You are on page 1of 6

Modality-Instrumental-I.

pdf

javi_roman10

INGLÉS INSTRUMENTAL I (NIVEL B2)

1º Grado en Estudios Ingleses

Facultad de Filosofía y Letras


Universidad de Granada

Reservados todos los derechos.


No se permite la explotación económica ni la transformación de esta obra. Queda permitida la impresión en su totalidad.
Inst I – MODALITY SYSTEMS Dr Rocío Montoro

MODALITY

1. Definition 2. Types of modality

Modality is a topic primarily discussed in linguistics but its impact 2.1 Deontic modality
on stylistic approaches to language has been enormously felt.
However, decisions as to which elements are to be considered Deontic modality, first of all, is the modal system of ‘duty’, as it is
under the general notion of modality vary depending on the concerned with a speaker’s attitude to the degree of obligation
discipline. In general, modality can be defined as the potential of attaching to the performance of certain actions. (Simpson 1993: 43)
language to project the speaker’s or writer’s attitude about the
proposition expressed. The term ‘attitude’ is here amply and loosely Deontic modality markers:
defined, so attitudinal stances may refer to a variety of speaker
responses ranging from desire to obligation and duty, certainty or 1. Modal verbs: may, should, must
uncertainty concerning the likelihood of the propositional content 2. Adjectives and participles in ‘BE … THAT’ and ‘BE … TO’
of the utterance. (Nørgaard, Busse and Montoro 2010: 113) constructions: ‘You are permitted to leave’, ‘It is possible for
you to leave’, etc.

The interpersonal function, as the term itself suggests, is about how Clearly, the deontic system is of crucial relevance to the strategies of
we orientate, shape and measure our utterances as discourse. This social interaction, especially to tactics of persuasion and politeness.
function is expressed principally by the grammatical system of Indeed, when we come to consider some of the linguistic features of
modality which is that part of language which allows us to attach persuasive discourse such as advertising language, deontic
expressions of belief, attitude and obligation to what we say and modality will provide a valuable analytic tool. (Simpson 1993: 44)
write. Modality is therefore the grammar of explicit comment, and it
includes signals of the varying degrees of certainty we have about 2.2 Boulomaic modality
the propositions we express, and of the sorts of commitment or
obligation that we attach to our utterances. (Simpson 2004: 123) It is extensively grammaticised in expressions of ‘desire’.

Boulomaic modality markers:

Modal lexical verbs indicating the wishes and desires of the speaker
are central:

a64b0469ff35958ef4ab887a898bd50bdfbbe91a-8941431

Reservados todos los derechos. No se permite la explotación económica ni la transformación de esta obra. Queda permitida la impresión en su totalidad.
Reservados todos los derechos. No se permite la explotación económica ni la transformación de esta obra. Queda permitida la impresión en su totalidad.
Inst I – MODALITY SYSTEMS Dr Rocío Montoro

1. I hope that you will leave 5. You should have been right (i.e. in the context of ‘If you
2. I wish you’d leave followed the instructions carefully’). (Simpson 1993: 44-45)
3. I regret that you’re leaving.
Epistemic modality markers:
Adjectival and participial constructions in a ‘BE … TO’ or ‘BE …
THAT’ framework can carry boulomaic commitment although Despite the obvious centrality of the modal auxiliaries in the
related modal adverbs may also be used: system, epistemic modality may be grammaticized through a range
of other devices. Modal lexical verbs are one means:
1. It is hoped that you will leave. (BE+participle+THAT)
2. It’s good that you’re leaving. (BE+adjective+THAT) 1. I think you are right.
3. It is regrettable that you’re leaving. (BE+adjective+THAT) 2. I suppose you’re right.
4. Hopefully, you’ll leave. (modal adverb) 3. I believe you are right.
5. Regrettably, you’re leaving. (modal adverb) (Simpson 1993:
45) as are adjectives in the familiar ‘BE…TO’ and ‘BE…THAT’
constructions:
2.3 Epistemic modality
1. You are sure to be right.
The epistemic system is possibly the most important regarding the 2. It’s certain that you’re right.
analysis of point of view in fiction. And as the epistemic modal 3. It’s doubtful that you’re right.
adverb in the previous sentence (spot it!) should suggest, epistemic
modality is concerned with the speaker’s confidence or lack of There is also a group of epistemic modal adverbs which includes,
confidence in the truth of a proposition expressed. In the following but is not restricted to, the following: arguably, maybe, perhaps,
examples, the modal auxiliaries are now used in their epistemic possibly, probably, certainly, supposedly, allegedly. (Simpson 1993: 45)
sense. They convey varying degrees of epistemic commitment to the
basic proposition You are right:
2.3.1 Categorical assertions
1. You could be right.
2. You may be right.
Speakers also have the option of expressing the basic proposition in
3. You must be right.
its ‘raw’ form; or in other words, as a categorical assertion:
4. You might have been right.
• You are right.

a64b0469ff35958ef4ab887a898bd50bdfbbe91a-8941431

Viajes Universitarios a Marruecos, Ibiza, Algarve... ¡Haz clic aquí y RESERVA AHORA!
Reservados todos los derechos. No se permite la explotación económica ni la transformación de esta obra. Queda permitida la impresión en su totalidad.
Inst I – MODALITY SYSTEMS Dr Rocío Montoro

Categorical assertions express the strongest possible degree of 1. a. It’s clear that you are right.
speaker commitment. In this respect, they are ‘epistemically non- b. You’re clearly right.
modal’. Epistemic expressions thus function to distinguish non- 2. a. It’s obvious that you’re right.
categorical assertions from categorical ones by signalling that the b. You’re obviously right.
speaker’s commitment to the truth of the proposition encoded in the 3. a. It’s apparent that you’re right.
utterance is qualified. (Simpson 1993: 45) b. Apparently, you’re right.
4. a. It’s evident that you’re right.
b. You’re evidently right. (Simpson 1993: 46)

It is worth adding that verbs which represent straightforward


mental processes do not de facto constitute part of the perception
modal system. Statements of the sort I saw the game or I heard the
noise are simply categorical assertions presenting observations on
the part of the speaker. By contrast, examples 1–4 incorporate some
linguistic justification for the speaker’s commitment to the truth of a
proposition based on reference to external signs. (Simpson 1993: 46-
47)
(Simpson 1993: 46)
3. Other modality markers
2.4 Perception modality
a) Modal adverbs:
Perception modality […] is best regarded as a subcategory of certainly, probably, surely, perhaps.
epistemic modality. It is distinguished by the fact that the degree of b) Evaluative adjectives and adverbs:
commitment to the truth of a proposition is predicated on some lucky, unlucky, fortunately, regrettably.
reference to human perception, normally visual perception. c) Verbs of knowledge, prediction, evaluation:
(Simpson 1993: 46) seem, believe, guess, foresee, approve.
d) Generic sentences:
Perception modality markers: Generalized propositions claiming universal truth and
usually cast in a syntax reminiscent of proverbs or scientific
Adjectives in ‘BE…THAT’ constructions are especially important, as laws.
are related modal adverbs:

a64b0469ff35958ef4ab887a898bd50bdfbbe91a-8941431

Si tienes dificultades en cualquier materia, te asignamos un profe idóneo ¡Clic aquí!


Inst I – MODALITY SYSTEMS Dr Rocío Montoro

e) Verba sentiendi:
Words denoting feelings, thoughts, and perceptions,
primarily signals of a subjective point of view
f) Words of estrangement:
These expressions pretend that the author – or often one
character observing another – does not have access to the
feelings or thoughts of the characters. They emphasise an act
of interpretation, an attempt to reconstruct the psychology
of the character by reference to the signs that can be gleaned
by external observation. (Adapted from Fowler, 1986)

References

Fowler, R. (1986) Linguistic Criticism. Oxford: OUP


Nørgaard, N., Busse, B. and Montoro, R. (2010) Key Terms in
Stylistics. London: Bloomsbury
Simpson, P. (1993) Language, Ideology and Point of View. London and
New York: Routledge.
Simpson, P. (2004) Stylistics. A Resource Book for Students. London
and New York: Routledge.

a64b0469ff35958ef4ab887a898bd50bdfbbe91a-8941431

Reservados todos los derechos. No se permite la explotación económica ni la transformación de esta obra. Queda permitida la impresión en su totalidad.

You might also like