You are on page 1of 11

Human Organization, Vol. 73, No.

3, 2014
Copyright © 2014 by the Society for Applied Anthropology
0018-7259/14/030224-11$1.60/1

Of What is This a Case?: Analytical Movements in


Qualitative Social Science Research
Christian Lund
Case studies are often presented as self-evident. However, of what the material is a case is actually less evident. It is argued
in this article that the analytical movements of generalization, speciication, abstraction, and concretization can make us more
conscious of what our work might be a case, and that the same data have the potential to make different cases depending on
these analytical movements. An analytical matrix is developed, and the four movements and various pitfalls are discussed.

Key words: case study, analytical movements, generalization, abstraction, theorization

Introduction a distinction between concrete micro situations, which are


immediately accessible to the researcher, and more abstract
o, what is it a case of? As I was inalizing a book and aggregated cases. By micro cases, he refers to events

S on land struggles in Northern Ghana, the publishers


asked me to write a couple of abstracts. They asked
for abstracts for the libraries, the catalogue, the booksell-
and problems that the participants as well as the observers
are able to discern as relatively discrete sets of events and
actions. Cases of this nature could be a land conlict, a lo-
cal election, a cockight, or even an opening of a bridge in
ers, and the marketing department of 150, 90, 50, and 15
words, respectively. After working on the book for years, modern Zululand.2 More aggregated and abstract cases such
producing such succinct abstracts proved more dificult than as “the economy of France” or “corruption in Indonesia” are
imagined. The book dealt with the complexities of conlicts, established through concepts. The participants may well ex-
the cultural idioms of ownership and obligation, the impor- perience them, but they are not readily or easily discernable.
tance of national policies, the ambiguities of local histories While scale matters, and while this distinction is intuitively
and politicking, the violence of political competition, the appealing, the common feature for both kinds of cases is,
gerrymandering by electoral commissions, the elasticity of however, that they are intellectually constructed—either by
ethnicity, the illegal government land acquisitions, and it participants, observers, or both.
analyzed people’s dexterous reconiguration of public and Case studies are often presented as self-evident. How-
private. But of what was it a case? ever, of what the material is a case is actually less evident. In
A case is an edited chunk of empirical reality where this article, I will discuss elements for a conceptual strategy
certain features are marked out, emphasized, and privileged to help answer that question. Hence, the present article is not
while others recede into the background. As such, a case is about case study design or planning how to engage a ield
not “natural,” but a mental, or analytical, construct aimed at in a systematic and formal way. There is a broad “design”
organizing knowledge about reality in a manageable way. literature where hypotheses and variables are explicitly linked
This covers many forms.1 Olivier de Sardan (2008) makes to particular cases and sub-cases and where principles of data
collection are examined.3 The present text is more an attempt
to investigate the potential of one’s work once research has
begun. While the planning and design of case studies are
Christian Lund is professor at the Department of Food and Resource important before the ield is entered into, the data is often
Economics at the University of Copenhagen. Comments and questions
from many people have helped to structure the argument. In particular, somewhat unwieldy and full of generous surprises. In this
input from Jesse Ribot, Alice Kelly, Anja Nygren, Ben Jones, Benedikt situation, it is important to be able to rethink of what one’s
Korf, Eric Hahonou, Erin Collins, Iben Nathan, Jean-Pierre Olivier de work is a case as part of the research process. The following
Sardan, Jens Friis Lund, Louise Fortmann, Mariève Pouliot, Muriel pages provide elements for a conceptual strategy to help in-
Côte, Pauline Peters, Pierre Petit, Siddharth Sareen, Tobias Hagmann, vestigate this. An analytical matrix of different dimensions of
Tomas Martin, and Veronica Gomez-Temesio (who initially prompted the
writing), have improved the text. The author also owes a debt of grati- this kind of research is laid out. Subsequently, I discuss some
tude to the three reviewers for illuminating and instructive comments of the dificulties of generalizing, abstracting and theorizing
and suggestions. The remaining errors and infelicities are his alone. from a particular case.

224 HUMAN ORGANIZATION


An Analytical Matrix
Table 1. Analytical Matrix
To know what our case studies are about, it is useful to
locate their contents between the very speciic and the very Concrete Abstract
general. It is equally useful to know where they sit between
the very concrete and the more abstract. Two open-ended Speciic Observations Concepts
continua stretch between speciic and general, and between
concrete and abstract, respectively. This enables the organiza- General Patterns Theories
tion of our research in a matrix.
There is often a conlation between terms. In more ca-
sual language, we often mistake the speciic for the concrete prediction, and cumulative accretion of knowledge—some of
and the general for the abstract. However, they are not the the key virtues of the natural sciences—are not possible for
same, and it pays to be precise, so let us irst establish what the social sciences as context dependent empirical enquiries
they actually mean. It may be easiest to think about some of human activity. This does not mean that social science
synonyms for each: does not produce knowledge, but it is historical and not un-
equivocal. Yet, the epistemological ethos of natural sciences
Specific: Circumscribed, limited, particular, precise,
has managed to dominate as an ideal of all scientiic activity.
restricted, singular, special, unequivocal,
This is unfortunate as it may lead to conjecture that social
unique…
science is science of a lower quality.4 It need not be. But it
General: Common, commonplace, extensive, pervasive,
is a different science.
prevalent, ubiquitous, universal, widespread…
Concrete: Actual, authentic, corporeal, in-context, not for-
malized by the analyst, real, palpable, tangible… An Example—Who Owns Bolgatanga?
Abstract: Conceptual, decontextualized, detached, ideal,
ideational, intangible, transcendental… To explain the navigation between these different types
of claims, let us take the point of departure with a speciic
The continua are open-ended rather than two sets of absolute and concrete case, namely land conlicts in Bolgatanga in
binary opposites. Things can be more or less speciic or gen- Northern Ghana and the institutional implications of a con-
eral—more or less concrete or abstract. Most claims about stitutional change that restructured land ownership (Lund
our cases are a combination of speciic, general, concrete, and 2008). In 1979, the Ghanaian government worked to change
abstract, and it is the movement between these dimensions— the country’s constitution. In order to gain support for dif-
generalization, speciication, abstraction, and concretiza- ferent policies, the government promised parliamentarians
tion—that makes us conscious of what our work might be a from the northern constituencies that they would modify the
case. In the simplest form, one might argue that the different constitution. Hitherto, the land tenure regime had been vastly
combinations of abstractions and generalizations represent different between the South of the country and the North.
different—connected—intellectual enterprises: immediate While chiefs were considered owners of the land in the South,
observations, observations of patterns, conceptualizations, land was “held in trust by government” in the North. This dif-
and theorizations (Table 1). When we analyze data, we are ference dated back to when the Gold Coast and Ashanti were
breaking a complex substance into smaller parts. However, a colony, while the Northern Territories were a protectorate.
we are not always suficiently aware of what goes where. In need of the “northern vote,” the government promised
Our research has the potential to be a case of many things to “return land to its original owners” by a constitutional
depending on the coniguration of our speciications and amendment. However, when the law was passed, it transpired
generalizations, and our concretizations and abstractions. It is that the chieftaincies of the North, who saw themselves as
through these analytical movements that the case is produced the obvious original owners of the land, had rival claimants.
out of seemingly amorphous material. Spiritual igures, earthpriests, and their families came forth
Different disciplines may put more emphasis on one and claimed that whereas chiefs might well have been the cus-
movement, as it were, than others, and different inquiries todians of land in most of the country, they had never played
also begin at different places in the matrix. However, most that role in the northernmost parts of what was now Ghana.
research entails activity in all four directions, and few social Instead, earthpriests had historically been allocating land,
science inquiries can afford to be oblivious to any of these sanctifying its use, and endorsing transactions. Consequently,
dimensions. The social sciences are the empirical sciences of they claimed to be the “original owners.” Things came to a
historical reality. A discipline is essentially historical when head when government had to pay compensation to “owners”
its statements cannot be completely severed from the context whose property had been appropriated illegally. It required
from which data were drawn. It is the distinguishing feature that the government identiied, and by that token, recognized
of social sciences, which, contrary to natural sciences, cannot either the chiefs or the earthpriests as rightful owners. In the
“control for context” (Dilley 1999; Passeron 2006). Proof, end, the courts ruled in favor of the earthpriests.

VOL. 73 NO. 3, FALL 2014 225


Somebody is ighting somebody else over a piece of land. indings in a comparative perspective of time and place. I
This is a speciic event (or set of events); it takes place at a deliberately use the word “comparison” loosely. Some dis-
precise place in a circumscribed slice of history. It is unique ciplines have developed very rigorous, systematic regimes
in the sense that this struggle took place then and there. The of comparative analysis. That is ine.7 In the present context,
case is also concrete. This actual conlict was played out I basically look for resonance with other cases in different
between real people in an actual place. Now, while this is localities or different times, or both8. By resonance, I mean
a good starting point, a concrete case of a speciic struggle that different elements, dynamics, and relations could be
is not very interesting in and of itself from a social science recognized from one case to the other. Such cases are not nec-
perspective. Social inquiries—as empirical and historical essarily similar. Indeed, they may be quite different, yet there
sciences—become truly interesting only when they relate are some elements that resonate between them. For example,
to other inquiries. The question was, of what is this a case? one may work on land conlicts in Africa and ind stimulat-
To answer this, we need to move to considerations about ing resonance with the works on primitive accumulation by
generalizing, abstracting, and theorizing. Thompson (1975) and Marx (1954). Thompson and Marx’s
works do not explain African land grabs. They may even
Resonance operate with concepts that are dificult to transpose from one
context to another. Nevertheless, certain dynamics of resource
Information and knowledge are different. The difference control and the ex-post legalization of illegal land appropria-
lies in what we as analysts do to the information. Sometimes, tion may echo between these distinct (con-) texts. In fact, it
especially in policy and consulting work, we encounter per- may be the difference in contexts that make the particular
functory claims to objectivity, such as: “let the naked facts qualities of organization, dynamics, and relations resonate
speak for themselves.” However, no “naked facts” ever spoke and be mutually illuminating. Resonance can inspire us to
to anyone except through concepts, however vaguely deined. look for elements, which we had not initially thought about
This line of thinking has roots in Kant’s work. He argues but which are obviously signiicant in work by others. And
that rather than insisting that our cognition relects “real” it may help us to generalize, abstract, and theorize our own.
objects, we may try to see “real” objects as conforming to our
cognition. That is, we “see” things through a lens of a priori Generalizing
concepts formed through experience; these newly observed
things then become part of our new experience, and we can The speciic and concrete study in question was about
have another, new, look. This suggests a never-ending, itera- land reform and ownership in Ghana. But what was the
tive approximation between a priori concepts, cognition of general signiicance of groups of people ighting over land
“the world,” and the formation of renewed a prioris.5 By not ownership in and around Bolgatanga at that particular time?
questioning the concepts and categories with which we read Different kinds of generalization are usually possible and
the “naked facts,” it is easy to make a set of observations look useful, and often case studies combine several kinds. However,
speciously unequivocal and pervasive. This does not qualify it is important irst to distinguish generalization from abstrac-
as scholarly work. tion. Generality can refer to empirical as well as analytical
Scholarly inquiry is not objective; we have objectives generalization.9 Empirical generalization is an extrapolation.
with our research, that is, certain concerns we want to in- Here, knowledge of a limited number of events are claimed to
vestigate. Science itself cannot tell us whether an issue is be valid for a larger group. Analytical generalization, on the
signiicant or not. As investigators, we establish frames of other hand, is an identiication of fundamental or constituent
inquiry through which we understand the world. This fram- properties in an event or phenomenon. I refer to the latter as
ing establishes, and is established through, the language we “abstraction” and deal with it in the following section.10
employ to speak about our concerns. This includes the choice But even when we deal with generalization in restricted
of concepts and theoretical questions. Words like “wealthy,” sense as empirical, several forms of inferences are possible.
“poor,” “farmer,” “migrant,” “government,” “risk,” “rights,” The kind we often think about is formal generalization. One
and “property” all have simple colloquial meanings in our will never be able to talk to, or get data from, everybody in
daily interaction. None of them are unequivocal, but this the studied group. Hence, generalization from some observa-
rarely poses big problems in our everyday use of them. As tions to the group as such is inevitable.11 The research on land
concepts, however, they require the precision that theoretical conlicts in Bolgatanga included a large number of cases in
pedigree can afford them. Concepts illuminate certain dy- order to map out what conlicts are typically about, who is
namics, processes, and relations, while they occlude others. typically involved, what authorities are typically engaged,
Hence, concepts are politically charged by the simple fact that how claims are typically argued, and how conlicts typically
they orient our inquiry. This requires explicit relexivity so unfold. A common error is to let one or few informants speak
that the reader is made privy to our generalizations, abstrac- on behalf of the entire group or to present one incidence as
tions, and theorizations.6 typical without conidence in the data. It was therefore impor-
Historical, empirical, research is, strictly speaking, about tant for the credibility of the research that it gave some basis to
singular events. However, most such studies situate their see patterns. Conidence is established through iteration and

226 HUMAN ORGANIZATION


triangulation until a certain degree of saturation is reached. others.” Some of the most important “others” often prove to
That is, through iterative interviews (or other forms of data be the informants, people in the area, the interlocutors. Their
collection), information becomes increasingly predictable, reactions to the questions, their counter examples, and their
and surprises peter out (Bauer and Aarts 2000; Olivier de willingness to point out yet other people to meet, played a
Sardan 2008). Data from many single cases or samples thus bigger role in shaping up my case than I had dared to suggest
construct a corpus and enable one to say something about in the research proposal (see Fortmann 2008; Herzfeld 2001).
the typicality and rarity of particular observations. Formal Truth be told, it is often only quite far into the research process
generalization therefore also relates to relevance. It could and after many conversations in situ, that one can see what
show that the research problem was not insigniicant—that it kind of work the case can do. Thus, the opening questions
was not an entirely exceptional occurrence—and that it had are merely a irst step in a long series of gradual precisions,
general relevance. and one often ends up answering a slightly different question
Generalization, from the phenomena observed in one from what one set out to ask.
context to another, depends on the purpose of the analysis. In The choice of historical and geographical perspective is
arguing for the general validity in comparative settings of a important here. There is no right or wrong, only more or less
phenomenon we have studied, there is a risk—a temptation— pertinent and convincing. This choice is ours, as analysts.
to overreach and universalize. Or rather, if we are compelled My study could have compared two similar towns and areas
to universalize, there is a risk that we will argue for the general in the Upper East Region of Ghana. It could even have been
validity of our analysis. Most times, we will fail.12 contextualized with the Norman Conquest of England and
A way to reduce this risk is to reassess (or recall) why the creation of the Doomsday Book in 1086 or to other more
the case is studied. Often, attempts to make universal claims recent restructurings of land tenure.
are misguided. In most instances, the purpose is not to make Eventually, the research in Bolgatanga was about restora-
universal declarations,13 and listing caveats to cover oneself is tion of a customary authority and about reversal of colonial
to akin to scratching where it doesn’t itch. Generalization out policies and entitlements, and it was about legal infrastruc-
of the close historical and geographical context is, rather, to ture. The most relevant context in which to view the research
enter into a dialogue where one’s research resonates with other seemed to be the colonial legacies of land legislation in Africa,
works. The work of others may serve as a basis for a form however. It made sense to see the tribulations in Bolgatanga
of triangulation, not in order to establish actual validity but as a case of post-colonial land reform that reinstated custom
to suggest likelihood and probability. As a form of scholarly (whatever that might be) as a leading principle for organizing
communication, generalizations are provisional propositions, land ownership and control. The research produced a general
such as: “The apparently simple solution of conferring land argument, that in a context of legal and institutional pluralism
to customary igures is not so simple because the opportunity and rising competition over land, restoration of property may
will make competing customary igures emerge, and complex hold the promise of greater command over the beneits of land
competitions will ensue.” Others’ work will afirm or contra- for the “original owners” but is likely to simply relocate the
dict this proposition’s generalizability, as one’s will theirs. It tension to a conlict over the deinition of “owner.” Thus, a
is in the tension between contextualization of one’s work in reversal of land tenure (like what took place in 1979 in Ghana)
the broadly accepted literature and at the same time saying opens a hornet’s nest of potential conlict over land claims and
something new that adds, challenges, or changes it, that new over competing claims as to who has the authority to settle
knowledge is produced. Our work should make sense as well such conlicts. In short, the analysis produced a general argu-
as new sense. Sometimes new sense may look like non-sense ment that this type of land legislation is likely to be far from
(or indeed, nuisance) if it is too unfamiliar. This increases the “successful,” almost regardless of success criteria.
“burden of persuasion” of one’s argument.
A third kind of generalization combines with the above Abstracting
two. Cases, if carefully selected, can be used to debunk exist-
ing general understandings.14 For the research in question, it So, of what is this work a case in a more abstract way?
was worth inspecting the emerging general view that land The point of departure may well have been the speciic and
tenure reforms in Africa would be more successful, if they concrete, but any study is analyzed through a set of concepts.
reintroduced customary categories and principles, because, Even “pure” description relects some editorial principles,
it was assumed, “custom” would be widely shared by people which are in fact, conceptual. By using concepts, we abstract
concerned.15 If a study of a situation, where this is most likely and edit the data. We make particular inherent qualities of it
to be true, shows that it isn’t, then it would suggest that it prominent. “Social scientists do not discover new events that
generally is not true. nobody knew about before. What is discovered is connections
However, carefully selecting the case poses no small and relations, not directly observable, by which we can un-
problem. How and when does one know whether or for what derstand and explain already known occurrences in a novel
a case is critical? How will one even know what it was about way” (Danermark et al. 2002:91). The empirical material as
before it is studied? The honest answers are: “gradually,” such is not our responsibility, but the choice of concepts and
“late,” “one doesn’t,” and more generally, “with the help of the rigorous collection of data is.

VOL. 73 NO. 3, FALL 2014 227


Our choice of concepts—just as our choice of historical power and force concentrating in the hands of the few could
and geographical contextualization—partly deines a case. have been examined through a lens of political economy. The
There are many concepts, which will make only modest most rewarding concepts through which to draw exciting
sense in a given case, but there is usually more than one set insights seemed, however, to be property and access linked to
of concepts that will make a lot of sense. Again, the choice of the concepts of authority and power. In the abstract, the study
an appropriate lens falls to the researcher. Here, experience, was a case of the mutual production of rights and authority.
creativity, and imagination play an important role. One’s By analyzing property conlicts as constitutive of political
experience from previous research continues to “ferment” authority, it began to make sense how both property and
and bring questions, perspectives, and connections to the authority are created through recognition of the legitimacy
observations that do not simply emerge from the data itself. of the respective claims. The inherent properties of the land
Moreover, in addition to comprehensive knowledge about conlicts were, indeed, “recognition of claims as rights.” This
alternative theories and frames of interpretation, abstraction allowed a recontextualization of the land conlicts as dynam-
requires a creative reasoning process to “discern relations ics of recognition between and among claimants of land and
and connections not evident or obvious, to formulate new claimants of authority.
ideas about the interconnections of phenomena, to think Yet, even if one is convinced that “property” is relevant
about something in a different context, […] to ‘see something to study, what should one actually look for? “Property” is
as something else”’ (Danermark et al. 2002:93). This is not too abstract a term to immediately observe. It is dificult to
without complications, however. One fundamental problem imagine a “phenomenology of property” because property
is how to be open to the unexpected, to what one was not is already an abstraction, and the chances are slim that the
already looking for. Researchers of all stripes have often made researcher and the people (s)he talks to (all) share an under-
“discoveries,” which were absolutely analogous to what they standing of that word. One might try to imagine coming home
already knew (Eco 1998). For example, it could be argued one evening during ieldwork, happy and content, because
that the experience of the “large abstraction” we choose to today “property” was encountered in the ield: what, then,
call capitalism always arrives in “quite personal, concrete, would one have actually seen? One could have seen (heard
localized, and mediated forms” (Scott 1985:348). However, about) transfers of land between people, heritage and sales,
this does not mean that all personal, concrete, localized ex- occupations and evictions, deeds and documents of planning
periences can meaningfully be abstracted into “capitalism,” and taxation, of protest and petition, and narratives of dispute.
although many have tried. This relates to the Kantian idea that Property in itself is dificult to see, however. It is a practical
we observe, interpret, and infer through a prioris. There seems exercise to deconstruct and operationalize key concepts such
to be no clean escape except to be as inclusive and honest as “property” into many observable, empirical elements sig-
and open as possible in one’s observations, interpretations, nifying different aspects of the “whole.” This exercise works
and inferences (Olivier de Sardan 2008). Strongly deductive well for most concepts, such as “contention,” “corruption,”
reasoning carries with it the risk of permanent “re-discovery” “exclusion,” “honor,” “neo-liberalism,” etc.16
of the concept or the model in the empirical material. This is Conceptual claims are not easy to prove. The proof of
a safe, yet ultimately boring, undertaking. this pudding is in its utility. If the conceptual framework can
Our preferred concepts are, sometimes, quite abstract— make sense of the analyzed data, and especially, if it can
sometimes so much so that they do not really have an im- help others to better understand their own work in different
mediate precise empirical reference (it is the very nature of contexts, it is very successful. It might be useful to illustrate
abstraction). We are therefore obliged to track and explain with a fragment of ethnography at this point:
the movement back and forth between concrete manifesta-
tions of abstract phenomena and be explicit about how we Box 1. The Incident of Mrs. B, the Earthpriest, and the
operationalize the concepts. The question is what did we Royal Hotel
actually observe that made us think that we saw these phe-
In 1977, Mrs. B bought a small hotel and about seven
nomena? Some concepts may be so abstract (like “state,” acres of land in Bolga. The seller had been given the land
“hegemony,” or indeed, “capitalism”), that we may even by the government as compensation for land he had had to
need to disaggregate their constituent concepts before they give up when the dual highway was constructed in town.
become empirically visible. Abstraction and concretization Initially, Mrs. B walled but a small part of her land, letting
are translations. And it generally pays to pass through opera- the rest lie undeveloped. This land was cultivated by the
local inhabitants of the village and had been so for as long
tional steps. Going back and forth between abstract concepts as anyone could recall. Over the years, the Royal Hotel
and empirical observations in the progressive approximation and Mrs. B prospered, and at one point in the late 1990s,
of both helps to better discern the phenomenon empirically she decided to wall all of her land in view of developing it
and describe it conceptually. further. This caused great discontent with the local people,
The events in Bolgatanga could have been decontextual- who saw themselves as illegitimately dispossessed. To
them, the initially walled compound was tolerable, though
ized by a focus on how cultural idioms give value to certain essentially squatting on their land—land they had never
representations and narratives. Likewise, different forms of

228 HUMAN ORGANIZATION


generalization are plausible (Passeron 2006). This is, in fact,
ceded with consent. Moreover, since 1979, land seized by
an empirical question. Sometimes, our constructions collapse,
government without proper acquisition was to be handed
back to its original owners—the earthpriests to distribute and we have to start over. Pre-ieldwork and post-ieldwork
to land users. To Mrs. B, the opposite was equally clear. ideas, for example, rarely look alike. Fortunately!
She had a 99-year lease signed by the—at the time—ap- Theorization has its challenges. Some research seems to
propriate authority, the chief; she had paid land rent for venture forth with very ixed theoretical ideas about certain
all seven acres; and she had a site-plan approved by the
dynamics or relations. They engage empirical data in order
Town and Country Planning Ofice.
The local earthpriest and Mrs. B discussed the issue, to conirm the theoretical propositions. Sometimes, the use
but no settlement was reached. The situation remained the of theory becomes rather ritualistic, and the speciic and
same for a few years. The earthpriest and the population concrete indings easily end up as apt illustrations of exist-
found it futile to pursue the matter as long as Mrs. B was ing knowledge. Some pieces of ethnography that claim to be
well connected to the political establishment of the town
inductive in their approach are really rather deductive (Becker
as the regional treasurer and large-scale patroness of the
ruling National Democratic Congress (NDC). To resign 1986; Mitchell 1983). There is no shortage of studies where
is not to acquiesce, however. Hence, on the day follow- applications of Marxist, Foucauldian, Weberian, or other
ing the defeat of NDC in the national elections in May fashionable frameworks essentially end up merely conirm-
2001, the villagers mobilized and knocked down the wall ing that Marx, Foucault, Weber, and others were clever.
shielding the seven acres and the Royal Hotel. Cultivation
The actual knowledge does not change or evolve by such
was resumed the same rainy season, and only debris now
marked Mrs. B’s claim. “application.” It is not put on the line, as it were, and theory
has merely been fuelled by data as a machine. This also goes
Signiicant leads can be teased out of the concrete incidents for more contemporary work. Fashion in science can hardly
and events surrounding Mrs. B’s land conlict. First, both Mrs. be avoided, but it is odd how some writers become virtual
B and the villagers could justify their claims with reference to talismans without reference to whom one’s argument cannot
history, legal documents, and new legislation. They identiied be considered valid or serious among peers (Cribb 2005).
different authorities that could recognize and validate them. The Does this mean that we should avoid grand theory and
incidents also vividly demonstrate that these authorities’ power never wrestle with Weber and others? Not at all. But theory
varied over time and that the recognition of their legitimacy was can be wrestled with in many different ways. It is useful to
crucial for the effective validity of their endorsements of land operate with a distinction between explanatory and heuristic
claims. What is “new” in the research is not that “somebody frameworks. As an explanatory framework, theory is a set of
is ighting somebody else over a piece of land.” Rather, the interrelated substantive statements venturing to say something
novelty was to establish the connection between competing new about the social world, either for a circumscribed sec-
land claims and competing claims to authority. It conveyed tion of it or, in some cases, attempting a systematic theory of
a new, additional dimension to a known occurrence of land society. A heuristic framework, in contrast, is a set of concep-
conlict. It was to see something as something else. Some 40 tual tools, which, rather than telling us anything substantive
cases of this sort were studied in depth to establish a pattern about the social world, suggests ways of approaching it. The
of events and knead the concepts into shape. value of this type of theory must be assessed in terms of what
questions are asked and how they interrogate the empirical
Theorizing phenomena. In short, we may distinguish between substantive
propositions and propositions that are predominantly meth-
How do we combine generalizations and abstractions odological, that is, heuristic (Lund 2010; Mouzelis 1995).17
to move in the direction of theorization? Of what would the In reality, most works do both. Most works have substantive
work be a case, if generalized and abstracted? What claims, if and heuristic elements. Most works say something substantive
any, could possibly be made from work in and on Bolgatanga, about the world they cover (be it “land in Africa,” “the In-
that could have purchase in times and places and possibly dustrial Revolution,” or “Modernity”) and something—often
ields beyond land conlicts in that small place? Recall that implicitly—about how to get to know that.
generalization is an attempt to see resonance with events Grand theorists, such as Marx, Foucault, and Weber, are
and processes, largely at the same level of abstraction but in therefore not irrelevant or incommensurable with research
different temporal or spatial contexts. Abstraction, in turn, is on a dynamic context removed from the contexts that once
an attempt to identify inherent decontextualized qualities or inspired their work. They provide a repertoire of possible
properties in the studied events. Theorization, inally, is about factors, forces, and relations one may not have thought of and
moving from observation of empirical events, through con- may not observe if one is not aware that they may be at work.
cepts, to be able to say something about the inherent qualities However, they do more than that. It often pays handsomely
and dynamics in contexts other than the ones studied. That is, to look to such theories more for their heuristic utility and
there is both an element of decontextualization or abstraction conceptual adequacy than for their substantive propositions as
and an element of transfactual corroboration in the process. if they were an inventory of universal connections or general
The litmus test for any social science research is to what extent causalities. In short, to understand the political economy of
the indings and statements at various levels of abstraction and rural Africa, it may be very productive to look to Marx for

VOL. 73 NO. 3, FALL 2014 229


Table 2. Analytical Matrix—Now with Data
Concrete Abstract

Speciic Land reform Property-authority


Land conlicts Recognition
Reversal of colonial policies Institutional competition over jurisdiction
Legal infrastructure

General Post-colonial societies State formation through the mutual


Normative/institutional pluralism constitution of rights and authority
Re-invention of custom

the questions he asks about power, property, and control and not merely talking about property rights but rights more
rather less rewarding to look at the (ultimately historically generally (property as well as citizenship, for example), and
contingent) answers he provides in his class analysis of 19th then we are, possibly, not merely talking about post-colonial
century Europe. Likewise, to understand state-society rela- Africa but society in general through time. This would lead
tions in Indonesia, it may be a good idea to look to Foucault to propositions on how and why state formation is a dynamic
for the questions he asks about discourse and power and less of rights and authority; how the value of material and human
inspiring to transplant his substantive propositions on prison- resources vary in time and are captured in different ways;
ers and punishment in 18th century France to the archipelago. and how legitimacy is not a ixed quantity but produced in
We can often learn as much from how and why questions context. I will not go on about the substance here; I have
have been asked in other circumstances as we can from the done that elsewhere (inter alia Lund 2011).
historical answers they yielded. Other people’s work is a
spring-well of ideas about how to approach the world, even The Analytical Matrix Revisited
if it is about something we do not work on ourselves. Con-
ceptual tools and incisive questions to investigate historical The same study has many dimensions of inquiry. Gen-
realities have a lot of mileage, whereas the propositions of eralizing, abstracting, and theorizing produce many claims
substantive theories have variable expiry dates and seem to of a different nature. The relative weight of the different
have less new knowledge to offer once removed from their contributions from a study is likely to be quite uneven. The
contexts. For example, the argument about the dynamic in- research is a big contribution to the small ield of the speciic
teraction between a generalized ethos and a particular form and concrete land conlicts in Bolgatanga and a very small
of economic interaction in The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit contribution to the big ield of general and abstract state for-
of Capitalism (Weber 2001) travels well if treated as a ques- mation. In a schematic form, the research could be organized
tion or inquiry. Other texts may have equivalent effects on in the matrix (Table 2).
one’s thinking, even if they are about something completely The answer to “of what is it a case?” is therefore: “it
different. Obviously, our choice of questions conditions how, depends.” The study used as an example in this article is a
and consequently also what, we can see, but by focusing on case of land struggles in Bolgatanga. In a general sense, it is
questions, we may be less inclined to simply “re-discover” a case of post-colonial land reform and the reconiguration
somebody else’s model on our data. of customary categories of ownership. In a conceptual sense,
The research on Bolgatanga enabled theorization about the work is a case of the mutual constitution of property and
“property in Africa.” This conjoined generalization with the con- authority. And, inally, in a theoretical sense, it is a case of state
ceptual abstractions. That is, it combined propositions about post- formation and the production of public authority through the
colonial societies, African in particular, with propositions about production of rights. It is not the actual empirical phenomena,
property and authority. This was in the cards with the research which are a case; it is our efforts at generalizing, abstracting,
concerns and the collected data. However, the study had even and theorizing that make a case of the phenomena. It is how we
wider (more general) and fundamental (more abstract) potential. string together words in convincing prose and not simply in a
The abstractions of land conlicts into dynamics of property and matrix that produces an argued, reasoned, and compelling case.
authority could possibly be abstracted another notch. Hence, of what it is a case lies outside of the data themselves.
The relationship between property and authority is
mediated by a social contract of reciprocal recognition of From Neat Heuristics to Reiterative Practice
rights and legitimated political power. If this is so, maybe
the work could be a further theoretical contribution to the Up until now, the process has been described as open
body of work on state formation. Hence, possibly, we are inquiry and going from observations through patterns and

230 HUMAN ORGANIZATION


concepts to theory. This, of course, is not a true representation us to argue for our choice of frame. And data saturation and
of what actually happens. One does not end up in Bolgatanga triangulation provide the necessary conidence in the material
by pure accident. One does not begin the exploratory phase of and give a deep knowledge of the multiple elements and their
research with a completely open mind. And one is not equally connections. We stare at the amorphous mass we call data, and
interested in all aspects of human life. One is already primed patterns begin to emerge. This is not so different from what
by conceptual and theoretical impulses from scholarly work mathematicians in their technical language call solution by
on different places and issues. I had started thinking long inspection.20 Intense observation creates a gestalt of the whole,
before I began to think about Bolga.18 and a solution simply clicks into place. Sometimes. When it
Moreover, one is constantly, sometimes aimlessly, mov- happens, it happens not simply by gradual, linear, theoriza-
ing back and forth between observations, generalizations, tion but when enough concepts, enough material, and enough
abstractions, and theorization rather than following a neat inspection produce momentary clarity. It is what marks out
trajectory from one square to the next as hopscotch from start authentic and original scholarship. This may explain why it
to inish. Methods are not as systematic as science claims takes so long….
(Feyerabend 1975). The orderliness of one’s method is easier
to establish in hindsight as futile detours can be erased to make Notes
it look more coherent and neat than it felt and was at the time.
But only by shuttling between larger theoretical questions and
1
Gerring (2004:342) even argues that the term is a “deinitional
morass.” Case may mean “qualitative,” “small N,” “ethnographic,”
detailed observations can we institute the problem and explain “clinical,” that it investigates “single phenomena,” that it is “in ield,”
it. It is the movement between them and their articulation that that it “traces processes,” etc. Illuminating works in social science
produces epiphanies and analytical knowledge. Theoretical include Flyvbjerg (2001, 2006), George and Bennet (2005), Olivier de
questions help to deduce critical areas of inquiry, and detailed Sardan (2008), Platt (1992), Ragin and Becker (1992), Stake (1995),
ield research of an inductive nature allows us to investigate Vennesson (2008), and Yin (2003).
concrete dynamics.19 2
Cases of this ilk owe a debt to the Schools of Manchester (Ferguson
The choices of sample, of concepts, and of theory and 1999; Gluckman 1958; Mitchell 1983; van Velsen 1978) and Chicago
the movements between them progressively narrow down (Goffmann 1989; Platt 1992). See also Geertz (1973).
the range of possible arguments. Even seemingly innocuous
choices have effects in this vein. Serendipitous encounters
3
Bennett and Elman (2006); Flyvbjerg (2001); Gerring (2004);
Gomm, Hammersley, and Foster (2000); Ragin and Becker (1992);
with informants lead interviews and discussions onto new Stake (1995); and Yin (2003) provide excellent overviews of what job
paths. Particular conceptual framings highlight certain dy- of knowledge production cases can perform.
namics while others dim as a consequence. Each small and big
choice forecloses certain, hitherto possible, perspectives, and 4
For more elaborate lamentation, see Bourdieu (1977), Flyvbjerg
the arguments gradually irm up (Becker 1986). To discuss (2001), Gould (2003), Mills (2000), and Passeron (2006). Burawoy
(1998:12-16) shows vividly how natural science inspired methods (what
one’s work with others on a regular basis may be the most he terms “positive science methods”) in social science, despite the best
important practice to gradually hone in on the potentiality intentions, are inevitably compromised because of context, respondents’
for generalization, abstraction, and theorization of the case. relexivity, and the impossibility of perfect replication. This is no reason,
While it can be terrifying to expose one’s thoughts—half- however, not to use quantiiable data as part of analyses.
baked as they may be—to others, not least one’s informants, 5
For an entry into this, Wolf (1999) is excellent; Kant (1953) is
the dividends are high. Others’ experience and their various obviously excellent, also. For a more poetic take, have a look at T.S.
ways of making associations usually provide new perspec- Eliot’s (1954) The Rock.
tives and insights about one’s work and the existing truths
worth taking up arms against. The most striking thoughts 6
“Objectivity” is a perennial debate in science. For old classics,
sometimes come from places one would least expect, from see Taylor (1961) and Weber (1963); for a new one, see Butler (2009).
Bhaskar (2008) and the school of critical realism (e.g., Danermark et
people working within and without one’s area, historical al. 2002; Forsyth 2003; Korf 2006; Sayer 1992) attempt an ontological
period, ield, and discipline. understanding of social structures as “real”, that is, constructed and
The frequent movement back and forth between the produced but not imaginary, an epistemology that recognizes that it can
speciic and the more general and between the concrete and only relect a partial experience of reality, and inally, that the research
the more abstract usually leads us to read more conceptual process is inevitably framed by social and political context.
and theoretical work than we will ever be able to use con- 7
See, for example, Geddes (2003), Lieberson (1991), Lijphart (1975),
structively to present our results convincingly in a text. It and Sartori (1991).
also leads us to collect much more evidence than we end up
using. Superluous theories and excess data are not amassed 8
For careful discussions about the usefulness of bringing different
in vain, though. It could be argued that expertise is achieved cases together, see Burawoy (1998, 2009); Dilley (1999); Herzfeld
(2001); Hilgers (2013); Katzenstein et al. (1995); Moore (2005); Ragin
on the basis of intimate knowledge of a very large number of (1987); Tilly (1984).
cases in an area and knowledge from a wider ield. Compre-
hensive conceptual consciousness allows us to be aware of 9
Danermark et al. (2002) call them “empiricist” and “realist”; Yin
complementary and competing explanations, and it enables (2003) opts for “statistical” and “analytical,” respectively.

VOL. 73 NO. 3, FALL 2014 231


10
The distinction between the two generalizations may blur. First, Bennett, Andrew, and Colin Elman
even simple empirical categories immediately familiar to us are abstract 2006 Qualitative Research: Recent Developments in Case Study
representations of the real and not the real they represent. Second, Methods. Annual Review of Political Science 9(1):455-476.
we often generalize about complex rather than singular and simple
phenomena. With increasing aggregation, increasing abstraction tends Bhaskar, Roy
to follow. Still, it makes sense to distinguish between generalization at [1975] 2008 A Realist Theory of Science. London, United Kingdom:
largely the same level of abstraction and abstraction as decontextualiza- Verso.
tion of observations.
Blundo, Giorgio and Jean-Pierre Olivier de Sardan
For a discussion of internal and external generalization, see Olivier
11
2006 Everyday Corruption and the State. London, United Kingdom:
de Sardan (2008). Zed Books.

12
Failing to universalize may be the least of our peccadilloes, how- Bourdieu, Pierre
ever. The very ambition to universalize is borne by an epistemology that 1977 Outline of a Theory of Practice. Cambridge, United Kingdom:
tends to dismiss positionality, situatedness, and the politics of knowl- Cambridge University Press.
edge (Fortmann 2008). Feminist scholarship has dealt with these issues
extensively. Interesting places to start exploring the social construction Burawoy, Michael
and contradiction of positionality are Butler (1990), de Beauvoir (2011), 1998 The Extended Case Method. Sociological Theory 16(1):4-33.
and Haraway (1988, 1996). 2009 The Extended Case Method. Berkeley: University of
California Press.
13
Conspicuous exceptions are Marx and Weber’s historical theories
about capitalism and modernity. They have been subjected to deter- Butler, Judith
mined efforts at universalization by some of their most prominent 1990 Gender Trouble. London, United Kingdom: Routledge.
interpreters, Althusser (1970) and Parsons (1951). For entertaining 2009 Frames of War: When is Life Grievable? London, United
critiques of these efforts, see Thompson (1978) and Cohen, Hazelrigg, Kingdom: Verso.
and Pope (1975).
Castree, Noel
14
See Flyvbjerg (2001, 2006) on different types of case studies (criti- 2005 The Epistemology of Particulars. Human Geography, Case
cal, extreme, maximum variation, and paradigmatic) and the structure Studies, and “Context.” Geoforum 36(5):541-544.
of argument they can each support.
Cohen, Jere, Lawrence E. Hazelrigg, and Whitney Pope
15
After decades of advocating reform of land tenure systems in Africa 1975 De-Parsonizing Weber - A Critique of Parsons’ Interpretation
by eradication of custom, the World Bank (2003) and other international of Weber ’s Sociology. American Sociological Review
organizations changed to a position where custom was seen as a possible 40(2):229-241.
medium for equitable, functional, and affordable reform.
Cribb, Robert
16
For works that attempt to operationalize these very concepts, see 2005 Circles of Esteem, Standard Works, and Euphoric Couplets.
Blundo and Olivier de Sardan (2006); Castree (2005); Hall, Hirsch, and Critical Asian Studies 37(2):289-304.
Li (2011); Stewart (1994); Tilly (2008).
Danermark, Berth, Mats Ekström, Liselotte Jakobsen, and Jan Karlsson
The literature on these distinctions is rich. Mills (2000); Mouzelis
17
2002 Explaining Society: Critical Realism in the Social Sciences.
(1995); and Passeron (2000, 2006) are especially useful. London, United Kingdom: Routledge.

18
And we’re back to Kant again. de Beauvoir, Simone
[1949] 2011 The Second Sex. London, United Kingdom: Vintage.
19
To engage with this huge debate, Burawoy (1998, 2009); Danermark
et al. (2002); Kuhn (1970); Mills (1953, 2000); Passeron (2006); and Dilley, Roy
Sayer (1992) are good starting points. 1999 The Problem of Context. In The Problem of Context.
Roy Dilley, ed. Pp. 1-46. Oxford, United Kingdom: Berghan
20
For interesting observations on mathematical beauty as “enlighten- Books.
ing” rather than “true,” see Rota (1997).
Eco, Umberto
References Cited 1998 Serendipities. Language and Lunacy. London, United
Kingdom: Phoenix.
Althusser, Louis
1970 For Marx. London, United Kingdom: Vintage Books. Eliot, T.S.
1954 Selected Poems. London, United Kingdom: Faber and Faber.
Bauer, Martin, and Bas Aarts
2000 Constructing a Research Corpus. In Qualitative Researching Ferguson, James
with Text, Image, and Sound. A Practical Handbook for Social 1999 Expectations of Modernity. Myths and Meanings of Urban Life
Research. Martin Bauer and George Gaskell, eds. Pp. 19-37. on the Zambian Copperbelt. Berkeley: University of California
London, United Kingdom: Sage. Press.

Becker, Howard Feyerabend, Paul


1986 Writing for Social Scientists. Chicago, Ill.: Chicago University 1975 Against Method. Outline of an Anarchist Theory of
Press. Knowledge. London, United Kingdom: New Left Books.

232 HUMAN ORGANIZATION


Flyvbjerg, Bent Hilgers, Mathieu
2001 Making Social Science Matter. Why Social Science Inquiry 2013 Observation Participante et Comparaison. Anthropologie et
Fails and How It Can Succeed Again. Cambridge, United Sociétés 37(1):97-115.
Kingdom: Cambridge University Press.
2006 Five Misunderstandings about Case-Study Research. Kant, Immanuel
Qualitative Inquiry 12(2):219-245. [1783] 1953 Prolegomena. To Any Future Metaphysics That Will Be
Able to Present Itself as a Science. Manchester, United Kingdom:
Forsyth, Tim Manchester University Press.
2003 Critical Political Ecology. London, United Kingdom:
Routledge. Katzenstein, Peter, Peter Evans, James C. Scott, Susanne Hoeber
Rudolph, Adam Przeworski, Theda Skocpol, and Atul Kohli
Fortmann, Louise, ed. 1995 The Role of Theory in Comparative Politics: A Symposium.
2008 Participatory Research in Conservation and Rural World Politics 48(1):1-49.
Livelihoods. Doing Science Together. London, United Kingdom:
ZSL/Wiley-Blackwell. Korf, Benedikt
2006 Cargo Cult Science, Armchair Empiricism, and the Study of
Geddes, Barbara Violent Conlict. Third World Quarterly 27(3):459-476.
2003 Paradigms and Sand Castles. Theory Building and Research
Design in Comparative Politics. Ann Arbor: University of Kuhn, Thomas
Michigan Press. [1960] 1970 The Structure of Scientiic Revolutions. 2nd ed.
Chicago, Ill.: Chicago University Press.
Geertz, Clifford
1973 The Interpretation of Cultures. New York: Basic Books. Lieberson, Stanley
1991 Small N’s and Big Conclusions. An Examination of the
George, Alexander L., and Andrew Bennet Reasoning in Comparative Studies Based on a Small Number of
2005 Case Studies and Theory Development in the Social Sciences. Cases. Social Forces 70(2):307-320.
Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Lijphart, Arend
Gerring, John 1975 The Comparable-Cases Strategy in Comparative Research.
2004 What is a Case Study and What is it Good For? American Comparative Political Studies 8(2):158-177.
Political Science Review 98(2):341-354.
Lund, Christian
Gluckman, Max 2008 Local Politics and the Dynamics of Property in Africa.
1958 Analysis of a Social Situation in Modern Zululand. Manchester, Cambridge, United Kingdom: Cambridge University Press.
United Kingdom: Rhodes-Livingstone Institute/Manchester 2010 Approaching Development—An Opinionated Review.
University Press. Progress in Development Studies 10(1):19-34
2011 Property and Citizenship. Conceptually Connecting Land
Goffmann, Erwin Rights and Belonging in Africa. Africa Spectrum 46(3):71-75
[1974] 1989 On Fieldwork. Journal of Contemporary Ethnography
18(2):123-132. Marx, Karl
[1887] 1954 Capital, vol 1. Moscow, Russia: Progress Publishers.
Gomm, Roger, Martyn Hammersley, and Peter Foster, eds.
2000 Case Study Method: Key Issues, Key Texts. London, United Mills, C. Wright
Kingdom: Sage. 1953 Two Styles of Research in Current Social Studies. Philosophy
of Science 20(4):266-275.
Gould, Stephen Jay [1959] 2000 The Sociological Imagination. Oxford, United
2003 The Hedgehog, the Fox, and the Magister’s Pox. Mending Kingdom: Oxford University Press.
the Gap Between Science and the Humanities. New York: Three
Rivers Press. Mitchell, James Clyde
1983 Case and Situation Analysis. Sociological Review 31(2):187-
Hall, Derek, Phil Hirsch, and Tania Li 211.
2011 Powers of Exclusion. Singapore: National University of
Singapore Press. Moore, Sally Falk
2005 Comparisons: Possible and Impossible. Annual Review of
Haraway, Donna Anthropology 34:1-11.
1988 Situated Knowledges: The Science Question in Feminism and
the Privilege of Partial Perspective. Feminist Studies 14(3):575- Mouzelis, Nicos
599. 1995 Sociological Theory. What Went Wrong? Diagnosis and
[1985] 1996 A Cyborg Manifesto. Science, Technology, and Remedies. London, United Kingdom: Routledge.
Socialist-Feminism in the Late 20th Century. In Simians, Cyborgs,
and Women: The Reinvention of Nature. Donna Haraway, ed. Pp. Olivier de Sardan, Jean-Pierre
149-181. New York: Routledge. 2008 La rigeur du qualitatif. Les contraintes empiriques de
l’interpretation socio-anthropologique. Louvain-la-Neuve,
Herzfeld, Michael Belgium: Brylant.
2001 Performing Comparisons: Ethnography, Globetrotting, and
the Spaces of Social Knowledge. Journal of Anthropological Parsons, Talcott
Research 57(3):259-276. 1951 The Social System. New York: The Free Press.

VOL. 73 NO. 3, FALL 2014 233


Passeron, Jean-Claude Thompson, E. P.
2000 Le raisonnement sociologique. La preuve et le contexte. In 1975 Whigs and Hunters: The Origin of the Black Act. New York:
Qu’est-ce que la société? Yves Michaud, ed. Pp. 38-51. Paris, Pantheon Books.
France: Éditions Odile Jacob. 1978 The Poverty of Theory and Other Essays. London, United
[1991] 2006 Le raisonnement sociologique. Un espace non- Kingdom: Merlin Press.
poppérien de l’argumentation. Paris, France: Michel Albin.
Tilly, Charles
Platt, Jennifer 1984 Big Structures, Large Processes, Huge Comparisons. New
1992 Case Study in American Methodological Thought. Current York: Russel Sage Foundation.
Sociology 40(1):17-48. 2008 Contentious Performances. Cambridge, United Kingdom:
Cambridge University Press.
Ragin, Charles C.
1987 The Comparative Method. Moving Beyond Qualitative and van Velsen, Jap
Quantitative Strategies. Berkeley: University of California Press. 1978 The Extended—Case Method and Situational Analysis. In The
Craft of Social Anthropology. Arnold Leonard Epstein, ed. Pp. 129-
Ragin, Charles C., and Howard Becker, eds. 149. London, United Kingdom: Tavistock Publications.
1992 What is a Case? Exploring the Foundations of Social Inquiry.
Cambridge, United Kingdom: Cambridge University Press. Vennesson, Pascal
2008 Case Studies and Process Tracing: Theories and Practices. In
Rota, Gian-Carlo Approaches and Methodologies in the Social Sciences: A Pluralist
1997 The Phenomenology of Mathematical Beauty. Synthese Perspective. Donatella Della Porta and Michael Keating, eds. Pp.
111(2):171-182. 223-39. Cambridge, United Kingdom: Cambridge University
Press.
Sartori, Giovanni
1991 Comparing and Miscomparing. Journal of Theoretical Politics Weber, Max
3(3):243-257. [1904] 1963 Objectivity in Social Sciences and Social Policy. In
Philosophy of the Social Sciences. Maurice Alexander Natanson,
Sayer, Andrew ed. Pp. 355-418. New York: Random House.
1992 Method in Social Science: A Realist Approach. 2nd ed. [1905] 2001 The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism.
London, United Kingdom: Routledge. London, United Kingdom: Routledge.

Scott, James C. Wolf, Eric


1985 Weapons of the Weak: Everyday Forms of Peasant Resistance. 1999 Envisioning Power: Ideologies of Dominance and Crisis.
New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press. Berkeley: University of California Press.

Stake, Robert E. World Bank


1995 The Art of Case Study Research. London, United Kingdom: 2003 Land Policies for Growth and Poverty Reduction. Washington,
Sage D.C.: World Bank.

Stewart, Frank Henderson Yin, Robert K.


1994 Honor. Chicago, Ill.: University of Chicago Press. 2003 Case Study Research: Design and Methods. London, United
Kingdom: Sage Publications.
Taylor, Paul W.
1961 Normative Discourse. Englewood Cliffs, NJ.: Prentice-Hall.

234 HUMAN ORGANIZATION

You might also like