You are on page 1of 19

This article appeared in a journal published by Elsevier.

The attached
copy is furnished to the author for internal non-commercial research
and education use, including for instruction at the authors institution
and sharing with colleagues.
Other uses, including reproduction and distribution, or selling or
licensing copies, or posting to personal, institutional or third party
websites are prohibited.
In most cases authors are permitted to post their version of the
article (e.g. in Word or Tex form) to their personal website or
institutional repository. Authors requiring further information
regarding Elsevier’s archiving and manuscript policies are
encouraged to visit:
http://www.elsevier.com/copyright
Author's personal copy

Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 43 (2012) 341–358

Contents lists available at SciVerse ScienceDirect

Studies in History and Philosophy of Science


journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/shpsa

What is a text?
Adrian Wilson
Philosophy Department, University of Leeds, Leeds LS2 9JT, United Kingdom

a r t i c l e i n f o a b s t r a c t

Article history: This paper argues that textuality—the property of being a text—is assigned by the reader, rather than
Received 13 December 2011 constituting an inherent property, and that the being of texts was both captured and mystified by
Available online 8 February 2012 the figure of ‘the text’ as this developed from the 1970s onwards. Textuality consists in the abstraction
of verbal content from its origins, entailing the apprehension of that content as copresent with the
Keywords: reader; and it is given a material embodiment in the process of publication, especially in the production
Authorship of canonical works, which together comprise the locus classicus of the textual apprehension. Whole
Epistemology
disciplines—here termed the hermeneutico-canonical disciplines—are based upon that apprehension,
Hermeneutics
Historiography
and the discipline or approach known as hermeneutics consists of its theoretical elaboration. In con-
Reading trast, the discipline of history rests upon the apprehension of the verbal under the sign of the document
Textuality or its cognates, and this difference renders intelligible the longstanding relationship of mutual suspi-
cion between hermeneutics and history. The historiography of science, remarkably enough, manages
to combine these approaches; the paper concludes by suggesting that these can be brought into a more
fruitful synthesis by investigating historically the construction of scientific canons.
Ó 2012 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.

When citing this paper, please use the full journal title Studies in History and Philosophy of Science

This paper is concerned with a cluster of issues which, while bounds—expanded dramatically on two fronts: it came to refer
pertinent to the historiography of science,1 extend well beyond to a literary work, in place of the word ‘work’ itself, and it began
the boundaries of that discipline. For the question considered to subsume the written-or-printed word as such, in all its mani-
here—what is a text?—arises across a very broad disciplinary range, fold forms. This new and elastic usage had no clear or specific ba-
as do such associated themes as authorship and canonicity, to which sis in any of the previous uses of ‘text’;2 it seems to have
that question will lead us. Indeed this exploration will necessarily be developed unnoticed within literary criticism and related disci-
concerned with disciplines themselves, since as we shall see, it is dis- plines,3 and to have been given decisive momentum by certain
ciplines which constitute not just texts themselves, but also the very seminal essays of Jacques Derrida and Roland Barthes. Derrida’s
figure of the ‘text’. De la Grammatologie of 1967 announced the principle that ‘il n’y
a pas de hors-texte’, ‘there is no outside-of-the-text’;4 Barthes’s ‘La
1. Preamble: from the figure of the text to the question of the mort de l’auteur’ of 1968 replaced the personal figure of the author
text with the impersonal figure of écriture, that is, writing; and his ‘De
l’oeuvre au texte’, which appeared in 1971, installed the new figure
From the late 1960s onwards the usage of the word ‘text’— of the text in place of the traditional category of ‘the work’.5 After
originally confined within philological and bibliographic these pieces were translated into English in the mid-1970s, it

E-mail address: A.F.Wilson@leeds.ac.uk


1
Cf. Shapin & Schaffer (1985), Cunningham (1989), Jardine (1991), Shapin (1992), Christie (1993), Secord (2004).
2
See the entry for ‘text’ in the old Oxford English Dictionary [hereafter OED] (12 vols., 1933, vol. xi).
3
For literary criticism see Holland (1975), 1980 reprint, p. 118. Other disciplines in which this figure developed were hermeneutics and the history of ideas; cf. below, at n.116.
4
Derrida (1967), p. 227; Derrida (1974), p. 158. Strictly speaking this remark was tautologous, since in theory, at least, it was based on reading the pertinent passage from
Rousseau’s Confessions ‘as a text’—Derrida’s emphasis—‘and not as a document’: Derrida (1967), p. 214; cf. Derrida (1974), p. 149. In practice, Derrida’s reading of that passage
worked through a covert play between textual and documentary apprehensions: see Burke (1992), pp. 123–38.
5
Barthes (1968, 1971). Cf. the 1968 essay by Gérard Genette entitled ‘‘‘Stendhal’’‘ (in quotation-marks), translated in Genette (1982), pp. 147–82. See also Banfield (1985), pp.
1–22; Burke (1992), Sutrop (1994), Keefer (1995).

0039-3681/$ - see front matter Ó 2012 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.
doi:10.1016/j.shpsa.2011.12.027
Author's personal copy

342 A. Wilson / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 43 (2012) 341–358

became routine to describe ‘works’ in the traditional sense, and the meaning of the term is so obvious [that] there is scarcely a liter-
writings of other kinds as well, as ‘texts’. The new usage became ary handbook that troubles to mention it’.15 Another had the courage
hegemonic in the 1980s, leading to a vast outpouring of studies to ask ‘What is meant by the term ‘‘text’’?’ and came up with these
whose premise was ‘texts’ or ‘the text’ and whose theme was answers: that ‘it may initially be seen as a situated use of language
denominated, in another new usage, as ‘textuality’.6 Moreover, marked by a tense interaction between mutually implicated yet con-
the reference of ‘text’ was extended to embrace (as a recent tech- testatory tendencies’; that texts possess both ‘documentary and
nical dictionary puts it) ‘any cultural object of investigation’,7 with worklike aspects’; that ‘to the extent that a text is not a mere docu-
the effect that ‘textuality’ came to be seen as a property not just of ment, it supplements existing reality’; that ‘a text is a network of
the written word but also of human lives and even of the social or- resistances’; and finally, that ‘whatever else they may be, texts are
der itself—despite Derrida’s own disavowal of such interpretations.8 events in the history of language’.16 If these vacuous gestures suc-
All this rested upon the expanded usage of that once-innocent ceeded only in defining ‘text’ as indefinable, they had the merit of
word ‘text’. Yet so far as I have been able to find, the shift in usage making relatively explicit a difficulty which was usually left tacit
itself has never been discussed, still less has its history been writ- at the time, and which has remained so to this day.17
ten.9 On the contrary, the figure of the text in its new application has In contrast, and indeed in a curious counterpoint, the analogous
been unreflectively assigned the status of a simple real; the gaze of question ‘What is an author?’ was posed explicitly as early as
theory, in the very act of focusing upon the property of textuality, 1969—specifically by Michel Foucault, in a lecture which he gave
has taken for granted the site and home of that property, namely in March of that year and which, like Barthes’s essays on the author
the figure of the text itself. Thus in a strange paradox, ‘the text’ is and the text, was to appear in English in 1977.18 Foucault’s 1969
at once the most theorised and least theorised of concepts. lecture ‘Qu’est-ce qu’un auteur?’ was a response to Barthes’s ‘La mort
To the extent that the question what is a text? has been raised at de l’auteur’, published in the previous year, where Barthes had in-
all, the answers have begged the question. Derrida simply evaded stalled écriture in place of the author-figure. Although Foucault hap-
the issue from the outset.10 Barthes was inconsistent—assigning pily added his own signature to the author’s death-warrant, he
the constitution of the text now to the reader, now to the writer;11 wanted not just to abolish the author-figure but also to interrogate
deploying the figure of the text both as a substitute for the individual its meaning, for he suspected that figure to be more durable than
work and in a transcendent sense, as the replacement and extension Barthes had imagined: indeed, he argued that écriture itself had
of the figure of écriture.12 And he claimed that ‘a Theory of the Text’ ‘merely transposed the empirical characteristics of an author to a
in this transcendent, capitalised sense was unattainable, since ‘the transcendental anonymity’.19 Foucault’s answer to his own question
Text’ put in question the very possibility of a ‘meta-language’ in ‘What is an author?’ was that ‘the author’ is a constructed figure, the
which to articulate such a theory.13 Other commentators, then and product and embodiment of a discursive convention which he
since, have attained no greater clarity. Paul Ricoeur, for instance, termed ‘the author-function’. Although this novel conception was
simply identified the textual as the written, thereby echoing the highly illuminating in some respects, it also served in other ways
new usage rather than interrogating it.14 One theorist effectively to obscure the nature of the author-figure, as we shall shortly
equated the text with the literary work, and observed: ‘Evidently see.20 But if Foucault’s achievement was double-edged with respect

6
The entry for ‘textuality’ in the old OED gave this solely as an occasional synonym for ‘textualism’, in the sense of ‘strict adherence to the text, especially of the Scriptures’.
7
Payne (ed.) (1996), p. 530.
8
In 1977 Derrida remarked, in criticism of such appropriations: ‘it was never our wish to extend the reassuring notion of the text to a whole extra-textual realm and to
transform the world into a library by doing away with all boundaries . . .’. See Derrida (1979), p. 84; for the context, n.10 below. Cf. Burke (1992), pp. 126–7.
9
The new usage was not registered in the new OED (20 vols., 1989, vol. xvii), though it is perhaps implicit in the 1977 quotation given there to illustrate the combined terms
‘text linguistics’ and ‘text linguist’, and the associated new usage for ‘textuality’ is registered there in quotations from as early as 1970. In the online OED, the new usage of ‘text’
began to appear in the draft 1993 additions under ‘Linguistics’, and its extended form was registered in the draft additions of July 2009.
10
No definition was offered in Derrida (1967). In 1977 Derrida circled around the question thus: ‘If we are to approach a text, it must have an edge. The question of the text, as it
has been elaborated and transformed in the last dozen or so years, has not merely ‘‘touched’’ . . . all those boundaries that form the running border of what used to be called a text,
of what we once thought this word could identify, i.e., the supposed end and beginning of a work [etc.] . . . What has happened, if it has happened, is a sort of overrun that spoils all
these boundaries . . . and forces us to extend the accredited concept, the dominant notion of a ‘‘text’’, of what I still call a ‘‘text’’, for strategic reasons in part . . .’ The passage went on
to endorse the breaking of these boundaries, yet then to make the disclaimer quoted in n.8 above. Derrida thereupon asked: ‘What are the borderlines of a text?’—thus taking as
given the reference of ‘text’ itself. See Derrida (1979), pp. 83–5.
11
‘La mort de l’auteur’ made it explicit that texts are constituted by the reader: Barthes (1968), pp. 66–7; Barthes (1977), pp. 147–8. In ‘De l’oeuvre au texte’ this formulation
was retained, but its emphasis was muted, and it was now implied that some authors can produce texts (as distinct from works); thus ‘Georges Bataille wrote texts, or even,
perhaps, a text, one single text’ [un seul et même texte]: Barthes (1971), pp. 76, 71, my translation; cf. Barthes (1977), pp. 163, 157. On the paradox that Bataille and certain other
authors were exempted from the death-sentence, see Burke (1992), pp. 45, 87.
12
In ‘La mort de l’auteur’, ‘texts’ were taken as equivalent to individual works: Barthes (1968), pp. 64, 65, 66; Barthes (1977), pp. 145, 146, 147. In ‘De l’oeuvre au texte’ the
predominant usage was transcendent and capitalised (‘le Texte’), but from time to time Barthes reverted to the concrete and individual reference, signalled as un-capitalised:
Barthes (1971), pp. 70, 76; Barthes (1977), pp. 156, 163.
13
Barthes (1971, p. 77, 1977), p. 164.
14
‘Let us call a text every utterance or set of utterances fixed by writing’: Ricoeur (1971), p. 135.
15
Holl (1975), 1980 reprint, p. 118 and passim.
16
LaCapra (1980), pp. 247, 250, 263 (on which cf. p. 257), 274, 275. In fact, the effective usage of ‘text’ in this essay was simple enough: it was merely a generic designation for
canonical texts. What is remarkable, in a paper devoted to theoretical clarification, is that this concrete reference had to be covered-over. Cf. below, at n.144.
17
The persistent obscurity of the figure of the text is illustrated by each of two complementary approaches to the problem of its definition. The entry in Payne (ed.) (1996), p.
530, opts for vagueness, in the end offering no definition at all. In contrast Pope (1995) seeks to be specific, with results that are instructively incoherent. ‘By text’, writes Pope (p.
3), ‘I mean any more or less cohesive communicative act which involves a substantial verbal component and is in some way recorded’. This definition is doubly inappropriate,
since (a) what can be recorded is not the communicative act but its verbal component (the conceivable exception to this, namely film, is not itself examined in the book save as a
medium of thought-experimental rewriting, e.g. pp. 83–92); and (b) in practice, the use of ‘text’ throughout the book denotes not communicative acts (the performances of
human agents) but their recorded verbal products. Thus it would have been more accurate, as well as more coherent, to define ‘text’ as (for instance) ‘any recorded verbal
component or product of a communicative act’. The effect of Pope’s very different definition is to construe the verbal record as the communicative act itself; as will emerge in due
course, this remarkable elision is no accident (cf. n.72 below). Correlatively, the book nowhere discusses (though its bibliography cites) the descriptive speech-act theory of
Austin, which was concerned precisely to distinguish between the communicative act and its verbal component. Instead, Pope’s brief discussion of speech-act theory is confined
to its prescriptive variants—this in order to write speech-act theory out of consideration (pp. 127–9). Cf. Austin (1962).
18
Foucault (1977). For another version see Harari (ed.) (1980), pp. 141–60; for bibliographic details see Burke (1992), pp. 89–94.
19
Foucault (1977), p. 119. Cf. below, at n.77.
20
Below, at n.30.
Author's personal copy

A. Wilson / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 43 (2012) 341–358 343

to what he called ‘the question of the author’, his approach was tion will be following what is now a well-trodden track: the exten-
straightforwardly mystifying with respect to what we may term sion of literary analysis beyond the confines of imaginative
the ‘question of the text’. For as I have shown elsewhere,21 his lec- literature, for instance to writings in philosophy,27 in history,28
ture not only failed to pose the latter question, but also worked to and in science itself.29
exclude it from the analytic field. This Foucault achieved through a It will be convenient to begin by considering the ‘question of the
veritable cluster of rhetorical strokes: by playing between the figures author’, partly to settle accounts with Foucault’s essay and also be-
of the ‘text’ and the ‘work’; by differentially distributing those two cause this will bring into focus the physical being of ‘texts’. I shall
figures within the structure of his argument; and by deploying the then be in a position to address directly the question that I have ta-
word ‘text’ in three different ways—referring in turn to the authored, ken as my title. My answer will lead us, by way of canonicity and
the written and the uttered. The remarkable result was that even as disciplines, to the tension between Hermeneutik and Geschichte and
the unreflective figure of the author was replaced by the critical con- thence to some possible implications for the historiography of sci-
cept of ‘the author-function’, so the figure of the text slipped beyond ence and medicine.
the analytical horizon, covertly acquiring the status of a natural kind.
In this respect Foucault’s treatment accurately anticipated the wider 2. Who is Aristotle?
subsequent fate of the text-figure.
While the central aporiai of Foucault’s lecture were associ- The question Foucault posed in 1969 was ‘What is an author?’.
ated with the generic figures of author and text, his specific As this wording implied, the effect of his lecture was to eliminate
examples entailed a further ambiguity: namely the question the personal quality of the author-figure, introducing in its stead
as to whether ‘the’ author-function was one phenomenon or the impersonal ‘author-function’. The positive side of this thesis,
several. For although Foucault insisted that ‘the author-func- that is, the argument that the figure of the author is an interpreta-
tion . . . does not operate in a uniform manner in all discourses, tive construct, was convincingly argued; but its negative moment,
at all times, and in any given culture’,22 such potential discur- that is, the obliteration of the personal being of ‘the author’, was
sive distinctions were implicitly suppressed by the vast referen- accomplished not by explicit argument but instead by a series of
tial sweep of his argument: Homer and Flaubert, Aristotle and covert rhetorical manoeuvres.30 This was the very technique with
Nietzsche, Galileo and Darwin were just a few of the figures which, as we have seen, Foucault simultaneously buried the ‘ques-
whom he summoned together into a single gallery of authors.23 tion of the text’.31 Ironically enough, Foucault’s deft erasure of the
Similarly, Foucault’s points of departure were on the one hand author-as-person was doubly at odds with his own purposes. For
his own Les mots et les choses, a work in the history of science, in the first place, it is precisely the quality of personal being that
and on the other hand Barthes’s ‘Death of the author’, which the ‘author-function’ confers upon ‘the author’, which means that
was concerned with imaginative literature;24 his most sustained to suppress this attribute of the author-figure is to lose sight of the
discussion was devoted to Marx and Freud, yet his argument working of the author-function itself; and secondly, the larger ques-
was framed within a quotation from Beckett;25 and when he tion Foucault wanted to raise was ‘the privileges of the subject’,32 yet
came to illustrate the textual devices underlying the author-func- he had suppressed from the analytical field just those qualities
tion, he juxtaposed ‘a novel narrated in the first person’ with ‘a which the author-figure shares with the figure of the subject. In
mathematical treatise’.26 The author-function thus emerged as a short, as I have put this elsewhere, Foucault had replaced one mys-
transdiscursive phenomenon, notably pertaining indifferently to tery by another;33 his powerful insight was achieved at the price of a
fictional and non-fictional works alike. specific blindness.34
Since the present paper will necessarily be ranging across a sim- This aporia of Foucault’s ‘What is an author?’ has been nicely
ilarly wide canvas, it may be helpful to delineate at the outset the captured by Sean Burke, whose excellent critical discussion is
scope of this inquiry and its disciplinary associations. My main headed with the aptly rephrased question ‘What (and who) is an
concern is with the ‘question of the text’; but this will entail author?’.35 Burke’s rewriting of Foucault’s title leads us, then, to pre-
addressing the related ‘question of the author’ as well. These cisely the question which Foucault worked so hard to eliminate:
themes will be pursued in non-fictional domains, particularly namely, ‘Who is an author?’. But if we are to follow this direction,
(though by no means exclusively) the history of the sciences; but it becomes necessary to rephrase the question yet again. For the
as it happens, much of the argument will also apply to ‘texts’ of question ‘who is an author?’ cannot admit of an answer, since a
a literary kind. Further, various conceptual resources and points ‘who’ has to refer to an individual: the very bearing of ‘who’ is lost
of reference will be drawn from literary theory, and adapted to if it is applied to an abstract figure such as ‘an author’. That is why
present purposes as occasion requires. In this respect my investiga- I am asking here ‘Who is Aristotle?’. It would equally be possible

21
Wilson (2004).
22
Foucault (1977), pp. 130 (quoted), 125–7.
23
Some examples, in alphabetical order, with page-numbers in Foucault (1977): Aristotle 121, Buffon 113, Darwin 114, Flaubert 117, Galileo 133 and 136, Homer 122, Newton
136, Nietzsche 118, Sade 118, Shakespeare 122. The one systematic distinction Foucault drew was between authors of works on the one hand, and authors of ‘discursive practices’
(notably Marx and Freud) on the other: pp. 131–6.
24
See respectively ibid., pp. 113–15 and 118–20 (where Foucault’s reference to Barthes was left implicit).
25
For Marx and Freud see ibid., pp. 131–6; for Beckett, pp. 115, 138.
26
Ibid., pp. 120–30.
27
For instance Derrida (1967), de Man (1979), Rée (1987).
28
Hexter (1971), pp. 15–76 (an essay first published in 1968); Hexter (1972), pp. 299–329; White (1973), Ricoeur (1983-85), Cook (1988).
29
See for instance Shapin & Schaffer (1985), Benjamin et al. (eds.) (1987), Latour (1987), Woolgar (1988), pp. 67–82; Myers (1990), Woolgar (1993).
30
Wilson (2004).
31
See above, at n.21.
32
Foucault (1977), p. 137.
33
Quoting loosely from Wilson (2004). In fact this point was made with respect to the subsidiary theme of the author’s name, but it is equally applicable to the larger,
surrounding question of the author’s being.
34
Cf. de Man (1983), p. 16 and passim.
35
Burke (1992), pp. 89–94; emphasis added. Burke’s critique, while leading in a similar direction to my own (Wilson, 2004), focuses on different passages within the lecture
(particularly on the Marx-Freud discussion: cf. n.23 above). See also Banfield (1985), Nesbit (1987), Biriotti & Miller (eds.) (1993).
Author's personal copy

344 A. Wilson / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 43 (2012) 341–358

to ask, say, ‘Who is Foucault?’, ‘Who is Freud?’, or (as I shall indeed 2. Our own relation to the virtual author is a relation of co-
be asking later on) ‘Who is Locke?’.36 presence. This is why ‘Aristotle’, as we are told, ‘speaks’ of Nat-
Consider the following sentences, excerpted from Richard Rob- ure, and can ‘tell us’ things about her. The use of the present
inson’s introduction to his 1962 translation of two books of Aris- tense; the fact that he addresses us; the fact that he does so
totle’s Politics: through the medium of speech—all these announce his pres-
ence-with-us.
Aristotle often speaks of Nature as if she were a person and per-
3. The virtual author arises from the works, rather than the other
haps a divine person. Nature is a kind of goddess to him, not
way around; or to be more precise, the virtual author arises from
explicitly acknowledged as such but acting as such. He consid-
our apprehension of the works.43 One marker of this is that virtual
ers himself able to tell us of certain universal principles on
authors manage unaided to write their own posthumous works: that
which nature acts. For instance, he tells us in Politics I 2 that
is to say, we routinely elide the constitutive role of editors in bring-
‘Nature never makes things penuriously . . .’37
ing such works into being, assigning these works solely to their
To whom do Robinson’s words refer? Who is this ‘Aristotle’? ‘authors’.44 The same applies to the work of translators: thus the vir-
Clearly this is not the flesh-and-blood Aristotle, who is reckoned tual author named Aristotle converses with us in our language, Eng-
to have died over 2,000 years before these words were written; lish, a language which did not exist when the historical individual
for the ‘Aristotle’ discussed here is very much alive. He is en- named Aristotle was writing. Another such marker is the fact that
gaged in speaking; he is in our presence, for he tells us things; the relation between author and works varies according to our
moreover, we experience a certain closeness to him, enabling own disciplinary angle of approach. Sometimes, as in the case of
us to infer what is going on in his mind: ‘He considers himself ‘Aristotle’, the virtual author tends to be linked, albeit loosely, to
able to tell us...’. It is precisely as if he were in the room with his or her oeuvre as a whole. Sometimes the same name effectively
us, engaged in a conversation. In short, we are not dealing here designates more than one virtual author: thus the ‘Locke’ of the
with the historical person Aristotle, a long-dead individual who Two Treatises of Government is a political theorist, whereas the
happened to leave certain writings which we may read and from ‘Locke’ of the Essay concerning Human Understanding is a philosopher
which we might, with a struggle, infer something of his being.38 of knowledge, and these two Lockes are seldom connected with one
On the contrary, this ‘Aristotle’ is here with us, alive and well, in another, or indeed with the Locke-or-Lockes who wrote or authored
excellent condition, full of ideas, and talking to us: in a nutshell, still other works.45 And sometimes again, as in the case of Adam
he is a living person.39 Smith, the virtual author is associated with a single work, whereas
I shall call this ‘Aristotle’ the virtual author. He is not the his- the historical writer of the same name was far more prolific.46
torical individual named Aristotle, who (so we take it) wrote the 4. As a corollary, the integrity of the virtual author is textual,
words of the book we are reading (such as the Politics); rather, not biographical, in origin. Hence the fact that the virtual author
he is a virtual individual who is read in that text, who is con- can assimilate various features of the historical author, while
structed by the reader. The virtual author is a projection of the nonetheless remaining thoroughly virtual in character. Such bio-
act of reading.40 Far from being merely a quirk of Robinson’s, or graphical details can be so assimilated, without transforming
peculiar to the figure of Aristotle, this mode of apprehension is the virtual author into the historical author, because they are
the very norm of reading, certainly in the case of those non-fic- pendant from a textual frame: they are typically adduced in or-
tional works with which I am concerned, and arguably (as we der to resolve detailed local puzzles in the work.47
shall see) in imaginative literature as well.41 Without attempting The concept of the virtual author has certain analogues in re-
an exhaustive account, I shall suggest four characteristics of the cent literary and philosophical theory, though its resemblances
virtual author. with these should not be overstated. In particular, the virtual
1. The virtual author has the attributes of a person. This is author is different in kind from the concept of the ‘implied author’,
shown most clearly by the use of the author’s name, and by developed by Wayne Booth;48 for Booth’s ‘implied author’ is con-
the associated use of personal pronouns and adjectives to refer structed by the writer and then apprehended by the reader, whereas
to the author. It also emerges in the fact that we tend not only the virtual author is specifically a construct of the reader.49 The true
to agree-disagree with the virtual author’s written views, but literary cognates of the virtual-author concept are the ‘postulated
also to entertain feelings of attraction or repulsion towards her narrator’ of Jonathan Culler, the ‘postulated author’ of Alexander
or him.42 Nehamas and the ‘fictional author’ of Gregory Currie. Nevertheless

36
Below, at nn.45, 65, 161.
37
Robinson (1962), p. xvii.
38
This, of course, we also learn from Foucault’s ‘What is an author?’, but not in the way that is emerging here.
39
Thus, just as ‘Aristotle often speaks of Nature as if she were a person’ (above, at n.37), so we can say that Robinson ‘often speaks of Aristotle as if he were a person’. For the
record, this reflexivity is fortuitous: I did not notice it when choosing this passage by way of example, but only afterwards.
40
Cf. Ricoeur (1971), pp. 136–7.
41
Thus Foucault switched into the present tense when paraphrasing St Jerome’s De Viris Illustribus: Foucault (1977), p. 127. On the reading of fiction see below, at n.48.
42
For instance, see Collingwood (1946), pp. 29–31; Robinson (1962), pp. 32–3; Livingston (1993), p. 112.
43
This is true even of a living writer, as is shown vividly and poignantly by the variety of public constructions of that author who bears the name Salman Rushdie. See Spivak
(1993), Ni Fhlathuin (1995), and cf. Ricoeur (1971), pp. 136–7.
44
Foucault himself drew attention to this with respect to Nietzsche. See Foucault (1977), pp. 118–19; the specific rhetorical role of this passage is discussed in Wilson (2004). Cf.
also Genette (1982), as cited in n.5 above. From a vast range of possibilities (in addition to Aristotle and Nietzsche, think for instance of Marx, Saussure and Wittgenstein), I select
two relatively recent examples; in each of these cases the editor’s contribution is usually overlooked. (1) Collingwood (1946) in fact bore the considerable stamp of its editor, T.M.
Knox: see van der Dussen (1993) and Wilson (1993b). (2) Austin (1962) was the work not just of Austin but also of its editor, J.O. Urmson, as the latter’s introduction made clear.
45
See Harris (1994). Another example: the geographer Kant versus the philosopher Kant (below, at n. 65).
46
Christie (1987b), pp. 202–3.
47
Thus Robinson’s virtual ‘Aristotle’ was informed by the life of the historical Aristotle: for instance, Aristotle was within the same general culture as Plato and Thucydides
(Robinson [1962], p. xv); he was ‘the philosophic tutor of Alexander the Great’ (p. 15); he was writing in Athens (e.g. pp. 40, 102, 116, 122).
48
Booth (1961), Booth (1979). Booth’s concept is adapted to non-fictional works in Rée (1987); cf. also Woolgar (1993).
49
Thus Booth’s ‘implied author’ is cognate with Iser’s ‘implied reader’ (reformulated by Genette as the ‘virtual reader’), rather than with the concepts of Culler, Nehamas and
Currie (discussed below). See Iser (1978), pp. 20–38; Ricoeur (1984-88), vol iii, pp. 170–1, 317 n.37.
Author's personal copy

A. Wilson / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 43 (2012) 341–358 345

the virtual author differs in certain important ways from the con- be argued that ‘he’ is the very primordium of the canonical
cepts of Culler,50 Nehamas,51 and Currie.52 Some of these differ- author. Rather, this mode of apprehension is characteristic of all
ences may arise from the fact that these various interpretative canonical authors, that is to say, of canonical texts. Canonical
figures pertain to the reading of imaginative literature, as of authors are routinely evoked as co-present with ourselves; and
course does Booth’s ‘implied author’,53 whereas the figure denoted they are indeed so present, in the form of their works, for this
here as the virtual author is associated with non-fictional works. is the very definition of their canonical status. Canonicity is a par-
In this respect the concept of the virtual author is akin to Jorge ticular form of survival, of permanence, of presence. The canonical
Gracia’s philosophical theory of authorship, though Gracia’s con- text lives by virtue of its presence; as soon as it ceases to have
ception, too, differs in its emphasis from that developed here.54 this life, it ceases to be canonical, with the effect that the virtual
But what should particularly be noted is that the concept of the author too passes away.56
virtual author enables us to resolve the central problem which Nevertheless a virtual author can also attain presence and
was raised-and-suppressed by Foucault’s ‘What is an author?’. acquire life in another, second-order way: that is, an epony-
We have seen that Foucault’s considerable positive accomplish- mous existence as the name attached to what we may call a
ment—namely his discovery that the author is a construct—was canonical achievement. For example, the virtual author Ranke is
achieved at the formidable price of erasing the personal quality very well-known in historiographic discussions, but not from
of the author-figure. The concept of the virtual author enables his works—rather from the incessantly-quoted phrase wie es
us to preserve Foucault’s discovery while also reinstating that eigentlich gewesen, ‘as it actually happened’. In this attenuated
which Foucault suppressed: for the virtual author is both a con- form Ranke is alive, even though his works are not—as will ap-
struct and a person. pear later on, when I shall be quoting this same phrase.57 This
I have identified the virtual author by attending to an instance particular mode of virtual existence is of course especially famil-
of everyday usage, that is, to the significance of the word ‘Aristotle’ iar in the sciences, whose various ‘laws’ are designated by their
as used by Robinson. But this does not exhaust the familiar mean- respective authorial eponyms—the quasi-tribute which science
ings of that word, for there is also another usage: we say, for in- pays to its own past. In fact, of course, such laws typically owe
stance, that ‘we find in Aristotle’ such-and-such a doctrine, their judicial status, and often enough a significant measure of
method, argument. Here we are of course referring to the works their very content, to posthumous acts of abstraction and appro-
of Aristotle. Thus the word ‘Aristotle’ has not one meaning but priation.58 Thus eponymy, whether attached to ‘doctrines’ or to
two: it refers both to the virtual author and to that author’s works. ‘laws’, rests upon some act of violence performed upon the works
This double usage is no accident. On the contrary, it enables us to and activities of the historical individual who bore the same
clarify just who this ‘Aristotle’ is: the virtual author is the text con- name. Yet in this respect the attenuated, eponymous virtual
strued as a human agent. And as we shall now see, this in turn helps author is no different from the virtual author whose existence
to explain how the virtual author comes into being, how she or he rests upon full-scale canonical ‘works’, for as will emerge more
is endowed with life. fully below, the canonical ‘work’ is also a retrospective construct,
Our relation of co-presence with the virtual author ‘Aristotle’ a later appropriation.59 The ‘second-order’ presence of eponymy,
doubtless derives in part from our own assimilation of the writ- then, merges imperceptibly into the actual presence of the
ten to the spoken, and of the spoken in turn to what is con- works—as is suggested, with respect to the discipline of philoso-
ceived as the subjective.55 But this co-presence also has a real phy, by Watson’s concept of ‘shadow history’. On Watson’s ac-
and physical basis in the being of the text. It is precisely because count, philosophy proceeds by way of a continuous, shifting,
texts such as the one called the Politics are present—physically one-sided quasi-dialogue with what is taken to be its own past,
present upon our bookshelves—that ‘Aristotle’ himself is present. but is in fact a ‘shadow’ of that past, that is, a highly selective
In short, ‘Aristotle’ really is, as I put it just now, ‘in the room with history. This ‘shadow history’ acquires a life of its own, becoming
us’. The physical presence of the text becomes the existential pres- in fact more real than the past of which it is the shadow.60 And
ence of the virtual author, who as we have seen is the text-as- this ‘shadow’ is to the past itself much as the virtual author is to
agent. None of this is confined to ‘Aristotle’—even though it could the historical author.

50
Culler (1975), pp. 146, 197–202. There can be more than one of Culler’s ‘postulated narrators’ in a single text, whereas the virtual author is a single individual who is expected
to be consistent within a given work.
51
Nehamas (1981), Nehamas (1987). (1) The virtual author is a purely descriptive concept, whereas Nehamas’s ‘postulated author’ has a prescriptive element. (2) The concept of
the virtual author does not require any necessary link with an entire oeuvre (see above, at n.45), whereas Nehamas insists that the ‘postulated author’ is connected with an oeuvre,
not with a single work. As it appears to me, Nehamas’s concept does not require this; but I must bow to the author who has postulated the postulated author! See Nehamas
(1987), p. 274. (3) The virtual author is depicted here as a person, whereas Nehamas stresses that the ‘postulated author’ is a character, not a person (ibid., pp. 273, 285). In fact it
may be that some further category, distinct from both ‘person’ and ‘character’, is being invoked both by the ‘postulated author’ and by the ‘virtual author’.
52
Currie (1990), pp. 79–83. (1) Like Nehamas, Currie includes a prescriptive element in his concept. (2) Although most of Currie’s discussion implies that the ‘fictional author’ is
purely a construct of the reader, at one point he suggests that a writer may place a ‘fictional author’ within a novel (p. 78 n.32). This would radically distinguish Currie’s ‘fictional
author’ from the present concept of the ‘virtual author’ and from the 1987 version of Nehamas’s ‘postulated author’. However it is conceivable that Currie might not insist on this
point: cf. the change in Nehamas’s formulation between 1981 and 1987, documented in the next note.
53
One would expect that Nehamas’s ‘postulated author’ and Currie’s ‘fictional author’, being creations of the reader, are distinct from Booth’s ‘implied author’; but in fact the
matter is more complex. Originally Nehamas downplayed the difference between his concept and Booth’s, but in his later formulation Nehamas indeed stressed this difference:
see Nehamas (1981), p. 145 n.36; Nehamas (1987), pp. 273–4. Currie’s ‘fictional author’ is ambiguous in this regard: see the previous note, and cf. also Currie (1990), p. 76 n.31.
Booth (1988), reiterating and developing the concept of the ‘implied author’, lists Nehamas’s 1987 essay in its bibliography but does not discuss his conception.
54
Gracia (1990), whose concern is analytic, distinguishes the historical author from three separate interpretative figures: the ‘composite author’ (a figure which incorporates the
contribution of editors); the ‘pseudo-historical author’ (the picture which we construct of the historical author); and the ‘interpretative author’ (the author whom we posit in the
act of interpreting a text). The present concept of the ‘virtual author’ is phenomenological rather than analytic, and combines these three figures into one. See also Gracia (1994).
55
Derrida (1967), passim.
56
On the mystification inherent in such locutions as ‘‘Aristotle says’’, and their hidden basis in the physical book, cf. Secord (2004), pp. 661, 670. The mortality of virtual authors
is nicely conveyed by McCrea (1990).
57
See below, at nn.133, 137.
58
Cf. Brannigan (1981), p. 94 and passim. On Mendel’s law (one of the cases analyzed by Brannigan), see Charnley and Radick (in press); another familiar example is what are
known as ‘Koch’s postulates’, on which see Carter (2003), pp.144–5. On appropriation in the sciences more generally see Jardine (1991), pp. 74–6, 130–45 and passim.
59
See below, at n.111.
60
Watson (1993). Cf. n.108 below.
Author's personal copy

346 A. Wilson / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 43 (2012) 341–358

The distinction between the virtual author and the historical from their authorial and publishing histories.66 ‘In this usage’, McG-
author corresponds precisely to Michael Oakeshott’s distinction ann went on,
between the ‘practical past’, that is, the past-as-present in our cul-
we are dealing with ‘texts’ which transcend their concrete and
ture, and the historical past, that is, the past that has passed.61 The
actual textualities.67 This usage of the word text does not mean
significance and aptness of Oakeshott’s powerful category of the
anything written or printed in an actual physical state; rather,
‘practical past’ is well conveyed by his alternative formulation: ‘the
it means the opposite: it points to an Ur-poem or meta-work
didactic or so-called living ‘‘past’’’.62 The ‘practical past’ is indeed liv-
whose existence is the Idea that can be abstracted out of all con-
ing, and it has this living quality because it has been assigned a
crete and written texts which have ever existed or will ever exist.
didactic use in the present. And it is just this complex of presence
and significance—condensed by Oakeshott into the pregnant adjec- While McGann was here referring specifically to literary works,
tive ‘practical’—which characterises the canonical in each of its his remarks are applicable across the full terrain of what is
forms. Thus canonical texts, canonical achievements, virtual authors now called the textual. McGann’s point was that the designation
and ‘shadow history’ all belong to the practical past; and this helps ‘text’, in abstracting the object to which it refers from its ‘actual
to reveal that Oakeshott’s conception is even more cogent and fruit- physical state’, turns it into ‘a timeless object, unconnected with
ful than his own exposition has suggested. For Oakeshott deliber- history’.68 This is as true of the writings of Aristotle, Locke, New-
ately limits his examples ‘to the commonplace’;63 but this ton or Kant as of the writings of Blake, of Byron, of Emily Dick-
drastically restricts the scope of his argument, since the domain of inson—the examples McGann was discussing; and it is true, too,
‘the commonplace’, namely the shared culture of the present age, of the extension of ‘text’ to refer to the written-or-printed as
is almost vanishingly narrow. In fact, of course, we inhabit not one such.
culture but many, each with its own distinctive ‘practical past’; Here McGann accurately identified a salient feature of the new
and once this diversity of ‘the present’ and of ‘the’ practical past is usage. Yet the apprehension of the ‘text’ as a ‘timeless object’ by no
brought into focus, the considerable strength of Oakeshott’s concept means began with this usage; on the contrary, this was of very long
becomes more apparent.64 It is for just this reason that we have standing. We have already encountered just this apprehension in
more than one Locke (the political theorist and the philosopher of Robinson’s approach to Aristotle’s Politics, and more generally in
knowledge), more than one Kant (the geographer and the philoso- the nature of the canonical text. Thus the new usage of ‘text’ is
pher), and so on.65 So too, while ‘Aristotle’ is very much alive, he is double-edged. On the one hand, as McGann rightly observed, it is
living not in our culture as a whole but at certain specific sites within inherently mystifying in that it abstracts the objects to which it re-
that culture. fers from their material existence. On the other hand, this usage
By way of recapitulation, we may observe that the full force of also has a positive side, albeit unwittingly; for it has actually
the question ‘Who is Aristotle?’ emerges if we pose it as three brought to the fore and rendered semi-explicit the very mode of
questions—underlining each of its three words in turn. The ques- apprehension which it reflects. And it is that mode of apprehension
tion ‘Who?’ opens the theme of the virtual author’s personal being. with which I am concerned.
The question ‘is?’ draws attention to the implied presence of this I can now suggest an answer to the question ‘what is a text?’, in
figure. And the question ‘Aristotle?’ leads us into the apparent dou- the form of five propositions. These are not to be understood as
ble meaning, namely author and works, which is in fact a single ‘propositions’ in the analytical sense; on the contrary, they are con-
meaning, namely the canonical text-as-agent. joined, each implying the others, so that together they comprise an
interrelated complex.
3. What is a text?
1. The attribute of being a text—to denote which we may adapt
As we saw at the outset, the shift of usage entailed in the new the word textuality69—does not inhere in any given object;
figure of the ‘text’ has attracted curiously little discussion. Never- rather, textuality is assigned to such an object by the reader
theless that transmutation did draw some perceptive comments and by wider cultural processes which constitute the very pos-
in the early 1980s from the literary theorist and critic Jerome J. sibility of reading. The explicit or implicit designation ‘text’,
McGann, who was concerned at that time with the relationship be- then, is not a neutral description of written and printed mate-
tween the literary ‘work’ and the bibliographic ‘text’. It seems that rials, but on the contrary is a particular way of positioning
this thematic gave McGann an interest in retaining the older them. Thus what Stanley Fish has written of the ‘shape’ of
usages, thereby leading him to adopt a critical stance towards texts—that this ‘shape’ is conferred by ‘interpretive strate-
the new figure of the text. In particular he observed that the new gies’—extends still further, to their very being.70 In short, a text
usage is profoundly mystifying, in that it abstracts works from is not a natural object; rather, textuality is a mode of
the actual and contingent events of their ‘bibliographies’, that is, apprehension, a practical construal.

61
See Oakeshott (1983), pp. 1–44, particularly pp. 16–19, 34–44; also p. 106.
62
Ibid., p. 39 (and see further below, at nn.74, 110).
63
Ibid., p. 19 n.2.
64
It is precisely the practical past that is invoked in the following remarks (Lowenthal, 1985): ‘The past is everywhere. All around us lie features which, like ourselves and our
thoughts, have more or less recognizable antecedents’. These are the opening sentences of a book whose entire content is a meditation on the practical past, associated with a
systematic elision of the distinction between the practical past and the historical past, and which accordingly treats Oakeshott’s argument to summary dismissal (ibid., p. 237). In
view of this orientation Lowenthal’s title—The Past is a Foreign Country—may seem paradoxical, since the image of the foreign emphasizes the gulf between past and present. But
the apparent paradox is resolved by the accompanying figure of country, for a ‘foreign country’ can be visited, and is thus present. Hence too the active figure of the present in
Lowenthal’s title, taken from the opening sentence of L.P. Hartley’s novel The Go-Between: ‘The past is a foreign country; they do things differently there’.
65
Above, at n.45; Brewer (1973), p. 102; Livingstone (1990).
66
McGann (1985b), p. 117. This particular essay was written in 1980-1 (see p. 132).
67
Notice that McGann was adapting the word ‘textuality’; cf. n.69 below.
68
Ibid., p. 118. The context of these remarks was McGann’s critique of the concept of ‘final authorial intention’; see further McGann (1983), McGann (1991), p. 179 et seq., esp. p.
183; and n.98 below.
69
Using the word differently from (1) its original usage (cf. n.6 above); (2) the usage associated with the recent figure of the text; and (3) McGann’s use in the passage just
quoted (cf. n.67 above).
70
Fish (1980), p. 13.
Author's personal copy

A. Wilson / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 43 (2012) 341–358 347

2. That construal consists, as McGann observed, in abstracting ver- son that writing [écriture] is the destruction of every voice [voix],
bal content from its material embodiment; or, more precisely, of every origin. Writing is that neutral, that composite, that
from its original material embodiment and, correlatively, from oblique space where our subject slips away, the [photographic]
its original setting of action. A printed book, a manuscript letter, negative where every identity is lost, starting with the identity
a shopping-list, an encyclopaedia, a handbill—all these physical of the very body which writes.75
objects, these products of the pen and the press, lose their differ-
In order to arrive at his answer Barthes first of all built up—it is
entiae as they are apprehended as texts.71
tempting to say, had to build up—a play between writing and
3. This mode of apprehension is by its very nature doubly self-
speech, a play which settled upon speech at the precise point where
oblivious. In the first place, the quality of textuality is projected
he posed his question: Qui parle ainsi?76 Thus the figure of écriture
into the object itself. Secondly, and as a corollary, the abstracted
was constructed by way of the figure of the written-apprehended-
verbal content is assigned the quality of reality, independent of
as-the-spoken, that is to say, the written-in-presence—amply bear-
its material embodiment and from the setting of action in
ing out Foucault’s suspicion that the features of the author-figure
which it arose.72
had been transposed, in concealed form, upon écriture. Or to put
4. The objects to which textuality is assigned can and do arise var-
the point more sharply, if écriture erases ‘every identity’, the figure
iously from the present, from the past, and (as with various
of écriture also erases the acts of écrire and publier, by apprehending
writings appropriated here)73 from a liminal zone between the
their product under the sign of speech.77 The effect of this covert
two. But textuality projects all such objects onto the plane of
assimilation of writing to speech was to project the written onto
the present. Thus in its principal application, namely to past writ-
the plane of the present. And this quality of the Barthesian figure
ings, textuality entails the actual presence of the past; that is, tex-
of écriture was shared by the new figure of the text.
tuality is precisely an instance of Oakeshott’s ‘practical past’.74 It
To recapitulate: The mode of apprehension delineated by our
is this which makes possible the relation of co-presence which
five propositions did not arise with the recent figure of the text:
constructs the ‘virtual author’.
on the contrary, it is as old as the written trace itself, for it develops
5. Textuality is given a material embodiment in the act of publication
spontaneously in the acts of reading and cultural appropriation.
or republication. The canonical text is the physical form of the
The contemporary figure of the text is simultaneously illuminating
designation ‘text’; it makes that designation real, by restoring
and mystifying. It crystallises this mode of apprehension, embody-
to the ‘text’ the materiality it has lost. It is precisely in this mate-
ing it in the form of a name—a name which reifies the written-or-
rial form that the past actually is present. However this is always,
printed word, thereby accurately reflecting the mode of apprehen-
and necessarily, a new material form; correlatively, such publica-
sion itself. Paradoxically, the new figure of the text is appropriate
tion situates the text in a new setting of action. Thus, once again
in the very mystification which it effects; for it captures, echoes
in accordance with Oakeshott’s fruitful distinction, the past that
and compounds that reification of the verbal which is entailed in
is present is not the same as the past that has passed.
the co-presence of the read. And it thus becomes intelligible that
the figure of the text has so persistently eluded coherent definition.
A ‘text’, then, is a constructed object, just as an ‘author’ is (so we
have learnt from Foucault) a constructed individual. Far from being
a neutral description of a pre-existing object, the designation ‘text’ 4. The self-oblivion of the textual construal
reassigns the object to which it refers: it positions that object in a
seemingly transtemporal space, which is in fact the space of co- I have observed that my five propositions are mutually-imbri-
presence with the reader, or more widely of presence within the cated; in other words, they stand or fall together. But the pivotal
reader’s world. The attribution of textuality assimilates the object into point, which is also the most elusive, is Proposition 3: the claim
the cultural world of the present. This was captured with perfect if that the textual apprehension is self-oblivious, that it assigns to
unwitting accuracy by Roland Barthes himself, in the opening pas- its object those qualities which arise from the apprehension itself.
sage of ‘La mort de l’auteur’—the essay which put forward the figure Thus although this proposition has already been illustrated indi-
of écriture, which was closely enmeshed with the new figure of the rectly with reference to Barthes’s concept of écriture, it will be
text. To bring out what was at stake here I shall abridge and selec- helpful to exemplify it further and directly. To this end I shall
tively emphasise the English translation of this classic paragraph, now consider two examples: first Hans-Georg Gadamer’s concep-
supplying the original French words where appropriate: tion of hermeneutics, together with its development by Hans Rob-
ert Jauss, then a paper of Tony Bennett’s which proposed a new
In his story Sarrasine, Balzac, referring to [parlant de] a castrato Marxist approach to literary texts. It will thus emerge that the
disguised as a woman, writes [écrit] the following sentence: ‘It self-oblivion of the textual construal runs across a wide range of
was Woman herself, with her sudden fears, her irrational theoretical positions.
whims, her instinctive worries, her impetuous boldness, her Gadamer’s ‘philosophical hermeneutics’, which is concerned
fussings and her delicious sensibility.’ Who is speaking thus? with the nature and basis of the act of understanding, is addressed
[Qui parle ainsi?] Is it the hero of the story . . .? Is it the individual to the concerns of traditional Hermeneutik—the tradition which
Balzac . . .? Is it Balzac the author . . .? Is it universal wisdom? Dilthey constructed from resources supplied by such earlier figures
Romantic psychology? We shall never know, for the good rea- as Schleiermacher and Droysen78—but has taken those concerns in a

71
As Barthes himself put it (1971, p. 71): ‘l’oeuvre se tient dans la main, le texte se tient dans le langage’ (‘the work is held in the hand, the text is contained within language’, my
translation).
72
It is this (widespread) move which makes possible the further (occasional) step of taking the text itself as a ‘communicative act’ (n.17 above). The latter construal, by assigning
agency to recorded words, of course completes the effacement of the various human actions (such as writing, editing, publishing) which actually produced those words.
73
For instance writings by Foucault, Robinson, Oakeshott, McGann, Fish; and others below.
74
Above, at n.61.
75
Barthes (1968), p. 61; translation adapted from that in Barthes (1977), p. 142.
76
Cf. Banfield (1985), pp. 2–3.
77
écrire and publier: writing and publishing. For Foucault on écriture see above, at n.19.
78
‘The’ hermeneutic tradition is itself complex, as is the hermeneutic concept of tradition: see for instance Szondi (1970), Szondi (1995), Bleicher (1980), Gusdorf (1988), Bruns
(1992), pp. 1–17, 195–212. See further below, from n.126 onwards.
Author's personal copy

348 A. Wilson / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 43 (2012) 341–358

radically new direction.79 On the one hand, Gadamer fits entirely mode of being is not conferred through the act of use but, on
within the frame of traditional hermeneutics, in that his substantive the contrary, inheres within them. And correspondingly, their
work has precisely been concerned with the study of canonical texts canonisation does not construct their cultural worth but rather re-
and authors, starting with Plato. On the other hand, his approach flects it.
represents a radical departure from that tradition, in that he has This conception reaches its ironic apogee in Gadamer’s notion of
abandoned its telos of a realist or objective determination of mean- the ‘classical’. For in a paradoxical contradiction of his own frame-
ing. For Gadamer, understanding is necessarily anchored in the per- work, Gadamer has concluded that the classicism of the works of
spective of the interpreter; all that can be attained is a ‘fusion of the ancients is, literally, ‘timeless’.85 It is at just this point that Gad-
horizons’ between the interpreter’s perspective and that of the amer’s own pupil Hans Robert Jauss departs from his mentor, accu-
author (or the text) being read. The goal of a definitive determination rately observing that this posited immanence and permanence of the
of meaning is not only elusive but illusory, a denial of the situated classical violates the very precepts of Gadamer’s approach.86 Indeed,
nature of the very act of interpretation. Thus Gadamerian hermeneu- Jauss takes this criticism still further, arguing that Gadamer’s model
tics calls not for a suppression of the interpreter’s viewpoint, after of aesthetic experience in general is itself ‘classical’ (in the sense of
the manner of traditional hermeneutics, but on the contrary for an ancient-and-humanist) in type, centred as it is upon mimesis and
adequate awareness of the role and nature of that viewpoint. Such recognition—experiential structures violated, on Jauss’s analysis,
an awareness Gadamer has sought through a cluster of concepts both in the medieval world and in the modern age.87 According to
adapted from Heidegger’s account of the existential basis of under- Jauss’s critique, then, not only has Gadamer explicitly assigned time-
standing. According to Heidegger, all understanding is rooted in a lessness to the classical works themselves; he has also insidiously
founding ‘fore-structure’, entailing a fore-having (Vorhabe), a fore- conferred just such a timelessness upon the ancient-and-humanist
seeing (Vorsicht) and a fore-conception (Vorgriff); and it is this mode of aesthetic experience, mistakenly taking this historically-
‘fore-structure’ which constitutes the very possibility, and the partic- specific interpretative mode as general and universal. Thus Gad-
ular being, of any given object of study.80 Gadamer, applying this ap- amer’s entire conception stands in need of revision, for it becomes
proach to the act of textual interpretation, suggests that such necessary to relativise and historicise just those modes of experience
interpretation entails a fore-projection (Vorentwurf), associated with whose historical mutability he has obliterated. Here, then, is the
a series of ‘fore-meanings’ which ‘make up our fore-understand- starting-point for Jauss’s own ‘aesthetics of reception’,88 which com-
ing’.81 From this starting-point Gadamer arrives—to the anguish of bines Heideggerian resources such as the concept of Vorgriff (fore-
such critics as Habermas, Hirsch and Betti—at a radically relativist conception) with further concepts drawn from Russian Formalism.
position, entailing for instance the notion that ‘prejudice’ is a fruitful Jauss’s reception-aesthetics offers a framework for grasping the his-
hermeneutic instrument.82 torical mutability not just of meanings but also of meaning itself, a
Taken in the most general terms, Gadamer’s position vis-a-vis framework structured around the central concept of a ‘horizon of
his critics is surely unassailable, since the very aim of objectivity expectations’.89
proclaimed (in different ways) by Betti and Hirsch must itself But while in these respects Jauss has ably criticised and cre-
entail an interpretative fore-projection (Vorentwurf), as must atively adapted Gadamer’s approach, he too is confined within
the critical-theoretical aim of Habermas. But my concern is not the Vorhabe of textuality itself—and with equally ironic results.
with those debates but rather with the limits of Gadamer’s It is not just that the objects of ‘reception’ are precisely canoni-
own framework. We can approach this issue by observing that cal texts (usually depicted by Jauss within the older idiom of
the concept of textuality outlined above could happily be re- ‘works’); more than this, Jauss’s very concept of ‘reception’ re-
phrased in the very Heideggerian language upon which Gad- peats and compounds the self-oblivion of the act of textualisa-
amer’s hermeneutics is based. On the present argument, tion. For in Jauss’s schema, as the word ‘reception’ itself
textuality is precisely a Vorhabe, a fore-having: it is a ‘mode of implies, the canonical works are always unproblematically pres-
apprehension’ which construes its object in a particular way, ent-and-available for-and-before the act of ‘reception’: that is,
assigning to that object a specific mode of being. And since her- ‘reception’ does not constitute those works, it merely and pre-
meneutics is specifically concerned with the study of canonical cisely receives them as pre-given objects. Thus Jauss’s choice of
texts—as Gadamer has repeatedly made clear—it follows that the term ‘reception’ is no accident, for ‘reception’ is the neces-
the Vorhabe of textuality is constitutive of hermeneutics.83 Yet sary cognate of his concept of the nature of the literary work it-
this is precisely what Gadamer’s analysis does not bring out. self. As he has explained:
Throughout his patient exposition of the nature, presuppositions
Literary works differ from purely historical documents precisely
and objectives of hermeneutics, he simply takes as given the exis-
because they do more than simply document a particular time,
tence of its objects.84 ‘Texts’ for Gadamer just are texts: their
and remain ‘speaking’ to the extent that they attempt to solve

79
Gadamer (1965), Gadamer (1976). A very interesting meditation on Gadamer’s hermeneutics is Bruns (1992).
80
Heidegger (1962), pp. 191–5, particularly p. 193. ‘Fore-structure’ translates the German term Vor-Struktur.
81
Gadamer (1965, pp. 250–2, 1975), pp. 265–8, quoted from p. 268. ‘Fore-meaning’ translates the German term Vormeinung; ‘fore-understanding’, the German Vorverständnis.
These Gadamerian terms overlap in various ways with those of Heidegger’s Being and Time (Heidegger 1962): thus Heidegger made extensive use of Entwurf, the basis of
Vorentwurf (p. 185n.), and he occasionally used Vormeinung (p. 192, where Macquarrie and Robinson translate this as ‘assumption’). I have not come across any discussion which
compares these respective clusters of concepts, apart from Dreyfus (1980), pp. 10–11; cf. below, at n.92.
82
Gadamer (1975, pp. 277–307, 1976), p. 9. For Gadamer’s critics see Bleicher (1980), and cf. Margolis (1993).
83
On the relation between Heidegger’s Vorhabe and Gadamer’s set of concepts see further below, at n.92.
84
See for instance Gadamer (1975), p. 537, where ‘the task of hermeneutics’ is specified as ‘the task of interpreting transmitted texts’ (and. cf. p. 295). As will emerge in due
course, the word ‘transmitted’ here performs a massive work of elision: cf. n.167 below. (The word used in the German original was überlieferten, which conveys both ‘transmitted’
and ‘traditional’: Gadamer [1965], pp. 508, 279.)
85
Gadamer (1975), pp. 285–90, particularly p. 288; cf. Bruns (1992), pp. 154–5.
86
Jauss (1982), pp. 30–1.
87
Ibid., passim, e.g. Chapter 3 (pp. 77–109). Jauss in turn is criticised by de Man (‘Introduction’, in ibid., pp. xxii–xxiv), on grounds which, though differently anchored
(specifically in the question of rhetoric) are compatible with the terms of Jauss’s critique of Gadamer; indeed de Man here convicts Jauss of just that unavowed classicism which
Jauss has detected in Gadamer. Cf. below, at n.91.
88
As distinct from a more ‘traditional’ or conventional ‘aesthetics of representation’ (ibid., pp. 18–19, 40).
89
Ibid., pp. 22, 94 and passim (Vorgriff); 22–34 and passim (horizon of expectations); 16–19, 32–3, 41, 72 (Russian Formalism).
Author's personal copy

A. Wilson / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 43 (2012) 341–358 349

problems of form or content, and so extend far beyond the Bennett positioned his own approach to ‘texts’ by means of a
silent relics of the past.90 double difference—demarcating his conception first from post-
structuralism, then from traditional Marxist literary criticism. It
With this formulation (which notably invokes the figure of the writ-
was in the latter context that the shape of his argument began to
ten-as-speaking), Jauss has elegantly concealed all that goes to con-
emerge. After semi-aligning himself with Ernesto Laclau’s post-
stitute a text, a canonical work. By attributing its present availability
modernist version of Marxism,97 Bennett mounted a telling set of
to its verbal content, he has silently erased the material premise of
arguments against what he described as the implicit assumption of
that availability, namely the act of republication. And in an identical
traditional Marxist criticism, namely:98
gesture, he has assigned its literary status to the work itself, thereby
obliterating the existential premise of that status, namely the the assumption . . . that the relations between literary texts, other
apprehension of the reader or critic. Thus Jauss himself has repro- ideological phenomena and broader social and political pro-
duced, on another plane, the very timelessness for which he has cesses can be determined . . . by referring such texts to the condi-
rightly criticised Gadamer.91 tions of production obtaining at the moment of their origin.
In short, the hermeneutic conceptions of Gadamer and of Jauss
Against that assumption he made the following pivotal statement of
obey and display a single, shared limit. On the one hand, each of
principle (with my emphasis added):
them has elegantly demonstrated the importance of hermeneutic
‘fore-projections’, of the interpretative ‘fore-understanding’. On To the contrary, the actual and variable functioning of texts in
the other hand, neither of them has captured the more fundamen- history can only be understood if account is taken of the ways
tal moment of the hermeneutic ‘fore-structure’, namely its fore- in which such originary relations may be modified through
having or Vorhabe—that is, the prior apprehension of textuality it- the operation of subsequent determinations—institutional and
self. For Heidegger’s concept of Vorhabe, which pertains to the discursive—which may retrospectively cancel out, modify or
apprehended being of the apprehended object, has no equivalent overdetermine those which marked the originating conditions
in the conceptions of either Gadamer or Jauss.92 Rather, the terms of a text’s production.
used by Gadamer and Jauss are concerned not with the apprehended
The meanings of texts, then—their ‘actual and variable functioning...
being of the apprehended object but with the subsidiary domain of
in history ‘—are produced historically, and therefore mutably, by
its apprehended meaning.93 Thus the conceptual net deployed by
‘subsequent determinations’. But the texts themselves are produced
Gadamer and by Jauss captures no more and no less than what it
under certain earlier, ‘originating conditions’. That is, Bennett
is designed to capture: it grasps the constructed nature of textual
stripped away the constitutive importance of ‘the moment of their
interpretations, but necessarily elides the constructed nature of tex-
origin’ at the level of meaning, while retaining that posited moment
tuality itself, that is, the fact that textuality is a fore-having, a Vorha-
at the level of the objects themselves. The concept of ‘the originat-
be. This boundary of their achievement stems precisely from the fact
ing conditions of a text’s production’ proclaimed that textuality in-
that Gadamer and Jauss themselves are anchored in this very fore-
heres in the object as an essential and irreducible property acquired
having, which arises from their grounding in the hermeneutic tradi-
at the moment of its birth.
tion. The fact that textuality is a construal is simply invisible both for
This double move comprised the very foundation of Bennett’s
Gadamer and for Jauss: forming as it does the very precondition of
argument. On the one hand, at many points his exposition brought
their field, textuality is necessarily taken as a given.94 This displays
out precisely the present Proposition 1, that is, the fact that the
precisely that self-oblivion to which my third proposition refers.95
quality of being a text is assigned to the object rather than inhering
The same oblivion is equally apparent, and perhaps more poi-
in it. On the other hand, in every case Bennett instantly recoiled
gnant, in the very different perspective of Tony Bennett, as
from this insight, restoring the quality of textuality to the ‘texts’
developed in his appositely-titled essay ‘Texts in history’, pub-
themselves. This can be illustrated through Bennett’s account of
lished in 1987.96 Here Bennett went to the very brink of capturing
his own central, and very fruitful, concept—the concept of a
the constructed nature of textuality, only to withdraw at the last
‘reading formation’, which can perhaps be seen as the more active
moment.

90
Ibid., p. 69.
91
Cf., from a different and technical angle, de Man’s criticism of Jauss (n.87 above).
92
Heidegger (1962), pp. 199, 276, 279, 313, 337, 364, 370, 424 (though for an important qualification see n.94 below). It will be recalled that in Heidegger’s terms, Vorhabe
comprised one of the three aspects or moments of the Vor-Struktur of understanding (above, at n.80); on the other two aspects (Vorsicht and Vorgriff) cf. the next note. Gadamer’s
elision of Vorhabe has been observed by Dreyfus (1980, pp. 10-11), who however glosses Vorhabe in a different way from that suggested here: cf. also Dreyfus (1991), pp. 199–202.
93
In Heidegger’s account, apprehended-meaning was the principal concern of the other two aspects of the Vor-Struktur of understanding, namely Vorsicht (fore-seeing) and
Vorgriff (fore-conception): see for instance ibid., pp. 200, 358–9. However, to complicate the picture, these occasionally touched upon apprehended-being (see particularly p.
275)—and for a converse and more serious complication, see the next note.
94
This discussion has implicitly presented Heidegger’s own treatment as exempt from these limitations; but this picture, while rhetorically convenient here, is not strictly
accurate. For in the course of the very passage in which Heidegger defined the Vor-Struktur of understanding in the first place, he implied that his account pertained specifically to
textual interpretation: Heidegger (1962), pp. 191–2, at p. 192. If this were taken literally, it would undermine the use to which Vorhabe was subsequently put throughout Being
and Time; and it would proclaim that Vorhabe, too, as well as Vorsicht and Vorgriff, pertains to apprehended-meaning rather than to apprehended-being (cf. the previous two
notes). Thus it seems that this particular remark of Heidegger’s has to be interpreted as a slip on his part—a slip which took the being of the text for granted in precisely the same
way as was to be done by Gadamer, by Jauss, and subsequently (cf. the next note) by de Man.
95
A similar elision is to be found in Paul de Man’s brief discussion of Heidegger’s conception: de Man (1983), pp. 29–31, particularly p. 30. In that passage, Vorhabe (misprinted
as Forhabe) is first equated with ‘fore-structure’ (which is technically inaccurate) and is then glossed as ‘foreknowledge’ (which assimilates Vorhabe to Vorsicht and Vorgriff).
Further, it is suggested that ‘for the interpreter of a poetic text, this foreknowledge is the text itself’, and ‘the text itself’ is seen as ‘what was already there’ before the act of
interpretation. The effect of these moves is to turn the bearing of Vorhabe from apprehended-being to apprehended-meaning, and relatedly to elide yet again the fact that
textuality is an apprehension.
96
Bennett (1987), pp. 63–81; cf. to similar effect Bennett (1990).
97
For a helpful discussion of the work of Laclau and his collaborator Chantal Mouffe, see Curry (1993).
98
Bennett (1987), p. 69. This point of Bennett’s corresponds to McGann’s critique of ‘final authorial intention’ (n.68 above). McGann’s target is the ‘New Criticism’, which saw
authorial production as individual, whereas Bennett’s target is Marxist criticism of the type exemplified by Lukacs, which saw authorial production as social. But McGann and
Bennett are united—rightly, from the present point of view—in drawing attention to what has intervened between the past act of authoring, however construed, and the present
act of reading. Thus Bennett’s ‘reading formations’, discussed below, have much in common with McGann’s ‘secondary moments of textual production and reproduction’, for
which see McGann (1985c). However, see n.103 below.
Author's personal copy

350 A. Wilson / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 43 (2012) 341–358

and processual analogue of Jauss’s ‘horizon of expectations’. Ben- clearer indication of the force of Proposition 3 is difficult to
nett’s exposition of the ‘reading formation’ began as follows (again imagine.
with my emphases):99
. . . I want to suggest that the proper object for Marxist literary 5. Canons, traditions, disciplines
theory consists not in the study of texts but in the study of read-
ing formations. By a reading formation, I mean a set of discursive The attribute of textuality is materialised, according to Proposi-
and inter-textual determinations which organize and animate tion 5, in the form of canonical texts. Such texts are closely and
the practice of reading, connecting texts and readers in specific reciprocally tied to traditions: each tradition creates its own canon
relations to one another in constituting readers as reading sub- of classic texts, while conversely the canon justifies the tradition,
jects of particular types and texts as objects-to-be-read in partic- giving it reality and cultural weight. Correspondingly, tradition
ular ways. This entails arguing that texts have and can have no gives solidity to textuality, making it very difficult to detach any gi-
existence independently of such reading formations, that there is ven piece of writing from the textuality which has been assigned to
no place independent of, anterior to or above the varying reading it. The canon intensifies this, for each individual ‘text’ is so to speak
formations through which their historical life is variously modu- tethered to all the others in the canon: their textualities all support
lated, within which texts can be constituted as objects of knowl- each other. The strongest form that this takes is what we might call
edge. Texts exist only as always-already organised or activated to the canonical chain: a historical sequence of texts, together com-
be read in certain ways just as readers exist as always-already prising a movement of some sort—perhaps of progress, perhaps a
activated to read in certain ways . . . series of repetitions, or perhaps both—which confers the sem-
blance of historical continuity.106
Almost everything that Bennett wrote here—particularly the clause I Whenever we contemplate a canonical chain, it appears as if the
have emphasized—is entirely consonant with the present argu- textuality of its constituent elements is an unarguable and self-
ment.100 Yet he immediately continued (once more with my constituted fact. Each author in the canonical tradition typically re-
emphases): fers to her or his predecessors, either explicitly (as in non-fictional
The consequence of this so far as Marxism is concerned . . . is traditions) or implicitly (in a developing genre of imaginative liter-
that it should seek to detach texts from socially dominant read- ature); these self-affirmed filiations seemingly confirm the conti-
ing formations and to install them in new ones.101 nuity of the tradition, the objective existence of its canon, the
mutual tethering of the various canonical texts, and the reality of
The grammar of this sentence betrays the underlying assump- their several textualities. In these circumstances it may seem per-
tion that texts are in fact conceived here as givens: in a seeming verse to argue, as I am doing here, that textuality is assigned by our
paradox, textuality itself is not a product of reading formations, own act of interpretation. This calls for two comments, concerning
since ‘texts’ remain ‘texts’ before, during and after the operations firstly the textuality of the individual texts and secondly the reality
of ‘detaching’ and ‘installing’ them. A close reading of the remain- and integrity of the tradition as a whole.
der of Bennett’s essay reveals that this assumption pervaded its en- In the first place, textuality can indeed be a real historical qual-
tire argument.102 Correlatively, and strangely enough for a Marxist, ity, insofar as a past tradition itself endowed certain objects with
Bennett construed the constitution of ‘texts’ as a series of reading that quality: but in every case, that textuality had its origin not
processes; his account made no mention of such material activities in the objects themselves but rather in the acts of appropriation
as commissioning, writing, dedicating, subscribing, editing, publish- performed by such traditions. The writings of Aristotle would be
ing, printing, buying and selling.103 so many meaningless marks on old pieces of paper or parchment,
Bennett’s position can be summed up as follows. That which is were it not for the actions of (for instance) the medieval schoolmen
historically mutable, and is accordingly the object of both inquiry who conferred on those writings the quality of textuality. Such acts
and intervention, is what-kind-of-text a text is.104 But the ‘fact’ that of appropriation embrace both physical preservation and existen-
the text is a text is an attribute which inheres within it, a property tial survival, or in Heidegger’s terminology, both Vorhandenheit
which was conferred at birth and which the text will carry for ever (presence-at-hand) and Zuhandenheit (readiness-to-hand)—reveal-
afterwards.105 In short, despite all that Bennett has argued about ing, incidentally, that these are connected.107 The Vorhandenheit of
the constitution of texts through ‘reading formations’, and despite a text, that is to say its physical availability, requires its transcription
his very title, ‘Texts in history’, it emerges that textuality is ahistor- and publication; this is precisely what is involved in canonisation. Its
ical—or perhaps it would be more accurate to say atemporal. A Zuhandenheit, that is, its imbrication with present human activities,

99
Bennett (1987), pp. 70–1.
100
The ‘almost’ arises from the way that the word ‘texts’ was used in the second quoted sentence (this particular usage is ambiguous in this respect), and from the word
‘modulated’ towards the end of the quoted passage (the present argument entails replacing this by the word ‘constituted’). In addition, the definition of a ‘reading formation’ as ‘a
set of discursive and inter-textual determinations’ might be taken to suggest that the social is itself merely discursive and textual; such a position (which was probably not
Bennett’s, but which his definition did not preclude) would differ from that underlying the present argument.
101
Ibid., p. 71 (rendering ‘consequences’ into the singular). The omission in this quotation is Bennett’s discussion of Marxist theory, as distinct from Marxist criticism. For the sake
of convenience and clarity, I have focused on Bennett’s discussion of criticism; but his remarks about theory were entirely of a piece. The concern of theory, he observed here, is ‘to
analyse the determinations which are operative in the processes whereby meanings are produced in relation to textual phenomena’. This displays precisely the problem to which
I am drawing attention: ‘meanings are produced’, but ‘textual phenomena’ are givens or premises—in effect, pre-existent raw materials to which meanings are assigned.
102
See for instance ibid., pp. 75–6, where in the very act of arguing against ‘the concept of the ‘‘text itself’’‘, Bennett unwittingly invoked that very concept; also pp. 72, 74–5.
103
Admittedly, Bennett wrote at one point that reading formations have the effect of ‘shaping’ a text ‘in the historically concrete forms in which it is available as a text-to-be-
read’, and a little later that ‘texts are material phenomena’ (ibid., pp. 72, 75). Yet if this was meant to allude to such processes as physical canonisation, it is remarkable that this
was nowhere stated in the essay. The ironic result is that Bennett emerges as less ‘Marxist’ than McGann; for McGann’s ‘secondary moments of textual production and
reproduction’ (see n.98 above) refer precisely to the physical production of texts in their material form as books, whereas Bennett’s ‘reading formations’ pertain in effect to the
consumption of these material objects.
104
‘Inquiry’ and ‘intervention’ refer to Bennett’s categories of theory and criticism respectively: cf. n.101 above.
105
This structure is exhibited in less explicit form by many other formulations, for instance those of LaCapra (1980, p. 261), Fish (above, at n.70), Heidegger and de Man (nn.94-5
above).
106
Note that Foucault’s ‘archaeology’ (Foucault, 1972), while breaking such continuities, did not challenge textuality; on the contrary, texts were precisely its raw material. Cf.
further n.167 below.
107
Heidegger (1962), pp. 102–7.
Author's personal copy

A. Wilson / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 43 (2012) 341–358 351

necessarily entails an act of appropriation, a putting-to-use in what ‘Boyle’—identities which had been stable for about two centuries;115
is always a new context—of which the Thomist appropriation of Aris- it also puts in question the identities of the respective canons
totle offers a striking example.108 But it is equally intrinsic to such themselves.
appropriation that it is self-oblivious: the textuality that it confers To summarise: At first glance, textuality appears to inhere in
on an object is projected into that object, and is seen as inhering the elements which comprise canonical chains. Yet the very solid-
therein. And to the extent that this really happens, textuality is in- ity of this appearance arises precisely from the fact that the indi-
deed real.109 Thus Aristotle-for-the-schoolmen (to continue with this vidual ‘texts’ are viewed in their preassigned places as links in
example), although entirely virtual and textual, was nevertheless a the canonical chain. And the canonical chain is itself a retrospec-
very real part of the medieval cultural world. Seen from our own tive construct which performs some specific cultural work.
day, such a case as Aristotle-for-the-schoolmen may be described, The phenomenon of canons-and-traditions leads us to the asso-
adapting Oakeshott’s language, as a former practical past.110 Any such ciated theme of disciplines. For the academic discipline is precisely
former practical past was an aspect of what is now the historical the modern embodiment of such traditions; and it is specifically
past, that is, the past which has passed. And in that historical past for a discipline that a canon has reality. Now while every discipline
the given former practical past was as real as life itself. constructs for itself a canonical lineage, there are certain disci-
Secondly, the apparent integrity of the canonical chain is in fact plines whose very existence consists in the interpretation of a tex-
conferred retrospectively, selectively, and to a degree arbitrarily. tual canon: most notably literary criticism, hermeneutics, and the
The continuity of the chain, the definition of what are to count as history of ideas. These disciplines, therefore—the hermeneutico-
its constituent ‘links’, the closure which seals these ‘links’ into their canonical disciplines, as we may call them—take texts in their tex-
place within the chain—all these are, necessarily, retrospective tuality as their very objects; and this has several consequences
constructs. One indication of this arbitrary and retrospective char- which are germane to my theme.
acter of canonical chains is the fact that despite their durability, First, it is intelligible that (as we saw at the outset) it was from
canons turn out to be historically mutable. This is familiar enough just these disciplinary sites, especially from literary criticism, that
with respect to the literary canon, and indeed is unsurprising in the contemporary figure of the text arose. For these disciplines de-
that context, in view of such considerations as the politics of gen- ploy the very mode of apprehension which is embodied in that fig-
der, changes in taste, and the shifting institutional setting of liter- ure. Their material consists of canonical texts; their object is the
ary criticism.111 So too the question as to what comprises ‘the’ verbal content of these texts; and they apprehend that object as
Western philosophical canon is a repeatedly-contested issue, (in the words of Proposition 4) ‘the actual presence of the past’.
marked for instance by pronounced divisions between different na- This constitution of the textual object, then, comprises what can
tional cultures.112 Further, the very distinction between ‘literary’ and be called the hermeneutico-canonical perspective—that is, in Heideg-
‘philosophical’ canons is proving increasingly difficult to sustain.113 ger’s language, the interpretative fore-having (Vorhabe) which
But the point has a still wider relevance, as can be illustrated by con- characterizes the hermeneutico-canonical disciplines. The figure
sidering some of the implications of Shapin and Schaffer’s seminal of the text is neither more nor less than the condensation and con-
Leviathan and the Air-Pump.114 Until that book appeared in 1985, gealment of this perspective.116 And the wider application of that
the canonised ‘Hobbes’ was a major figure in the ‘history of political figure, first as the designation of the written and then to denote
thought’, but played no part in the ‘history of science’; while the can- ‘any cultural object of investigation’,117 is the projection of the her-
onised ‘Boyle’ was prominent in the ‘history of science’, but absent meneutico-canonical perspective onto the domain of the real.118
from the ‘history of political thought’. These two canonised figures Second, while all of these disciplines are in some measure—
were blissfully ignorant of each other’s existence—though neither some of them in considerable measure—concerned with the past,
of them suffered from this solitude, for each had his own allies their focus is specifically upon (in Oakeshott’s formulation) the
and enemies, his own canonical companions in love and hate. But ‘practical past’, that is, the past that is present. The contrast, of
Shapin and Schaffer entirely reconstructed these canonical relations, course, is with the discipline of history, Geschichte, whose domi-
and this in a twofold way. Not only did they position Thomas Hobbes nant orientation is towards the ‘historical past’, the past that has
and Robert Boyle together, through a reconstruction of their active passed. This disparity is by no means absolute, for it can be and
and heated exchanges in the 1660s. More than this, Leviathan and is elided in many ways: for instance, some historians are in fact ori-
the Air-Pump also depicted a Hobbes and a Boyle who for all their ented to the ‘practical past’;119 some species of literary criticism are
deep disagreements shared one premise which divided both of them radically historicist; and the practical past can itself be apprehended
from their respective subsequent canonisations: namely that ‘politi- along a variety of different lines, for instance stressing its chronolog-
cal’ and ‘natural’ philosophies were conjoined at their very heart and ical ordering to a greater or lesser degree.120 Further, as we are about
basis. This not only shakes the canonical identities of ‘Hobbes’ and to see, the tension between the practical past and the historical past

108
Some further, modern examples emerge in Watson (1993), Livingston (1993), and associated papers in the Journal of the History of Philosophy 31. This exchange, especially
Watson’s paper, beautifully brings out the selective and reconstructive nature of such ‘historical’ appropriations. Cf. above, at n.60.
109
This is precisely analogous to the fetishistic character of commodities as construed by Marx. Commodities can only be commodities by being assigned an objective quality;
they do indeed possess this quality; but they possess it precisely through the self-oblivion of the very act which assigns it to them.
110
Oakeshott (1983, pp. 38–9) gives the example of Livy-for-Machiavelli, though without distinguishing this as a former (rather than present) practical past.
111
See for instance, from a now substantial literature, Kermode (1983), Eagleton (1984), Spender (1986), McCrea (1990), Guillory (1993); and, for a counterblast to Guillory,
Bloom (1994).
112
See Margolis (1993) and also associated essays in The Monist 76 (1993), pp. 421–93.
113
See for instance Ricoeur (1984-88), Cascardi (ed.) (1987), Gadamer (1975), Bruns (1992); and the works cited in n.27 above.
114
Shapin & Schaffer (1985).
115
Simon Schaffer tells me that the latest instance he could discover of Boyle and Hobbes being coupled together was in the 1760s. Their identities as canonical figures arose
from the publication of their collected works, dating from the 1750s-’70s and the 1820s-’40s respectively.
116
Cf. n.16 above.
117
Above, at n.7.
118
Barthes, however, presented this in very different terms, as the realisation of a new interdisciplinarity: Barthes (1971, pp. 69–70, 1977), pp. 155–6.
119
For example Lowenthal (n.64 above).
120
Thus Bloom (1994), while specifically concerned with the past, deliberately eschews a chronological organization, placing Shakespeare before Chaucer and Dante. Notice that
this move, which would be meaningless with reference to the historical past, makes perfect sense as a way of treating the practical past.
Author's personal copy

352 A. Wilson / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 43 (2012) 341–358

as objects of study is expressed in various ways, according to its dis- historical knowledge.126 And just as this opposition to Rankean
ciplinary sites. Nevertheless this distinction captures the fundamen- Geschichte stretched back from Dilthey to Droysen, so too it has
tal axis of difference between history on the one hand and the extended forwards from Dilthey to Gadamer and Jauss.127 This
hermeneutico-canonical disciplines on the other. particular disciplinary gulf therefore merits special attention, as
Third, it is precisely at the intersection between hermeneuti- the site where the tension between the practical past and the
co-canonical and historical orientations, and between the practi- historical past as objects of study has become most manifest.
cal past and the historical past as objects of study, that the The hermeneutic critique of historiography is threefold. In the
historiography of science is situated.121 For although this disci- first place, history characteristically posits and perpetuates a rup-
pline has largely broken the bounds of the textual focus with ture between past and present, whereas the concern of hermeneu-
which it began, so that it now takes in such themes as institutions tics is to bridge between them. As Droysen put it, in a remark
and practices, laboratories and experiments, networks and inter- which Jauss has quoted with approval:
ests, it nevertheless retains an orientation to a textual canon.
That which was, does not interest us because it was, but
The canon may expand to include, for example, Newton’s alchem-
because in a certain sense it still is, in that it is still effective
ical and scriptural studies, yet it retains a stable core in the Prin-
because it stands in the total context of things which we call
cipia and the Optics; to no small extent we read (say) Darwin’s
the historical, i.e., moral world, the moral cosmos.128
notebooks in order to illuminate (say) The Origin of Species; and
while we can now see Galileo the courtier, we have by no means One might gloss this as saying that the historical past has to be
forgotten—nor should we—Galileo the author.122 Hence the fact assimilated to the practical past in order to be real. Second,
that even such a contextualist, revisionist and practice-oriented and relatedly, historiography only seeks to attain an Erklarung,
work as Leviathan and the Air-Pump is concerned not only with that is, a detached knowledge of the past, whereas the form of
(to quote its subtitle) the experimental life but also with the canon- knowledge which hermeneutics seeks is Verstehen, an under-
ical authors Hobbes and Boyle. Hence too the fact that Latour’s Sci- standing which comprises an encounter of mind with mind
ence in Action is framed within the rhetorical analysis of scientific through what are conceived as the products of mind. Third,
writings, conceived precisely as texts; or again the fact that Jar- spokesmen for hermeneutics have repeatedly made magisterial
dine’s The Scenes of Inquiry takes Gadamer’s hermeneutics as a claims to the effect that hermeneutics provides the necessary
central point of reference.123 In short, although the historiography foundation for any historical method.129 Gadamer himself, true
of science is no longer inscribed within the orbit of canonicity (as both to his own tradition and to his own originality, has repeated
it originally was, for instance with Whewell),124 canonicity is ines- this argument in a particularly interesting form,130 and so in his
capably inscribed within the historiography of science. The reason turn has Jauss.131 It is this foundational claim which is especially
for this has been well put by Shapin: the discipline ‘as it has been, significant; for whereas the other aspects of the hermeneutic cri-
presently is, and likely will remain’ derives its identity and its dis- tique express what is ultimately a matter of preference, this claim
cursive authority from its focus upon such canonical figures as consigns Geschichte to a subordinate place and installs Hermeneu-
Newton, apprehended specifically and selectively as contributors- tik as the master-discipline. The basis of this argument can be
to-the-tradition-of-science.125 That is to say, the discipline is irre- summarised as follows. Hermeneutics is by definition that ‘science
ducibly anchored in the study of specific traditions and of their of interpretation’ which studies what is entailed in the very act of
canonical achievements—achievements which are for the most interpretation: namely a reciprocal transaction between the inter-
part embodied precisely in canonical texts. What is perhaps preter and the object of interpretation, a transaction which neces-
remarkable about the historiography of science is that it manages sarily engages the present being and situation of the interpreter as
to combine hermeneutico-canonical and historical orientations in one of the terms of this exchange. And historical knowledge rests
a more or less peaceful coexistence. precisely upon interpretation and is grounded in the specific posi-
Finally, and in sharp contrast, there is one particular herme- tion of the interpreter, that is to say in the historian’s situation in
neutico-canonical discipline which has actually constituted itself the present. In short, historical knowledge is posited upon just
in explicit opposition to the discipline of history: namely Herme- that act (the act of interpretation) and just that encounter
neutik (hermeneutics) itself. For it was specifically Geschichte (between the present and the past) of which hermeneutics is
(that is, history, histoire, storia) which Dilthey constructed as the systematic study; and thus Geschichte rests upon Hermeneutik.
the Other for his Hermeneutik. Indeed, at the level of substance Yet historians, particularly historians in the Anglophone tradi-
this antithesis began still earlier, with Droysen’s Historik of the tion, have remained singularly unmoved by these arguments; in-
1850s; for while Droysen was explicitly concerned with the deed, they have effectively ignored them.132 And to the extent
methods of Geschichte, he effectively conceived Geschichte as that they have sought a rationale for their own interpretative
Hermeneutik, in opposition to Ranke’s objectivist conception of practices at all, they have consistently tied themselves to the

121
It is this, as much as technical considerations, which accounts for the longstanding and persistent separation between the historiography of science and Geschichte at large. Cf.
Porter (1990), Jardine (1991), p. 130; Wilson (1993a), pp. 30–1.
122
Biagioli (1993).
123
Latour (1987), chap. 1 and passim; Jardine (1991), pp. 68–76.
124
Christie (1993), pp. 397–8. Cf. Cantor (1991), Laudan (1993).
125
Shapin (1992), p. 347. Shapin’s wider argument, that the figures of inner and outer are in practice inescapable for the historiography of science, points in the same direction.
126
Gadamer (1975), pp. 212–18, particularly pp. 216–18; White (1973), pp. 270–3; MacLean (1982), Schleier (1990), pp. pp. 112–16; Southard (1995).
127
The apparent exception is Paul Ricoeur, who treats Geschichte with far more respect: see particularly Ricoeur (1984-88), vols. i and iii. Accordingly, Ricoeur marginalises the
conflict between Geschichte and Hermeneutik, preferring to assimilate them to one another. But the effect of this elision is to leave the hermeneutic critique intact; moreover, as it
turns out, the terms on which Ricoeur assimilates the two favour Hermeneutik over Geschichte (see n.153 below).
128
J.G. Droysen, Historik, quoted in Jauss (1982), p. 59 (for citation see n.24, p. 202); MacLean (1982), p. 354 n.23.
129
See for instance Dilthey (1900), Heidegger (1962), p. 450; Ermarth (1978), pp. 245, 264; Gadamer (1976), pp. 11–12; Bleicher (1980).
130
Gadamer (1975), pp. 335–41: this argument culminates in positing ‘the text’ as ‘the universal’. The passage is considered by Hoy (1978), pp. 146–60.
131
Jauss (1982), chap. 2 (pp. 46–75).
132
For example, there is no mention of hermeneutics, nor of Droysen, Dilthey or Gadamer, in Tosh (1992). Hermeneutics was not discussed in Elton (1967), and received only a
brief and brutal dismissal in Elton (1991), pp. 29–30; see further n.157 below. Nevertheless it is significant that hermeneutics appeared on Elton’s map in 1991; cf. also Marwick
(1989), p. 289. This shift probably results from the assimilation of hermeneutics by the social sciences in the 1980s: see below, at n.136.
Author's personal copy

A. Wilson / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 43 (2012) 341–358 353

source-critical methods associated particularly with Ranke—who has from Hermeneutik. The same is suggested by the fact that the figures
served precisely as the central target for the hermeneutic critique.133 of ‘document’,140 ‘record’, ‘source’ and ‘evidence’, so ubiquitously de-
These two disciplinary traditions, then, are agreed only in taking ployed and so necessary for the historian’s task, nevertheless re-
Ranke as an emblematic figure, attaching opposite valuations to that main—like the very different figure of the text—untheorized. Thus
figure.134 The indifference of historians to the hermeneutic challenge the figure of the document and its kindred might well be interro-
works de facto to confound the hegemonic claims which have ema- gated along lines analogous to those followed here in examining
nated from hermeneutics; yet it has to be remarked that historians the figure of the text.
have yet to produce a theorised refutation of those claims.135 This On the other hand, against the hermeneutic critique it must be
dialogue of the deaf, curious enough in itself, becomes still more observed that a tradition that has yet to grasp the nature of its own
striking now that hermeneutics has—since about 1980—acquired a underlying Vorhabe141 is scarcely justified in ascribing to itself the
serious reception in the social sciences.136 founding status which it has claimed. Further, Hermeneutik in its
The radical disparity between these two perspectives becomes turn has more to learn from Geschichte than has yet been acknowl-
intelligible in the light of the understanding of textuality devel- edged. For the practical past, in its textualised form as in any other,
oped here, allied to Oakeshott’s distinction between the practical is a residue of the historical past, or in other words, the is that has
past and the historical past. As we have seen with respect to Gad- survived implies a was that has not; and it is Geschichte which sets
amer and Jauss, hermeneutics has concentrated on the study of itself the task of reconstructing that historical past, the past-
canonical texts, without however problematising their textuality. which-has-passed. Thus the very premise of that which Hermeneutik
Both the choice of this object and the failure to thematise that strives to know is that which Geschichte strives to know. One might
choice are bound up with the conception of knowledge which her- sum up this point, and the implications of this section as a whole, by
meneutics deploys, a conception radically different from that saying that it is precisely in canons and traditions that the historical
which animates historiography. For Hermeneutik, knowing is the past and the practical past are conjoined. What this might mean con-
knowing of meaning, which entails that the knower is in the pres- cretely—particularly for the historiography of science and medi-
ence of the known. The object of knowledge, then, can only be the cine—will emerge in the next and final section, where I shall
‘practical past’, the past which is present, for it is this and this alone examine more closely the antinomy between Hermeneutik and Ges-
which could have meaning, which could (as Droysen put it) ‘inter- chichte, as refracted through a specific and unique confrontation
est us’. For Geschichte, in contrast, knowing is the recovering of ac- from the fairly recent past.
tions and events, of that which occurred, that is, in Ranke’s phrase,
what actually happened, eigentlich gewesen.137 Here the object of 6. Hermeneutics versus history
knowledge is defined and circumscribed by the past tense of its verb
(happened, gewesen);138 the concern of Geschichte, then, is with the Although what I am calling the hermeneutic challenge has been
‘historical past’, the past that has passed. It is precisely for this rea- ignored by historians, it happens that there took place in 1985/
son that historians typically deploy such figures as ‘document’ and 1991 a contest in print which was concerned with the very themes
‘record’ (which invoke the historical past itself), or ‘source’ and ‘evi- of that challenge. One of the many ironies of this little battle was
dence’ (which invoke the act of discovering that past), rather than that neither of the combatants noticed that their differences pre-
the figure of the ‘text’ (which invokes the practical past as against cisely mirrored the longstanding gulf between Hermeneutik and
the historical past, the act of interpretation as distinct from the act Geschichte. Indeed, in this and other respects the exchange served
of discovering). chiefly to perpetuate and extend the mutual incomprehension of
What gives bite to the hermeneutic challenge is the fact that the the two approaches. Nevertheless it will be fruitful to examine that
very use of the past tense implies and yet conceals the figure of the exchange, both because its very aporiai illustrate what is at stake
present. Indeed, it might be said that the perennial disagreements here, and because it will lead us to a practical version of the ques-
of historians over the significance of the present in the knowing of tion at hand.
the past reflect a collective discomfort which is inherent in their The two participants in this micro-debate were Dominick LaCa-
enterprise.139 This aporetic quality of the figure of the present in his- pra, writing in 1985, and Geoffrey Elton, lecturing in 1990.142 Both
toriographic discourse indicates that Geschichte has much to learn protagonists were reiterating and extending arguments which they

133
Ermarth (1978), passim, e.g. pp. 58, 311; Gadamer (1975), passim, e.g. pp. 211, 262; Jauss (1982), p. 8. Some historians pledge allegiance to source-criticism (for instance Marc
Bloch, Kitson Clark, G.R. Elton, E.P. Thompson); others (for example, Herbert Butterfield, E.H. Carr, J.H. Hexter) eschew or marginalise it, treating the historian’s raw material as
‘facts’, ‘data’ or ‘records’ rather than as ‘sources’ or ‘evidence’; both groups have however ignored hermeneutics. For a survey of historians’ proclaimed approaches, see Wilson
(1993b).
134
Thus Ranke has far more citations than any other author in Tosh (1992). In Marwick (1989), Ranke has just one close rival as to citations—namely Marc Bloch, who was also an
enthusiast for source-criticism. See Bloch (1954), pp. 50–57, 66–75, 91–113.
135
So far as I am aware, only a few attempts have been made to connect the two traditions: one from a legal historian (Emilio Betti), two from adherents of hermeneutics
(Gadamer, Ricoeur) and one from a philosopher (Alex Callinicos). See Bleicher (1980), pp. 51–94, at pp. 83–4; Gadamer (1975), pp. 335–41 (cf. above, at n.130); Ricoeur (1965), pp.
21–40; Ricoeur (1981), chap. 11; Ricoeur (1984-88), vol. iii, pp. 304, 305–6 (and see further n.153 below); Callinicos (1995), pp. 88–90. At a less explicit level, however, two of the
seminal works of the Anglophone philosophy of history can be seen as sites of intersection between Hermeneutik and Geschichte: Bradley (1874) and Collingwood (1946).
136
However, cf. n.132 above. For hermeneutics and the social sciences see Bleicher (1980), Ricoeur (1981), Thompson (1981), Giddens (1984), pp. 327–34; Hekman (1986),
Habermas (1987), Outhwaite (1987), Heller (1989) and cf. Wilson (1993a), p. 55.
137
Cf. above, at n.57.
138
Cf. Christie (1987a), p. 9.
139
Some historians (amongst them the author of this paper) have depicted the historian’s position-in-the-present merely as an obstacle to understanding, which is at best a one-
sided treatment of the matter: see for instance Butterfield (1931), Wilson & Ashplant (1988), Elton (1991), p. 65. Others have striven to assign a positive role to the historian’s
present embeddedness, but the terms in which they have formulated this have been so varied and haphazard as to yield no coherent picture. Examples of such efforts include
Bloch’s invocation of the historian’s personal experience (discussed rather inconclusively by Oakeshott); Collingwood’s re-enactment doctrine (which has been demolished by
Ricoeur); Hexter’s concept of the historian’s ‘second record’; Carr’s dialogue-between-past-and-present (on which I have commented elsewhere) and his notion of selection. See
Bloch (1954), p. 44; Collingwood (1946), pp. 282–302; Hexter (1972), pp. 102–44; Carr (1964), Oakeshott (1983), pp. 68–9; Ricoeur (1984-88), vol. iii, pp. 144–7; Wilson (1993b),
p. 55 n.38.
140
The figure of the ‘document’ also has a different and technical use in ethnomethodology; but here I am referring only to its invocation in historiography.
141
See above, at n.83 onwards.
142
LaCapra (1985), pp. 136–8; Elton (1991), pp. 60–1.
Author's personal copy

354 A. Wilson / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 43 (2012) 341–358

had published before this time. Elton had first set out his approach to showed in detail with a penetrating critique of Ginzburg’s The Cheese
historical inference in his The Practice of History of 1967, and had and the Worms.151 Hence the ‘dialogical model of knowledge’ was
developed it further in subsequent books which appeared in 1970 necessary not only for intellectual history but even for the interpre-
and 1983.143 LaCapra, a generation younger than Elton, began to ad- tation of (as LaCapra put it) ‘documents in the narrow sense of the
vance his own methodological arguments in a paper of 1980, which word’.152 For he argued that documents themselves, in this ‘narrow’
was reprinted in 1982 (and which I have already had occasion to or realist sense, were in fact ‘texts’, and thus required a ‘dialogical’
cite). Initially LaCapra had not brought these ideas into juxtaposition encounter.153
with Elton; instead he had taken as his Other-figure Leopold von The counterposed figures of ‘documentary’ and ‘dialogical’
Ranke, thus unconsciously repeating a classical stroke of hermeneu- forms of knowledge, and the privileging of the latter, recapitulated
tic polemic.144 But in his History and Criticism of 1985 LaCapra took the standard themes of the hermeneutic critique. But LaCapra’s
the bold step of taking the living author Geoffrey Elton as his target. argument was distinctive in certain ways, not least in being
And it was to this sally that Elton responded during his Cook Lec- pitched against living figures such as Ginzburg and Elton. Notice
tures, delivered at Michigan in 1990 and printed in his Return to that LaCapra’s picture exemplified once more the present Proposi-
Essentials of 1991. tion 3, that is to say, the self-oblivion of the textual construal; for
While LaCapra’s own disciplinary anchoring was in ‘intellectual whereas LaCapra sometimes depicted the figure of the document as
history’, he positioned his approach with reference to literary crit- a construal (and indeed this was one of the major achievements of
icism—whence his title, History and Criticism.145 His target was his book), he consistently took the figure of the text as referring to a
what he called a ‘documentary model’ of historical knowledge; Elton real.154 It was precisely this asymmetrical treatment of the two fig-
served him—or rather, a fragment of Elton’s methodological writing ures which enabled LaCapra to mount his most radical claim: that
taken out of context served him—as an exemplar of this model.146 the ‘dialogical model’ is required even for attaining the purposes of
But even though his account of Elton’s approach was highly mislead- a ‘documentary’ historian such as Elton. On this view, the figure of
ing,147 LaCapra’s stance towards the ‘documentary model’ in general, the document is absorbed by the figure of the text—corresponding
and Elton’s version of it in particular, was by no means one of unre- of course to the claim that hermeneutics provides the foundation
mitting hostility. On the contrary, he was seeking to promote a ‘un- for historiography.
ion’ between ‘history and criticism’, and in line with this eirenic When Elton came to respond to LaCapra’s remarks, that is, in
purpose he acknowledged that the ‘documentary model of knowl- the course of his third and final Cook Lecture of 1990, he began
edge’ had its merits and was even necessary: ‘Indeed’, he explained, by subtly refiguring LaCapra’s argument, and indeed its very terms,
‘I would readily agree with many of [Elton’s] specific rules-of-thumb in such a way as to eliminate its more radical claims.155 (This recip-
for teaching and research.’148 Nevertheless LaCapra claimed that this rocated a move which LaCapra had already performed upon Elton’s
‘documentary model’ was deficient in three intertwined respects. In own previous writings.156) Elton’s paraphrase assigned a realist sig-
the first place, for all its virtues, the model was insufficient even for nificance to the figure of the document—thereby excising LaCapra’s
its own purposes, because it worked to deny in theory and to con- depiction of that figure as a construal, and burying his associated
strain in practice the irreducible role of the imagination in the con- suggestion that the ‘documentary model’ cannot even attain its
stitution of historical knowledge.149 Secondly, the documentary own purposes.157 And in a complementary move, Elton restricted
model was quite inadequate for the specific domain of ‘intellectual the reference of the figure of the text to canonical texts. The effect
history’, since the materials of the latter enterprise were not docu- of these strokes was to delimit the scope of LaCapra’s claims, con-
mentary in type. Rather, those materials—that is to say, canonical signing his argument to the particular sphere of the history-of-ideas
texts—required a different kind of reading, which LaCapra character- or ‘intellectual history’. This complex and potent rhetorical work was
ised as a ‘dialogical model of knowledge’.150 Thirdly, and completing all achieved by the following dense little summary:
this critical circle, the documentary model served in practice to li-
Dr. LaCapra . . . maintains that what I have said may apply to
cense an uncontrolled and uncritical use of sources, precisely by
documents but is of no relevance to the historian of ideas
ignoring the textual qualities of documents themselves—as LaCapra
who uses ‘texts’. What he calls my ‘model of knowledge’ he

143
Elton (1967), pp. 81–113, e.g. pp. 93, 100, 102, 103, 111; Elton (1970) pp. 73–111; Fogel and Elton (1983), pp. 91–5.
144
LaCapra (1980), p. 273 (1982 reprint, pp. 78–9); cf. above, at n.16.
145
Notice that both ‘intellectual history’ (or history-of-ideas) and literary criticism (in certain of its historicist forms) can be seen as Anglophone cognates of hermeneutics.
146
The book as a whole was not framed around Elton; rather, Elton was specifically invoked as the focus of its conclusion: LaCapra (1985), pp. 135ff.
147
In particular, LaCapra focused upon Elton’s claims for the achievements of ‘historical method’ (ibid., p. 135), referring only allusively to Elton’s account of the method itself (this
in the remark quoted immediately below, from p. 136). For some of the consequent ironic elisions see n.151 below.
148
Ibid., p. 136; and similarly p. 138. It was characteristic of the LaCapra-Elton exchange that LaCapra did not specify what any of these sites of agreement actually were. Notice
too the figure ‘rules-of-thumb’, which consigned Elton’s methodology to a sub-theoretical status.
149
Ibid., p. 18 and passim.
150
Ibid., p. 36 and onwards.
151
Ginzburg (1980), LaCapra (1985), pp. 45–69. Ironically, LaCapra’s critique of Ginzburg was entirely in keeping with Elton’s precepts: see for instance pp. 62–3. The same was
true of his criticisms of le Roy Ladurie and Chevalier (pp. 119, 125–6); on the former, cf. Elton (1991), p. 55.
152
LaCapra (1985), p. 38.
153
Ibid., pp. 38, 141; cf. also pp. 19–20, 126. Paul Ricoeur, too, assimilates the figure of the document to that of the text, though with the very different intent of glossing over the
conflict between Hermeneutik and Geschichte (cf. n.135 above). But this eirenic attempt (which proceeds by way of the linking concept of the trace) is unsuccessful, for Ricoeur
acknowledges that the alleged ‘equivalence’ between ‘a hermeneutics of texts and a hermeneutics of the historical past’ has to be heavily qualified: it is only ‘partial’, it applies
‘largely’ and ‘with all the necessary reservations’. Strikingly, these ‘reservations’ are left unspecified; thus a work which proceeds by an aporetic method leaves this particular
aporia unexamined. See Ricoeur (1983-85), vol. iii, pp. 401–2, 413; translation adapted from that in Ricoeur (1984-88), vol. iii, pp. 221–2, 229. (The fact that Ricoeur uses the
phrase ‘the historical past’ is fortuitous, for he does not discuss Oakeshott.)
154
In its concrete reference, nevertheless, the figure of the text had three different meanings in LaCapra (1985). The textual sometimes coincided with the verbal (pp. 21, 128);
usually it amounted to the quality of rhetorical efficacy (pp. 19–20, 38, 126, 141); and occasionally it denoted literary texts (p. 129 and n.6).
155
The three lectures, which broadly speaking comprised a riposte to discourse analysis and deconstruction, formed a tightly-constructed unity; amongst the themes I am
necessarily suppressing here is the pivotal role which the figure of LaCapra played in this larger and carefully-crafted structure.
156
Cf. n.147 above. Elton gained some polemical mileage by drawing attention to the fact that LaCapra had misrepresented his views, without of course noticing that he was
returning this favour.
157
Elton betrayed no awareness that LaCapra’s argument was akin to the hermeneutic critique of historiography: cf. n.132 above.
Author's personal copy

A. Wilson / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 43 (2012) 341–358 355

declares to be ‘necessary but not sufficient for historical We may take it that Elton’s formulation requires us to see Locke’s
research’, and it will not suffice ‘in a field such as intellectual Two Treatises as responding to (for instance) the conjunctures of
history’.158 the 1679-80 Exclusion Crisis in which they were written, and the
Revolution of 1688 which led to their publication.162 Translated into
Thus the LaCapra-depicted-by-Elton, far from claiming that the ‘dia-
this concrete case, then, Elton’s claim would be that the Two Treatises
logical model’ was required even for attaining the purposes of the
were generated by these specific historical contexts, and by Locke’s
‘documentary model’, had adopted a policy of semi-peaceful coexis-
particular insertion within those contexts (for instance, his own
tence—rendering unto Elton the things that were Elton’s, namely
political allegiance and discursive framework); and that it is this
document-based historiography. But even this displaced and di-
context-of-genesis into which the historian must first of all enquire.
luted rendering of LaCapra’s argument did not satisfy Elton himself,
But on the present argument, the Exclusion Crisis and the Revolution
who was unwilling to make the reciprocal gesture. On the contrary,
were only the beginning of the context-of-genesis of what we read
Elton now turned the tables on LaCapra: as Elton depicted the mat-
as Locke’s Two Treatises. For in fact we encounter the Two Treatises
ter, in a precise inversion of LaCapra’s argument, the figure of the
(or any other canonical work) specifically in the form of a text: that
‘source’—effectively equivalent to the figure of the document—ab-
is, the Two Treatises are profoundly enmeshed in textuality before
sorbs the figure of the text.
they reach us, and indeed it is only in that condition that they can
Elton achieved this delicate coup by reiterating and extending
‘reach us’ at all. More particularly, as James Tully has observed of
the methodological approach for which he had been arguing since
the Two Treatises:163
the late 1960s. Elton’s methodology comprised a document-genet-
ic version of source-criticism: under this rubric, as he had put it in It is now well known that Locke’s immediate audience received
1970, ‘the first question’ which historians ‘must ask of all evidence’ his work predominantly with silence and, when [they] noted
is: ‘why and by whom was this material produced?’.159 Elton now [it], with abuse. The first point at which it became an important
took the further step of portraying the ‘history of ideas’ as falling element in an English political movement was in the early nine-
within this rubric. In riposte to LaCapra, or rather, to his own refig- teenth century. Locke was read as the father of modern social-
uration of LaCapra, he asserted (with my emphases): ism . . . The second major wave of interpretation is the liberal
one, which can be said to have been securely established in
The error here lies first and foremost in the failure to realize
the 1930s . . .
that the sources used by the historian of ideas are like all other
historical sources inasmuch as they were produced in the past, Thus the virtual author whom we call ‘Locke’-the-political-theorist,
survive into the present, and require instructed analysis before embodied in the textuality of the Two Treatises, was constructed by
they can be understood and used . . . The specific techniques a complex intervening tradition whose most important moments
involved in understanding them may well be peculiar to them- began over a century after the death (1704) of the mortal being
selves, even as the techniques for correctly understanding pri- named John Locke. It is precisely as a result of this tradition that—
vate letters differ markedly from those needed to comprehend as our unreflective use of language revealingly puts it—‘we read
legal proceedings or archaeological finds. Yet the same basic Locke’ today, and that Locke’s Two Treatises are available for reading
rules—the questions how and why they came into existence—apply in the form of modern editions. The same applies, mutatis mutandis,
to them all equally.160 to the works of any and every canonical author.164
Hence the context-of-genesis of the Two Treatises—that which
In effect Elton thus mounted the novel claim that it is Geschichte
Elton’s formulation would require us to reconstruct—is not con-
which provides the foundation for Hermeneutik, rather than the
fined to 1679, to 1688, to Locke’s lifetime. Rather, that context-
other way around. On this view, his own methodology bridged
of-genesis necessarily includes the ‘context’ which generated their
the divide between the hermeneutico-canonical and historiographic
twentieth-century textuality. Thus to reconstruct the genesis of the
disciplines, in such a way as to install history as the dominant part-
Two Treatises would entail attending not only to the setting of
ner. Within the frame of Elton’s rhetoric, then, the creative synthe-
Locke’s actions but also to the entire intervening tradition which
sis for which LaCapra had been striving had been realised in an
has deposited the Two Treatises upon our own bookshelves. Fur-
entirely ironic form.
thermore, since this tradition by definition extends inclusively to
Now the concept of textuality developed here offers a different
the present day, this radically enlarged definition of ‘context’
perspective on Elton’s picture, and indeed upon the LaCapra-Elton
would also include a reflexive moment.165
exchange as a whole. In order to make this point it will help to have
Seen from this standpoint, Elton and LaCapra were in hidden
an example (for Elton, perhaps significantly, did not offer any); I
and ironic agreement; for each of them was suppressing just this
shall use Locke, who was mentioned earlier, and specifically ‘Locke’
point, though they achieved this shared effect in complementary
the political theorist, author of the Two Treatises of Government.161
ways. (a) By assimilating canonical texts to ‘sources’,166 by describ-

158
Elton (1991), pp. 59–60.
159
Elton (1970), p. 88; notice here the figure of ‘evidence’, implicitly construed as a real. On the relationship between Elton’s methodology and traditional source-criticism see
Wilson (1993b), pp. 301–11, particularly pp. 304, 309.
160
Elton (1991), p. 60. Significantly, Elton did not at this point invoke the one historian of ideas whose work he had endorsed, for a different polemical purpose, in his previous
lecture: Quentin Skinner. Had Elton cited Skinner here, he would have been faced with a series of embarrassments, for Skinner deploys the figure of the text, not the document or
source; he works to reconstruct contexts of utterance, not contexts of genesis; he has never aligned himself with Elton’s method; and on the contrary, his approach rests upon the
speech-act theory of J. L. Austin, whereas Elton consistently resisted any recourse to present theories in the interpretation of past materials. Hence, perhaps, the fact that soon
after praising Skinner’s substantive work, Elton had subtly distanced himself from Skinner’s theorizing—as if in preparation for the move in Lecture 3 which I am considering. See
Elton (1991), pp. 37–8, 42, 63, 65; Austin (1962), Skinner (1969), Skinner (1988).
161
See above, at n.45.
162
Laslett (1960).
163
Tully (1993), pp. 96–7. Tully goes on to depict two further and subsequent ‘Whig’ interpretations, as well as a fifth school to which his own work belongs; the latter is
associated with Skinner’s approach, on which cf. n.160 above.
164
Hobbes and Boyle offer further examples: cf. n.115 above.
165
All this converges with Gadamer—particularly his stress on tradition and on the hermeneutic Vorentwurf—but from a non-Gadamerian angle; cf. Gadamer (1975), Gadamer
(1976).
166
As I too have done, in a different way: Wilson (1993b), p. 327 n.14.
Author's personal copy

356 A. Wilson / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 43 (2012) 341–358

ing these as ‘produced in the past’, and by means of the deceptively the history of canonisation itself. Such a historiography, which
simple phrase ‘survive into the present’,167 Elton assigned the gene- has already been undertaken for the English literary canon,172
sis of such texts solely to their contexts of first origin.168 Relatedly, would necessarily employ the methods of both Hermeneutik and Ges-
he treated the figure of the source in turn as a natural kind—eliding chichte. And while grounded in particular cases, it could also extend
the role of the historian in constituting remains-of-the-past as to the phenomenon of textuality as such, reflexively embracing the
sources, and thereby fixing the figure of the source in its requisite history of the canonically-based disciplines themselves.173 An in-
temporal locus, that is, within the past-to-be-studied. The result of quiry of this kind would pose anew, concretely and historically,
these moves was to suppress the distinctive character of the canon- the question: what is a text?
ical text, and so to erase the role of intervening tradition—which is
precisely what constitutes canonical texts, assigning them the very
Acknowledgments
property of textuality. (b) In contrast, LaCapra rightly distinguished
between the figure of the text and the figure of the document; and
For help with this paper I thank Marina Benjamin, Mike Beaney,
indeed he went still further, by noticing from time to time that the
John Forrester, Richard Francks, Graeme Gooday, Mark Jenner,
figure of the document is itself a construal. Here, however, his ap-
Chris Kenny, Sharon Macdonald, Peter Millican, Gregory Radick, Si-
proach reached its limit, for he treated the figure of the text as a nat-
mon Schaffer, Jamie Stark, Roger White, and a reader for Studies in
ural kind—just as Elton treated the figure of the ‘source’. The effect of
History and Philosophy of Science. I am particularly indebted to John
this move was again to elide the historical origins of textuality; but
Christie, Marina Frasca Spada and Nick Jardine, for a wealth of ad-
LaCapra’s elision worked in the opposite direction to Elton’s. One
vice which has enriched the argument in many ways. All errors are
might say, drawing once more on Oakeshott’s conception, that Elton
my own responsibility.
had collapsed the practical past into the historical past, and that
LaCapra had performed the complementary manoeuvre.
It thus emerges that the very space which separates LaCapra’s References
conception from Elton’s—and more broadly, which divides her-
Austin, J. L. (1962). In J. O. Urmson (Ed.), How to do things with words. Oxford:
meneutics from historiography—holds out the prospect of unit-
Clarendon Press.
ing them, of comprising the ground upon which they might Banfield, A. (1985). Écriture, narration and the grammar of French. In J. Hawthorn
meet. For what we have just seen is that textuality, being a his- (Ed.), Narrative from Malory to motion pictures (pp. 1–22). London: Edward
torical product, can be taken as a historical explanandum. In the Arnold.
Barthes, R. (1968) La mort de l’auteur, reprinted in Barthes (1984), pp. 61–67;
history of science, this would entail reconstructing (for instance) transl. as The death of the author, in Barthes (1977), pp. 142–148.
those processes of transmutation which turned ‘the Honorable Barthes, R. (1971) De l’oeuvre au texte, reprinted in Barthes (1984), pp. 69–77;
Robert Boyle’ into ‘Boyle’, the not-so-honourable Thomas Hobbes transl. as From work to text, in Barthes (1977), pp. 155–164.
Barthes, R. (1977). Image music text (Transl. S. Heath). London: Fontana/Collins.
into ‘Hobbes’; which separated these two figures from each Barthes, R. (1984). Le bruissement de la langue. Paris: Éditions du Seuil.
other, assigned them new companions, installed them as mem- Benjamin, A. E., Cantor, G. N., & Christie, J. R. R. (Eds.). (1987). The figural and the
bers of distinct disciplinary families; in short, which conferred literal: Problems of language in the history of science and philosophy, 1630–1800.
Manchester: Manchester University Press.
upon them those mantles of canonical identity in which we Bennett, T. (1987). Texts in history: The determinations of readings and their texts.
encounter them today.169 The same applies in the allied field of In D. Attridge, G. Bennington, & R. Young (Eds.), Post-structuralism and the
the history of medicine, where canonisation also invites recon- question of history (pp. 63–81). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Bennett, T. (1990). Outside literature. London: Routledge.
struction. Consider for instance the figure of ‘Sydenham’, to be dis-
Biagioli, M. (1993). Galileo, courtier: The practice of science in the culture of absolutism.
tinguished of course from the bodily Thomas Sydenham who died Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
in 1689. The virtual author ‘Sydenham’, perhaps first constructed Biriotti, M., & Miller, N. (Eds.). (1993). What is an author? Manchester: Manchester
University Press.
by Herman Boerhaave,170 has a history of his own, a history which
Bleicher, J. (1980). Contemporary hermeneutics: Hermeneutics as method, philosophy
largely remains to be written. By the 1750s that history would al- and critique. London: Routledge.
ready take us not only to Boerhaave’s Leyden but also to Sauvag- Bloch, M. (1954). The historian’s craft (French original 1949) (Transl. P. Putnam).
es’s Montpellier, to the Edinburgh of Monro primus, to the Manchester: Manchester University Press.
Bloom, H. (1994). The Western Canon: The books and school of the ages. New York:
Lichfield and London of Drs Swan and Johnson, to Huxham’s Plym- Harcourt Brace.
outh, and doubtless to many other places besides.171 Yet this Booth, W. C. (1961). The rhetoric of fiction. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
would only be the beginning: we would have to traverse further Booth, W. C. (1979). Critical understanding: The powers and limits of pluralism.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
distances, crossing the threshold of la clinique and reaching the Booth, W. C. (1988). The company we keep: An ethics of fiction. Berkely: University of
two Sydenham Societies of nineteenth-century Britain, in order California Press.
to reconstruct that textualisation of ‘Sydenham’ which installed Bradley, F. H. (1874). The presuppositions of critical history. Oxford: Parker.
Brannigan, A. (1981). The social basis of scientific discovery. Cambridge: Cambridge
him in medical history’s pantheon, conferring the quality of time- University Press.
less presence which—paradoxically—makes him and his works an Brewer, J. G. (1973). The literature of geography: A guide to its organisation and use.
object of historical knowledge today. London: Clive Bingley.
Bruns, G. L. (1992). Hermeneutics ancient and modern. New Haven: Yale University
What we might envisage, then—for the history of science and
Press.
medicine just as for the history of ideas, for Boyle and for Syden- Burke, S. (1992). The death and return of the author: Criticism and subjectivity in
ham just as for Hobbes and for Locke—is the project of writing Barthes, Foucault and Derrida. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

167
Compare the use of ‘transmitted’ by Gadamer, or by his translators (n.84 above), which made the same elision but to a very different purpose. Yet another version of this
elision, again with its own distinctive rhetorical work to perform, was made by Foucault with respect to ‘the statement’ (l’énoncé), the basic unit of analysis for his ‘archaeology’.
Formulating the ‘survival in time’ of the statement as what he called its ‘remanence’, Foucault asserted that ‘remanence is of the nature of the statement’: see Foucault (1972), p.
124. This confirms, if confirmation were needed, that canonical texts were the materials for ‘archaeology’ (cf. n.106 above); note also that the figure of the énoncé assimilated the
written to the spoken.
168
Compare, ironically enough, Bennett’s ‘originating conditions of a text’s production’ (above, at n.98).
169
Cf. Jardine (1991), pp. 130–45, and see Graham et al. (eds.) (1983).
170
Cunningham (1990), pp. 40–66, at pp. 47–50.
171
See for example Lawrence (1985), p. 155; Cunningham (1989), Cunningham (1990), Martin (1990).
172
Cf. n.111 above.
173
This can be seen as a ‘longue-durée’ aspect of the ‘knowledge in transit’ programme, for which see Secord (2004).
Author's personal copy

A. Wilson / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 43 (2012) 341–358 357

Burke, S. (Ed.). (1995). Authorship: From Plato to the postmodern. Edinburgh: Genette, G. (1982). Figures of literary discourse (transl. A. Sheridan). New York:
Edinburgh University Press. Columbia University Press.
Butterfield, H. (1931). The Whig interpretation of history. London: Bell. Giddens, A. (1984). The constitution of society: Outline of the theory of structuration.
Callinicos, A. (1995). Theories and narratives: Reflections on the philosophy of history. Cambridge: Polity.
Cambridge: Polity Press. Ginzburg, C. (1980). The Cheese and the Worms: The cosmos of a sixteenth-century
Cantor, G. N. (1991). Between rationalism and romanticism: Whewell’s miller (Italian original 1976) (transl. J. and A. Tedeschi). Baltimore: Johns
historiography of the inductive sciences. In M. Fisch & S. Schaffer (Eds.), Hopkins University Press.
William Whewell: A composite portrait (pp. 67–86). Oxford: Clarendon Press. Gracia, J. J. E. (1990). Texts and their interpretation. Review of Metaphysics, 43,
Carr, E. H. (1964). What is history? Harmondsworth: Penguin (first published 1961). 495–542.
Carter, K. C. (2003). The rise of causal concepts of disease: Case histories. Aldershot: Gracia, J. J. E. (1994). Can there be texts without historical authors? American
Ashgate. Philosophical Quarterly, 81, 245–253.
Cascardi, A. J. (Ed.). (1987). Literature and the question of philosophy. Baltimore: Johns Graham, L., Lepenies, W., & Weingart, P. (Eds.) (1983), Functions and uses of
Hopkins University Press. disciplinary histories (Vol. vii). Dordrecht: Reidel (Sociology of the Sciences
Charnley, B., & Radick, G. (in press). Intellectual property, plant breeding and the Yearbook).
making of Mendelian genetics. In C. MacLeod, & G. Radick (Eds.), Owning and Guillory, J. (1993). Cultural capital: The problem of literary canon formation. Chicago:
disowning invention: Intellectual property and identity in the Technosciences in University of Chicago Press.
Britain, 1870–1930 (Studies in History and Philosophy of Science special issue). Gusdorf, G. (1988). Les Origines de l’herméneutique. Paris: Payot.
Christie, J. R. R. (1987a). Introduction: Rhetoric and writing in early modern Habermas, J. (1987). The philosophical discourse of modernity: Twelve lectures (transl.
philosophy and science. In Benjamin, et al. (Eds.) (1987), (pp. 1–9). F. Lawrence). Cambridge: Polity.
Christie, J. R. R. (1987b). Adam Smith’s metaphysics of language. In Benjamin, et al. Harari, J. V. (Ed.). (1980). Textual strategies: Perspectives in post-structuralist criticism.
(Eds.) (1987), (pp. 202–227). London: Methuen.
Christie, J. R. R. (1993). Aurora, Nemesis and Clio. British Journal of the History of Harris, I. (1994). The mind of John Locke. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Science, 26, 391–405. Heidegger, M. (1962) Being and Time (German original 1927), transl. J. Macquarrie
Collingwood, R. G. (1946). The idea of history. Oxford: Clarendon Press (cited from and E. Robinson (Oxford: Blackwell).
Oxford: Oxford University Press edition, 1961). Hekman, S. J. (1986). Hermeneutics and the sociology of knowledge. Cambridge:
Collingwood, R. G. (1993). In W. J. van der Dussen (Ed.), The idea of history (revised Polity.
edition, with Lectures 1926–1936). Oxford: Clarendon Press. Heller, A. (1989). From hermeneutics in social science toward a hermeneutics of
Cook, A. (1988). History/writing. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. social science. Theory and Society, 18, 291–322.
Culler, J. (1975). Structuralist poetics: Structuralism, linguistics and the study of Hexter, J. H. (1971a). Doing history. London: Allen and Unwin.
literature. London: Routledge. Hexter, J. H. (1972). The history primer. London: Allen Lane (first published 1971).
Cunningham, A. (1989). Thomas Sydenham: Epidemics, experiment and the Good Holland, N. N. (1975). Unity identity text self, PMLA 90, 813–22, reprinted in J. P.
Old Cause. In R. French & A. Wear (Eds.), The medical revolution of the seventeenth Tompkins (Ed.) (1980), Reader-response criticism from formalism to post-
century (pp. 164–190). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. structuralism (pp. 118–33). Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Cunningham, A. (1990). Medicine to calm the mind: Boerhaave’s medical system, Hoy, D. C. (1978). The critical circle: Literature, history and philosophical hermeneutics.
and why it was adopted in Edinburgh. In Cunningham, & French (Eds.) (1990), Berkely: University of California Press.
(pp. 40–66). Iser, W. (1978). The act of reading: A theory of aesthetic response. London: Routledge
Cunningham, A., & French, R. (Eds.). (1990). The medical enlightenment of the (German original 1976).
eighteenth century. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Jardine, N. (1991). The scenes of inquiry. Oxford: Clarendon.
Currie, G. (1990). The nature of fiction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Jauss, H. R. (1982). Toward an aesthetic of reception (transl. T. Bahti, from German
Curry, P. (1993). Towards a post-Marxist social history: Thompson, clark and essays published at various dates 1970–1980). Minneapolis: University of
beyond. In Wilson (Ed.) (1993), (pp. 158–200). Minnesota Press.
de Man, P. (1979). Allegories of reading: Figural language in Rousseau, Nietzsche, Rilke Keefer, D. (1995). Reports of the death of the author. Philosophy and Literature, 19,
and Proust. New Haven: Yale University Press. 78–84.
de Man, P. (1983). Blindness and Insight: essays in the rhetoric of contemporary Kermode, F. (1983). Institutional control of interpretation, in his Essays on Fiction
criticism (2nd ed., revised, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press; first 1971–82 (pp. 168–84). London: Routledge.
published as a collection 1971). LaCapra, D. (1980). Rethinking intellectual history and reading texts, History and
Derrida, J. (1967). De la Grammatologie (Translated as Derrida (1974)). Paris: Theory 19, 245–76; reprinted with additions in D. LaCapra & S. L. Kaplan (Eds.)
Éditions de Minuit. (1982), Modern European Intellectual History: reappraisals and new perspectives
Derrida, J. (1974). Of Grammatology (Transl. G.C. Spivak, translation of Derrida (pp. 47–85). Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.
(1967)). Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. LaCapra, D. (1985). History and criticism. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press).
Derrida, J. (1979). Living on (transl. James Hulbert). In Harold Bloom, et al. (Eds.), Laslett, P. (1960). Introduction to John Locke, Two Treatises of Government.
Deconstruction and criticism (pp. 75–176). London: Routledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Dilthey, W. (1900). The development of hermeneutics (transl. H.P. Rickmann). In Latour, B. (1987). Science in action: How to follow scientists and engineers through
Rickmann (Ed.), (1976) Wilhelm Dilthey: Selected writings (pp. 247–60). society. Milton Keynes: Open University Press.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Laudan, R. (1993). Histories of science and their uses: A review to 1913. History of
Dreyfus, H. L. (1980). Holism and hermeneutics. Review of Metaphysics, 34, 3–23. Science, 31, 1–34.
Dreyfus, H. L. (1991). Being-in-the-World: A commentary upon Heidegger’s Being and Lawrence, C. (1985). Ornate physicians and learned artisans: Edinburgh medical
Time, Division I. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press. men, 1726–1776. In W. F. Bynum & R. Porter (Eds.), William Hunter and the
Eagleton, T. (1984). The function of criticism from the spectator to post-modernism. eighteenth-century medical world (pp. 153–176). Cambridge: Cambridge
London: Verso. University Press.
Elton, G. R. (1967). The practice of history. (Sydney: University of Sydney Press (cited Livingston, D. (1993). Good and bad shadow history of philosophy. Journal of the
from London: Fontana/Collins edition, 1969)). History of Philosophy, 31, 111–113.
Elton, G. R. (1970). Political history: Principles and practice. London: Allen Lane. Livingstone, D.N. (1990). Geography. In Olby, et al. (Eds.) (1990).
Elton, G. R. (1991). Return to essentials: Some reflections on the present state of Lowenthal, D. (1985). The past is a foreign country. Cambridge: Cambridge University
historical study. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Press.
Ermarth, M. (1978). Wilhelm Dilthey: The critique of historical reason. Chicago: McCrea, B. (1990). Addison and Steele are Dead: The English department, its canon, and
University of Chicago Press. the professionalization of literary criticism. Newark, N.J.: University of Delaware
Fish, S. (1980). Is there a text in this class? Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.
Press. McGann, J. J. (1983). A critique of modern textual criticism. Chicago: University of
Fogel, R. W., & Elton, G. R. (1983). Which road to the past? Two views of history. New Chicago Press.
Haven: Yale University Press. McGann, J. J. (1985a). The beauty of inflections: Literary investigations in historical
Foucault, M. (1977). What is an author? (French original 1969), transl. D.F. method and theory. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Bouchard and S. Simon, in D. F. Bouchard (Ed.), Language, counter-memory, McGann, J. J. (1985b). The text, the poem, and the problem of historical method, in
practice (pp. 113–138). Oxford: Blackwell. McGann (1985a) (pp. 111–132).
Foucault, M. (1972). The archaeology of knowledge (French original 1969) (transl. McGann, J. J. (1985c). The monks and the giants. In Jerome J. McGann (Ed.), Textual
A.M. Sheridan Smith). London: Tavistock (cited from London: Routledge edition, criticism and literary interpretation (pp. 180–200; also included in McGann
1989). (1985a), pp. 69–89). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Gadamer, H.-G. (1965). Wahrheit und Methode: grundzuge einer philosophischen McGann, J. J. (1991). The textual condition. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press.
Hermeneutik (translated as Gadamer (1975)). Tubingen: J.C.B. Mohr (first MacLean, M. J. (1982). Johann Gustav Droysen and the development of historical
published 1960). hermeneutics. History and Theory, 21, 347–365.
Gadamer, H.-G. (1975). Truth and method, transl. W. Glen-Doepel, Ed. G. Barden and Margolis, J. (1993). Canons for objectivist interpretation. The Monist, 76, 494–507.
J. Cumming (London: Sheed and Ward); cited here from the second, revised Martin, J. (1990). Sauvages’s nosology: Medical enlightenment in Montpellier. In
edition, transl. revised by J. Weinsheimer and D.G. Marshall (1989/1993, q.v. p. Cunningham, & French (Eds.), (pp. 111–137).
xix for translation details), translation of Gadamer (1965). Marwick, A. (1989). The nature of history. London: Macmillan, 3rd ed.
Gadamer, H.-G. (1976). Philosophical hermeneutics (transl. and Ed. D.E. Linge). Myers, G. (1990). Writing biology: Texts in the social construction of scientific
Berkely: University of California Press. knowledge. Madison, Wisconsin: University of Wisconsin Press).
Author's personal copy

358 A. Wilson / Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 43 (2012) 341–358

Nehamas, A. (1981). The postulated author: Critical monism as a regulative ideal. Skinner, Q. (1969). Meaning and understanding in the history of ideas, History and
Critical Inquiry, 8, 131–149. Theory 8, 3–53, reprinted in Tully (Ed.) (1988), pp. 29–67.
Nehamas, A. (1987). Writer, text, work, author. In Cascardi (Ed.) (1987), (pp. 265– Skinner, Q. (1988) A reply to my critics, in Tully (Ed.) 1988. pp. 231–88.
291). Southard, R. (1995). Droysen and the Prussian school of history. n.p.: University Press
Nesbit, M. (1987). What was an author?, Yale French Studies, no. 73, 229–57; of Kentucky.
partially reprinted in Burke (ed.) (1995), pp. 247–262. Spender, D. (1986). Mothers of the Novel: 100 good women writers before Jane Austen.
Ní Fhlathúin, M. (1995). Postcolonialism and the author: The case of Salman London: Routledge.
Rushdie. In Burke (Ed.) (1995), (pp. 277–284). Spivak, G. C. (1993). Reading The Satanic Verses, in Biriotti and Miller (Eds.) (1993),
Oakeshott, M. (1983). On history and other essays. Oxford: Blackwell. pp. 104–34.
Olby, R. C., Cantor, G. N., Christie, J. R. R., & Hodge, M. J. S. (Eds.). (1990). Companion Sutrop, M. (1994). The death of the literary work. Philosophy and Literature, 18,
to the history of modern science. London: Routledge. 38–49.
Outhwaite, W. (1987). New philosophies of social science: Realism, hermeneutics and Szondi, P. (1970) Schleiermacher’s hermeneutics today, in Szondi (1986), pp. 95–
critical theory. Basingstoke: Macmillan Education. 113.
Payne, M. (Ed.). (1996). A dictionary of cultural and critical theory. Oxford: Blackwell. Szondi, P. (1986). On textual understanding and other essays (transl. Harvey
Pope, R. (1995). Textual intervention: Critical and creative strategies for literary studies. Mendelsohn) Manchester: Manchester University Press.
London: Routledge. Szondi, P. (1995). Introduction to literary hermeneutics (transl. Martha Woodmansee)
Porter, R. (1990). The history of science and the history of society. In Olby et al. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
(Eds.) (1990). Thompson, J. B. (1981). Critical hermeneutics: A study in the thought of Paul Ricoeur
Rée, J. (1987). Philosophical tales: An essay on philosophy and literature. London: and Jurgen Habermas. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Methuen. Tosh, J. (1992). The Pursuit of History: Aims, methods and new directions in the study of
Ricoeur, P. (1965). History and truth (French original 1955, 1964) (transl. C.A. modern history, revised edn. London: Longman (first published 1984).
Kelbley). Evanston: Northwestern University Press. Tully, J. (Ed.). (1988). Meaning and context: Quentin Skinner and his critics.
Ricoeur, P. (1971). What is a text? Explanation and understanding. In D. M. Cambridge: Polity.
Rasmussen (Ed.), Mythico-Symbolic Language and Philosophic Anthropology (The Tully, J. (1993). An approach to political philosophy: Locke in contexts. Cambridge:
Hague, Martinus Nijhoff), pp. 135–50; reprinted in Ricoeur (1981), Ch. 5. Cambridge University Press.
Ricoeur, P. (1981). In J. Thompson (Ed.), Hermeneutics and the human sciences: Essays van der Dussen, W. J. (1993). Editor’s Introduction to Collingwood (1993).
on language, action and interpretation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Watson, R. A. (1993). Shadow history in philosophy. Journal of the History of
Ricoeur, P. (1983–85). Temps et récit, 3 Vols. (translated as Ricoeur (1984–88)). Philosophy, 31, 95–109.
Paris: Éditions du Seuil. White, H. (1973). Metahistory: The historical imagination in nineteenth-century
Ricoeur, P. (1984–88). Time and Narrative, 3 Vols. (translation of Ricoeur (1983–85)). Europe. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Wilson, A. (Ed.). (1993). Rethinking social history: English society and its interpretation,
Robinson, R. (1962). (transl. and ed.), Aristotle’s Politics Books III and IV. Oxford: 1570–1920. Manchester: Manchester University Press.
Clarendon Press. Wilson, A. (1993a). A critical portrait of social history, in Wilson (Ed.) (1993).
Schleier, H. (1990). Ranke in the manuals on historical methods of Droysen, Lorenz, pp. 9–58.
and Bernheim. In G. G. Iggers & J. M. Powell (Eds.), Leopold von Ranke and the Wilson, A. (1993b). Foundations of an integrated historiography, in Wilson (Ed.)
Shaping of the Historical Discipline (pp. 111–123). Syracuse, N.Y.: Syracuse (1993), pp. 292–335.
University Press. Wilson, A. (2004). Foucault on the question of the author: A critical exegesis.
Secord, J. A. (2004). Knowledge in transit. Isis, 95, 654–672. Modern Language Review, 99 (2004), 339–363.
Shapin, S. (1992). Discipline and bounding: the history and sociology of science Wilson, A., & Ashplant, T. G. (1988). Whig history and present-centred history.
as seen through the externalist-internalist debate. History of Science, 30, Historical Journal, 31, 1–16.
333–369. Woolgar, S. (1988). Science: The very idea. Chichester: Ellis Horwood.
Shapin, S., & Schaffer, S. (1985). Leviathan and the air-pump: Hobbes, Boyle and the Woolgar, S. (1993). What is a scientific author? in Biriotti and Miller (Eds.) (1993),
experimental life. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press). pp. 175–90.

You might also like