You are on page 1of 12

HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC, 32 (August 2011), 199–209

The Structure of Frege’s Thoughts


Marian Zouhar
Institute of Philosophy, Slovak Academy of Sciences, Slovakia
marian.zouhar@gmail.com

Received 10 June 2010 Accepted 5 November 2010

Fregean thoughts (i.e. the senses of assertoric sentences) are structured entities because they are composed of
simpler senses that are somehow ordered and interconnected. The constituent senses form a unity because some
of them are ‘saturated’ and some ‘unsaturated’. This paper shows that Frege’s explanation of the structure of
thoughts, which is based on the ‘saturated/unsaturated’ distinction, is by no means sufficient because it permits
what I call ‘wild analyses’, which have certain unwelcome consequences. Wild analyses are made possible because
any ‘unsaturated’ sense that is a mode of presentation of a concept together with any ‘saturated’ sense forms a
thought. The reason is that any concept can be applied to any object (which is presented by a ‘saturated’ sense).
This stems from the fact that Frege was willing to admit only total functions. It is also briefly suggested what
should be done to block wild analyses.

1. Introduction
According to Frege’s post-1890 theory, a thought is a compound semantic entity that is
expressed by assertoric sentence. A thought is composed of the senses expressed by the
constituent sub-expressions of a sentence. The constituent senses are of two fundamentally
different kinds – ‘saturated’ones and ‘unsaturated’ones; a thought emerges when the former
kind of sense ‘saturates’ the latter kind of sense. The resulting thought is both compound
and structured because the constituent senses can be identified as proper parts of it.
According to my main thesis, Frege’s explanation of the structure of thoughts is prob-
lematic. For, if the explanation is based merely on the ‘saturated/unsaturated’ distinction,
there is no chance to block what I call wild analyses of thoughts. But wild analyses have to
be eliminated as possible analyses of thoughts.
To begin with, a cursory overview of Frege’s fundamental logical and semantic notions
would be appropriate. An expression of a given language1 both expresses a sense and des-
ignates a denotation. The sense of an expression is a mode of presentation of its denotation
(cf. Frege 1984b, p. 158). For every sense, there is at most one denotation of which it is a
mode of presentation. There are two kinds of denotations: objects and functions (cf. Frege
1984a, p. 147). A concept ‘is a function of one argument, whose value is always a truth-
value’ (Frege 1979a, p. 119; cf. also Frege 1984a, p. 146). A function of two arguments
whose value is always a truth-value is a relation (cf. Frege 1984a, p. 154). There are two
kinds of expression – proper names and functional expressions. Proper names designate
objects and functional expressions designate functions; concept-words designate concepts
and go with functional expressions. Assertoric sentences designate truth-values. There are
two truth-values: the True and the False. Since the truth-values are objects, assertoric sen-
tences are proper names. The sense of an assertoric sentence is called a thought (cf. Frege
1984b, 1984f ).2 Thoughts are modes of presentation of truth-values. Frege’s theory involves

1
For the sake of simplicity, references to language will be suppressed throughout the paper.
2
This point is somewhat simplified because it is only assertoric sentences complete in every respect that express thoughts.
According to Frege, many assertoric sentences fail to express thoughts. He calls them sometimes quasi-sentences. A quasi-
sentence ‘has the grammatical form of a sentence and yet is not an expression of a thought, although it may be a part of a

History and Philosophy of Logic ISSN 0144-5340 print/ISSN 1464-5149 online © 2011 Taylor & Francis
http://www.informaworld.com DOI: 10.1080/01445340.2010.539054
200 Marian Zouhar

simple and general criteria for distinguishing (i) proper names from functional expressions;
(ii) the senses of proper names from those of functional expressions; and (iii) the deno-
tations of proper names from those of functional expressions. They are all based on the
‘saturated/unsaturated’ distinction.
The paper is organized in the following way: I start with the observation that Frege’s
thoughts are composed of simpler parts that form a certain unity rather than a mere list
of constituent senses. Frege’s explanation of the unified nature of thoughts is presented in
Section 2. Next, I put forth the idea that this explanation permits wild analyses of thoughts
and I point out that such analyses are unacceptable (Section 3). In Section 4, I track the
possibility of wild analyses down to Frege’s theory of functions. Finally, a way out of these
predicaments is briefly suggested (Section 5).

2. Thought and its unity


A thought expressed by a sentence is both compound and structured. It is compound
because it consists of the senses expressed by the sub-expressions of the sentence. As Frege
claims, ‘[a]s the proper name is part of the sentence, so its sense is part of the thought’ (Frege
1979d, p. 191). So, thoughts can be taken ‘as composed of simple parts’ which ‘correspond
to the simple parts of the sentences’ (Frege 1984h, p. 390). In the case of a sentence, we are
capable to identify retrospectively its simple constituent expressions; analogously, when we
have a thought, we are capable to identify backwards its simple constituent senses. However,
being compound is not the same as being structured; for a mere list of senses is compound as
well without being structured. What is required is that the constituent senses of a thought be
mutually interconnected in certain ways to form a unity.3 By parity of reasoning, a sentence
is not just a mere list of the constituent expressions; they form a unity, because they are
mutually interconnected according to the laws of grammar.
Since the thought is not a mere list of the constituent senses, we may ask:
[H]ow a thought comes to be constructed, and how the parts are so combined together
that the whole amounts to something more that the parts taken separately[?] (Frege
1984h, p. 390)
Let us call this the problem of thought-unity. Frege’s solution to it is ingenious. He claims:
For not all the parts of a thought can be complete; at least one must be ‘unsaturated’,
or predicative; otherwise they would not hold together. For example, the sense of
the phrase ‘the number 2’ does not hold together with that of the expression ‘the
concept prime number’ without a link. We apply such a link in the sentence ‘the
number 2 falls under the concept prime number’; it is contained in the words ‘falls
under’, which need to be completed in two ways – by a subject and an accusative;
and only because their sense is thus ‘unsaturated’ are they capable of serving as a
link. (Frege 1984c, p. 193)

sentence that does express a thought, and thus a part of a sentence proper’ (Frege 1979d, p. 190). A quasi-sentence is capable
to express, at most, a mode of presentation of a concept as opposed to that of a truth-value. In general, this holds for sentences
in which ‘the mere wording, which can be made permanent by writing or the gramophone, does not suffice for the expression
of the thought’ (Frege 1984f, pp. 357–358); glaring examples are sentences in which the present tense indicates the time of
utterance (as opposed to timelessness; cf. Frege 1984f, p. 358) or sentences featuring demonstrative or indexical expressions
(cf. Frege 1984f, p. 358). Anyway, I pretend the sentences used as examples in the present paper do express thoughts.
3
It is easy to see that the constituent senses have to be unified somehow in order to become a thought. According to Frege, a
thought is something ‘to which the question “Is it true?” is in principle applicable’ (Frege 1979f, p. 253). Thus, the thoughts are
bearers of truth-values. However, a list of senses can be neither true nor false; the constituent senses have to be interconnected
in accordance with certain specific (logical) relations; being truth-evaluable can be viewed as a product resulting from the
application of these relations to the constituent senses.
The Structure of Frege’s Thoughts 201

Frege sorts out the constituent senses in two categories: those that are complete or
‘saturated’ and those that are incomplete or ‘unsaturated’. An ‘unsaturated’ sense involves
at least one empty place to be supplemented with another sense. It is impossible for two
complete senses to hold together; they form just a mere list of two senses. But if a complete
sense fills an empty place in an incomplete sense, what we get is a unity featuring the two
senses as its constituents. A thought is a unity because an ‘unsaturated’ constituent sense is
completed with a ‘saturated’ one.
At the level of expressions, there occurs a similar problem that may be labelled the problem
of sentence-unity. According to the traditional logic, sentences such as ‘Socrates is wise’ can
be analysed into the subject term ‘Socrates’, the copula ‘is’, and the predicate term ‘wise’.
Now, how is it possible to distinguish the sentence ‘Socrates is wise’ from a mere list of the
three expressions ‘Socrates’, ‘is’, and ‘wise’? The traditional logic has it that it is the copula
that serves as a unifying device forming sentences from isolated expressions. However, it
remains rather unclear how it does in fact unify the isolated expressions into a whole. The
unifying force of the copula is merely postulated without any deeper explanation.
Frege’s analysis of sentences is radically different:
Statements in general … can be imagined to be split up into two parts; one complete
in itself, and the other in need of supplementation, or ‘unsaturated’. (Frege 1984a,
p. 146)
Concept-words (or functional expressions in general) are ‘unsaturated’and involve empty
places ready for completions; on the other hand, proper names are complete. The sentence
‘Socrates is wise’ is analysed into the proper name ‘Socrates’ and the concept-word ‘( ) is
wise’ in which the empty place is indicated by the round brackets. This picture generalizes:
Any sentence is analysed into an ‘unsaturated’ constituent having at least one empty place
and the appropriate number of (‘saturated’) proper names.
The problem of sentence-unity closely resembles that of thought-unity. The solutions to
both of them are based on the parallel ‘saturated/unsaturated’ distinctions. It remains to
be explained why the empty places go with concept-words (or functional expressions in
general) rather than with proper names. Frege’s answer can be read off this quotation:
As a mere thing, of course, the group of letters ‘and’ is no more unsaturated than any
other thing. It may be called unsaturated in respect of its employment as a symbol
meant to express a sense, for here it can have the intended sense only when situated
between two sentences: its purpose as a symbol requires completion by a preceding
and a succeeding sentence. It is really in the realm of sense that unsaturatedness is
found, and it is transferred from there to the symbol. (Frege 1984h, p. 393; italics
mine)
Thus, the concept-word is incomplete because it expresses an incomplete sense. It is
senses that are ‘saturated’ or ‘unsaturated’ in the first line. Expressions are such only in
a derivative manner. However, this is not the end of story. There remains another open
question: why should we suppose that it is the sense of ‘is wise’ rather than that of ‘Socrates’
that is ‘unsaturated’? As far as I can see, the answer lies in Frege’s distinction between
concepts (functions) and objects; for this reason, it is postponed to Section 4.

3. Thought and wild analysis


The ‘saturated/unsaturated’ distinction is crucial to presenting thoughts as structured
entities – a thought is structured because the empty place in the incomplete constituent
sense is ‘saturated’ by a complete sense. Now it seems that the ‘saturated/unsaturated’
distinction does not suffice to determine the unique structure of the thought. For,
202 Marian Zouhar

a thought can be split up in many ways, so that now one thing, now another appears
as subject or predicate. The thought itself does not yet determine what is to be
regarded as the subject. (Frege 1984c, p. 188)4
Let us adopt, for the sake of simplicity, the following agreement: If E is an expression,
[E] designates the sense of E.5 Now, consider the following thought:
(1) [Caesar conquered Gaul]
It can be analysed in three different ways (cf., e.g. Frege 1984a); we might get (i) the
‘saturated’ sense [Caesar] and the ‘unsaturated’ sense [( ) conquered Gaul];6 (ii) the ‘satu-
rated’ sense [Gaul] and the ‘unsaturated’ sense [Caesar conquered ( )]; (iii) the ‘saturated’
senses [Caesar] and [Gaul] and the double ‘unsaturated’ sense [( ) conquered ( )].7 Thus,
(1) may have the following structures:
(1a) [(Caesar) conquered Gaul]
(1b) [Caesar conquered (Gaul)]
(1c) [(Caesar) conquered (Gaul)]
If (1) has structure (1a), it is about Caesar and claims that he conquered Gaul; if it has
structure (1b), it is about Gaul and claims that it was conquered by Caesar; and if its structure
is (1c), it is about Caesar and Gaul and claims that the former conquered the latter.
Now, what is important for us is that all these analyses obey just a single principle. It may
be called The Principle of Analysis and is based on the ‘saturated/unsaturated’ distinction:
Whenever a thought is analysed, it is split up into an ‘unsaturated’ part, which has
at least one empty place, and the required number of ‘saturated’ parts that fill up the
empty place(s) in the ‘unsaturated’ sense.
Thus, whenever we analyse a thought what we have to get is a mode of presentation of
a concept or a relation and the required number of modes of presentation of objects. Any
analysis which conforms to this principle is admissible.
Frege seems to adhere also to a converse version of this principle, as witnessed by the
second sentence in the following quotation:
By analysing a singular thought we obtain components of the complete and of the
unsaturated kind, which of course cannot occur in isolation; but any component of
the one kind together with any component of the other kind will form a thought.
(Frege 1979d, p. 187; italics mine)

4
Despite certain vital differences between his early and mature semantic theories, Frege adopted a similar standpoint as early as
in his Begriffsschrift: ‘For us, the different ways in which the same conceptual content can be considered as a function of this
or that argument have no importance so long as function and argument are completely determinate’ (Frege 1967, p. 23). So,
different analyses of the same conceptual content are possible provided what we get is a completely determinate function and
argument.
5
This notation should make it plain that I am concerned here solely with thoughts and other kinds of sense rather than with
sentences and other kinds of expression.
6
The sign ‘( )’ indicates empty place. Frege usually used Greek letters ζ , ξ , etc., in the same manner. I shall sometimes write
‘(E)’ to indicate that E fills the empty place.
7
Different analyses of the same thought have no bearing on the identity of the thought. In particular, the thought (1) as analysed
in accordance with (i) and the thought (1) as analysed in accordance with (ii) are one and the same thought. However, this is
far from being obvious. Frege himself seemed to be of different opinions when he discussed a somewhat different example. On
the one hand, he claimed that [S] and [non-non-S] (where S is a complete sentence expressing a thought) are different thoughts
because one of them – as opposed to the other one – involves two occurrences of [non-( )] (cf. Frege 1984g, p. 389). In another
paper, however, he said that [S] and [non-non-S] are the same thought (cf. Frege 1984h, pp. 404–405) (moreover, [S] is supposed
to be the same thought as [S and S] and [S or S], etc.!). What we may see here is that sometimes Frege took the structure of a
thought as essential to its identity and sometimes he did not (for an excellent discussion see Tichý 1988, p. 32).
The Structure of Frege’s Thoughts 203

The converse version – or the Principle of Synthesis, as we may call it – runs:


Whenever an ‘unsaturated’ sense (that is a mode of presentation of a concept or a
relation), which has at least one empty place, is filled up with the required number
of ‘saturated’ senses a thought results.
Wolfgang Carl gives an apt summary of Frege’s position that is completely compatible
with the above principles. Furthermore, he points to a possible awkwardness which can be
read off Frege’s ideas:
This ability to consider a thought as being composed in different ways from its
constituents is limited only by the requirement that one draw a definite distinction
between concept and object, but within the limits of this distinction one is perfectly
able to form concepts for which there is no predicate in ordinary language and to
take arguments as objects that are not objects in any ordinary or metaphysical sense
of the word. (Carl 1994, p. 67)
The second half of Carl’s quotation should be taken seriously. In what follows, I shall use
this observation to show that the above principles lead to difficulties for Frege’s theory of
thought-structure. When we consider simple examples such as [Socrates is wise] or [Caesar
conquered Gaul], everything goes smoothly despite the fact that various analyses of the
same thought might be available. However, in the case of more complex thoughts, it is
sometimes possible to produce also analyses deviating from conventional ones in certain
respects; I call them wild analyses. Such analyses can be offered for some thoughts in which
several ‘unsaturated’ senses can be discerned. Typical examples are thoughts expressed by
compound sentences such as ‘a is  * b is ’, where ‘a is ’ and ‘b is ’ are sentences
and ‘*’ is a connective.
The following example concerning the thought
(2) [Socrates thinks and Plato sings]
explains what I have in mind. Here are two analyses of the thought, one that is conventional
and the other that is wild (the arrow indicates splitting):
Conventional analysis:
1. [Socrates thinks and Plato sings] → [Socrates thinks] + [( ) and ( )] + [Plato sings].
2. [Socrates thinks] → [Socrates] + [( ) thinks].
3. [Plato sings] → [Plato] + [( ) sings].
Wild analysis:
1. [Socrates thinks and Plato sings] → [Socrates thinks and Plato] + [( ) sings].
2. [Socrates thinks and Plato] → [Socrates thinks] + [( ) and ( )] + [Plato].
3. [Socrates thinks] → [Socrates] + [( ) thinks].
In both cases, we have the same simple constituent senses – namely [Socrates], [( )
thinks], [( ) and ( )], [Plato] and [( ) sings] – but the structure of (2) can be captured in two
different manners:
(2a) [((Socrates) thinks) and ((Plato) sings)]
(2b) [(((Socrates) thinks) and (Plato)) sings]
Here (2a) corresponds to the conventional analysis and (2b) to the wild one. According
to the wild analysis, thought (2) can be derived in the following way: complete the sense
[( ) thinks] with the sense [Socrates] – the ‘saturated’ sense [Socrates thinks] results; next,
204 Marian Zouhar

supplement the sense [( ) and ( )], which is double ‘unsaturated’, with two ‘saturated’ senses
[Socrates thinks] and [Plato] – the ‘saturated’sense [Socrates thinks and Plato] arises; finally,
supplement the sense [( ) sings] with the sense [Socrates thinks and Plato] – the ‘saturated’
sense [Socrates thinks and Plato sings] results. What is unusual in this derivation is that
the sense [( ) and ( )], which is supposed to be ‘saturated’ with two thoughts under normal
circumstances, is filled with different kinds of sense. However, this move is in complete
agreement with the Principle of Synthesis.
Both analyses are permitted because they follow the ‘saturated/unsaturated’ distinction.
They obey Frege’s dictum quoted above that ‘a thought can be split up in many ways, so that
now one thing, now another appears as subject or predicate’. This dictum is preserved in
any of the following partitions of (2) into subject and predicate ((2c) and (2f) are simplified
versions of (2a) and (2b), respectively):8
(2c) [(Socrates thinks) and (Plato sings)]
(2d) [(Socrates thinks) and Plato sings]
(2e) [Socrates thinks and (Plato sings)]
(2f) [(Socrates thinks and Plato) sings]
Now let us turn to some consequences. For the sake of argument, suppose it is true that
Socrates thinks as well as that Plato sings; thus, (2) is true. It can be shown the two analyses
lead to widely different results. When we apply the concepts presented by [( ) thinks] and
[( ) sings] to Socrates and Plato, respectively, we get the True in both cases and when we
apply the relation presented by [( ) and ( )] to the True twice over, the result is again the
True. The conventional analysis conforms to our assumption. The wild analysis, however,
gives another result. When we apply the concept presented by [( ) thinks] to Socrates, the
True results; next, when we apply the relation presented by [( ) and ( )] to the True and
Plato as its arguments, its value is the False (see Section 4 for explanation); finally, when
we apply the concept presented by [( ) sings] to the False, the resulting value is again the
False. So, the wild analysis leads to different results than the conventional one.
This is unacceptable for Frege’s theory of senses. For he claims that for any sense there is
at most one denotation; consequently, if the thoughts T1 and T2 are modes of presentation of
different truth-values, they have to be different thoughts. When we assume the wild analysis
concerns the very same thought as the conventional one, we offend against this essential
feature of Frege’s theory. So, in spite of the fact that (2f) (or (2b)) involves the mode of
presentation of a completely determinate concept and that of a completely determinate
object, ‘saturating’ the former with the latter should not produce (2). This is at odds with
the Principle of Analysis which admits that a thought can be split up at will provided the
‘saturated/unsaturated’ distinction is preserved.
Now, the above reason for rejecting (2f) (or (2b)) seems to be just a specific feature of
this kind of example. By way of comparison, consider the thought
(3) [1 is even and Plato sings]
We have:
Conventional analysis:
1. [1 is even and Plato sings] → [1 is even] + [( ) and ( )] + [Plato sings].

8
It can be seen, moreover, that the following partition is not possible:
(2g) [(Socrates) thinks and Plato sings]
The reason is that [( ) thinks and Plato sings] cannot be generated from [( ) thinks], [( ) and ( )], [Plato] and [( ) sings]. In
particular, [( ) thinks] (qua an ‘unsaturated’ sense) cannot fill an empty place in [( ) and ( )] which can be ‘saturated’ only
with complete senses. In other words, [Socrates] is not a proper subject of (2) and [( ) thinks and Plato sings] is not a proper
predicate of it.
The Structure of Frege’s Thoughts 205

2. [1 is even] → [1] + [( ) is even].


3. [Plato sings] → [Plato] + [( ) sings].
Wild analysis:
1. [1 is even and Plato sings] → [1 is even and Plato] + [( ) sings].
2. [1 is even and Plato] → [1 is even] + [( ) and ( )] + [Plato].
3. [1 is even] → [1] + [( ) is even].
The structure of (3) is parallel to that of (2); so, we have either (3a) or (3b):
(3a) [((1) is even) and ((Plato) sings)]
(3b) [(((1) is even) and (Plato)) sings]
It is easy to see that thought (3) has to be necessarily false. Both analyses conform to
this fact. First, consider the conventional analysis: applying the concept presented by [( )
is even] to 1 gives us the False and applying the concept presented by [( ) sings] to Plato
gives us the True; finally, applying the relation presented by [( ) and ( )] to the False and the
True results in the False. The same outcome is achieved when the wild analysis is followed:
the value of the concept presented by [( ) is even] for argument 1 is the False and the value
of the relation presented by [( ) and ( )] for the arguments the False and Plato is the False
as well; finally the value of the concept presented by [( ) sings] for the False is again the
False. So, the reason for rejecting (2b) (and (2f)) as a proper analysis of (2) need not be
generalized for (3b).
Both thoughts (2) and (3) are perfectly on par; they can be taken as substitution instances
of [x is φ and y is ψ]. Yet, the latter can be analysed both conventionally and wildly without
doing any harm to some other postulates of Frege’s theory while the former can be analysed
either merely conventionally or merely wildly. Wild analyses are such because they may
lead to unpredictable consequences and portray different thoughts (albeit very similar to
each other in certain respects) as requiring different treatments.

4. Total functions and wild analysis again


Since it is the Principle of Analysis that makes wild analyses possible, it might be instruc-
tive to explore the motivations underlying it. In doing so, we have to return to Frege’s
ontology of objects and concepts (functions). For Frege’s ontology justifies why the func-
tion presented by [( ) and ( )], despite being a truth function, is capable to take as its
arguments both truth-values and non-truth-values.
First of all, it is important to notice that
[t]he peculiarity of functional signs, which we here called ‘unsaturatedness’, natu-
rally has something answering to it in the functions themselves. They too may be
called ‘unsaturated’. (Frege 1984e, p. 292)
and that
the argument does not belong with a function, but goes together with the function
to make up a complete whole; for a function by itself must be called incomplete, in
need of supplementation, or ‘unsaturated’. (Frege 1984a, p. 140)
On the other hand, since an ‘object is anything that is not a function’ (Frege 1984a,
p. 147), objects are complete or ‘saturated’. Furthermore,
[w]hat in the case of a function is called unsaturatedness, we may, in the case of a
concept, call its predicative nature. (Frege 1979a, p. 119)
206 Marian Zouhar

The predicative nature of concepts is just a special case of their ‘unsaturatedness’ (Frege
1984c, p. 187n).9 To say that concepts can be applied, or predicated, to objects is tantamount
to saying that objects fall, or can be subsumed, under concepts (Frege 1979d, p. 183; 1989d,
p. 193). So, to say that concepts are ‘unsaturated’ or that they involve empty places to be
filled with arguments is just a metaphorical way of saying that they can be applied to
something.
Now it should be observed that all functions are total for Frege. Consequently, concerning
concepts, it holds that
for any argument they shall have a truth-value as their value; that it shall be deter-
minate, for any object, whether it falls under the concept or not. In other words: as
regards concepts we have a requirement of sharp delimitation. (Frege 1984a, p. 148;
italics mine; cf. also Frege 1984d, p. 245)
This fact is crucial for Frege and it can be illustrated by various passages. For example:
The sentence ‘ > 2’ [where ‘’ designates the sun] is false, because the sun is
not a number, and only numbers can be greater than 2. Accordingly the sentence
‘( > 2) ⊃ (2 > 2)’ would be true, regardless of whether its right hand side were
true or false – and it ought to be one or the other. (Frege 1984d, p. 245)
Frege is not bound to say that ‘ > 2’is an ill-formed sentence; for the relation designated
by ‘>’ is total and, thus, defined for any couple of arguments whatsoever. Similarly, when
he introduced the so-called horizontal stroke, i.e. the sign ‘−x’ (where x is a variable), he
presented it as a sign for a total function: its value is the True if its argument is the True;
otherwise – i.e. when its argument is either the False or something that is not a truth-value
at all – its value is the False (Frege 1984a, p. 149). As a result, both ‘−1 + 3 = 5’ and
‘−4’ designate the False, because ‘1 + 3 = 5’ designates the False while ‘4’ designates a
non-truth-value. In a similar vein, Frege introduced another total function designated by
‘−x’ such that its value
is the False just for those argument for which the value of −x is the True, and,
conversely, is the True for the arguments for which the value of −x is the False.
(Frege 1984a, p. 150)
Since the value of −x is the True just for the argument the True, the value of  x is the
False provided it takes as its argument the True; and since the value of −x is the False if it
takes as its argument either the False or a non-truth-value, so the value of  x is the True
if it is applied either to the False or to a non-truth-value. In particular, both ‘ 1 + 3 = 5’
and ‘ 4’ designate the True.10 Finally, Frege defines the implicative function ‘if y, then x’
such that its value

9
Although Frege points out that ‘[t]he words “unsaturated” and “predicative” seem more suited to the sense than the [denotation]’,
he readily adds that ‘still there must be something on the part of the [denotation] which corresponds to this, and I know of no
better words’ (Frege 1979a, p. 119n).
10
I should stress that Frege’s discussion concerning the function  x is rather murky. For if we take the definition quoted in the
main text, it seems that  x is a total function that is defined for all objects whatsoever, be they truth-values or not: the function
 x is allowed there to take as its arguments everything that can be an argument of the function −x. However, a few lines below
it is written: ‘I conceive of  x as a function with the argument −x : ( x) = ( (−x)) where I imagine the two horizontal
strokes to be fused together. But we also have: (−( x)) = ( x), since the value of  x is always a truth-value’ (Frege 1984a,
p. 150). This suggests that  x may take as its arguments exclusively truth-values because the value of −x is a truth-value for
whatever argument it takes. So, it seems that  x is a partial function.
Now, the question is how to handle this apparent contradiction. I think we should take the official definition of  x as what
is superior to all other formulations concerning  x. Anyway, we are obliged to explain away the seeming contrariwise
formulations. The quotation given above continues: ‘I thus regard the bits of the stroke in “ x” to the right and to the left of
the stroke of negation as horizontals’ (Frege 1984a, p. 150). This implies that the two horizontal strokes form a compound sign
The Structure of Frege’s Thoughts 207

is to be the False if we take the True as the y-argument and at the same time take
some object that is not the True as the x-argument. (Frege 1984a, p. 154)

Thus, if the x-argument is the True or the y-argument is either the False or a non-truth-
value, the value of the implicative function is the True.
As far as I can see, there are at least two important reasons why Frege is willing to permit
only total functions.11 First, if it would be possible that there be at least one argument for
which a concept does not give any value, the concept would not have sharp boundaries and
could not be well defined according to Frege’s standards. No uncertainty is permitted and
for any object whatsoever it has to be clear whether it falls under the concept in question or
does not.12 Secondly, if the concept designated by ‘F( )’ would not give any value for the
argument designated by ‘a’, the compound expression ‘F(a)’ would designate nothing at all
and could not appear in scientific discourse. This would be problematic even for expressions
such as ‘3 ÷ 0’ which occur in mathematical discourse, for the sentences such as ‘3 ÷ 0 =
1’ could not be taken to say something false while the sentences such as ‘3 ÷ 0  = 1’ could
not be taken to say something true.13
Now we are ready to justify the idea that wild analyses of thoughts are not excluded by
Frege’s overall theory. It is easy to see that Frege’s claim quoted above that ‘any component
of the [“unsaturated”] kind together with any component of the [“saturated”] kind will
form a thought’ is made possible because of his insistence that all functions he is willing to
recognize are total. ‘Unsaturated’senses are such because they are modes of presentations of
concepts (functions) and ‘saturated’senses are such because they are modes of presentations
of objects. And as we are allowed to apply any concept to any object without any restrictions,
so we have to be allowed to supplement any ‘unsaturated’ sense with any ‘saturated’ sense
without any restrictions. For this reason, it is possible to analyse the thought [1 is even and
Plato sings] wildly, i.e. to split it up into [1 is even and Plato] and [( ) sings]. For, the sense
[1 is even and Plato] can be correctly generated from the senses [1 is even], [( ) and ( )] and
[Plato], respectively. The double ‘unsaturated’ sense [( ) and ( )] can be ‘saturated’ with any

with the stroke of negation; this compound sign can be taken as a unit that can be prefixed to a sign for an argument of the
function. The sign of its argument need not involve the horizontal stroke because the stroke is already a part of the compound
sign. Consequently, the function designated by the compound sign may take as its arguments any x; it is not required that it be
applied only to something designated as ‘−x’ (for any x). The identity ‘( x) = ( (−x))’ can be taken to mean that when we
apply the function −x to a particular argument, α, what we get is the same as when we apply it to the argument −α. It need
not be taken to mean that whenever the function is applied to something, it is, in fact, applied only to truth-values (designated
by ‘−x’).
In fact, there are at least two different kinds of evidence for the claim that Frege permitted the function  x to take as its
arguments also non-truth-values. First, anything that can be substituted for x in ‘−x’ can be substituted also for x in ‘ x’.
The letter x is the same variable in both ‘ x’ and ‘−x’. Secondly, Frege suggests to read ‘ 2’ as ‘2 is not the True’ (Frege
1984a, p. 150); i.e. the function designated by ‘( ) is not the True’ (which is just the function  x) takes here as its argument
the number 2 (which is a non-truth-value). If the function −x was allowed to take just truth-values as its arguments, ‘2 is not
the True’ should be properly reformulated as ‘(−2) is not the True’ and taken as saying that the False is not the True (because
‘−2’ designates the False). So, Frege probably did not take  x as a partial function.
11
Pavel Tichý presents a thoroughgoing analysis of Frege’s horror vacui – as he describes his repudiation of partial functions –
in Tichý 1988, p. 31.
12
This fact is highlighted in numerous places in Frege’s writings (cf. Frege 1979c, p. 15; 1979d, pp. 195–196; 1979e, pp. 229,
241, 243–244; 1984a, p. 148). Frege adopted it also in his pre-1890 works (cf. Frege 1950, p. 87). The paramount motive
underlying his views on logic was that proofs in logic and mathematics should be conducted in the most rigorous manner
possible (cf. Frege 1967, 5ff.). The call for sharp definitions of concepts was an essential part of this enterprise.
13
Frege claims that ‘the proper name formed from this function-name and any proper name whatever in the argument-place must
always have a [denotation], provided only that this last proper name [designates] something. For the proper name thus formed
out of our function-name and this proper name is a part of the proper name of the True’ (Frege 1979c, p. 155). If an expression
designates nothing, it belongs to fictional discourse and cannot be used in scientific discourse (cf. Frege 1979a, p. 118; 1979b,
p. 130; 1979d, p. 194; 1984b, p. 163).
208 Marian Zouhar

couple of (complete) senses because the function presented by [( ) and ( )] has to give some
value for any couple of arguments (objects); thus, it can be ‘saturated’ with a thought (e.g.
the sense [1 is even]) as well as with something that is not a thought (e.g. the sense [Plato]).

5. Conclusions
Let us recapitulate. There are two fundamentally different kinds of senses, ‘saturated’
ones and ‘unsaturated’ ones. A sense is ‘saturated’ because it is a mode of presentation
of an object that is itself ‘saturated’, and a sense is ‘unsaturated’ because it is a mode of
presentation of a concept (or, more generally, a function) that is itself ‘unsaturated’. If we
‘saturate’ the latter kind of sense with a former kind of sense, what we get is a thought that
is compound (because the constituent senses are proper parts of the thought) and structured
(because the constituent senses form a unity). There is no other restriction that is to be met
in combining senses into thoughts. As a result, it is possible to analyse certain kinds of
thought wildly, i.e. to split them up into rather unexpected constituent senses.
Now, what should be done to block wild analyses? First of all, notice that all functions are
total for Frege because he took it that to give some value for any object whatsoever was the
same as to have sharp boundaries. Thus, the totality of concepts (functions) is essential to
them to be well defined. If the two things were separated, the above problems need not arise.
It means that what we need is to preserve the concepts as having sharp boundaries while
allowing them to be partial. This would be possible provided Frege’s theory of functions
be supplemented with a version of the theory of types. Given this supplementation, the
concepts are allowed to give no value for certain kinds of argument. If all objects were
assorted into types, the concepts might be defined only for certain types, i.e. for certain
subsets of the set of all objects. The concepts would have sharp boundaries in that sense
that for every item in a given subset it gives some value or other; on the other hand, they
would remain undefined for the members of the other subsets. This would not mean that
the concepts are not well defined but that it is inadmissible to apply them to the members
of the other subsets.
Given this suggestion, it is easy to see that the above problems would not arise. Consider
again the thought [1 is even and Plato sings]. If the function presented by [( ) and ( )] was
allowed to take only truth-values as its arguments, it would be forbidden to fill the empty
places in [( ) and ( )] with senses that are not modes of presentation of truth-values. The
double ‘unsaturated’ sense [( ) and ( )] could be ‘saturated’ only with thoughts. Since [Plato]
is not one, it could not be used as a completion of [( ) and ( )]. Consequently, there would
be no way to build up [1 is even and Plato]. At the same time, it would be forbidden to split
up the thought [1 is even and Plato sings] into [( ) sings] and [1 is even and Plato]. The wild
analysis is thus blocked.

Acknowledgement
I am indebted to Pavel Cmorej and three anonymous referees of History and Philosophy of Logic for their
valuable suggestions.

References
Carl, W. 1994. Frege’s Theory of Sense and Reference: Its Origins and Scope, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Frege, G. 1950. The Foundations of Arithmetic, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Frege, G. 1967. ‘Begriffsschrift, a formula language, modeled upon that of arithmetic, for pure thought’, in J. van
Heijenoort, ed., From Frege to Gödel, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, pp. 5–82.
Frege, G. 1979a. ‘Comments on sense and meaning’, in G. Frege, ed., Posthumous Writings, Oxford: Basil
Blackwell, pp. 118–125.
Frege, G. 1979b. ‘Logic’, in G. Frege, ed., Posthumous Writings, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, pp. 126–151.
The Structure of Frege’s Thoughts 209

Frege, G. 1979c. ‘The argument for my stricter canons of definitions’, in G. Frege, ed., Posthumous Writings,
Oxford: Basil Blackwell, pp. 152–156.
Frege, G. 1979d. ‘Introduction to logic’, in G. Frege, ed., Posthumous Writings, Oxford: Basil Blackwell,
pp. 185–196.
Frege, G. 1979e. ‘Logic in mathematics’, in G. Frege, ed., Posthumous Writings, Oxford: Basil Blackwell,
pp. 203–250.
Frege, G. 1979f. ‘Notes for Ludwig Darmstaedter’, in G. Frege, ed., Posthumous Writings, Oxford: Basil Blackwell,
pp. 253–257.
Frege, G. 1984a. ‘Function and concept’, in G. Frege, ed., Collected Papers on Mathematics, Logic, and Philosophy,
Oxford: Basil Blackwell, pp. 137–156.
Frege, G. 1984b. ‘On sense and meaning’, in G. Frege, ed., Collected Papers on Mathematics, Logic, and
Philosophy, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, pp. 157–177.
Frege, G. 1984c. ‘On concept and object’, in G. Frege, ed., Collected Papers on Mathematics, Logic, and
Philosophy, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, pp. 182–194.
Frege, G. 1984d. ‘On Mr. Peano’s conceptual notation and my own’, in G. Frege, ed., Collected Papers on
Mathematics, Logic, and Philosophy, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, pp. 234–248.
Frege, G. 1984e. ‘What is a function?’ in G. Frege, ed., Collected Papers on Mathematics, Logic, and Philosophy,
Oxford: Basil Blackwell, pp. 285–292.
Frege, G. 1984f. ‘Thoughts’, in G. Frege, ed., Collected Papers on Mathematics, Logic, and Philosophy, Oxford:
Basil Blackwell, pp. 351–372.
Frege, G. 1984g. ‘Negation’, in G. Frege, ed., Collected Papers on Mathematics, Logic, and Philosophy, Oxford:
Basil Blackwell, pp. 373–389.
Frege, G. 1984h. ‘Compound thoughts’, in G. Frege, ed., Collected Papers on Mathematics, Logic, and Philosophy,
Oxford: Basil Blackwell, pp. 390–406.
Tichý, P. 1988. Foundations of Frege’s Logic, Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.
Copyright of History & Philosophy of Logic is the property of Taylor & Francis Ltd and its content may not be
copied or emailed to multiple sites or posted to a listserv without the copyright holder's express written
permission. However, users may print, download, or email articles for individual use.

You might also like