You are on page 1of 1

SIRULIUKTS ANU bET(JI\LJ

(92) If Johnhasat leasttwo cars,thethird oneparkedoutsidemustbe somebody


or two). The implicature then is that more than two (i.e., possibly three)peoplewho else's.
smoke and drink live to the relevantlesserage. This seemsright.
Clearly,here too we want to accommodatein the antecedentof (92) an "and no more"
proviso.I.e., we want to restrictour considerationto setsof worlds from which people
3.2.2. Default override with more than two cars are excluded. The effect of this accommodationis the same
As we observed,the default is usually the strong meaning.However, implicatures as the computation of an implicature. But if we are right, the mechanismthrough
can be cancelled.Under the presentview, cancellation amounts to a simple kind of which this happensis very different from how implicatures come about normally. In
backtracking. Let me illustrate with a few examples. (In what follows, c + S stands (92) the implicature is not added locally. It is accommodatedat somepoint to avoid
for the incrementationof context c by S.) a near contradiction.
A first consequenceof this view is that we would expect phenomenalike those
(S9) a. Johnor Theoarethere'Maybe/infact, they both are' exemplifiedin (90) and (91) to be hard to obtain in contextswhereaccommodation
vs there'(theo'))
b. (c + there'(sue') is hard. In particular, we know that accommodationwith antecedentsof conditional
vs there'(theo')) + there'(sue')n (there'(theo')
c. (c + there'(sue') or quantificational domains is relatively common. But, for instance,it is quite hard
in the scopeof negation or of a negative quantifier (as in the famous"no one ate with
Here is what one expects.One first processesthe first sentencein (89a) and addsit to theking becausethere is no king"), and indeed in such contexts it is much harder to
the context, as in (89b). At the point where the first sentenceis processed,the hearer havethe appearanceof implicature preservation.
will hypothesize that the strong interpretation of (89a) is being intended (as that is
the default). Then, the secondsentenceis processedand added to the context, as in (93) No one skippedthe first or secondcourse.
(89c). But this resultsin a contradictionbecausethe exclusiveinterpretationof or is
incompatiblewith the secondsentence.At that point, the hearerthrows away the strong It is hard or impossible to construe (93) as equivalent to 'onoone skipped the first or
interpretation of the first sentenceand switches to the plain one (in accordancewith secondcourse but not both." To the extent that this happens,immediately the sen-
Stalnaker's1978felicity conditions).Items like infact or maybeare markersto sig- tencegets a very strong metalinguistic flavor.
nal that some backtracking must take place. A secondconsequenceis that if somethingprevents us from reintroducing a
We also noticed in section2.2thatsometimes implicaturesarenot cancelledwhen removedimplicature, we should be in trouble (i.e., the sentenceshouldsound awk-
one would expect them to be. The example we discussedthere was ward). Something like (94) might be a casein point:

(90) It was a two coursemeal.But everyonewho skippedthe first or the secondcourse (94) ??No onewho earns940,000a yearcanaffordthishouse
enjoyedit more.
I believethat this sentenceout of the blue is strange(we need to add an understood
The point is that or in this sentenceis not construedinclusively, becauseotherwisea "or less").The reasonis the following. First you removethe "exactly" implicature in
contradictionwould ensue(at leastin "normal" contexts).Now in casessuchas (90), the DE context of no. At that point we would get a sentencesuch as "No one who
my theory predicts that the strong interpretation and the plain interpretation are one earns$40,000 a year or more can afford this house," which (given what afford
and the same. So, how does such a sentencecome to have the reading it seemsto means)is a contradiction (or a near contradiction). At that point, we try to intro-
have ("Everyone who skipped the first or the secondcoursebut not both enjoyed the ducethe implicature. But the result is not much better (why should it be that no one
meal more")? How come we see what looks like an implicature in a context where who earnsexactly $40 a year should not be able to afford this house).So in the end
we wouldn't expect one? A simple way of thinking about this is in terms of accom-
we are left with a pragmatically odd sentence.
modation. We know that quantificational domains are subject quite generally to such
I shouldconcludethis discussionby pointing out that the caseof nonmonotone
phenomena.The interpretation of (90) requires a domain of people who don't skip
quantifierslike (95) now also follows.
toth courses.This yields the sameeffect that we would obtain by not removing the
locally added implicature. (95) a. Exactlytwo studentssmokeor drink.
Casesof a similar sort are also pointed out in Levinson (2000), who discusses,
b. exactlytwo (student')(smoke'vs drink')
for example,
c. exactlytwo (student')(smoke'v drink')
else's.
(91) If Johnhastwo cars,the third oneparkedoutsidemustbe somebody
Thescalarinterpretationof (95a) is (95b), and the plain one is, of course,(95c), despite
Notice how this sentencebecomes a blatant non-sequitur if we introduce an overt the fact that the strong and the weak interpretation are, in this case,informationally
"at least" in the antecedent: independentof each other (i.e., neither entails the other). The reasonwe expect the

You might also like