterrorism decreases there will no longer be ter- as discussed in Remark 1, given that we are in a separating
rorism. When the government types are willing to sepa- equilibrium, p has an ambiguous effect on the likelihood
rate, the extremists do not engage in terrorism because of terrorism being employed.
THE PROPAGANDA OF THE DEED 377

Conclusion Appendix
A.1 Proof of Lemma 1
This article has explored the strategic logic underlying
the use of terrorist violence for a specific political end— A member of the aggrieved population supports the ex-
increasing support for a terrorist movement among an ag- tremist faction if and only if
grieved population. A central challenge in understanding
the root causes of terrorism is comprehending the mech- ␾i ≥ p̄v(M | ␪) + (1 − p̄)v(M | 0) + ␤ f (D) − ␲w ≡ ␾.
ˆ
anisms by which practitioners of violence hope to achieve The probability that the extremists gain control is the
their objectives. Such an understanding is essential for ˆ + ⑀ < −1 (1 − x). This is given by
probability that ␾
explaining patterns of terrorist violence and variations in −1
Pr(E ) = G ( (1 − x) − ␾).
ˆ Thus, we have
the effectiveness of terror campaigns, as well as for for-
mulating public policies intended to curb the dangers of ∂Pr(E )
= −g (−1 (1 − x) − ␾)
ˆ
terrorism. ∂ p̄
Our model explores only one of several plausible mo- × (v(M | ␪) − v(M | 0)) < 0,
tivations for the deployment of terror. However, we be-
lieve the mechanism we describe plays an important role where the inequality follows from v(M | ␪) −
in many terrorist conflicts, not least some of those that v(M | 0) > 0.
fill our newspapers in the present day. In our view, terror-
ist organizations often attempt to increase their political
support—sometimes succeeding—by provoking govern-
A.2 Proof of Lemma 2
ments into counterterror responses that inflict damage Taking the expression for Pr(E) from the proof of
(economic and otherwise) on a population of people who Lemma 1,
already perceive themselves to have reason to support the
∂Pr(E )
terrorists. Such responses can, moreover, leave the popu- = −g (−1 (1 − x) − ␾)␤
ˆ f  (D) > 0,
lation with the impression that the government is uncon- ∂D
cerned with their welfare, increasing the appeal of armed where the inequality follows from f  (D) < 0.
conflict.
Of course, if the mobilization dynamics we have mod-
eled are correct, then governments engaged in counter- A.3 Proof of Lemma 3
terrorism face a profound dilemma. They may be aware
There are four possible pure strategy profiles for the two
that crackdowns are counterproductive, in the sense of
government types. We denote a strategy profile according
increasing mobilization, but may have no other reason-
to (␴ 0 , ␴ ␪ ) where ␴ 0 is the strategy chosen by the hard-
able option for increasing security. This is especially likely
line government ( = 0) and ␴ ␪ is the strategy chosen by
for governments facing a terrorist vanguard that lives
the soft-line government ( = ␪).
and operates in the midst of the aggrieved population, in
(uc, dc). Under this separating strategy profile, strate-
isolation from the nonaggrieved population. Our model
gies fully reveal type; so the population forms posterior
highlights the trade-offs in question and clarifies the
belief p̄ = 1 upon observing dc but p̄ = 0 upon observing
mechanisms by which the counterterrorism dilemma op-
uc.
erates, but offers no pat public policy remedies for gov-
For a soft-line government, the payoff from choosing
ernments confronted with this dilemma.
dc is
The closest we come to a clear policy implication is
the idea that perceptions, not just physical facts, matter. U␪ (dc | (uc, dc))
In the model, two endogenous mechanisms affect mobi- = Pr(E | p̄ = 1, d)(u␪ (E ) + ␪(1 − ␤) f (d))
lization decisions by the aggrieved population: the actual ¯ ¯
damage inflicted by the counterterror campaign and the + (1 − Pr(E | p̄ = 1, d))(u␪ (M) + ␪ f (d)) − k̄
¯ ¯
population’s perceptions of the government’s intentions.
while the payoff from deviating to uc is
Governments trapped in conflicts with terrorists living
in the midst of a general population may be unable to U␪ (uc | (uc , dc ))
avoid the former but can, perhaps, adopt policies outside
= Pr(E | p̄ = 0, d)(u
¯ ␪ (E ) + ␪(1 − ␤) f (d))
¯
of their direct counterterror tactics that positively affect
the latter. + (1 − Pr(E | p̄ = 0, d))(u
¯ ␪ (M) + ␪ f (d)) − k.
¯
¯
378 ETHAN BUENO DE MESQUITA AND ERIC S. DICKSON

Thus, the soft-line government will choose dc so long as Because k̄ − k > 0 and u0 (M) − u0 (E ) > 0, equa-
¯
¯ − Pr(E | p̄ = 1, d)]
[Pr(E | p̄ = 0, d) tion (6) implies Pr(E | p̄ = 1, d) ¯ > Pr(E | p̄ = 0, d).
¯
¯ But then ␪[ f (d) − f (d)] − ␤␪[ f (d) Pr(E | p̄ = 0, d) −
¯
× [u␪ (M) − u␪ (E )] + ␪[ f (d) − f (d)]
¯ ¯
¯ Pr(E | p̄ = 1, d)]
f (d)
¯ ¯
¯ > 0, implying that equations (5)
¯
+ ␤␪[ f (d)¯ Pr(E | p̄ = 0, d)
¯ and (6) cannot be simultaneously satisfied (because
u␪ (M) − u␪ (E ) > u0 (M) − u0 (E )). So there can be no
− f (d) Pr(E | p̄ = 1, d)] ≥ k̄ − k. (2) equilibria of the type (dc , uc ).
¯ ¯ ¯
Similarly a hard-line government choosing uc will receive (dc, dc). Under this pooling strategy profile, strate-
payoff gies do not fully reveal type; the population maintains
U0 (uc | (uc, dc)) = Pr(E | p̄ = 0, d)u
¯ 0 (E ) posterior belief p̄ = p upon observing dc but updates to
posterior belief p̄ = 0 upon observing uc (as this is the
+ (1 − Pr(E | p̄ = 0, d))u
¯ 0 (M) − k.
intuitive off-equilibrium-path belief).
¯
Deviating to dc yields payoff For a hard-line government, the payoff from choosing
dc is
U0 (dc | (uc, dc)) = Pr(E | p̄ = 1, d)u0 (E )
¯
+ (1 − Pr(E | p̄ = 1, d))u0 (M) − k̄. U0 (dc | (dc , dc )) = Pr(E | p̄ = p, d)u0 (E )
¯ ¯
Thus, the hard-line government may choose uc so long as + (1 − Pr(E | p̄ = p, d))u0 (M) − k̄
¯
¯ − Pr(E | p̄ = 1, d)]
[Pr(E | p̄ = 0, d) while the payoff from deviating to uc is
¯
× [u0 (M) − u0 (E )] ≤ k̄ − k. (3)
U0 (uc | (dc , dc )) = Pr(E | p̄ = 0, d)u
¯ 0 (E )
¯
As such the condition for equilibrium existence is
+ (1 − Pr(E | p̄ = 0, d))u
¯ 0 (M) − k.
[Pr(E | p̄ = 0, d)
¯ − Pr(E | p̄ = 1, d)] ¯
¯ Thus, the hard-line government may choose dc so long as
× [u␪ (M) − u␪ (E )] + c 1 ≥ k̄ − k
¯
¯ − Pr(E | p̄ = 1, d)]
≥ [Pr(E | p̄ = 0, d) [Pr(E | p̄ = 0, d)
¯ − Pr(E | p̄ = p, d)]
¯ ¯
× [u0 (M) − u0 (E )] (4) × [u0 (M) − u0 (E )] ≥ k̄ − k. (7)
¯
where c 1 ≡ ␪[ f (d) − f (d)] ¯ + ␤␪[ f (d)¯ Pr(E | p̄ = 0, A similar calculation shows that a soft-line government
¯
¯ − f (d) Pr(E | p̄ = 1, d)]. Note that ␤ ∈ (0, 1) and
d) will choose dc so long as
¯ ¯ ≥ Pr(E ¯| p̄ = 1, d) (by Lematta 1 and
Pr(E | p̄ = 0, d)
¯
2) imply that c 1 > 0. This, in turn, implies that the [Pr(E | p̄ = 0, d)
¯ − Pr(E | p̄ = p, d)]
¯
absolute value of the second term cannot exceed that of × [u␪ (M) − u␪ (E )] + ␪[ f (d) − f (d)]
¯
the first. This along with u␪ (M) − u␪ (E ) > u0 (M) − ¯
u0 (E ) and k̄ > k implies that the equilibrium exists for a − ␤␪[ f (d) Pr(E | p̄ = p, d)
¯ ¯ ¯
non-empty set of conditions. − f (d)¯ Pr(E | p̄ = 0, d)]
¯ ≥ k̄ − k.
(dc, uc). Under this separating strategy profile, strate- ¯
gies fully reveal type; so the population forms posterior Because
belief p̄ = 0 upon observing dc but p̄ = 1 upon observ- ␪[ f (d) − f (d)]
¯ − ␤␪[ f (d) Pr(E | p̄ = p, d)
ing uc. Using similar calculations to those done above, we ¯ ¯ ¯
find that the soft-line government will choose uc so long − f (d)¯ Pr(E | p̄ = 0, d)]
¯ >0
as
and u␪ (M) − u␪ (E ) > u0 (M) − u0 (E ), only the con-
[Pr(E | p̄ = 1, d)
¯ − Pr(E | p̄ = 0, d)]
straint on the hard-line government binds. So equation
¯
× [u␪ (M) − u␪ (E )] + ␪[ f (d) − f (d)]
¯ (7) gives the conditions for the existence of this discrim-
¯ inating pooling equilibrium.
− ␤␪[ f (d) Pr(E | p̄ = 0, d) (uc, uc). Under this pooling strategy profile, strate-
¯ ¯
− f (d)
¯ Pr(E | p̄ = 1, d)]
¯ ≤ k̄ − k, (5) gies do not fully reveal type; the population maintains
¯ posterior belief p̄ = p upon observing uc but updates to
and that the hard-line government will choose dc so long
as posterior belief p̄ = 1 upon observing dc (as this is the
intuitive off-equilibrium-path belief). Calculations simi-
[Pr(E | p̄ = 1, d)
¯ − Pr(E | p̄ = 0, d)]
¯ lar to those above indicate that the soft-line government
× [u0 (M) − u0 (E )] ≥ k̄ − k. (6) may choose uc so long as
¯
THE PROPAGANDA OF THE DEED 379

¯ − Pr(E | p̄ = 1, d)]
[Pr(E | p̄ = p, d) the extremist faction will choose to play t if and only
¯ if
× [u␪ (M) − u␪ (E )] + ␪[ f (d) − f (d)]
¯
¯ Pr(E | p̄ = 0, D = d)
¯ − Pr(E | p̄ = p, D = 0)
− ␤␪[ f (d) Pr(E | p̄ = 1, d)
¯ ¯ ¯ − Pr(E | p̄ = 1, D = d)].
≥ p[Pr(E | p̄ = 0, D = d)
− f (d)¯ Pr(E | p̄ = p, d)]
¯ ≤ k̄ − k (8) ¯
¯ (9)
while the hard-line government will choose uc so long as
Consider fixed values of all of the parameters of the
[Pr(E | p̄ = p, d)
¯ − Pr(E | p̄ = 1, d)] model. It is clear that equation (9) will be fulfilled for
¯
certain distribution functions , depending on their
× [u0 (M) − u0 (E )] ≤ k̄ − k.
¯ shapes, but not for others. For Perfect Bayesian equilib-
Because rium (t; uc , dc ), this condition must hold simultane-
¯ − ␤␪[ f (d) Pr(E | p̄ = 1, d)
␪[ f (d) − f (d)] ously with the separating equilibrium conditions found
¯ ¯ ¯ in equation (4). But note that equation (4) includes condi-
− f (d)¯ Pr(E | p̄ = p, d)]
¯ >0
tions on Pr(E | p̄ = 0, d) ¯ and Pr(E | p̄ = 1, d) but not on
¯
and u␪ (M) − u␪ (E ) > u0 (M) − u0 (E ) only the constraint Pr(E | p̄ = p, D = 0), which it leaves as a free parameter.
on the soft-line government binds. So equation (8) gives So obviously the two conditions can be simultaneously
the conditions for the existence of this undiscriminating fulfilled, and therefore Perfect Bayesian equilibria (t; uc ,
pooling equilibrium. dc ) of the model do exist. An identical argument with the
inequality of (9) reversed establishes that Perfect Bayesian
equilibria (nt; uc , dc ) also exist.
A.4 Proof of Proposition 1
First consider the government pooling strategy profiles A.5 Note on Equilibrium Ranges
(uc , uc ) and (dc , dc ) which by Lemma 3 can be sustained
in equilibria of the subgame in which the extremist fac- It will be useful for the following Propositions to define
tion has launched a campaign of violence. If the extremist the following notation:
faction chooses t and government types pool on (uc , uc ) u×
␪ ≡ u ␪ (M) − u ␪ (E )
(resp., (dc , dc )), the posterior belief is p̄ = p and the level
of damage is D = d¯ (resp. D = d), whereas if the extrem- u×
0 ≡ u 0 (M) − u 0 (E )
¯
ist faction chooses nt, the posterior belief is also p̄ = p ␥1 ≡ [Pr(E | p̄ = 0, D = d)
¯
but the level of damage is lower, D = 0. When government
− Pr(E | p̄ = 1, D = d)]u×
types pool, therefore, by Lemma 2, Pr(E) is strictly higher ¯ ␪
when the extremists play t than when they play nt. This ␥2 ≡ [Pr(E | p̄ = 0, D = d)
¯
combined with the results in Lemma 3 demonstrates both
that (t; uc , uc ) and (t; dc , dc ) support Perfect Bayesian − Pr(E | p̄ = 1, D = d)]u×
¯ 0
equilibria as stated in the Proposition, and also that (nt; ␥3 ≡ [Pr(E | p̄ = 0, D = d)
¯
uc , uc ) and (nt; dc , dc ) cannot support Perfect Bayesian
− Pr(E | p̄ = p, D = d)]u×
equilibria. ¯ 0
By Lemma 3, the separating strategy profile (dc , uc ) ␥4 ≡ [Pr(E | p̄ = p, D = d)
¯
cannot support an equilibrium of the relevant subgame,
− Pr(E | p̄ = 1, D = d)]u×
so it cannot form a component of a Perfect Bayesian ¯ ␪
equilibrium of the overall game. But consider the sep- c 1 ≡ ␪[ f (d) − f (d)] + ␤␪[ f (d)
¯ ¯ Pr(E | p̄ = 0, d)¯
¯
arating strategy profile (uc , dc ), which can support an
− f (d) Pr(E | p̄ = 1, d)]
equilibrium of the relevant subgame. If the extremist fac- ¯ ¯
tion plays nt they have probability of victory Pr(E | p̄ = c 4 ≡ ␪[ f (d) − f (d)]
¯ + ␤␪[ f (d) ¯ Pr(E | p̄ = p, d)¯
¯
p, D = 0) whereas if they play t, with probability p the − f (d) Pr(E | p̄ = 1, d)].
government is revealed to be of the soft-line type and the ¯ ¯
extremists have probability of victory Pr(E | p̄ = 1, D = We note that u× ␪ > u ×
0 > 0 (by assumption); that c 1 >
d) whereas with probability 1 − p the government is re- c 4 > 0 (because ␤ ∈ (0, 1) and because Lemma 1 implies
¯
vealed to be of the hard-line type and the extremists have that Pr(E | p̄ = 0, d) ¯ and that ␥ i >
¯ > Pr(E | p̄ = p, d));
×
probability of victory Pr(E | p̄ = 0, D = d). ¯ As a result 0 for all i (the u parts are positive definite as stated above;
380 ETHAN BUENO DE MESQUITA AND ERIC S. DICKSON

the difference-of-probability terms are positive definite by References


Lemmata 1 and 2. Further, ␥ 1 > ␥ 2 by the ordering of the
u× terms; ␥ 2 > ␥ 3 by Lemma 1; and ␥ 1 > ␥ 4 by Lemma Abadie, Alberto. 2006. “Poverty, Political Freedom, and the
1. As such, ␥ 1 > ␥ 2 > ␥ 3 and ␥ 1 > ␥ 4 with the ordering Roots of Terrorism.” American Economic Review (Papers and
of ␥ 4 ambiguous relative to ␥ 2 and ␥ 3 . proceedings 96(2): 50–56.
These definitions allow us to rewrite the Perfect Abadie, Alberto, and Javier Gardeazabal. 2003. “The Economic
Costs of Conflict: A Case Study of the Basque Country.”
Bayesian equilibrium conditions as follows:
American Economic Review 93(1):113–32.
Pooling: (t; uc, uc): ␥4 + c 4 ≤ k̄ − k. Arce, Daniel G., and Todd Sandler. 2007. “Terrorist Signalling
¯ and the Value of Intelligence.” British Journal of Political Sci-
Pooling: (t; dc, dc): k̄ − k ≤ ␥3 . ence. Forthcoming.
¯
Separating: (t; uc, dc): ␥2 ≤ k̄ − k ≤ ␥1 + c 1 Bell, J. Bowyer. 1971. “The Myth of the Guerrilla: Revolutionary
¯ − Pr(E | p̄ = p,¯ D = 0) ≥ Theory and Malpractice.”
and Pr(E | p̄ = 0, D = d)
Bell, J. Bowyer. 1977. Terror Out of Zion: Irgun Zvai Leumi,
p[Pr(E | p̄ = 0, D = d) ¯ − Pr(E | p̄ = 1, D = d)].
LEHI, and the Palestine Underground, 1929–1949. New York:
¯
St. Martin’s Press.
Separating: (nt; uc, dc): ␥2 ≤ k̄ − k ≤ ␥1 + c 1
and Pr(E | p̄ = 0, D = d) ¯ − Pr(E | p̄ = p,¯ D = 0) ≤ Blomberg, S. Brock, Gregory D. Hess, and Akila Weerapana.
2004. “Economic Conditions and Terrorism.” European Jour-
p[Pr(E | p̄ = 0, D = d) ¯ − Pr(E | p̄ = 1, D = d)].
nal of Political Economy 20(2):463–78.
¯
Note that the existence conditions for the separat- Bloom, Mia M. 2004. “Palestinian Suicide Bombing: Public Sup-
port, Market Share and Outbidding.” Political Science Quar-
ing equilibria and for (t; dc , dc ) are disjoint as stated terly 199(1):61–88.
in the text because ␥ 3 < ␥ 2 , and that the conditions for Bueno de Mesquita, Ethan. 2005a. “The Quality of Terror.”
(t; uc , dc ) and (nt; uc , dc ) are also disjoint (except in American Journal of Political Science 49(3):515–30.
the knife-edge case when the extremist faction is indif- Bueno de Mesquita, Ethan. 2005b. “The Terrorist Endgame: A
ferent between t and nt). And when ␥ 4 + c 4 > ␥ 3 , no Model with Moral Hazard and Learning.” Journal of Conflict
pure-strategy Perfect Bayesian equilibrium exists when Resolution 49(2):237–58.
k̄ − k ∈ (␥3 , min(␥2 , ␥4 + c 4 )). Clark, Robert P. 1990. Negotiating with ETA: Obstacles to Peace
¯ in the Basque Country, 1975–1988. Las Vegas: University of
Nevada Press.
A.6 Proof of Proposition 3 de Figueiredo, Rui J.P. Jr., and Barry R. Weingast. 2001. “Vi-
cious Cycles: Endogenous Political Extremism and Political
Consider the equilibrium conditions as written in the Violence.” Institute of Governmental Studies Working paper
above “Note on Equilibrium Ranges,” and note that none #2001-9.
of the ␥ ’s, c’s, or Pr’s are functions of the k’s. Fix ␥ 4 + c 4 DeNardo, James. 1985. Power in Numbers: The Political Strat-
and ␥ 1 + c 1 . Then for all k̄ − k ∈ (0, mi n(␥3 , ␥4 + c 4 )) egy of Protest and Rebellion. Princeton: Princeton University
¯ Press.
the unique Perfect Bayesian equilibrium must be (t; dc ,
dc ). And for all k̄ − k ∈ (␥1 + c 1 , ∞), (t; uc , uc ) must be Enders, Walter, and Todd Sandler. 1996. “Terrorism and Foreign
¯ Direct Investment in Spain and Greece.” Kyklos 49(3):3331–
the unique Perfect Bayesian equilibrium. And a separating
52.
equilibrium clearly exists for at least some k̄ − k between
¯ English, Richard. 2003. Armed Struggle: The History of the IRA.
these ranges. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Funes, Maria J. 1998. “Social Responses to Political Violence in
the Basque Country: Peace Movements and Their Audience.”
A.7 Proof of Proposition 4 Journal of Conflict Resolution 42:493–510.
Consider the equilibrium conditions as written in the Ginkel, John, and Alastair Smith. 1999. “So You Say You Want
a Revolution: A Game Theoretic Explanation of Revolu-
above “Note on Equilibrium Ranges,” and note that none tion in Repressive Regimes.” Journal of Conflict Resolution
of ␥ 1 , ␥ 2 , the k’s, or c 1 are functions of prior belief p. 43(3):291–316.
∂␥3
∂p
> 0 and ∂␥ ∂p
4
< 0 and ∂c ∂p
4
< 0 by Lemma 1; these re- Krueger, Alan B., and David Laitin. 2004. “Kto Kogo? A Cross-
lations imply that the equilibrium ranges of (t; uc , uc ) Country Study of the Origins and Targets of Terrorism.”
and (t; dc , dc ) both grow as p increases. The range over Typescript. Princeton University.
which a separating equilibrium exists is unchanged, and Kydd, Andrew, and Barbara F. Walter. 2002. “Sabotaging the
Peace: The Politics of Extremist Violence.” International Or-
the effect of changes in p on which separating equilibrium ganization 56(2):263–96.
exists is ambiguous because both sides of the relevant in- Lapan, Harvey E., and Todd Sandler. 1988. “To Bargain or Not to
equality condition increase in p and the ordering depends Bargain: That Is the Question.” American Economic Review
on the details of the distribution . 78(2):16–21.
THE PROPAGANDA OF THE DEED 381

Lapan, Harvey E., and Todd Sandler. 1993. “Terrorism and Sig- Rosendorff, Peter, and Todd Sandler. 2004. “Too Much of a
naling.” European Journal of Political Economy 9(3):383–97. Good Thing? The Proactive Response Dilemma.” Journal of
Lichbach, Mark Irving. 1987. “Deterrence of Escalation? The Conflict Resolution 48(4)657–71.
Puzzle of Aggregate Studies of Repression and Dissent.” The Sandler, Todd, and Walter Enders. 2005. “Transnational Ter-
Journal of Conflict Resolution 31:266–97. rorism: An Economic Analysis.” In The Economic Im-
Mishal, Shaul, and Avraham Sela. 2000. The Palestinian Hamas: pact of Terrorist Attacks, ed. Harry W. Richardson, Peter
Vision, Violence, and Coexistence. New York: Columbia Uni- Gordon, and James E. Mooore II. Aldershot, UK: Edward
versity Press. Elgar, pp. 11–34.
Overgaard, Per Baltzer. 1994. “The Scale of Terrorist Attacks Siqueira, Kevin, and Todd Sandler. 2007. “Terrorist Versus the
as a Signal of Resources.” Journal of Conflict Resolution Government: Strategic Interaction, Support and Sponsor-
38(3):452–78. ship.” Journal of Conflict Resolution. Forthcoming.
Pape, Robert A. 2003. “The Strategic Logic of Suicide Terror- Zirakzadeh, Cyrus Ernesto. 2002. “From Revolutionary Dreams
ism.” American Political Science Review 97:343–61. to Organizational Fragmentation: Disputes over Violence
Powell, Robert. Forthcoming. Defending Against Terrorist At- within ETA and Sendero Luminoso.” Terrorism and Politi-
tacks with Limited Resources. American Political Science cal Violence 14(4):66–92.
Review.

You might also like