You are on page 1of 53

Philosophical Perspectives on Suicide:

Kant, Schopenhauer, Nietzsche, and


Wittgenstein Paolo Stellino
Visit to download the full and correct content document:
https://textbookfull.com/product/philosophical-perspectives-on-suicide-kant-schopenh
auer-nietzsche-and-wittgenstein-paolo-stellino/
More products digital (pdf, epub, mobi) instant
download maybe you interests ...

Biota Grow 2C gather 2C cook Loucas

https://textbookfull.com/product/biota-grow-2c-gather-2c-cook-
loucas/

Bad Words: Philosophical Perspectives On Slurs David


Sosa

https://textbookfull.com/product/bad-words-philosophical-
perspectives-on-slurs-david-sosa/

Philosophical Perspectives on Land Reform in Southern


Africa Erasmus Masitera

https://textbookfull.com/product/philosophical-perspectives-on-
land-reform-in-southern-africa-erasmus-masitera/

Wittgenstein and Interreligious Disagreement: A


Philosophical and Theological Perspective 1st Edition
Gorazd Andrej■ (Auth.)

https://textbookfull.com/product/wittgenstein-and-interreligious-
disagreement-a-philosophical-and-theological-perspective-1st-
edition-gorazd-andrejc-auth/
Delphi Collected Works of Arthur Schopenhauer
Illustrated Arthur Schopenhauer

https://textbookfull.com/product/delphi-collected-works-of-
arthur-schopenhauer-illustrated-arthur-schopenhauer/

Arthur Schopenhauer The World as Will and Presentation


1st Edition Arthur Schopenhauer

https://textbookfull.com/product/arthur-schopenhauer-the-world-
as-will-and-presentation-1st-edition-arthur-schopenhauer/

Wittgenstein Religion and Ethics New Perspectives from


Philosophy and Theology Mikel Burley

https://textbookfull.com/product/wittgenstein-religion-and-
ethics-new-perspectives-from-philosophy-and-theology-mikel-
burley/

Emotion in Sports Philosophical Perspectives Yunus


Tuncel

https://textbookfull.com/product/emotion-in-sports-philosophical-
perspectives-yunus-tuncel/

Unravelling the Soil Microbiome: Perspectives For


Environmental Sustainability Rama Kant Dubey

https://textbookfull.com/product/unravelling-the-soil-microbiome-
perspectives-for-environmental-sustainability-rama-kant-dubey/
Philosophical
Perspectives
on Suicide
Kant, Schopenhauer,
Nietzsche, and Wittgenstein

Paolo Stellino
Philosophical Perspectives on Suicide
Paolo Stellino

Philosophical
Perspectives on
Suicide
Kant, Schopenhauer, Nietzsche,
and Wittgenstein
Paolo Stellino
Nova Institute of Philosophy
Universidade Nova de Lisboa
LISBOA, Portugal

ISBN 978-3-030-53936-8    ISBN 978-3-030-53937-5 (eBook)


https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-53937-5

© The Editor(s) (if applicable) and The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature
Switzerland AG 2020
This work is subject to copyright. All rights are solely and exclusively licensed by the Publisher, whether
the whole or part of the material is concerned, specifically the rights of translation, reprinting, reuse of
illustrations, recitation, broadcasting, reproduction on microfilms or in any other physical way, and
transmission or information storage and retrieval, electronic adaptation, computer software, or by similar
or dissimilar methodology now known or hereafter developed.
The use of general descriptive names, registered names, trademarks, service marks, etc. in this publication
does not imply, even in the absence of a specific statement, that such names are exempt from the relevant
protective laws and regulations and therefore free for general use.
The publisher, the authors, and the editors are safe to assume that the advice and information in this book
are believed to be true and accurate at the date of publication. Neither the publisher nor the authors or
the editors give a warranty, expressed or implied, with respect to the material contained herein or for any
errors or omissions that may have been made. The publisher remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional
claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

This Palgrave Macmillan imprint is published by the registered company Springer Nature Switzerland AG.
The registered company address is: Gewerbestrasse 11, 6330 Cham, Switzerland
Preface

According to Baruch Spinoza, “a free person thinks about death less than
anything, and his wisdom is a meditation not on death but on life”
(Ethics, IV, 67). Writing a book on the philosophy of suicide does not
necessarily mean to meditate on death. This is what I tried to explain—
often with no success—to all those friends and colleagues that in recent
years kept asking me why I had chosen to work on such a gloomy subject.
Of course, I could have reminded them of Camus’ well-known opening
words of The Myth of Sisyphus: “There is but one truly serious philosophi-
cal problem and that is suicide.” But the fact is that whereas I am not
persuaded by Camus’ claim, I am truly convinced that meditating on
suicide means, to a great extent, meditating on fundamental questions
that directly concern life, not death. Among others, these questions are:
How do we conceive our obligations to society, friends, and family?
Which is the set of moral values according to which we choose to orien-
tate our life? Which is the value that we give to our autonomy and free-
dom? Is this value non-negotiable? And how do we conceive dignity? Is it
a “property” that, in specific situations, can be undermined or
deteriorated?
I began to take interest in these questions almost fifteen years ago
when, almost accidentally, I attended a session of the seminar of the
Bioethics Research Group of the University of Valencia. At the time, I
was still a PhD student and the subject of my dissertation (on Nietzsche
v
vi Preface

and Dostoevsky) had little to do with bioethics. Juan Carlos Siurana


Aparisi, the director of the research group, drew my attention to the fact
that Nietzsche’s stance on suicide was almost unexplored by bioethicists.
I began looking for Nietzsche’s remarks on suicide in his writings and
posthumous fragments. What struck me immediately was Nietzsche’s
joyous and almost poetical conception of free death. The possibility of
conceiving death differently, that is, as a festival was something new for me.
I left Spain in 2010. At the time, I had two main concerns: to find a
post-doc position and to work on the English translation of my disserta-
tion. I temporarily set aside my interest on the topic of suicide and
devoted myself completely to Nietzsche and Dostoevsky. It was an inter-
national conference on Kant and Nietzsche, held in 2012 in Lisbon, that
gave me the occasion to work again on the philosophy of suicide. From
that moment, suicide has been, somewhat intermittently, one of my main
topics of research. The idea of writing this book occurred to me some
years later, when I noticed that there was a fil rouge that linked Kant’s,
Schopenhauer’s, Nietzsche’s, and Wittgenstein’s views of suicide. I will
motivate my choice to place these four philosophical perspectives on sui-
cide side by side in the Introduction, so that there is no need to dwell on
it here.
Some chapters of this book are based on material previously published
in P. Stellino, “Nietzsche on Suicide”, Nietzsche-Studien, 42 (2013):
151–177, and in P. Stellino, “Kant and Nietzsche on Suicide”, Philosophical
Inquiry, 39/2 (2015): 79–104. Although in both cases I heavily reworked
their content for this book, I would like to thank both journals for per-
mission to revise and reuse these publications.
My research particularly benefited from the works of three specialists
on the philosophy of suicide: Margaret P. Battin, Héctor Wittwer, and
Michael Cholbi. Wittwer’s book Selbsttötung als philosophisches Problem:
Über die Rationalität und Moralität des Suizids particularly helped me at
the initial stage of my research to understand the complexities of the dif-
ferent arguments that are put forward in the debate concerning the ratio-
nality and morality of suicide.

LisbonPaolo Stellino
23 April 2020
Acknowledgements

I owe a great debt to the following friends and colleagues who read single
chapters of this book and provided me with extremely valuable feedback:
Roberta Pasquarè and Lorena Cebolla Sanahuja (chapter on Kant),
Christopher Janaway and Vilmar Debona (chapter on Schopenhauer),
Marta Faustino and Maria Cristina Fornari (chapter on Nietzsche), and
Vicente Sanfélix Vidarte and Modesto Gómez Alonso (chapter on
Wittgenstein). I am also most grateful to the anonymous reviewer for
providing very useful critical and constructive comments on the entire
manuscript.
I would like to thank Brendan George and Lauriane Piette, from
Palgrave Macmillan, and Charanya Manoharan, from Springer, for their
help and support. I would also like to thank João Constâncio for kindly
supporting my work since the first day I arrived in Lisbon. I should also
mention that this book would not have been possible without the sup-
port of the Portuguese Fundação para a Ciência e a Tecnologia (FCT).
A part of this book was written during my stay in Montpellier. I would
like to thank Pascal Nouvel for welcoming me at the Centre d’Éthique
Contemporaine. A special thought goes to Nadia El Eter and Guillaume
Bagnolini, who shared with me the daily routine at the Centre.
A word of gratitude goes to all the friends who, inside and outside
academia, near and far, have accompanied me during this journey. I can-
not help mentioning Maria Cristina Fornari, Luca Lupo, and Pietro
vii
viii Acknowledgements

Gori. In particular, I shared with Pietro all the ups and downs of the
academic life as well as the experience of building a new life in a new
country with our respective families.
Finally, I am deeply thankful to my family for their constant support,
and to Audrey for her love and for sharing her life with me (despite the
fact that I am a philosopher). E lucevan le stelle…
Contents

1 Introduction: Bringing Kant, Schopenhauer, Nietzsche,


and Wittgenstein Together  1
References  9

2 Immanuel Kant: The Moral Duty of Self-­Preservation 11


2.1 Contextualizing Kant’s Prohibition of Suicide  11
2.2 Arguments from the Lectures on Ethics  23
2.3 Arguments from the Published Writings  40
2.4 Concluding Remarks  64
References 66

3 Arthur Schopenhauer: The Metaphysical Futility of Suicide 71


3.1 Schopenhauer’s Critique of Religious and Philosophical
Arguments against Suicide  78
3.2 Schopenhauer’s Metaphysical Worldview  90
3.3 The Futility of Suicide 100
3.4 Concluding Remarks 117
References118

ix
x Contents

4 Friedrich Nietzsche: A Free Death at the Right Time123


4.1 Voluntary versus Involuntary Death 131
4.2 Free Death and Quick Death 143
4.3 Meaninglessness and Suicide 155
4.4 Concluding Remarks 173
References174

5 Ludwig Wittgenstein: Suicide as the Elementary Sin179


5.1 The Sources 189
5.2 Wittgenstein’s View of Ethics 199
5.3 Wittgenstein’s Remarks on Suicide 208
5.4 Concluding Remarks 221
References223

6 Conclusion: What Kant, Schopenhauer, Nietzsche, and


Wittgenstein Can Teach Us About Suicide227
References240

Index243
About the author

Paolo Stellino is Researcher at the Nova Institute of Philosophy, New


University of Lisbon, Portugal. His main fields of research interest are the
history of nineteenth- and twentieth-century philosophy, ethics, and phi-
losophy of cinema. He has published many articles in international peer-­
reviewed journals and has authored several book chapters. He is the
author of the book Nietzsche and Dostoevsky: On the Verge of Nihilism (2015).

xi
Abbreviations

Kant
References to Kant’s writings are cited according to the volume and page
number of the Academy Edition (Kants gesammelte Schriften).
A Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View
CPR Critique of Pure Reason [1781 cited as A/1787 cited as B]
CPrR Critique of Practical Reason
LE Lectures on Ethics
G Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals
MM The Metaphysics of Morals
NF Notes and Fragments
R Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason

Schopenhauer
References to Schopenhauer’s writings are cited according to the follow-
ing abbreviations and the page number of the editions listed in the
bibliography.

BM On the Basis of Morals


MR Manuscript Remains in Four Volumes
PP (I & II) Parerga and Paralipomena
WWR (I & II) The World as Will and Representation

xiii
xiv Abbreviations

Nietzsche
References to Nietzsche’s works are cited by abbreviation, chapter (when
applicable) and section number. For the sake of brevity, the chapter might
be identified only by a key word (for instance, Clever instead of Why I Am
so Clever). Nietzsche’s posthumous fragments are cited by year, group,
and fragment number according to the standard Colli and Montinari
edition. Nietzsche’s letters are quoted using the symbol # plus the stan-
dard reference number of the letter.

A The Anti-Christ
BGE Beyond Good and Evil
BT The Birth of Tragedy
EH Ecce Homo
GM On the Genealogy of Morality
GS The Gay Science
HH Human, All Too Human
HL On the Use and Disadvantage of History for Life
L Letters
NW Nietzsche contra Wagner
PF Posthumous Fragments
SE Schopenhauer as Educator
TI Twilight of the Idols
WS The Wanderer and His Shadow
Z Thus Spoke Zarathustra

Wittgenstein
Quotes from the Tractatus are cited by reference to the number of the
section. Quotes from the Notebooks and the Geheime Tagebücher are cited
by reference to the day of the entry.

CV Culture and Value


GT Geheime Tagebücher. 1914–1916
LE Lecture on Ethics
NB Notebooks. 1914–1916
TLP Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus
1
Introduction: Bringing Kant,
Schopenhauer, Nietzsche,
and Wittgenstein Together

In Ancient Greece death was seen as an exit door that led “from here to
yonder”, as Socrates puts in Plato’s Phaedo (117c/Plato 1997), that is,
from life on earth to the afterlife. One of the key philosophical questions
concerning death was whether man had the right to open the door. In an
earlier passage from the same dialogue, Socrates explains to Cebes that
“we men are in a kind of prison, and that one must not free oneself or run
away” (Phaedo, 62b)—at least, not “before a god has indicated some
necessity to do so” (Phaedo, 62c). Some centuries afterwards Epictetus,
the Stoic philosopher, expressed a different opinion. Life should be pre-
served as long as it is beneficial, but if it becomes unbearable, one can give
it up. As he writes in a well-known passage from the Discourses, “[h]as
some one made a smoke in the house? If he has made a moderate amount
of smoke I shall stay; if too much, I go outside. For one ought to remem-
ber and hold fast to this, that the door stands open” (Discourses I, XXV,
18/Epictetus 1956).
Since antiquity, the arguments put forward by philosophers have
become more solid and sophisticated. Nevertheless, the main question to
be answered remains the same: do we have a right to voluntarily put an
end to our life? This question can be essentially declined in two different,

© The Author(s) 2020 1


P. Stellino, Philosophical Perspectives on Suicide,
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-53937-5_1
2 P. Stellino

but strictly related, questions: (1) is suicide morally permitted? and (2)
can suicide be considered (at least in certain situations) a rational act? An
analytic approach to this question is typical of recent, contemporary phi-
losophy of suicide, which is now treated as an independent branch of
philosophy. With few exceptions (like St. Thomas Aquinas and Hume),
past philosophers have considered the question of the morality and/or
rationality of suicide in a rather fragmentary way, so that their arguments
in favour or against suicide, often to be found in detached passages of
different works, must be pieced together in order to get a general view. As
will be shown, this is precisely the case with the four philosophers consid-
ered in this book.
Nowadays, there are several valuable studies that offer an overview of
the several philosophical (and religious) arguments that can be put for-
ward in support or against one’s right to commit suicide. The works of
Cosculluela (1995), Battin (1996), Wittwer (2003), and Cholbi (2011)
are good examples of this. The scope of these studies is often introduc-
tory. This means that, in presenting the several arguments pro and con
they gain in comprehensiveness, but inevitably lack in depth.1 The aim of
this book is to address some of the same questions that these studies
address. To this end, however, a different approach is followed. Attention
is focused on four modern perspectives, which can be considered as rep-
resenting or illustrating four different views of suicide. Putting forward
seven different arguments against suicide and defending a strict prohibi-
tion of this act, Kant is a representative of the anti-libertarian view.
Schopenhauer also essentially opposes suicide, but he does it as a conse-
quence of his metaphysical view of the world, which is thoroughly pes-
simistic. His stance exemplarily shows that a pessimistic worldview does
not necessarily go hand in hand with a pro-attitude towards suicide.
Contrary to Kant, Nietzsche is rather favourable to voluntary death, at
least in certain specific situations. His stance, reminiscent of the Stoics’,
can be thus considered as representative of the libertarian view. Finally,
Wittgenstein considers suicide from the standpoint of his mystical–reli-
gious worldview, conceiving it as the elementary sin. Addressing these

1
Due to its length, Wittwer’s study combines, to a certain extent, comprehensiveness and depth.
1 Introduction: Bringing Kant, Schopenhauer, Nietzsche… 3

different but, as will be shown, complementary positions, this book pro-


vides an unusual way of understanding the phenomenon of suicide in an
integrated way. The book of course does not pretend to have an exhaus-
tive character on the immense topic it touches upon, but what it lacks in
comprehensiveness it gains in depth.
The reason to consider Kant’s, Schopenhauer’s, Nietzsche’s, and
Wittgenstein’s views of suicide in the same book also derives from the fact
that, as mentioned in the Preface, there is a fil rouge that links these views
together. In the Appendix to the first volume of the World as Will and
Representation, Schopenhauer clearly acknowledges that “however differ-
ent the content of my line of reasoning is from that of Kant, it has clearly
been very heavily influenced by Kantian ideas, it necessarily presupposes
them, and takes them as its point of departure” (WWR I: 443/
Schopenhauer 2010). When it comes to morality and its grounding,
however, Schopenhauer’s view is “diametrically opposed to Kant’s in its
essential points” (BM: 122/Schopenhauer 2009). This can be clearly seen
in Schopenhauer’s negative evaluation of Kant’s view of suicide.
Schopenhauer is very critical of the way in which Kant approaches sui-
cide and several pages of his prize essay On the Basis of Morals are devoted
to criticizing some of the arguments put forward by the latter.
Nietzsche’s relation to Schopenhauer recalls, to a certain extent,
Schopenhauer’s relation to Kant. Nietzsche was deeply influenced by
Schopenhauer (“my great teacher”, he called him in the Preface to the
Genealogy of Morality; GM, Preface, 5/Nietzsche 2006) and this influence
is not limited to the former’s early philosophy, as is often believed. At the
same time, however, Nietzsche was a profound critic of Schopenhauer’s
life-denying philosophy. Thus Nietzsche partly elaborates his view of sui-
cide in opposition to his teacher’s, and, more in general, to pessimistic
attitudes to life. Indeed, due to the influence of Schopenhauer’s thought,
pessimistic philosophies were à la mode in the second half of the nine-
teenth century and Nietzsche knew them well. Furthermore, as men-
tioned, Nietzsche’s view is also antithetical to Kant’s—although this
antithesis is not the result of Nietzsche’s direct confrontation with Kant’s
arguments against suicide, but it rather depends on Nietzsche’s more gen-
eral critique of his moral theory.
If Schopenhauer criticizes Kant’s view of suicide, and if Nietzsche
opposes Schopenhauer’s (directly) and Kant’s (indirectly) approaches to
4 P. Stellino

suicide, Wittgenstein’s most important remarks on suicide date from the


early period, that is, at a time when his philosophy was strongly influ-
enced by Schopenhauer’s metaphysics (which takes Kant’s transcendental
idealism as starting point, as mentioned). Given that Schopenhauer
exerted a major influence on the early Wittgenstein’s understanding of
the world and of ethics, it is not surprising to see that this influence also
extends to the latter’s view of suicide. In passing, it should be also men-
tioned that although it is not possible to know whether Wittgenstein was
familiar with Nietzsche’s remarks on suicide, it is a fact that in 1914
Wittgenstein bought the eighth volume of Nietzsches Werke (GT 8.12.14/
Wittgenstein 1992), which contained several texts from 1888.
Wittgenstein was most interested in Nietzsche’s The Anti-Christ. In his
Wittgenstein biography, Ray Monk comments on Wittgenstein’s interest
in Nietzsche as follows: “More stimulating was a writer whose view could
not have been more antithetical to the Tolstoyan Christianity that
Wittgenstein had come to embrace: Friedrich Nietzsche” (Monk 1991:
121). In reality, Wittgenstein’s interest in Nietzsche can be easily
explained. Indeed, although it is true that The Anti-Christ was a virulent
attack upon the Christian religion and that Wittgenstein was “deeply
affected” by Nietzsche’s hostility against Christianity (GT 8.12.14),
Nietzsche’s work was strongly influenced by Tolstoy’s view of Christianity
(Llinares Chover 2010). As will be shown, precisely this view contributed
to an important extent to shape Wittgenstein’s view of suicide.
As one can see, there is a clear connection between Kant’s,
Schopenhauer’s, Nietzsche’s, and Wittgenstein’s views of suicide. This
connection, however, does not constitute the only reason for this book.
Another reason is that, with the exception of Kant, the other three phi-
losophers considered here are often ignored in the field of philosophy of
suicide. This lack of attention seems to be motivated by reasons that are
different in each case. Schopenhauer’s opposition to suicide may be
regarded as unappealing since it presupposes his peculiar and, by now,
outdated metaphysics of the will. However, Schopenhauer is among the
philosophers who gave most importance to the topic of suicide (like
Hume, he dedicated a specific essay to suicide) and in his writings one
can find interesting considerations of various nature on this subject.
These considerations go far beyond his argument for the futility of
1 Introduction: Bringing Kant, Schopenhauer, Nietzsche… 5

suicide based on metaphysical grounds and Schopenhauer’s approach to


suicide is highly worthy of attention for the broadness of its scope and for
being ahead of his time, among other reasons. One of the aims of this
book is thus to revaluate Schopenhauer’s view of suicide and bring it to
the attention of contemporary scholars.
In the field of philosophy of suicide Nietzsche has received even less
attention than Schopenhauer. This may come as a surprise if one consid-
ers that his published writings contain several remarks on suicide and
that a speech from the first part of Thus Spoke Zarathustra is significantly
entitled On Free Death. This lack of attention can be differently accounted
for. One reason might be the fragmentary and unsystematic character of
Nietzsche’s approach to suicide. Another reason might be the strong rhe-
torical component of the texts in which he presents his view. As will be
shown, however, although Nietzsche tends to appeal to emotions instead
of defending his position with proper arguments, he nonetheless gives his
readers reasons that support his argumentation, and these reasons can be
scrutinized and examined just in the same way as Kant’s, Schopenhauer’s,
and Wittgenstein’s arguments can be. A third reason that might explain
why Nietzsche’s view of suicide is often ignored in secondary literature on
philosophy of suicide is the fact that, along with the notion of free death,
he also defends a quick death for all those who cling to life out of cow-
ardice and fear, and refuse to take a timely leave from it. Without denying
that considered from a contemporary perspective this latter notion
appears unsettling, one should resist here the temptation of decontextual-
izing Nietzsche’s words and reading them through the distorting prism of
our historical perspective. In any case, the notions of free and quick death
can and should be kept separated, so as to judge Nietzsche’s arguments in
favour of voluntary death without any bias.
Of the four philosophers considered in this study, Wittgenstein is the
one who has received less attention in the field of philosophy of suicide.
To my knowledge, the only in-depth study on Wittgenstein’s view of
suicide is the very recent paper by Gómez Alonso (2018) which, however,
mainly (although not uniquely) focuses the attention on the relation
between Wittgenstein’s early view of suicide and Schopenhauer’s meta-
physics of the will. This lack of attention may be explained by the fact
that Wittgenstein’s remarks on suicide are very few in number and that in
6 P. Stellino

order to grasp their meaning it is necessary to understand some of the


very complex and difficult notions that he introduces in his Tractatus
Logico-Philosophicus. Once this difficult step is overcome, however,
Wittgenstein’s view of suicide appears very insightful and directly linked
to some of the most profound thinkers of the nineteenth century such as
Tolstoy, Dostoevsky, Kierkegaard, and James, among others.
Unlike Schopenhauer’s, Nietzsche’s, and Wittgenstein’s views of sui-
cide, Kant’s view has been the subject of countless studies—as the
extended bibliography of the second chapter of this book clearly shows.
This should not be surprising, given that Kant’s moral theory has exerted
and continues to exert such an extraordinary influence on contemporary
bioethics and applied ethics. Even in this case, however, some clarifica-
tions are needed. First, although there are several informative studies on
Kant’s view of suicide, to my knowledge, there is no comprehensive study
in English on this subject. The only paper that presents an overview of
Kant’s several arguments against suicide is Wittwer’s (2001). However,
this paper is almost twenty years old (although the analysis developed in
it is still compelling) and is written in German, being therefore not easily
accessible to the anglophone audience. Second, existing literature usually
tends to focus the attention on Kant’s arguments from the published
writings, ignoring the arguments put forward in the Lectures on Ethics.
Almost no attention has been paid, for instance, to Kant’s freedom argu-
ment in the Collins lectures (see Sect. 2.2.3), according to which suicide
would imply a self-contradiction of freedom. This is very surprising, con-
sidering that a similar line of argumentation is sometimes advanced
within the context of the contemporary debate on assisted suicide. The
aim of the first chapter of this book is thus to provide a comprehensive
study of Kant’s view of suicide and an in-depth examination of all his
arguments against suicide. Third and finally, recent literature in English
on this subject tends to question the conventional reading of Kant as a
philosopher who categorically prohibits suicide. Some scholars even
argue that, in certain situations, Kant’s moral philosophy can be read as
justifying not only a right, but even a duty to suicide. As I will show in
the following chapter, these readings are often based on misunderstand-
ings deriving either from incomplete information or from a lack of philo-
logical accuracy.
1 Introduction: Bringing Kant, Schopenhauer, Nietzsche… 7

The methodology followed in this study primarily consists in a close


and attentive reading of the primary sources (published writings, Nachlass,
lectures, diaries, and letters). When necessary, attention is given to the
German original. The main aim is to provide a complete overview of
Kant’s, Schopenhauer’s, Nietzsche’s, and Wittgenstein’s views of suicide.
As far as possible, each stance is presented as a unitary whole. On the
other hand, however, chronological differences are taken into account.
Kant’s arguments from the Collins lectures (pre-critical period), for
instance, are distinguished from the arguments that can be found in the
published writings. At the same time, correspondences between the for-
mer and the latter are nevertheless emphasized. With the help of the rel-
evant bibliography on the subject, the arguments in favour of or against
suicide put forward by the four philosophers considered in this study are
explained, contextualized (when necessary), examined, and critically
assessed. The approach of this book is thus not so much historical as
philosophical in nature.
This book is constituted of four main chapters and a conclusion. To
each philosopher’s view of suicide is devoted one, single chapter. The fol-
lowing is a brief overview of the content of each chapter. Chapter 2 pro-
vides an in-depth examination of Kant’s arguments against suicide. After
a contextualization of Kant’s prohibition of suicide (§2.1), following
Wittwer (2001), I identify seven different arguments against the moral
permissibility of suicide: three from the Lectures on Ethics (§2.2) and four
from the published writings (§2.3). For each of them, I present the argu-
ment (and possible variations), point out strengths and flaws, and discuss
possible objections and counter-objections, taking into consideration the
abundant bibliography on the subject. I conclude that, against a recent
trend in secondary literature, which tends to read Kant as justifying not
only a right, but even a duty to suicide, Kant does not allow for any
exception to his strict prohibition of suicide.
Chapter 3 provides a full and complete analysis of Schopenhauer’s
view of suicide. Drawing on the limited secondary literature on this sub-
ject (essentially, Fox (1980), Birnbacher (1985), Jacquette (1999, 2000),
and Janaway (2017)), I first focus on Schopenhauer’s dismissal of previ-
ous religious and philosophical arguments against this act, giving particu-
lar attention to his critique of Kant’s arguments (§3.1). Subsequently, I
8 P. Stellino

briefly review the main points of his metaphysical worldview. Particular


attention is given to Schopenhauer’s gloomy understanding of human
condition and to his conception of death (§3.2). Having sketched the
main features of what is commonly known as Schopenhauer’s pessimism,
I finally examine Schopenhauer’s own argument for the futility of suicide
as well as his position on asceticism and on voluntary death by starva-
tion (§3.3).
In Chap. 4 I turn my attention to Nietzsche. Given his unsystematic
approach to suicide, I piece together his remarks and observations on the
subject in order to get a unitary picture. What is characteristic of
Nietzsche’s view of suicide is that he approaches this topic from two dif-
ferent, but interrelated points of view. On the one hand, he considers the
question of whether, in certain specific situations, voluntary death can be
a fully rational and natural choice. Within this context, he defends the
idea of a free death at the right time. On the other hand, Nietzsche con-
siders suicide from what might be defined as a proto-existentialist stand-
point: the problem is to judge whether life is or is not worth living in a
world devoid of meaning and purpose. Given the difference between the
two approaches, I consider them separately. Thus, after a brief introduc-
tion in which I contextualize Nietzsche’s view of suicide, I first consider
his arguments in favour of the rationality of voluntary death (§4.1).
Subsequently, I turn my attention to the notion of “free death”, focusing
particularly on some puzzling aspects that we are faced with when con-
sidering Nietzsche’s view of suicide. I also contrast Nietzsche’s free death
with his polemic notion of “quick death” (§4.2). Finally, I consider how
Nietzsche deals with the aforementioned question of whether life is worth
living in a world devoid of meaning and purpose. Following a chrono-
logical order (early, middle, and late Nietzsche) and giving special atten-
tion to previous literature (essentially Young 2003 and Loeb 2008), I
conclude that Nietzsche’s answer to this question is affirmative (§4.3).
Chapter 5 is devoted to Wittgenstein’s view of suicide. Attention is
focused on the early period. This choice is motivated by two main rea-
sons: first, Wittgenstein’s most interesting remarks on suicide date from
this period, and second, suicide was an intensely personal matter and a
relatively recurrent thought for the young Wittgenstein. After an intro-
duction in which I show how Wittgenstein’s early life was affected by
1 Introduction: Bringing Kant, Schopenhauer, Nietzsche… 9

several suicides and how he himself often thought of this possibility, I


first consider some of the important sources that influenced and shaped
his view of suicide (§5.1). Subsequently, in order to contextualize his
otherwise obscure remarks on suicide, I offer an overview of Wittgenstein’s
peculiar worldview, as it is presented in the Tractatus, as well as of his
understanding of ethics (§5.2). Finally, in the third and last section, I
turn the attention to Wittgenstein’s remarks on suicide, explaining their
meaning and elucidating Wittgenstein’s peculiar view of suicide (§5.3).
In Chap. 6, I present the most important conclusions that can be
drawn when Kant, Schopenhauer, Nietzsche, and Wittgenstein are put
into dialogue with each other. What do these philosophers have to say
about suicide? What can we still learn from them? Here I address these
questions, pointing out limits and merits of the four approaches consid-
ered in this book.

References
Battin, M. P. (1996). The Death Debate. Ethical Issues in Suicide. Englewood
Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Birnbacher, D. (1985). “Schopenhauer und das ethische Problem des
Selbstmords”, Schopenhauer-Jahrbuch, 66: 115–129.
Cholbi, M. J. (2011). Suicide. The Philosophical Dimension. Peterborough, ON:
Broadview Press.
Cosculluela, V. (1995). The Ethics of Suicide. New York/London: Garland
Publishing.
Epictetus. (1956). The Discourses as Reported by Arrian, the Manual, and
Fragments (Vol. 1). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press; London:
Heinemann (Loeb Classical Library).
Fox, M. (1980). “Schopenhauer on Death, Suicide and Self-Renunciation”, in:
id. (ed.), Schopenhauer: His Philosophical Achievement. Brighton:
Harvester Press.
Gómez Alonso, M. (2018). “Wittgenstein, Schopenhauer and the Metaphysics
of Suicide”, Revista de Filosofia Aurora, 30 (49): 299–321.
Jacquette, D. (1999). “Schopenhauer on Death”, in: C. Janaway (ed.), The
Cambridge Companion to Schopenhauer. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 293–317.
10 P. Stellino

Jacquette, D. (2000). “Schopenhauer on the Ethics of Suicide”, Continental


Philosophy Review, 33: 43–58.
Janaway, C. (2017). “Schopenhauer’s Consoling View of Death”, IFCoLog
Journal of Logics and their Applications, 4 (11): 3705–3718.
Llinares Chover, J. B. (2010). “The Early Wittgenstein, Tolstoy’s Kurze Darlegung
des Evangelium and Nietzsche’s Der Antichrist”, in: L. Perissinotto, V. Sanfélix
(eds.), Doubt, Ethics and Religion. Wittgenstein and the Counter-Enlightenment.
Frankfurt a. M.: Ontos Verlag, 105–128.
Loeb, P. S. (2008). “Suicide, Meaning, and Redemption”, in: M. Dries (ed.),
Nietzsche on Time and History. Berlin/New York: de Gruyter, 163–190.
Monk, R. (1991). Ludwig Wittgenstein. The Duty of Genius. London:
Vintage Books.
Nietzsche, F. (2006). On the Genealogy of Morality. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Plato. (1997). Complete Works. Indianapolis/Cambridge: Hackett
Publishing Company.
Schopenhauer, A. (2009). The Two Fundamental Problems of Ethics. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Schopenhauer, A. (2010). The World as Will and Representation (Vol. I).
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Wittgenstein, L. (1992). Geheime Tagebücher. 1914–1916. Vienna: Turia & Kant.
Wittwer, H. (2001). “Über Kants Verbot der Selbsttötung”, Kant-Studien,
92: 180–209.
Wittwer, H. (2003). Selbsttötung als philosophisches Problem. Paderborn: Mentis.
Young, J. (2003). The Death of God and the Meaning of Life. London/New York:
Routledge.
2
Immanuel Kant: The Moral Duty
of Self-­Preservation

2.1  ontextualizing Kant’s Prohibition


C
of Suicide
According to Margaret P. Battin, underlying the 2000-year-old theoretical
debate about how we die and which should be the individual’s role in his or
her death is the Stoic/Christian divide: “whether one’s role should be as far
as possible active, self-assertive, and responsible and may include ending
one’s own life—or, on the other hand, acceptant, obedient, and passive in
the sense of being patient, where ‘allowing to die’ is the most active step that
should be taken” (Battin 2005: 6). Despite his willingness to recognize that
there seems to be something moral in the Stoic attitude to suicide and that
sometimes suicide is a mark of great heroism, Kant follows the Christian
tradition in his consideration of self-preservation as “the first, though not the
principal, duty of man to himself” (MM, 6/Kant 1991: 421).
In recent times, several studies have questioned the conventional read-
ing of Kant as a philosopher who categorically prohibits suicide.1 This has

1
See Cosculluela (1995: 39), James (1999), Cholbi (2000, 2010, 2015), Brassington (2006),
Cooley (2006, 2007a, 2013, 2015), Rhodes (2007), and Harter (2011). See also Gregor (1963:

© The Author(s) 2020 11


P. Stellino, Philosophical Perspectives on Suicide,
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-53937-5_2
12 P. Stellino

led Michael Cholbi (2015: 607) to claim that, “thanks to recent scholar-
ship, Kant is no longer seen as the dogmatic opponent of suicide that he
appears to be at first glance.” Scholars have argued that, in certain situa-
tions, Kant’s moral philosophy can be read as justifying not only a right
but even a duty to suicide. Dennis R. Cooley (2007a, 2007b, and 2015),
for instance, defends a Kantian moral duty for the soon-to-be demented
to commit suicide. Other scholars focus attention on the casuistical ques-
tions presented in the Metaphysics of Morals (MM, 6: 423f.), arguing that
some of them seem to permit suicide.2
One may wonder why, if Kant thought that in some occasions suicide
could be permitted or even be considered as obligatory, he is reported to
have said that suicide is not permitted “under any condition” (LE, Collins
27/1997: 372) and “under any circumstances” (LE, Vigilantius 27: 603).
That Kant was unsympathetic to suicide is also shown by his cold and
almost indifferent reply to Maria von Herbert, an Austrian woman and a
student of his philosophy who, on the verge of suicide, wrote to him ask-
ing for his help and advice. Von Herbert was desperate because of a
heartbreak and sought comfort in Kant’s philosophy but could not find
it. As a result, in August 1791 she wrote to Kant asking for help, for com-
fort or for counsel to prepare her for death. Kant answered in spring 1792
but was unable to relieve the young woman’s grief. Von Herbert wrote
again in January 1793 but Kant never replied. Eventually, the woman
took her life in 1803.3
To this, one must add that Kant’s views of suicide are very derogatory.
In the Lectures on Ethics, suicide is described as “the most abominable of
the crimes that inspire horror and hatred [das abscheulichste Laster des
Grausens und des Haßens]” (LE, Collins 27: 347) and as “the most dread-
ful thing [das schrecklichste] that a man can do to himself ” (LE, Collins
27: 391). By committing it, the human being “puts himself below the

135–136) and Battin (1996: 108–112). On the other hand, for a reading of Kant as opposing
suicide in all circumstances, see de Vleeschauwer (1966), Brandt (1975), Wittwer (2001), Unna
(2003), and Schüssler (2012). Hill (1991: 85) ascribes to Kant a “rigoristic opposition to suicide.”
He nonetheless finds Kant’s position untenable and claims that “the spirit of his idea of humanity
as an end in itself […] leads to a more tenable position.”
2
See, particularly, James (1999).
3
On this, see Langton (1992).
2 Immanuel Kant: The Moral Duty of Self-Preservation 13

beast” (LE, Collins 27: 372) and “makes himself into a monster” (A, 7:
259). How can these categorical and harsh claims be reconciled with the
reading according to which “Kant does implicitly and explicitly allow
exceptions to the general rule” (Cooley 2007a: 38)?
In reality, some of the interpretations that defend the view according
to which Kant would have allowed exceptions to his categorical prohibi-
tion of suicide are based on misunderstandings deriving either from
incomplete information or from a lack of philological accuracy. Kant’s
consideration of Cato’s suicide is, in this sense, paradigmatic.4 In the
Lectures on Ethics, Kant introduces Cato’s suicide by claiming that “sui-
cide can also come to have a plausible aspect [scheinbare Seite], whenever,
that is, the continuance of life rests upon such circumstances as may
deprive that life of its value; when a man can no longer live in accordance
with virtue and prudence, and must therefore put an end to his life from
honourable motives” (LE, Collins 27: 370). Cato had only two options
available to him: either to fall into Caesar’s hands—something which he
considered dishonourable—or to take his life and preserve his honour. As
Kant puts it, “he viewed his death as a necessity; his thought was: Since
you can no longer live as Cato, you cannot go on living at all” (LE,
Collins 27: 370f.).
According to Kant, Cato’s suicide constitutes “the one example [das
einzige Beyspiel] that has given the world an opportunity of defending
suicide” (LE, Collins 27: 371). Scholars often refer to this passage to
show that Kant’s attitude towards suicide is not as dogmatic as it prima
facie appears to be.5 Surprisingly, the same scholars have failed to remark
that later in the same lecture Kant again discusses Cato’s suicide. If on the
one hand Kant claims that Cato’s suicide was a mark of heroism and
courage, he also adds, on the other, that “if Cato, under all the tortures
that Caesar might have inflicted on him, had still adhered to his resolve
with steadfast mind, that would have been noble; but not when he laid
hands upon himself. Those who defend and teach the legitimacy of

4
Cato the Younger or “Uticensis” (95–46 BC) was a Roman statesman and Stoic, known for his
moral integrity. He was one of the defeated of the Great Roman Civil War (49–45 BC). Unwilling
to live in a world governed by Caesar, whom he considered a tyrant, Cato decided to commit sui-
cide, thus becoming a symbol of virtue.
5
See Battin (2006: 107), Cooley (2006: 333, 336; 2007a: 38; 2013: 367), and Harter (2011).
14 P. Stellino

suicide inevitably do great harm in a republic”6 (LE, Collins 27: 374). As


Yvonne Unna (2003: 464) points out, “Kant’s reasoning suggests that it
is one thing to sympathize with a person’s wish to die an honorable death,
yet another to justify the act of suicide. A violation of honor does not
justify ‘self-murder’.”
Another source of misunderstanding stems from the five casuistical
questions that follow the section dedicated to suicide in the Metaphysics
of Morals7 (MM, 6: 423f.). Given the fact that Kant poses the questions
but does not provide an answer (at least, not in the Metaphysics of Morals),
scholars have often taken the casuistical questions either to be open and
unanswered, or even to permit suicide in some cases. So, for instance,
both Battin (1996: 110) and James (1999: 49, 52) claim that Kant seems
to consider Curtius’ suicide as morally justifiable. Yet, Vigilantius reports
Kant as saying that “it can never be allowable for me deliberately to yield
up my life, or to kill myself in fulfilment of a duty to others; for example,
when Curtius plunges into the chasm, in order to preserve the Roman
people, he is acting contrary to duty” (LE, Vigilantius 27: 629).
In 2003, Yvonne Unna published a very detailed and compelling study
of Kant’s casuistical questions in the Kant-Studien. Unna’s purpose was to
put to rest any possible speculation about how Kant would have answered
these questions by showing that Kant had actually answered or suggested
an answer to four of the five casuistical questions of the Metaphysics of
Morals elsewhere—more precisely, in the Anthropology, in the Vigilantius
lectures, and in the Nachlaß. Unna’s conclusion was that “all of Kant’s
replies confirm that he categorically rejects suicide as immoral”8 (Unna
2003: 454). It is unfortunate to observe that Unna’s paper has been often
ignored by later studies on Kant’s view of suicide. For instance, Cooley
claimed on various occasions that Kant seems to consider the suicide of

6
On this, see Seidler (1983 : 446).
7
The first three questions refer to the following historical figures: Curtius (hurling oneself to certain
death to save one’s country), Seneca (killing oneself to preserve one’s honour), and Frederick the
Great (carrying lethal poison in war to be able to commit suicide rather than be captured and
forced to agree to conditions that would prove harmful to the state). The fourth question is about
a man bitten by a mad dog, who prefers to take his life rather than cause harm to others. The fifth
and final question concerns the moral permissibility of smallpox inoculation, which at that time
could cause death.
8
See also Schüssler (2012: 77–81).
2 Immanuel Kant: The Moral Duty of Self-Preservation 15

the man bitten by the rabid dog (MM, 6: 423f.) not only morally permis-
sible but also morally obligatory.9 This cannot be the case, for as Unna
(2003: 461f.) rightly points out, Kant dismisses this possibility in a pas-
sage from the Lectures on Ethics.10 It is, therefore, not true that “Kant the
casuist was more conciliatory than Kant the doctrinarian”11 (De
Vleeschauwer 1966: 254) nor that “many ‘casuistical questions’ remain”12
(Cholbi 2000: 172).
As this brief analysis shows, there has been some misunderstanding on
Kant’s attitude towards suicide in past years due to partial reading of
Kant’s writings, lectures, and Nachlaß, incomplete information on exist-
ing bibliography, and lack of philological accuracy in reading the texts,
among other factors. Needless to say, this does not mean that all studies
that aim to refute Kant’s alleged rigorism are based on false premises or
lack philological accuracy. On the contrary, there exist plausible interpre-
tations that point to concrete difficulties in Kant’s view of suicide. One of
these difficulties particularly concerns the fact that some of the examples
chosen by Kant to strengthen his argumentation are in reality ad hoc
examples. Another problem concerning Kant’s stance on suicide is linked
to the intricate relation between suicide and concepts such as dignity and

9
See Cooley (2006: 333; 2007a: 38–39; 2013: 367; 2015: 284). In his reply to Cooley’s paper
(2007a) on a Kantian moral duty for the soon-to-be demented to commit suicide, Stephen
R. Latham (2007: 50) draws the attention to Unna’s paper. Apparently, this reference has gone
unobserved by Cooley.
10
See LE, Vigilantius 27: 603: “To destroy oneself, therefore, through an act voluntarily under-
taken by the sensory being, can never be permitted, so that a suicide (autocheiria) can never, under
any circumstances, be regarded as allowable. Suppose, if you will, such cases as that of a slave, for
example, who should lose his life in consequence of an attempted but abortive bid for freedom; or
that one bitten by a mad dog should feel quite plainly the effects of madness; can either of them
take his own life? The first considers a life of slavery to be no such life as is suited to humanity; the
second foresees his own death, and the possibility, likewise, of harming others through his urge to
bite. Nevertheless, they both frustrate all attempts whereby they might be freed from their unhappy
condition and are preserved from harm, e.g., by having themselves tied up at the appropriate time;
quite recently a remedy for the mad dog’s bite has been found, in administering oil to the victim
internally, and trying to anoint him completely on the outside.”
11
As a general rule, I have personally translated all citations in languages other than English.
12
I acknowledge my mistake in Stellino (2015: 98, n. 48; due to an unfortunate misunderstanding
with the publisher, this article was not published in its final and revised version). According to
Schmidt and Schönecker (2017: 164–165), “The crucial point of [Kant’s] casuistry is not the ques-
tion whether there are exceptions to the rule, that is, whether suicide ‘in specific cases’ can be per-
mitted, but rather whether concrete cases of self-disembodiment [Selbstentleibung] entail self-murder
[Selbstmord].”
16 P. Stellino

autonomy—concepts that play a pivotal role in Kant’s philosophy as well


as in contemporary bioethics. I will address these issues later in this chap-
ter. For now, I will present Kant’s arguments for the immorality of suicide
and consider some of the critiques that have been addressed or can be
addressed to them.
Before I proceed with the analysis of Kant’s arguments, however, I
must draw attention to a fundamental distinction between Kant’s ethics
and Kantian ethics. Following Allen W. Wood (2008: 1), we can say that
Kant’s ethics is “the theory Kant himself put forward,” whereas Kantian
ethics is “an ethical theory formulated in the basic spirit of Kant.” When
considering Kant’s attitude towards suicide, it is essential to distinguish
between what Kant actually said and what one could say without betray-
ing the spirit of his philosophy. There is a non-negligible difference
between claiming that in certain occasions Kant seems to justify a right
or a duty to suicide, and claiming that on certain occasions a Kantian
right or duty to suicide seems to be justifiable. Thomas E. Hill (1991:
85), for instance, ascribes to Kant a “rigoristic opposition to suicide.” He
nonetheless finds Kant’s position untenable and defends a modified
Kantian view according to which “some suicides are justified and even
commendable” (id.: 95). In what follows, I will only focus attention on
Kant’s attitude to suicide, leaving aside the rather different question of
whether a Kantian right or duty to suicide might be, on certain occa-
sions, justifiable.
With this distinction in mind, we can now consider Kant’s several
arguments for the impermissibility of suicide. As Seidler (1983: 440)
points out, the topic of suicide “is virtually absent in Kant’s pre-critical
works, but it began to occupy him seriously in the mid-1770s and
received explicit treatment in all major ethical writings thereafter.” The
relevant passages, though not the only ones, can be found in the
Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, the Critique of Practical Reason,
the Metaphysics of Morals, the lectures recorded by Collins and Vigilantius,
and the Nachlaß.13 The German word that Kant uses to refer to the act of

13
See G, 4: 421–422, 429; CPrR, 5: 44; MM, 6: 422–424; LE, 27: 190–192, 208–210, 342–347,
369–378, 601–603, 627–630; NF 6801, 19: 165–166. See also § 77 of the Anthropology from a
Pragmatic Point of View (7: 258–259).
Another random document with
no related content on Scribd:
The words were still on her lips when a door opened behind them
somewhere in the dark, cool hall, and Mabin started guiltily. She and
Langford were standing just within the front doorway, out of hearing
of any one in the house. But she forgot that she could not be heard,
and felt confused and shy when a man’s voice, very low, very gentle,
said:
“Langford, is that Miss Rose?”
“Yes, sir,” said Langford, as Mabin’s eyes at last saw which door it
as that was open, and the servant passed her toward the drawing-
room.
“I will see her if she wants to speak to me,” were his next, most
unexpected words.
Mabin entered the drawing-room, and found herself face to face
with the mysterious Mr. Banks.
He was standing in the middle of the long room, and as the young
lady came in he held out his hand to her and offered her a seat. His
hand was cold, his face looked more worn, more gray than ever, and
as he moved he tottered, like a man recovering from an illness, or on
the verge of one. But Mabin thought, as she looked at him, that her
fancy that he must be insane was a mistaken one. It seemed to her
now that there was the imprint of a great grief, an ever-present
burden of melancholy, upon the grave stranger, but that his
straightforward, clear eyes were the sanest she had ever seen.
“You wish to speak to me? To ask me some questions, I
suppose?” he said courteously, as he leaned against the
mantelpiece and bent his head to listen.
“Yes.”
Then there was a pause. It was rather a delicate matter to accuse
this grave, courteous gentleman of a burglarious entry into another
person’s house. Mabin had not felt the full force of this difficulty until
now when she sat, breathing quickly, and wondering how to begin,
while Mr. Banks still politely waited.
“I saw you just now in the garden,” she burst out at last, feeling
conscious that her voice sounded coarse and harsh after his quiet
tones, “and I recognized you. And I thought it was better to tell you
so, to tell you that I knew it was you who—who——”
How could she go on? She didn’t. She broke down altogether, and
sat looking at the gently stirring branches of the trees outside,
wishing that she were under the shelter of their cool freshness,
instead of going through this fiery ordeal indoors.
Then it suddenly became clear to her that Mr. Banks had been
seized with a new idea.
“I suppose then,” he said, and she was delighted to see that he
was at last beginning to feel some of the embarrassment which she
was suffering, “that you are the lady who followed me through the
drawing-room of ‘The Towers’ a fortnight ago?”
“Yes, yes.”
“Then I don’t know how to apologize to you. I don’t know what to
say to excuse myself. In fact, there is nothing for it but to confess
that ill health had made me a sleepwalker, and that this is not the
first time I have been put into very embarrassing situations by this
terribly unfortunate habit.”
Mabin frowned frankly. She was an honest, truthful girl, and this
man lost her respect the moment he began to tell her what she knew
to be falsehoods. Her indignation gave her courage. It was in a much
more assured tone that she went on:
“I know it is not the first time, because it happened the very night
before. But I know also that you were not asleep, because when you
saw that the person in the room was not the person you expected to
find there, you went away. Besides, I saw you when you had got out
into the garden,” added she quickly, “and you were quite wide-
awake. At first I thought you must be a burglar, and I was dreadfully
frightened; but when I saw you were not, I was more frightened still.
And do you think it is right to come into people’s houses like that at
night and frighten them into fainting fits?”
And Mabin, who had sprung off her chair in her excitement,
confronted him with quite an Amazonian air of defiance and
reproach.
She felt remorseful, however, almost before she came to the end
of her harangue. For he took her onslaught so meekly, so humbly,
that she was disarmed. When she had finished, he began to pace
quickly up and down the room.
“I know it’s wrong, I know it, I know it,” he repeated, as if to
himself. “I know I ought not to be here at all. I know I am exposing
myself and—and others” (his tone dropped into an indescribable
softness on the word) “to dangers, to misery, by my presence. And
yet I have not the strength of mind to go.”
He did not once turn his head to look at his visitor as he uttered
these words; indeed she thought, by the monotonous, almost
inaudible tones in which he spoke, walking hurriedly up and down,
with his eyes on the ground, that he did not even remember that he
was not alone. And when he had finished speaking, he still continued
his walk up and down, without so much as a glance in her direction,
until suddenly, when he had reached the end of the room where she
was sitting, he drew himself up and fixing his eyes upon her, asked
abruptly:
“Did she know? Did she guess? Did you tell her?”
Mabin had an impulse of amazing astuteness. She had come here
to find out why Mr. Banks made burglarious entry into “The Towers!”
Here was an opportunity of finding out the relations between him and
her friend.
“Tell whom?” said she, pretending not to understand.
“Lady Ma——”
He checked himself at once, and was silent.
“Do you mean Mrs. Dale?” said Mabin.
“Yes, I mean Mrs. Dale,” replied he impatiently.
“I didn’t tell her anything,” said Mabin. “I didn’t dare. And she
thought she dreamt she saw you the night before; but I know it must
have been you she saw.”
“She saw me!” cried Mr. Banks, with a sudden eagerness in his
voice, a yearning in his eyes, which kept Mabin dumb. Noticing at
once the effect his change of manner had on his listener, he checked
himself again, and turned his head away.
Still Mabin remained silent. In truth she was beginning to feel
alarmed by those glimpses into a story of passion and of sorrow
which were being flashed before her innocent young eyes. A blush
rose in her cheeks; she got up from her chair, and made a step
toward the door, feeling for the first time what a daring thing she had
done in making this visit.
“I—I think so. I must suppose so,” said she quickly. “And that was
why she changed her room.”
A look of deepest pain crossed the face of Mr. Banks. His brows
contracted, his lips quivered. Mabin, with the righteous indignation of
the very young against sins they cannot understand, felt that every
blow she struck, cruel though it might be, helped to remove a peril
from the path of her friend. With glowing cheeks and downcast eyes
she added:
“Why do you try to see her? If you cannot see her openly, why do
you try to see her at all? And when only to think she saw you in a
dream made her tremble and faint and lock the door.”
If she had looked up as she spoke, the words would have died
upon her lips. For the agony in his face had become pitiful to see.
For a few moments there was dead silence in the room. Although
she wanted to go, she felt that she could not leave him like this, and
she wanted to know whether her injunctions had had any effect. She
was startled by a hollow laugh, and looking up, she met the eyes of
Mr. Banks fixed upon her with an expression which seemed to make
her suddenly conscious how young and ignorant she was, and how
mad to suppose that she could have any influence upon the conduct
of older men and women.
“I ought not to have come,” she said with a hot blush in her
cheeks, “I am too ignorant and too stupid to do anything but harm
when I want to do some good to my friends. But please do not laugh
at me; I only spoke to you to try to save Mrs. Dale, whom I love, from
any more trouble.”
“Whom you love! Do you love her too?” said Mr. Banks, with the
same change to tenderness which she had noticed in his tone once
before. “Well, little one, then you have done your friend some good
after all; for I promise you I will not try to see her again.”
Mabin was filled with compunction. Mr. Banks did not talk like a
wicked man. She longed to put down his unconventional behavior to
eccentricity merely; but this was hard, very hard to do. At any rate
she had obtained from him a definite promise, and she tried to get
another.
“And—please don’t think me impertinent—but wouldn’t it be better
if you went away from here? You know there is always the risk of her
seeing you, while you live so near, or of finding out something about
you. Please don’t think me impertinent; but really, I think, after what I
have seen, that if she were to meet you suddenly, and know that she
was not dreaming, it would kill her.”
Again his face contracted with pain. Mabin, looking down, went on:
“Remember all she has to suffer. When that old woman—an old
lady with a hard face—came to see her, and scolded her——”
Mabin stopped. An exclamation on the part of Mr. Banks had
made her glance at him; and she was astonished to see, in the hard
look of anger which his features had assumed, a likeness, an
unmistakable likeness, to the “cat.”
“Oh!” cried the girl involuntarily.
“Go on with what you were saying,” said Mr. Banks sharply. “An
old lady came here, scolded her——”
“And poor Mrs. Dale was miserable. She did not want me to stay
with her; she said she was too wicked; she was more miserable than
I have ever seen any one before. I am so sorry for her; so sorry.”
She stopped. A strange expression, in which there was a gleam of
wistful hope, had come into Mr. Banks’ face. Mabin put out her hand
quickly:
“Good-by,” she said. “I think I am glad I came. I’m sure you are not
hard-hearted enough to make her any more unhappy than she is.”
But Mr. Banks, taking her hand, would not let it go, but walked with
her to the door.
“You will let me come with you—as far as the gate of the garden,”
he said quite humbly. “You are right to trust me. I love your ‘Mrs.
Dale,’ and would not do her any harm. But—it is difficult, very
difficult, to know what would be best, happiest, for her.”
They were in the hall by this time; and Mr. Banks, still holding the
girl’s hand very gently in his, had pushed open the door which led
into the garden. Instead of going out at once, he turned to look
earnestly in Mabin’s young fair face.
“I wish you were a little older,” he said at last; “then I could tell you
the whole story, and you could help me to find out the right thing to
do.”
“I am nineteen,” expostulated Mabin; “and, though he doesn’t
know it, papa often takes my advice.”
Mr. Banks smiled kindly.
“I have no doubt of it,” said he. “Nineteen is a great age. But not
quite great enough to bear the burden of such a pitiful story. Come.”
Reluctantly letting her hand drop, he followed her down the steps
into the garden, and Mabin, with all the interest of the visit in her
mind, could not repress her delight at finding herself once more in
the garden she loved so well. Mr. Banks watched her bright face, as
her eyes wandered from the smooth lawn to the borders full of
geraniums and pansies, rose-bushes and tall white lilies.
And when she found herself once more in the grass walk, she
could not repress an exclamation of pleasure.
“You are fond of your garden,” said he. “You must have found it
hard to give it up to a stranger!”
Mabin acknowledged the fact with a blush, and, encouraged by his
questions, told him some details about her own gardening, and her
own pet flowers. Chatting upon such matters as these, they soon
reached the side gate in the wall, and passing into the lane, came to
the plantation behind “The Towers.”
And suddenly to the consternation of Mabin, she heard two voices,
within the wood, which she recognized as those of Rudolph and Mrs.
Dale.
She turned quickly to Mr. Banks.
He stopped and held out his hand.
“I have not forgotten my promise,” said he; “I will leave you now
and—and I promise that I will not try to see her again.”
The next moment he had disappeared—only just in time. For as
the garden gate shut behind him, Mrs. Dale, with a white face and
wild eyes, broke through the trees and confronted Mabin.
“Who was that? Whose voice was that?” she asked in almost a
shriek.
Mabin sprang forward and put a caressing arm round her.
“He will never come near you again,” she whispered, feeling that
concealment of the identity of their neighbor with the supposed
phantom was no longer possible.
But, to her distress and amazement, Mrs. Dale’s face instantly
grew rigid with grief and despair, and she sank, trembling and
moaning, to the ground.
“I knew it! I was sure of it! Oh, my punishment is too great for me
to bear!” she whispered hoarsely.
CHAPTER XII.
A HORRIBLE SECRET.

Poor Mabin gazed down blankly at the crouching figure of Mrs.


Dale.
Were the complications of this mysterious history never to end.
The little lady had shown terror at the mere sight of this man’s
portrait; she had abandoned a room in which she had, as she
thought, only dreamt of him. And yet now, when Mabin tried to
reassure her by repeating his assurance that he would not force
himself upon her again, the inconsistent woman gave every sign of
the most profound sorrow.
Mabin looked, with her perplexity puckering her pretty face, at
Rudolph, who had emerged from the wood in his turn. He however,
was too deeply intent upon watching Mrs. Dale to notice his fiancée’s
expression, and Mabin felt a pang of jealousy, which she tried in vain
to stifle.
“Don’t talk to her,” said Rudolph presently, as Mrs. Dale struggling
with herself, and still white and trembling, got upon her feet. “Run
into the house, Mabin, and get some eau de Cologne, and—and
don’t go too fast, or you will get a headache.”
But Mabin, who felt hurt at this evident attempt to get rid of her,
lingered, and offered the help of her arm to her friend. But to her
astonishment and bitter annoyance, Mrs. Dale not only shrank from
her, but cast upon the young girl a look full of resentment.
“Pray, don’t take so much trouble. I am quite, quite well,” she said
coldly. “And I can walk alone, thank you.”
She had already withdrawn the arm Mabin had taken, and was
plunging into the plantation with reckless steps, as if anxious to bury
herself from observation. And she hastily put her handkerchief to her
eyes and dashed away the tears which rose as she spoke.
Mabin drew herself up, and choked down a rising sob. What had
she done that she should be treated like this? But the climax of her
trouble came, when Rudolph, springing across the grass, and
keeping his eyes still fixed anxiously on Mrs. Dale, as the little lady in
black staggered blindly through the trees, touched her arm gently
and whispered:
“You had better leave her for a little while, dear; she will be herself
again presently.”
Mabin turned her back upon him, and marched off, without a word,
in the direction of the house. He called to her to stop, to listen; but
she would do neither. Wounded to the core, first by her friend, in
whose cause she had been working, and then by her lover, she felt
that she could not trust herself in the vicinity of either of them without
an outbreak of grief or of anger to which her pride forbade her to give
way.
She was in a whirl of feeling; she hardly saw the flowers or the
trees as she walked; she scarcely knew whether she trod on grass
or on gravel as she made her way straight into the house, shut
herself up in her room, and sat down, in a passion of sullen
resentment, by one of the high windows.
It seemed to her that she had sat there for hours, sore, perplexed,
too miserable to think or to do anything but suffer, when her attention
was attracted by a sound which made her start up and look out of
the window. There, sauntering along between the broad beds of the
kitchen-garden, stooping, from time to time, to hunt under the leaves
for a late strawberry, or to gather a flower from the clumps of sweet-
william and of clove-pinks which made a fragrant border to the more
substantial products of the garden, was Mrs. Dale.
No longer melancholy, no longer silent, but bubbling over with high
spirits, and laughing lightly at every other word of her companion, the
lady in black looked more radiant than Mabin had ever before seen
her, and appeared to be as light-hearted and incapable of serious
thought as a child in the sunshine.
And her companion was Rudolph, who followed her, listened to
her, laughed with her, and seemed thoroughly satisfied with her
society.
This was the cruellest blow of all. That the deceitful woman who
could pretend to be so miserable at one moment, and could throw off
her grief so lightly the next, should have taken Rudolph and caused
him to forget the girl he pretended to care for so much! Mabin
watched them with a face wrinkled with despair, until her tears hid
them from sight. But even then, Mrs. Dale’s voice, always gay,
always bright, rang in her ears to the accompaniment of Rudolph’s
deeper tones.
The girl, however, was not weak-minded enough to cry for long.
The sound of the voices had scarcely died away when she sprang to
her feet, bathed her face, and did her best to hide the traces of her
grief. Pride had come to her assistance. She would show them both
that she did not care; that Mrs. Dale might amuse herself with
Rudolph, might carry him off altogether if she pleased, and she
would not break her heart about it.
She was ready to go downstairs, and was crossing the room for
that purpose, when there came a little tap at the door, and Mrs.
Dale’s voice cried:
“May I come in?”
For answer Mabin turned the handle, and her friend, looking at her
inquiringly, tripped into the room with a little affected air of penitence.
“I’m so sorry I was cross, dear, just now. Will you forgive me? I
was worried, and unhappy—and—— But I’m better now, and so I’ve
come to ask you to forgive me, and to come down to tea.”
She slid her arm round the girl’s waist. But Mabin could not
disguise the change in her own feelings, which she could not help.
She drew herself away with a laugh.
“I’m glad you are happier, and—and better,” she said stiffly. “I
thought you were, when I saw you just now in the kitchen-garden.”
Mrs. Dale looked up at her mischievously.
“Why, you silly child, you have been making yourself miserable. It
is of no use for you to try to deny it,” said she. “I believe you are
jealous, Mabin. You would not be, dear, if you knew all about it.”
She spoke very kindly; and by one of those rapid changes of mood
and manner which were her greatest charm, her face became
suddenly clouded with an expression of gentle sadness.
But Mabin’s unhappiness had been too great to be effaced by a
few gentle words. And her pride would not allow her to bend, to
come to the explanation her friend might be willing to give.
“You are quite wrong,” she said coldly; “I am glad to see him so
happy. I am not jealous.”
And she passed out of the room, as Mrs. Dale invited her to do,
and went downstairs with her head very high in the air, and a sense
of deep resentment at her heart.
At the dining-room door Rudolph met her, with a rose for her in his
hand, and a pretty speech on his lips about her unkindness in hiding
herself away for so long. But then, unluckily, Mabin’s sharp eyes
detected that he threw a glance of intelligence at Mrs. Dale, and
choosing instantly to fancy that there was a little conspiracy between
the two to “get round” her, she was so reserved and silent and stiff
as to make conciliatory advances impossible.
They had tea on the lawn, but it was a very brief affair, for Rudolph
jumped up from his seat in about a minute and a half, and said to
Mrs. Dale:
“If you will write it out now, I will take it at once.”
And then, Mrs. Dale, with a nod of intelligence, rose in her turn,
and went quickly into the house.
Mabin sat very still, looking at the grass.
“Let me put your cup down, dear,” said Rudolph, who seemed to
be subdued by the consciousness of what was in store for him.
As he took the cup, he managed to get hold of her hand.
“And now, Mabin, what’s the matter?”
“Nothing,” said she with a grand air; “and you are treading on my
frock.”
“I beg your pardon. I don’t think I was treading on your frock, by
the bye. It is the table that is on it.”
So he went down on one knee, released her dress, and remained
in his humble attitude, which brought him too low for her to avoid
meeting his eyes, as she would have liked to do.
“And now, Mabin, tell me why you are unkind again so soon.”
“You had better get up. Mrs. Dale might see you,” was the icy
answer.
“Well, and why shouldn’t she see me? Mabin, don’t behave like
this; it isn’t worthy of you. I couldn’t have thought it possible you
would sulk without any cause, as you are doing.”
“Without any cause? When Mrs. Dale and you both were unkind,
making excuses to send me away, and——”
She stopped, afraid for her self-control. Rudolph taking a seat
beside her, went on very quietly:
“She was very unhappy; you had said something, without knowing
it, which gave her a great shock. She was hardly mistress of herself;
you must have seen that.”
“But why was I to be sent away, like a child, without any
explanation? When I had just been doing a very difficult thing, too, to
try to help her!”
“What was the difficult thing?”
“I had called at ‘Stone House,’ and seen this man who calls
himself Mr. Banks, and got him to promise that he wouldn’t get into
‘The Towers’ at night, as he has done twice, and frighten her.”
At this, much to her indignation, Rudolph’s mouth curved into an
irrepressible smile. Mabin sprang up. But before she had fled very
far, he caught her up, and insisted on keeping pace with her, as she
ran toward the house.
“Stop, Mabin, and consider. If you run into the house, you will go
straight into Mrs. Dale’s arms; and if you don’t, I will send her to your
room after you. You had much better ‘have it out’ with me.”
So she turned and confronted him fiercely.
“Why did you laugh at me?”
“I can hardly tell you. No, don’t go off again; I mean that the
reason is part of a secret that is not mine.”
“A secret, of course; I knew that. A secret which has been
confided to you, but which I am not to know.”
Rudolph was silent.
“Can you expect me to be satisfied, to be laughed at and
neglected, while you and Mrs. Dale exchange confidences, and forg-
g-get me?”
“Now, Mabin, you are silly, my darling, silly, childish! You have
known just as well as I that there was a secret somewhere. Can’t
you be content to wait till the proper time comes for you to be told,
instead of behaving like an inquisitive school-girl?”
Now this was the very worst sort of speech he could have made. If
Rudolph had not been himself a good deal excited that afternoon by
the story which Mrs. Dale had confided to his ears, he would have
exercised greater restraint, greater choice in his words, and would
have given more consideration to his fiancée’s point of view.
Mabin grew white.
“I can wait, certainly,” she said with a sudden change to an
extremely quiet manner and tone, “for the great secret which
absorbed you so deeply. But there is another, a little mystery, which I
want to know now; and that is—how a woman who is in the depths of
despair at four o’clock, as Mrs. Dale appeared to be, can be in the
very highest spirits at five? Or is that a secret I have to wait to
know?”
“It’s all part of the same story,” replied Rudolph humbly, feeling
perhaps that greater demands were being made upon her patience
than was quite fair. “And I can only repeat that you will know
everything presently.”
“And why not now?”
“The whole thing was confided to me, and I don’t feel at liberty to
say any more even to you! Surely you can trust me, can trust us
both. Why, Mabin, I thought you were so proud of your loyalty to your
friends!”
The tears sprang to the girl’s eyes. She was giving way, and yet
feeling all the time that she had not been well treated, when unluckily
she noticed a little movement on the part of her companion, and
looked up quickly enough to see that Mrs. Dale, with a mischievous
smile on her face, was standing at the door of the house, and waving
a strip of paper to him as a signal.
“Go. Make haste. Mrs. Dale wants you!” cried Mabin bitterly.
And without leaving him time to protest or explain, she ran away.
That evening passed uncomfortably for both Mabin and Mrs. Dale.
When they met at dinner, they both showed traces of recent tears on
their pretty faces, and both unwisely tried to behave as if nothing had
happened to disturb the usual course of things.
Mrs. Dale did indeed make advances toward a modified half-
confidence; but it was so abundantly evident that she did so against
her will, and that she was afraid of saying too much, that she
repelled rather than encouraged the shy, proud girl.
Rudolph did not return. This was another sore point with poor
Mabin, who ended by persuading herself that Mrs. Dale had
succeeded in alienating from her the affections of her lover.
So that the hours dragged wearily by until bed-time, and both
ladies showed an unusual anxiety to get early to bed.
But next morning there was a change in Mrs. Dale’s manner; she
had lost her feverish high spirits, and was in such a state of nervous
irritability that even the sound of Mabin’s voice, coldly asking a
question at the breakfast-table, made her start and flush painfully.
Her eyes were heavy; her cheeks were white; there were dark lines
under her eyes which told of a sleepless night.
Mabin felt sorry for her, and was quite ready to “kiss and be
friends.” After all, she said to herself with resignation not unmingled
with bitterness, if Rudolph found the lovely widow with the interesting
history more attractive than a girl with no fascinating mystery
attached to her, it was not his fault, and it was not surprising. She felt
ashamed now of her jealousy and ill-temper of the previous evening,
excusable as they had been. And she deliberately made up her mind
that, whatever happened, she would take matters quietly; and even if
Rudolph deserted her altogether for Mrs. Dale, that she would give
him up without a murmur, whatever the effort cost her.
After all, what was the use, she said to herself with a heavy sigh,
of trying to keep a man’s love against his will? It had been a very
fleeting happiness, that of his love; but the superstitious feeling the
girl had had about its suddenness made her inclined to accept the
loss of it as inevitable; and no one would have guessed, from her
calm manner and measured voice, that Mabin was suffering the
keenest sorrow she had ever known.
It was Mrs. Dale who was reticent to-day. She told Mabin that she
expected a visitor that evening, but she did not say who it was. And
from the fever which burned in her eyes, and the restlessness which
increased upon her as the day went on, the young girl guessed that
some matter of great importance was to be discussed or arranged.
Was the visitor to be Mr. Banks? she asked herself. But she did
not dare to put the question to her hostess.
One unprecedented occurrence signalized the occasion. The
musty drawing-room was turned out, aired, and prepared for the
reception of the visitor.
“Do take your work in there, and leave it about, and try to make
the place look a little less like a charnel-house,” cried Mrs. Dale to
Mabin that afternoon, when they had gone together to inspect the
state apartment.
“It does look rather dreary certainly,” admitted Mabin. “But it won’t
look so bad to any one who hasn’t been used, like us, to knowing it
is always shut up.”
“That’s true. I hadn’t thought of that. However, I still beg you to
drop a few bits of filoselle about, and to read a few books and strew
them about. And I’ll run out and get some bits of copper beech and
bracken to fill those yawning bowls. Flowers would be quite lost in
them.”
“Not the peonies. They would look splendid!” Mabin called out
after her, as the widow went out through the French window on to
the gravel path outside.
It was already late in the afternoon, and, darkened as it was by the
trees and shrubs which grew near the large windows, the room was
so dimly lighted that Mabin took her work—it was still the cooking
apron—to the window. It had required some self-control to take up a
piece of work to which such recent memories were attached; and as
she sewed, Mabin had great difficulty in keeping back the tears.
Here were the very stitches Rudolph had put in, the very bag on
which their fingers had closed together. She felt the thrill of that
contact now.
And even as she let the apron fall into her lap, while the longing to
hear his voice speak tender words in her ear stirred in her heart and
made it beat fast, she heard his footstep on the gravel outside; she
saw him pass the window.
Scarcely repressing the cry: “Rudolph! Rudolph!” which rose to her
lips, she saw that he was hurrying across the grass without having
seen her. And looking out of the window, she saw that Mrs. Dale was
standing under the lime trees, holding out her hand to him with a
smile of greeting.
And the look of confidence and pleasure which irradiated the
widow’s face filled Mabin with despair.
She stood still at the window, but she no longer saw anything; she
was blinded by her tears. She hardly heard the door of the drawing-
room open, or, if she heard, she did not notice it. She did not turn her
head when the door closed.
It was not until a hard voice, close to her, said dryly:
“Are you the young lady whom I met here before—who refused to
take the warning I gave?” that Mabin, dashing away the tears from
her blinded eyes, recognized in the erect figure standing beside her
Mrs. Dale’s former mysterious visitor.
“I—I beg your pardon,” said Mabin hastily; “I—I did not see you
come in. You want to see Mrs. Dale. I will go and tell her.”
“You need not take that trouble,” replied the majestic lady in the
same hard tones as before. “She expects me. She sent for me by
telegraph yesterday.” And following the glance Mabin threw across
the lawn, she asked quickly, and in a harsher tone than ever: “Who is
the young man with her?”
“Mr. Bonnington, the Vicar’s son,” answered Mabin in a low voice.
“And what is he doing here?”
“He’s a friend of Mrs. Dale’s, and a friend of mine too,” added the
girl with the generous wish to save her friend from the anger she saw
in the elder woman’s eyes. “I am engaged to him.”
“Engaged to him! Engaged to marry him!” repeated the other
sharply. “And you trust him with that woman!”
Mabin’s loyalty was fired by the tone.
“Yes. She is my friend,” said she proudly.
The elder lady uttered a short, hard sound, which she meant for a
derisive laugh.
“Well, you are an independent young person, upon whom
warnings are thrown away. However, it may be of passing interest for
you to know that the lady you call your friend—” Mabin put her hands
to her ears, instinctively guessing that she was to hear some horrible
thing. In the darkness of the room the face above her seemed to her
to be distorted with the passion of a fiend as, in a voice so piercing
that the girl heard it distinctly, in spite of herself; she went on: “that
the lady you call your friend has ruined the life of a man who loved
her.” And Mabin caught her breath, thinking of the white face of Mr.
Banks. Still the hard voice went inexorably on: “and that she
murdered her own husband!”
Mabin uttered a shriek, as her hands fell down from her ears.
CHAPTER XIII.
MRS. DALE’S VERSION OF THE STORY.

The terrible words rang in Mabin’s ears as she remained staring at


the hard, vindictive face of the elder woman, hardly yet realizing all
that the accusation meant.
Mrs. Dale had murdered her own husband! Surely, surely it was
not true. She might be vain, frivolous, a coquette; but a murderess!
The girl instinctively shook her head.
The gaunt visitor, with an acid and unpleasant smile, sat down on
one of the fragile-looking papier-maché chairs, with mother-of-pearl
inlaid ornamentation, which dated the furnishing of the room.
“I—I can’t believe it. No, I won’t believe it!” whispered Mabin
hoarsely.
“There is no necessity for your doing so,” retorted the other with
indifference. “As it is a very unpleasant thing to believe, indeed, I
think you are wise to discredit it. And since she has alienated all her
old friends, it is fortunate that she can manage to find new ones.”
As the lady spoke, Mabin felt the horror she had experienced melt
gradually into pity for the poor little lady whom this hard woman had
in her power. And with compassion came resistance.
“Why shouldn’t she have friends?” she asked hotly. “Mrs. Dale is
not a hypocrite. She is deeply sorry for what wrong she has done;
she never denies that she has done something which has spoiled
her life. And I like her better for being able to be happy in spite of it,
sometimes, than if she pretended she could never smile again.”
“Well, of course, for such a trifle as the murder of her husband,
you could not expect a woman of her light temperament to trouble
herself very long!” said the visitor with grim irony.
“I don’t mean that. I know how much she suffers. But look how
young she is. How could you expect that she could never be happy
for a single moment any more? Doesn’t God forgive us our sins,
when we repent truly? And isn’t it by His laws that we can’t be numb
to any feeling but one all our lives?”
“You are a very powerful advocate, I am sure! Perhaps if you had
had a son whose life had been ruined by this woman’s conduct, you
would be less enthusiastic.”
These words startled Mabin, and made her look at the harsh
visitor in a new light. And she saw, or fancied she saw, in the
handsome but stern features of the old lady, a trace of the worn face
of her father’s tenant. She came a step closer, with her eyes intently
fixed on the lady’s countenance.
“Are you,” she asked in a whisper, “a relation of Mr. Banks?”
The visitor started, and seemed intensely astonished, and even
alarmed, by this question. She made no answer for a few moments,
which she passed in deep thought. Then, raising her head, and
looking straight into the girl’s eyes, she said calmly:
“And who is Mr. Banks?”
“One of the old friends of Mrs. Dale, who cares for her as much as
any new one!” replied Mabin promptly.
The other lady frowned.
“I didn’t want an epigram. I wanted to know who this Mr. Banks
was, and where you had met him,” she said tartly.
Mabin, seeing what a strong impression her rash words had made
wished she had not uttered them. While she was still wondering how
she should get out of her difficulty, with as little harm as possible to
Mrs. Dale, a sharply uttered question made her start.
“Has he—has this Mr. Banks met M-M-Mrs. Dale?”
She stammered over the lady’s name, just as Mr. Banks himself
had done.
“No,” answered Mabin promptly.
And at this answer the old lady, suddenly breaking down in the
intensity of her relief, fell back in her chair and gasped out:
“Thank Heaven!”
Mabin’s thoughts moved quickly. Stirred by the excitement of this
interview, she tried to find a way of serving Mrs. Dale; and it occurred
to her if this fierce old lady could meet Mr. Banks, he would perhaps
be able to tone down her ferocity. After a short pause she asked:
“Would you like to see him?”
“What? Is he here? You told me——”
The old lady was now so much excited and alarmed that she could
scarcely gasp out the words.
“He is staying not far from here,” replied Mabin cautiously.
The visitor got up.
“No, I do not wish to see him. I wish to see no one but Mrs. Dale. I
cannot understand why she keeps me waiting like this. I have come
all the way from Yorkshire to oblige her, at great inconvenience to
myself.”
Mabin could not understand it either, knowing as she did that Mrs.
Dale had expected her visitor. In the present state of affairs every
unlooked-for occurrence assumed a portentous aspect, so that she
felt rather alarmed.
“I will go and tell her you are here,” she said.
She was glad to be out of the presence of this terrible woman. And
as she ran out into the garden and then dropped into a sedate walk
as she passed the drawing-room windows, her heart went out to the
old lady’s victim more than it did to that of the young one.
Under the lime-trees, where she had last seen Mrs. Dale, she met
Rudolph alone. She greeted him with a white face, and without a
smile.
“Where is she—Mrs. Dale?” she then asked at once.
Rudolph, flushing a little at her manner, answered gravely:
“She was sent for to see some one, and went indoors. But then
she fainted, and they took her into the dining-room.”
“Thank you. I must go to her.”
Rudolph ran after her as she returned to the house.
“What has happened? You have learned something, found out
something. What is it?”
Mabin turned, and he saw that the tears were springing to her
eyes.
“I have, oh, I have!” she whispered hoarsely. “But don’t ask me
now. I can’t tell you now. I must go to her.”
He did not detain her, and she ran into the house and softly
opened the door of the dining-room. Mrs. Dale was lying on the hard
horsehair sofa, with her eyes closed. Two of the servants were
present, with fans and smelling-salts, and the usual remedies for a
fainting-fit.
As usual in the case of a household where there is a skeleton in
the cupboard, the servants took sides, and each of the opposing
parties was represented on this occasion. For while the housemaid,
Annie, was her mistress’ sworn champion, the parlormaid, who also
waited on Mrs. Dale, was suspected to be in the pay of the enemy,
the old lady now in the drawing-room.
As Mabin entered Mrs. Dale opened her eyes, and sat up.
“I must go, I must go,” she said in a weak and husky voice, as if
hardly yet mistress of herself.
“Yes, you shall go, in one minute,” said Mabin. And springing
forward with ready kindness and affection in her face, she signed to
the servants to leave them together. “Let me do your hair for you; I
can do it, I know I can,” she went on gently, touching the beautiful
fair hair which had become loose and disordered, and looking with
tender compassion into the blue eyes, which seemed to have lost
their brilliancy, their bright color.
Mrs. Dale stared with wide-open, dull eyes at the forms of the two
servants, as they left the room. Then she turned her head slowly,
and looked long at the young girl whose arm was now around her.
“Why are you so kind to me now?” she asked at last in a weak and
almost childish voice that went straight to Mabin’s heart. “You were
not kind last night!”
The first answer Mabin gave was a slight pressure of the arm upon
Mrs. Dale’s shoulder. Then Mabin bent down and whispered in her
ear:
“I didn’t know so much then!”
The little slender form in her arm shivered.
“What—what do you know now?” Then recollecting the events
which had preceded her own loss of consciousness, she suddenly
sprang off the sofa. “I know! I know! That cruel woman told you! I
must go to her; oh, I must go!”
“Well, let me do up your dress first.”
And Mrs. Dale then perceived that the upper part of her bodice
had been unfastened by the maids, and that her face was still wet
from the sprinkling of water they had given her. She submitted to
Mabin’s assistance, therefore, in arranging her hair and her dress,
without another word being exchanged between them. When she

You might also like