You are on page 1of 53

Which Is the Fairest One of All?

A Positive Analysis of Justice Theories

James Konow

Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. 41, No. 4. (Dec., 2003), pp. 1188-1239.

Stable URL:
http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0022-0515%28200312%2941%3A4%3C1188%3AWITFOO%3E2.0.CO%3B2-X

Journal of Economic Literature is currently published by American Economic Association.

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at
http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained
prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in
the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.

Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at
http://www.jstor.org/journals/aea.html.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed
page of such transmission.

The JSTOR Archive is a trusted digital repository providing for long-term preservation and access to leading academic
journals and scholarly literature from around the world. The Archive is supported by libraries, scholarly societies, publishers,
and foundations. It is an initiative of JSTOR, a not-for-profit organization with a mission to help the scholarly community take
advantage of advances in technology. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

http://www.jstor.org
Fri Feb 22 11:34:22 2008
Journal of Economic Literature
Vol. XLZ (December 2003) pp. 1188-1239

Which Is the Fairest One of All?


A Positive Analysis of Justice Theories

o n u n during, either the whole ofhis Iqe, or Jack Knetsch, and Richard Thaler 1986);res-
A7 that of nrzy corzsiderable part of it, ever trod
steadily arzd unqoonnly irz the path .. . ofjustice,
olution of social choice problems such as
locating nuclear-waste facilities (Felix
. . . whose conduct was not principally directed
by n regard to the renti,rtents of the strppo.ied oberholzer-Gee, Iris Bohnet, and Bruno
in~partialspectator, of the great irzinute of the Frey 1997);public-utility regulation (Edward
breast, the great judge and arbiter of conduct. Zajac 1985);and labor unemployment due to
- Adanz Snzith (17,591p. 357 efficiency wages (e.g., George Akerloff and
Janet Yellen 1990).The view that "By now we
have substantial evidence suggesting that
1.Introduction fairness motives affect the behavior of many
Justice arguments are now widely invoked people" iErnst Fehr and Schmidt
to improve theoretical and analysis 1999) is expressed in mainstream economics.
in nearly evey field of economics This contrasts with the traditional belief of
Incolporated into game theoy (e,g,, many economists that justice is chimerical or
Matthew Rabin 1993), fairness predicts the A more stance
deviations from pure self-interest obselved in placed it outside the domain of economics,
many laboratoly experiments (e.g., werner better left to philosophers, political scientists,
cllth and ~ ~ i ~i~~~ h ~ ~ impact
~ 1990) d or sociologist^. There has been a steady
has also been cited in many real-world con- trend, however, of increasing interest in and
texts, including the intermittent failure of Of justice in the Pro-
product markets to clear ( ~ ~gahneman,
~ i ~ lfession, even partially displacing e f f i c i e n ~ ~ . ~
This is not to say, of course, that economists
are or should be abandoning their traditional
Loyola Mavmount Uni\-ersit)r I thank the editor and
three anonymous referees of the Journal of Ecotlorrtic
Liternture; Alison Alter, G a v Bolton, John Coleman, G a v "his is suggested, for example, by an examination of
Charness, James Devine, Jon Elster, Duncan Fole!; Silnon studies doculnented on EconLit. The number of entries for
Gachter, II'ulf Gaertner, Guillermina Jasso, Serge- the 1970s under the ke)~vord"efficiency" outnumber those
Christophe Kolm, Alexander Kritikos, Axel Ockenfels, Joe under "justice" or "fairness" (not counting those under the
Oppenheimer, Richard Posner, Matthew Rabin, Erik equivocal term "equit)-") by sixteen to one. For the 1980s
Schokkaert, John T. Scott, Alois Stutzer, Pe!ton Young, Ed this ratio falls to about nine to one, and for the 1990s this
Zajac, and participants at the meetings of the Public gap further narrows to 4.4 to one. In fact, if one considers
Choice Society, Social Choice and Welfare Society, and entries under the ]EL classification system in operation
International Societ)- for Justice Research for many help- since 1991 through the present, hits under the code closest
ful suggestions and comments. An!- remaining errors or to justice (DG3: Equity, Justice, Inequality, and Other
shortcomings are, of course, my o ~ m I. also thank Jack Normative Criteria and Measurement) outnumber those
Knetsch for perlnission to use questions fro111 Kahneman, under that closest to efficient!. (DG1:Allocative Efficiency;
Knetsch, and Thaler (1986). Cost-Benefit Analysis) almost two to one.

1188
Konow: A Positive Analysis of Justice Theories 1189

interest in efficiency. Instead, stimulated by A second, closely related goal of the paper
empirical evidence and, perhaps, the percep- is to propose and defend an integrated justice
tion of increasing economic inequality, they theory that synthesizes previous approaches
are expanding their studies to encompass a and explains actual values as the conflation of
wider set of distributive concerns. Despite four distinct forces or elements. These ele-
the emerging consensus in economics over ments of justice inspire four corresponding
the relevance of fairness, though, no such theoretical categories (or families)into which
agreement yet exists among economists or, each of the theories is placed and analyzed.
for that matter, among psychologists, political The category equality and need covers theo-
scientists, sociologists, or philosophers, about ries that incorporate a concern for the well-
the proper theory of justice. being of the least well-off members of socie-
ty including egalitarianism, social contract
1.1 Two Goals of the Study
theories (chiefly Rawls), and Marxism. They
One goal of this paper is to conduct a posi- inspire the Need Principle, which calls for
tive analysis of leading positive and normative the equal satisfaction of basic needs. The
theories ofjustice, where a remarkable lacuna utilitarianism and welfare economics family
exists in the literat~re.~ By positive analysis I comprises utilitarianism, Pareto Principles,
mean that each theory, whether originally and the absence of envy concept, which have
conceived for this purpose or not, will be grown out of consequentialist ethics, or the
evaluated in terms of how accurately it tradition in philosophy and economics that
describes the fairness preferences of people. emphasizes consequences and end-states.
In this paper, the terms fairness, justice, and They are most closely associated with the
equity always refer to the view of Adam Efficiency Principle, which advocates maxi-
Smith's impartial spectator whose judgment is mizing surplus. The category equity and
not biased by any personal stake. The discus- desert includes equity theory, desert theory,
sion includes both distributive justice, which and Robert Nozick's theory. Together they
concerns fair outcomes, as well as procedural inform the Equity Principle, which is based
justice, which addresses fair processes, on proportionality and individual responsibil-
whereby the more extensive treatment of the ity. The context family discusses the ideas of
former reflects the relative emphasis in the Kahneman, Knetsch, and Thaler; Michael
justice literature. Justice is operationalized Walzer; Jon Elster; H. Peyton Young; and
here mostly in relation to material wealth, the Bruno Frey and Alois Stutzer, among others.
chief concern of most economists, even This fourth family does not generate a dis-
though it is clear that the forces discussed tributive principle but rather deals with the
often impact noneconomic domains. Other dependence of justice evaluation on the con-
factors that affect allocations include altruism, text, such as the choice of persons and vari-
reciprocity, spite, kinship, and friendship. ables, framing effects, and issues of process.4
These are significant but distinct phenomena,
which nevertheless underscore the import
and timeliness of studyingjustice, given grow- When dealing with such an extensive literature, e\-en a
ing evidence that some behavior previously wide-ranging review callnot be comprehensive. Although I
have striven to include the most influential theories of jus-
attributed to these forces (especiallyreciproc- tice, some theories are omitted because they are not pri-
ity) is likely due to distributive preferences. marily theories of justice (e.g., game theories), or because
their focus is more remote from the subject matter of eco-
nolnics (e.g., jurihcal theories), or because their incolpo-
There are, however, excellent surveys on more narrow ration into the four elements that frame the study seems
topics from which this paper has also profited, e.g., forced (rights theories). Actually, the paper seeks to repre-
Bernard Cullen (1994) reviews nonnative philosophical sent the breadth of the literature in a relatively concise
theories and Erik Schokkaert (1994) nonnative economic manner by treating many theories while focusing on those
theories. aspects of each that contribute to the integrated theon.
1190 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XLI (December 2003)

While proceeding through the sometimes action, global warming, labor-management


intricate analysis that follows, the reader can conflicts, "fair" trade negotiations, and
better maintain a sense of unity if he or she debates on the taxation of income, inheri-
keeps in mind the dual goals of this paper and tances, and corporate dividends. The fre-
the framework that structures them. On the quency and vehemence of such claims, often
one hand, the specific theories discussed accompanied by sacrifices, attest to a convic-
offer very different, and sometimes contra- tion on the part of the advocates regarding
dictory, perspectives on the meaning of jus- both their normative value and their power
tice. On the other hand, I argue for a general to persuade and, thereby, to alter outcomes.
theory of justice as a unifylng framework for These observations are significant because
the specific theories. These ostensibly disso- they indicate that fairness, in fact, appeals to
nant objectives are reconciled by the follow- a common moral sense, which, when applied
ing two facts. First, the general theory guides to specific cases, is subject to some interpre-
the classification of a specific theory into the tation. In particular, biases often emerge
category (i.e., element of the general theory) when stakes are involved; e.g., Kenneth
that is judged as most helpful for &stilling the Binmore (1994) reports a strong tendency by
specific theory's most salient contribution to subjects, when debriefed following bargain-
understanding actual justice views. ing experiments, to describe their self-serv-
Nevertheless, the evidence, taken as a whole, ing decisions during the experiments as
does not confirm any single theory in toto and "fair." Various studies, including those of
sometimes even refutes central suppositions Linda Babcock et al. (1995), Tore Ellingsen
or conclusions. Both favorable and unfavor- and Magnus Johannesson (2003),and myself
able evidence on the specific theories, how- (Konow 2000), trace this bias in large part to
ever, produces lessons for the general theory. deception, both of others and of oneself,
Second, it should be emphasized that the regarding what is fair. These studies also
general framework around which the analysis indicate that, although biases sometimes
is organized is an integrated theoy , but not a widen the range of predicted outcomes,
composite t h e o y : justice is more than the behavior is still constrained by fairness.
sum of its parts. The three principles of jus- Thus, justice is not amorphous or arbitrarily
tice must be weighted, and context provides malleable, and, as I seek to show in this
the weighting scheme in specific cases. The paper, fairness preferences usually converge
argument is that each category captures an when stakes are removed.
element that is important to crafting a posi- These facts suggest at least two important
tive theory of justice but that no single family reasons for seeking a descriptively accurate
or theory within a family suffices to this end. theory of impartial justice. First, social sci-
Instead, fairness views are best explained by entists must consider how justice, alone or in
an integrated approach that acknowledges tandem with other goals (such as self-inter-
the influence of the three principles of jus- est or reciprocity), affects the phenomena
tice, whereby the weight on each is deter- they study. Although stakeholders often sub-
mined by the context. This method enables ject justice to biased and differing interpre-
one to treat justice rigorously and to reconcile tations, in order to have moral force, their
results that often appear contradictory or at claims cannot be capricious but must be
odds with alternative theories. constructed around impartial standards.
Whereas observed behavior typically results
1.2 Reasons for this Research Agenda
from multiple motives, a study of impartial
People justify their positions and behavior justice consciously aims at separating the
in a wide range of situations based on justice, effects of unbiased justice, biased justice,
for example, in connection with affirmative and other motives.
Konow: A Positive Analysis of Justice Theories

A second important motivation for a study and Reiner Eichenberger 1996 for an inter-
of impartial justice concerns normative and esting example of how several such concerns
policy analysis in philosophy, law, and the interact in the area of social choice).
social sciences. One specific purpose is in the Unfortunately, field studies, though often
area of conflict resolution: given the afore- useful for demonstrating the impact of fair-
mentioned fairness biases that often insinuate ness, are usually not designed for evaluating
themselves into legal, economic, and political theories of fairness. Ones that elicit motives,
debates, impartial justice provides a standard such as those mentioned above, are few,
against which to evaluate and reconcile con- and competing forces always threaten to
flicting interests. In more general terms, the undermine clear inferences about fairness.
appropriate role of such a study for normative The evidence brought here to bear on the
analysis depends on one's stance on certain justice theories is marshaled from numerous
questions of moral epistemology (i.e., how studies spanning different disciplines and
one knows what is moral). Some scholars find employing various methods. Because of the
the impartial values of real people to be a afore-mentioned difficulties with inferring
compelling foundation for an ethical theory. ethical intent from behavior in the field,
As Tibor Scitovsky puts it, "An important part however, the results cited are largely from
of the economist's task is to find out how well studies that utilize experimental and survey
the production and distribution of goods and designs. In moral contexts, these methods
services conform to the public's wishes. The permit better control over confounding fac-
first thing to ascertain in this connection is tors and stronger statements about causality.
what the public's wishes are" (1986, p. 3). In particular, the primary goal is to track the
Philosophers, including Mill, Rawls, Nozick, values of the impartial spectator rather than
and \Valzer, tacitly acknowledge the merit of the implicated takeh holder.^ Much of the
this approach by asserting that crucial prem- evidence presented, therefore, comes from
ises of their theories are consonant with gen- studies that encourage participants to pre-
erally accepted values. Even those who would scind and abstract from personal stakes. The
derive prescriptive theories in another man- survey method, in particular, exhibits low
ner cannot ignore the actual preferences self-interest bias in general attitude sumeys
their own theories will confront. As the bro- (e.g., of support for income redistribution
mide "ought implies can" suggests, any nor- as in Christina Fong 2001) as well as in
mative theory with a claim to relevance must vignettes, or questions that present hypo-
direct actions that are sustainable in the real thetical scenarios and elicit preferences over
world of real values. them (e.g., Menahem Yaari and Maya
Bar-Hillel 1984). An advantage of experi-
1.3 Empirical Method
ments, on the other hand, is that they pro-
Fairness is widely regarded as a motive vide behavioral measures of preferences and
behind much behavior observed in the real demonstrate the willingness to act on them
world (or the "field), a view substantiated by when stakes are involved. One drawback of
results of quasi-field studies that actually ask this method for the current purpose, howev-
implicated parties about their motives, such er, is that the stakes in most experiments are
as Babcock, Xianghong W n g , and George
Loewenstein (1996); Alan S. Blinder and
Don H. Choi (1996); and David I. Levine %ulnerous studies have exposed a self-serving bias in
(1993). Fairness, however, is often offset or fairness judgments by stakeholders in the field, e.g.,
reinforced by other motives, such as self- Babcock, \L7ang,and Loewenstein (1996), as well as in the
laboraton e.g.,John Kagel et al. (1996) and Konow (2000).
interest, public spirit, friendship, and recip- David Messick and Keith Sentis (1979) have found this
rocal altruism (see Frey, Oberholzer-Gee, stakeholder bias even when payments are hypothetical.
Journal of Economic Litenature, Vol. XLl (December 2003)

personal and contribute to a self-serving of convenience samples. After biasing their


bias. Another is that even clear departures representative sample study in favor of sub-
from self-interest cannot necessarily be ject pool effects by selecting the most con-
attributed to justice as opposed to other trozjersial questions from the studentlparent
preferences since motives are usually not survey, Schokkaert and Capeau relate the
elicited. This paper attempts to balance responses from the general population to
these concerns by establishing corroborative socio-economic variables including income,
patterns across evidence from both experi- sex, age, education, and profession. Based on
ments and surveys. logit estimations, they conclude that the
Since many surveys and all experiments "most striking fact is the extremely small
cited here use student subjects, the question amount of variance which can be explained
arises as to whether this group is representa- using these equations. This is not completely
tive of the general population. In the most surprising . . . It is even rather comforting in
comprehensive examination of subject pool this case: if the answers to our cases really are
effects in economics experiments, Sheryl ethically inspired, one would not a priori
Ball and Paula-Ann Cech (1996) report the expect the socio-economic variables in our
results of various studies, including ones rel- equations to have much explanatory power"
evant to justice such as bargaining and pub- (p. 337). Moreover, I will argue that, even
lic goods experiments, which compare stu- when significant differences across samples
dent and non-student populations. With one surface, they are best explained not by dif-
exception, they "find little evidence of sub- ferent values but by patterned variations in
ject pool effects" between different popula- subject interpretation of a shared set of jus-
tions. The available evidence on such effects tice principles based on differences in sub-
from fairness surveys points in the same ject information, experiences, or interests,
direction. For instance, many of the which is entirely consistent with, indeed is
Kahneman, Knetsch, and Thaler (1986) predicted by, the theory proposed here (see
results from telephone interviews with especially sections 4.2 and 5.2).
Canadian adults have been substantially Many results cited here, including some
replicated, including with adult populations previously unpublished ones, make use of
in Germany and Switzerland (Frey and vignettes. Numerous significant economic
Werner Pommerehne 1993) and with U.S. studies have employed this method (e.g.,
adults and college students (Konow 2001, Gordon B. Dahl and Michael R. Ransom
and the current study). Erik Schokkaert and 1999; Kahneman and Amos Tversky 1979),
Bart Capeau (1991) relate judgments of and it has proven especially useful for justice
Belgian respondents about fair distributions research (e.g., Blinder and Choi 1990;
of gains and losses in diverse scenarios to Kahneman, Knetsch, and Thaler 1986;
subject pool choice and to the socio-econom- Levine 1993). Still, this method is less com-
ic characteristics of subjects. They compare mon in economics than, say, psychology, so I
results from Schokkaert and Bert Overlaet will briefly review it and its application in the
(1989) with 243 college students enrolled in present study. A characteristic feature of
an introductory economics course, Overlaet vignettes is their contextual richness, which
(1991) with 234 parents of a different group has been shown to aid reasoning; e.g.,
of economics students, and their own survey \Villiam M. Goldstein and Elke U. \Veber
with a representative sample of 810 adults (1995) report that when a problem is pre-
from the general population. The authors sented to people in abstract form, "they do
find that the three groups exhibit generally spectacularly bad at it," whereas when it "is
the same pattern of choices and conclude fleshed out with understandable content,
that "there is no need to worry" about the use there is remarkable improvement." In
Konow: A Positive Analysis of Justice Theories 1193

addition, vignettes are less prone to the mis- numerous vignettes of the author. These
understandings, caused by ambiguities about comprise telephone interviews with a gen-
relevant details, that often plague other eral adult population and written question-
instruments. In fact, vignettes have been naires completed by college students. The
used to improve surveys about "objective" surveys were designed and conducted to
variables such as employment data (Elizabeth produce meaningful results and to avoid
Martin and Anne Polivka 1992). Moreover, subject pool and response biases in line with
Marilyn Lewis Lanza et al. (1997) report evi- sound practices for survey research (e.g.,
dence that responses to vignettes closely Floyd J. Fowler 2002, and Jon A. Krosnick
reflect reactions to events in the real world. 1991). Fairness wording was explicitly used
An important strength of this method for jus- for purposes of validity, i.e., to ensure the
tice research is that it offers a flexible and instrument measures what it claims to meas-
easily controlled means to provide informa- ure, an important issue given evidence that
tion that can prove relevant to fairness, for what is "fair" may differ from what is "good
example, details about effort or needs. The or what people prefer (see section 6).7
answer formats may be qualitative or quanti-
tative, but most studies cited here used the ' Other measures included the following. Different ver-
former except where otherwise indicated. Of sions that comprised different subsets of the master list and
course, a legitimate concern is that the con- that varied the order of questions aimed at avoiding sys-
tematic order effects. When there were contrasting ver-
tent specificity of vignettes might limit the sions of a scenario, each subject faced at most one version
generality of their resultsS6 A common of a scenario in order not to encourage any tendency
approach to this question is to examine the toward overly similar or dissimilar responses across ver-
sions. A number of steps helped to minimize satisficing,
robustness of claims through different ques- i.e., suboptimal cognitive processing: scenarios were for-
tions or versions of questions that vary con- mulated briefly and clearly to reduce task difficulty, and
textual elements. In fact, this also enables one answer formats were qualitative and simple, which has also
been shown to improve reliability (i.e., consistency on
to establish evidence on the issue of whether retests). Relative to personal interviews, the telephone and
justice is context specific or whether common self-administered surveys we used afford greater anonymi-
principles apply across dfferent contexts. ty and are associated with more candid responses. The tele-
phone interviews were conducted on a random sample of
Another strategy is to compare results across adults in Los Angeles, a city that, given its culturally diverse
studies that employ other methods and data. and large immigrant population, is probably more repre-
Both techniques are employed in this study: sentative of the world population than most samples.
Random digit dialing addressed issues of sample selection,
for the new as well as previously published and, to promote attentiveness, each telephone interview
results, claims are evaluated, where possible, posed no more than five questions and lasted no longer
using multiple sources and methods. than five minutes. The response rate of 47 percent, consid-
ered good for telephone interviews, was achieved by brief
Although there exists much evidence on interviews, up to twelve attempts to contact respondents
justice, some theories considered here have and interviewing non-English speakers in their native
not heretofore been examined as represen- tongue. Written questionnaires were presented to students
in a wide range of undergraduate classes at Loyola
tations of impartial justice. For that reason, Marymount University and lasted no more than ten min-
this evidence is supplemented by previously utes. This written format was preferred for more intricate
unpublished results drawn from a database scenarios, which telephone respondents tend to process
poorly Although the telephone interviews drew from a
containing the responses of 3178 subjects to more general population, there were several other advan-
tages of the written surveys. The questionnaires achieved
A counterargument is that, given the above- virtually a 100 percent-response rate and, by being self-
mentioned misgivings about decision-making in abstract administered, reduced if not eliminated possible interview-
form, even a single vignette is more general by establishing er-induced bias. More educated respondents, such as these
compelling findings in one, as opposed to no, context. college students, are also less susceptible to various types of
Indeed, in this author's experience, conclusions based on satisficing. Finally, several of the same or similar questions
this method seem no less general when tested in different were posed to both the adult and college respondents with-
contexts and with different methods than those derived out large differences across samples, consistent with the
from abstract questions or experimental tasks. findings of Schokkaert and Capeau (1991) on this matter.
1194 Journal of EcononlJic Litel rature, Vol. XLI (December 2003)

1.4 Organization of the Paper opposed to competitive relationships.


Mikula and Thomas Schwinger (1973), for
Section 2 addresses equality and need,
example, study allocation decisions among
section 3 covers utilitarianism and welfare
36 pairs of soldiers in the same unit who per-
economics, section 4 is devoted to equity and
form a task that generates joint earnings.
desert, and section 5 deals with context. The
They find that many subjects who perform
paper's development resembles a Hegelian
well relative to their partners act against
dialectic in which a theory is presented as a
their own interests and allocate earnings
thesis, often supported by evidence, only to
equally, an effect that is stronger when sub-
be confronted by its antithe.sis in the form of
jects are paired with partners they like. This
counter-arguments and evidence contrary to
result, which Mikula and his colleagues have
the theory. Ultimately, however, the goal is to
identified elsewhere (see Mikula 1980),
reach a synthesis of the theories at the end
stands in stark contrast, however, to the
of each section in the form of a principle or
"self-interest" bias that almost all other
lesson. Section 6 concludes with an even
researchers find in allocation experiments
broader approach that seeks to synthesize
(e.g., Robert Forsythe et al. 1994; Elizabeth
the four elements of justice.
Hoffman et al. 1994). The fact that each
group in Mikula's experiments favors a rule
2. Equality and h7eed
that is to its disadvantage, equality by high
Theories of equality and of need are usu- performers and proportionality by low per-
ally characterized by a concern for the wel- formers, suggests that his experimental
fare of those in society who are the least design is not capturing a distributive prefer-
advantaged. Interpreted as a preference on ence for equality, which should be shared by
the part of real people for equally satisfying all, but rather something closer to a "gen-
basic human needs, they form a principle of erosity bias" on the part of both groups. The
justice. additional fact that this effect is stronger
when subjects like their partners reinforces
2.1. Egalitarianism
the impression that an interpersonal affinity
The most primitive, and probably oldest, distinct from fairness is at work.
notion of justice associates equity with Numerous studies employing survey
equality. Justice has been construed as designs are unfavorable to the descriptive
equality of original positions, opportunity, value of egalitarianism. One source of data is
proportions and rights. Our discussion from vignette studies of micro-ju~stice,or of
begins with egalitarianism, by which I mean fairness to and among individuals, such as
the equality of outcomes. This simplest and Konow (1996) and Schokkaert and Capeau
strongest notion of equality has often been (1991).These indicate a frequent preference
declared to be one of several principles of for unequal allocations and that equal out-
justice (e.g., Morton Deutsch 1985). comes are only fair as a special case, e.g.,
Equality is also sometimes taken as a point of when variables subjects consider relevant to
departure for studies of inequality (e.g., fairness happen to be equal across individu-
Yoram Amiel and Frank A. Cowell 1999). als. Survey studies of macro-ju~stice,or of jus-
Kai Nielsen's "radical egalitarian" concept of tice at the societal level, uniformly show
distributive justice (1985) advocates the abo- strong opposition to equal outcomes. When
lition of material inequalities. the U.S. general public is asked about the
Some social psychologists (e.g., Deutsch just distribution of income, only 7 percent of
1985; Gerold Mikula 1980) propose that 938 respondents to the survey reported in
equality is the principle in a multi-criterion Herbert McCloskey and John Zaller (1984)
system that is favored in cooperative as and 3 percent of the 1415 respondents in
Konow: A Positive Analysis oflustice Theories

James Kluegel and Eliot Smith (1986) sup- those "that free and rational persons con-
port complete or near equality of income. In cerned to further their own interests would
fact, Guillermina Jasso (1999) reports, based accept in an initial position of equality" (p.
on probability samples (N=8810), that if 11).They are manifested as part of a .social
people received what they consider just, the contract, or an original agreement for the
distribution of income would be less, not basic structure of society. This agreement is
more, equal than the actual distribution in chosen in the original position, a hypotheti-
eight of thirteen countries studied. cal situation in which people are behind a
Despite widespread evidence of support "veil of ignorance" of their places in society,
for departures from equal outcomes, equali- i.e., their social status, wealth, abilities,
ty can, as stated above, emerge as a special strength, etc. Rawls argues that, since per-
case within a more general system, i.e., the sonal differences are unknown and every-
uncontroversial concept of "treating equals one is rational and similarly situated, this
equally." In other cases, equality appears to "veil of ignorance makes possible a unani-
be invoked, not as a general principle, but as mous choice of a particular conception of
a convenient approximation when the con- justice" (p. 140).
text renders "first-best" justice too complex Competing contractarian theories of justice
or thorny (see section 6). If the evidence have framed the question somewhat differ-
casts doubt on equality as one of several prin- ently. Binmore (1994) and David Gauthier
ciples, it topples egalitarianism as the single (1985) employ game theory to examine the
concern. Although complications can arise emergence of justice through bargaining. In
implementing even this simple rule (e.g., his Treatise of Social Justice (1989), Brian
does one equalize goods, income, or utility?), Barry rejects both the Rawlsian and game-
the plethora of disputes over justice suggests theoretic approaches and suggests that princi-
it is not as straightforward as equal outcomes. ples of justice result, not from individual
choice or bargaining, but rather from debate
2.2. Rau;ls and the Social Contract
in which others are convinced of the reason-
The publication of John Rawls's major ableness of principles, even if they run count-
work, A T h e o y of Justice, in 1971 was a er to their interests. Serge-Christophe Kolm's
landmark event in several respects. It provid- theory of the "liberal social contract" (1985)
ed the principal impetus to the resurgence of departs from other contractarian theories in
interest in justice among philosophers, and several respects. Kolm's contract is an agree-
even many social scientists, during the twen- ment between real parties aware of their posi-
tieth century. In addition, the authors of tions and not between fictitious individuals
nearly every subsequent normative treatment behind a veil of ignorance, agreements may
of justice have felt obliged to formulate their be reached for subsets such that not all deci-
theories within Rawls's framework, or at least sions require unanimity, and people are moti-
to define their positions with reference to his vated not only by self-interest but also by
contribution. In part a critique of utilitarian- altruism. As in the case of the present study,
ism, A Theoy of Justice builds upon the the- the goal of Brian Skyrms's Evolution of the
ory of the social contract associated with Social Contract (1996) is descriptive rather
Locke, Rousseau, and Kant. Equality plays a than normative. Specifically, Skyrms employs
central role in Rawls's theory, as does duty, evolutionary dynamics to explore the devel-
including the duty to help those in need. opment of the existing implicit social contract.
Rawls is concerned with social justice, or Returning to Rawls, on whom we will
"a standard whereby the distributive aspects focus here, he claims two justice principles
of the basic structure of society are to be would be chosen in the original position.
assessed (p. 9). The principles of justice are The first emphasizes equality, including
1196 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XLI (December 2003)

equal rights, liberties, and opportunities. purges the procedures of any explicit men-
The second principle (later called the differ- tion of justice or fairness (Paul Oleson 2001).
ence principle) has been the subject of The experimental evidence on Rawlsian
greater commentary. Rawls himself states justice seems to constitute a near-categorical
this second principle as the general concep- rejection of its crucial premise.
tion of his theory: "All social primary Nevertheless, legitimate questions can be
goods-liberty and opportunity, income and raised about the efficacy of the experimental
wealth and the bases of self-respect-are to design. Passing through the laboratory door
be distributed equally unless an unequal dis- is not necessarily equivalent to passing
tribution of any or all of these goods is to the through a veil of ignorance, and previously
advantage of the least favored (p. 303).The formed knowledge and expectations might
difference principle, then, is a maximin rule taint subjects' reasoning. In addition, the
for the distribution of the goods, material structured discussion of the Frohlich and
and other, that Rawls regards as primary. Oppenheimer experiments resembles more
The difference principle is the part of Barry's debate leading to consensus than
Rawls's theory that has generated the great- Rawls's perfect coincidence of individual
est volume of hostile reaction and on which choices. On the other hand, this aspect does
he is generally considered most vulnerable. seems to err in Rawls's favor by allowing his
Kenneth Arrow (1973) and John Harsanyi principle to be chosen even without identi-
(1975) raise objections from the perspective cal individual preferences. If the difference
of welfare economics. Perhaps the most principle really represents shared values, it is
damaging criticism, however, is of the psy- difficult to grasp why, even behind an imper-
chological assumption that people in the fect veil, it does not emerge with greater fre-
original position prefer to maximize mini- quency.
mum outcomes to the complete exclusion of The question both Rawls and this study ask
any other goals. Norman Frohlich and Joe is premised on a kind of impartiality. Rawls's
Oppenheimer (1992; 1987 with Cheryl thought experiment, however, involves indi-
Eavey) have conducted various laboratory viduals who are presumed to have a stake in
experiments aimed at inducing the original the outcome and who, by assumption, are
position. University students, assigned to motivated in their choice of principles solely
groups of five subjects, are introduced to by self-interest. Our question, by contrast,
and tested on their understanding of four concerns the choices of impartial spectators
distributive rules (including maximum who are not stakeholders and who are
expected value and the difference principle). assumed to be motivated by social prefer-
The subjects then discuss the rules. If they e n c e ~In
. ~addition, we do not presume that
arrive at a unanimous agreement, they are they deliberate over or even have any explicit
randomly assigned to different income class- awareness of ethical theory, but only that their
es and are paid according to income class preferences be guided by general principles
and group choice of rule. Subjects almost that can be deduced from their decisions.
always reach a consensus, and the vast The failure, therefore, of the Frohlich and
majority agree to a mixed rule: maximum Oppenheimer experiments to confirm
expected value subject to a constraint on the Rawls's hypothesis does not necessarily rule
minimum income. Rawls's difference princi-
ple is the least favorite rule, being chosen by 'This might seem like a difference without a distinc-
only one of 81 groups. Similar results tion, but that is not so. For example, an egalitarian who is
emerge in experiments conducted in risk-loving over his o\m allocations would prefer rules that
generate equal splits as impartial spectator but might favor
Australia, Canada, Poland, Japan, and the a very disperse distribution of outcomes in the original
United States and in a replication that position.
Konow: A Positioe Analysis ofJustice Theories

TABLE1. Questions l A , 1B and 1 C

1A. The owner of a small office supply store has two employees, Mike and Bill. They are equally productive and
hardworking and are both currently earning $7 per hour. The owner decides to move his store to a new location
nearby where he knows business will be better. He lets his workers know that if they wish to continue at the new
location he \\ill be able to raise their wage. He explains that they will continue to have the sarne responsibilities but
that one worker will earn $8 per hour and the other $12 per hour. H e also explains that which worker gets the high-
er wage will be determined later on the basis of a coin toss. The workers can choose to go with the owner to the
new location under these terms or to find similar work elsewhere for their current $7 per hour. They both choose
to go with the owner. Please rate the store o\\neris terms for the new wages as:
Fair 14% Unfair 8 6 4 N = 142

1B. Suppose Mike and Bill begin working for a computer software company at the same time and in the same
capaci9: Initially they both earn a salary of $50,000 per year. After a trial period Mike demonstrates that he is hard
working, productive and performs far beyond initial expectations. Bill, on the other hand, is lazy, unproductive and
performs far below initial expectations. Their supervisor decides to give Mike a $10,000 per year raise and to cut
Billis salan by $1000. Please rate the supervisor's decision to raise Mike's salan and to cut Bill's as:
Fair 80% Unfair 20% N = 177
1C. Mike and Bill are identical twins who were reared in an identical family and educational enkironment. They
are the sarne in terms of physical and mental abilities, but Mike is more industrious than Bill. For that reason, after
they begin their careers Mike ends up earning more than Bill. Please indicate whether you view such a difference
in their earnings as:
Fair 99% Unfair 1% N = 150

it out as a theory of justice in this other their preference for this unequal but
sense. A different instrument, which pur- improved state by choosing it over an oppor-
posely seeks to elicit views of impartial spec- tunity to duplicate the conditions of the ini-
tators, is better suited to this objective. In tial state. Nevertheless, 86 percent of the
this vein, the opposition cited to equal out- 142 (N) respondents judge this contract
comes in the previous section is generally unfair.
unfavorable to Rawlsian justice. More spe- A possible shortcoming of question 1A is
cific evidence is provided by the vignettes in that respondents might reason that the
table 1.' Question 1A incorporates several owner's terms are unfair because they con-
characteristics of Rawls's thought experi- jecture that the owner could also choose ex
ment. TLVO individuals find themselves ini- post equality by raising the wages of both to
tially in a situation of equality, which is fol- the same level (e.g., $10 per hour). One can
lowed by a randomly determined state in approach this problem differently. Rawlsian
which their lots differ. Additionally, the pro- respondents, in keeping with the difference
posed contract permits allocations that sat- principle, should oppose any change that
isfy the difference principle: By accepting leaves the least advantaged person worse off.
the owner's offer, they will both be better off A corollary of this is that, beginning from a
than initially (including the least advantaged position of equality, any change that makes
person), and they both even demonstrate one person better off while making another
worse off is not fair. Question 1B tests this
In this study questions assigned the same number but corollary and finds that, in this context, 80
different letters (e.g., l A , l B , 1C) were always put to dif- percent of the 177 respondents do, in fact,
ferent groups of respondents. Questions from the written support such a change, in opposition to
questionnaires are identified by italicized question num-
bers (e.g.,I A ) ,whereas ones from the telephone interviews equality and to the difference principle.
are identified by question numbers set in bold (e.g.,8A). Here the two parties appear similar, except
1198 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XLI (December 2003)

with regard to effort and productivity. relationships" (Karl Marx and Friedrich
Question 1C accentuates the equality of Engels 1958, vol. 2, p. 128). Marx seems to
starting positions of two individuals while associate justice with rights and proportion-
focusing on the role of differential effort, ality, which lead to inequalities. Instead, he
and respondents almost unanimously view endorses the communist distributive princi-
unequal rewards as fair. The latter two ques- ple, "From each according to his ability, to
tions highlight the fact that the drawbacks of each according to his needs!" (1875, p. 531).
Rawls's theory are not limited to what it con- Standing in contrast to these scant canon-
tains but also to what it lacks. His framework ical writings is an extensive literature on
denies, or at least fails to assign any role to, Marxian justice. Scholars of Marx have inter-
factors not due to the vagaries of "Nature." preted his view of justice as, in Marx's words,
Question l C , in particular, demonstrates "obsolete verbal rubbish" of capitalism
that inequalities can be fair even when (Allen Buchanan 1981), a critique of capital-
Nature bestows on individuals identical abil- ism (Gary Young 1981), a juridical rather
ities and positions. than moral concept (Robert Tucker 1969;
In defense of Rawls, his goal is to describe Allen Wood 1981), and a set of historically
the principles that govern the general struc- dependent principles that always reflect a
ture of society,which, he claims, might differ concern for equality and need (Jeffrey H.
from those that apply in more specific cases Reiman 1981).Whether or not Marx thought
(p. 8), such as, perhaps, those above. On the of justice in terms of need, this seems the
other hand, if they are genuinely general, most promising approach for a Marxian the-
these principles must apply to a substantial ory (as opposed to a Marxian critique) of jus-
number of specific cases, a point he also tice. There is no denying the centrality of
makes (p. 9), yet one is hard pressed to find need as a principle of distribution for Marx.
evidence of significant support for the dif- Agnes Heller (1974), for example, writes
ference principle. Nevertheless, other "We can see, then, that in the new economic
aspects of Rawls's theory resonate with pop- discoveries which Marx regarded as his own,
ular values. In the context of duty, he stress- the concept of need plays one of the main
es the importance of helping the needy, roles, if not actually the main role" (p. 25).
although he grounds this rule on the self- Experiments provide both implicit and
interested desire to insure oneself against explicit evidence of need as a general distrib-
being a victim of misfortune (pp. 338-39). utive concern. In the dictator experiment,
Rawls's attention to need and a kind of one subject (the dictator) is given a f ~ e sum
d
impartiality probably represent his two most of money, any amount of which he may share
significant contributions to justice theory. with an anonymous counterpart, who has no
recourse. Catherine Eckel and Philip
Grossman (1996) conduct a dictator experi-
Justice is a highly controversial concept ment in which some subjects allocate to
among scholars of Marxism and has been anonymous student counterparts and others
subject to very divergent interpretations. to an established charity. They find donations
Marx's own treatment of justice is sparse, to the presumably more needy charities to be
and commentators have often read it as significantly greater than those to fellow stu-
rejecting justice, indeed the whole of moral- dents. In the ultimatum game experiment, a
ity, as a bourgeois construct that is specific proposer selects an offer to make to a respon-
to context and history, and for which der, who can choose to accept, in which case
socialism no longer has any use. Engels the pie is divided as proposed, or to reject, in
writes that "justice is but the ideologised, which no one gets anything. In the ultima-
glorified expression of the existing economic tum games of David Kravitz and Samuel
Konou:: A Positive Analysis of Justice Theories 1199

Gunto (1992), responders are more likely to essential for tolerable living" and should be
accept low offers from (unknown to them, satisfied equally for all. Nevertheless, Raphael
fictitious) proposers who appeal to their own argues one must consider not only need but
need. Wulf Gaertner, Jochen Jungeilges, and also utilitarian concerns, i.e., the effects on
Reinhard Neck (2001) find between 66 per- incentives for efficiency: "Justice, then, is
cent and 93 percent of 340 college students thought to require a basic minimum of equal
surveyed prefer funding to satisfy the needs satisfactions ... Above that line, room is left
of a handicapped child over educating an for individuals to do as they think fit" (p. 54).
intelligent child. It is unclear, however, from Raphael's comments imply, similar to
these studies whether need is a justice prin- Rawls', a lexicographic ordering of goals:
ciple or some other distributive motive. basic needs take priority over other concerns
Moreover, studies of macro-justice paint a but, once satisfied, attention turns to effi-
different picture. McCloskey and Zaller ciency. The evidence cited above does sug-
(1984) report that only 20 percent in the gest that people care not only about need but
United States think a person's wages should also about adverse incentive effects of basing
depend on his needs versus the importance allocations solely on need, which is why they
of his job (N=938),and only 6 percent think oppose it as the foundation for a system of
it would be fairer to pay people's wages distribution. In addition, a scenario involving
according to economic need rather than a grant to an impoverished nation (Konow
based on how hard they work (N=967). 2001) provides specific evidence that satis-
Similarly, Kluegel and Smith (1986) find that faction of basic needs for food, shelter, and
only 13 percent of 1468 U.S. respondents clothing is considered "fair." Moreover, as
think a person's income should be based on efficiency is increasingly jeopardized in that
family needs rather than skills, although a scenario, the concern for basic needs dimin-
large minority of 41 percent agrees that it ishes and is eventually overruled by efficien-
would be fairer to pay people based on what cy, implying a tradeoff. Finally, in a survey
they needed to live rather than the kind of study by Helmut Lamm and Schwinger
work they do (N=669). These studies indi- (1980), respondents allocate earnings
cate that need affects distributive choices between two students who require different
and preferences but do not resolve whether amounts of money to purchase their books.
that fact is related to fairness. Most divisions are unequal, with average allo-
cations usually satisfying the differing needs.
2.4. The Need Principle
The following conclusions seem consis-
Basic needs often factored into the writings tent with the evidence presented here.
of political economists who lived during much Empirical studies provide almost no sup-
earlier stages of economic development (e.g., port for egalitarianism, understood as
Thomas Malthus 1798; Henry George 1879). equality of outcomes, or for Rawls's differ-
Today whole nations are protected from dire ence principle, although they do reveal a
need. Nevertheless, one out of every seven concern for the least advantaged, in line
people in the world still lives in hunger, with core ideas of Man, Rawls, and their
according to a United Nations agency followers. The themes of equality and need
(www.wfp.org). The philosopher D. D. can be found in a more defensible rule I
Raphael (1980) appeals for the primacy of will call the Need Principle: just allocations
equality and basic needs and claims that jus- provide for basic needs equally across indi-
tice demands there be "a basic minimum for viduals. Specifically, the evidence can be
all even if some of those affected could not reconciled with a multi-criterion justice
achieve it by their own efforts" (p. 56). Basic theory in which, as suggested by Raphael,
needs are the material means considered "as this concern tends to dominate when basic
1200 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XLI (December 2003)

T.~BLE
2. Question 2

2. Jane has baked 6 pies to give to her two friends, Ann and Betty, who do not know each other. Betty enjoys pie
twice as much as Ann. In distributing the pies, what is fairer:
A. 2 pies to Ann and 4 to Betty, or 40%
B. 4 pies to Ann and 2 to Betty, or 4%
C. 3 pies to each? 56%
x=211

needs are endangered. Nevertheless, when produce the greatest possible balance of
needs differ across individuals, satisfying good over bad, where good is understood to
needs at an equal level implies unequal mean happiness or pleasure. Jeremy
material allocations. In addition, this princi- Bentham, who is responsible for the first
ple is not absolute: preferences over it are precise formulation of this theory (1789),
not lexicographic but are instead consistent advocated what is sometimes called act util-
with a trade-off between need and other itarianisin. According to Bentham, one
distributive goals. should at every moment act so as to pro-
mote the greatest aggregate happiness. This
3. Utilitarianism and Welfare Econo~nics
is contrasted with the views of another
Much evidence, such as that cited in the famous utilitarian philosopher and political
previous section regarding efficiency, indi- economist, John Stuart Mill, who champi-
cates that people care about outcomes at the oned a version now usually called rule utili-
social, and not just individual, levels. The tarianism (1861). Mill proposed that one act
theories discussed in this section share the according to the general rules of conduct
property that they reflect a concern for the that produce the greatest happiness (e.g.,
overall consequences of allocations or alloca- never lie, never steal), even if the rules do
tion schemes. In moral philosophy, these not maximize aggregate happiness in every
belong to the school of consequentialist the- instance. For Mill, justice is the most
ories, which judge the rightness of an act important and binding subset of these
based on its consequences. These are con- inoral rules.
trasted, for example, with deontological the- Welfare economics is derived from act
ories, which stress the relevance of other fac- utilitarianism. Economic acts, i.e., choices,
tors, such as the Kantian concern with are evaluated in terms of their consequences
intentions, in evaluating the morality of an for social welfare. This, in turn, typically
act. Most of normative economics is firmly depends on a composite evaluation of indi-
rooted in consequentialist ethics, having vidual welfare or utility, an approach
grown philosophically out of the Utilitarian Amartya Sen calls welfaris71z (1979).
traditions of Bentham and Mill. This is Classical economists, keeping with
apparent in the prominent place welfare Bentham, assumed individual utility to be
economics assigns to efficiency, a concern cardinally measurable and interpersonally
we will consider as a principle of justice. comparable and aggregated individual utili-
ties additively to derive social welfare.
Utilitarianism implies that resources be allo-
Utilitarianism is the leading consequen- cated first to the person who derives the
tialist theory of ethics and the chief forebear greater marginal utility. Consider question 2
in the lineage of welfare economics. It is the in table 2. According to utilitarianism, A is
moral doctrine that one should act so as to the preferred choice among these three
Konow: A Positive Analysis of Justice Theories 1201

because the largest amount goes to the per- vary the benefit to one of the indwiduals and
son who derives the greatest pleasure. In ask subjects to choose the fairest of five
fact, a large minority of respondents (40 per- quantitative allocations. In two versions (Q1
cent) identifies this as fairest. Alternative B, and Q2), an identical 82 percent of the
which is chosen by only 4 percent, suggests respondents (N= 163 and N = 146, respective-
equality across individuals, not at the mar- ly) choose unequal quantities of the foods to
gin, but in total levels of utility, a concept of each person in order to equalize the total
justice implied by Sen's Weak Equity Axiom derived health benefit to them.'' Other stud-
(1973, p. 18). Nevertheless, a small majority ies provide support for the use of subjective
(56 percent) selects an equal split of the values. 69 percent of 81 college respondents
resource. to question 1D in Konow (1996) regard as
Utilitarianism proposes that welfare com- fair an unequal distribution of food that pro-
parisons be made, not on the basis of goods duces an equal level of satisfaction. Similarly,
or money, but rather using the subjective Gerald Leventhal, Jurgis Karuza, and
values derived from goods, money, etc. This William Fry (1980) conclude based on survey
raises the question of the appropriate metric studies that "The emphasis is on equalizing
ofjustice, that is, of the unit of account for the members' psychic gratification rather
justice evaluation, and whether it should be than actual outcomes" (pp. 182-83). Overall,
allocable variables such as goods and money, the evidence suggests that derived values are
or derived values such as health, satisfaction, important for justice evaluation and that
pleasure and happiness. The results to ques- maximization of these values holds some
tion 2 seem mixed: the majority choice of C sway, but that fairness is associated more
suggests a preference for equality in goods, with the equalization of derived totals.
but the relatively strong showing for A
3.2. Pc~retoPrinciples
implies that pleasure has significant pull.
Another possibility is that utilitarianism cor- Around the turn of the twentieth century,
rectly emphasizes subjective values but that Vilfredo Pareto (1906) defined a means for
C strikes a compromise between maximizing analyzing social welfare that does not rest on
total utility and equalizing utility across indi- the strong cardinality and comparability
viduals along the lines Sen suggests. assumptions of utilitarianism. Although util-
The close split on question 2 is not typical itarianism continues to find its defenders
of survey findings on this issue or on fairness (e.g., see Harsanyi 1955, 1975), the Pareto
preferences, in general.10 Most evidence Principle has been more widely embraced by
favors Sen's thesis. Yaari and Bar-Hillel
(1984) present college applicants in Israel " The other questions in this study, however, generate
with a scenario in which two individuals disperse responses, and no single category garners the sup-
port of a significant majority. Yaari and Bar-Hillel conclude
metabolize the nutritional value of two foods that "The only general conclusion which we are prepared
differently. Different versions of the question to draw from our work so far is that a satisfactory theory of
distributive justice would have to be endowed with con-
siderable detail and finesse" (p. 22). Their seminal study
lo A clear and significant majority response emerges makes important contributions by employing survey tech-
for almost all questions in our survey. The evidence indi- niques for the comparison of justice concepts, by
cates that more evenly divided responses are due, not to approaching fairness research as an ongoing process of dis-
major divisions of opinion among respondents, but rather covery and revision and by establishing some important
to the fact that the views of most are close to indifference findings in this area. I believe that the inability to draw
between the response categories (e.g., see the results of clearer conclusions from many of their questions is proba-
question 8 in Konow 2001; see footnote 11 for other rea- bly due to the facts that the theories they set out to test are
sons). The close splits found in question 2 and versions of not specifically justice theories, and that many of the sce-
question 3 are less typical but are reported here to narios are too complex for most respondents to evaluate
demonstrate with brevity the effects of multiple goals or with reference to their moral intuition, indeed perhaps for
principles. many to evaluate by any standard.
Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XLZ (December 2003)

economists as embodying an ostensibly continuous public goods analogues subjects


innocuous value judgment, namely, it choose a level of cooperation through
endorses any change that makes someone amounts contributed to a public good. In
better off without making anyone else worse either case, the equilibrium of rational, self-
off. Despite the fact that this concept is tout- interested subjects is Pareto dominated by a
ed as relying on weaker informational and cooperative outcome. Alvin Roth (1995)
ethical conditions than utilitarianism, certain reports that prisoner's dilemma experiments
of its deficiencies have also been noted, usually yield cooperation bounded well away
among others, that it does not produce a from both zero and 100 percent. John
complete ordering of allocations. In (not Ledyard (1995) finds that total contributions
entirely successful) attempts to overcome in public goods experiments typically lie
this shortcoming, variations and refine- between 40 and 60 percent of the group
ments, generically known as the optimum. These results are favorable to the
Compensation Principle, have been pro- Pareto Criterion, although, of course, coop-
posed by Nicholas Kaldor (1939), John eration in these studies might also be moti-
Hicks (1940), Scitovsky (1941), and Paul vated by altruism or equity. Comparing, say,
Samuelson (1950). The Compensation public goods experiments to dictator experi-
Principle endorses any change in which the ments, however, a distinguishing feature of
gains of some are more than sufficient to the former is the size of total surplus, a con-
compensate any losses of others, even if the cern that is reinforced by (the possibility of)
prescribed compensation does not actually partial compensation for cooperation.
occur.12 In a further step away from the Moreover, public goods contributions tend
Pareto Principle, all measurable gains and to run higher than the usual average dictator
losses are often treated equally, in which contributions of about 5 to 25 percent.
case the Pareto Principle reduces to the Bargaining experiments provide more
maximization of allocable variables such as compelling evidence of an efficiency motive.
surplus or wealth. Pareto himself did not In Hoffman and Matthew Spitzer (1985) two
portray his principle as a justice theory, but subjects are presented with sets of alloca-
this version of his principle has been inter- tions that generate different individual and
preted as such, e.g., by Richard Posner in his joint payoffs. One of the subjects is the con-
book The Economics of Justice (1981). troller, the person who can choose unilater-
Although careful to set his views apart from ally the payoffs. The controller is selected by
utilitarianism, Posner defends the claim that winning a preliminary game or randomly by
justice be equated with economic efficiency, a coin flip, depending on the treatment. In
specifically, with wealth maximization. face-to-face negotiations, however, the other
Certain experimental results intimate a subject can attempt to persuade the con-
concern for Pareto efficiency. In prisoner's troller to choose specific payoffs and to agree
dilemma experiments subjects make a to transfers of payoffs between the parties.
discrete decision about whether to cooper- Although the controller is essentially a dicta-
ate with one another, whereas in the more tor, 91 percent of Hoffman and Spitzer's 86
pairs reach agreements that maximize joint
-
12The basic Pareto construct is the strong Pareto
Criterion, which states that an allocation, X,is Pareto pre-
surplus, and about one-half of the transfer
deiisions result in equal or near equal splits,
ferred to (or Pareto dominates) another, Y,if at least one
person is better off, and no one is worse off, with X than meaning that was often achieved
with Y.The simple version of the Compensation Principle at some sacrifice to controllers. Prompted by
states that an allocation, X,is preferred to another, Y,if it the ~ ~ and spitzer
f experiment,
f ~ paul ~ ~
is potentially Pareto preferred, that is, if it is h~pothetical-
ly possible to undertake lump-sum redistribution from X to and Graham ( lgg4)
achieve an allocation that Pareto dominates 2 '. explore a variation that allows pairs of
Konow: A Positive Analysis of Justice Theories

subjects (N = 104) to engage in mutually equal splits, and around 22 percent act effi-
beneficial trades from guaranteed initial ciently, tending to maximize total surplus.
earnings. They find that 97 percent of their On average, though, dictators give them-
584 negotiations maximize joint payoffs. selves a larger payoff than their counterparts
These experiments with direct negotiation when giving lowers or does not change the
support surplus maximization under condi- total (at four of four such prices) and give
tions that, through the availability of transfers, their counterparts a larger payoff than them-
permit, not only potential, but actual Pareto selves when giving increases the total (at two
improvements. How is this goal affected in of three such prices).
the absence of transfers and direct negotia- These experiments suggest that many
tion? Gary Charness and Brit Grosskopf subjects are motivated to maximize surplus,
(2001) conduct dictator-like experiments in but they do not resolve whether people
which the "dictators" face anonymous coun- regard this motive as fair. In table 3, ques-
terparts and select between two allocations: tion 3, which appears in different versions,
one gives equal payoffs to both and the other seeks to address this. Question 3A asks sub-
involves unequal payoffs, usually favoring the jects to decide whether it is fair to adopt the
counterpart, that sum to more than the equal more efficient policy X, which produces a
payoffs. Between 66 percent and 88 percent total of 240 but creates unequal benefits,
of dictators (N = 61) choose allocations that over policy Y, which produces a smaller total
maximize total surplus, giving their counter- of only 200 but divides the benefits equally.
parts up to twice as much as themselves, Sixty-two percent of respondents deem the
sometimes even at a small sacrifice. Charness choice of the efficient policy fair.
and Rabin (2002) find a similar willingness to Nevertheless, this support is quite labile, as
sacrifice in order to increase the total, revealed by two other versions of the ques-
although in the games they study this willing- tion. These versions are identical to A except
ness varies with relative payoffs and with the for variations in the size of the total benefits
previous choices of counterparts. Alexander from policy X,which are identified by itali-
Kritikos and Friedel Bolle (2001) similarly cized passages. In version B the total under
find that 58-100 percent of dictators (N = 80) X decreases to 210, whereas in C the total
in a binary choice dictator game prefer allo- under X rises to 290, and in both cases sup-
cations that maximize earnings over ones that port for X slips versus version A.13 Although
are more equal or even that favor themselves. these shifts are not significant, stronger
Perhaps the most thorough study related results have been reported for a similar sce-
to the efficiency motive is that of James nario. Four versions of question 5 in Konow
Andreoni and John Miller (2002). In their (2001) identify solid support for the strong
variation on the dictator game, dictators Pareto Criterion but weaker backing for the
select gifts under conditions that differ Compensation Principle. Moreover, the
according to budget size and price of giving fragility of efficiency as it conflicts with
money to counterparts. The latter is manip- other principles of justice is demonstrated
ulated in the sense that one dollar foregone there by statistically significant shifts in
by the dictator increases the counterpart's support across versions.
payoff by $0.25, $0.33, $0.50, $1, $2, $3, or At the macro level, efficiency appears to
$4. Andreoni and Miller find that the vast figure more prominently in views of fairness.
majority of subjects (N = 176) have well- McCloskey and Zaller (1984) report that 78
behaved preferences for giving, falling into
one of three categories: about 47 percent act "' he weakened support in version B reflects perhaps
the view that the efficiency benefit is insufficient to justify
selfishly, keeping nearly all for themselves, the inequality, whereas the increased inequality in version
30 percent tend to allocate so as to achieve C is perhaps seen as intolerably large.
1204 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XLI (December 2003)

TABLE3. Question 3

3A. Suppose, as used to be the case, that the US government makes land available to farmers at no cost provided
they reside on their claim and cultivate it. Each farmer may sell whatever he produces. Suppose as well that there
are just two applicants, Farmer Adams and Farmer Brown, interested in two tracts of land, 1and 2. Tract 1is more
productive than tract 2 and the tracts are located too far apart for one applicant to work both. The government may
choose among one of the following two policies, X or Y:
X. Farmer A d a m gets tract 1 and produces 150 bushels of wheat and Farmer Brown gets tract 2 and produces
90 bushels for a total of 240.
Y. Farmer Adams and Farmer Brown share tract 1 evenly whereby each then produces 100 bushels for a total
of 200.
The government chooses policy X. Please rate this as fair or unfair:
Fair 62% Unfair 38% N = 104

3B. ...
X. Farmer A d a m gets tract 1 and produces 120 bushels of wheat and Farmer Brown gets tract 2 and produces
90 bushels for a total of 210. . . .
Fair 52% Unfair 48% N = 105

3 C . ...
X. Farmer A d a m gets tract 1 and produces 200 bushels of wheat and Farmer Brown gets tract 2 and produces
90 buslzels for a total of 290. . . .
Fair 55% Unfair 45% N = 109

percent of 938 respondents find that "Under another. The no envy criterion has been gen-
a fair economic system people with more eralized to include considerations of number
ability would earn higher salaries." This is of agents, groups of agents, common choice
presumably because, as 85 percent of 967 sets, envy-free trades, leisure, output and
persons surveyed agree, "Giving everyone labor ability and has spawned the concept of
about the same income regardless of the egalitarian equivalence.
type of work they do would destroy the Absence of envy is an appealing construct
desire to work hard and do a better job." and seems like a reasonable goal. The ques-
tion asked in this study, however, is whether
3.3. Absence of Envy
it describes allocations people call fair, or
The theory of fairness with the purest eco- whether it is distinct. Robin Boadway and
nomic pedigree, and the usual definition of Neil Bruce (1984) are skeptical about equat-
equity in welfare economics, is the absence ing the two: "I might envy a friend's lucky
of envy criterion. The concept was first for- find in an antique store yet perceive no
mally stated by Duncan Foley (1967) and 'unfairness' that he, not I, owns it" (p. 175).
was further developed by Hal Varian (1974), This inspired question 4 in table 4, which
Elisha Pazner and David Schmeidler (1978), tests the simple envy-free concept that
William J. Baumol (1986), and others. Part applies to final allocations only. Even though
of the motivation for this research agenda is respondents are encouraged in this scenario
as a way to narrow the set of permissible to "envy" the other's allocation, a sizable 87
Pareto optima, thereby identifying alloca- percent judge it fair. It is possible, though,
tions that are both efficient and equitable. In that respondents would be envy-free if one
the simplest form, an allocation is envy-free interpreted the bundle more broadly, e.g., to
if no agent prefers (i.e., envies) the bundle of include the time spent searching for the
Konow: A Positive Analysis of Justice Theories 1205

TABLE4. Questions 4 and 5

4. You and an acquaintance would both like to have a rare record album. Your acquaintance spends several hours
a week looking in used record stores whereas you never bother to look. The acquaintance finds the album.
Fair 87% Unfair 13% N = 299

5. Chris, who is blind, does not like TV and Pat, who is a vegetarian, does not like hamburger. Suppose that Chris
and Pat work for the same company in the same capacity and earn the same base salaly. The time comes for the
end of the year bonus. Chris, who works much harder than Pat, receives a $2 coupon for a hamburger. The less
productive Pat, on the other hand, receives as a bonus a $2000 wide screen television.
Fair 10% Unfair 90% N = 260

album.'* Question 5, also in table 4, howev- necessarily at odds with justice but instead is
er, is free of this concern. In this scenario, itself a type of justice. Results reported in
although one person works harder, both McCloskey and Zaller (1984) show that effi-
individuals receive as bonuses goods that the ciency figures prominently in popular con-
other could not possibly desire regardless of ceptions of a fair economic system. At the
work effort, but 90 percent of respondents micro-justice level, however, support for the
find this unfair. Pareto Principles is sensitive to the size of
Absence of envy is questionable not only benefits, and other results (Konow 2001)
as a description of justice but also of what is indicate that efficiency can be overturned by
meant by envy in common parlance: it seems competing justice principles. Utilitarianism
quite possible that I would like to have challenges us to think of efficiency, and jus-
another person's allocation, but that I do not tice, not only in terms of goods or wealth
experience the resentful feeling about his but, where possible, of the subjective values
advantage that the word envy typically con- derived from them. The metric, or the unit
notes. Randall Holcombe (1997) similarly of account, of justice turns out to be an
rejects equating fairness with absence of important issue and one to which we will
envy, He faults the envy-free criterion for return in section 5. The evidence in this sec-
examining only outcomes and argues that tion also indicates that the maximization of
justice requires that one look at the process derived values does exercise some pull on
by which the outcome obtains. This seems views of justice, although the mixed results
consistent with the results of questions 4 and suggest that, as with goods or wealth, the
5, in which rewards conflict with individual maximization of these values is not the sin-
contributions. These results support the gle goal of fairness. Many of the counterex-
claim that justice requires consideration of amples to efficiency point toward equalizing
relative merits associated with the process by values, which seems to contradict the rejec-
which outcomes are generated as well as of tion of egalitarianism in section 2. As we will
the magnitude of the outcomes. see in the following sections, however,
equality can be relegated to a special case
3.4. The EfJiciency Principle
within justice principles that generally call
Various studies have demonstrated that for inequality. The evidence on the absence
people often seek to maximize surplus, of envy criterion underscores the main con-
sometimes at a personal cost, and that this clusion of this section: although justice
goal is regarded as "fair." These findings requires consideration of the consequences
suggest that efficiency in this sense is not of acts, specifically, of the size of total sur-
plus, the efficiency criterion is too austere to
l4 I am indebted to a referee for this point. serve as a general theory of justice. One
1206 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XLI (December 2003)

must also attend to the process by which became owned, and the principle of justice
outcomes obtain, and this is central to the in transfer, which addresses the transfer of
theories discussed in the following section. holdings from one person to another. Nozick
cites as violations of these principles hold-
ings that result from theft, fraud, enslave-
4. Equity and Desert
ment and forcible exclusion from competing
The common thread in this class of theo- in exchange. Nevertheless, he fails to spell
ries is the presumed dependence of fair allo- out details of how his theory applies to spe-
cations on individual actions. This contrasts cific situations or social systems. What is
with the motive investigated in section 2 to emphasized and exposited with some speci-
satisfy needs or in section 3 to maximize sur- ficity, however, is the asserted justice of
plus, with no necessa y dependence on indi- holdings that result from free choices, best
vidual actions. Theories of equity and desert illustrated by Nozick's often cited "Wilt
are the intellectual progeny of two philosoph- Chamberlain" example. In this thought
ical traditions: the distributive justice theory experiment, the reader is first asked to sup-
of Aristotle and the natural lawldesert theory pose that the initial distribution, call it Dl,
of John Locke. This section presents theories perfectly satisfies whatever justice principle
and explores evidence on the questions of the reader favors. Then fans drop a separate
desert, i.e., which individual characteristics admission price into a special box for
are relevant to justice, and of equity, i.e., Chamberlain, which results in his receiving
what, exactly, the functional relationship is of much larger income than anyone else.
individual characteristics to just allocations. Nozick challenges the reader to find the new
distribution, D2, unjust since people volun-
4.1. Nozick
tarily moved to it. Note there is no conflict in
The political philosopher Robert Nozick this example with just acquisition because
occupies a position at one extreme in this the reader is free to presuppose any original
class of theories. In Anarchy, State and distribution, D l . Instead, this example
Utopia (1974), Nozick argues that justice is addresses justice in transfer.
exclusively concerned with rights that are I know of no previous empirical tests of
determined by the historical acquisition by the entitlement theory, even of the celebrat-
and transfer of property among individuals. ed Chamberlain case, so I asked a somewhat
Thus, he argues that justice has nothing to updated variation on this scenario. Question
do with Rawls's original position, in which 6 in table 5 considers the case of Michael
history does not yet exist, or with end-state Jordan, who in a similar manner receives
theories, such as utilitarianism, which ignore $25 million (actually modest, in comparison
history. Each approach is, in a sense, either to his actual earnings) from one inillion fans
too early or too late. Moreover, Nozick is a who drop $25 each into his box during one
fervent advocate of individually based fair- season. In version A, this follows a redistrib-
ness over attempts to promote the social ution of wealth according to the respon-
good. Individual choice is paramount, as dent's favorite distribution, along the lines of
demonstrated in his modification of the Nozick's Dl. Nevertheless, 59 percent of
Marxian maxim "From each as they choose, respondents judge the post-season distribu-
to each as they are chosen" (p. 160). tion, D2, unfair, in contradiction to the prin-
Nozick's "entitlement" theory of justice ciple of justice in transfer. In version B of
concerns the rights of individuals to their this question, the assumed redistribution to
possessions or "holdings." The core of his fair levels follows, rather than proceeds, the
theory is two principles: the principle ofjus- basketball season, and there is a significant
tice i n acquisition, or how things originally increase in the proportion of respondents
Konow: A Positiue Analysis of Justice Theories 1207

TABLE5. Question 6

6A. Suppose tlzat you are able to change the wealth ofece y o n e in the world to the kcels tlzat you consider nwst
fail: Let us say that you do so. Now suppose that Alichael Jordan, being greatly in demand, signs the following con-
tract with a team: in each home game, $25 from the price of each ticket of admission goes to him. The season starts,
and as people buy their tickets, they drop a separate $25 of their admission price into a special box with Jordan's
name on it. At the end of the season, 1 million people attend his home games, and Michael Jordan winds up with
$25 million. Please rateJordan's earnings as:
Fair 41% Unfair 59% N = 137

6B Suppose that Jfzchael Jordan, Now suppose that you are able to change the z~ealtho f e ~yeo n e zn the world
to the lecels tlzat you conszder most fazr Let us say tlzat you do so \Vould Jordan stzll earn $25 inzllzon
J

Yes 24% No 76% N=83

(76 percent) who deem Jordan's salary that is not supported by the evidence. The
unfair ( P = .01).15 One reading of this following section attempts to clarify desert,
increased opposition to D2 in version B ver- i.e., the quality that makes certain variables
sus A is that respondents also expect the ini- relevant to justice, and to demonstrate that
tial distribution, Dl, to be unfair, i.e., the justice is related to choice, but not in the
final distribution in B results not only from broad sense implied by Nozick.
the current unfair transfers but, presumably,
4.2. Theories of Desert
from previous unfair acquisitions and trans-
fers. That is, people mistrust not only histor- A good point of departure for a discussion
ical transfers but perhaps also original acqui- of desert is the justice theory of James
sitions. These results cast doubt on broad Buchanan (1986).Of the theories discussed in
support for Nozick's minimal role for wealth this section, Buchanan's is closest to Nozick's
redistribution.16 in terms of the wide berth given to inhvidual
Nozick has a very broad conception of the action and the limited role envisioned for
individual choices that may be construed as state intervention. Nevertheless, Buchanan,
just. The minimal role he foresees for the in contrast to Nozick but similar to Rawls, for-
state suggests the view that allocations mulates a contractarian theory, although his
resulting from unencumbered processes do builds upon a very different set of claims
not, except to a minor degree, diverge from about inhvidual preferences from Rawls's.
those prescribed by justice. As a description Justice is chiefly relevant in the constitutional
of actual justice views, Nozick's theory has phase in which people establish a contract for
merit for highlighting the individual and the the rules of the game. Buchanan identifies
role of choice. Its focus on process makes four factors that determine the distribution of
it an early treatment of procedural justice claims on economic income and wealth: luck,
(see section 5.2). The entitlement theory, choice, effort, and birth. He considers the rel-
however, says that all allocations resulting evance of effort least controversial but
from freely chosen transfers are fair, a claim believes that the only inequalities that conflict
with common views of justice are ones caused
ls In this paper. P-values refer to significance levels
only by the fourth factor, birth (pp. 129-30).
from two-tailed tests of differences in cited proportions.
l6 Another interpretation of the difference in the mag- At the opposite extreme, a common view
nitude of opposition to the entitlement theory bet\veen is that differences owing to birth, luck and
these t\vo versions of question 6 is that version A makes the choice are all unfair and that only differ-
ostensible justice of the volunta~)transfer process more
salient. But then its failure to find strong support when it ences attributable to effort are fair. A fre-
comes under closer scrutiny is even more significant. quent finding (and claim) of social scientists
1208 Journal of Economic Lite rature, Vol. XLI (December2003)

is that individual effort affects the perceived Michaels (1971) conduct an experiment with
fairness of allocations. This is consistent with 32 college students who are paid a fixed fee
the results to Questions l B , l C , 4, and 5 of to evaluate rewards to different hypothetical
this paper. Some argue that those who individuals. In this study, subjects are told
expend greater effort are more deserving (erroneously) that their responses will deter-
but that other characteristics, such as talent, mine the payments that will be given to par-
intelligence, physical skill, educational ticipants in a later study of physical perform-
opportunities, etc., are irrelevant and should ance (a vertical jump test), and that the goal
not affect rewards. A corollarv i
is that for is to devise the fairest schedule of payments.
each "type," i.e., set of irrelevant characteris- The hypothetical individuals differ along
tics, rewards should vary positively with four dimensions: body height, training,
effort and be equal for those who expend the effort and performance. The results of
same effort. Indeed, Tohn Roemer (1998) Leventhal and Harold Whiteside (1973) sug-
argues for taking this "one step further: he gest that performance is rewarded as a dis-
sees effort partially as a characteristic of type tinct concern from desert, as a kind of effi-
and one for which a Derson should not be
I
ciency motive. For a given level of
held entirely accountable. performance, though, Leventhal and
Most evidence casts doubt on birth and Michaels find that desert varies directly with
emphasizes effort as a determinant of jus- effort and inversely with height, which is
tice.17 For example, Leventhal and James mostly a characteristic of birth, and training,
which is chosen for and not by the hypothet-
ical individuals.
l 7 One finding that is anomalous in several respects is
reported in Schokkaert and Capeau (1991). A scenario Numerous studies have examined the role
there calls for respondents to select the most fair division of effort versus luck in fair allocations. For
of a bonus between two salesmen. In one version of this example, in the Hoffman and Spitzer (1985)
question, one of the salesmen brings in more orders than
the other, which is attributed to differences in effort, and experiment discussed in section 3.2, one
85 percent of students (N = 40) and 90 percent of parents person from each of the 86 bargaining pairs
(of a different group of students, N = 50) distribute most of (the controller) is in an advantaged position
the bonus to the salesman who exerts greater effort. The
results for another variation on this question, though, sug- because of either winning a game of skill or
gest a role for innate traits, which even Buchanan consid- because of the toss of a coin, depending on
ers irrelevant: in this version the difference in orders is due the treatment. In the coin toss treatment,
to the fact that one of the salesmen has greater "natural
charm." Interestingly, a majority of both students and par- most subjects agree to equal or near equal
ents support an unequal division favoring the more charm- splits, whereas in the game treatment, there
ing salesman. As previously mentioned, Schokkaert and is a significant tendency for the controller to
Capeau conclude that subject pool effects are not serious,
but here we see that this support is significantly stronger receive a larger fraction, a tendency that is
( P = .02) among parents (76 percent, N = 55) than among reinforced if subjects are told that the con-
students (56 percent, N = 39), where most of the remain- trollers "earned" that right. Hoffman and
ing students (41 percent) favor equality. These results are
based on small samples, but, assuming they are robust, a Spitzer conclude that subjects care about
plausible explanation for them, and for the difference expenditure of effort but not about luck.
between the two populations, is the presence of an effi- Burrows and Loomes (1994) come to similar
ciency concern: rewarding the more talented individual
promotes productivity by giving the person with the conclusions based on a two-stage bargaining
greater marginal product an incentive to work harder and experiment. Specifically, in Stage 1,104 sub-
by encouraging an efficient allocation of labor, perhaps by jects are assigned random endowments after
prompting the less talented individual to switch to a job in
which his comparative talents are greater. This seems more which they engage paimise in face-to-face
likely to be a concern of parents than of students since the bargaining over trades designed to generate
former typically have more work experience and are more mutual benefits. In Stage 2 , 4 7 subjects who
sensitized to such issues (section 5 discusses how justice
preferences can be both based on general principles but had participated in Stage 1 earn their
context- and, therefore, experience-dependent). endowment based on their performance in a
Konou;: A Positive Analysis of Justice Theories 1209

word search task before bargaining over luck is not, such that the consequences of
trades. After Stage 1bargaining, 64 percent the former are fair whereas those of the lat-
of trades generate equal final payoffs. After ter are not.
Stage 2 bargaining, however, 72 percent of The fact that option luck and brute luck are
final payoffs are unequal and favor the sub- often intertwined complicates the task of
ject with the better performance in the task. finding clear measures of each. The level and
Burrows and Loomes conclude "that many quality of one's education, for example, are
people believe that when different individu- affected partly by the hazards of birth, e.g.,
als have a similar ability and opportunity to parents' education, local schools, etc. On the
put in effort, those that put in more effort other hand, education also reflects individual
should get a greater reward because they are choices that involve calculated gambles, e.g.,
relatively deserving. . . . By contrast, when effort expended, years of schooling, and
initial endowments were determined by degree programs selected, which in turn
chance, the majority of participants did not affect one's productivity. Schokkaert and Leo
attempt to sustain the differentials in the Lagrou (1983) asked 180 adult professional
bargaining that followed" (pp. 220-21). active men to estimate the actual average
Finally, Bradley Ruffle (1998) conducts dic- income as well as the fair income for twelve
tator and ultimatum experiments (N = 108 well-known occupations. With few excep-
and N = 102, respectively) involving a coin tions, individuals whose occupations require
toss in one set of treatments and relative per- greater training or education are generally
formance on a general knowledge and skill- seen as deserving higher incomes. In addi-
testing quiz in another set of treatments. He tion, the rankings of fair and actual incomes
also concludes that giving is motivated most- are strihngly similar, although the distribu-
ly by a concern for fairness that is based on tion of fair incomes is much more compressed
effort, not luck. than that of estimated actual incomes.
Thus far, desert appears to be related to A conjecture suggested by this and similar
effort but not to birth or luck. What of studies is that fair incomes roughly preserve
Buchanan's fourth characteristic, choice? the ranking of actual incomes because the
Ronald Dworkin proposes a political theory latter reflect fairly well the value (mediated
that emphasizes equality but that tolerates by markets) that society places on individual
the limited measure of inequality that he contributions, i.e., a more temperate version
argues would follow by allowing the effects of Nozick's idea that rewards should depend
of choice alone to operate. He states that on being chosen. Moreover, incomes corre-
"individuals should be relieved of conse- late positively with education because of the
quential responsibility for those unfortunate usual increased productivity. Education
features of their situation that are brute bad does not confer higher fair income, however,
luck, but not from those that should be seen if it is not accompanied by greater produc-
as flowing from their own choices" (2000, p. tivity, consistent with the findings that 83
287). He makes a helpful distinction percent (N = 670) agree to pay workers
between two types of luck: "Option luck is a more for producing more, but that 74 per-
matter of how deliberate and calculated cent (N = 668) disagree with paying more to
gambles turn out-whether someone gains the person with more education when two
or loses through accepting an isolated risk he people are doing the same type of work
or she should have anticipated and might (Kluegel and Smith 1986). In Overlaet
have declined. Brute luck is a matter of how (1991) respondents choose the fairest distri-
risks fall out that are not in that sense delib- bution of a bonus between two workers who
erate gambles" (1981, p. 293). Option luck, perform the same job and work equally
then, is a matter of choice, whereas brute hard. Equal splits are chosen by 68 percent
1210 Jour~zalof Economic Literature, Vol. XLI (December 2003)

of respondents (N = 50) when the workers are responsible, but not if it is due to factors
differ by education and by 88 percent (N = outside their control.lg
52) when they differ by position. In another This concept of desert helps explain vari-
variant, however, 86 percent (N = 52) give ous experimental results. For instance,
more to the worker who exerts greater responders in the ultimatum games of Kagel,
effort. Thus, equal splits are preferred when Chung Kim, and Donald Moser (1996) are
the descriptions of education and position significantly more likely to reject low offers
suggest they do not impact productivity, but when proposers make deliberately low and
a greater contribution, and therefore unfair offers than when proposers are not
reward, is im lied when one worker exerts aware of, and therefore not responsible for,
greater effort.q 8 the meager offers. The design of Sally
These results indicate that desert incorpo- Blount's (1995) ultimatum experiments on
rates effort and choices that affect an indi- 231 MBA students is explicitly informed by
vidual's contribution, but it disregards birth, attribution theory. In different treatments,
(brute) luck, and choices that do not affect responders are told that the proposed split
productivity. This suggests a general charac- was made by a random number generator, a
teristic for distinguishing variables relevant neutral third party or a proposer.
to justice along the lines of attribution theo- Responders are significantly more milling to
nj (e.g., Fritz Heider 1958, Julian Rotter accept unfair offers that are random than
1966; and Bernard Ilieiner and Andy Kukla ones that come from the proposer or a third
1970). Attribution theory is a social psychol- party, consistent with attribution of responsi-
ogy theory that purports to explain behavior bility. Using results of attitude surveys from
based on causal attributions of responsibility. a random national sample of 3626 labor-
That is, attribution theorists say that people force participants, Fong (2001) finds a
infer causes of events and are motivated to strong positive relationship between support
assign responsibility to agents for those for income redistribution and beliefs that
events. Ilihen so doing, people evaluate the one's fortune is determined by forces outside
extent to which an agent has contributed to one's control. Advocates of redistribution,
the outcome, specifically, they hold an agent for example, believe that wealth is caused by
accountable only for those factors that the external circumstances and that bad luck as
agent can influence. Although its creators opposed to lack of effort causes poverty. In
envisioned attribution theory as a general this spirit, Samuel Bowles and Herbert
behavioral theory, its application in the cur- Gintis (1998) propose a system of asset-
rent context to justice is obvious: desert is based redistribution that tends toward
directly related to individual responsibility equality while compensating agents for their
for contributions to outcomes. Those who actions.
contribute more are more deserving if their Studies that explicitly elicit fairness pref-
contribution is due to factors for which they erences have come to similar conclusions,

'' The result that 68 percent (N = 50) believe seniority


warrants greater pal- is less clear-cut as respondents might lg The nomenclature of this school implies that the
infer several factors. For instance, the more senior worker motivation of interest resides with the individual assessing
might be more productive because of experience. the outcome rather than the agent, and that it is not solell-
Rewarding this worker's choice to remain with the employ- or even mostly an ethical theory The desert concept we
er could also promote efficiencl- because it helps the are investigating here, on the other hand, focuses on the
employer avoid search and training costs. In addition, responsibility of the agent, rather than another's attribu-
respondents might assume that the more senior worker's tion of the agent's responsibility, and views this primarill- as
needs are greater than those of a presumed newcomer to a moral issue. Regardless of these different points of view,
the labor market, i.e., that she is more likely to have however, attribution t h e o offers
~ a promising criterion for
children, a mortgage, etc. distinguishing the variables that determine desert.
Konou;: A Positive Analysis oflustice Theories 1211

much of which is summarized in Ronald 4.3. EauituJ Theoru


I J

Cohen (1982) and Weiner et al. (1971).


Equity theory originated with the work of
More recently, Lisa Farwell and Weiner
sociologists and social psychologists includ-
(1996) conduct six survey studies with 948
ing George Homans (1958); J. Stacy Adams
undergraduates that examine the effect of
(1965); and Elaine Walster, G. William
perceived responsibility on fair rewards and
Walster, and Ellen Berscheid (1973). Similar
punishments in a variety of contexts. Their
to attribution theory, proponents of equity
scenarios include poor class performance
theory had ambitions for developing a gen-
because of low effort versus low aptitude,
eral theory of social interaction. Unlike attri-
spilling a drink at a party because of gestur-
bution theory, however, equity theory was,
ing carelessly versus being bumped, and
from its inception, designed with the intent
acquiring AIDS because of promiscuous sex
to elucidate the role of justice in social inter-
versus from a blood transfusion. They find
action. It has also informed the work of
that "a responsibility-based equity rule was
economists, including Reinhard Selten
considered an appropriate basis for alloca-
(1978) and Giith (1994). Equity theorists
tions even in the case of AIDS" (p. 878). The
typically trace the origins of their approach
Schokkaert and Lagrou (1983) study asks
to Aristotle's Nicoinachean Ethics (1925). In
180 adults to evaluate the fairness of fifteen
the fourth century B.C., Aristotle explicated
possible justifications for income differ-
a theory of justice based on proportionality.
ences. The majority responses are generally
In equity theory, Aristotle's proposition is
consistent with rewarding choices that are
usually expressed for two persons, A and B,
more highly valued and for which agents
in terms of outcomes, denoted 0, and
may be held accountable, e.g., for responsi-
inputs, denoted I, as the equity formula:
bility, carrying risks, effort, and education,
but not for intellectual versus manual labor,
private versus public employment, or white-
collar versus blue-collar. Some other results
are more ambiguous, such as the support for Inputs are usually thought of as a participant's
income differences based on family size or contributions to an exchange and outcomes as
being a scarce specialist. These probably the consequences, potentially positive or neg-
reflect the impact of non-desert justice con- ative, that a participant has incurred in this
cerns such as need, in the case of family size, connection. Equity theorists posit that people
and efficiency, in the case of scarce special- are motivated in their social interactions not
ists. This is consistent with the findings of only by self-interest but also by a desire to
Jasso and Peter Rossi (1977) whose survey establish or restore perceived equity and to
indicates that fair earnings increase not only reward or punish others for behavior they
with education but also with number of chil- perceive as just or unjust, respectively.
dren and for being married. Despite the clarity of its theoretical for-
To summarize, the evidence from experi- mulation, the predictions of equity theory
ments and surveys generally indicates that have rarely been tested with equal rigor.
someone whose contribution is more highly Most studies of equity theory have been the-
valued is more deserving if that person bears oretical or have attempted to confirm the
responsibility for the contribution but not if hypothesized relationship between inputs
it is due to factors outside his or her control. and outcomes in general terms without
What still remains unanswered is how, specifically establishing the strict propor-
exactly, relevant factors are related to fair tionality mandated by the equity formula
allocations. We turn to this question in the (see, for example, Walster, Walster, and
following section. Berscheid 1978). One piece of evidence that
Journal of Economic Lite rature, Vol. XLI (Deceinber 2003)

is indicative of the proportionality rule for plans. Clark concludes that equality is the
micro-justice is reported in table 5 of standard when initial incomes are random
Schokkaert and Overlaet (1989). There one but that proportionality can matter when
finds different versions of a vignette in which benefit levels are earned. In an experiment
two salesmen are working at a fair, and with a total of 360 students (Konow 2000),
respondents are to select the fairest division subjects first generate earnings by perform-
of a premium among them. When the two ing a task, viz., by preparing letters for mail-
make equal contributions to the success of ing. Each subject is paired with an anony-
the fair, 69 percent to 73 percent of respon- mous counterpart with whom their joint
dents (N = 39 and N = 41, respectively) split earnings are divided in the next phase. In
the premium equally or nearly equally (i.e., one treatment, each subject is credited with
within ?4 percent of the total premium). 50 cents per letter prepared, and a third
When, on the other hand, one salesman party, the so-called "benevolent dictator," is
(Peters) has been at the stand twice as much paid a f ~ e fee
d to decide how much of the
as the other (Johnson),60 percent to 63 per- joint earnings to allocate to each of the sub-
cent of respondents (N =40 and N = 38, jects. Because of substantial differences in
respectively) give Peters approximately task performance, the percentage of joint
twice the amount of Johnson, i.e., they dis- earnings attributable to one of the paired
tribute in proportion to work time (within ? subjects ranges from 29 percent to 73 per-
4 percent of the total premium). cent of the total. The allocations by the
Proportionality emerges even though benevolent dictators are, on average, in pro-
Johnson normally earns more than Peters portion to subject earnings. In fact, depend-
and despite the fact that, in one version of ing on the version of this treatment, the frac-
this question, Peters is Johnson's assistant tion of benevolent dictators allocating
and, in the other version, Peters is described exactly, and not merely approximately, in
as "unqualified and Johnson as having a proportion to earnings runs as high as 79
"university degree." Along similar lines, percent.
Question 5 in Konow (1996) asks 295 Other evidence, however, strongly contra-
respondents to divide $1200 between two dicts proportionality. In a different treat-
grocery store managers, one of whom works ment of the Konow (2000) study, one of the
twice as many hours as the other. Here 85 paired subjects earns from 25 percent to 75
percent choose an exact $800/$400 propor- percent of the joint total. Nevertheless, 87
tional split over a $600/$600 equal split or a percent of benevolent dictators choose equal
$700/$500 intermediate division. In a splits, and the mean division of earnings
macro-justice context, Lisa Ordbfiez and does not significantly differ from one-half.
Barbara Mellers (1993) find survey respon- The difference in this treatment compared
dents prefer income distributions with to the one described above is that all sub-
stronger work-salary correlations. jects have time to prepare an equal number
Economics experiments have also of envelopes (viz., ten), and their earnings
addressed proportionality. In Jeremy Clark's differ solely because of arbitrary differences
study (1998), 120 subjects vote for one of in the per-letter credits (e.g., one subject in
two plans that generate different distribu- a pair is credited with, say, 65 cents per let-
tions of payoffs. In some treatments initial ter whereas the other is credited with, say,
incomes are "earned based on relative per- 35 cents per letter). This contradicts the pro-
formance on a multiple choice general portionality of allocations to earnings found
knowledge quiz. Final payoffs result from in the treatment discussed earlier (although
initial incomes that are adjusted for costs note that it is consistent with proportionality
and benefits that differ within and across of allocations to letters prepared). Thus,
Konow: A Positive Analysis of Justice Theories 1213

results of economics experiments suggest inputs to determine allocations depends on


that proportionality can be found, but that whether observers view those differences in
its applicability in different contexts requires inputs as within the control of agents. Jerald
further specification. Greenberg (1979) asks 72 students to choose
That the evidence on proportionality from fair compensation for four workers who dif-
psychology and sociology is not more decisive fer according to work duration and produc-
is probably due, in part, to the fact that those tivity. H e finds that respondents pay more
disciplines are primarily concerned with for greater duration and greater productivi-
behavior that does not easily yield to quantifi- ty, generally proportionately. The strength
cation, e.g., the quality of marital, race, or with which they employ the proportionality
workplace relations. In part, though, the chal- rule varies, however, in a patterned way.
lenge to equity theory across all disciplines Previous to the study, subjects completed a
and the reason, I believe, for its failure to so-called Protestant Ethic Scale that meas-
prosper after its initial popularity in the 1960s ures the degree of agreement or disagree-
and 1970s, is the difficulty in identifying a cri- ment with various statements about the
terion for determining what may serve as an causal relationship between hard work and
" .
input." As orignally formulated, equity the- success or productivity. Those who scored in
ory permits people to avail themselves of any the lower quarter on this scale (i.e., see this
variables they perceive as relevant to justice. causal link as weak) tend, in the subsequent
This version is able to explain everything but survey, to choose significantly more equal
then, of course, it also explains nothing, since payments regardless of productivity,
it does not generate refutable propositions. although they still pay proportionately for
In subsequent work, equity theory has often work duration. These results suggest that
been interpreted as stating that outcomes be fair allocations are in proportion to the
proportional to actual, as opposed to per- inputs an agent is perceived as controlling,
ceived, contributions (e.g., Giith 1994). This but that the classification of manipulable
rendering, however, runs counter to evidence inputs is open to some individual interpreta-
that not all contributions count for purposes tion. Nevertheless, the fact that subject
of justice (e.g., Burrows and Loomes 1994; interpretation of relevant inputs varies con-
Konow 2000). A growing number of social sistently with their beliefs about individual
scientists, however, have merged equity theo- control over productivity supports the claim
ry with the attribution theory discussed in the that it is the perceived degree of control that
previous section as a means to solving this governs the choice of inputs.
problem, an approach we examine below. The accountability principle is a precept
of justice based on the distinction between
4.4. The Equity Principle
factors one can influence, or discretionary
Leventhal and Michaels (1971) were per- cariables, and those one cannot, or exoge-
haps the first equity theorists to recognize nous c a r i a b l e ~This
. ~ ~ leads to a generaliza-
the need to narrow the class of inputs rele- tion of the equity formula, the entitlement
vant to fair outcomes and to propose that fonnz~la,which expresses the fair allocation,
this distinction be based on the control an or entitlement, of an individual in terms of
agent exercises over inputs. Although equity outputs, inputs, endowments and costs.
theorists and attribution theorists have gen- Simply put, it calls for an agent's allocation to
erally gone their separate ways, the sugges- be in direct proportion to his or her relevant
tion of Leventhal and Michaels is precisely discretionary variables but to be free of any
what a synthesis of these two schools effects of exogenous variables. The results of
implies. Brenda Major and Kay Deaux
(1982) report that the fairness of using 20 This is a principle I proposed in my 1996 paper.
1214 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XLI (December 2003)

written questionnaires and telephone inter- water, possibly at a higher cost that justifies
views support this principle. The accounta- the price increase and results in a fairer dis-
bility principle can also be advanced as an tribution of surplus. The results to survey
explanation for the aforementioned dictator question 2A in Konow (2001) indicate that
experiment results (Konow 2000). In that the fair price adjusts for fair costs and cre-
study, benevolent dictators allocate in pro- ates a fair distribution of surplus. Similar
portion to subject earnings when differences evidence about the just price comes from
in those earnings are due to discretionary the ultimatum game experiments of Marc
variables, i.e., the number of letters subjects Knez and Colin Camerer (1995) who con-
prepare, but allocate equal splits when earn- clude that subjects determine fair terms of
ings differences are due solely to exogenous transaction based on fair costs plus a fair
variables, i.e., arbitrary dfferences in per division of surplus (which, in their study,
letter credits. subjects appear to interpret egocentrically
Extension of this thinking to bargaining exacerbated by ambiguity about the value of
and markets suggests a theory of the "just surplus).
price." Robert Frank (1988) proposes that a The studies discussed in this section
fair transaction is one that produces an equal examine the dependence of justice on indi-
distribution of the surplus from the transac- vidual actions. In Nozick's theory, individual
tion. This definition has much explanatory choice determines both fair and, in uncon-
power, although I would modify "equal" to strained exchange, actual allocations. For
"fair," i.e., a fair distribution of surplus is in Buchanan, the chief adversary of justice in
proportion to each person's discretionary free markets is birth, whereas the influences
inputs to the transaction. Moreover, one of choice, luck and effort are just. Sorting
must specify that fair costs are determined through the forces that have some claim to
by each individual's responsibility for those relevance, we find that attribution theory
costs and not necessarily according to oppor- provides a powerful criterion for describing
tunity costs or even incurred costs. This desert according to the views of most peo-
interpretation is consistent with survey ple. Combined with equity theory, it implies
results reported by Frey and Pommerehne the Equity Principle, i.e., fair allocations
(1993). They ask German and Swiss house- across individuals are proportionate only to
holds to judge the fairness of a price increase the inputs they control, a claim that also
for bottled water at a sightseeing point on a finds support from surveys and experiments.
particularly hot day when the number of hik- Therefore, when we refer in our further dis-
ers demanding water outstrips the available cussion to equity, it will be in this specific
supply. 78 percent of respondents (N = 452) sense. Nevertheless, the results of various
find such a price increase unfair (Question studies (e.g., Schokkaert and Capeau 1991;
2), but 64 percent ( N = 148) consider the Leventhal and Michaels 1971) indicate that
increase more acceptable when a hot day people do not value this precept to the
normally occurs during the season consid- exclusion of other distributive goals but
ered than when it is unforeseeable (implied rather weigh this concern against a desire for
by Question 5 ) .When the heat is unexpect- efficiency and need. The conclusion of the
ed, the hikers cannot be held responsible, previous three sections is that a descriptive
and since the suppliers have not taken any theory of justice should incorporate the
relevant discretionary action, a price three corresponding distribute motives we
increase is not fair. When the heat is to be have discussed. So far we have neglected,
expected, however, the hikers have the however, to tackle certain crucial and diffi-
option of bringing their own beverage, and cult questions that have to be answered by
the suppliers could increase their stock of anyone evaluating justice in the real world.
Konow: A Positive Analysis of Justice Theories 1215

For example, among what group of persons the reference transaction, "a relevant prece-
should one make the comparisons, how does dent that is characterized by a reference
one judge when relevant information is miss- price or wage, and by a positive reference
ing, and what determines the relative impor- profit to the firm" (p. 729). They propose a
tance of each of the principles? These are ~rincipleof dz~alentitlement that governs
some of the issues addressed in the following community standards of fairness:
section.
Transactors have an entitlement to the terrns of
the reference transaction and firms are entitled
5. Context to their reference ~ r o f i tA. firm is not allowed to
increase its profits by arbitrarily violating the
Many investigations into justice have entitlement of its transactors to the reference
emphasized how views of fairness vary with price, rent or wage. \Vhen the reference profit of
a firm is threatened, however, it rnay set new
contextual elements such as the historical
terms that protect its profit at transactors'
terms of transactions, the group of individu- expense (pp. 72930).
als being compared, the type of good being
distributed and the framing of information. KKT offer results from Canadian tele-
This section examines the impact of these phone interviews in support of the dual enti-
and other aspects of context on the inter- tlement principle. Two of their questions
pretation of just allocations. A concept appear in table 6 along with results from my
defended here is that justice is context survey, whereby KKT's questions have been
dependent, i.e., impartial justice obeys gen- renumbered to maintain proper sequencing
eral principles, but these principles require here and their results are indicated in paren-
a set of people and variables that the context theses to distinguish them from mine.
provides. Question 7 (KKT's question 14) illustrates
5.1. Kahneman, Knetsch, and Thaler the unfairness, according to 91 percent of
respondents, of a firm's arbitrary violation of
Probably the most widely cited descrip- a transactor's reference rent. Question 8A
tive study of justice in economics is that of (KKT's question 8) is a similar scenario,
Kahneman, Knetsch, and Thaler, hereafter which I replicated (P = .56), that differs sig-
KKT, (1986). This paper is significant for a nificantly from 7 (P < .01). This provides an
number of reasons, including its original use example of a firm's right, in the view of 72
of rich vignettes, inductive method, and percent (75 percent) of my (KKT's) tele-
many findings. In this section I will outline phone respondents, to change transaction
KKT's theory, examine evidence on it, and terms at the transactor's expense in order to
suggest lessons from their research that, in protect the firm's reference profit.21
a broader framework, prove crucial in These and other results from KKT's study
understanding views of fairness. (e.g., questions 1, 2A, 2B, 3, 7, 9A, 9B, 10,
KKT propose a theory of fair transactions and 12) are consistent with their claims that
that depends on the roles of economic firms are entitled to receive a positive sur-
agents, the history of transaction terms and plus but not to change historical terms of
framing effects. In ~articular,their approach transaction arbitrarily, or even due to
deals with the case of firms (merchants, changes in opportunity costs or demand
landlords or employers) and transactors shifts. More specifically, though, the dual
(customers, tenants or employees). From entitlement principle implies a lexicographic
their examples, in which a firm often consists
of a single person, it appears that firm means Actwdly, KKT used four, rather than two, response
categories (Completely Fair, Acceptable, Unfair, and Very
price setter and transactor means price taker. Unfair) in their study, which they reported in condensed
An important construct in their analysis is form as Acceptable and Unfair in their paper.
1216 Journal of Econo7nic Literature, Vol. XLI (December 2003)

TABLE6. Questions 7 (KKT 14) and 8A (KKT 8), 8 B and 8C

7. A landlord rents out a srnall house. When the lease is due for renewal, the landlord learns that the tenant has
taken a job \,cry close to the house and is therefore unlikely to move. The landlord raises the rent $40 per rnonth
more than he was planning to do.
Fair (91% Unfair (91)% N = (157)

8A. A landlord owns and rents out a single small house to a tenant ~ v h ois living on a fixed income. A higher rent
would mean the tenant ~vouldhave to mo\.e. Other small rental houses are available. The landlord's costs have
increased substantially over the past year and the landlord raises the rent to cover the cost increases when the ten-
antis lease is due for renewal.
Fair 2 ( 7 5 % Unfair 28 (25)% "c= 131 (151)

8B. A landlord owns and rents out apartments to tenants who are living on fixed incornes. Higher rents would mean
the tenants would ha\,e to mo\,e. Other anartments are not available. The landlord's costs have increased over the
past year. The lantilord raises the rent to cover the cost increases when the tenant's leases are due for renewal, even
though he could cover his costs with a p0sitiL.e but reduced profit mlthout raising rents.
Fair 38% Unfair 62% N = 126

8C. A \\fell-to-do landlord owns nurnerous buildings. one of which is a srnall retirement home whose tenants are all
0

living on small fixed incomes. A higher rent would mean significant sacrifice to the retirees, and rnost are too ill to
rnove elsewhere. Nevertheless, the landlord raises their rent to reflect recent cost increases, even though he could
still cover his costs anti enjoy a healthy profit on the retirement horne nlthout raising rent.
Fair 12% Unfair 88% A'= 100

ordering of the firm's reference profit over A crucial issue for dual entitlement theory
the transactor's reference transaction when is the determination of reference transac-
the two conflict, as opposed, for example, to tions. KKT argue that, where there is a histo-
a tradeoff between firm and transactor sur- ry of transactions between a firm and trans-
plus. My question 8B from written question- actor, recent transactions are adopted, unless
naires explores this aspect of the theory: sev- the terms were explicitly temporary. For new
eral tenants are affected by the rent transactions, competitive prices are used.
increase, other apartments are not available Their question 2 illustrates this distinction
and it is explicitly stated that the landlord between established and new transactions
could receive a positive but reduced profit with the case of a shop owner who lowers the
without raising rents. Now only 38 percent wage he pays to an employee from $9 per
find it fair for the firm to raise the rent in hour to $7 per hour in response to a decrease
order to protect its reference profit, a signif- in the labor market wage. In version A of this
icant 34 percent point drop from 8A (P < question, the employee has worked in the
.01). Question 8C from telephone interviews shop for six months, and 83 percent of 98
pushes this point further by stating that the respondents judge the wage decrease unfair.
landlord is the well-to-do owner of numer- In version B, the current employee leaves,
ous buildings, that some of the tenants are the employer offers the lowered wage only to
too ill to move, and that the landlord could the replacement, and only 27 percent of the
still enjoy a healthy profit without raising the 125 surveyed find this unfair.
rent, and only 12 percent now judge a rent Nevertheless, they find that this rule is not
increase fair, significantly below both 8A and always straightforward. KKT's question 3,
8B (P < .01).These findings suggest that the which I report in table 7 as question 9A,
firm/transactor distinction does not drive involves the same decrease vis-2-vis a refer-
these results. ence wage for the same reason as in KKT's
Konou;: A Positive Analysis oflustice Theories 1217

TABLE
7. Questions 9A (KKT 3), 9B and 9C; 10A and 10B

9k A house painter employs two assistants and pays them $9 per hour. The painter decides to quit house painting
and go into the business of providing landscape semices, uhere the going wage is lower He reduces the workers'
wages to $7 per hour for the landscaping work.
Fair (63)% Unfair (37)% N= (94)

9B lanrlscape semzces W ~ t about


h the saine tline and effort, the former house paznter's projits fall szgnzjicantly
zn hzs n e u busmess In lanc-lscape semlees the gozng uage zs louer so he reduces
F a r 67% Unfdlr 33% N = 220

9C landscape semzces Wzth about the same tznw and effort, the former house paznterk profits mse stgnzjicant-
ly 1" hzs new buszness hle~ertheless,zn landscape semzces the gotng &age 1s l o t ~ e rso he reduces
Fair 34% Unfa~r66% 9=213

10A An ~ndependentl)owned fast food restaurantfaces competztzon from a nuirlber of other local fnstjbod restau-
rants The restaurant's pnces have been stable for some tirne IVould bou expect the restaurant's pnces to ~ t cus-
s
torners to be falr or unfa~rp
Fair 91% Unfa~r9% N=259

10B fast food restaurant ts located tn an atrport uhere there are ltinlted dzntng opportunztzes
Fair 29% Unfair 71% 9= 227

2A, but now a 63 percent majority finds this longer readily come to mind" (KKT, pp.
fair. They conclude that "the entitlement of 730-31). I think the relationship between
an employee to a reference wage does not adaptation of fairness judgments, stability
carry over to a new labor transaction, even and information that KKT identify is an
with the same employer" (p. 730). Questions important one, and I will return to it below.
9B and 9C, which were posed in my written Let us ask, however, whether normality is all
questionnaires, examine the robustness of that is needed for fairness. In table 7,91 per-
this interpretation by stating explicitly the cent of respondents to version A of question
effect on the employer's profit of his chang- 10 from my survey expect stable prices to be
ing businesses. Compared to 9A, the wage fair if they persist in the face of competition,
decrease is viewed as fair by 67 percent of whereas version B demonstrates that only 29
respondents if the employer's profits fall percent expect stable prices to be fair if they
(P = .49) but as unfair by an almost identical emerge under conditions of limited compe-
66 percent if his profits rise (P < .01). These tition ( P < .01). Thus, stability or normality
results refute KKT's explanation and suggest per se does not confer fairness.
that this approach can only be saved by The most significant contribution of
amending it with exceptions that seem KKT's study, I believe, is to our understand-
increasingly ad hoc. ing of what one might call contextz~alefects.
Another more parsimonious statement of These are the ways in which information
the reference transaction is this: "It should about context affects fairness judgments.
perhaps be emphasized that the reference Specifically, their research contains astute
transaction provides a basis for fairness judg- observations about justice and established
ments because it is normal, not necessarily versus new transactions, the duration of
because it is just. Psychological studies of transactions, competitive prices, stability and
adaptation suggest that any stable state of adaptation. Indeed, given the seemingly
affairs tends to become accepted eventually, capricious nature of some results and the
at least in the sense that alternatives to it no disagreements sometimes observed, one
1218 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XLI (December 2003)

might conclude that justice is itself merely a turn, is governed by the same considerations
kind of contextual effect. An alternative view as other distributions, i.e., one must consid-
is that justice is guided by general principles er prices in relation to need, efficiency and
that are impacted by contextual effects. As equity. This interpretation is also consistent
KKT point out, "Agreement on general prin- with additional KKT results. For example,
ciples of fairness ... does not preclude dis- they find in their (not my) questions 9A and
putes about specific cases" (p. 730). In any 9B that it is fair for a firm to lower workers'
case, as evidence presented in this paper wages to market levels if the firm is making
suggests, justice is also a phenomenon out- a loss but not if it is making a profit. Also, it
side the domain originally addressed by is unfair to auction a popular Christmas gift
KKT of price changes between firms and to the highest bidder (question IS), which
transactors: patterned values are observed in presumably distributes the surplus dispro-
levels (e.g.,income, wealth, output) and not portionately (and, therefore, inequitably) to
just changes, in non-market distributions the seller, unless the proceeds go to
(e.g., gifts, sharing of joint production, gov- UNICEF, which benefits the needy.
ernment grants) as well as market transac- An important question is whether just
tions, and among agents in other roles (col- prices have any impact on actual prices. KKT
leagues, friends, students). This does not in answer in the affirmative,citing several addi-
itself represent a flaw in KKT's theory, but it tional survey results (to questions 17A, 17B,
does indicate the need for a more general 18A, and 18B).Aiming to test KKT's theory,
approach to account for many findings about Steven Kachelmeier, Stephen Limberg, and
justice. Michael Schadewald (1991)employ a multi-
The discussion that follows presents what I period market experiment using 64 subjects
think are the main lessons from KKT's study with posted bid pricing, i.e.,buyers post bids
and the research it spawned. This is organ- and sellers choose whether to sell. In the first
ized around three groups of issues. First, we ten periods, the competitive equilibrium
consider fairness in transactions including results in an equal split between buyers and
fair costs, fair prices and the role of competi- sellers of total surplus. In the following ten
tion. Second,we examine information effcts, periods, a sales tax increases both the equi-
or how people process information about librium price as well as sellers' share of prof-
variables relevant to justice in forming their it in equilibrium. Three treatments are con-
views. Third, we look at how justice views are ducted with different subjects under
determined when the metric, or standard of different information conditions. In one
measurement, is the derived subjective valz~e. treatment, all subjects are informed of the
Transactions. The results to questions 8 sellers' share of total surplus, in another they
and 9 above cast doubt on the lexicographic are informed of the increased marginal cost
rule protecting firm profit that is embedded and in a control they are informed of neither.
in dual entitlement theory: the fairness of a Based on KKT, they argue that in the second
change in transaction terms is sensitive to ten periods buyers will resist price increases
the relative benefits to and burdens on the under profit disclosure more than under
buyers and sellers. An explanation for these marginal cost disclosure. The former reveals
results was proposed in section 4.4 of this that profit now exceeds the reference profit,
paper: the just price produces a fair division whereas the latter provides a rationale for
of the surplus from a transaction. Thus, fair price increases based on cost increases.
prices should be adjusted, in questions 8 and Their predictions are confirmed: although
9, in order to share more fairly the lesser or market prices eventually approach the high-
greater surplus associated with the new cir- er equilibrium level for all conditions, the
cumstances. The fair division of surplus, in adjustment under profit disclosure is more
Konow: A Positive Analysis of Justice Theories 1219

gradual and the average price remains lower consider information effects, or how the
even in the final period than under marginal explicit information in a context affects the
cost disclosure. Robert Franciosi et al. evaluation of justice through its impact on
(1995) replicate this experiment with 144 the implicit assumptions of the evaluator.
subjects and a few alterations, notably posted One response to sparse information is sim-
offer pricing, i.e., sellers, not buyers, post ply to assume away any differences across
prices and buyers choose whether to pur- persons relating to justice. This ceteris
chase. Their results are mostly consistent pnribus assunzption seems most appropriate
with those of Kachelmeier et al. except that when the available information provides no
Franciosi et al. find that the fairness effect basis for such differences. There are many
dissipates over time as prices converge to the examples from written and telephone surveys
competitive equilibrium. Thus, these studies of ceteris paribus assumptions about need,
imply that fairness influences market prices efficiency, equity and surplus from transac-
in the short run, but this impact is more like- tions." Further evidence is implied by the
ly to be sustained when buyers set prices Roth and Keith Murnighan (1982) experi-
(e.g., typical labor markets) than when sellers ment, in which pairs of subjects bargain over
set prices (e.g., usual product markets). "lottery tickets" or opportunities to win prizes
Nothing in the procedures of the that differ in value to each player. When the
Kachelmeier et al. and Franciosi et al. exper- prize values are common knowledge to both
iments suggests any moral asymmetry players, they tend to allocate lottery tickets
between buyers and sellers, i.e., there is no unequally so as to equalize expected dollar
obvious basis for unequal shares of surplus ~ a ~ o f f On
s . the other hand, when neither
because of, say, need or desert. In the initial knows the value of the other player's prize,
periods, price quickly converges to the equi- they tend to equalize the lottery tickets, con-
librium level, which coincidentally produces sistent with their making the ceteris paribus
an equal split of the surplus. In the second assumption about the values of the prizes.
set of periods, subjects resist the movement The results of the Kachelmeier et al. and
toward an equilibrium that generates Franciosi et al. experiments suggest that sub-
unequal shares, when they are aware of this jects make the ceteris paribus assumption
inequality. These findings are consistent about shares of surplus until explicit informa-
with the notion of a fair division of surplus tion to the contrary is revealed. Similarly, one
from transactions. In addition, the results probable reason competition is commonly
suggest a lesson about competition and fair- regarded as fair is because it lacks the dis-
ness: in the absence of any explicit informa- proportionate power explicitly present in
tion to the contrary, subjects have no basis non-competitive markets.
for resisting competitive prices on fairness At other times, information, although
grounds. In fact, KKT observe that prices in incomplete, can provide a basis for extrapo-
competitive markets tend to be regarded as lation. That is, the context may contain infor-
fair, according to versions of their questions mation from which people can extrapolate to
2, 3, 4, 9, 13, and of my question 10. We will form reasonable assumptions about relevant
return to these points below. differences. For example, LVeiner and Kukla
Znfornzation Effects. As KKT point out, (1970) find that subjects, using a quantitative
fairness judgments are sensitive to the scale, infer effort from relative performance.
information provided in a scenario. When Survey respondents have also been found to
information is incomplete, historical, mar- extrapolate from a seller's profession to its
ket or stable prices can influence the profitability (Konow 2001). In the current
assumptions people make about factors rel-
evant to justice principles. Here we will " For instance, see Konow (2001)
Journal of Economic Litejrature, Vol. XLI (December 2003)

study, the results to question 9 in table 7 sug- perceived as less unfair if the demand shift
gest that respondents use information about occurs at predictable intervals, alternative
the new industry, and perhaps the lower supplies exist, buyers are previously
wage rate there, to form the assumption that informed of and able to prepare themselves
the employer's profits would fall in his new against the price increase, and sellers do not
business were he not to lower his employees' profit from the price increase. These results
wages. Such extrapolation also provides one suggest that people oppose price changes
explanation for the relevance of historical that are suspected of forcing an unfair redis-
terms for current transactions: current pay- tribution of surplus to the benefit of the
ments can be based on past ones if the latter price setter.
are assumed to be fair. This effect is implied Subjective Values. As discussed in section
by the bargaining experiment of Simon 3.1, people prefer to use derived values as
Gachter and Arno Riedl (2001). Their nine- the metric, or unit of account, for justice
ty subjects take a general knowledge quiz evaluation. Where possible, then, fairness
and are told that past pay was according to will be measured in terms of subjective val-
performance, where "winner" earnings were ues such as pleasure, happiness or utility
double those of the "loser." They then bar- rather than objective values such as income,
gain over a fixed sum from positions of wealth or goods. What is the correspon-
strategic equality in which these historical dence between the former and the latter? I
claims are sunk. Nevertheless, both winners will discuss three possibilities.
and losers largely accept historical payments First, as illustrated in examples in section
as the standard for fair and actual compensa- 3.1, people often use levels of satisfaction,
tion (although the two groups also exhibit a pleasure or happiness to form judgments
self-serving bias). about fair allocations. In economics this is
Finally, KKT note that fairness is often commonly modeled using a function that rep-
associated with stability. If people adapt to resents endstate utility, whereby subjective
stable values because, as they state, "alterna- values are a function of the final allocations of
tives to it no longer readily come to m i n d objective variables. In this case, fair alloca-
(pp. 730-31), this represents an information tions measured in subjective terms may differ
effect. As the results to question 10 in table from those measured in objective terms
7 indicate, however, stable outcomes can because of differences across individuals in
also be unfair. Only under a regime of com- utility. As suggested by the discussion of infor-
petition is stability associated with fairness in mation effects above, however, unless such
that scenario. One factor that probably con- differences are explicit, people tend to make
tributes to the perceived fairness of stable the ceteris paribus assumption about total
outcomes is the implicit assumption that and marginal utility such that subjective and
they usually obtain because they can with- objective values lead to the same allocations.
stand or have actually survived competitive KKT offer evidence of a different avenue
threats. At a minimum, stable prices are of influence for subjective values: the fair-
opposed to expedient pricing policies that ness of a change in transaction terms some-
respond to unexpected shifts in supply or times depends on features that seem incon-
demand and that, as several KKT examples sequential for final allocations. One instance
demonstrate, tend to be viewed as oppor- of this is the difference in fair wages
tunistic and unfair. The mail surveys of a between an established and a new employee
representative sample of 407 Swiss house- in KKT's question 2. Another is their ques-
holds by Frey and Beat Gygi (1988) lead to tion 4 where a company's 7 percent real
similar conclusions. Their results show rais- salary reduction is unfair according to 62
ing price in response to a demand increase is percent of those surveyed when there is no
Konow: A Positive Analysis of Justice Theories 1221

inflation (version A, N = 125) but fair newcomer does not, it is unfair to reduce the
according to 78 percent when accomplished wage of the former, since it unjustly imposes
through salary increases that fail to keep up a loss on him and provides a gain to the
with inflation (version B, N = 129), a signifi- employer. Similarly, workers are typically
cant shift ( P < .01). Yet another case is endowed with a nominal, not real, salary, so
based on whether transaction terms are the salient reference point for gains and loss-
framed as normal or as temporary. For es in KKT's question 4 is nominal. Finally, it
example, in their question 5, a car dealer is fair to eliminate a discount (KKT 5) or a
responds to a shortage of a popular model. bonus (KKT 6), since they are explicitly tem-
In version A, the dealer sells the car at $200 porary and not endowed, whereas it is unfair
above the list price, which 71 percent of to impose unfavorable terms on another that
respondents (N = 130) consider unfair, deviate from the norm. Max Bazerman
whereas in version B the dealer eliminates a (1985) reports evidence suggesting that such
previous $200 discount, which only 42 per- an endowment effect influences the wage
cent (N = 123) judge unfair (P < .01). In decisions of real arbitrators. Sixty-nine expe-
their question 6, the business of a small rienced arbitrators are asked to evaluate 25
company has recently not increased as hypothetical wage cases and to assign sub-
before, and in version A it reduces workers' jective weights to various criteria. Although
wages by 10 percent, which 61 percent (N = arbitrators differ among themselves about
100) deem unfair, whereas in B it eliminates the significance of each factor, the most
a previous 10 percent annual bonus, which common decision is to maintain the status
only 20 percent (N = 98) find unfair (P < quo in levels by adjusting wages by the aver-
.01). KKT characterize these as framing age negotiated increase in the industry. This
effects and incorporate this last case into policy distributes the changes fairly across
their fairness theory by excluding explicitly wage earners. Casual empiricism, I believe,
temporary transactions from serving as ref- also supports the endowment effect as a per-
erence transactions. suasive explanation for many rules that are
Consider the following explanations for defended as fair. For example, certain rights
these effects (i.e., money illusion, estab- and benefits are often "grandfathered," or
lished versus new transactions, and normal available to previous recipients but not to
versus temporary transaction terms) within a newcomers. Such clauses, frequently codi-
framework of justice principles. Various fied in law, protect the endowment of estab-
studies (e.g., Kahneman and Amos Tversky lished beneficiaries without imposing a sub-
1979) suggest that preferences are deter- jective loss on unendowed newcomers.
mined by gains or losses relative to some These two approaches, endstate utility
reference value as opposed to endstates, and endowment effect, offer different, and
whereby losses are coded more heavily than often conflicting, subjective values for judg-
gains of equal magnitude. Survey respon- ing fairness. Evidence has been presented in
dents evaluate the fairness of these changes favor of both effects. Which will serve as the
anticipating their subjective effects on the metric of justice seems to be resolved in the
implicated parties. Specifically, they may same manner as the choice of objective ver-
incorporate an endou;ment effect (Thaler sus subjective values: it depends on the
1980), that is, they take as the reference information provided by the context. If the
value the transaction terms to which the par- stated context emphasizes levels rather than
ties have adapted based on agreements or changes, justice evaluators tend to focus on
understandings about relevant values. Thus, endstate utility. If, on the other hand,
since the established employee in KKT's changes and endowments are salient, people
question 2 has an endowed wage but the will be sensitive to endowment effects. A
1222 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XLI (December 2003)

third possibility is that people form a com- practices and customs pertaining to the dis-
posite judgment involving both effects, each tribution of socially valued goods. They
weighted according to its salience in the con- claim the principles of justice differ accord-
text. This is exactly the conclusion at which ing to the set of persons, good, institution,
Eldar Shafir, Peter Diamond, and Tversky culture, country, region, historical context
(1997) arrive in their study of money illu- and precedents. Carried to the extreme, this
sion: people tend to adopt the frame that is approach views justice as atomistic and pre-
presented but, when confronted with multi- cludes any theory of it. The usual more
ple representations, they form an average moderate version entails many unrelated
that is weighted by the salience of each. principles, each confined to its own specific
Thus, the wage cut in KKT's question 2A is context.
unfair because the worker's explicit tenure We begin by examining briefly the work of
with the employer stresses the endowment three scholars of local justice: Jon Elster
effect, whereas it is fair to offer the reduced (1992), Michael Walzer (1983), and H.
wage to the newcomer in version 2B since he Peyton Young (1994). These authors share
will not experience that as a loss, and the certain common interests, goals and conclu-
employer can achieve fair levels by comply- sions. They all articulate a context specific
ing with the more salient (presumably com- view of justice. They also define justice as in
petitive) market wage. Although Bazerman very broad terms, encompassing a very wide
finds that arbitrators focus on the fairness of range of issues including the distribution of
wage changes, consistent with an endow- not only material wealth but also political
ment effect, he also finds that the financial power, family privileges and public duties. In
health of the firm figures prominently in particular, they tend to focus on fair rules of
their considerations, suggesting a concern distribution, especially for goods the alloca-
about fairness in levels of surplus between tion ofwhich is problematic. For example, all
firms and workers. three deal with military service (conscription
This subsection sought to illustrate how and/or demobilization) and access to higher
the empirical work of Kahneman, Knetsch, education, Elster and Young examine kidney
and Thaler helps to clarify important contex- transplants and allocation of building space,
tual effects. These involve the interpretation and jialzer and Elster treat immigration.
of fairness when transactions are salient, On the other hand, there are certain dif-
information effects, including the ceteris ferences among the three, if only in their
paribus assumption, extrapolation and stabil- method and emphasis. To some extent, they
ity, and subjective values, including endstate vary in the degree of context specificity they
utility, the endowment effect and a weighted argue, where Walzer challenges most vigor-
average of these two. ously the applicability of any theory. In terms
of approach and method, Elster views justice
5.2. Theories of Local Justice
more from the perspective of sociology,
Some researchers have concluded that Walzer from political philosophy and history,
justice does not yield to the level of abstrac- and Young from economics and mathemat-
tion that is associated with "general" or ics. Finally, although applications of justice
"global" theories. Instead, they argue that, are highlighted in the work of all three, I
at best, one can uncover an array of princi- think it is fair to say that Walzer's emphasis
ples that are "local," or specific to individual relative to the others is normative, Elster's
contexts. These advocates of what are some- descriptive and Young's policy-oriented.
times dubbed "phenomenological" theories Taken together, the major works of these
of justice point to the wide variation in three authors on justice form an excellent
rules, arguments, legislation, court rulings, and wide-ranging case for local justice. I will
Konou;: A Positice Analysis of Justice Theories 1223

begin by summarizing briefly the arguments as with social goods, by the understandings
of each. or meanings people attach to them. But
Michael Walzer begins his book, Spheres of from whence do these meanings derive, and,
Justice (1983),by defining the subject matter if from history and culture, how? It seems
of distributive justice very broadly: "Nothing they are given wide berth: although Walzer
can be omitted (p. 3). He rejects the possi- downplays such cases, he notes that one can
bility of a theory of justice and argues "that to think of a society with a moral right to hair-
search for unity is to misunderstand the sub- cuts (p. 88 n.) and even the Indian caste sys-
ject matter of distributive justice" (p. 4). tem can be just ( p p 313-15). Ultimately, it is
Instead he advances the radical claim that unclear what qualifies here as first principles
"the principles of justice are themselves plu- and, consequently, what, if anything, is gen-
ralistic in form; that different social goods erated in the way of refutable propositions.
ought to be distributed for different reasons, In his book Local Justice (1992), Jon
. . . and that all these differences derive from Elster's goal is more descriptive and narrow
different understandings of the social goods than Walzer's: "I consider the conceptions of
themselves-the inevitable product of histor- justice held by actors who are in a position to
ical and cultural particularism" (p. 6). influence the selection of specific procedures
In terms of identifying what justice is (as or criteria to allocate scarce resources" (p. 5).
opposed to what it is not), Walzer distinguish- Although he also expresses skepticism about
es "simple equality," or equal allocations of a the prospects for a robust theory of justice,
social good across all individuals, from "com- he is more optimistic than Walzer. Elster
plex equality." Under complex equality, given favors a list of allocative principles over glob-
the socially understood autonomy of each al theories. In his book Equity: In Theory
sphere, it is not necessarily unjust that some and Practice (1994), H. Peyton Young's goal
in the sphere of politics are more powerful or is closer to Elster's than Walzer's: "The aim of
that some in the sphere of money are more this book, then, is to examine how societies
wealthy, but it is unjust, for example, for solve 'everyday' distributive problems" (p.
politicians to use their power outside their xii). Although Elster and Young emphasize
sphere to acquire money, or for the rich to use justice principles as mechanisms, Young in
their wealth to secure political influence. The particular concentrates on the technical diffi-
most important distributive issue is member- culties of putting justice into practice. Much
ship, i.e., who belongs to a sphere, including of the motivation behind Young's work (and,
family, industry, neighborhood, and, first and to some extent, Elster's) are problems of
foremost, the political community. indivisibility and heterogeneity that crop up
Within each sphere, justice might require in designing policies for the distribution of
simple equality, e.g., equal basic education, scarce resources such as kidneys, apportion-
or inequality, e.g., unequal professional ment of congressional seats, real assets in
training, which he also calls complex equali- inheritances and child custody. They note the
ty. Walzer seems to use complex equality in large assortment of mechanisms that have
at least two senses: to denote the autonomy been used to regulate the allocation of such
of spheres and to connote a deviation from resources including proportionality, queuing,
simple equality within a sphere. It is unclear rotation, lottery, seniority and precedent.
where the equality is in this second type of The rich description and incisive analysis
complex equality. Perhaps it means the fur- of Elster and Young instill a profound
ther subdivision of spheres into members appreciation of the challenges facing alloca-
who are then equal within each sphere, but tors. The problems and their solutions are
what guides this division and delineation? not transparent, and the consequences are
Presumably these questions are determined, often not trivial. There are many situations,
1224 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XLI (December 2003)

however, in which such problems are not of different justice principles in a given con-
insurmountable or even significant. For text, and procedural justice, or process fair-
example, many goods are, for all intents and ness, which includes the study of mecha-
purposes, arbitrarily divisible, e.g., food, nisms aimed at implementing the justice
energy, money denominated assets. Other principles. Below I will explore these themes
goods are convertible into a divisible and as well as evidence that bears on each.
homogeneous form, e.g., the assets of an Scope Effects. When making fairness judg-
estate may be sold and divided among the ments, people must choose the set of indi-
beneficiaries. Nevertheless, it is quite cor- viduals and allocations to compare. Scope
rect that attributes such as indivisibility (or effects refer to how context affects perceived
lumpiness) and heterogeneity may require fairness through its impact on these choices.
special measures. In fact, these problems LValzer treats the choice of persons, which
might obstruct any solution that most he calls membership, extensively. His con-
people would consider genuinely fair. cern is with how membership influences and
A lack of uniformity and exactitude in prac- is influenced by distributive decision-mak-
tical rules for achievingjustice does not, how- ing. He argues that no aspects of justice,
ever, imply that the values that underlie and including membership, are immutable, but
motivate those rules are equally diverse and boundaries will emerge, which will be
ambiguous. There are really two distinct regarded for some time by implicated parties
questions. An analogy may be drawn to effi- as fair. Moreover, he claims that there is a
ciency. The Pareto and Compensation moral asymmetry between members and
Principles, for example, are conceptually clear non-members: for example, citizens of a
standards even if, say, institutional constraints country have certain rights and privileges
prevent their full implementation. Similarly,if that are not accorded non-citizens. Walzer
context precludes a "first-best" justice solu- asks how the boundaries between individu-
tion, principles of justice may guide one to a als should be constituted, whereas the cur-
"second-best" justice solution. Elster and rent paper asks how the choice of individuals
Young seek rules or mechanisms for imple- being compared affects views of justice.
menting just outcomes. The concern of the Although this paper promotes a general
present paper, on the other hand, is with the theory of justice, empirical results and
shared views of justice, even if its realization is everyday observations suggest that, in a par-
problematic or impossible. The former topic ticular sense, people solve justice problems
is crucial if justice is to be more than merely in a "local" way. Specifically,membership, or
an abstract concept. The latter question, how- the "reference group" as it is known in social
ever, is also important, not only because of the psychology, is handled as other contextual
frequent consensus on what measures justice issues: people take the group that seems
requires, but also as a means of evaluating most proximate in terms of comparability
alternative mechanisms precisely when there and salience and then apply general princi-
are practical obstacles, discord or uncertainty. ples. Thus, workers make comparisons to
I believe that there are at least four impor- co-workers, children to their siblings or
tant lessons about contextual effects that can peers, residents to neighbors and experi-
be gleaned from these theories of local jus- mental subjects to other subjects. This bol-
tice. Views of justice are affected by how the sters Walzer's claim about the importance of
context affects or produces scope effects, membership. On the other hand, I am
which pertain to the choice of which individ- unaware of any evidence on the putative
uals and allocations to compare, competing fairness of the privileged status of members.
forces such as self-interest, the weighting of So far as Walzer's examples accord with
justice principles, or the relative importance intuition, however, one need not appeal to a
Konow: A Positive Analysis of ]tlstice Theories 1225

separate principle of justice. The mainte- function not only of the surplus from this
nance of boundaries around nations, firms, transaction but also of the distribution of
labor unions, families, etc., can be traced to income or profit external to it. The set of rel-
a practical requirement for efficient social evant allocations might also vary intertempo-
planning and coordination as well as to the rally and include past or future allocations,
endowment effect.23 e.g., should income taxes be based on life-
Is membership, as Walzer suggests, usual- time income or be adjusted by income aver-
ly well-defined, or is it sensitive to the infor- aging? The scope of both allocations and
mation available? The results to survey ques- individuals can be involved, e.g., should
tion 9 of Konow (2001) suggest the latter. descendents of slaves be compensated for
Here the CEO of a multinational corpora- the unfairly appropriated product of their
tion earns $9 million per year, which is ancestors' labor?
described in version A as "around that of Survey and experimental studies help
CEOs at comparable corporations" and in address such matters. In question 8 of
version B as "around 300 times that of the Konow (2001),a furniture manufacturer sells
average worker at his corporation." The chairs to a retailer subject to price controls
same salary is judged fair by 70 percent of that allow the furniture manufacturer only a
137 respondents in version A but by only 43 very small and unfair profit on the chairs.
percent of 150 respondents in version B This is judged unfair by 79 percent of 88
(P < .01). It appears that the salient refer- respondents when chairs are the only item
ence group in version A is the CEO's profes- the furniture manufacturer produces but as
sional cohorts whereas in version B it is his unfair by only 35 percent of 85 respondents
fellow employees. Dictator experiments by when chair sales represent a small fraction of
Eckel and Grossman (1996) and myself the furniture producer's otherwise profitable
(2002) have also demonstrated that the gen- business (P < .01). Thus, the fairness of this
erosity of decision makers depends on the transaction is sensitive to information about
identity of counterparts. In those studies, the parties' allocations from other transac-
dictators contribute significantly more when tions. H8kan Holm and Peter Engseld (2001)
their counterparts are charities than when conduct ultimatum and dictator experiments
they are student cohorts. Thus, casual in which responders (recipients) are identi-
empiricism, surveys and experiments sug- fied as low income (having annual incomes
gest that membership is important for jus- below about $10,000) or high income (having
tice, that people typically resolve it locally, incomes above about $30,000). Similar to the
relying on the available context, but that dictator experiments with charities and stu-
membership is neither uniquely defined nor dents reported previously, they find that pro-
necessarily stable. posers (dictators) make significantly greater
The second issue is the scope of compari- proposals to low-income responders than to
son for allocations. For example, scope high-income responders and, in treatments
effects can materialize in determining that permit this choice, are significantly more
whether a family's income is relevant to the likely to choose as their responders low
price it should pay for telephone services or income subjects. Here again, the fairness of
electricity. Here the just price might be a one allocation, viz., the division of the exper-
imental earnings, is affected by information
30 That is, as preciously explained, current disparities in about other allocations, viz., income from
le\~elsacross different groups may be justified on fairness non-experimental sources. These results
grounds if the levels are endowed. Opening up member- support a type of locality, not in the sense of
ship to unequal groups in order to equalize levels causes
gains and losses that generate unequal subjective values context specific, but rather as general princi-
that are dependent on changes rather than le\~els. ples that are interpreted in the context. In
Journal of Economic Litenature, Vol. XLZ (December 2003)

particular, scope effects indicate that people societies, Henrich et al. (2001) find that
evaluate fairness using both the individuals offers vary widely but the mean offers of the
and the allocations suggested by the context. Machiguenga remain the lowest of any
Competing Forces. By definition, the only society studied.
general proposition about justice that phe- Several explanations are possible for
nomenological theories produce is that none observed differences across cultures. Roth
exists. One way, therefore, to test them is to and his colleagues consider the hypothesis
examine differences and similarities in justice that subjects share the same fairness values
values across different "boundaries." One but differ in degrees of bargaining aggressive-
boundary that Walzer, Elster, and Young all ness. If that were the case, though, one would
identify as relevant to justice is that of nations. expect higher rates of disagreement in coun-
Various studies have drawn conclusions about tries where offers tend to be low, which they
justice based on surveys or bargaining experi- do not find. Thus, they conjecture that "the
ments conducted in different countries. Here observed subject-pool differences are cultur-
I will review evidence from several such stud- al in character" (p. 1092). Similarly, Henrich
ies and examine whether the pattern of concludes that the Machiguenga do not pos-
behavior and attitudes they uncover is best sess the same sense of fairness as Westerners,
explained by culture specific conceptions of indeed, perhaps no such sense at all.
justice or, alternately, by the influence of goals An alternate hypothesis is that subjects
that compete with universal justice principles. share a common concept of fairness but that
Roth et al. (1991) run a multi-round ulti- they differ in their willingness to act on it.
matum game in the United States, Slovenia, Even within countries there is wide variation
Japan, and Israel, and find significant differ- in levels of generosity, so why should there
ences in offers and that tend to increase over not be similar differences across countries?
rounds. Nevertheless, modal offers are still all This simply suggests that the tradeoff
in the range of 50 percent to 40 percent by between self-interest and justice differs on
the final round. Offers in the same range average across cultures, but not that self-
emerge from a replication by Robert Slonim interest and justice mean something differ-
and Roth (1998) in the Slovak Republic and ent in different places. Moreover, a greater
from a two-round ultimatum experiment by role for self-interest, as opposed to the bar-
Lisa Cameron (1999)in Indonesia with stakes gaining aggressiveness Roth et al. mention,
that vary by factors of 25 and 40, respectively. does not imply higher rates of disagreement
Probably the most dramatic cross-cultural in the ultimatum game: in the case of
study of this sort is Joseph Henrich's (2000) extreme self-interest, the proposer always
single round ultimatum experiment with 21 offers the smallest unit, the responder
pairs of the Machiguenga, a people of the always accepts, and disagreement never
Peruvian Amazon, and fifteen pairs of UCLA occurs. This is a close description of the
graduate students using stakes equivalent to a Machiguenga where only one of 21 offers
little more than two days labor. Comparing was rejected, even though their average
his results to those of Roth et al., Cameron offers were much lower than among other
(1999), and Hoffman et al. (1994), Henrich cultures. In fact, Henrich et al. seem to
finds small and sometimes significant differ- move in this direction, attributing the
ences across subject pools, but the observed experimental differences to the
Machiguenga are the most notable outliers effects of social institutions on incentives to
where the modal offer is 15 percent, the act on self-interest, fairness or reciprocity,
mean offer is 26 percent, and low offers are and noting how the experiment, therefore, is
rarely rejected. In a subsequent paper that likely construed by subjects given the con-
expands this experiment to 15 small-scale texts familiar to them.
Konow: A Positive Analysis of Justice Theories 1227

Bargaining experiments might prompt a (1992) experiments and replications dis-


distinct motive, usually called reciprocity, cussed in section 2.2, which seek to reveal
that leads agents to reward or punish others distributive preferences by inducing objec-
for their compliance with or deviation from tivity, bring us closer to this question. The
social norms such as fairness (see Rabin similarity of results across five countries sug-
1993 for a formal model of this). Numerous gests that, when subjects are distanced from
experimental and theoretical studies have their self-interest, cross-cultural differences
examined reciprocity as a force separate diminish, although there is no uniform evi-
from distributive motives such as fairness, dence on whether fairness motivates their
e.g., Fehr, Gachter, and Georg Kirchsteiger decisions. The bargaining study of Nancy
(1997); Joyce Berg, John Dickhaut, and Buchan, Eric Johnson, and Rachel Croson
Kevin McCabe (1995); James Cox (2003); (2003), on the other hand, also elicits fair-
Armin Falk and Urs Fischbacher (1998); ness attitudes from U.S. and Japanese stu-
Gary Bolton and Axel Ockenfels (2000); dents, but since subjects express their views
Fehr and Gachter (2000) and references following the bargaining phase, these judg-
therein. Although reciprocity experiments ments are likely biased by rationalization
have been replicated in several countries, (see Babcock et al. 1995 on this).
there is still little in the way of cross-cultural Survey studies of justice attitudes further
studies. But the central of the cur- separate subjects from their self-interest by
rent study is not whether there are variations removing any material stake. In addition,
in the willingness to reciprocate fair behav- they can address what objective parties
ior in different societies, or in the relative consider fair for others, not what they
importance of self-interest versus fairness, would choose for themselves, not what they
or even in expectations of fairness, but consider fair for themselves, and not even
rather whether the justice concepts them- what they think should be done (which is
selves differ across cultures. Unfortunately, potentially distinct). The results of such
these studies on bargaining and reciproci&, studies across different countries are
while shedding light on important behavioral remarkably similar, often identical. For
phenomena, do not provide an answer to this example, several of the hypothetical scenar-
question.24The Frohlich and Oppenheimer ios Kahneman, Knetsch, and Thaler ask in
Canada have been presented to diverse
24 I believe there are a number o f additional reasons to populations in other countries. When asked
be skeptical o f the Machiguenga results as they bear on about an increase in the price of snow shov-
this question. There is not only the possibility that the els after a snowstorm, 82 percent of 107
Machiguenga are more self-interested, but also several
other explanations. For instance, the goal o f the experi- Canadian respondents view it as unfair
ment was explicitly presented to the Machiguenga as (KKT 1986) versus a virtually identical 83
"playing a fun game for money." Presumably familiar with percent of 215 in Germany and Switzerland
games but not laboratory experiments, they (more than
U.S. college students) might have understood this to be a (Frey and Pommerehne 1993). Cutting an
game o f luck, the goal o f which was to win the jackpot, not established worker's wage because of
to distribute earnings. In fact, responders indicated they increased unemployment is seen as unfair
viewed their random selection into that role simply as bad
luck, and those few proposers who did offer 50 percent by 83 percent of KKT's 98 Canadian
later explained it based on fairness. Moreover, as Henrich respondents and also by an identical 83
reports, the Machiguenga are self-sufficient:they produce percent of 258 U.S. respondents (Konow
mostly for their own needs, and "anonymous transactions
are almost unknown." They have little need for money and 2001; question 8A in the current paper pro-
rarely work for it. Consequently, even though they live in a vides another example of similar responses
developing country, the stakes o f less than $7 they played with these two subject pools). Robert
for might not have presented them with as significant a
moral decision as that faced by U C L A students who played Shiller, Maxim Boycko, and Vladimir
for $160. Korobov (1991) pose several questions
1228 Journal of Econorizic Literature, Vol. XLI (December 2003)

inspired by KKT in telephone interviews Weighting oflustice Principles. In contrast


with U.S. and Russian respondents. Even in to the evidence presented above, some sur-
countries with such disparate economic and vey studies suggest significant cultural differ-
political histories and before the imple- ences in justice attitudes. For example,
mentation of fundamental market reforms Gaertner et al. (2001)construct a scenario in
in Russia (interviews were administered in which a small society can fund the basic
May 1990),people express strikingly similar training of a handicapped person, which
views of fairness. Sixty-six percent of 131 evokes a concern for need, or finance the
Russians and 68 percent of 119 Americans more advanced education of an intelligent
find it unfair to raise the price of flowers child, which implies a greater economic ben-
because of a holiday (P = .78),66 percent of efit and, hence, a concern for efficiency. A
131 Russians and 70 percent of 120 majority of university students in all coun-
Americans deem it unfair to raise the price tries studied prefers helping the handi-
of tables without a change in costs (P = .46), capped person but the strength of support
and 57 percent of 98 Russians and 61 per- differs by up to 27 percent, being weakest in
cent of 115 Americans judge it fair to raise two newly liberalized Eastern European
rents on summer homes that are now more economies. Conclusions about fairness from
conveniently located because of a new rail- this study, however, must be tempered by
way line ( P = .58).Not all such studies have the fact respondents are asked to choose the
revealed such a high level of international alternative they think should be realized, not
agreement (I will consider some others the one they consider most fair. This opens
below). But the increased coincidence of the door for the competing forces mentioned
results usually found when justice values above. Virginia Murphy-Berman et al.
are more specifically targeted is notewor- (1984), on the other hand, explicitly elicit
thy. It lends credence to the view that what- fairness judgments about the distribution of
ever variation in generosity one observes in a bonus between a needy worker and a
experiments is due more to differences deserving worker. They find college students
across cultures in the willingness to act on in India were significantly more inclined
justice than to differences in the concept of than their U.S. counterparts to favor the
justice itself. needy worker.
Justice is one part of the whole-it does Although the authors of these two studies
not exhaust the forces that impact alloca- lean toward the view that justice norms are
tions. The danger, if one construes justice culturally relative, this does not follow if jus-
too broadly, is of failing to see the trees for tice is a multi-criterion concept. By analogy,
the forest. Fairness often competes with the assumption of self-interest does not
self-interest, and Fehr and Schmidt (1999) imply that everyone derives the same utility
suggest how the strategic environment can from the same set of goods.There are nation-
affect which motive dominates. In other al differences in commodity preferences-
social interactions, such as parenting, other why should the same not be true of prefer-
motives such as love and unconditional altru- ences for justice principles? This does not
ism might figure more prominently. mean that justice is idios,yncratically valued
Similarly, kind and harmful acts among col- (in fact, there is probably less cultural varia-
leagues or neighbors are probably motivated tion in preferences for justice than for
less by love or fairness than by opportunities goods). Instead, it merely implies that the
for reciprocity. As this subsection has information, experiences and expectations
attempted to demonstrate, it is important to given by the context determine the interpre-
be vigilant about identifying the distinct role tation of the principles and the weight
of justice among distributive forces. attached to each. The national differences
Konow: A Positive Analysis of Justice Theories 1229

observed in the Gaertner et al. study could We have examined some evidence on the
be due, not only to differences in forces other claim of local justice of culture specificity,
than justice, but also to the greater wishes but the strongest argument against phenom-
and expectations of inhabitants of economies enological theories is probably a persuasive
in transition for efficiency and growth. general theory. It is interesting that, when
Similarly, the greater emphasis of Indian stu- pressed to generalize, advocates of local jus-
dents on need presumably reflects the tice often come up with rules that resemble
greater awareness and reality of substantial the same three principles we have identified
material need in that society. here. Walzer, for example, lists three distrib-
In a survey study of the general public in utive principles: need, desert, and free
thirteen countries that include the United exchange (pp. 21-26). In his scheme, free
States, Japan, and Western and Eastern exchange replaces efficiency, but this substi-
European countries, Duane Alwin, Galin tution makes sense if one considers Walzer's
Gornev, and Ludmila Khakhulina (1995) emphasis on mechanisms and the putative
predict variations in fairness judgments strength of free markets as the usual mecha-
based both on justice principles as well as on nism for achieving efficient outcomes. Elster
culturally determined perceptions. They states four lexicographic propositions (p.
find significant differences, including with 240), which I paraphrase as follows: (1)max-
respect to equal opportunity and need satis- imize total welfare, (2) deviate from (1) if
faction. Nevertheless, a majority in each necessary to ensure a minimum level of wel-
country agrees that equal shares of income fare, (3) deviate from (2) if people fall below
and wealth are not fair and that those who the minimum level because of their own
work harder deserve to earn more. Yoshihisa choices, and (4) deviate from (3) if the failed
Kashima et al. (1988) report that Japanese choices are due to conditions beyond their
and Australian university students exhibit control. Although our principles are not
preferences for equality, equity, and need, ranked, Elster's proposition (1)is a clear call
but that there is a weakly significant differ- for efficiency, and (2) is a statement of basic
ence in the emphasis each places on the first needs. Propositions (3) and (4) are reminis-
two goals. These and previously discussed cent of desert, whereby individuals are
results seem more convincingly explained by rewarded or punished for the choices they
culturally dependent weights on justice prin- control but not for the ones they do not.
ciples than by ad hoc assumptions about cul- Young's list is more a set of policy rules than
ture specific norms, because the former pro- values, but it is interesting that he supports
vides a more plausible account of the pattern the notion of trade-offs among a few princi-
both of similarities as well as of differences ples and that he cites the use of rules that
across countries. Indeed, the greatest chal- reflect the three principles of this study (p.
lenge with cross-cultural studies is typically 28). He notes that the point system for allo-
to explain, not the differences, but the strik- cating kidneys in the United States is based
ing preponderance of similarities between on three criteria: (1) efficacy, or the likeli-
people in different countries. These similar- hood the transplant will be a success, (2)
ities surface, not only in views expressed in need, or the lack of alternatives such as dial-
surveys (responses to questions in the ysis, and (3) disadvantage, which compen-
Faidunfair format reported here are no sates for the bad luck of having a kidney that
more than 4 percent apart), but also in is hard to match. Efficacy is an obvious
behavior from experiments (in six of seven counterpart for efficiency in this context: a
countries Henrich 2000 cites, modal offers higher probability of success, ceteris
in the ultimatum game are 40 percent to 50 paribus, means a greater expected benefit.
percent). Need is even more obvious. Disadvantage
1230 Journal of Economic Literature, 7701. XLZ (December 2003)

reflects the desert norm: individuals with number to serve for several years. Elster
difficult to match kidneys are compensated traces queuing to desert and need. The rela-
because they are not responsible for that tionship to desert seems correct in situations
unfortunate fact. in which purchasing power depends mostly
Procedural Justice. Studies of local justice on variables for which people are not
frequently treat not only distributivejustice, responsible (e.g.,luck, birth) and willingness
or fair outcomes, but also procedural justice, to wait depends more on variables for which
or fair processes. In fact, one of the most sig- they are responsible (e.g., effort, choices).
nificant dividends from this school is what it Queuing probably also improves allocations
teaches about fair practices, customs, rules, to more needy persons. Even efficiency
policies and laws. Procedural justice can be might be served to some degree (although
viewed in two ways: as the application of dis- presumably less than with price rationing) as
tributive justice or as something distinct. higher valued buyers, ceteris paribus, will be
On the one hand, just procedures can help more willing to wait. Thus, fair processes
realize just outcomes. The procedures are may be grounded, in part, on these princi-
then means for fulfilling distributions pre- ples of distributive justice.
scribed by the principles of distributive jus- On the other hand, some argue that pro-
tice. It should be noted that, as a matter of cedural justice is valued for itself, inde-
terminology, principle and procedure are pendent of outcomes. Indeed, Nozick's
sometimes used in different senses in the approach (section 4.1) has been character-
justice literature. For example, many advo- ized as the extreme case of procedural jus-
cates of local justice refer to lotteries, rota- tice since allocations are judged (almost)
tion and queuing as principles, whereas I call entirely based on the processes by which
them procedures or mechanisms and they obtained. Juridical applications have
reserve the term principle for a higher level figured prominently in much of this litera-
of abstraction, both for distributive and pro- ture from the pioneering work of John
cedural justice. Local justice theorists do, Thibaut and Laurens Walker (1978) to that
however, distinguish levels of generality. of Tom R. Tyler and E. Allan Lind (2000).
Elster and Young note that, when an item is The growing significance of process over
indivisible, a lottery gives equally deserving outcome is also observed in the arena of
individuals an equal chance. This can be political philosophy and theory, where the
seen as a second best solution: when the theme of discourse looms large.
context complicates or precludes ex post jus- Philosopher and social theorist Jiirgen
tice, this mechanism at least creates ex ante Habermas (1984) proposes a theory of com-
justice. Rotation might similarly help with municative action, which introduces a
indivisible or imperfectly divisible benefits process of inclusive and rational discourse
or burdens. Young points out that rotation aimed at attaining agreement among par-
also eliminates the tension between the ex ties. Habermas and political scientists, such
ante and ex post justice of a lottery. Viewed as John S. Dryzek (1990),advocate an appli-
as means to an end, the desirability of a pro- cation of this to the public sphere called
cedure depends on how well it satisfies "deliberative democracy." This design has
potentially conflicting distributive principles been associated with justice, and morality in
in the context. For example, shared custody general. In fact, political scientists Tracy
might be a practical solution in the case of Sulkin and Adam Simon (2001) conduct
divorce, whereas it could simply be too cost- ultimatum games the results of which indi-
ly in efficiency terms to train all draft-age cate that deliberative opportunities create
men for, say, a few months of service rather both more just outcomes as well as
than simply selecting at random the needed enhanced perceptions of fairness.
Konow: A Positive Analysis of Justice Theories

In economics, Sen has been an important that both outcomes and procedures matter to
contributor to clarifying the distinction perceptions of justice. Using scenarios from
between process and outcome and to stress- politics, healthcare, the market and the work-
ing the importance of process for social place, he concludes that people view as more
choice theory (1995). Frey and Stutzer fair procedures that permit them greater par-
(2001a,b) distinguish outcome utility from ticipation, freedom and information. The
process utility and propose measuring the empirical study of procedural justice by econ-
latter using reported "satisfaction with life." omists is in its infancy, but it represents an
Specifically, in support of claims regarding exciting and important direction of research.
deliberative democracy, they offer evidence
5.3.Context Dependence
that people derive procedural utility from
the ability to participate more directly in the We have examined contextual approaches
political decision making process. Using data to justice and some lessons derived from evi-
from Swiss cantons, they report that in juris- dence on them. The work of Kahneman,
dictions with higher degrees of direct Knetsch, and Thaler contributes to our
democracy, the population is more satisfied, understanding of fair transactions, informa-
both because of more satisfactory outcomes tion effects and subjective values. The stud-
as well as enjoyment of greater participation ies of Elster, Walzer, Young, and Frey and
rights. One outcome they cite (2001b) con- Stutzer, among others, help to clarify issues
cerns compensation of public employees: of membership, competing forces, the
more directly democratic institutions restrict weighting of justice principles and process.
the ability of politicians to "buy" the support Social scientists, and economists in particu-
of low-ranked public employees, resulting in lar, are relative newcomers to the study of
lower compensation to them. High-ranked justice. It should not be surprising, then, if
public employees, on the other hand, must time and effort are needed to sort through
be compensated with higher pay for their these so-called contextual effects and to
reduced power under direct democracy. A identify the general forces at work. This is
second outcome they note is that inhabitants not unlike past experience where, in the
of more directly democratic cantons are early stages of developing theories of mar-
more satisfied, controlling for demographic kets or efficiency, general principles were
variables, income and population size. As obscured by indivisibilities, discontinuities,
evidence of procedural utility, Frey and heterogeneity, informational imperfections
Stutzer (2001a) point to the greater benefit and institutional constraints. Nevertheless,
to Swiss nationals in comparison to foreign as Walzer acknowledges, the existence and
residents. In particular, they attribute this validity of a general theory of justice can only
difference to the existence, rather than the be determined by means of empirical work:
activation, of participation rights of the "It may be the case .. . that certain internal
nationals. principles, certain conceptions of social
Do people not only value procedures goods, are reiterated in many, perhaps in all,
above and beyond their outcomes but also human societies. That is an empirical matter.
specifically value them as being fair? A fre- It cannot be determined by philosophical
quent refrain in this paper is that social argument among ourselves-nor even by
behavior and social preferences do not nec- philosophical argument among some ideal
essarily signify a concern for justice but version of ourselves" (p. 314, n.).
instead could be motivated by reciprocal The idea running through this section is
altruism, familial responsibility, friendship or that justice is a context dependent, but not
even self-interest. Paul Anand (2001) offers context specijiic, phenomenon. That is, its
evidence from a survey of 130 British voters principles do not change according to
Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XLI (December 2003)

context. Instead, justice is a general phe- ple but argues that it mostly falls away in
nomenon, and it is a potential, if not always modern market economies). To my knowl-
realized, force across many contexts. The edge, the first statement of three principles
effects of context should also not be seen as resembling those here is due to Frohlich and
contamination of some ideal, because no Oppenheimer. Based on their experimental
such pristine context-free justice exists. study of preferences for distribution mecha-
Justice evaluation, for example, requires a nisms, they speculate that "distributive jus-
reference group, or choice of relevant indi- tice involves the competing claims of entitle-
viduals, to which to apply the principles, ments, need, and the desirability of
whether it be one's friends, colleagues, preserving incentives" (1992, p. 1761, which
neighbors, citizens or all the people of the they later call just deserts, need and efficien-
world, and justice principles provide no cy (1994, p. 152). Moreover, they conclude
guidance on such questions. Context is the that "If an ethically problematic situation
indispensable element that supplies the peo- involves a conflict between competing val-
ple, variables, time framework and weight- ues, then the strength and weight of those
ing of principles that result in justice prefer- values have to be taken into consideration in
ences. Because individuals may interpret the determination of what is fair" (1992, p.
context differently, unanimity is rarely 176).Frohlich and Oppenheimer do not for-
found, but the high level of agreement usu- mally state the three motives in detail or test
ally observed and the patterned variations them empirically, but such a formulation has
consistent with the contextual effects dis- been proposed and tested using surveys
cussed here indicate that justice is not arbi- (Konow 2001). Dictator experiments
trary, idiosyncratic or capricious. designed to test equity and need (Konow
Nevertheless, the study of justice requires 2000, 2002) establish the relevance of those
an acute awareness of the important but principles when monetary stakes are
often subtle role of context. involved.
John T. Scott et al. (2001) propose a theo-
6. Pluralistic Justice
ry based on four principles that form the
Previous sections have classified and aimed union of the sets listed above, i.e., equality,
to synthesize theories of justice within four equitylmerit, efficiency and need. As equali-
distinct elements of an integrated theory. We ty has played such a prominent role in justice
conclude with an even broader attempt at research, let us consider briefly whether its
synthesis that places the proposed theory in omission from the three principle theory
the context of multi-criterion, or pluralistic, defended here is justified. To clarify, I
justice theories, and considers evidence on acknowledge that equality is a common rule
preferences over the multiple principles. of fairness, i.e., a frequently used mecha-
In social psychology, one of the leading nism. Indeed, Skyrms (1996; 1999 with
pluralistic approaches is that of Morton James Alexander) demonstrates the attrac-
Deutsch (1985),who proposes three princi- tive properties of replicator dynamics for
ples, viz., equality, equity (or proportionality) explaining the emergence of equality when
and need, which in his scheme are specific to agents have no special claim based, say, on
different contexts. David Miller (1976) advo- need or desert. What is in dispute is whether
cates a system based on desert and need in equality is a principle of fairness, i.e., a dis-
which, similar to the current paper, social tinct goal that holds generally and not mere-
context affects in a systematic manner the ly as a special case of general principles.
weight attached to each justice principle as Equality is obviously fair when individuals
well as the importance of justice relative to are equal based on the salient justice princi-
other goals (he also names rights as a princi- p l e ( ~ )i.e.,
, equal desert, need or efficiency.
Konou;: A Positive Analysis of Justice Theories

As discussed in section 2, equality is proba- this claim about equality and solidarity is
bly most often associated with need as peo- apocryphal.25 Even if equality were accord-
ple's basic needs are usually assumed equal, ed status as a general principle in solidarity
consistent with the Murphy-Berman et al. relationships, however, that would still not
finding that Indian subjects tend more make it a general principle of justice.
toward equality than Americans. Echoing Habitual use of equality among friends, for
Leventhal (1976), they conjecture "that example, does not necessarily imply that it is
when the level of resources is low, need may just, but only that it is friendly.
become more salient as an allocation strate- A final point about equality pertains to
gy. In such situations, maintaining minimal the frequent pleas for equality of opportuni-
standards for all recipients may become ty based on appeals to fairness. Note,
more important than increasing the stan- though, that the stated goal in this case is
dards for a few meritorious individuals" not to equalize allocations but only opportu-
(p. 1270). nities, whereby no final outcome, let alone
The more significant hindrance to deter- an equal one, is guaranteed. Indeed, such
mining whether equality is a general princi- arguments are often accompanied by pro-
ple or merely a special case is the presence posals to allocate resources unequally in
of contextual effects that complicate these favor of the disadvantaged in order to "level
efforts. As Miller writes, "In the case of the playing field" (e.g., Roemer 1998). This
equality, on the other hand, there is poten- concern figures ~ r o m i n e n t in
l ~ the discus-
tially always an ambiguity: is equality being sion of allocations to minors, especially of
valued as positively the right thing in the cir- general education. Equality of opportunity
cumstances, or is it being chosen by default, is easily reconciled with the Equity
as it were, in the absence of reliable infor- Principle: the goal is to compensate people
mation about desert or need?" (1992, pp. for factors not under their control such that
559-60). The latter is consistent with the those who contribute more will benefit
evidence cited in section 5.1 of this paper more, but two persons who bear equal
about the ceteris paribus assumption: survey responsibility will experience equal out-
and experimental evidence suggest that peo- comes. This explains why equal opportunity
ple, when they lack information about fac- policies are so persuasively argued with
tors relevant to evaluating justice based on respect to basic education. Children are in a
its principles (e.g., effort, choices, costs, formative phase in which they are acquiring
luck, basic needs, productivity), assume that important skills that will favorably or unfa-
such factors are equal across individuals. In vorably impact their future welfare in dra-
that case, the best possible estimate of fair matic ways. Both because of their develop-
allocations is equal splits. mental level and their constrained freedom
Giith (1988) notes that equality some- of choice, we typically do not hold children
times emerges as a rule when contributions accountable for relevant circumstances such
or rewards are not very important. This
could be explained by efforts to avoid costly '%or example, consider a group of friends settling the
bill after dinner together in a restaurant. The frequent
information search or, consistent with the choice of equal splits is probably due in no small part to a
motives if not outcomes of the Orley desire by the parties not to incur the cost of calculating
Ashenfelter et al. (1992) experiment, costly each diner's individual responsibility including tax and tip
as well as the (perhaps more significant) cost to friendships
disputes. Deutsch argues that equality is the in the form of potential disputes and the appearance of
justice principle that applies in the context of pettiness. Indeed, if more were at stake, e.g., if one party
solidarity relationships such as friendships. If had ordered a small salad with a glass of water whereas the
other party had ordered a four-course meal with wine, the
equality is chosen to avoid information and friends would probably discard the equality rule and agree
dispute costs, however, it seems likely that to a more accurate tallying of accounts.
1234 Journal of Economic Litel pature, Vol. XLI (December2003)

as family income, school district, exposure of providing resources to each, and the
to educational resources at home, etc. severity of the need of each. Ordbfiez and
Adjustments for these morally arbitrary fac- Mellers (1993) corroborate these trade-offs
tors are consistent with the Equity for macro-justice. Although they motivate
Principle. This and the other cases above, their study with reference to the equality-
however, require no appeal to a separate efficiency trade-off, the income distributions
principle of equality. their 150 student respondents evaluate
A final matter for a multi-criterion theom quantitatively reflect different degrees of
of justice is the precise relationship concurrence with the three motives dis-
between the various principles in the pref- cussed here. Subjects compare societies that
erences of individuals. Does the salient differ with regard to mean salary, which
principle reign absolute or do people enter- reflects an efficiency concern, the correla-
tain several principles contemporaneously? tion between work (which includes merit,
If the latter, are preferences over principles, effort, etc.) and salary, which corresponds
for example, lexicographic or do they reflect roughly to the Equity Principle, and the
trade-offs? Evidence previously presented height of the minimum salary, which may be
in this paper, as well as the comments of below or at the poverty level, evoking a con-
Miller, and Frohlich and Oppenheimer, cern for basic needs. The results indicate
point toward the second answer to each of subjects value each of these goals and weigh
these questions. Here we will specifically one against the other.
consider studies that examine Lreferences Ordbfiez and Mellers elicit two sets of
when the degree of conflict between the responses: one for the "more fair" society
three principles is varied. and the other for the society in which the
A vignette study (Konow 2001) examines respondents would "prefer to live." They
pair-wise trade-offs between the three prin- find that fair and preferred income distribu-
ciples of equity, efficiency and need.26 The tions do not necessarily coincide.
results are consistent with the simple model Specifically, fair distributions correlate most
of convex preferences proposed there in strongly with the work-salary correlation,
which agents are averse to allocations that reflecting a concern for the Equity Principle.
deviate from the levels prescribed by the Preferred distributions, on the other hand,
principles. Regarding their relevance to correlate most strongly with minimum salary
micro-justice, Linda Skitka and Philip and mean salary, in that order, pointing
Tetlock (1992) find trade-offs among 235 toward the Need and Efficiency Principles,
student subjects who quantitatively rate allo- respectively. This implies that people value
cations to hypothetical recipients who differ equity but prefer to live in societies that sac-
with respect to their responsibility for or con- rifice some equity in order to provide for
trol over their circumstances, the efficiency higher minimum and mean earnings.
This finding dovetails with a subtle but
important property of justice that has been
"The study by Gaertner, Jungeilges, and Neck (2001) traced to Aristotle. The argument is that jus-
provides especially thorough evidence on the trade-off
between two of these principles: need and efficiency. tice terminology is used in different senses,
Subjects in five countries face two hypothetical situations the more specific sense corresponding to the
involving the allocation of scarce resources to one of two Equity (or Accountability) Principle and the
policies. One policy addresses basic needs while the level
of benefits from the other policy are varied across four dif- most general sense connoting the whole of
ferent versions of each scenario. Depending on the ques- morality. Thus, in one sense, "fair" refers
tion and country between 26 percent and 79 percent of only to equity, and, in another sense, means
respondents who initially chose the first policy switch to
the second as the benefits of the second rise, consistent "good and also includes need and efficien-
with a trade-off between need and efficiency. cy. Typically, the terms fair and just connote
Konow: A Positive Analysis ofJustice Theories

a mixture of these two sense^.'^ By compar- 2. Leonard Berkowitz, ed. NY, London: Academic
Press Inc, pp. 267-99.
ing preferences for "fair" versus "right" allo- Akerlof, George A. and Janet Yellen. 1990. "The Fair
cations when equity, need and efficiency Wage-Effort Hypothesis and Unemployment,"
conflict, one finds support for these claims Quart. J. Econ. 105:2, pp. 255-83.
Alexander, James, and Brian Skyrms. 1999. "Bargaining
(Konow 2001). The implication of these with Neighbors: Is Justice Contagious?" J.
studies is that equity (i.e.,justice in the spe- Philosophy 96:1, pp. 588-98.
cific sense) guides but does not monopolize Alwin, Duane F.; Galin Gornev and Ludmila
Khakhulina. 1995. "Comparative Referential
distributive preferences: people care about Structures, System Legitimacy, and Justice
equity, but the allocations they prefer for Sentiments: An International Comparison," in Social
themselves and consider right are also influ- Justice and Political Change. James R. Kluegel,
David S. Mason and Bernd Wegener, eds. NY:
enced by concerns for efficiency and need. Walter de Gruyter, Inc, pp. 1 0 9 3 1
This paper has examined the descriptive Amiel, Yoram, and Frank A. Cowell. 1999. Thinking
power of many influential positive and nor- About Inequality: Personal Judgment and Income
Distributions. Cambridge: Cambridge U. Press.
mative theories of justice employing numer- Anand, Paul. 2001. "Procedural Fairness in Economic
ous results that have now been collected by and Social Choice: Evidence from a Survey of
social scientists. The theories, as well as the T70ters,"J.Econ. Ps ch 22, pp. 247-70.
Andreoni, James, a n 1 ~ d h nH Miller. 2002. "Giving
empirical evidence on them, contribute to According to GARP: An Experimental Test of the
an understanding of shared concepts of jus- Consistency of Preferences for Altruism,"
tice, although no single theory suffices to Econometrica 70:2, pp. 737-53.
Aristotle. 1925. Ethica Nicomachea. Trans. W. D. Ross.
that end. A multi-criterion theory of justice London: Oxford U. Press.
. 1973. "Some Ordinalist-Utilitarian Notes
is proposed in which three justice principles
are interpreted, weighted and applied in a KI
on Raw s's Theory of Justice," J. Philosophy 70:9, pp.
245-63.
manner that depends on the context. This Ashenfelter, Orley; Janet Currie, Henry S. Farber and
integrated theory purports to offer a broad Matthew Spiegel. 1992. "An Experimental
and systematic account of popular views of Comparison of Dispute Rates in Alternative
Arbitration Systems," Econometrica 60:6, pp.
justice. Probably the most significant chal- 140733.
lenge to this or any theory, however, is to Babcock, Linda; George Loewenstein, Samuel
incorporate the impact of context on justice Issacharoff and Colin Camerer. 1995. "Biased
Judgments of Fairness in Bargaining," Amel: Econ.
evaluation, and much work remains in this Rev. 85:5, pp. 133743.
regard. If these issues can be resolved, the Babcock, Linda; Xianghong Wang and George
resulting theory of justice would provide Loewenstein. 1996. "Choosing the Wrong Pond:
Social Comparisons in Negotiations that Reflect a
immeasurable assistance in many ways: it Self-Serving Bias," Quart. J . Econ. 111:1, pp. 1-19.
could help to explain phenomena impacted Ball, Sheryl B. and Paula-Ann Cech. 1996. "Subject
by it, to distinguish distributive preferences Pool Choice and Treatment Effects in Economic
Laboratory Research," Research Experiment. Econ.
from other motives such as self-interest, rec- 6, pp. 239-92.
iprocity and altruism, and to guide social Barry, Brian M. 1989. Denmcracy, Power, and Justice:
policies. Essays in Political Theory. NY, Oxford: Clarendon
REFERENCES Press and Oxford U. Press.
Baumol, William J. 1986. Superfairness: Applications
Adams, J. Stacy. 1965. "Inequality in Social Exchange," and Theory. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
in Adounces in Experimental Social Psychology, vol. Bazerman, Max H. 1985. "Norms of Distributive
Justice in Interest Arbitration," Ind. Lab. Relat. Rez;.
38, p p 558-70.
2i Actually, fair in the general sense can include any Bentham, J. 1789. An Introduction to the Principles of
moral criterion, e.g., familial duty, friendship, love, reci- Morals and Legislation. London: Payne.
procity, etc. The current paper adopts an intermediate Berg, Joyce; John Dickhaut and Kevin McCabe. 1995.
approach: justice encompasses preferences over alloca- "Trust, Reciprocity, and Social History," Games
tions but not over behavior. This might conflict with some Econ. Behaz;. 10:1, pp. 1 2 2 4 2 .
uses of justice terminology, but my sense is that this level Binmore, Ken. 1994. Game T h e o y and the Social
of specificity comes closest to common usage while making Contract, Vol2: Just Playing. Cambridge, MA: MIT
a useful distinction from that which is merely "good." Press.
Journal of Economic Lite rature, Vol. XLI (Dece~izber2003)

Blinder, Alan S. and Don H. Choi. 1990. "A Shred of Equality of Resources," Philosophy Public Affairs
Evidence on Theories of Wage Stickiness," Quart. J. 1O:l, pp. 283-345.
Econ. 105:4, pp. 1003-15. . 2000. Soccrcign Virtue: The Theory and
Blount, Sally 1995. "When Social Outcornes Aren't Practice of Equality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard U.
Fair: The Effect of Casual Attributions on Press.
Preferences," Org. Behac. Human Decision Eckel, Catherine C. and Philip J. Grossman. 1996.
Processes 63:2, pp. 1 3 1 4 4 . "Altruism in Anonymous Dictator Games," Games
Boadway, Robin and Neil Bruce. 1984. Welfare Econ. Behaz;. 16, pp. 181-91.
Economics. Oxford, NY: Basil Blackwell. Ellingsen, Tore and Ma nus Johannesson. 2003. "Sunk
Bolton, Gary E. and Axel Ockenfels. 2000. "ERC: A Costs, Fairness, an3 Disagreement," Stockholm
Theory of Equity, Reciprocity, and Competition," School Econ.
A i m r Econ Rez; 90:1, g p 166,-93. Elster, Jon. 1992. Local Justice: How Institutions
Bowles, Samuel and Her ert G ~ n t ~1998. s. Recasting Allocate Scarce Goor1.r and Necessary Burdens, NY:
Egalitarianism: New Rules for Communities, States Russell Sage Foundation.
and Markets. The Real Utopias Project, vol. 3. Erik Falk, Armin and Urs Fischbacher. 1998. "A Theory of
Olin Wright, ed. NY: T7erso. Reci rocity," U. Zurich manuscript.
Buchan, Nancy R.; Rachel T.A. Croson and Eric J. Farweh), Lisa, and Bernard Weiner 1996. "Self-
Johnson. 2003. ''When Do Fairness Beliefs Influence Perceptions of Fairness in Indixidual and Group
Bargaining Behavior: Experimental Ecidence from Contexts," Personality Social Psych. Bull. 22:9, pp.
Japan and the United States," forthcoming, J. 867-991.
Consunwr Res. Fehr, Ernst and Simon Gachter. 2000. "Fairness and
Buchanan, Allen E. 1981. "The Marxian Critique of Retaliation: The Economics of Reciprocity,"J . Econ.
Justice and Rights," Canadian J . Philosophy 7:Supp., Perspect. 14:3, pp. 159-81.
DD. 269306. Fehr, Ernst; Simon Giichter and Georg Kirchsteiger.
~ d h a n a nJames
, M. 1986. Liberty, Market and State: 1997. "Reciprocity as a Contract Enforcement
Political Economy in the 1980s. NY: NYU. Press, Device: Experimental Evidence," Econometrica
Columbia U. Press. 654, pp. 833-60.
Burrows, Paul, and Graham Loomes. 1994. "The Fehr, Ernst and Klaus M. Schmidt. 1999. "A Theory of
Impact of Fairness on Bargaining Beha~ior,"Empil: Fairness, Competition and Cooperation," Quart. J.
Econ. 19, pp. 201-21. Econ. 114:3, pp. 817-68.
Cameron, Lisa A. 1999. "Raising the Stakes in the Fole): Duncan K. 1967. "Resource Allocation and the
Ultimatum Game: Experimental Evidence from Public Sector," Yale Econ. Essays 7, pp. 45-98.
Indonesia," Econ. Inquiry 37:1, pp. 47-59. Fong, Christina. 2001. "Social Preferences, Self-
Charness, Gary and Brit Grosskopf. 2001. "Relative Interest, and the Demand for Redistribution," J .
Payoffs and Happiness: An Experimental Study," J. Public Econ. 82:2, p 22546.
Econ. Behaz;. Org. 45:3, pp. 301-28. Forsythe, Robert; Jo?i'L Horowiti, N.E. Sacin and
Charness, Gary and Matthew Rabin. 2002. Martin Sefton. 1994. "Fairness in Simple
"Understanding Social Preferences with Simple
Tests," Quart. J. Econ. 117:3, pp. 817-69.
Bargaining
L,

p p 347-69.
.
" Experiments," Games Econ. Bchaz;. 6,

Clark, Jeremy. 1998. "Fairness in Public Good Franciosi. Robert: Praveen Kuid. Roland Michelitsch.
Provision: An Investigation of Preferences for TJernon' Smith 'and Gang ~ e n g .1995. "~airnessj
Equality and Proportionality," Canadian J. Econ. Effect on Temporary and Equilibrium Prices in Post-
31:3, pp. 708-29. Offer Markets," Econ. ]. 105:431, pp. 938-50.
Cohen, Ronald L. 1982. "Perceiving Justice: An Frank, Robert H. 1988. Passions within Reason. NY:
Attributional Perspective," in Equity and Justice in W.W. Norton Co.
Social Behacior. Jerald Greenberg and Ronald L. Frey, Bruno S. and Beat Gygi. 1988. "Die Fairness von
Cohm. e d s NY: Academic Press.jp. 119-60. Preisen," Schtcci;erischc Zcitschrift TJolkswirtschaft
Cox, James C. 2003. "How to I entlfy Trust and Statistik 124:4, pp. 51941.
Reciprocity," forthcoming, Games, Econ. Behac. Frey, Bruno S.; Felix Oberholzer-Gee and Reiner
Cullen, Bernard. 1994. "Philoso hical Theories of Eichenberger. 1996. "The Old Ladv Visits Your
Justice," in P s t i a : Interdia:ip!nay Pcrspecti~es. Backyard: A Tale of Morals and ~ a r k e t s , "J. Polit.
Klaus R. Scherer, ed. Chippenham, Wiltshire, UK: Econ. 104:6, pp. 1297-313.
Antony Rowe Ltd, pp. 15-64. Frey, Bruno S. and Werner W. Pommerehne. 1993.
Dahl, Gordon B. and Michael R. Ransom. 1999. "Does "On the Fairness of Pricing-an Empirical Survey
Where You Stand Depend on Where You Sit? Among the General Population," 1. Econ. Behac.
Tithing Donations and Self-Serving Beliefs," Amer Org. 20, pp. 295-307.
Econ. Rec. 89:4, pp. 703-27. Frey, Bruno S. and Alois Stutzer. 2001a. "Beyond
Deutsch, Morton. 1985. Distributi~e Justice. Bentham-Measuring Procedural Utility," CESifo
Bin hamton, NY: \'ail-Ballou Press. work. paper 492, Center Econ. Studies and Institute
Dryzef, John S 1990 Discursire Deimcracy: Politics, for Econ. Research, Munich.
Policl and Political Science. Cambridge and NY: . 2001b. "Outcome, Process and Power in
Canitridge U. Press. Direct Democracy," Public Choice 107, pp. 271-293.
Dworkin, Ronald. 1981. "What Is Equality? Part 2: Frohlich, Norman and Joe A. Oppenheimer. 1992.
Konow: A Positive Analysis of Justice Theories
Choosing Justice: An Experimental Approach to Amel: Econ. Rec. 91:2, pp. 73-78.
Ethical Theoy. Berkeley and LA: U. California Press. Hicks, John R. 1940. "The \'aluation of Social Income,"
. 1994. "Preferences for Income Distribution Economica 7, . 105-24.
and Distributive Justice: A Window on the Problems Hoffman, Eliza%$h; Kevin McCabe, Keith Shachat
of Using Experimental Data in Economics and and Vernon Smith. 1994. "Preferences, Property
Ethics," Eastern Econ. J . 20:2, p 147 55. Rights, and Anonymity in Bargaining Games,"
Frohlich, Norman; Joe A, OppenReimer,;nd Cheryl L. Games Econ. Behau. 7, pp. 34G80.
Eavey. 1987. "Laboratory Results on Rawls's Hoffman, Elizabeth and Matthew L. Spitzer. 1985.
Distributive ustice," Brit. 1. Polit. Sci. 17, pp. 1-21. "Entitlements, Rights, and Fairness: An
/
Gaertner, Wul ; Jochen Jungeilges and Reinhard Neck.
2001. "Cross-Cultural E uity Evaluations: A
Experimental Examination of Sub'ects' Concepts of
Distributive Justice," J Legal Stud 14, pp. 259-97.
Questiannaire-Experimentj Approach," Europ. Holcombe, Randall G. 1997. "Communications:
Econ. Rev. 45, pp. 953-63. Absence of Envy Does Not Imply Fairness," South.
Gauthier, David. 1985. "Bargaining and Justice," in Econ. J . 63:3, pp. 797402.
Ethics and Economics. Ellen Frankel Paul, Jeffrey Holm, H2kan and Peter Engseld. 2001. "Choosing
Paul, and Fred D. Miller, Jr., eds. Oxford: Basil Bargainin Partners: An Experimental Study on the
Blachvell, pp. 2 9 4 7 . Impact ofgInformation About Income and Gender,"
Gachter, Simon and Arno Riedl. 2001. "Moral Property econ. dept. Lund U. Sweden.
Rights in Bargaining," dept, econ. and econometrics, Homans, George C. 1958. "Social Behavior as
Amsterdam, The Netherlands; St. Gallen, Exchange," Amel: J. Sociology 63, pp. 59W306.
Switzerland. U. Amsterdam, U. St. Gallen. Jasso, Guillermina. 1999. "How Much Injustice Is
George, Henry. 1879 [1914]. Progress and Poverty. San There in the World? Two New Justice Indexes,"
Francisco, NY: Random House. Amer: Sociol. Rez;. 64:1, pp. 133-68.
Goldstein, William M. and Elke U. Weber. 1995. Jasso, Guillermina and Peter H. Rossi. 1977.
"Content and Discontent: Indication and Implications "Distibutive Justice and Earned Income," Amer:
of Domain Specificity in Preferential Decision Sociol. Rev. 42, pp. 639-51.
Making," Psych. Learning Motivation 32, pp. 83-136. Kachelmeier, Steven .; Stephen T. Limberg and
Greenberg, Jerald. 1979. "Protestant Ethic
Endorsement and the Fairness of Equity Inputs,"].
d
Michael S. Schadew d. 1991. "A Laboratory Market
Examination of the Consumer Price Response to
Research Personality 13, p. 81-90. Information About Producers' Costs and Profits,"
Guth, Werner. 1988. "On t e Behavioral Approach to Account. Rev. 66:4, pp. 694-717.
Distributive Justice: A Theoretical and Experimental Kagel, John H.; Chung Kim and Donald bloser. 1996.
Investigation," in Aspects of Distributive Justice. "Fairness in Ultimatum Games with Asymmetric
Shlomo blaital, ed. NY: NYU Press, pp. 703-17. Information and Asymmetric Payoffs," Games Econ.
. 1994. "Distributive Justice: A Behavioral Behac. 13:l, pp. 100-10.
Theory and Em irical Evidence," in Essays on Kahneman, Daniel; Jack L. Knetsch and Richard
Economic P ~ y c h o ~H. ~ yBrandstitter
. and Werner Thaler. 1986. "Fairness as a Constraint on Profit
Guth, eds. pp. 153-75. Seeking: Entitlements in the Market," Amer: Econ.
Guth, Werner and Reinhard Tietz. 1990. "Ultimatum Rec. 76, pp. 7 2 8 4 1 .
Bargaining Behavior: A Survey and Comparison of Kahneman, Daniel and Amos Tversky. 1979. "Prospect
Experimental Results,"J. Econ. Psych. 11,pp. 41749. Theory: An Analysis of Decision Under Risk,"
The Theoy of Communicative Econometrica 47:2, pp. 273,277-78.
kommunikativen Handelns) Kaldor, Nicholas. 1939. "Welfare Propositions of
Trans. Thomas McCarthy. Boston: Beacon Press. Economics and Interpersonal Comparisons of
Harsanyi, P h n Cithics, 1955. "Cardinal Welfare, Utility," Econ. J . 49, p 549 51
Individua istic and Interpersonal Kashima, Yoshihisa; Migael G e g i , Kenichiro Tanaka
Comparisons of Utility," J. Polit. Econ. 63, pp. 309-21. and Hiroko Isaka. 1988. "Universalism in Lay
Harsanyi, John C. 1975. "Can the Maximin Princi le Conceptions of Distributive Justice: A Cross-
Serve as a Basis for Morali ? A Critique of Jo n
9
Rawls's Theory," Amel: Po it. Sci. Rez;. 69, pp.
K Cultural Examination," Int. ]. Psych. 23, pp. 51-64.
Kluegel, James R. and Eliot R. Smith. 1986. Beliefs
594606. About Ine uality: Americans' Views of What Is and
Heider, Fritz. 1958. The Psychology of interpersonal What OuJt T O ' B ~NY: . Aldine De Gruyter.
Relations. NY: John Wiley & Sons. Knez, Marc J. and Colin F. Camerer. 1995. "Outside
Heller, Agnes. 1974. The Theoy of Need in Man. 0 tions and Social Comparison in Three-Player
London: Allison & Busby Limited. UPtimatum Game Experiments," Games Econ.
Henrich, Joseph. 2000. "Does Culture Matter in Behav. 10:l, pp. 65-94.
Economic Behavior? Ultimatum Game Bargaining Kolm, Serge-Christophe. 1985. Le Contrat Social
among the Machiguenga of the Peruvian Amazon," Libdral: Philosophie et Pratique du Libdralisme.
Amel: Econ. Rez;. 90:4, pp. 973-79. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.
Henrich, Joseph; Robert Boyd, Samuel Bowles, Colin Konow, James. 1996. "A Positive Theory of Economic
Camerer, Emst Fehr, Herbert Gintis and Richard Fairness," J. Econ. Behav. Org. 31:1, pp. 1 3 3 5 .
McElreath. 2001. "In Search of Homo Economicus: . 2000. "Fair Shares: Accountability and
Behavioral Experiments in 15 Small-Scale Societies," Cognitive Dissonance in Allocation Decisions,"
Journal of Econolizic Literature, Vol. XLI (Decelizber 2003)
Anwr. Econ Rec. 90:4, pp. 1072-92. Marx, Karl and Friedrich Engels. 1958. Selected
. 2001. "Fair and Square: The Four Sides of Ivorks. London: Lawrence and Wishart.
Distributive Justice," J. Econ. Behac. Org. 46:2, pp. McCloskey, Herbert and John Zaller. 1984. The
137-64.
-. American Ethos: Public Attitudes Touard Capitalism
2002. "Mixed Feelings: Theories and Ecidence and Democracy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard U. Press.
of \{'arm Glow and Altruism," econ. dept., Lovola Messick, David M. and Keith l? Sentis. 1979. "Fairness
Maqqnount U. a ~ PreferenceYJ.
d Exper. Sociul Psych 15:4,ip.41834.
Kravitz. David A. and Samuel Gunto. 1992. "Decisions . 1983. "Fairness, Preference, an Fairness
and Perceptions of Recipients in Ultimatum Biases," in Equity Theory: Psychological and
Bargaining Games," J. Socio-Econ. 21:1, 65-84. Sociological Perspectines. Dacid 41. Messick and
Kritikos, Alexander and Friedel Bo?~'. 2001. Karen Cook, eds. NY: Praeger Publishers, pp. 61-94.
"Distributional Concerns: Equity- or Efficiency- Mikula, Gerold, ed. 1980.Justice and Social Interaction:
Oriented?" Econ. Letters 73:3, pp. 333-38. Experinwntal and Theoretical Contributions from
Krosnick, Jon A. 1991. "Response Strategies for Coping Psychological Research. NY: Springer-\'erlag.
with the Cognitive Demands of an Attitude Measure Mikula, Gerold and Thomas Schwinger. 1973.
in Surveys," Applied Cognitice Psych. 5, pp. 213-36. "Sym athie zum Partner und Bediirfnis nach
Lamm, Helmut and Thomas Schwinger. 1980. "Norms f'
sozia e r Anerkennung als Determinanten der
Concerning Distributive Justice: Are Needs Taken Aufteilung gemeinsam erzielter Gewinne,"
Into Consideration in Allocation Decisions?" Social Psychologische Beitrage 153, pp. 396407.
Psych. Quart. 43:4, pp. 425-29. Mill, John Stuart. 1861 [1979]. L7tilitarianism.
Lanza, Marilyn Lewis; James Carifio, Ivor Pattison and Indianapolis and Cambridge, MA: Hackett Pub. Co.
Carol Hicks. 1997. "Validation of a Vignette Miller, David. 1976 [1979]. Social Justice. Oxford:
Simulation of Assault on Nurses by Patients," J. Clarendon Press.
Nursing Scholarship 29:2, 151-54 , 1992. "Distributive Justice: What the People

Ledyard, John 0 1995 'Pu\?;c Goods: A Survey of Think," Ethics 102, pp. 555-93.
Experimental Research," in The Handbook of Murphv-Bennan, Virginia; John J. Berman, Purnima
Experimental Economics. John H. Kagel and Ahin E. ~ingfi,An'u Pachauri and Pramod Kumar. 1984.
Roth, eds. Princeton: Princeton U. Press, p 111-94. "Factors Aifecting Allocation to Needy and Meritorious
Leventhal, Gerald S. 1976. "The D i s t r i g ~ i o nof Recipients: A Cross-CulturalComparison,"J. Personal.
Rewards and Resources in Groups and Social Psych. 46: 6, pp. 126F72.
Organizations," in Advances in Experimental Social Nielsen, Kai. 1985. Equality and Liberty. Totowa, NJ:
Psychology, L701. 9. Leonard Berkowitz and Elaine Rowman and Allanheld.
\IJalster, eds. NY: Academic Press, pp. 92-131. Nozick, Robert. 1974. Anarchy, State, and L'topia. NY:
Leventhal, Gerald S.; Jurgis Kan~zaand \t7illiam Rick Basic Books.
FT 1980. "Beyond Fairness: A Theon of Allocation Oberholzer-Gee, Felix; Iris Bohnet and Bnlno Frey.
Preferences," in J ~ ~ s t i cand
e Social Interaction: 1997. "Fairness and Competence in Democratic
Experimental and Theoretical Contributions from Decisions," Public Choice 91:1, pp. 89-105.
Psychological Research. Gerold Mikula, ed. NY: Oleson, Paul E. 2001. "An Experimental Examination
Springer Verla pp 167 218 of Alternative Theories of Distributive Justice and
Leventhal, Gerah s a n d j a m i s 16 Michaels 1971. Economic Fairness," unpub. dissertation, U. Arizona.
"Locus of Cause an Equity Motivation as Ordbfiez, Lisa D. and Barbara A. Mellers. 1993.
Determinants of Reward Allocation," I. Personalitu "Trade-offs in Fairness and Preference Judgments,"
Social Psych. 17 3, pp. 229-35. in Psycholo ical Perspectives on Justice. Barbara A.
Leventhal. Gerald S. and Harold D. LVluteside 1973. Mellers a n 2 Jonathan Baron, e d s Cambridge, UK:
"E u i 6 and the Use of Reward to Elicit High Cambridge U. Press, pp. 138-54.
Pe~ormance,;./ Personal Soc?al Psych 251. ps. 7%. Overlaet, Bert. 1991. "Merit Criteria as Tustification for
Lexine, David I. 1993. "Fairness, Markets, an Ability Differences in Earnings,"J. Econ. psych. 12:4, pp.
to Pay: Exidence from Compensation Executives," 689-706.
Anlcr. Econ. Rec. 83:5, pp. 1241-59. Pareto, Vilfredo. 1906 [1971]. Manual of Political
Major, Brenda and Kay Deaux. 1982. "Indixidual Economy. NY: Augustus M. Kelley
Differences in Justice Behavior," in Equity and Justice Pazner, Elisha A,, and David Schmeidler. 1978.
in Social Behaviol: Jerald Greenberg and Ronald L. "Egalitarian Equivalent Allocations: A New Concept
Cohen, eds. NY: Academic Press, pp. 43-76. of Economic Equit);" Quart. J. Econ. 92, pp. 671-87.
Malthus, Thomas R. 1798 [1914]. An Essay on the Posner, Richard A. 1981. The Economics of Justice.
Principle ($Population. London: J.M. Dent & Sons. Cambridge: Haward U. Press.
Martin, Elizabeth and Anne Polivka. 1992. "The Effect Rabin, Matthew. 1993. "Incorporating Fairness into
of Questionnaire Redesign on Conceptual Problems Game Theory and Economics," Amel: Econ. Rec.
in the Current Population Sumey," Proceedin s of
a
Amel: Statist. Assoc. Section on Suroey Met orl.~,
Aug., pp. 655-60.
83:5, p 1281-302.
Raphasf D.D. 1980 Justice and Liberty London:
Athlone Press.
Marx, Karl. 1875 [1993]. "Critique of the Gotha Rawls, John. 1971. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge:
Programme," in Justice. Alan Ryan, ed. Oxford: Belknap Press of Hanard U. Press.
Oxford U. Press, pp. 159-63. Reiman, Jeffrey H. 1981. "The Possibility of a Marxian
Konow: A Positiue Analysis of Justice Theories

The09 of Justice," Canadzan J Phzlosophy 7 Supp , Shiller, Robert J.; Maxim Boy-cko and Vladimir
vv 307-22 Korobov. 1991. "Popular Attitudes toward Free
~ & m e r ,John E. 1998. Equality of Opportunity. Markets: The Soxiet Union and the United States
Cambridge: Harvard U. Press. Compared," Arne,: Econ. Rev. 81:3, pp. 385400.
Roth, Alvin E. 1995. "Introduction to Experimental Shtka, Linda J. and Philip E. Tetlock. 1992. "Allocating
Economics," in The Handbook of Experimental Scarce Resources: A Contingency Model of
Econonlics. John H. Kagel and Ahin E. Roth, eds. Distributive Justice," J. Expe,: Social Psych. 28:6, pp.
Princeton: Princeton U. Press, pp. 3-109. 491-522.
Roth, Alvin E. and J. Keith Murnighan. 1982. "The Shrms, Brian. 1996. Evolution ofthe Social Contract.
Role of Information in Bargaining: An Experimental NY: Cambridge U. Press.
Study," Econornetrica 50:5, p 112342. Slonim, Robert, and Alvin E. Roth. 1998. "Learning in
Roth, Akin E.; Vesna Prasnifar, Masahiro Okuno- High Stakes Ultimatum Games: An Experiment in
Fujiwara and Shmuel Zan~ir.1991. "Bargainin and the Slovak Republic," Econometrica 66:3, pp.
a r k Behavior in Jerusalem, L'ublana, 569-96.
Pittsburgh, m d Tokyo: An Experimental Study" Smith, Adam. 1759 [1809]. The Theory of hloral
Arne,: Econ. Rec. 81:5, pp. 1068-95. Sentiments. Glasgow: R. Chapman.
Rotter, Julian B. 1966. "Generalized Expectancies for Sulkin, Tracy- and Adam Simon. 2001. "Habermas in
Internal versus External Control of Reinforcement," the Lab: A Study of Deliberation in an Experimental
PSIchological Monographs 80:1, p. 609. Setting," Polit. Psych. 22:4, pp. 809-26.
Rufde, Bradley- J. 1998. "More Is Better, but Fair is Thaler, Richard H. 1980. "Toward a Positive Theoy of
Fair: Tipping in Dictator and Ultimatum Games," Consumer Choice,"J. Econ. Behac. Org. 1, pp. 39-60.
Games Econ. Behac. 23, pp. 247-65. Thibaut, John and Laurens \\'alker. 1978. "A T h e o y of
Samuelson, Paul A. 1950. "Evaluation of Real National Procedure," California Lau: Rev. 66, pp. 541-66.
Income," Oxford Econ. Papers 2, pp. 1-29. Tucker, Robert C. 1969. The Mamian RecOl~tiona~j
Schokkaert, Erik. 1994. "The Economics of Idea. NY: \IJ.\IJ. Norton.
Distributive Justice, \\'elfare and Freedom," in Tyler, Tom R. and E. Allan Lind. 2000. "Procedural
Justice: Interdisciplinary Perspectices. Klaus R. Justice," in Handbook of Justice Research in Law.
Scherer, ed. Chippenham, \IJiltshire, UK: Antony Joseph Sanders and \! Lee Hamilton, eds. NY:
Rowe Ltd, pp. 65-113. Kluwer Academicfflenum Pub., pp. 65-92.
Schokkaert, Erik and Bart Capeau. 1991. \'anan, Hal R. 1974. "Equity, Envy and Efficiency" J.
"Interindividual Differences in Opinions about Econ. Theory 9, pp. 63-91.
Distributive Justice," Kyklos 44:3, pp. 2 5 4 5 . \Valster, Elaine; G. \IJilliam \t7alster and Ellen
Schokkaert, Erik and Leo Lagrou. 1983. "An Empirical Berscheid. 1973. "New Directions in Equity
c hDistributive Tustice." 1. P ~ ~ b lEcon.
AL~L ~ r o a to ic 21. Research," J . Personal. Social Psych. 25:2, p 151-76.
33-52. . 1978 Eyility: Theory and Rerearcf.' Boston.
Sctiikaert, Erik and Bert Overlaet. 1989. "Moral London, Sydney Toronto: Al$n and Bacon, Inc.
Intuitions and Economic Models." Social Choice \Valzer, Michael. 1983. Spheres ($Justice: A Defense o f
Welfare 6, p 19-31 Pluralisnz and Eq~lality.NY: Basic Books, Inc.
Scito\sky. Titor 1941 "A Note on \\'elfare \IJeiner, Bernard; Irene Frieze, Andy Kukla, Linda
Propositions in Economics," Rev Econ Stud 9, pp Reed, Stanley-Rest and Robert M . Rosenbaum. 1971.
77-88 "Perceiving the Causes of Success and Failure," in
Scitovsky, Tibor 1986 Hurnan Des~reand Econonnc Attribution: Perceiving the Ca~lsesof Behavior.
~ati&ction: Essays on the Frontiers of Econonlics. Edward E. Jones, Da\id E. Kanouse, Richard E.
NY: NYU Press. Nisbett, Stuart k l i n s , and Barbara \Veiner, eds.
Scott, John T.; Richard Matland, Philip Michelbach Morristown, NJ: General Learning Press, pp.
and Brian Bornstein. 2001. "Just Deserts: An 95-120.
Experimental Study of Distributive Justice Norms," LVeiner, Bernard and And Kukla. 1970. "An
Ame,: J. Polit. Sci. 45:4, pp. 749-67. Attributional Analysis of Acgievement Motivation,"
Selten, Reinhard. 1978. "The Equity Principle in J. Personal. Social Psych. 15:1, pp. 1-20.
Economic Behavior," in Decision Theonj and Social Wood, Allen. 1981. Karl M a n . London: Routledge &
Ethics; Issues in Social Choice. H. Gottinger and \V. Kegan Paul.
Leinfellner, eds. Dordrecht: Reifel Pub., pp. 289301. Yaari, Menahem E. and Maya Bar-Hillel. 1984. "On
Sen, Amartya. 1973 [1997]. On Economic Inequality, Di\iding Justly," Social Choice Welfare 1:1, pp. 1-24.
Expanded Edition with a Substantial Annexe b Youn , Gar): 1981. "Doing Man; Justice," Canadian J.
James E Foster and Amartya S e n OxfordY Ph$osophy i:Supp., p p 251-68.
Clarendon Press. Young, H . Peyton. 1994. Equity in Theory and
. 1979. "The \\'elfare Basis of Real Income Practice. Princeton: Princeton U. Press.
Comparisons: A Suney," J. Econ. Lit. l 7 : l , pp. 1 4 5 . Zajac, Edward E. 1985. "Perceived Economic Justice:
. 1995. "Rationality and Social Choice," A m , : The Example of Public Utilit). Regulation," in Cost
Econ. Rec. 85:l, pp. 1-24. Allocation: Methorl.~, Principles, Applications. H.
Shafir, Eldar, Peter Diamond, and Amos Tversky. 1997. Peyton Young, ed. North-Holland: Elsevier Science
"Money- Illusion," Quart. J. Econ. 1122, pp. 341-74. Pub. B.\: pp. 119-53.

You might also like