You are on page 1of 7

Extended essay

J Med Ethics: first published as 10.1136/jme-2023-109716 on 2 April 2024. Downloaded from http://jme.bmj.com/ on April 5, 2024 at The Hong Kong Polytechnic University. Protected by
More than an idea: why ectogestation should become
a concrete option
Andrea Bidoli ‍ ‍

Correspondence to ABSTRACT social implications of pregnancy. A brief overview


Andrea Bidoli, Public Health, This paper calls for the development of a method of of the context in which women come to form
University of Copenhagen,
København, Denmark; ectogestation as an emancipatory intervention for their attitudes towards reproduction may help our
​andrea.​bidoli@​sund.​ku.d​ k women. I argue that ectogestation would have a dual discussion later. Therefore, in the next section, I
social benefit: first, by providing a gestational alternative present and criticise some of the norms and pres-
Received 5 November 2023 to pregnancy, it would create unique conditions to sures related to pregnancy, which affect all women,
Accepted 9 March 2024 without aiming to provide a comprehensive analysis
reevaluate one’s reproductive preferences—which, for
women, always include gestational considerations— of such a vast and complex topic.
and to satisfy a potential preference not to gestate.
Enabling the satisfaction of such a preference is Social norms on pregnancy: an overview
particularly valuable due to the pressures women Whether we adhere to a containment or parthood
face to embrace pregnancy as central to their identity, view of pregnancy, which respectively define fetuses
while at the same time being penalised by it. Second, as merely contained within/surrounded by the
ectogestation would address certain specific negative gestating person or as a part of them,8 fetuses are
social implications of gestation and childbirth, which inside the gestating persons. Such a unique dynamic
cannot be avoided through social measures as they are imposes certain limitations, which I discuss later,
caused by the corporeal nature of these phenomena. and is at the basis of the social expectation for preg-
Finally, I argue that it is unfair to hold ectogestation to a nant people to prioritise fetal interests over their
higher standard than other innovations such as modern own needs and desires. For instance, during preg-
contraceptives and non-­medical egg freezing. nancy, eating is under such a strict scrutiny that it
becomes a ‘significant social act charged with moral
meaning’.9 Gestating persons are expected to adhere
INTRODUCTION to the highest standards of nutrition, both by them-

copyright.
Complete ectogestationi—a process of extracorpo- selves and by society, as they are considered morally
real gestation able to replace pregnancy entirely— responsible for the well-­ being of the fetuses (and
has been widely discussed within the bioethics later, of the children). ‘Healthy eating’, in line with
literature. Arguments in favour generally focus on dietary guidelines, is associated with ‘good moth-
the promotion of gender equality, the increase in ering’, causing pressures to justify any infringement
reproductive autonomy for people of all genders of nutritional norms.9 This attitude is not limited
and the prevention of physical harm,1–3 while to the realm of food: regulations on the use and
concerns relate to inequality in access, the rein- consumption of drugs, alcohol and tobacco by preg-
forcement of existing oppressive norms and the nant people have implications that go well beyond
potential creation of new ones.4 5 In particular, judgement. It can be argued that the criminalisation
some scholars claim that, within our current social of pregnancy—‘(t)he process of attaching punish-
environment, ectogestation would have a limited ments or penalties to women for actions that are
equality-­promoting and freedom-­promoting poten- interpreted as harmful to their own pregnancies’ii
tial and that supporting it would frame female 10
—is a social control policy hidden behind the
physiology—rather than the social response to it— ‘best interest of the (future) child’ principle. In this
as the source of gender inequality.6 Moreover, it context, the management of substances’ misuse is
has been claimed that focusing on complete rather positioned ‘at the nexus of public health and criminal
than partial ectogestation overstates the ‘scientific justice intervention’.11 This can affect illegal drugs’
realities’ and ‘accords undue priority to imagined users as well as people taking prescription drugs as
gender parity in heteronormative reproduction part of their medical treatment. Moreover, persons
at the expense of other issues of reproductive planning to gestate, actively pregnant or breast
freedom’, ‘reducing existing imbalances in the way feeding are often pressured to pause, or even denied,
the work of parenting is distributed in heterosexual certain medications. Such a resistance can affect both
relationships to the period of gestation’.7 drugs known to be teratogenic, as well as substances
© Author(s) (or their This paper aims to join the body of literature only potentially harmful to fetuses. In fact, there is a
employer(s)) 2024. No supporting the prospect of an ectogestative future.
commercial re-­use. See rights I will argue that ectogestation would have a unique
and permissions. Published
by BMJ. emancipatory potential through its impact on the ii
According to Amnesty International, ‘(t)his includes
formation process of reproductive preferences and laws that punish actions during pregnancy that would
To cite: Bidoli A. the opportunity it would offer to avoid certain not otherwise be made criminal or punishable. It also
J Med Ethics Epub ahead of refers to other laws not specific to pregnancy but which
print: [please include Day are either applied in a discriminatory way against preg-
Month Year]. doi:10.1136/ nant women and/or have a disproportionate impact on
i
jme-2023-109716 Hereinafter, ‘ectogestation’ (and ‘ectogenesis’, when pregnant women which can in practice work as de facto
quoted) always refers to ‘complete ectogestation’. criminalisation’.10

Bidoli A. J Med Ethics 2024;0:1–7. doi:10.1136/jme-2023-109716    1


Extended essay

J Med Ethics: first published as 10.1136/jme-2023-109716 on 2 April 2024. Downloaded from http://jme.bmj.com/ on April 5, 2024 at The Hong Kong Polytechnic University. Protected by
significant lack of data on whether medications are safe for fetuses Such a statement is detrimental to both mothers, who are assigned
due to the historical exclusion of pregnant subjects from clinical disproportionate responsibilities, and fathers, whose parental role
trials,12 and it is (mostly) women who pay the price of this exclu- is depicted as important at best, but not essential like mothers’.
sion. The social expectation for mothers to prioritise fetal and Furthermore, political measures and socioeconomic policies,
child health regardless of the consequences on their own well-­ such as those differentiating parental leaves by gender, can rein-
being is widespread; as stated by Susan Chase and Mary Rogers, force the expectations for mothers to be the primary caretakers
a good mother should be, ‘above all, (…) selfless. Her children and maintain an unequal gender division of labour.26 The soci-
come before herself and any other need or person or commit- etal interest in supporting a preference for reproduction via
ment’.13 This narrative goes well beyond gestation. For instance, pregnancy is also reflected, for example, in social praise as well
the choice of a method of delivery (which, in any case, will involve as financial incentives from the State, such as ‘baby bonuses’
some pain and discomfort) is often influenced by interests others’ or publicly funded methods of medically assisted reproduc-
than the birthing person’s. While a preference for vaginal deliv- tion. Policies, laws and regulations, together with technological
eries can reflect social pressures towards what are (questionably) opportunities and cultural norms, do shape people’s preferences.
deemed ‘natural births’,14 several investigations have found that They are often ‘explicitly designed to produce certain prefer-
labouring patients are pressured into having—or not having— ences’,27 which can be problematic per se but even more when
caesarean sections15–17 and epidurals,18 as well as being subject to the preference they encourage is harmful.
other ‘minor’ procedures without their consent.19 The role of pregnancy within the patriarchy, therefore, proves
Pregnancy does not only affect gestating individuals but has to be extremely complex: it is used both as a pretext to discrim-
a much wider social impact. Historically, pregnancy has been inate women and as an oppressive tool that relegates them to
the most evident single-­sex feature, which led gestation, partu- certain roles, praising those who embrace such roles and ostra-
rition, and lactation—which are, in themselves, biological cise those who do not. This is what Evie Kendal refers to as
processes—to be framed as the foundation of the social concepts the twofold ‘social burden of pregnancy’: ‘social expectation
of womanhood and motherhood. Since a very early age, children demands women become pregnant, and then pregnancy serves
are exposed to motherhood—and, in particular, motherhood to materially damage women’s social lives and limit their future
through pregnancy—being depicted as ‘normal’ and central to opportunities’.21
a woman’s identity. Their gender socialisation will inevitably be
shaped by the depiction of a woman’s ‘childbearing capacity’20 as
her main function, resulting in girls and, later on, women being REPRODUCTIVE OPTIONS AND ADAPTIVE PREFERENCES
pressured ‘to pursue self-­actualisation through procreation’,21 With this context in mind, it can be argued that ‘complex socio-­
regardless of whether they eventually choose to have children political factors’ (…) make it unlikely’7 for ectogestation to be
and ‘of any social benefit they may receive if they do’.21 This can possible in the near future, especially since there is no technolog-

copyright.
be particularly challenging for women who cannot be pregnant, ical breakthrough in sight. Chloe Romanis and Claire Horn refer
including transgender women; at the same time, people who to this last point to claim that the ‘technological possibilities to
gestate but are not women might have difficulties dealing with claim legitimacy for a future of (ectogestation)’7 have been over-
such a strongly gendered process. stated, and that focusing on such uncertain and distant future
Moreover, pregnancy is a corporeal process requiring certain possibilities is damaging. On the contrary, I consider the limited
sacrifices that has no equivalent in male physiology; as such, it is research on it as a reason to discuss complete ectogestation even
used to associate women’s ‘nature’ with ‘passivity, unconditional more. For those ‘future possibilities’ to become real, they need to
giving, sacrificing, suffering’.20 As claimed by Janice Raymond, be a research priority, which results from being on top of or, at
‘(a)ltruism has been one of the most effective blocks to women’s least, included in the political agenda. Ectogestation is neither. It
self-­
awareness and demand for self-­ determination’22 causing is hard to believe it is simply a coincidence that the research and
women’s bodies to be ‘the raw material for other’s needs, desires market on new reproductive technologies enabling pregnancy
and purposes’.22 In this view, ‘(t)he cultural norm of the altruistic is constantly expanding, while there is none on replacing preg-
woman (…) derives from a social context in which women give nancy.iv The lack of gestational alternatives could be explained
and are given away, and from a moral tradition that celebrates by the instrumental role that maintaining female-­only pregnancy
women’s duty to meet and satisfy the needs of others. The cultural as the sole gestational method plays in preserving patriarchal
expectation of altruism has fallen most heavily on pregnant social structures. Acknowledging this role allows to address the
women, so that one could say they are imaged as the archetypal tension that may derive by presenting ectogestation as emancipa-
altruists’.22 Claims that women are meant to be the primary care- tory when many of those who could benefit from avoiding gesta-
takers are grounded in the physical vicinity and the responsibilities tion and childbirth—women, mostly—seem to yearn for them.
and dependence involved in the gestational relation, in childbirth, Given how ‘efficient exploitation requires that those exploited
and nursing.23 This narrative positions women as physically and be relatively (…) self-­maintaining’,28 it is essential that women
conceptually closer to children than men, and it has been used keep choosing—without being explicitly forced—to engage in a
to construct the concept of a ‘sacred’ mother–child connection method of gestation (and, more generally, of reproduction) that
that should not be severed. Such a connection is often claimed harms them.3 29 It serves patriarchy that women find value in
to be different not only from the father–child one, but also from
the relation between a mother and a child she did not gestate. In
fact, the gestational tie has been framed as morally superior, with against their will and, at times, even against their legally recognised
philosophers claiming that birth parents have stronger parental gender. See, for instance, Alaattinoğlu, D. & Margaria, A. (2023). Trans
rights,24 and judicial bodies stating that, at birth, ‘every child parents and the gendered law: Critical reflections on the Swedish regula-
tion, International Journal of Constitutional Law, 21(2), 603–624.
should have a mother’,25 defined as the person who bore them.iii iv
See Bidoli and Di Nucci3 for a discussion on whether ectogestation
is a case of undone science, which is research that is not done because
iii
This proves particularly harmful for trans men who gestate and birth those with resources do not have an interest in it, or have an interest in
their own children, as in most countries they are registered as ‘mothers’ it staying ‘undone’.

2 Bidoli A. J Med Ethics 2024;0:1–7. doi:10.1136/jme-2023-109716


Extended essay

J Med Ethics: first published as 10.1136/jme-2023-109716 on 2 April 2024. Downloaded from http://jme.bmj.com/ on April 5, 2024 at The Hong Kong Polytechnic University. Protected by
pregnancy or, even better, that they perceive it as natural and nancy and childbirth independently of the arrival of their
therefore do not question the origin of their desire for it. child.’35 viii Even more, Smajdor claims that ‘(t)he necessity
In light of this, I suggest that a preference for pregnancy might of women for gestating and nurturing society’s children is so
be the result of oppressive norms and of the historical lack of entrenched in our consciousness that we fail to recognise that
gestational options. Let me start by outlining women’s possible we could change the situation’.35
reproductive preferences at present: C. Some women want a child but not a pregnancy. A clarifica-
A. Some women do not desire a child nor a pregnancy. This tion is due here: some might simply not want to be preg-
preference does not generally match social norms, there- nant themselves and would be satisfied by adopting a baby
fore, often resulting in stigma and disproportionate judge- or having one through a gestational carrier. My focus here,
ment.30 31 Nonetheless, with the notable exclusion of forced however, are those women who desire to avoid pregnancy
pregnancies, this preference can be satisfied. These women altogether. This preference may be driven by a number of
may simply not want to be parents, or they might have taken reasons, including but not limited to ethical concerns about
a more contingent decision, related for instance to the spe- exposing someone to the risks of gestation (regardless of
cific environment in which they would have to raise their compensation), not wanting to be subject of the social and/
children, or to the current inevitability of pregnancy. or legal implications of surrogacy, or a desire to weaken the
B. Some women want a childv and a pregnancy. This preference, above-­mentioned connection between mothers/women and
if physically possible, can be satisfied, and it matches pro- pregnancy. In its latter version, this preference cannot be sat-
natalist social norms. This latter aspect is likely part of why isfied.
such a preference is broadly respected and supportedvi, espe- Being able to choose not to bear children, as in preference
cially when it fits the heteronormative version of a nuclear (A), has been crucial to distance women from the motherhood
family. As mentioned, in addition to the lack of gestational mandate.ix Catharine MacKinnon states that ‘once a woman
alternatives, several factors may influence the formation of can choose not to bear children, to do so would constitute a
this preference. To some women, ‘the experience of preg- project, suggesting that childbearing is ‘natural’ only so long as
nancy might fit the conception of a project’32 and can be con- it is ‘fate’.36 With significant differences as well as similarities to
sidered a ‘not easily substitutable’32 component of their own the impact of adoption practices, surrogacy has disrupted the
identity. Pregnancy can also be perceived as a valuable part interdependence of motherhood and pregnancy, by allowing to
of the childrearing process, as one of the various ways to be sever such connection at an individual level. Despite these steps
involved in the (future) child’s life (e.g., by nurturing the fe- forward, though, women are not yet collectively able to choose
tus through your body, or having a privileged access to their to have children and not bear them. Pregnancy still affects their
first movementsvii). Therefore, a desire for motherhood via fate, as they are still—as a category—in charge of/responsible
pregnancy can derive from the combination of one’s values, for/burdened by gestation.

copyright.
personal situation, and social context. However, a prefer- This reflects on my claim that a desire for pregnancy can be a
ence for pregnancy cannot be assessed without reflecting on preference adapted ‘to and for oppression’,37 and more precisely
two key factors. First, the pronatalist narrative girls grow up a preference ‘formed in oppressively limited circumstances’.38
in, which presents pregnancy as a natural part of reproduc- Women can already try to imagine whether they would choose
tion, a ‘normal’ experience that all women, and women only, ectogestation should it be a possibility; among those who do,
should desire. Kendal claims that ‘pronatalistic enculturation some believe they would opt for it, some do not, and others
may diminish women’s autonomy in their reproductive deci- prefer not taking a stance until it can be more than specula-
sions, leaving them subject to overwhelming social pressures tion. However, coming to terms with a potential desire to avoid
and ‘unconscious desires’.21 Second, even if we accept the pregnancy could be extremely difficult when faced with the
formation of reproductive preferences as autonomous, we lack of an alternative as well as the complete absence of polit-
must consider the other factor, i.e., the available choices. As ical will to satisfy such a desire. Moreover, in a scenario where
argued by Claire Chambers, ‘(e)ven a perfectly rational, free- there is no institutional effort to expand one’s ‘limited circum-
ly choosing individual is constrained by the fact that she must stances’ (as shown by the lack of practical research promoted
choose from the options that are available to her, and that on the matter), becoming aware of the constrained origin of
are cast as appropriate for her’.33 Therefore, in the context one’s preference would not only not be enough to potentially
of patriarchy, and ‘in the struggle against patriarchal practic- change it, but it could also prove particularly challenging to deal
es, women should see their own present attitudes towards re- with. This might hinder a full, open reconsideration of one’s
production as contingent’.34 Anna Smajdor emphasises how, desires. For this reason, the development of an ectogestational
with pregnancy being the only way to have children, women method is particularly important: by concretely expanding the
‘have no reason to question the value or importance of preg- choice architecture, it would encourage a collective reevaluation
of reproductive preferences in a non-­coercive way. Differently
v
from now, such an assessment would go beyond speculation,
The desire for children can be due to a natural instinct, socialisation or since ectogestation would finally offer the possibility to choose
a combination of both and more. For the purpose of this paper, I will not
discuss whether the desire to reproduce and the desire to have biological/ between gestational methods and enable a practical (and not
genetical offspring are ethical. only conceptual) separation of gestation from the human body,
vi
Racism, classism, ableism and other forms of discrimination may and especially from female bodies.
result in women from different social groups being judged differently
for comparable reproductive choices. See, for instance, Kallianes, V.
and Rubenfeld, P. (1997) Disabled Women and Reproductive Rights,
viii
Disability & Society, 12:2, 203–222 and Masters, N.T., Lindhorst, T. In the case of surrogacy, the benefit considered greater than the risks
P., Meyers, M. K. (2014) Jezebel at the Welfare Office: How Racialized could be, for example, ‘gratification’ or financial compensation; as this
Stereotypes of Poor Women’s Reproductive Decisions and Relationships is not the focus of my paper, however, I will not elaborate further on
Shape Policy Implementation, Journal of Poverty. 18(2), 109–129. this point.
vii ix
I thank Fiona Woollard for this comment. Sadly, the right to abortion is far from being globally guaranteed.

Bidoli A. J Med Ethics 2024;0:1–7. doi:10.1136/jme-2023-109716 3


Extended essay

J Med Ethics: first published as 10.1136/jme-2023-109716 on 2 April 2024. Downloaded from http://jme.bmj.com/ on April 5, 2024 at The Hong Kong Polytechnic University. Protected by
This argument allows me to object to Giulia Cavaliere’s claim preference might require to ‘advocate policies that go against
that ‘the value of ectogenesis (…) lies in the political perspec- the express preferences and values of existing women’.27 This
tive that it can advance’.6 Cavaliere insists on how gender does not mean I am calling for a ban pregnancy; rather, I simply
justice requires fair reproductive opportunities for all, including support making pregnancy one of multiple gestational options.
those pregnant now and those who would choose pregnancy
in a hypothetical future society with more than one gestational
option. She supports ectogestation as a ‘provocation’, as a MORE THAN SOCIAL OPPRESSION
radical proposal aiming at putting existent reproductive issues In this section, I discuss how the corporeal nature of pregnancy
under the spotlight, rather than at its own realisation. In fact, can harm gestating persons beyond their health, by having a
to serve her point, such a technology does not need to actually negative impact at a social level.
exist: the idea of it is enough to ask ‘Why do we want to replace Cavaliere warns about framing ectogestation as ‘liberatory’,
pregnancy? Which issues are ectogestation expected to solve?’ claiming it identifies the source of oppression in female physi-
By posing these questions, Cavaliere argues that the core of the ology and overlooks the ‘broader systemic issues that contribute
issues is social, not biological and that action is missing due to a to the upholding of oppressive norms’.39 Along the same lines,
lack of political will, rather than the limits of current technology. Lisa Campo-­ Engelstein states that disembodying gestation
For instance, a meticulous deconstruction of sexist, classist, and cannot solve women’s inequality since its ‘root cause’ is not preg-
racist biases in medical professionals would improve the quality nancy, but ‘a systemic social structure of oppression’.40 Romanis
of care, and a stronger commitment to invest in healthcare emphasises ‘the importance of good reproductive healthcare to
would result in better infrastructure, facilities and equipment, as better guarantee equality and freedom’,41 and Claire Horner
well as better trained and less overworked staff. As proven by the calls for a society where ‘women (are) no longer economically,
significant differences in between high-­income and low-­income socially or physically disadvantaged due to pregnancy and birth,
settings, maternal morbidity and mortality can be significantly despite still becoming pregnant’.42
reduced (although, not completely prevented) through acces- While I share those hopes, I believe that social change cannot
sible quality care.3 completely eliminate pregnancy’s social and physical risks. It
I praise and share Cavaliere’s commitment not to dismiss can improve healthcare services and tackle discrimination, but
these current issues as ‘impossible to solve’ unless a cutting-­edge not prevent all the negative effects pregnancy can cause. For
technology comes to the rescue, and I support her call for polit- example, many people highly value activities such as work,
ical action on these matters. Indeed, even if ectogestation were hobbies and sports; however, despite their best intentions not to
possible, all those who would still get pregnant would deserve to abandon such activities, some may have a physiological need to
be treated fairly and effectively. However, my aim here is to show do so caused by their pregnant state or by certain consequences
that women have been harmed both by having their reproduc- of gestation or childbirth. Usually, this concern is minimised, if

copyright.
tive preferences driven by oppressive social norms, stigmatising at all considered, under two assumptions: first, women should
preference (A), and by the lack of gestational options, keeping not value activities such as work or exercise more than having a
preference (C) impossible to be satisfied. While Cavaliere limits child. Some would claim that women should not value anything
ectogestation’s social contribution to political provocation, I more, except maybe taking care of their partners and family;
argue that that is only part of its potential. Sometimes, asking if they do, they are likely considered mean, heartless women
the question is not enough; an answer is required for change unwilling to make a sacrifice for their children and therefore
to happen. Ectogestation would provide a unique contribution, undeserving of becoming mothers. Since this narrative is related
first by encouraging a collective reevaluation of the value given to the expectation of selflessness previously addressed, here I
to pregnancy and then, should this preference come to be, by focus on the other assumption, namely that only few exceptional
actually enabling reproduction without pregnancy. This would career paths can truly be hindered by pregnancy. First, that is
allow women and, eventually, all people to rethink reproduction not true—one does not need to be a professional athlete, actor,
completely and do it differently. or model for pregnancy to interfere with their profession in a
Questioning a preference for pregnancy, which has historically significant way. More importantly, though, a person's social life
been not only in line with an oppressive system but foundational is (generally) not limited to their jobs. Conditions like hyper-
for it, can arguably weaken such system; the call for ectogesta- emesis gravidarum, depression and anxiety, pre-­ eclampsia or
tion is therefore not limited to the intention of offering a safe any complication resulting in bed rest would negatively affect
alternative to a burdensome process, but it includes its socially most persons' professional and social life. Even ‘minor’ common
disruptive potential. As most preferences derive from what is, or consequences like fatigue, constipation, frequent urination or
is not, available (including objective and perceived availability), perineal laceration can influence one’s ability to perform well
‘the mere fact that they are adaptive is not what makes them at work, have sexual relations, enjoy social outings and activi-
problematic’.27 A preference for pregnancy is to be questioned ties they might otherwise want to do. While all types of harm
as it is in line with the needs and interest of an oppressive social pregnancy can cause are expected to be forgotten once the baby
structure, resulting, for example, in different socioeconomic is born,3 these ‘minor’ effects on one’s lifestyle are particularly
prospects across and within sexes. A common objection to this disregarded and trivialised, and those concerned with them are
argument is that it refers to a social problem requiring social encouraged to ‘toughen up’ when not guilted into feeling selfish,
measures. However, a preference for pregnancy goes beyond leaving many women to deal with their worries in silence
that, as it brings a specific population group to engage with Emily Jackson concedes that ‘being relieved of the burdens
serious risks for a reward, with many of those risks being physio- of pregnancy might enable women to compete more equally in
logical and not social. For this reason, even if it may seem coun- the workplace during their children’s gestation’,43 but without
terintuitive to promote something that seemingly goes against equality in care work after birth, ‘eliminating pregnancy
the most common preference (i.e., to promote a method to would not necessarily eliminate gender inequality’.43 Romanis
avoid pregnancy—for women’s sake—when most women want and Horn agree, claiming that pregnancy is ‘just one 9-­month
to be pregnant), the implications of such a gendered adaptive passage in raising a child’.44 Moreover, Cavaliere warns about
4 Bidoli A. J Med Ethics 2024;0:1–7. doi:10.1136/jme-2023-109716
Extended essay

J Med Ethics: first published as 10.1136/jme-2023-109716 on 2 April 2024. Downloaded from http://jme.bmj.com/ on April 5, 2024 at The Hong Kong Polytechnic University. Protected by
defending perspectives seemingly freeing women from ‘the Stating this does not mean doubting that the oppressive social
‘tyranny of pregnancy’ and childbirth’ only to deliver them framework women live in has a negative impact on their expe-
‘into the tyrannical hands of a precarious, unfair and potentially riences as pregnant beings, nor implying that pregnancy is still
exploitative labour market’.6 On this view, free of patriarchal the sole, or main, determining cause of current male oppres-
constraints, pregnancy could be a different, maybe easier and sive dominance.49 For these reasons, ectogestation would indeed
generally better experience,45 as its oppressiveness could be not be a solution to social issues due to structural injustices, nor
determined by its happening ‘under conditions of male domi- the only measure needed for women’s liberation. What I claim,
nation’.46 Capitalistic demands can indeed play a negative though, is that it is the only way to avoid certain social implica-
role, since a system of production that requires consistent—if tions caused by pregnancy.
not relentlessly increasing—efficiency poorly coexists with any
form of perceived weakness. In such a system, which penalises
any ‘less-­than-­optimal’ performance, ‘(c)hild-­bearing threatens A REASONABLE BET
to diminish the contribution a woman in the subordinate class Finally, I want to address the objection that, even if we accept
can make as a direct producer and as a participant in necessary female-­only pregnancy was an essential factor in the creation
labour’.47 of oppressive social norms, those have developed in such a way
I support these scholars’ commitment to pointing out that a throughout history that they no longer necessitate that biological
disproportionate amount of parenting labour falls on mothers basis. To Cavaliere, this makes ectogestation’s chances of success
regardless of whether they gestated, as this is socially assigned in dismantling oppressive gender norms dependent on a ‘bet’,
and occurs after pregnancy. After birth, any parenting task can since ‘(o)nly introducing a new reproductive technology or prac-
theoretically be performed by parents regardless of their sex and tice (even one that so radically changes biological reproduction)
gender. When this is not the case, it is likely due to social norms does not determine how and whether such a technology or prac-
and gender roles; moreover, a study suggests non-­ gestating tice will go about shaping current arrangements, and social values
expectant parents can affect the fetus and can perform parenting and norms’.6 Similarly, Jackson claims that ‘without equality in
tasks even during the gestational period.23 My claim, however, is the distribution of household labour after birth, most notably
that pregnancy itself cannot be shared. The physical and some- in relation to childcare, (…) eliminating pregnancy would not
times psychological consequences of gestation and childbirth can necessarily eliminate gender inequality’.43
affect the person’s well-­being in ways that would not be solved, It is possible to accept that women’s oppression would not be
for instance, by equal treatment policy in the workplace or equal solved by ectogestation (therefore supporting the parallel need
parental leave, because they do not originate there.x for social interventions), while arguing that it could make such
To address the concerns about capitalist pressures, I want to a contribution that it is worth ‘betting’ on it, especially given
point out how these objections are not exclusive to ectogesta- its potential unique benefits. We can commit to tackling the

copyright.
tion. For instance, non-­medical egg freezing (NMEF) encoun- social phenomenon of women’s oppression from both sides:
ters similar opposition, with claims that its use to postpone while we implement social measures aimed to erode oppressive
pregnancy for career purposes means adapting—instead of norms and oppose those using biology as an oppressive tool,
fighting—the unfair labour market. According to Thomas Søbirk we can take power away from them by making this ‘tool’ no
Petersen,48 while the system is to blame when people who need longer necessary, by transforming pregnancy from being the only
time off cannot get it, we should not assume that the desire reproductive option to simply one of two gestational methods.
not to be pregnant at a certain point of one’s career—there- As famously stated by De Beauvoir, ‘human society is never left
fore resorting to NMEF to maximise one’s chances to become to nature. And in particular, (…) the reproductive function has
a (genetic) parent later on—is due to structural constraints. In no longer been controlled by biological chance alone but by
addition, one could resort to NMEF at a certain time of their design’.50 In this context, redesigning biological processes such
life for reasons not related to work, such as the lack of a partner as gestation can be ‘a potential space of emancipatory gender
to parent with, which cannot be solved by social measures such political interventions’.51
as improving childcare services and parental leave. In the same Moreover, it is true that supporting ectogestation as an
way, even though it would not automatically improve women’s emancipatory measure might be a bet, even a ‘high risk-­high
career prospects or gender parity in care labour, ectogestation reward’ one. Given the high stakes of the case, though, it
would allow people to avoid the physical harm and the lifestyle can be argued that valid reasons in favour of it, not certain-
limitations related to pregnancy and childbirth. Being able to ties, should be enough to consider the risk ‘reasonable’. Let’s
work could also benefit their well-­being, not by aligning to the take the case of modern contraceptives as an example of
demands of an unfair economic system, but simply because they an innovation that has had major health and social impli-
may genuinely care and enjoy their profession. cations, by preventing sexually transmissible diseases and
My aim is to emphasise that pregnancy can cause physical undesired pregnancies. At the moment of their introduction
harm with potential negative social repercussions and that those on the market, expecting the strong social change contra-
limitations are not caused by negative externalities but by preg- ceptives eventually brought was indeed a bet: there was
nancy being a corporeal experience. Therefore, until gestation no guarantee against the risk of a low or no uptake, which
is tied to one’s body, avoiding them entirely is just not possible. would have significantly limited their impact. As contracep-
tives’ cost may not be affordable to everyone, there is a risk
x
It is also relevant to notice how women not only undertake more of exacerbating class inequalities, since those more likely
parental tasks, but they often do so while still recovering from the toll to get unwillingly pregnant earlier and more often are also
of pregnancy and childbirth, which—to stress the point—is caused by those with less access, conceptually and practically, to abor-
the physicality of the process. It should also be highlighted that such toll tion services. This is where State action is most needed, by
varies from person to person, due to both individual physical differences
and social factors, such as racism and classism; see Birthrights. (2022).
subsidising contraception for all, or at least for those most
Systemic Racism, Not Broken Bodies. An inquiry into racial injustice and with less means. Even serious issues such as cases of poor or
human rights in UK maternity care. 1–100. mentally ill people coerced or forced to use contraception, 52
Bidoli A. J Med Ethics 2024;0:1–7. doi:10.1136/jme-2023-109716 5
Extended essay

J Med Ethics: first published as 10.1136/jme-2023-109716 on 2 April 2024. Downloaded from http://jme.bmj.com/ on April 5, 2024 at The Hong Kong Polytechnic University. Protected by
which certainly must be addressed, do not undermine the 4 Horn C. Ectogenesis, inequality, and coercion: a reproductive justice-­informed analysis
revolutionary benefits contraception has brought in terms of of the impact of artificial wombs. BioSocieties 2023;18:523–44.
5 Lee JY, Bidoli A, Di Nucci E. Does Ectogestation have oppressive potential Journal of
health, reproductive autonomy, and sexual liberation. Social Philosophy 2023.
This shows how it should not be such a concern that the 6 Cavaliere G. Gestation, equality and freedom: Ectogenesis as a political perspective. J
introduction of ectogestation might not guarantee an equal Med Ethics 2020;46:76–82.
7 Chloe Romanis E, Horn C. Artificial wombs and the Ectogenesis conversation: A
redistribution of responsibilities and expectations among misplaced focus? technology, abortion, and reproductive freedom. IJFAB: International
parents, nor automatically change the norms defining Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics 2020;13:174–94.
women’s ‘role in social reproduction and the effects of 8 Kingma E. Were you a part of your mother?: the metaphysics of pregnancy for an
having such role on their lives at home and in the work- in-­detail discussion of these two models of pregnancy. Mind 2019;128:609–46.
9 Copelton DA. "You are what you eat": nutritional norms, maternal deviance, and
place’.6 As long as there are valid reasons to believe certain neutralization of women’s Prenatal diets. Deviant Behavior 2007;28:467–94.
benefits could derive from it (including but not limited to 10 Amnesty International. Criminalizing pregnancy: policing pregnant women who use
those discussed in this paper), ectogestation should not be drugs in the USA (AMR 51/6203/2017), Available: https://www.amnesty.org/en/​
held to a higher standard than contraception was, or than documents/amr51/6203/2017/en/ [Accessed 23 May 2017].
11 Stone R. Pregnant women and substance use: fear, stigma, and barriers to care.
any other innovation. Very few policies or products, if any, Health Justice 2015;3:2.
are promoted expecting a guaranteed outcome, since even 12 McKiever M, Frey H, Costantine MM. Challenges in conducting clinical research
the best evidence-­b ased models cannot account for all unex- studies in pregnant women. J Pharmacokinet Pharmacodyn 2020;47:287–93.
13 Chase SE, Rogers MF. Mothers and children: Feminist analyses and personal
pected variables.
narratives. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press, 2001: 230.
14 Colomar M, Opiyo N, Kingdon C, et al. Do women prefer Caesarean sections?
A qualitative evidence synthesis of their views and experiences. PLoS One
CONCLUSION 2021;16:e0251072.
This paper supports ectogestation as a means of emancipa- 15 Sakai-­Bizmark R, Ross MG, Estevez D, et al. Evaluation of hospital cesarean
delivery–related profits and rates in the United States. JAMA Netw Open
tion for women. I argued that ectogestation would have a 2021;4:e212235.
dual social benefit: first, by providing a gestational alterna- 16 Oster E, McClelland WS. Why the C-­section rate is so high. The Atlantic October 17,
tive to pregnancy, ectogestation would create unique condi- 2019.
tions to reevaluate one’s reproductive preferences—which, 17 Romanis EC. Why the elective Caesarean lottery is ethically Impermissible. Health Care
Anal 2019;27:249–68.
for women, always include gestational considerations—and 18 Hill A. Women in labour being refused epidurals, official inquiry finds. The Guardian,
to satisfy a potential preference for reproduction without 2020.
pregnancy. Enabling the satisfaction of such a preference 19 van der Pijl M, Verhoeven C, Hollander M, et al. The ethics of consent during labour
and birth: Episiotomies. J Med Ethics 2023;49:611–7.
is particularly valuable due to the pressures women face to
20 Koedt A, Levine E, Rapone A. Radical Feminism. New York: Quadrangle Books. P,
embrace pregnancy as central to their identity, while at the 1973: 375.
same time being penalised by it. Second, I emphasise how 21 Kendal E. Equal opportunity and the case for state sponsored Ectogenesis. In:

copyright.
certain social negative implications of gestation and child- Equal Opportunity and the Case for State Sponsored Ectogenesis. London: Palgrave
Macmillan, 2015: 10.
birth are caused by these being corporeal phenomena, and 22 Raymond JG. Women as wombs: reproductive technologies and the battle over
would therefore not be solved by social measures. Finally, women’s freedom. Spinifex Press, 1995: 51.
I consider how some objections to ectogestation resemble 23 Fontana D, Schoenbaum N. Unsexing pregnancy; 2019. Columbia Law Rev,;119:309–
those to other innovations, such as modern contraceptives 68.
24 Gheaus A. Biological Parenthood: gestational, not genetic. Australasian Journal of
and non-­ m edical egg freezing. I argue that ectogestation Philosophy 2018;96:225–40.
should not be treated differently than comparable technol- 25 R (McConnell and YY). V registrar general for England and Wales [2020] EWCA Civ
ogies without a valid reason and that, given its potential 559. n.d. Available: http://www.bailii.org/ew/cases/EWCA/Civ/2020/559.html
unique contribution to women’s emancipation, it is worth 26 Gheaus A, Robeyns I. Equality-­promoting parental leave. Journal of Social Philosophy
2011;42:173–91.
the bet. 27 Levey A. Liberalism, adaptive preferences, and gender equality. Hypatia
2005;20:127–43.
Twitter Andrea Bidoli @andreabidoli 28 Frye M. The politics of reality. Freedom, Calif: Crossing Press, 1983.
29 Smajdor A. The moral imperative for Ectogenesis. Camb Q Healthc Ethics
Acknowledgements I want to thank Giulia Cavaliere and Ezio Di Nucci for their 2007;16:336–45.
comments on an earlier draft of this paper. 30 Ashburn-­Nardo L. Parenthood as a moral imperative? moral outrage and the
Contributors AB is the sole author of this article and guarantor. Stigmatization of voluntarily Childfree women and men. Sex Roles 2017;76:393–401.
31 Hintz EA, Brown CL. Childfree by choice: stigma in medical consultations for voluntary
Funding This study was funded by Velux Fonden (00026589). sterilization. Women’s Reproductive Health 2019;6:62–75.
Competing interests None declared. 32 Rulli T. Preferring a genetically-­related child. J Moral Philos 2014;13:669–98.
33 Chambers C. Sex, culture, and justice. In: Sex, culture, and justice. The limits of choice.
Patient consent for publication Not applicable. Penn State University Press, 17 May 2018.
Provenance and peer review Not commissioned; externally peer reviewed. 34 Hedman C. The artificial womb: patriarchal bone or technological blessing? Radical
Philosophy 1990;056:15–24.
Data availability statement Data sharing not applicable as no datasets 35 Smajdor A. In defense of Ectogenesis. Camb Q Healthc Ethics 2012;21:90–103.
generated and/or analysed for this study. No data are available. 36 MacKinnon C. Toward a feminist theory of the state. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard
University Press, 1989: 58.
ORCID iD 37 Cudd AE. Adaptations to oppression. In: Oshana MAL, ed. Personal Autonomy and
Andrea Bidoli http://orcid.org/0000-0003-3835-9513 Social Oppression. New York: Routledge, 2015: 142–60.
38 Walsh MB. Adaptive preferences, and social contract theory. Hypatia
2015;30:829–45.
REFERENCES 39 Cavaliere G. Ectogenesis and Gender‐Based oppression: resisting the ideal of
1 MacKay K. The ’tyranny of reproduction’: could ectogenesis further women’s liberation assimilation. Bioethics 2020;34:727–34.
Bioethics 2020;34:346–53. 40 Campo-­Engelstein L. Reproductive Technologies are not the cure for social problems. J
2 Takala T. Human before sex? Ectogenesis as a way to equality. In: Simonstein F, Med Ethics 2020;46:85–6.
ed. In Reprogen-­Ethics and the Future of Gender. Netherlands: Springer Press, 41 Romanis EC. Partial ectogenesis: freedom, equality and political perspective. J Med
2009: 187–95. Ethics 2020;46:89–90.
3 Bidoli A, Di Nucci E. Beyond pregnancy: A public health case for a technological 42 Horner C. Imagine a world… where ectogenesis isn’t needed to eliminate social and
alternative. IJFAB: International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics economic barriers for women. J Med Ethics 2020;46:83–4.
2023;16:103–30. 43 Jackson E. Degendering reproduction Med Law Rev 2008;16:346–68.

6 Bidoli A. J Med Ethics 2024;0:1–7. doi:10.1136/jme-2023-109716


Extended essay

J Med Ethics: first published as 10.1136/jme-2023-109716 on 2 April 2024. Downloaded from http://jme.bmj.com/ on April 5, 2024 at The Hong Kong Polytechnic University. Protected by
44 Horn C, Romanis EC. Establishing boundaries for speculation about artificial wombs, 49 Whetmore EAW. Empowering women—A series of articles about the surge in and
Ectogenesis, gender, and the Gestating body. In: Dietz C, Travis M, Thomson M, eds. A fragmentation of Mid-­20Th-­century American feminist theory: article 1: radical
jurisprudence of the body. Palgrave Macmillan Ltd, 2020: 227–54. notions. SAGE Open 2014;4:215824401454378.
45 Cohen Shabot S. Constructing subjectivity through labour pain: A Beauvoirian 50 De Beauvoir S. The second sex. In: Vintage. P.716 (ebook). 2011.
analysis. European Journal of Women’s Studies 2017;24:128–42. 51 CCCBLAB. Helen Hester: “Biology is not destiny, it can be technologically
46 Thompson D. Radical Feminism today. In: Radical Feminism Today. 1 Oliver’s Yard, 55
transformed", . 2019.Available: https://lab.cccb.org/en/helen-hester-biology-is-not-​
City Road, London EC1Y 1SP United Kingdom : SAGE Publications Inc, 2001: 117.
47 Vogel L. Marxism and the oppression of women. In: Marxism and the Oppression of destiny-it-can-be-technologically-transformed/
Women: Toward a Unitary Theory. BRILL, 2013: 151. 52 Nørby Hansen N, Dehlendorf C, Holt K. Grønlandske Politikere Reagerer På
48 Petersen TS. Arguments on thin ice: on non-­medical egg freezing and Individualisation Spiralsag. In: The Dangerous Rise of the IUD as Poverty Cure. The New York Times,
arguments. J Med Ethics 2021;47:164–8. 2019.

copyright.

Bidoli A. J Med Ethics 2024;0:1–7. doi:10.1136/jme-2023-109716 7

You might also like