You are on page 1of 10

The Praxis of Art’s 241

Deschooled Practice
John Baldacchino

Abstract

Art’s relationship with education is often charac- ness. No possibilities for art or learning could ever
terised by paradox. Yet art is often reified within emerge unless a radically different set of condi-
an education system that refuses to see the tions give way to a state of affairs where knowl-
pedagogical strengths of paradox. This article edge is a matter to be discovered but never deter-
approaches art education from three positions. mined, and where a fixed ground is transformed
The first is that art is a construct that is neither into a wide horizon.
natural nor necessary. The second is that there
are no aesthetic or pedagogical imperatives, but
that art education is the recognition of ground-
lessness where paradox facilitates learning. The
third approach is to reposition art with regards to
its relationship with learning, education and
schooling. Here it is argued that art’s only choice
is to deschool learning. The latter is moved by an
underlying dilemma as to whether art, consid-
ered as an autonomous human act, could ever
engage with systems of learning without being
turned into a tool or a thing. Unless art education
is deschooled, the teaching and learning of art
remains trapped between the assumptions of
process and product. So the idea of art and educa-
tion as shared practices within schooling remains
somewhat dubious unless art’s practices are
recognised in parts perceived as wholes and
where conclusions are marked by open-ended-

JADE 27.3 (2008)


© 2008 The Author. Journal compilation © 2008 NSEAD/Blackwell Publishing Ltd
242 Art education is often characterised by how art of an outside does not stem from an anti-educa-
John Baldacchino and education converge at some point only to tional position. Rather, it comes from the desire
part ways again. This relationship sometimes for art to retain its specificity as it exercises its
appears wholesome and steadfast, sometimes power to resist reification (Marcuse 1979; 1991;
radically opposed and contradictory. It seems Lukács 1971; 1974; 1975). The arts could not be
that there are two variables that affect this rela- staked on hierarchies of knowledge (Rancière
tionship: the ever-changing nature of the educa- 2006). Even when we argue for art as being
tional context, and art’s ambiguous flux in its central to the notion of learning and (by political
practices and definition. A philosophy of art in consequence) the school, this necessitates a
education must start from the notion of educa- different strategy. This is where the relationship
tion as a human activity that cannot be pinned between art and education gets out of joint. If art
down to a finite concept. Likewise a philosophy conforms, it has no use to learning. If it becomes
of art cannot afford to be paralysed by a dualism synonymous with learning, then it is not art
fixed between product and process. anymore. If there is such a thing as art’s peda-
This article [1] first begins with the assumption gogical objective, it remains that of expressing,
that art and education are historical constructs sustaining and fulfilling such a double bind, such
that are neither natural nor necessary. Secondly it a paradox.
will be argued that art does not emerge from Ironically, any proscription of paradox in art
aesthetic or pedagogical imperatives, but that neutralises the way by which art is pedagogically
aesthetics and pedagogy partake of a wider hori- and aesthetically sustained. In her Existential
zon that does include, but is not limited to, the Encounters for Teachers, Maxine Greene (1967,
arts. Thirdly, art education remains dispensable. 29) argues that ‘to be ready to learn is to be ready
There would never be a straightforward case for for a leap’ and that
the ‘need’ to teach art in primary and secondary
schools, and less so in higher education. If that a person is most fully himself when he is aware of
were so, then art education is reduced to a case the limits of possibility; also, he is overtaken by
for art as an intellectual utility, with the result that, guilt when he becomes aware of possibility
as in the United States, art educators constantly unchosen nor unrealized. What is not chosen is a
justify art as a form of intelligence (Hickman 2005, negation; and a feeling of bad conscience may be
47), where art education is overwhelmed by experienced in a learning situation when a learner
cognitive development. refuses to tolerate suspense, to overcome inertia
Art educators must always be mindful that and to strive.
art’s relationship to schooling remains at best
dubious and at worst impossible. This has noth- Art cannot be identified within a paradigm or a
ing to do with how well we teach art or how far method, even when very often, art’s ‘methods’
should art serve human development. Beyond are identified with art practice. Though the recog-
the use of art in schools, the question has to do nition of arts- or practice-based research methods
with whether art could afford to be further reified could potentially distance art from the clutch of
within the fully-fledged industries of schooling the social sciences, research-practitioners in the
and culture where standardisation, accountability field cannot resolve art’s paradox, let alone the
and merit are deemed as categories of ‘success’ double bind of the arts and education [2]. Even
and where human development is invested in an when art practice is considered as a method (and
economy that hardly pays any attention to equal- the jury is still out on that), art remains quintessen-
ity and social justice. tially non-methodological and non-identitarian. In
A case for art education must emerge from other words, it cannot be identified with univocal
outside the school. In saying this, we should research models. Another necessary distinction
never shy away from declaring our enthusiasm to be made is that between art and knowledge. As
for the cause of the arts in education. The notion Gilson (2000) rightly argues, art is not a form of

JADE 27.3 (2008)


© 2008 The Author. Journal compilation © 2008 NSEAD/Blackwell Publishing Ltd
knowledge, even though we know art. By the Ralph Waldo Emerson’s Circles famously stating 243
same logic art does not teach us anything, though that ‘every man is not so much a workman in the John Baldacchino
we have a lot to learn with (rather than from or world, as he is a suggestion of that he should be.
through) it (Baldacchino 2007; 2008). Men walk as prophecies of the next age’ (Emer-
son 1941, 196).
Constructs constructing other constructs With this proviso, we can add that the idea of
Let us take some of these assumptions apart and a construct also implies groundlessness (Bald-
look at them closely, starting with the notion of a acchino 2005). The idea of groundlessness
construct, and moving on to how art education requires continuous engagement with ever-
lives up to art as a construct. changing cultural and contextual grounds that are
As a construct, art comes about and happens constantly reconstructed with art and through
in identifiable contexts. It also pertains to specific learning. As soon as the nature of ground is
circumstances that are equally considered as recognised as contingent, it becomes clear that
constructs. Both contexts and circumstances art refuses to lend itself to either relativism or
have a bearing on what artists ultimately do, even fixed totalities. The world that we reveal for
though contexts and circumstances are not the ourselves by ways of our artistic explanation
ingredients that make art. In this respect one demands of us that we engage with truth. In our
cannot plot art against a historicist grid or a socio- engagement with truth we also learn the possi-
logical inquiry. Even when historical and socio- bilities that lie ahead of us – always changing,
logical analyses are undeniably essential to study coming and going; always departing; always
art, presuming art as an a priori historical and returning. This is where we arrive at the nexus
social construct would be as misleading as between learning and what we often see in art as
assuming that art is simply a matter of form and acts of doing.
its objects. (Baxandall 1985; Wollheim 1980). We do art by engaging with a world of possi-
Here, the argument finds itself in a double bilities that is opened by the imagination. Greene
bind; that double bind where, Adorno (1999) (1978) positions the imagination at the heart of
reminds us, art as a social construct and as auton- praxis. Rather than equate praxis with a critical
omous form seems to oscillate dialectically with- practice, Greene’s notion of praxis implies a rela-
out any need for resolution. Keeping this double tionship between the self and a community in
bind in mind, one also realises how art retreats continuous expansion. Greene sees two major
and takes different positions by means of a avenues for this expanding community: educa-
continuous withdrawal (Lyotard 1988; 1989). As tion and the arts. Unlike Schiller (1967), in Greene’s
soon as it gains position, it must withdraw and work the aesthetic education of women and men
move on, sideways, and maybe even backwards. has no intention to mend the historical and philo-
In other words, what art ‘constructs’ by way of its sophical alienation of the beautiful from the good
specificity, immediately moves into the realms of and the true by attempting to artificially restore
further constructs that are then beholden to other some sort of overall consonance between
specificities. As a construct, art is never static. It aesthetics, ethics and metaphysics. Greene is
is a construct that in turn constructs other not into makeshift philosophical bridges. She
constructs. It returns onto itself, and refolds back regards the aesthetic avenue as upholding its
and forward, and it is never contained by or within autonomy while urging women and men to
a fixed and objectively defined meaning. In this consciously engage with the realities by which
way art never identifies or fixes facts or truths. Yet they have to live in the world.
it does not lend itself to relativism; and neither In Greene’s work, the criticality of praxis
does it allow human reason to be absorbed in an emerges as a reminder of everydayness. She
ideal totality. It simply returns on end. This reads this not only in existentialism and phenom-
reminds us of Nietzsche’s notion of eternal recur- enology as her philosophical points of departure,
rence (Nietzsche 1980, 178), and more so of but more so in works of art and literature, such as

JADE 27.3 (2008)


© 2008 The Author. Journal compilation © 2008 NSEAD/Blackwell Publishing Ltd
244 Virginia Woolf’s Mrs Dalloway and To The Light- aporetic moments. Art’s paradox can be
John Baldacchino house, and Toni Morrison’s Jazz and Sula where described as a possibility – the possibility of
the reader encounters the woman, the social self, groundless forms of meaning. These groundless
and the artist who learns from her everyday life, forms of meaning come across as philosophical
from her sensible approach to the quotidian. In practices – philosophical doings – that would
this engagement, an aesthetic sensibility grows never assume an end. They are like histories that
from what we make and do as acts of art and keep returning onto us with vengeance. As forms
generosity. So while we make the world in the of art these groundless forms of meaning sneak
image of what we assume as good, we also strive on us beyond their appearance of fixed and finite
to act by way of truth. But far from assuming a forms. It is not only contemporary art that offers
simplistic notion of making the world into a good this scenario of groundlessness. One could make
and true form of living, our aesthetic constructs an argument for groundlessness even in what
are also doings of an imagination that never abdi- appears to be ‘complete’ forms – such as a Carav-
cates from the world, even when it makes us aggio, or a Beethoven. In many ways, complete
aware of the fact that fixed grounds hold no hope forms like a Caravaggio or a Beethoven turn out
whatsoever for our engagement with the world. to be open and even less grounded than a Rothko
In an essay entitled ‘Aesthetic literacy in general or a Stockhausen.
education’ Greene (1991, 123) argues that Art’s groundlessness is not limited to ‘form’ –
understood as a finalised product, as a painting, a
to ‘do’ philosophy in the domains of the artistic- symphony or a play. The more a form appears to
aesthetic is to think about one’s thinking with regard be complete, the less it is grounded. At this point
to the ways in which engagements with the arts in one’s interaction with art, one would recognise
contribute to ongoing pursuits of meaning, efforts what Laclau (2005), in his political philosophy,
to make sense of the world. It is to reflect upon calls the moment when ground becomes hori-
perceived realities as well as those that have been zon. Reading this transformation in terms of art, it
conceptualized, and to ponder the phases of could be argued that on this horizon, one would
remembered experiences with the arts. not simply find the openness of our thoughts, but
more so a possibility for art as a doing, under-
As we learn how to do philosophy by pursuing stood in terms of Greene’s definition of ‘doing
meaning in the aesthetic and artistic sense, we philosophy’.
might also realise that art as doing leads to art’s The theorising of art cannot be distanced from
unavoidably paradoxical nature. As we do philos- what art ‘does in practice’. Inversely, in practising
ophy while also doing art, we realize art’s aporetic art we cannot allow ourselves, as artists, to
nature – an aporia being a ‘blank’ moment where remain trapped in an instrumental frame of mind.
neither argument nor reason could simply suffice An argument that simply finds solace in art as a
to unravel a paradox or contradiction. As the making, limits both the notion of art practice and
moment of aporia is also an opportunity of takes an essentialist view of art learning. Art is not
intense learning (as we find in Plato’s pedagogi- a product, even when there seems to be an
cal dialogues [3]), the act of art as aporia also object called art. Likewise art cannot be reduced
makes it possible for human knowledge to inhabit to a process, even when many make an argu-
that complex space which can be described as ment for art as a process in order to avoid it
the go-between between process and product, becoming a product. To define art from within the
beginnings and ends, potentiality and actuality. paradoxical assumption that it is an in-between
would help us understand the art form’s open
Groundless forms of meaning: beyond character (Eco 1962/1989).
product and process The task becomes more ominous as one
Just as we do philosophy, we come to do art by engages with the plurality of art’s nature, when
way of surviving its paradoxical nature and its one tries to assume (without ever concluding)

JADE 27.3 (2008)


© 2008 The Author. Journal compilation © 2008 NSEAD/Blackwell Publishing Ltd
what are the objects of art. Richard Wollheim to what it makes. This implies that the product- 245
confirms the difficulty of this task when he reveals process argument is a tautology. That is why Woll- John Baldacchino
the shortcomings of a method by which art and heim opts for neither process nor product.
its objects could be ‘defined’: Returning to the original question of a context
that is neither natural nor necessary for art and
[I]t may anyhow be that a more fruitful, as well as learning, I propose that we regard art as a possi-
a more realistic, enterprise would be to seek, not bility that is neither tied to assumptions of innate-
a definition, but a general method for identifying ness nor to the desperate notion of a need that
works of art … For the method might take this seems to be God-given or even ordered by a final-
form: that we should, first, pick out certain objects ised set of rules by which somehow we are then
as original or primary works of art; and that we beholden. Rather than art being necessary, we
should then set up some rules which, succes- can approach art from an opposite direction, by
sively applied to the original works of art, will give stating that art is autonomous from any universal
us (within certain rough limits) all subsequent or necessity. On the other hand, rather than art and
derivative works of art. (Wollheim 1980, 143) education providing us with secure grounds of
creativity and growth, we could say that at best,
Yet, this method leaves us in a quandary: we need to seek to continuously reconstruct
creativity and growth through our doings; and at
But can we arrive at a formulation of these rules? It least, we must make do with the circumstances
is important that at the outset we should be aware and act accordingly by opening ourselves to
of the immensity of the task. It is, in the first place, possibilities and thereby learn how to live through
evident that it would be insufficient to have rules these possibilities, which are not always ordered
which merely allowed us to derive from one work by how we fancy them to be.
of art another of the same, or roughly the same,
structure. We may regard it as the persistent ambi- Parts as wholes: betwixt learning and
tion of Academic theory to limit the domain of art education
to works that can be regarded as substitution- This takes the discussion straight into two issues
instances of an original or canonical work: but this that arise from any argument about art education.
ambition has been consistently frustrated. (Woll- The first has to do with the rift between learning
heim 1980, 144, emphasis added) and education. In a schooled context, learning
and education fall short of being equivalent or
To claim that the assumption of works of art as complementary. Yet one could initially argue that
substitution-instances could be avoided by insist- it is by means of a desired complementary posi-
ing that art is a process would open a further tioning of learning and education that we could
problem where the argument gets stuck with claim a certain amount of autonomy for ourselves
that other, related notion, of art as an activity that as art educators. However this convenience is
is beholden to a narrow notion of skills or even short-lived when one considers a second issue
knowledge. Pedagogically speaking, this opens that arises from art education: that any argument
tenuous questions like: ‘Is art to do with skills or for art in education must recognise the distinc-
concepts?’ or ‘Is it art?’ not to mention the classic tion between learning and education especially
bore: ‘Can we teach art?’ which invites the panto- when education always places art education in
mime reply: ‘Oh yes we can!’ positions of distinct uncertainty.
On the other hand, if one were to insist that the In other words, unless one distinguishes
process-product argument is irrelevant to the very between learning and education, one also stands
definition of art and its objects, it could be claimed a good chance of losing any argument for art in
that in being a construct that runs within the inter- education, because education has often fore-
stices of process and product, act and object, closed the plural possibilities by which art must
potential and fulfilment, art could never be reduced problematise learning critically and aesthetically.

JADE 27.3 (2008)


© 2008 The Author. Journal compilation © 2008 NSEAD/Blackwell Publishing Ltd
246 As an identitarian form of reasoning – as a form of collecting parts and never wholes. This is also
John Baldacchino thinking that assumes that all parts are equal to where, like Jacques Rancière’s ignorant school-
the whole – education forbids aesthetic criticality. master we come to declare that the whole is in
This is because aesthetic criticality is essentially the part, that everything lies in each, and not the
non-identitarian: it questions the assumption of a other way round (Rancière 1991, 33–9) [4]. This
totality that sums up its assumed parts. As a criti- leaves no space for the idealisation of education,
cal form of reasoning, art denounces the even when education appears to be progressive
summing of parts into wholes as an instrumental and learner-centred. If we were to idealise educa-
formula that only serves to legitimate the whole tion we would collect parts that fit the whole,
by suppressing its parts. rather than parts that are wholes. An idealised
However not all is lost. Given the contradictory education – whether progressive or traditional –
relationship between learning and education it sets goals that we could never reach. Art educa-
means that to advocate art education within tors know very well that set goals never gain any
schools is to argue that art in schools must retain consensus on what, ultimately, is the aim of
its non-identitarian modus operandi and more education.
critically, it could potentially deschool society, to Dewey, that quintessential philosopher who
use Illich’s term (1999). Despite the contradictory remained a sceptic over the assumption of
ring to such a concept, it is not contradictory to wholes, reminds us that an aim in education is
say that because and in spite of education, art rather curious if not outright nonsense. This is
educators have no choice but to be advocates of because education cannot afford to work towards
art in education. an external aim. The construction of an absolute
Here, Laclau’s suggestion that we move from and closed whole would distort the fact that
the notion of a ground to that of a horizon in polit- education’s goals are more likely to be found in
ical philosophy begins to gain further relevance to the plural eventualities that keep changing us as
education. By means of its groundlessness art human beings. A static aim towards a fictitious
facilitates knowledge over a horizon that would end is even more fictitious, especially when
value the whole (universality) from within its bestowed on education. Dewey’s position makes
assumed parts (particularities), the ‘parts’ being no compromise. He argues (1996, 100) that
that which knowledge achieves from the things
with which we engage every day. This recalls it is well to remind ourselves that education as
Stanley Cavell’s wonderful notion of the ‘world as such has no aims. Only persons, parents, and
things’ where he states that his assignment is teachers, etc., have aims, not an abstract idea like
‘not this or that collection … but collecting as education. And consequently their purposes are
such; or, as it was also specified to me, the philos- indefinitely varied, differing with different chil-
ophy of collecting’ (Cavell 2006, 236). dren, changing as children grow and with the
If, after Duchamp, we cannot see the point of growth of experience on the part of the one who
collecting as an analogy for art and the way we teaches.
learn with art, then art education is not worth
pursuing. Fortunately we could speak after Duch- The notion of an aim that is external to the needs
amp and like him we constantly seek, find and of learners is even more absurd when it comes to
collect a myriad objects that make art in their schooling, especially when we have to face the
elusive ways; pretty much as we find forms of polity of the school as a wilful imposition on learn-
knowledge that do not have to conform to the ing in the name of assumed needs that govern-
schooled knowledge-systems that the State ments and communities tend to barter between
wants us to blindly accept as necessary. This is themselves within education systems that are
not distant from what Cavell meant by collecting distinctly hegemonic. We know that the question
for the sake of it; and more specifically it articu- of the school is ultimately contingent on the
lates the act of collecting parts for the sake of implied reasons for a systematised notion of

JADE 27.3 (2008)


© 2008 The Author. Journal compilation © 2008 NSEAD/Blackwell Publishing Ltd
education. In the assumed ‘necessities’ that change education from the ways that have stifled 247
prompt education, the school is bounced off as a it. The latter has mainly emerged from a total John Baldacchino
system of education that is alien to the need of misunderstanding of learning from the part of
human learning. those who believe that schooling could improve
if you throw more money at it, or by simply reduc-
In Dewey’s words (1996, 100): ing class sizes.
Diverse pedagogies and a widening of subject
too rarely is the individual teacher so free from the matter yield a less systematised form of educa-
dictation of authoritative supervisor, textbook on tion, where schools will move away from fixed
methods, prescribed course of study, etc., that he aims and instead start to approximate the aims of
can let his mind come to close quarters with the human learning. This is not easy, given that
pupil’s mind and the subject matter. This distrust democracy in education sadly amounts to mere
of the teacher’s experience is then reflected in platitudes. However as we come to recognise
lack of confidence in the responses of pupils … (and as we become less scared of) the paradoxi-
Until the democratic criterion of the intrinsic signif- cal relationship between art and learning, we will
icance of every growing experience is recog- also begin to understand what this offers in terms
nized, we shall be intellectually confused by the of new pedagogies and a less systematised
demand for adaptation to external aims. education, which potentially could be deschooled.
This recognition offers us a possibility to under-
Conclusion: art education’s deschooled stand, at least conceptually for the time being,
perspective how a deschooled education could come about.
Some forty years ago Ivan Illich (1999) argued that One cannot promise that this will be bereft of
at points in history we realise that deschooling is contradictions; neither would I be inclined to go
as necessary as we thought schooling has always about avoiding any paradox, especially when, as
been essential for learning. Though we know that I have just argued, art cannot be sustained with-
by deschooling Illich did not mean the destruc- out paradox – more so when art’s paradoxical
tion of education but he was calling for a radically nature emerges from the aesthetic criticality of
different form of learning, we also know why his the imagination by which we come to open up
notion of deschooling remained prone to it being the realms of possibility.
dismissed as utopian and impractical. In fact it So rather than leaving the notion of deschool-
would be simplistic to argue that deschooling ing unexamined, I suggest that we give it context
simply equates to the abolition of schools per se. in terms of art. The whole question of deschooling
Rather we should be arguing that it is possible to art could be far more interesting and perhaps less
have education (i.e. as a construct, rather than a contentious if we try to understand how a subject
system, of learning) that is deschooled with phys- like art in the context of the school operates. This is
ical schools still standing. I suggest that to also a way of saying that to argue for the deschool-
achieve deschooling we have to retrace where ing of art is to argue that art will not be effectively
education as a system, and schooling as an insti- denatured and estranged from its aesthetic specif-
tution of learning, came to sustain the fallacy of icity. A deschooled art education will come nearer
external aims for education. to the particularity by which we do and indeed
I do not think this is an impossible task, espe- learn art. In other words, this will approximate
cially when we have also developed a more Cavell’s philosophy of collecting for collecting’s
robust pedagogical argument for wider (and sake: an exercise that is not hung up with the
other) subjects within the school – branching ‘useful standards of the accountable’, but makes
from art, drama and music. Furthermore, with way for a real criticality to emerge. I believe that
new forms of pedagogies which would have only a deschooled form of art education could get
been unthinkable and out of question even us to understand how art and education can share
twenty years ago, we must call for a need to their specifically different practices.

JADE 27.3 (2008)


© 2008 The Author. Journal compilation © 2008 NSEAD/Blackwell Publishing Ltd
248 In a brilliant yet not much known little essay enti- In a context of heterogeneity, the notions (and
John Baldacchino tled ‘Towards a Polis …’ Greene writes: practices) of autonomy and paradox are essential
ingredients for learning. In a perspectival view,
The ground ought to be laid in the course of art’s context and the way by which it engages
teacher education, so that teachers can embark with education comes across at variable points.
on practice with a consciousness of cultural Such points appear sometimes convergent,
complexities and quests for meaning. … Not only sometimes radically divergent. If such points are
does this mean that teachers-to-be may be to cohere with an assumed form of knowledge,
empowered to choose themselves as full partici- then art is socialised by a hierarchy of forms of
pants in the changing and ongoing life of what knowledge, which in turn would reduce art itself
once were disparate disciplines. Acquainted to a form of knowledge. This sociology of knowl-
themselves with perspectival viewing, with edge has been the most effective way to school
heterogeneity, with the open universes in which art into education, where learning becomes an
sense must be made, they may discover how to excuse for socialisation.
engage their own students in the interpretive Sociologies of knowledge cannot recognise
process. (Greene 1982, 6, emphasis added) perspectival forms of learning. Instead they seek
to avoid paradox by manipulating the epistemo-
Greene argues that the condition for this to logical contradictions that emerge from it (Bald-
happen is not only the cultivation of a perspecti- acchino 2002). This also means that such a soci-
val form of consciousness in teachers but more ology of knowledge will have no place for paradox
so an equality between subjects and a multiple in the way it sees the development of human
provision. In other words she is proposing a learning and understanding. Indeed the sociol-
system of education that is not hierarchical and ogy of knowledge insists on art (and every other
that has no epistemological priorities. This is not subject matter) as a form of knowledge and in
simply, then, a question of changing techniques turn it deems nonsensical any argument that
of learning, or simply a question of student- states that art is never knowledge even when it is
centredness. Student-centred pedagogies had a a knowable form. However I suggest that artists
good run for a long time now, but we have not yet and educators must insist that art may be a know-
achieved the desired levels of perspectival view- able form but never a form of knowledge. The
ing and heterogeneity in education, let alone in reason is that this difference is intrinsic, indeed
learning. essential, to art’s ever-changing nature. This is
This did not happen because teachers weren’t why, Gilson (2000, 13) argues, ‘it has seemed
good in what they do, but because the system of useful to recall the very essence of art conceived
education on one hand assumes learner-centred- in its true nature, that is to say, the art that makes
ness as a dogma that pays lip service to progres- things (ars artefaciens) rather than the things
sive education, while on the other hand the epis- which art makes (ars artefacta)’ – which further
temological hierarchies by which education is corroborates the critique of the duality between
schooled allow no space for a anti-utilitarian process and product.
education where learning could become open The arts portend neither fixed skills by which
enough to give learners their due autonomy. In one learns them, nor a fixed definition by which
effect autonomy does not come from student- one knows them. Neither do they emerge as
centredness, but from a perspectival notion of narratives that are always and at all times under-
education that rejects epistemological systems. stood by the same forms of human cognition.
In schools, intrinsically autonomous subjects like The changing goal-posts of art come from both
the arts find themselves socialised and thereby sides: from the art form and from the individual
‘made useful’, which means that learning art that engages with the form. Human beings have
becomes another way of making art’s intrinsic to adjust their understanding of art all the time,
specificity anathema. sometimes even with regards to the same work

JADE 27.3 (2008)


© 2008 The Author. Journal compilation © 2008 NSEAD/Blackwell Publishing Ltd
of art. What was ‘art’ yesterday is not ‘art’ today. could learn from the each that carries everything 249
What art will be tomorrow is a matter to be (pan being everything, and hekastos meaning John Baldacchino
discovered … which is where learning comes in each in Greek). The implication is that
as a practice that is always to be discovered but emancipation cannot afford to fall between the
never determined where the school and to some stools of universality and particularity, or a
extent education become contingent to a larger hierarchy where parts are summed in one
ground-turned-horizon. whole, but where in each part there is always
everything (see Rancière 1991).

Notes References
1. This article was originally presented (in Adorno, T.W. (1999) Aesthetic Theory. R. Hullot-
shorter form) as a paper on ‘Art And Education Kentor [Trans.]. London: Athlone Press
Parallel Philosophies, Shared Practices’ at the
Adorno, T.W. et al. (1976) The Positivist Dispute
School of Education, The University of the West
in German Sociology. New York: Harper & Row
of Scotland, on 13 February 2007.
Baldacchino, J. (2002) On ‘a dog chasing its
2. Recently, arts-based research has produced a
tail’: Gramsci’s challenge to the sociology of
fast growing line of publications. Just to
knowledge, in C. Borg, J. A. Buttigieg & P. Mayo
mention four books that came out in the last
[Eds] Gramsci and Education, New York:
four years, one gets Sullivan (2005), McLeod &
Rowman & Littlefield
Holdridge (2006), Bresler (2007) and Cahnmann-
Taylor & Siegesmund (2008). Indeed this is just a Baldacchino, J. (2005) Hope in groundlessness:
small sample. There are many others. art’s denial as pedagogy, Journal of Maltese
Undoubtedly this growing literature in the field is Educational Research, University of Malta,
laudable and one looks forward to a greater Vol. 3, No. 1
understanding of art-based research. However
Baldacchino, J. (2007) Art’s paradox as withness
what seems to be missing – and what one looks
and possibility. A response to David T. Hansen’s
forward to participate in – is a tangible debate
lecture ‘The idea of a cosmopolitan education as
over the philosophical and political implications
a response to a changing world’, Teachers
of the apparent need to ‘legitimize’ art as a form
College Columbia University (online). Available
of research. As evident from the great debate
from URL: pocketknowledge.tc.columbia.edu/
between Adorno and Popper on sociological
home.php/viewfile/19125 (accessed 29 May
research in the 1960s, now documented in
2008)
Adorno et al. (1976), the issue of research
cannot be simply methodological. As yet, I don’t Baldacchino, J. (2008) Learning with art, outwith
see evidence of a similar debate in arts-based the school: Stumbling upon Adami’s lines,
and art-educational research, although the inside Serra’s sequence, in H. Varenne, E. W.
literature is being produced at too fast and eager Gordon & L. Lin [Eds] Theoretical Perspectives
a pace to really assess where this debate could on Comprehensive Education: The Way
emerge. Forward. Lewiston, NY: The Edwin Mellen Press
(in contract)
3. I refer more specifically to Plato’s The Meno
and Symposium and the apocryphal yet not less Baxandall, M. (1985) Patterns of Intention: On
interesting Alcibiades I (see Plato 2005). the Historical Explanation of Pictures. New
Haven: Yale University Press
4. Here I refer to Jacotot’s ‘panecastic method’
in Rancière’s The Ignorant Schoolmaster, where Bresler, L. [Ed.] (2007) The International Hand-
it is argued that an emancipatory education will book of Research in Arts Education. Dordrecht:
emerge from a state of affairs where one Springer

JADE 27.3 (2008)


© 2008 The Author. Journal compilation © 2008 NSEAD/Blackwell Publishing Ltd
250 Cahnmann-Taylor, M. & Siegesmund, R. [Eds] Lukács, G. (1974) Conversations with Lukács. T.
John Baldacchino (2008) Arts-Based Research in Education. Pinkus [Ed.], D. Fernbach [Trans.]. London:
Foundations for Practice. New York: Routledge Merlin Press

Cavell, S. (2006) Philosophy the Day after Lukács, G. (1975) Estetica. A. Solmi [Trans.], F.
Tomorrow. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Fehér [Ed.]. Turin: Einaudi
Press
Lyotard, J. F. (1988) It’s as if a line … M. Lydon
Dewey, J. (1966) Democracy and Education: [Trans]. Contemporary Literature, Vol. 29, No. 3,
An Introduction to the Philosophy of Education. pp. 457–82
New York: The Free Press
Lyotard, J. F. (1989) Anamnesis of the visible, or
Eco, U. (1962) Opera Aperta. Milano: Bompiani Candour, in A. Benjamin [Ed.] The Lyotard
Editori. Translated as Eco, U. (1989) The Open Reader. Oxford: Blackwell
Work. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press
Macleod, K. & Holdridge, L. [Eds] (2006) Thinking
Emerson, R.W. (1941) The Works of Ralph Waldo Through Art. Reflections on Art as Research.
Emerson. Four Volumes in One. New York: New York: Routledge
Tudor Publishing Company
Marcuse, H. (1979) The Aesthetic Dimension:
Gilson, E. (2000) The Arts of the Beautiful. Toward A Critique of Marxist Aesthetics. Boston:
Champaign, IL: Dalkey Archive Press Beacon Press

Greene, M. (1967) Existential Encounters for Marcuse, H. (1991) One-Dimensional Man:


Teachers. New York: Random House. Studies in the Ideology of Advanced Industrial
Society. Boston: Beacon Press
Greene, M. (1978) Landscapes of Learning.
New York: Teachers College Press Nietzsche, F. (1980). Thus Spoke Zarathustra.
Harmondsworth: Penguin
Greene, M. (1982) Towards a Polis … PMI’s
Wingspan, [Vol. and No. unknown] pp. 6–7. Plato (2005) The Collected Dialogues of Plato:
Including the Letters (Bollingen Series LXXI).
Greene, M. (1988) The Dialectic of Freedom.
Princeton NJ: Princeton University Press
New York: Teachers College Press
Rancière, J. (1991) The Ignorant Schoolmaster:
Greene, M. (1991) Aesthetic literacy in general
Five Lessons in Intellectual Emancipation.
education, in 18th Yearbook of the National
Stanford CA: Stanford University Press
Society for the Study of Education. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press Rancière, J. (2006) The Politics of Aesthetics:
The Distribution of the Sensible. New York:
Greene, M. (1995) Releasing the Imagination:
Continuum
Essays on Education, the Arts and Social Change.
San Francisco: Jossey Bass Schiller, F. (1967) On the Aesthetic Education of
Man in a Series of Letters, E. M. Wilkinson & L. A.
Hickman, R. (2005) Why We Make Art And Why
Willoughby [Trans.], Oxford: Clarendon Press
It Is Taught. Bristol: Intellect
Sullivan, G. (2005) Art Practice as Research:
Illich, I. (1999) DeSchooling Society. London:
Inquiry in the Visual Arts, Thousand Oaks CA:
Marion Boyars
Sage
Laclau, E. (2005) On Populist Reason. London:
Wollheim, R. (1980) Art and its Object. With Six
Verso
Supplementary Essays, Cambridge: Cambridge
Lukács, G. (1971) History and Class Conscious- University Press
ness. R. Livingstone [Trans.]. London: Merlin
Press
JADE 27.3 (2008)
© 2008 The Author. Journal compilation © 2008 NSEAD/Blackwell Publishing Ltd

You might also like