You are on page 1of 18

1062539

research-article2022
HPY0010.1177/0957154X211062539History of PsychiatryJansson

Article

History of Psychiatry
2022, Vol. 33(1) 47­–64
From Melancholia to Depression: © The Author(s) 2022
Article reuse guidelines:
Disordered Mood in Nineteenth- sagepub.com/journals-permissions
DOI: 10.1177/0957154X211062539
https://doi.org/10.1177/0957154X211062539
Century Psychiatry journals.sagepub.com/home/hpy

Åsa Jansson
Durham University, UK

Abstract
My book From Melancholia to Depression: Disordered Mood in Nineteenth-Century Psychiatry charts how
melancholia was reconceptualized in the nineteenth century as a modern mood disorder and a precursor
to clinical depression. The book shows how this occurred chiefly in two ways. First, the idea of disordered
mood as a medical concept was created through the appropriation of language from experimental physiology
into the realm of psychopathology. Second, the interplay of statistical and diagnostic practices formed the
basis for modern psychiatric classification and facilitated the standardization of melancholia as a psychiatric
diagnosis. These developments were key to the reconceptualization of melancholia and the subsequent
emergence of clinical depression, and were foundational to modern psychiatric theory and practice.

Keywords
Classification, depression, melancholia, mood disorder, physiology

Introduction
In the twenty-first century, clinical depression has become ubiquitous. The World Health
Organization (WHO) considers it to be a leading cause of disability worldwide, and global con-
sumption of antidepressant medication has risen steadily since such drugs were first introduced on
the market (Organisation for Economic Co-operation and Development [OECD], 2015: 184;
WHO, 2018; Winerman, 2017; see also Healy, 1997). Some have argued that this apparent epi-
demic of pathological low mood can be attributed to the ills of modern society, while others have
suggested that it is the result of a medicalization of ‘normal’ sadness (Hidaka, 2012: 211; Horwitz
and Wakefield, 2007). Another perspective purports that two types of depression exist. One is a
milder, anxiety-based form, which has been referred to by different names over the centuries, and
increasingly corresponds to depression as commonly understood today. The other is an endoge-
nous, more severe depression, which medical literature has described with notable consistency
since antiquity; prior to the twentieth century, this was known as melancholia, but it has become
marginalized in diagnostic literature. This view has gained growing traction in recent years, with

Corresponding author:
Åsa Jansson, The Workplace, Down Rd, Bexhill, TN39 4HS, UK.
Email: asa.jansson@sabden.org.uk
48 History of Psychiatry 33(1)

an international group of clinicians and scholars calling for melancholia to be reinstated in the
major psychiatric manuals as a diagnosis distinct from Major Depressive Disorder (Parker et al.,
2010). Proponents of the ‘two depressions’ doctrine point to historical evidence to support the
argument that a clearly definable melancholic depression has always been part of the human condi-
tion, suggesting that it has been consistently described in medical literature throughout history (e.g.
Carroll, 2012; Fink and Taylor, 2007, 2008a, 2008b; Shorter, 2007).
While melancholia has existed as a concept (or concepts) since antiquity, scholars disagree over
whether it should be understood as a timeless, universal condition or whether the medical, cultural
and linguistic frameworks of different time periods are too diverse for any meaningful equivalence
to be made between, for instance, melancholia in the Middle Ages and the condition with the same
name described in the nineteenth century. Stanley Jackson’s Melancholia and Depression: From
Hippocratic Times to Modern Times (1986) remains the most impressive chronology of melancho-
lia to date. The book offers a continuity narrative, arguing that depressive illness, traditionally
known as melancholia, has shown ‘both a remarkable consistency and a remarkable coherence in
the basic cluster of symptoms’ across two millennia (p. ix). In a similar vein, Clark Lawlor (2012)
has mapped melancholia’s historical trajectory from ancient Greece to the ‘paradigm-changing
arrival’ of the third edition of the American Psychiatric Association’s Diagnostic and Statistical
Manual of Mental Disorders (DSM-III) published in 1980. Lawlor equally argues for significant
continuity across time, and laments the radical shift introduced with the new category Major
Depressive Disorder, based solely on descriptive psychopathology and which, he argues, expanded
into the realm of normal sadness. Edward Shorter is similarly critical of the DSM approach to mood
disorders. A proponent of the two depressions narrative referred to above, he argues for the exist-
ence of two distinct forms of depression, one that is endogenous (melancholia), and a socially and
culturally produced category, which is today the main form of depressive illness diagnosed in
primary care (Shorter, 2013; see also Borch-Jacobsen, 2009).
In contrast to these narratives, a number of writers have highlighted historical change (e.g. Bell,
2014; Radden, 2003; Rousseau, 2000). Misbach and Stam (2006) have mapped a conceptual shift
in the nineteenth century, whereby melancholia was ‘gradually reconceptualized as depression’
through a process of ‘medicalization’. Their discussion follows on from Berrios (1988), who
emphasized the role of French alienist Esquirol’s idiosyncratic term lymemanie (‘sadness mania’)
in the reconfiguration from intellectual to emotional insanity, arguing that the term helped bring
about a change in meaning of melancholia, before the latter became gradually replaced by depres-
sion. As these histories suggest, there was no straightforward transition from melancholia to
depression – the former was not simply replaced by the latter. Existing histories of melancholia in
the nineteenth century have, however, almost completely overlooked two events that were funda-
mental to the reconceptualization of the diagnosis: the appropriation of language and concepts
from experimental physiology to talk about emotion as a physiological phenomenon, and the role
of asylum statistics in the development of diagnostic categories and criteria.
My book From Melancholia to Depression: Disordered Mood in Nineteenth-Century Psychiatry
(Jansson, 2021) seeks to redress these existing gaps in the history of melancholia and depression.
In doing so, it also challenges the continuity narratives referred to above. The book maps a crucial
chapter in the history of psychiatry: How was melancholia transformed in the nineteenth century
from traditional melancholy madness into a modern biomedical mood disorder, paving the way for
the emergence of clinical depression as a psychiatric illness in the twentieth century? From
Melancholia to Depression charts two key events that were central to the development of psych­
iatric classification and which form a crucial part of the history of depression. First, it demonstrates
how the modern medical concept of mood disorder was created through the merging of physiology
and psychology into what scientists termed ‘physiological psychology’, showing how melancholia
Jansson 49

was reconfigured according to the new biomedical language that characterized this field of research.
Second, it maps the origins of the relationship between statistical and diagnostic practices in psy-
chiatry, which forms the basis for modern psychiatric classification, creating a framework that
eventually culminated in the internationally recognized American Psychiatric Association’s
Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (DSM). In sum, these two developments
were foundational to modern psychiatric theory and practice, and remain central to the discipline
today.
The book draws on a range of sources, including asylum records, medical textbooks and arti-
cles, statistical reports, and directives from the English and Scottish Lunacy Commissions. The
focus is primarily on the British context, with an emphasis on the uptake of physiology and German
neuropsychiatry into British psychological medicine. At a time when modern science offered new
and exciting tools for understanding the human body, language appropriated from experimental
physiology allowed physicians to speak about the unseen internal operations of the mind using the
analogy of sensory-motor activity. In this way, a new framework was created for explaining emo-
tion as an automated, involuntary reaction that could be internally triggered. Following from this,
‘disordered emotion’ was constituted as a physiological process occurring when the brain was
subjected to repeated ‘irritation’. This was the medico-scientific foundation of the new medical
concept affective insanity, the most common form of which was melancholia.
When it came to diagnosing asylum patients, however, internal biological explanations of dis-
ease were of little use. Instead, the focus was on externally observable symptoms of melancholia,
chiefly depression, mental pain and suicidal tendencies. The late-nineteenth-century symptomatol-
ogy of melancholia was in part constituted through statistical practices and was primarily descrip-
tive. At the same time, however, the symptoms that emerged as defining criteria of melancholia
were theorized within a biological explanatory framework. Diagnostic descriptions of melancholia
travelled back and forth between the casebook and the textbook, producing a disease concept that
on the surface displayed remarkable coherence yet simultaneously spoke volumes about the nego-
tiations that take place when medicine seeks to label and classify the complexities of human life.
In mapping these events, From Melancholia to Depression intervenes in current debates about the
role of classification in psychiatry. It offers a critical and contextualized historical perspective on
mood disorders, and contributes to emerging narratives in psychiatry, psychology and the medical
humanities that argue for a more flexible and dynamic approach to the diagnosis and treatment of
psychological distress.

Summary
From Melancholia to Depression maps the nineteenth-century reconceptualization of melancholia as
a modern psychiatric disorder. In doing so, it also tells the story of how mood disorder became a pos-
sible and plausible medical concept. The book contributes to a rich scholarship on melancholia and
depression in the history of psychiatry and psychology and the history of the emotions, as well as to
current debates about the role of diagnosis in psychiatry. It does so through four key arguments:

•• Experimental physiology and physiological psychology played a crucial role in the recon-
ceptualization of melancholia and the creation of the modern category mood disorder, as
ideas and concepts from these areas of research were appropriated by physicians to explain
the aetiology of disordered emotion.
•• The growth of asylum bureaucracy and the collection of asylum statistics helped to reshape
the melancholia diagnosis in the nineteenth century. The relationship between statistical
50 History of Psychiatry 33(1)

data and diagnostic categories has been central to psychiatry since the nineteenth century,
and played a key role in the development of systems of classification of mental disease.
•• The melancholia diagnosis was increasingly standardized toward the end of the nineteenth
century, coalescing around four key symptoms: depression, suicidality, mental pain and
religious delusions. This occurred in part as a result of a shift in recording practices, whereby
narrative descriptions were gradually replaced by single keywords under which a vast range
of acts and expressions were merged.
•• The history of melancholia and depression highlights the problems attached to classification
in psychiatry. The book places current debates about psychiatric diagnosis in the context of
historical debates as well as the dominant socio-economic framework, arguing for a nuanced
and flexible approach to the description, explanation and labelling of human emotionality.

Contents
Chapter 1 Introduction: Disordered Mood as Historical Problem
Chapter 2 The Scientific Foundation of Disordered Mood
Chapter 3 The Classification of Melancholia in Mid-Nineteenth-Century British Medicine
Chapter 4 Melancholia and the New Biological Psychiatry
Chapter 5 Statistics, Classification, and the Standardisation of Melancholia
Chapter 6 Diagnosing Melancholia in the Victorian Asylum
Chapter 7 Conclusion: Melancholia, Depression, and the Politics of Classification

Chapter 2: The Scientific Foundation of Disordered Mood


This chapter maps how cutting-edge empirical research in experimental physiology carried out in
the first decades of the nineteenth century provided a biological foundation for mental disorders in
which no visible changes to brain tissue could be found. It builds on the work of Roger Smith
(1971, 1992), LS Jacyna (1982), Kurt Danziger (1982) and others by demonstrating how some of
the core principles of physiological psychology were carried over into the realm of psychopathol-
ogy. The chapter takes a close look at the idea of psychological reflex action, a key concept that
facilitated a view of emotion as automated and involuntary, and thus prone to malfunction (for a
history of the reflex concept in the early nineteenth century, see Leys, 1990). It traces the trajectory
of psychological reflexion from internal scientific medicine to what became known as physiologi-
cal psychology, where it provided mid-century British writers with the tools to create a biomedical
framework for the phenomenon of disordered mood.
The chapter begins by discussing the history of the reflex concept and its role in the development
of a physiological model of emotion, highlighting the work of Archibald Billing in Britain and
Johannes Müller in Germany. Billing discussed at length two key concepts which were taken up by
the next generation of medical scientists to develop a biomedical model for disordered mood: ‘mor-
bid sensibility’ and ‘irritation’. He used the term morbid sensibility to describe ‘that state of the
nerves or central organs which renders them more susceptible to impressions than natural’. This
inherent sensibility of nerves made them susceptible to ‘irritation’, understood as a ‘diseased state’
of the nervous system which would produce ‘abnormal muscular contractions’ (Billing, 1838: 108–
9). The idea of irritation of the nerves causing an organ to become morbidly sensitive became central
Jansson 51

to biomedical explanations for disordered emotion put forward by later writers. Similar models were
offered by other contemporaneous British writers who, like Billing, referred much of the current
knowledge on the anatomy and physiology of the nerves to Bell and Magendie (e.g. Mayo, 1833,
esp. 286, 350–8; Solly, 1836, esp. 150–8). Two recurrent themes in particular should be noted here:
the idea that persistent irritation of the nerves caused them to become more sensitive and prone to
morbidity, and a model of involuntary reflexive action that did not include the cerebral hemispheres
in such activity. While Billing’s framework was later taken up in, and adapted to, psychological
medicine by the next generation of British physicians, in the early decades of British mental science
the impact of work produced by continental writers such as Prussian physiologist Johannes Müller
was at least as substantial, if not more so. Müller (1840: 933, 1354) described how emotion could
trigger involuntary bodily reactions such as ‘crying, sighing, and sobbing’. Going further than
Billing, he suggested that the brain could be excited by external stimuli.
Müller’s framework was built upon by Thomas Laycock and William Benjamin Carpenter in
the 1840s. Laycock’s first monograph, A Treatise on the Nervous Diseases of Women (1840), was
based on his observations as a physician at the York County Hospital, and outlined a theory of
unconscious mental reflexion. This was further developed in an article a few years later, ‘On the
reflex function of the brain’ (Laycock, 1845). Laycock drew an analogy between motor nerves and
those of the ‘sensorium’, suggesting that ‘sensation [is] analogous to movements, abolition of con-
sciousness to motor paralysis’ (Laycock, 1840: 113–14). He used the example of hydrophobia (fear
of water) to illustrate how involuntary emotional and motor reactions could be induced not just by
external stimuli such as physical contact with, or sight of, water, but also ‘by the mention of water’,
that is, by an idea alone. An involuntary emotional reaction – fear – would be triggered, and the
patient ‘immediately attempts to remove [the water]. This movement is strictly involuntary, and
not the result of sensation’. (Laycock, 1845: 301–2). A similar model of reflexivity was offered by
Laycock’s former university colleague Carpenter (1842), who coined the term ‘ideo-motor’ activ-
ity to describe this process. However, while Laycock extended the reflex to include all mental
functions, Carpenter maintained a clear division between the lower parts of the nervous system and
a higher realm which was not subject to reflexive action. Tracing the work of Laycock and
Carpenter into the realm of psychopathology, the chapter ends by looking at how physiological
psychology was gradually taken up by mid-century asylum physicians writing on mental disease.

Chapter 3: The Classification of Melancholia in Mid-Nineteenth-Century British


Medicine
At the time when Laycock first put forward the idea of psychological reflex action, the nosological
status of melancholia was contested. At the turn of the nineteenth century, French alienist Phillippe
Pinel (1806: xvi–xix, 242) had suggested that some forms of insanity manifested with only or pri-
marily a disturbance of emotion, while the intellect was left partially or wholly intact. The argu-
ment that mental disease could affect the emotions without the presence of delusion soon became
widely accepted, but at the same time new disease concepts proposed to classify such forms of
insanity threatened to eclipse melancholia as a diagnostic category. J.E.D. Esquirol proposed the
category ‘monomania’ to denote mental disease that manifested with only partial and limited delu-
sion, with the subcategory ‘sadness mania’ (lypemanie) to replace melancholia (Esquirol,
1838/1845: 199–233). Bristol physician James Cowles Prichard trained under Esquirol in Paris and
drew extensively on the latter’s nosology in his Treatise on Insanity (Prichard, 1835), the most
influential British textbook on mental disease published in the first half of the nineteenth century.
Following Esquirol, Prichard classified melancholia as a form of partial insanity, a type of madness
52 History of Psychiatry 33(1)

in which the intellect was only compromised in regard to one particular aspect or idea. This move
was significant for the subsequent classification of melancholia in Britain. In the following decade,
the Metropolitan Commissioners in Lunacy (a precursor to the nationwide Lunacy Commission set
up in 1845) adopted a nosology in which melancholia was classified as a form of partial insanity
alongside monomania and moral insanity (Metropolitan Commissioners in Lunacy, 1844).
James Davey, who worked under John Conolly at Hanwell Asylum and subsequently ran a pri-
vate facility near Bristol, merged this nosology with the new physiological psychology. He sug-
gested that melancholia was best understood as a form of ‘mania’ in which ‘the most prominent
symptom is grief’. He also described melancholia as a type of moral insanity, which he provided
with a biological explanation that drew on Billing’s work. He noted that Billing had demonstrated
that ‘the consequence of the brain or spinal cord becoming in a state of morbid sensibility is, that
their healthy actions are deranged’, and concluded that ‘“mental excitement”, such as anger, grief,
fear, etc., which are analogous to the direct irritation of the brain or spinal cord by a depressed
fracture or spicula of bone’ would, if carried on over time, result in a ‘state of morbid sensibility of
the nervous centres’ (Davey, 1855: 828–9, 831).
Other early-to mid-century writers also classified melancholia as a subcategory. For instance,
John Conolly (1846: 1) referred to the condition as a ‘variety of maniacal affection’, whereas
Joseph Williams (1852: 49–50) held melancholia to be a form of partial insanity alongside mono-
mania and moral insanity, largely in accordance with the nosology adopted by the Lunacy
Commission. This was also the approach taken by Henry Monro (1851: 12), who situated melan-
cholia and disordered emotion firmly within a physiological framework. Echoing the work of
German psychiatrist Wilhelm Griesinger (see below), Monro used the analogy of ‘tone’ to describe
a healthy versus diseased mind, suggesting that in melancholia the ‘tone’ of the brain was slack-
ened or lost. George Robinson offered a similar model, arguing that the brain could be excited into
involuntary emotional reflexion by psychological factors (recall the ‘mention’ of water in Laycock’s
example of hydrophobia discussed above). External or internal stimuli would cause repeated ‘irri-
tation’ of the brain, resulting in ‘painful affections in parts far distant from the original seat of irrita-
tion’. Emotion would, in the same way as sensation, travel as an automated reaction and trigger ‘an
elaborate chain of thoughts and sentiments’ (Robinson, 1859: 20–3, 43–5). Like Monro, Robinson
followed the Lunacy Commissioners in classifying melancholia as a form of partial insanity
together with monomania and moral insanity.
John Bucknill’s and Daniel Tuke’s widely read Manual of Psychological Medicine (1858) drew
together knowledge and research from across Europe, but early editions gave only limited space to
physiological explanations for mental disease, focusing instead primarily on a description of symp-
toms. The authors adhered to the prevailing view that melancholia could exhibit with or without
delusion, and they largely followed the nosology favoured by the Lunacy Commission, with the
exception that they perceived melancholia to be a form of monomania (pp. 157–9). In later edi-
tions, the authors gave greater emphasis to an internal, biomedical framework for mental disease
and discussed melancholia as an independent disease entity.
This was the approach taken by John Millar in his Hints on Insanity (1861), which favoured a
tripartite division of melancholia, mania and general paralysis. Millar’s work illustrates a shift in
the second half of the century toward classifying melancholia as an independent disease category,
which received growing attention in medical literature. This was at least in part a result of rising
concerns about suicidality and its association with melancholia. Millar made an observation that
was relatively peripheral in medico-psychological literature in the first half of the century, but
which later became widely accepted as a medical fact. ‘Every case of melancholia’, he suggested,
‘should be looked upon as having a suicidal tendency’ (pp. 22–3).
Jansson 53

Chapter 3 ends with a review of existing literature on melancholia by William Sankey (1863),
which indicated that, nosological disagreements notwithstanding, a coherent approach was begin-
ning to emerge. In published material there was growing agreement on the validity of a biomedical
approach to mental health and disease, and the view of emotion as cerebral and subject to disorder
was becoming widely accepted. While disagreement on the nosological status of melancholia pre-
vailed, descriptions of the disease were increasingly distinctive, precise and comprehensive.

Chapter 4: Melancholia and the New Biological Psychiatry


By the 1860s, the concept of disordered emotion as a physiological phenomenon was firmly estab-
lished in British medicine. The physiological models of mental operations proposed by Laycock
and others were foundational for this development. At the same time as Laycock put forward his
theory of cerebral reflex action, German physician Wilhelm Griesinger (1843/1968) had presented
an almost identical model which he referred to as ‘psychological reflex action’ (psychische
Reflexactionen). Unlike Carpenter and Laycock, Griesinger applied his theoretical framework for
mental reflex action to melancholia and disordered mood. His textbook on mental pathology, first
published in 1845 with a second, revised and expanded edition reaching a wide European audience
in the 1860s, offered one of the century’s most widely cited nosological descriptions of melancho-
lia firmly anchored in a physiological model of emotion (Griesinger, 1861: 34, 213–16).
Griesinger’s model for describing the internal aetiology of mental disease followed analogically
the kind of physiological description offered by Billing and other contemporary European writers
such as Müller. The ‘irritation’ of an organ leading it to become more sensitive or, in Billing’s
words, subject to ‘morbid sensibility’, served as a plausible aetiological explanation for affective
insanity. Language used to describe observable disease in organic tissue was applied to make the
unseen and unknown familiar and explicable. In this way, Griesinger was able to describe the inter-
nal events that produced a state of disordered emotionality, eventually leading to affective insanity
such as melancholia. These ideas were further developed in his later work. Noting that mental
images were accompanied by pain or pleasure, Griesinger suggested that a mind that had become
disordered after prolonged irritation was in a continuous state of mental pain. This pain could be
specific, relating to a particular idea, but more often it was vague and diffuse, affecting all ‘emotion
or the intellect as a whole’. ‘Much like in a bodily state of general pain and discomfort, so in the
mind a causeless feeling of trepidation, anxiety, etc., when long continued, will eventually develop
painful ideas.’ It was in such general mental pain and ‘lowness of spirits’ that melancholia con-
sisted (Griesinger, 1861: 25–34, 213–29).
A few years later, Henry Maudsley’s The Physiology and Pathology of Mind (1867) sought to
merge physiology and psychopathology, drawing heavily on the framework developed by Laycock,
Griesinger, Carpenter and others. Maudsley also endeavoured to settle the question of classifica-
tion, presenting what he argued to be the most accurate nosology based on empirical judgement. A
truly scientific system of classification, he argued, was one that divided mental disease into two
broad categories: ‘insanity without positive delusion and insanity with delusion, in other words,
into affective insanity and ideational insanity’, with further subdivisions of these (p. 2). In this way,
Maudsley insisted on a marked division between mental disorders where partial or complete delu-
sion was present, and those where only the emotions were affected. This move was particularly
significant as it occurred decades before German psychiatrist Emil Kraepelin presented his famous
affective/cognitive dichotomy with the diagnostic categories dementia praecox (later schizophre-
nia) and manic-depressive insanity. Maudsley’s classification saw melancholia divided between
the two umbrella categories, with simple melancholia in the former and delusional forms in the
latter, but this did nothing to diminish its growing significance in psychopathological literature nor
54 History of Psychiatry 33(1)

its status as an increasingly coherent disease category. On the contrary, the formal institution of
non-delusional, affective insanity into diagnostic literature, and the considerable attention Maudsley
awarded to the discussion of the symptomatology of both simple and delusional melancholia, was
an important step towards the standardization of the diagnosis in the second half of the century.
As Sankey’s (1863) literature review suggested, in the second half of the nineteenth century a
coherent approach to the classification of melancholia was beginning to emerge across Europe. At the
same time, important national and regional differences existed. For instance, in French literature the
concept of circular insanity, or folie circulaire, gained greater currency than in Britain. In the 1850s
two French alienists, Jules Baillarger and Jean-Pierre Falret, independently described a form of insan-
ity in which patients oscillated between melancholia and mania. Falret suggested that it was not
merely ‘a variety, but a specific form of insanity’ and gave it the name folie circularie. He viewed it
as a more or less lifelong, chronic illness, but with milder symptoms than were often found in melan-
cholia and mania proper (Falret, 1851; see also: Anon., 1854–55; Berrios, 1988: 301–2). While the
work of both physicians was taken up by medical writers elsewhere, the concept of circular insanity
only held minor presence beyond France. In Britain, a relationship between melancholia and mania
was noted in both published literature and asylum case notes, but when the term circular insanity or
folie circulaire was used, it was predominantly to talk of a sub-variety of melancholia or mania rather
than a distinct disease category. George Savage (1884a: 123) echoed the views of many of his peers
when he remarked that cases of genuine circular insanity were ‘extremely rare’ among English luna-
tics, suggesting that in most of the patients under his care who had exhibited such a circular symptom
picture, the proper diagnosis was one of ‘recurrent mania’, sometimes ending in dementia.
If the French model of circular insanity failed to gain widespread theoretical popularity or prac-
tical use in Britain, German late-nineteenth-century conceptions of melancholia were more exten-
sively appropriated. The second edition of Griesinger’s textbook, published in 1861 and translated
into English a few years later, was widely read across Europe and Britain. Its strong focus on a
psycho-physiological model of disordered mood and on the aetiology and symptomatology of
melancholia set the tone for the next generation of textbooks on psychopathology.
The Austrian neurologist and psychiatrist Richard von Krafft-Ebing made an important contri-
bution to late-nineteenth-century diagnostic literature with his comprehensive general textbook on
mental disease (Krafft-Ebing, 1879–1880); several editions were published, and it was also trans-
lated into English (Krafft-Ebing, 1903). The book incorporated significant sections from an earlier
short monograph entitled Melancholia: A Clinical Study, which situated melancholia within a
framework of physiological psychology (Krafft-Ebing, 1874). Krafft-Ebing argued that melan-
cholics experienced a form of ‘mental neuralgia’ (psychische Neuralgie) analogous to, but func-
tionally different from, physical neuralgia. This psychic pain defined and dominated the overall
mental state of the melancholic, and arose from internal rather than external causes. Once the
melancholic was trapped in a cycle of mental pain, every new impression generated more suffer-
ing, until the patient was ‘unable to rejoice over anything, but . . . equally unable to experience
sadness’ (pp. 1–6). For many melancholics, the only escape from this intolerable pain appeared to
be suicide. Here Krafft-Ebing expressed a view that was rapidly becoming dominant across
Western Europe, that ‘[t]he majority of people who commit suicide are melancholics’ (p. 65).
Krafft-Ebing’s description of melancholia, which highlighted depressed mood, mental pain and
suicidality, is illustrative of the increasingly coherent diagnosis that emerged in the last quarter of
the century. While disagreement on the nosological status of melancholia prevailed, descriptions of
the disease were increasingly distinctive, precise and comprehensive. By the turn of the twentieth
century, the melancholia diagnosis was remarkably standardized for the time, coalescing around
four key symptoms: depression, mental pain, suicidal tendencies and (in more severe cases) reli-
gious delusions.
Jansson 55

Chapter 5: Statistics, Classification, and the Standardization of Melancholia


In 1883, Thomas Clouston suggested that ‘a typical case of melancholia’ would run ‘a somewhat
definite course, like a fever’ and was characterized by ‘mental pain, emotional depression, and
sense of ill-being’, often accompanied by a ‘loss of self-control, or insane delusions, or uncontrol-
lable impulses towards suicide’, and ‘with no proper capacity left to follow ordinary avocations,
with some of the ordinary interests of life destroyed, and generally with marked bodily symptoms’
(Clouston, 1883: 37). The frequent use of ‘depression’ to describe the general emotional state of
the melancholic in the nineteenth century has led twentieth- and twenty-first-century scholars, both
in the human and natural sciences, to attempt to equate melancholia with the condition commonly
known today as clinical depression or Major Depressive Disorder. For nineteenth-century physi-
cians, the term was applied in a way that suggested a much more literal meaning, that of something
being ‘pressed down’. In melancholia, the ‘tone’ of the mind was slackened and subdued. Doctors
spoke of a ‘depression of spirits’, or an ‘emotional’ or ‘mental’ depression when describing melan-
cholia, but the term was predominantly used as a way to describe the overall state of the melan-
cholic mind, and as a way to contrast melancholia with mania – the opposite state of ‘mental
excitation’. Depression was not used in place of melancholia as a term denoting a specific disease,
but rather it was a key symptom of the condition, alongside suicidality, mental pain and religious
delusions. Clouston’s definition of melancholia (see above) illustrates an emerging consensus on
the defining features of the condition in the last quarter of the nineteenth century. While only a few
decades earlier the status of melancholia as an independent and widely accepted disease category
had been called into question, towards the end of the century physicians awarded significant atten-
tion to melancholia in diagnostic literature, where it was described in remarkably standardized
terms. The creation of a coherent and precise diagnosis was the result of an interplay of different
factors, including a near-universal adoption of a biomedical disease model, statistical analysis of
symptoms, and a change in recording practices in asylums. Central to the latter was the relationship
between asylum case notes and published literature (see below).
The statistical analysis of symptoms was of particular importance for the emergence of suicidal-
ity as a key symptom of melancholia. In the early decades of the century, suicidal tendencies were
not highlighted as a prominent symptom of melancholia, and statistical analysis was primarily
concerned with rates of completed suicides. The 1845 Lunacy Act (House of Commons, 1845)
stipulated that every county in England and Wales must provide for the care of pauper lunatics, and
created a national body, the Lunacy Commission, to oversee the management of county asylums.
The Act also set out a range of new provisions for asylums, and standardized some existing ones,
such as the documentation required for admission to an institution. This included a medical certifi-
cate of insanity (two for a private patient) stating the ‘facts indicating insanity’ as observed by a
physician, and a reception order, usually completed by a magistrate, poor house official, or relative
or friend of the lunatic. The latter asked for a yes or no answer as to whether the person to be admit-
ted was ‘epileptic, suicidal, or dangerous to others’. Upon admission, this information was trans-
ferred into the asylum casebook, where a diagnosis had to be recorded within a week. When asylum
superintendents completed their annual reports to the Lunacy Commission, they collated statistical
data pertaining to virtually every aspect of their institutions, including patient numbers and demo-
graphics, dietary regimens, financial records, and deaths, as well as diagnoses recorded. Physicians
increasingly also included tables on the number of ‘suicidal’ patients under their care, a practice
that was encouraged by the Lunacy Commission. When statistics on suicidality were merged with
statistics on diagnoses, the data suggested that suicidal tendencies were more common in melan-
cholia than in any other form of insanity.
56 History of Psychiatry 33(1)

This facilitated a growing focus on suicidality as a symptom of melancholia on asylum wards,


as well as in published literature. Among British asylum physicians, consensus formed around the
view that ‘the majority of melancholics are suicidal’ (Strahan, 1893: 104). The condition and the
symptom became mutually constitutive, illustrated by Henry Maudsley’s assertion that ‘[s]uicidal
feelings and attempts are common in melancholia, so much so that one suspects their actual or pos-
sible existence even when they have not been openly manifested’ (Maudsley, 1879: 384). As out-
lined in the next section, a wide range of different acts and expressions observed in melancholic
patients were merged under the ‘suicidal’ label. This led some physicians to question the validity
of asylum statistics for suicidality. For instance, George Savage, superintendent at Bethlem
Hospital, remarked that while ‘20 to 30 per cent’ of patients under his care were ‘described as sui-
cidal’ on admissions documents and in case notes, only a fraction of these were, he argued,
‘“actively suicidal”’ (Savage, 1884b: 17). Others expressed a similar view, and the usefulness of
statistics also became subject to a heated debate at one of the meetings of the Medico-Psychological
Association, the main professional body for British alienists. Inconsistent recording practices were
highlighted as a key issue, and Henry Monro declared that ‘of all the humbugs of the present day
that of statistics is the greatest’ (Royal Medico-Psychological Association, 1865: 415). Nevertheless,
the correlation between melancholia and suicidality persisted, and was closely linked to another
key symptom, mental pain.
The historical trajectory of mental pain as a symptom of melancholia is very different from that
of suicidality. In the late nineteenth century, mental pain was constituted in biomedical terms, a
‘psychalgia’ analogous to physical pain. However, its relationship to melancholia and sadness is
rooted in Christian doctrine, where it was closely linked to sin. At the turn of the eighteenth cen-
tury, philosopher Mary Astell held that ‘mental Pain is the same with Sin’, in the sense that ‘as a
musical Instrument, if it were capable of Sense and Thought, would be uneasie and in pain when
harsh discordant Notes are play’d upon it; so Man, when he runs counter to those Motions his
Maker has assign’d him . . . must needs be in Pain and Misery’ (Astell, 1705: 53). In a similar vein,
clergyman Richard Fiddes (1720: 639) explained mental pain as ‘that Anguish and Remorse of
Mind, which Sinners so naturally feel, and all of them, more or less, when they call their own Ways
to remembrance, and reflect upon their sins’.
This conception of mental pain is in stark contrast to that espoused by nineteenth-century physi-
cians, who explained it in physiological terms. At the same time, early modern ideas about mental
pain as closely tied up with sin were not simply erased with the advent of modern medicine.
Patients continued to experience their pain and distress in spiritual terms, but physicians wedded
to a psycho-physiological model of the mind and brain saw mental pain as functioning in the same
manner as physical pain. In this way, it would arise when the brain was subjected to repeated irrita-
tion. At the same time, unlike physical pain and visible lesions, mental pain was an abstract con-
cept, the perceived result of a physiological process that was theorized but which could not be
observed. In this way, mental pain as understood in nineteenth-century medicine was both meta-
phorical and literal. As described above, concepts derived from empirical research were appropri-
ated to explain unseen mental operations, which were nevertheless perceived to be real and tangible
physiological events. The language of the physiology of mind, centred on words like irritation,
tone and pain, was used to explain material cerebral processes as well as the abstract psychological
manifestations of these; this allowed physicians to argue that the same relationship existed between
psychological pain and involuntary action as between physical pain and automated muscular
activity.
While physicians conceptualized mental pain as a physiological phenomenon, most patients con-
tinued to experience their pain in spiritual terms. Melancholic patients were often weighed down by
overwhelming religious guilt, and frequently spoke of having committed ‘the unpardonable sin’,
Jansson 57

believing this to be the source of their suffering. For physicians, however, this was another symptom
of illness, usually referred to as ‘religious delusions’. While this symptom was generally not consid-
ered a defining feature of melancholia in the same way as depression, mental pain and suicidal
tendencies, it was nevertheless awarded significant attention in diagnostic literature, and was fre-
quently recorded in asylum case notes. Moreover, it allowed physicians to emphasize that only a
trained professional could correctly identify the real cause of melancholic patients’ suffering.
Clouston (1883: 38) remarked that melancholics were usually able to give a comprehensive descrip-
tion of their symptoms, thus aiding the physician in reaching a diagnosis, but they were, he argued,
almost always wrong about the cause of their depression due to ‘their false, ungrounded beliefs’.
Having ‘analysed the “causes” assigned by melancholics’ under his care over a number of years,
Clouston concluded that they were ‘wrong in ninety per cent of cases’ (see also Maudsley, 1895:
360–1). For melancholic patients, the profound religious despair and fear of God’s wrath they often
expressed were very much real, but for physicians this was an example of patients assigning an
incorrect cause to their suffering, the true source of which was an internal disorder understood in
physiological terms.

Chapter 6: Diagnosing Melancholia in the Victorian Asylum


Towards the end of the century, a biomedical model of disordered emotion dominated in Britain
and beyond. It underpinned the symptomatology of melancholia, and textbooks on psychopathol-
ogy generally included detailed discussions on brain physiology. When it came to diagnosing
patients, however, this model was of little use. While some physicians expressed the hope that
biology would one day aid in the diagnosis of mental disease, they were nevertheless forced to rely
on externally observable symptoms, in particular conversations with patients. Patient interviews
were, Clouston argued, especially helpful in the case of melancholia as the ‘patient is usually con-
scious that there is something wrong with him, which is not the case in most forms of insanity’
(Clouston, 1883: 37–8). At the same time, the symptoms recorded by physicians, such as depres-
sion or suicidal tendencies, were not communicated in those words by patients. Rather, a signifi-
cant amount of intellectual work was required to turn patient testimonies into precise and classifiable
symptoms. As asylum recording practices were made increasingly efficient and standardized,
events and experiences communicated by patients and their loved ones were translated into simple
key terms on the pages of casebooks. In this way, the melancholia diagnosis was standardized and
refined as it travelled back and forth between the casebook and the textbook.
In the late summer of 1874 Joseph Brown, assisting physician at the Royal Edinburgh Asylum
at Morningside, came across a case of melancholia that he considered significant enough to war-
rant publication. His article on a ‘Case of determined suicidal melancholia’, which appeared in the
Edinburgh Medical Journal later that year, described a patient whose actions offered a ‘striking
illustration of the great difficulty there exists in preventing a determined suicidal patient from
accomplishing his object’ (Brown, 1874: 402). The patient, Moses B., had been certified a lunatic
and admitted to Morningside (as the asylum was known) because his father and brother felt that he
could not ‘be left alone’ for the fear ‘that he would seek to destroy himself’. According to the cer-
tifying physicians, Moses believed that his soul was lost, and he was reported to have taken ‘a
poisonous dose of Belladonna’. When examined on admission, his ‘depression’ was described as
‘considerable’, and his ‘suicidal tendencies’ were noted as consisting in ‘taking belladonna, refus-
ing food, &c’. The patient’s recent mental symptoms were listed as ‘delusions such as that his soul
is lost, that he ought to die, and thinks he is committing great sins’. He was given the diagnosis
melancholia, with a special reference made to his persistent suicidal tendencies (Royal Edinburgh
Asylum, 1873–1894).
58 History of Psychiatry 33(1)

It is not surprising that Brown decided to write up the case of Moses B. for publication; it served
as an apt illustration of a typical case of melancholia, characterized by profound depression of
mind, persistent suicidal tendencies, and delusions of religious guilt. According to Clouston,
Morningside’s superintendent, such cases were becoming increasingly common. Clouston had
taken over the running of the asylum from his mentor, David Skae, the previous year, and immedi-
ately began instituting changes to recording practices that facilitated a standardization of diagnoses
and symptoms. He gradually replaced Skae’s (1863) aetiological system of classification, which
had organized mental disorders according to their cause (e.g. ‘mania of lactation’, ‘sun-stroke
mania’), with the more commonly used descriptive nosology that included diagnoses such as mel-
ancholia and general paralysis. Clouston also introduced casebooks with pre-printed section head-
ings, allowing for swifter and more uniform recording of symptoms. These changes facilitated a
noticeable standardization of symptoms as lengthy narrative descriptions were increasingly
replaced with brief key terms such as depression and suicidal tendencies (Jansson, 2021: ch. 6).
A similar picture emerged in other asylums across the country in the last quarter of the nine-
teenth century. A vast and highly varied landscape of human emotionality was increasingly flat-
tened into singular key words and brief descriptions, which created the appearance of uniformity.
This development was in part driven by a requirement to provide homogenous and comparable
statistical data on patient populations and diagnostics, which created a need for standardized
recording practices. In addition, these changes to how patient data were recorded were also facili-
tated by time constraints in a period when asylums and their populations were rapidly expanding
across the country. They formed part of a broad shift in record-keeping within western medicine
whereby longer, narrative descriptions of patients’ physical and mental states gave way to briefer
statements and descriptive keywords. John Harley Warner has aptly described this shift as a ‘new
epistemological and aesthetic sensibility, expressed as a narrative preference for what was univer-
sal and precise over what was individual and discursive’ (Warner, 1999: 109). The implications for
the melancholia diagnosis were that labels like depression and suicidality came to denote a wide
range of acts and expressions, producing a diagnosis that was increasingly standardized on its
journey between casebooks and published literature.
Walker and O’Connell (2012) have noted the homogenizing function of depression as a single
descriptive term for a range of emotional states associated with low mood, remarking that it ‘not
only replaced a wider vocabulary for a variety of experiences’, but that it ‘also flattened out the
individuality’ of those experiences. In the Morningside casebooks, the term depression was increas-
ingly used without explanation. For instance, Dorothy D.’s ‘depression’ was observed in ‘her con-
versation and the expression of her countenance’, Jane Ann C.’s depression was ‘exhibited in
manner, appearance, and communication’, Isabella Hutton’s depression was ‘marked, exhibited in
appearance and conversation’, and Catherine G.’s depression was simply ‘present in her expres-
sion’ (Royal Edinburgh Asylum, 1873–1894).
The process of homogenizing the recording of symptoms of melancholia was also particularly
evident in the use of the term ‘suicidal’. A vast range of acts and expressions were merged under
this label, as can be seen in the case of Moses B. referred to above (see also Jansson, 2013). He was
deemed suicidal prior to admission after having consumed ‘a poisonous dose of Belladonna’, and
according to Morningside’s physicians continued to make attempts on his own life once inside the
asylum. He was reported to have swallowed several stones, after which he complained of abdomi-
nal distress and declined his meals. This act of ‘refusing his food’ was seen as an attempt to commit
suicide by starvation, which was followed by another suicide attempt consisting in taking ‘an
overdose of alcohol’. Around two weeks after this incident, from which he subsequently recovered,
the patient ‘snatched’ from an attendant a bottle containing ‘a solution of guttapercha in chloro-
form’, which he proceeded to drink. According to Joseph Brown, the persistence with which Moses
Jansson 59

attempted to end his own life constituted a demonstrable example of the suicidal tendency in mel-
ancholics – so determined did the patient seem in his suicidal convictions that ‘his one and only
object in life is to destroy it’ (Brown, 1874; Royal Edinburgh Asylum, 1873).
In this one case, then, a number of acts were recorded as evidence of suicidal intent, and other
cases of suicidal melancholia widen the range further. Isabella M. was deemed suicidal because she
would walk ‘about the streets in a depressed state – found standing on the top balcony to jump over,
&c.’, and Alexander M. after he ‘wanted to get a knife’. Jane C. was noted as having ‘threatened’
suicide after she ‘wandered away to the Dean Bridges’ but did not jump in the river ‘as she says the
water was not deep enough’, and Alexander B. ‘said that he was tired of life and wished to have
done with it, but he has made no actual attempts’. In the case of Elizabeth R., the suicidal tendency
appeared to be derived from reports that she ‘wanders about at night’ and ‘refuses food’. Refusal
of food was equally the reason given for the suspected presence of suicidal intent in Jane Ann C.
and Isabella M., while in the case of Isabella H. no apparent reason was given beyond the ‘usual’
symptom of ‘depression’, deduced from the patient appearing ‘dull and melancholy and despond-
ent’. In a number of such cases where the ‘suicidal’ label came without explanation, such as those
of James C. and James W., both admitted in 1888, few symptoms were given beyond the familiar
‘depression’, ‘lowness of spirits’ and ‘despondency’ (Royal Edinburgh Asylum, 1873–1894). In
sum, the Morningside casebooks appeared to confirm the belief expressed by Maudsley (1879:
384) that ‘[s]uicidal feelings and attempts are common in melancholia, so much so that one sus-
pects their actual or possible existence even when they have not been openly manifested’.
A similar picture emerges from county asylums in England at this time. Brookwood asylum in
Surrey also introduced pre-printed headings in the 1870s, and many of its patients were labelled
suicidal in the apparent absence of suicidal acts or openly manifested intent. In the case of John G.,
no specific reason was given for considering him to harbour suicidal tendencies beyond the patient
stating that ‘he feels very low sometimes but cannot give any reasons for being so’. In patients
diagnosed with melancholia, any act or expression that could be construed as having self-injurious
intent was likely to be labelled suicidal. Ann F. was labelled as suicidal because she ‘seemed very
much depressed and expressed an intense feeling of melancholy, as if she would do herself an
injury’. Ann W.’s suicidality was reportedly manifested in ‘persistent refusal of food’, while Sarah
Elizabeth L. was said to have ‘attempted suicide by pressing her fingers slightly round her throat’,
which meant that she required ‘constant watching’ (Surrey County Asylum, 1868–1872).
Brookwood’s superintendent Thomas Brushfield (1880) expressed a similar scepticism regarding
statistics on suicidal patients as that voiced by George Savage. Clouston (1883: 118) was equally
wary of their reliability, noting that while the data suggested that melancholics were overwhelm-
ingly suicidal, experience suggested that ‘the actual risk of suicide being seriously attempted or
accomplished is much less than those figures seem to show’. Nevertheless, the recording practices
put in place by Clouston, Brushfield and others contributed to the widely accepted view of a close
relationship between melancholia and suicidal tendencies, with consequences for the admission,
diagnosis and care of melancholics in the late nineteenth century.
The developments outlined above have continued to shape medical perceptions of emotional
distress into the twenty-first century. The emergence of suicidality as a category separate from
suicide occurred within a wider context of psychiatric attention increasingly brought to bear upon
a range of ‘self-injurious’ behaviours (see Chaney, 2017; Millard, 2015). In twenty-first-century
psychiatry, ‘non-suicidal self-injury’ has become a firmly cemented diagnostic concept (see e.g.
APA, 2013: 803–5); however, the parameters and definitions of what distinguishes suicidal from
non-suicidal self-injury have shifted over time as these categories have been reconceptualized in
the context of contemporaneous cultural tropes about group and individual behaviours. In nine-
teenth-century medicine, ‘suicidal’ was a multivalent and shifting concept, yet while physicians
60 History of Psychiatry 33(1)

remarked on the ambiguity of the term and the statistical data it produced, they nevertheless con-
tinued to rely upon this category as a significant diagnostic criterion in the definition of
melancholia.

Concluding remarks
The conclusion of the book briefly considers diagnostic shifts at the turn of the twentieth century,
centred on Emil Kraepelin’s (1899) separation of affective and cognitive insanity, and Adolf
Meyer’s proposal to replace the term melancholia with depression (see New York Neurological
Society, 1905: 114).1 It then goes on to consider the problem of diagnosis in psychiatry in the con-
text of current debates around classification, as well as the relationship between psychiatric know­
ledge and wider socio-economic developments.
The story of how melancholia was reconceptualized as a modern biomedical mood disorder
highlights two inherent and prevailing tensions within psychiatric diagnostics: on the one hand
between biological disease models and descriptive nosologies, and on the other between precise
medical categories and the infinite variations of human emotionality. While nineteenth-century
doctors acknowledged the difficulty in attaching neat psychiatric labels to the diversity of acts and
expressions encountered in patients, they nevertheless remained convinced of the necessity for
psychiatric classification, no matter how flawed any such system was. In this way, they set the
trend for psychiatric epistemology from then onwards.
Disagreement prevails within psychiatry over how to classify mental disorders, but the argu-
ment that classification is necessary remains pervasive. At the same time, the usefulness of psych­
iatric classification is increasingly being challenged, with some critics arguing that it does more
harm than good (e.g. Kinderman, Read, Moncrieff and Bentall, 2013). Callard and Bracken have
highlighted the dangers of ‘diagnostic overshadowing’ (physical symptoms being automatically
attributed to existing psychiatric illness) as well as the negative consequences of long-term institu-
tionalization that can result from some types of psychiatric diagnoses Callard, Bracken, Davies and
Santorius (2013). They conclude that ‘the [mental health] interventions that have arguably empow-
ered people the most, such as innovative community services, have not been diagnosis specific’. It
is also important to note the difficult relationship between psychiatric diagnosis and identity.
Arguments for parity between physical and mental health often turn to biology for their defence,
suggesting that these two areas of pathology should be valued equally because depression is no
different from cancer or a broken leg. This argument is flawed and potentially harmful. Parity need
not be rooted in sameness. Psychiatric disorders are evidently not like a broken limb; unlike the
latter they concern the part of us that is at the core of our personhood – our minds. Regardless of
whether the cause of a person’s mental distress is primarily social or primarily biological, its mani-
festations tend to be predominantly (but not only) psychological, and consequently also relational
and identity-based, in ways that a broken leg is not. If we frame mental disorders in strictly biologi-
cal terms, we run the risk of imprinting human beings in all their complexity with simplistic,
reductionist biological stamps, which can potentially have a self-perpetuating effect.2
One the other side of the argument, however, there is also a danger in a wholesale rejection of
existing diagnoses as not ‘real’ or ‘true’. Depression currently exists in psychiatric literature as a
mental illness; people are diagnosed with and treated for depression in large numbers every year,
and millions of people across the world experience themselves as ‘having depression’ or ‘being
depressed’. These factors must all be seen as determinants of the existence of an illness, irrespec-
tive of how it entered medical knowledge. It is also undoubtedly the case that many people find it
helpful to understand their suffering in medico-scientific terms, and that this can alleviate feelings
of guilt, shame and personal responsibility. A more helpful and nuanced approach is one that
Jansson 61

accepts and validates both the concept and experience of depression (or melancholia) and other
psychiatric diagnoses as legitimate medical conditions, while at the same time giving equal weight
to other ways of understanding, experiencing and labelling psychological distress.

Declaration of conflicting interests


The author declared no potential conflicts of interest with respect to the research, authorship and/or publica-
tion of this article.

Funding
The author disclosed receipt of the following financial support for the research, authorship and/or publication
of this article: The research for this book was supported by the Wellcome Trust, grant no: 092988/Z/10/Z.

Notes
1. For a discussion on the relationship between melancholia and depression in the twentieth and twenty-
first centuries, see Jansson, 2020.
2. Moreover, attempts to destigmatize mental illness by equating it with other medical conditions can lead
people to feel ‘less optimistic about their ability to get better’ and increase public ‘perceptions of danger-
ousness and unpredictability’ of such disorders (Malla, Joober and Garcia, 2015: 147–50).

References
(a) Archival sources
Lothian Health Services Archives, Edinburgh University Library: Royal Edinburgh Asylum, Female and
Male Casebooks, 1873–1894, Ref: LHB 7/51/24–62.
Surrey History Centre, Woking: Surrey County Asylum (Brookwood) Male and Female Case Books, 1868–
1872, 3043/5/9/1/1-5; 3043/5/9/2/1-5.
(b) Publications and thesis
Anonymous (1855) Baillarger and Falret on a new species of insanity. Remarks on a variety of insanity, the
paroxysms of which are characterized by two regular periods, the one of depression and the other of
excitement. By Dr. Baillarger. American Journal of Insanity 11(3): 230–238.
American Psychiatric Association (APA) (1980) Diagnostic and Statistical Manual for Mental Disorders, 3rd
edn (DSM-III). Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Association.
American Psychiatric Association (APA) (2013) Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders, 5th
edn. Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Association.
Astell M (1705) Letter V: to Mr. Norris. In: J Norris, Letters Concerning the Love of God, between the Author
of the Proposal to the Ladies, and Mr John Norris. London: Manship and Wilkin.
Bell M (2014) Melancholia: The Western Malady. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Berrios GE (1988) Melancholia and depression during the nineteenth century: a conceptual history. British
Journal of Psychiatry 153: 298–304.
Billing A (1838) First Principles of Medicine, 3rd edn. London: S. Highley.
Borch-Jacobsen M (2009) The great depression. In: Making Minds and Madness: From Hysteria to
Depression. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 197–204.
Brown JJ (1874) Case of determined suicidal melancholia. Edinburgh Medical Journal 20: 396–402.
Brushfield TN (1880) On medical certificates of insanity. The Lancet 115: 638–642, 676–678, 711–713,
830–832.
Callard F, Bracken P, Davies A and Santorius N (2013) Has psychiatric diagnosis labelled rather than enabled
patients? BMJ 347: 4312–4313.
Carpenter WB (1842) Principles of Human Physiology. London: John Churchill.
Carroll BJ (2012) Bringing back melancholia. Bipolar Disorder 14(1): 1–5.
Chaney S (2017) Psyche on the Skin: A History of Self-Harm. London: Reaktion Books.
62 History of Psychiatry 33(1)

Clouston TS (1883) Clinical Lectures on Mental Diseases. London: J. & A. Churchill.


Conolly J (1846) Clinical lectures on the principal forms of insanity, lecture VII. The Lancet 47(1166): 1–4.
Danziger K (1982) Mid-nineteenth-century British psycho-physiology: a neglected chapter in the history of
psychology. In: Woodward WR and Ash MG (eds) The Problematic Science: Psychology in Nineteenth-
Century Thought. New York: Praeger, 119–142.
Davey JG (1855) Lectures on insanity: Lecture III. Association Medical Journal 3(140): 828–834.
Esquirol JED (1845) Mental Maladies: A Treatise on Insanity, trans. EK Hunt. Philadelphia, PA: Lea &
Blanchard; originally published in French in 1838.
Falret JP (1851) De la folie circulaire ou forme de maladie mentale characterisée par l'alternative réguliere de
la manie et de la mélancolie. Bulletin de L’Académie Nationale de Médicine 19: 382–400.
Fiddes R (1720) Fifty Two Practical Discourses on Several Subjects, Six of Which Were Never Before
Published. London: Wyat, Took, Barber, and Clements.
Fink M and Taylor MA (2007) Resurrecting melancholia. Acta Psychiatrica Scandinavica 115(S433): 14–20.
Fink M and Taylor MA (2008a) The medical evidence-based model for psychiatric syndromes: return to a
classical paradigm. Acta Psychiatrica Scandinavica 117: 81–84.
Fink M and Taylor MA (2008b) Restoring melancholia in the classification of mood disorders. Journal of
Affective Disorders 105(1–3): 1–14.
Griesinger W (1861) Die Pathologie und Therapie der Psychischen Krankheiten, 2 Aufl. Stuttgart: Adolf
Krabbe; first published in 1845.
Griesinger W (1968) Ueber psychische Reflexactionen: mit einem Blick auf das Wesen der psychischen
Krankheiten [1843]. Gesammelte Abhandlungen, Ersters Band: Psychiatrische Abhandlungen.
Amsterdam & Berlin: E.J. Bonset, 3–45.
Healy D (1997) The Antidepressant Era. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Hidaka BH (2012) Depression as a disease of modernity: explanations for increasing prevalence. Journal of
Affective Disorders 140(3): 205–214.
Horwitz AV and Wakefield JC (2007) The Loss of Sadness: How Psychiatry Transformed Normal Sorrow
into Depressive Disorder. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
House of Commons (1845) An Act (8 & 9 Vict. c. 100) for the Regulation of the Care and Treatment of
Lunatics, House of Commons, No. 373, Vol. IV: 181. London: HMSO.
Jackson SW (1986) Melancholia and Depression: From Hippocratic Times to Modern Times. New Haven,
CT, and London: Yale University Press.
Jacyna LS (1982) Somatic theories of mind and the interests of medicine in Britain, 1850–1879. Medical
History 26(3): 233–258.
Jansson Å (2013) From statistics to diagnostics: medical certificates, melancholia, and ‘suicidal propensities’
in Victorian psychiatry. Journal of Social History 46(3): 716–731.
Jansson Å (2020) Melancholia and depression. In: Oxford Research Encyclopedia of Psychology; accessed
(18 July 2021) at: https://oxfordre.com/psychology/view/10.1093/acrefore/9780190236557.001.0001/
acrefore-9780190236557-e-623
Jansson Å (2021) From Melancholia to Depression: Disordered Mood in Nineteenth-Century Psychiatry.
Cham: Palgrave Macmillan.
Kinderman P, Read J, Moncrieff J and Bentall R (2013) Drop the language of disorder. Evidence-Based
Mental Health 16: 2–3.
Kraepelin E (1899) Psychiatrie: ein Lehrbuch für Studirende und Aerzte, 6 Aufl. Leipzig: J.A. Barth.
Krafft-Ebing R (1874) Die Melancholie: Eine klinische Studie. Erlangen: Ferdinand Enke.
Krafft-Ebing R (1879–1880) Lehrbuch der Psychiatrie auf klinischer Grundlag: für practische Ärzte und
Studirende, 3 vols. Stuttgart: Ferdinand Enke.
Krafft-Ebing R (1903) A Text-Book of Insanity Based on Clinical Observations, trans. CG Chaddock.
Philadelphia, PA: FA Davis; originally published in German, 8th edn, in 1903.
Lawlor C (2012) From Melancholia to Prozac: A History of Depression. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Laycock T (1840) A Treatise on the Nervous Diseases of Women; Comprising an Inquiry into the Nature,
Causes, and Treatment of Spinal and Hysterical Disorders. London: Longman.
Laycock T (1845) On the reflex function of the brain. British and Foreign Medical Review 19: 298–311.
Jansson 63

Leys R (1990) From Sympathy to Reflex: Marshall Hall and His Opponents. New York: Garland Pub.
Malla A, Joober R and Garcia A (2015) ‘Mental illness is like any other medical illness’: a critical examina-
tion of the statement and its impact on patient care and society. Journal of Psychiatry & Neuroscience
40(3): 147–150.
Maudsley H (1867) The Physiology and Pathology of the Mind. London: Macmillan.
Maudsley H (1879) The Pathology of Mind, 3rd edn. London: Macmillan.
Maudsley H (1895) The Pathology of Mind: A Study of Its Distempers, Deformities, and Disorders, 4th edn.
London: Macmillan
Mayo H (1833) Outlines of Human Physiology. London: Burgess and Hill.
Metropolitan Commissioners in Lunacy (1844) Report of the Metropolitan Commissioners in Lunacy to
the Lord Chancellor, Presented to Both Houses of Parliament by Command of Her Majesty. London:
Bradbury & Evans.
Millar J (1861) Hints on Insanity. London: Henry Renshaw.
Millard C (2015) A History of Self-Harm in Britain: A Genealogy of Cutting and Overdosing. London:
Palgrave Macmillan.
Misbach J and Stam HJ (2006) Medicalizing melancholia: exploring profiles of psychiatric professionaliza-
tion. Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences 42(1): 41–59.
Monro H (1851) Remarks on Insanity: Its Nature and Treatment. London: John Churchill.
Müller J (1840) Elements of Physiology, trans. W Baly. London: Taylor and Walton; originally published in
German in 1835.
New York Neurologial Society (1905) Proceedings. Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease 32(2): 113–120.
Organisation for Economic Co-operation and Development (OECD) (2015) Pharmaceutical consump-
tion. Health at a Glance 2015: OECD Indicators. Paris: Organisation of Economic Co-operation and
Development Publishing, 84–85.
Parker G, et al. (2010) Issues for DSM-5: whither melancholia? The case for its classification as a distinct
mood disorder. American Journal of Psychiatry 167(7): 745–747.
Pinel P (1806) A Treatise on Insanity, trans. DD Davis. Sheffield: W. Todd; originally published in French
in 1801.
Prichard JC (1835) A Treatise on Insanity and Other Disorders Affecting the Mind. London: Sherwood,
Gilbert & Piper.
Radden J (2003) Is this dame melancholy? Equating today’s depression and past melancholia. Philosophy,
Psychiatry, & Psychology 10(1): 37–52.
Robinson G (1859) On the Prevention and Treatment of Mental Disorders. London: Longman.
Rousseau G (2000) Depression’s forgotten genealogy: notes towards a history of depression. History of
Psychiatry 11(1): 71–106.
Royal Medico-Psychological Association (1865) Proceedings at the annual meeting of the medico-psycho-
logical association, held at the Royal College of Physicians, on Thursday, July 13th, 1865. Journal of
Mental Science 11: 383–427.
Sankey WHO (1863) On melancholia. Journal of Mental Science 9(46): 173–196.
Savage GH (1884a) Insanity and Allied Neuroses: Practical and Clinical. London: Cassell.
Savage GH (1884b) Constant watching of suicidal cases. Journal of Mental Science 30: 17–19.
Shorter E (2007) The doctrine of the two depressions in historical perspective. Acta Psychiatrica Scandinavica
115(S433): 5–13.
Shorter E (2013) How Everyone Became Depressed: The Rise and Fall of the Nervous Breakdown. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Skae D (1863) A rational and practical classification of insanity. Journal of Mental Science 47: 309–319.
Smith R (1971) Physiological psychology and the philosophy of nature in mid-nineteenth century Britain.
Unpublished PhD Thesis, University of Cambridge.
Smith R (1992) Inhibition: History and Meaning in the Sciences of Mind and Brain. London: Free Association
Books.
Solly S (1836) The Human Brain, Its Configuration, Structure, Development, and Physiology. London:
Longman.
64 History of Psychiatry 33(1)

Strahan SAK (1893) Suicide and Insanity: A Physiological and Sociological Study. London: Sonnenschein.
Walker D and O'Connell A (2012) Introduction. In: Wetherall Dickson L, Ingram A, Walker D and O'Connell
A (eds) Depression and Melancholy, 1660–1800, Vol 1: General Introduction & Religious Writings.
London: Pickering & Chatto, vi et seq.
Warner JH (1999) The uses of patient records by historians: patterns, possibilities, and perplexities. Health
and History 1(2/3): 101–111.
World Health Organization (WHO) (2018) Manual of the International Statistical Classification of Diseases,
Injuries, and Causes of Death, 6th Revision. Geneva: World Health Organization.
Williams J (1852) Insanity: Its Causes, Prevention, and Cure, 2nd edn. London: John Churchill.
Winerman L (2017) By the numbers: antidepressant use on the rise. Monitor on Psychology 48(10): 120.

You might also like