You are on page 1of 4

Equality and Equal Opportunity for Welfare

- To some extent, it is the gap itself [between poor and rich people]
that is bad, not just the low absolute level of the standard of living
of the poor.
- He argues that the idea of equal opportunity for welfare is the best
interpretation of the ideal of distributive equality.
- According to equality of welfare, goods are distributed equally
among a group of persons to the degree that the distribution brings
it about that each person enjoys the same welfare.
- He takes welfare to be preference satisfaction, limited to self-
interested preferences.
- “first stage” and “second stage” rational preferences.
- FIrst stage is imagined to be considering full information relevant
to choice on the assumption that the results of this ideal
deliberation process can costlessly correct one’s actual
preferences.
- At second stage, one is imagined to be considering also
information regarding a) one’s actual resistance to advice regarding
the rationality of one’s preferences, b) the costs of an educational
program that would break down this resistance, and c) the
likelihood that anything approaching this educational program will
actually be implemented in one’s lifetime.
- No imperative of practical reason commands us to devote our lives
to the maximal pursuit of (self-interested) preference satisfaction.
Divergence from equality of welfare arising in these ways need not
signal any fault imputable to individuals or to society understood as
responsible for maintaining distributive equality.
An example of compensating for one’s religious upbringing has two
particularly tricky parts: first, if a person changes her values in the
light of deliberation, that bring her closer to the ideal of deliberative
rationality, the old values should be counted at a discount due to
their presumed greater distance from deliberative rationality.
Secondly, the example might motivate acceptance of equal
opportunity for welfare over straight equality of welfare rather than
rejecting subjectivist conceptions of equality altogether.
- An opportunity is a chance of getting a good if one seeks it. For
equal opportunity of welfare to obtain among a number of persons,
each must face an array of options that is equivalent to every other
person’s in terms of the prospects for preference satisfaction it
offers.
- The preferences involved are ideally considered second-best
preferences.
- Equal opportunity for welfare obtains among persons when all of
them face equivalent decision trees - the expected value of each
person’s best choice of options, second-best … nth-best is the
same. The opportunities persons encounter are ranked by the
prospects for welfare they afford.
- This criterion stated above is incomplete.
- People may differ in their awareness of their options, their ability
to choose reasonably among them, and the ability to carry out a
chosen option.
- Hence, more conditions needed, such can be summarised by
stipulating that a number of persons face effectively equivalent
options if one of the following is true:
1) the options are equivalent and the persons are on a par in their
ability to negotiate these options,
2) the options are nonequivalent in such a way as to counterbalance
exactly any inequalities in people’s negotiating abilities, or
3) the options are equivalent and any inequalities in people’s
negotiating abilities are due to causes for which it is proper to hold
the individuals themselves personally responsible.
- Equal opportunity for welfare obtains when all persons face
effectively equivalent arrays of options.
- The norm of equal opportunity for welfare is distinct from equality
of welfare only if some version of soft determinism or indeterminism
is correct. If hard determinism is true, the two interpretations of
equality come to the same.
- We run into the problem that in the real world, there will be
practical implications.
- The norm of equal opportunity for resources is vulnerable to the
“slavery of the talented” problem.
- Equal opportunity for welfare will often find tastes compensable,
including the talented person’s taste for the personal liberty to
command their own labour power - being born with high talent
cannot be a curse nor a blessing under equal opportunity for
welfare.
- If a person's having a capability is deemed valuable on grounds
independent of the person's own preferences in the matter, the
excess valuation would seem to presuppose the adequacy of an as
yet unspecified perfectionist doctrine the like of which has certainly
not yet been defended and in my opinion is indefensible. 19 In the
absence of such a defense of perfectionism, equal opportunity for
welfare looks to be an attractive interpretation of distributive
equality.

Lecture
- Brute luck vs option luck.
- Equality as neutral luck:
Can the fact that our talents are due to brute luck justify equality?
The inference from “the impact of luck should be undone” to “we
should aim for equality” is flawed.
The fact that our concern is with the distribution of goods that are a
matter of luck, for which people are not responsible, rather of
something else, does not in itself tell us how to distribute these
goods. Elizabeth Anderson’s point about social hierarchy nulls this
point!
- Argument from voluntary gambling. Stupid argument - gambling,
even if seen voluntarily, is not if it gets to the point where someone
would need to step in. Gambling stems from desperation and
becomes an addiction, something that is not voluntary.
- Gambling is captured by equality of opportunity - if they voluntarily
gambled and lost, then there is no moral incline to help them now
they’re below the welfare expectation.
- Argument for expensive tastes. Again, this does not apply to
Anderson’s theory since it simply is not of egalitarian concern.
- Harshness objection: luck egalitarians would not aid those who are
victims of their own imprudence. But withholding aid seems harsh.
Car crash claim from Anderson. There is an absolute point fo
egalitarianism that I believe no matter the context, everyone
deserves to participate in certain rights. These rights however, are
not absolute, and can be regulated. For example, free healthcare,
freedom of speech etc,.
- Metaphysical objection: luck egalitarianism depends on a
libertarian conception of free will. But that is dubious.
-

You might also like