You are on page 1of 23

State Formation

A Historical Systems Approach


This is a revised version of a paper originally written in 1995 as part of an
honours degree project. It is somewhat academic in nature, so be warned.
While my opinions on some of the issues discussed herein have changed
somewhat, my theoretical interests are substantially similar to those in this
paper.

Table of Contents
I. Introduction
II. Illusory Dichotomy: Coercion and integration in early states
III. Illusory Pyramid: Egalitarianism and the growth of complexity
IV.Illusory Force: Processes and causes of social evolution
V. Illusory Universality: Systems and history
VI.Conclusion: Implications for future state research

I.

Introduction

No thing great is created suddenly, any more than a bunch


of grapes or a fig. If you tell me that you desire a fig, I
answer you that there must be time. Let it first blossom, then
bear fruit, then ripen.
Epictetus, The Discourses, I, 15
The study of state formation, and social evolution in general, has
fallen out of fashion in recent years, particularly among ethnologists.
However, there is no methodological justification for this collapse,
although some researchers have been convinced to abandon this topic.
Relying on evidence from archaeology, ethnohistory and ethnology, I argue
that despite the serious errors committed by some scholars of political
evolution, the general evolutionary framework is essentially valid. I feel
that an approach to state formation generally informed by systems theory is
essential and workable; however, consideration must be given to the specific
historical conditions extant in any specific state society. We must come to
recognize that societies are neither infinitely particular nor widely
generalizeable, and that while many causal factors may lead to state
formation, trends of increasing political complexity are evident in widely
divergent societies. I offer the proposal that many aspects of societies
which are invisible to archaeologists can be fruitfully studied by
ethnographic and ethnohistorical research, and that interdisciplinary co-

operation is essential if the evolutionary framework is to be refined.


Upon opening a discussion of a topic which is no longer popular in the
anthropological literature, one must consider whether it has failed due to
the irrelevance of the paradigm, or due to other circumstances. What has
gone wrong with the study of the state among ethnologists? Certainly, one
might argue validly that overly broad synchronic comparisons have been made
between societies separated widely in their history and geography. The
method adopted by Claessen and Skalnk in their Early State Project which
seeks to define the state by a number of structural characteristics, while
useful for purposes of description, has little explanatory value in and of
itself, although it makes no such claim (Claessen 1978). Other scholars,
arguing purely from (often dogmatic) theoretical positions, which may
require that the data be made to fit the theory, seem always to fail the
test of generalizability. Does it make sense, however, to reject the
subject altogether, or should we seek rather to refine our theories? It is
the second approach which seems most fruitful, and which I adopt throughout
this paper.
It is apparent, upon examining recent scholarly works on the study of
the state, that archaeology has come to have a greater effect on the topic
within anthropology. Indeed, Karl Hutterer has argued that sociocultural
anthropologists no longer have any role to play in this subject. I dispute
strongly the claim that "it will be necessary to shift the responsibility
from ethnology to archeology" in order to construct evolutionary sequences
(Hutterer 1991: 237). It is essential, however, that the ahistorical,
synchronic ethnographic models which are used primarily for taxonomic
purposes be re-examined in light of the specific trajectories developed by
ethnohistorians and archaeologists.
I should also make clear to what I am referring as "a state". As a
preliminary definition, I suggest the following: a form of government in
which there exists centralized authority, hierarchical differences in access
to power and basic resources between individuals, reinforced by
institutionalized coercion, usually accompanied by the decline of kin
structures. As such, there is no reason to see these characteristics of
"the state" as more important than any other agglomeration of
characteristics. However, the recurrence of particular sets of traits in
diverse areas of the globe (Mesoamerica, South America, Africa, India,
China, etc.) indicates that there may still be some use in talking about
"state formation" as opposed to the more general "political evolution".
Political evolution, then, is the process by which societies change their
structures through time, generally in the direction of greater complexity.
I do not intend to discuss issues of social collapse or "devolution" in this
paper; certainly, the value of such terms within an evolutionary framework
can be debated.
There appear to be four fundamental illusions which some state
theorists have fallen under. Firstly, too much emphasis has been placed on
the dichotomy between coercive and integrative theories of the state,
leading to overly polarized positions which obscure the complex reality of
societies. Next, false notions of hierarchy and progress have led some to
see state formation as an end point of social evolution rather than part of
an ongoing process of increasing social size and complexity. Third, the
systemic forces which cause social evolution to occur have been
misidentified and misinterpreted by scholars under the influence of
paradigms from elsewhere in the life and social sciences. Finally, many

have existed under the illusion that state formation is a process which
imposes centralization upon non-state societies, rather than being an
outgrowth of their existing institutions and historical practices. I intend
not only to dispel these four illusions but to replace them with
constructive means by which anthropologists should revive state formation as
a worthwhile area of study.

II. Illusory Dichotomy: Coercion and integration in


early states

The chief foundations of all states, new as well as old or


composite, are good laws and good arms; and as there cannot be
good laws where the state is not well armed, it follows that
where they are well armed they have good laws.
Niccolo Machiavelli, The Prince, ch. 12
Until very recently, theorists on the topic of state formation have
largely been polarized into two schools: conflict theorists, who emphasize
the coercive role of the state in increasing and legitimating inequality,
and integration theorists, who point to the state's greater redistributive
ability as its primary causal feature. Neither of these two extreme
positions is wholly satisfactory in every state, and I would hazard that
neither is sufficient explanation in any state. As Machiavelli astutely
noted almost four centuries ago, both laws and arms make a good prince, and
it is impossible to have one without the other.(1)
The history of the study of states could theoretically be extended
back to the ancient philosophers, and thenceforth to the Enlightenment
philosophes such as Hobbes, Locke, and Rousseau. It is evident that the
tension between social contract, or integration models, and social conflict,
or coercive models, extends throughout this period, as argued effectively by
Haas (1982). In the anthropological literature on states, one would expect
no objection to the claim that most Marxists and materialists adopt coercive
models, while those emphasizing managerial functions would propound
integrative theories of state formation. However, the considerable evidence
on both sides of the debate (which I do not intend to review in detail)
immediately leads one to suspect that neither theory is wholly satisfactory.
Scholars who argue for the primacy of warfare as causal agent in state
formation have generally combined the two orientations of integration and
conflict due to the nature of their "prime mover". Webster notes that
warfare facilitated "the emergence and survival of privileged managerial
groups" (1975: 469) in order to co-ordinate military efforts and marshal
resources. However, this integrative role is contrasted with his assertion
that "Concentration of power is integrally related to concentration of
wealth, and derives from it" (1975: 468). This apparent contradiction
suggests that while initially, the need for integration enabled meritorious
or cunning individuals to acquire control over these resources, coercion and
differential access to resources reinforced this position due to the
resulting power differential.

Warfare is surely a necessary but insufficient condition for state


formation. However, this position, which has been advocated by Cohen (1978:
46) as part of complex events which synthesize various factors leading to
the centralization of authority, in no way argues that warfare is a prime
mover in social evolution. Neither do I accept the conclusion of Naroll and
Divale that because cross-cultural studies do not show a correlation between
warfare and territorial growth that "peaceful diffusion is more likely than
warfare to be the primary mechanism of selection in cultural evolution"
(1976: 121). The causes and consequences of warfare are both varied and
closely intertwined with other social events in societies. Warfare is
neither indicative of "coercion" or "integration", but requires that both
factors operate simultaneously. Surely we can accept that war has serious
influences on political leadership and social structure without arguing that
its presence somehow determines the future of the society.
The greatest methodological problem which scholars have faced in
interpreting archaeological data on archaic states is the establishment of
causal links which would support or reject the conflict or integration
positions. How, for instance, can data whose date can only be placed
accurately within a century be used to establish whether warfare preceded
the state, or the other way around, and so on? This problem is faced most
clearly by Haas (1982) in attempting to re-evaluate the archaeological data
on the "primary civilization", and is not completely resolved. However, we
do have a number of instances of historical state formation in Polynesia,
Africa and elsewhere, for which such details are known. Might it not be
productive, then, to examine the better known ethnohistorical examples in
order to aid in constructing analogies in order to understand the lesser
known archaeological states?
The best evidence we have, then, suggests that both coercion and
integration have their place in state formation. I offer the complementary
proposition that the dichotomy between the two is both unnecessary and
unimportant. Whether a mechanism is coercive or integrative is not the
primary determinant of its importance for the formation of states. The
excessive focus on the polar opposition of these two principles may stem
from the philosophes and their proposals of "social contract" and "social
coercion", neither of which were based on any real evidence, anthropological
or otherwise. Thus, while we may maintain that organizing irrigation
systems is "integrative" while enslaving one's conquered enemies is
"coercive", I offer as a testable hypothesis the notion that there may be
more important guiding principles of state formation as yet undiscovered.

III. Illusory Pyramid: Egalitarianism and the Growth of


Complexity
There is no steady unretracing progress in this life; we
do not advance through fixed gradations, and at the last one
pause ...
Herman Melville, Moby Dick, ch. 111
A great deal of ink has been spilt over the question of typology of

societies with regards to their political evolution. The classic theories


of Service (1962) and Fried (1967) are seminal in this matter. Each is
generally concerned with how egalitarian (or band) societies evolve through
intermediate stages into modern states. I agree with Upham that Service's
band-tribe-chiefdom-state and Fried's egalitarian-ranked-stratified-state
models "do not exist in their entirety in the real world; they are
categorical representations of reality that condense meaningful variability"
(Upham 1990: 89). The fact that these typologies are constructions does
not, however, eliminate their value as analytical tools, as long as we
understand that they have limited explanatory value and do not reflect the
fullness of social reality. The term "state" certainly should not be used
as a predictor of the existence or absence of specific traits associated
with state societies.
It should be emphasized that "egalitarian" societies are by no means
characterized by complete equality but of course are stratified in terms of
authority by age, sex and personal ability (Service 1975: 49). Trigger
reports that in many cases, even economic equality is not achieved within
these societies due to differences in merit and the perceived generosity (or
lack thereof) of individuals (1985: 50). The evolution of political
inequality should therefore not be treated as the origin of this inequality,
which has its basis in nature, but rather, in the true meaning of evolution,
its "unfolding". Likewise, "complex" societies often maintain considerable
vestiges of their earlier egalitarian condition, as evinced by the retention
at least somewhat of kinship and reciprocity as important principles in
states. I am, then, referring only to ideal types in the use of
"egalitarian", "complex" and other such terms, while acknowledging that
real-world societies are always found somewhere on a continuum of
complexity.
Regardless of the existence of broad stage-like categories, the way in
which these categories are related to one another has been fundamentally
misinterpreted. It is customary to imagine a "hierarchy" of political
evolution, with states at the pinnacle, chiefdoms and tribes in the middle
and band societies at the bottom. This pyramidal analogy can be found in
many structural Marxist arguments, such as that of Friedman (1975) and
Kristiansen (1991) which place the state at the centre of a spatial
hierarchy with chiefdoms and tribes on the periphery. It is essential,
however, that we examine the consequences of this geometric-spatial model of
social evolution for the errors of cause and effect which it engenders.
Kristiansen asserts that chiefdoms "are in many cases, perhaps most
cases, a secondary development" and that simpler societies are merely
devolved polities separated by geography or other circumstances from the
states upon which they are dependent" (1991: 27). This argument is wholly
teleological and obscures the processes by which such hierarchies of
societies (which certainly exist in colonial and post-colonial regions) are
formed. How, then, do we explain the existence of chiefdoms in places such
as pre-contact Polynesia, where states were unknown and ties to outside
state structures non-existent? It is extremely arrogant of those in state
societies to assume that merely because they can enforce dependence on
smaller-scale societies that such societies are somehow created by the
spatial relations between core and periphery.(2) Such attitudes also reveal a
hidden bias: that states are somehow the culmination or end-point of
processes of social evolution, and that modern nation-states have somehow
transcended the evolutionary paradigm. It is entirely possible for change
to be directional without being teleological.

I wish to make my point emphatically clear: political systems are not


arranged hierarchically, excepting specific instances where there is a
relationship between a central (core) state and various less complex
polities in the periphery. Gall and Saxe offer the following caution
regarding taxonomic classifications:
Since the taxonomy is concerned with trends of increasing
complexity, we should not assume that this is the only trend in
nature or that it is "progressive" in nature.... Nor does this
taxonomy substitute for an analysis of cultural processes.
Rather it provides a frame for assessing what is there and what
changes have taken place in the relationships between the
variables as it developed and why (1977: 257).
A hierarchy is a real structure, expressing relations of information
exchange and power between real entities. Hierarchical constructions of
evolutionary taxa do not express such relations, but rather describe a
fictitious evolutionary pattern which inevitably leads towards the state.
There always exists a danger that this model will become a straw man by
which some may seek to discredit the notion of the state. We should seek to
express the concept of complexity in quantifiable (if not perfectly so)
terms, before we may continue with the study of social evolution.
How, then, should we describe the directional process of increasing
complexity which characterizes social evolution? The most profitable
course, I think, is to adopt linear models which have descriptive value
based on real-world data such as settlement size, subsistence form and the
presence or absence of political traits. While researcher bias certainly
may influence a measurement for a single society, if trends are visible
throughout many societies, the cross-cultural research will have described
something with at least some basis in social reality. This sort of project
is undertaken by Carneiro (1967) using forty-six randomly selected
societies, in which population size is plotted against the number of
organizational traits present. Indeed, a fairly reliable logarithmic linear
correlation between the two variables exists.
What the sorts of studies that Carneiro and others have done
accomplishes is to establish variation between societies. What it does not
do is establish the variation of this change over time. However, as Jerome
Rousseau notes, "we do know something of archaic relations of production",
and may reasonably assume that hunter-gatherers of today, while certainly
different from archaic ones, possess the same basic subsistence forms and
political traits (Rousseau 1985: 38). We know further that "all primitive
nonegalitarian societies were not primordial, in the sense that they all
were preceded by egalitarian societies" (Khazanov 1985: 94); that is, the
original state of humanity was (relative) egalitarianism, and all nonegalitarian societies are transformations of earlier egalitarian ones.
These factors, then, form the basis for the claim that societies generally
increase in complexity through time. (3)
However, once we have established the linear model as one based in
factual data rather than speculation and teleology, what do with it? It is
important to realize that we cannot simply read the course of human history
by travelling up our new line of state formation. There are inevitable dips
and gullies in the process of state formation, as cities collapse, chiefdoms
divide, and polities everywhere experience periods of stability with little

structural transformation. We must be cautious, recognizing that a


descriptive model can do nothing for our understanding of process and
causation until we examine the specific histories of state societies.
However, this caution has not been heeded by all scholars. One of the
most egregious conclusions reached by those scholars who place descriptive
characteristics of states above the factors causing them is that of
Carneiro. Carneiro notes that the number of autonomous political entities
extant in the world has declined steadily from the beginning of humanity to
the present, and that as the number of states grows smaller, their size
grows larger - fair enough, so far. He then asserts that the curve of
declining polities leads inevitably to one conclusion: the emergence of a
world state (Carneiro 1978: 222). To do so, he invokes the principle of
competitive exclusion, an idea borrowed from biological evolution which
states that two species cannot coexist using the same niche indefinitely,
and one will eventually prevail, forcing the other to evolve or die out
(Carneiro 1978: 221).
Carneiro's contention that there is an inevitable decline in the
number of political groups requires that one accept that independent
aggregates existing in pre- and proto-human periods were also "political
groups". Otherwise, one would have to acknowledge that there was a time in
human history when there were no political groupings at all, followed by an
increase, which produces a curve rather unlike Carneiro's. Taken to its
extreme, all biological populations are in fact autonomous political groups
in Carneiro's sense of the term. We must also consider whether the
conditions of harsh competition and warfare required for this model actually
existed. Furthermore, it is by no means a foregone conclusion that the
world state is an inevitable result. Carneiro here confuses directionality
with teleology, a similar error to the pyramidal fallacy of the state
described above, when it is entirely unknown where the curve of autonomous
polities might be leading. We cannot predict "where" social evolution may
be going, simply because it is not "going" anywhere at all, but rather
processes acting at the present act to shape the future without any inherent
goal or end point.
The conclusion which we must draw from this analysis is clear. The
pyramid must be toppled, not only because it presents a misguided geometry
of political systems, but also because this analogy has resulted in the
rejection of social evolution entirely as a legitimate process. Yet the
limitations of the linear model of evolution must also be recognized. There
is surely a trend towards increasing complexity among societies over time;
however, due to the vagaries of societal collapse and stagnation, we cannot
clearly place the descriptive template of settlement size and political
differentiation atop the overall causal scheme of political evolution.
There is the ever-present danger that, as Carneiro and others have done, we
will extend the general evolutionary curves into predictive and explanatory
models which ignore or devalue process. What, then, can be done to
establish the process by which this evolution occurs?

IV. Illusory Force:


Formation

Processes and Causes of State

Evolution is not a force but a process, not a cause but a law.


John, Viscount Morley of Blackburn (1838-1923)
The linear model of state formation which I have presented suffers
from a further defect of great consequence, hopefully not a fatal one.
While the linear model has descriptive value, it has little or no
explanatory value. Merely establishing that the Chinese state has greater
differentiation among its political officials than do !Kung San bands tells
us nothing as to what causal factor or factors led to Chinese society being
as complex as it is. It also cannot explain why the !Kung San did not
develop inequality to the same degree. Although many scholars from
different fields have tried to explore the mechanisms of state formation, no
synthesis has been reached, as many of these models are purely speculative
and have no basis in ethnographic data. This flaw cannot be easily
addressed using synchronic ethnographic studies, but must be examined in
light of historical and archaeological data.
The question of evolutionary mechanism is central to social
evolutionary theory. On the one hand, biological models of adaptation have
been introduced in many forms to explain how each stage of political
evolution is "selected for" by virtue of their adaptive advantages. On the
other, we have materialist arguments from both cultural ecologists and some
Marxists which see the alteration of political structures as a response to
environmental conditions or to the mode of production of the society. Both
of these arguments have a certain amount of merit; selection of some sort
obviously occurs among societies, while material conditions undoubtedly
influence the emergence of states due to their centrality for human
existence. While certainly these arguments have lost much of their
explanatory force as universal predictors, it would be erroneous to assume
that they are no longer advocated. Indeed, due to the relative parsimony of
biological and "crude" materialist arguments, they retain a degree of
respectability as theories of state formation that I do not feel is
warranted.
Attempts by evolutionary biologists to explain the emergence of the
state have used the term "evolution" in a purely reductionist sense of an
increase in adaptive fitness in a particular environment. Jack Hill, a
parasitologist, suggests that it is a given that human beings will
inevitably seek greater prestige for the reproductive advantage it will give
them. States, then, are the culmination of a never-ending quest for greater
and greater prestige in order to have more offspring (Hill 1994: 224).
Hill's analysis, however, is wholly teleological as it assumes that the end
result (the state) is "adaptive" and then determines why it might be
adaptive for people to seek out this adaptive state.
Why, for instance, do states not evolve among chimpanzees, since it is
also true that the great apes have dominance hierarchies that give them
greater reproductive success? Have hunter-gatherers such as the !Kung San
somehow missed out on the opportunity to gain reproductive success by not
evolving to a "state" level of organization?
While Hill is certainly right
that a desire for power and prestige is an essential part of any leader
assuming command of a group, any increase in reproductive fitness in the
leader would necessarily be offset by the loss in reproductive success of
the underlings. In fact, why would close-knit bands of kin have any
competition for prestige at all, since one would be reducing one's inclusive
fitness by competing with close kin?

Hill does not account for the acceptance of the non-prestigious of the
laws and ordinances of those who gain prestige -why would one not simply
leave, or eliminate one's leader, or use other means to reduce the resultant
inequalities? He must assume that all states evolved in highly
circumscribed environments with strong competition for prestige, a situation
for which he provides no evidence. The final blow to Hill's argument
derives from the fact that in hunter-gatherer bands stratified by age and
sex, and thus young men know that they have only to wait for a few years
until their status rises, along with their reproductive success. There is
no reason to overthrow the leadership in such a stable situation, and there
is no evidence that this is how social evolution actually occurred. While
there are certain correlations between the acquisition of power and the
continuation of one's line, Hill has reduced a complex situation to such a
ridiculous degree that his argument has no merit whatsoever.
Roger Masters equates political evolution with game theory in
evolutionary biology, specifically the classic Prisoner's Dilemma. Masters
contends that the inevitable result of individual rational choices would be
some sort of "social contract" in which it is "natural" that the benefits of
law and government outweigh its costs (Masters 1982: 446-447). His sources
on state origins are those of Hobbes, Rousseau, Kant and Hegel, without
consideration of the anthropological evidence which suggests that the
"social contract" is an illusion of Western philosophers rather than a real
phenomenon. Masters' contention that the state is caused when equals gather
together to determine codes of proper or "altruistic" conduct supposes that
this "natural state of equality" existed (Masters 1982: 442), while I have
suggested above that it did not. This analysis falls prey to the same sort
of fault as Hill's, in that it may explain something about human sociality
but that it fails to consider the non-emergence of states as an equally
relevant fact as their actual formation. It is clear that while there may
be correlations between state formation and biological adaptive advantages,
evolutionary biologists have failed completely to produce adequate causal
agents for political evolution.
Having explored the ridiculous arguments from the biologists, let us
turn now to the materialists, whose arguments regarding state formation can
be separated roughly into two distinct groups. The first, Marxist and neoMarxist scholars, argue that material conditions and the mode of production
of a society are essential in transforming its political structures and
ideological behaviour. The other, called by some "vulgar Marxists", are
cultural ecologists who argue that a society's environmental conditions are
the primary determinants of its social structure and evolution. While both
of these arguments fail, they fail for different reasons, as I will detail
below.
Marxist arguments on state formation no longer rely extensively on the
writings of Marx himself; certainly, few would be found who still argue that
all societies must pass through a capitalist phase before reaching "the end
of history" with the advent of communism. Charles Maisels, a neo-Marxist,
rejects the notion that there is one universal line of evolution. Instead,
he argues that there are at least two divergent lines: one, that of east
Asia and the Andes, leading to the so-called "Asiatic" mode of production,
and the other, found in Mesopotamia, leading to a "city-state" system of
urban centers (1987: 331). The Marxist line of thought regarding state
formation generally requires the conversion of human beings and their
labour-products into use by wealthy elites (see Tosi 1976). As such, it is

a "coercion" theory which has as its primary mechanism the interaction of


material and human factors.
Marxists have certainly come farther than many in their emphasis on
historical processes and structural and ideological change in societies.
However, many Marxist scholars still have a tendency to see state formation
according to an orthodox Marxist scheme for which there is little evidence.
(4)
For instance, Patterson's description of the "pre-capitalist" Inca state
requires that one accept that "capitalism" is the inevitable successor to
whatever sort of "pre-capitalism" existed among the Inca (Patterson 1991).
I believe this to be entirely unsupported. Furthermore, the direct
translation of material conditions into ideology seems overly simplified;
while certainly one's subsistence method and production relations influence
one's way of thought, the notion that they are thereby determined seems a
bit far-fetched.
Many cultural ecologists have been centrally concerned with the
evolution of states, arguing that the primary mechanisms of cultural
evolution and the creation of states derive from the physical environment.
Heirs to the legacy of White and Steward, ecological models are not
necessarily deterministic, and are often quite refined with regards to the
interplay of cultural and material factors. Carneiro's argument that state
formation can only occur in highly circumscribed physical environments is of
this sort, as it recognizes that there is always the possibility that
"social circumscription" by other human populations may have the same effect
(Carneiro 1970: 737). Few scholars would now argue for a direct translation
of ecological circumstances into political expansion or contraction
(however, see Harris 1977). Terry Rambo, a cultural ecologist, presents his
case eloquently:
To a considerable extent, we have moved beyond use of gross
environmental variables (e.g. rain forests, deserts) into making
of quite fine-grained descriptions of the specific local
habitats within which specific cultural groups are functioning
(Rambo 1991: 92).
Environmental and ecological factors are such persuasive candidates
for "prime mover" status simply because they are so clearly related to means
of subsistence. The development of agriculture is surely the key to the
production of surplus, which is a necessary condition if a society is to
have non-producers among its leaders. However, most ecologists know very
well that agriculture is not adopted in many places where a surplus might be
produced, simply because of the intensive labour required (see Boserup
1965). We also need to explain, then, why states did not form in every
place where the environment was suitable; to do so, we must regard
environmental factors as necessary but insufficient conditions, as with so
many other factors. While ecologists have gone beyond the Marxists in
recognizing that societies are not simply material conditions writ large,
Marxist thought is much more amenable to the sort of historical thinking
which I feel is essential in order to understand the interaction of
variables in social systems.
We have seen that the evolution of the state has very different
features from evolution in nature. It should also be evident that states do
not represent crude transformations of material and ecological conditions,
as advocated by some cultural ecologists and Marxists. Nevertheless, it is

clear that societies represent systems of some sort, and are not merely
agglomerations of individuals even in the most undifferentiated of peoples.
By "system" I mean only any organized assembly of inter-related components,
and as such many types of systems (mechanical, organic, astrophysical,
social, etc.) can be identified. A key insight which is raised by Walter
Buckley is that a system "is not to be confused with the structure or
organization its components may take on at any particular time" (1967: 5,
italics in original). It may thus be said that while there are evolutionary
systems or social systems, there are only state structures which are the
physical manifestations of a social system at any given time.
Lest the reader think I am advocating some sort of metaphysical force
behind such systems, I must emphasize that systems are entirely the result
of human actions, the natural and constructed environment and the
interaction of the two. Nevertheless, the consequences of systems and the
structures they produce are often indifferent to or even contradictory to
the desires of their human components. Anyone who has ever invested in the
stock market is well aware that it is a system in which each actor desires
financial gain, and yet often the market can crash, causing financial harm
to all individuals concerned. Most social systems are, of course, far more
complex and cannot be so easily described. It is the job of the systems
theorist to explain how human actors and actions and the physical
environment are the sole causal agents which result in the creation of state
structures.
An important (and much misused) concept in systems theory is that of
feedback, of which positive (deviation-enhancing) and negative (deviationreducing) are the two forms. Buckley notes that feedback should not be
"equated simply with any reciprocal interaction between variables" (1967:
52). The classic example of negative feedback is a thermostat; when a
change to the initial condition of the system occurs (increase or decrease
in temperature), the system is sensitive to the change and responds by
reducing the deviation (either by sending a signal to introduce more heat or
by sending another signal to turn the heat off). To witness positive
feedback in action, the stock market example above is instructive. As soon
as any slight decrease occurs in a stock or a negative circumstance arises,
the system's sensors (human actors) react by attempting to sell the stock
before a more drastic decrease occurs. Since the market then has less
demand than supply, the overall effect (feedback response) is an increased
rate of decline. In the case of state formation and social evolution, it is
positive feedback with which we are most concerned, although negative
feedback and homeostasis are important and ongoing processes which
maintain stability in all societies, whether or not they are states.
Perhaps the most influential systems theorist working within a
cultural evolutionary framework has been Kent Flannery (Flannery 1972).
Flannery suggests that cultural evolution is most adequately explained
"multivariant causality" in which various factors are interrelated in a
complex of feedback loops, causal chains and other relationships (Flannery
1972: 423-424). By rejecting "prime movers" such as population pressure or
warfare, without denying the importance of such factors, multivariant
causality allows that these factors may operate in different directions, and
that each social system is unique. One may debate the value or existence of
Flannery's "generative rules" of the state as too simplistic or incomplete
scenarios. However, this objection does not require the rejection of the
theory, but rather careful research to test its validity.

Systems theory has been used with moderate success to analyze


instances of state formation among archaic civilizations which are known
archaeologically. Examining evidence in southwest Iran from Mesopotamian
sites, Wright and Johnson conclude that "only multiple variable changes"
could produce vast shifts in the political economy and exchange networks
present (1975: 284). The shift towards greater political centralization and
the loss of autonomy among smaller centres may have overloaded the existing
system's capability to process information, leading to the creation of
hierarchies to govern the new system. While Wright and Johnson admit that
their research is unsuccessful in that it is unable to answer what specific
causal factors led to the creation of centralized redistributive centres,
they offer a model which can be tested in order to explain specific
instances of state formation.
J. Stephen Athens attempts to criticize the systems approach of
Flannery, Wright and Johnson, arguing instead from an ecological perspective
that "an understanding of the evolution of complex social systems can only
proceed through an examination of factors relating to the stability of
agricultural production and the use of relevant variable dimensions of
analysis" (1977: 377). He claims that system theories "are unsuccessful
because they cannot predict state formation" (Athens 1977: 360). Certainly,
no one has ever claimed the usefulness of any model, including that of
systems theory, to predict when state formation will occur. Athens,
however, assumes that a theory which successfully addresses the question of
causation will be fully equipped for prediction. By arguing that any
successful theory of state formation should be universally applicable,
Athens forces himself into a position where he must reject any theory such
as systems theory which postulates that many possible evolutionary
trajectories can lead to the formation of similar structures. His argument
that multivariant causation is unfounded is therefore a highly tautologous
one.
Systems theorists have a response to Athens' qualms regarding
causation in the concept of equifinality. This is defined by Buckley as the
principle that a final condition of a system may be achieved by any number
of developmental routes (Buckley 1967: 60). To attempt to separate out
distinct causes, or even to emphasize one as primary, may not be useful
because the result is unknown until it emerges. The "final" result of the
interplay of factors is not merely the cumulation of causes to produce an
effect, but a process of interaction and amplification. It is thus not
possible to predict the emergence of the state with any regularity, or to
separate causes from their end result. Given that the evidence regarding
state formation suggests that there is no single factor that is sufficient,
and that even the necessity of many factors can be debated, it seems
reasonable to see whether different equifinal models of state formation can
be created.
A word of caution is necessary before continuing. Systems theory as a
model creates testable hypotheses, not complete accounts of incidences of
state formation. It should be acknowledged that these are not mechanical,
electronic or organic systems, but human creations, subject to the vagaries
of human existence and random chance. We must recognize that something as
simple as the untimely death of one's leader can have profound
consequences on history (as it did on the Mongol hordes), and there is nothing
like a hurricane to crush an incipient rebellion and unite individuals in a
rebuilding effort. Charles Spencer discusses the effect of the eruption of
the volcano Xitle as a precipitating event for the conquest of Cuicuilco by

the early Mesoamerican state of Teotihuacan (Spencer 1990: 22). As noted


above, the consequence of this randomizing factor is that we never know
exactly what parts of the system have priority in a given society, rendering
prediction impossible. And in no way do I mean to imply that because a
system is stable (has achieved equilibrium or homeostasis) that it is
"adaptive", to use a much-misused term. As Rappaport notes, "Social systems
... can make mistakes of which biological systems may be incapable"
(Rappaport 1977: 51). Still, recognizing this fact, we should proceed with
the knowledge that even an imperfect system is not a random aggregate, but a
structured grouping.

V.

Illusory Universality:

Systems and History

History abhors determinism but cannot tolerate chance.


Bernard de Voto (1897-1955)
I have placed myself thus far in the "systems theory" camp of
evolutionary explanation. However, I feel that this is a necessary but
insufficient means of depicting social evolution. After all, the day after
the stock market crashes, life goes on, and the rules of the game are the
same. Yet when societies evolve, they often undergo fundamental structural
change. I now intend to come to some sort of analysis regarding the changes
of such structures over time: in short, to indicate and explore the
fundamentally historical nature of social systems.
I have, so far, rejected any of the claims of evolutionary biology as
to its applicability to processes of state formation. However, there is one
respect in which the two types of systems, social and biological, are
clearly similar and in which a useful analogy can be drawn. It is selfevident that all evolutionary processes are essentially historical processes
which do not operate in some sort of vacuum. There has been a recent
movement among some evolutionists to modify the Darwinian paradigm of
evolutionary biologists, in recognition of the historical constraints which
limit the variation which can exist within populations. At the forefront of
this movement is Harvard biologist Stephen Jay Gould, whose works The
Panda's Thumb and Bully for Brontosaurus suggest that neither biological nor
cultural evolution can be understood in ahistorical terms (Gould 1980).
This principle of historical constraint aids in explaining why humans have
four limbs rather than some other number. Since humans' evolutionary
predecessors - fish, reptiles and other mammals - all had four limbs, it is
not possible for that trait to have been selected against, since no better
variation existed within those species (and even if one evolved as a
mutation, it would almost certainly be non-adaptive).
Indeed, just as the panda cannot simply evolve a thumb out of nowhere,
but must rely on existing morphological traits in order to produce an
adaptive advantage, Gould asserts that cultural evolution may operate
according to similar historical principles. He cites the example of the
retention of the suboptimal QWERTY keyboard as a historical quirk which is
now retained because of the incredible inertia that would have to be
overcome in order to change to a better system (Gould 1992: 71-72). While,
by his own admission, Gould's perspective on cultural evolution is that of
an interested amateur, there has been little consideration given to these

sorts of constraints among most social evolutionists, other than vague


statements to the effect that "of course, there are some historical
particularities in such-and-such society". Consequently, these
particularities are usually dismissed as being of little importance.
However, I see no reason to make such a broad assumption, and, indeed, many
scholars have begun to consider issues of historical constraints when
examining the evolution of particular societies.
A recent paper by William Keegan and Morgan Maclachlan, whose
ethnohistorical and archaeological analysis of the Bahamas traces the
evolution of Taino avunculocal chiefdoms, suggests ways in which political
evolution might be given its proper historical context. They assert that
the traditional (initial condition) of Taino matrilineality, bolstered by
the emergence of avunculocal residence due to internal warfare, led to
structural changes and a shift towards greater political differentiation
(Keegan and Maclachlan 1989: 620). One consequence of this change was a
shift in settlement pattern towards settlement clusters and larger towns,
"resulting from a male's desire to participate in his own lineage while
resident with his wife's" (Keegan and Maclachlan 1989: 624). With larger
population units came the inevitable need for co-ordination and conflict
resolution through the power of a chief. Environmental factors must also
have played a major role in Taino evolution. Keegan and Maclachlan remark
that avunculocal chiefdoms are always found in highly circumscribed
environments such as the Bahamas because they entail a great deal of
internal conflict that can only be resolved upon the emergence of one
dominant clan in order to produce stability (1989: 622). Finally,
technological changes such as the advent of large ocean-going canoes for
trade further bolstered the need for leadership and co-ordination among the
Taino in order to marshal resources (Keegan and Maclachlan 1989: 626).
We see in the emergence of Taino chiefdoms that (at least) four
distinct elements of the society - residence pattern, kinship structure,
physical environment and technology - act in combination to create a system
by which political evolution is the favoured or "natural" outcome. It would
be nave to regard any one of these as a "prime mover". The removal or
alteration of any one of those factors would have altered the evolution of
Taino political centralization, perhaps even halting it. It is quite
probable that if there had not been a great deal of initial conflict due to
the circumscribed environment, that disaffected Taino clans could depart the
region. It is equally likely that without the initial condition of
matrilineality, the men of the clans would have no reason to desire
clustered settlement patterns. We must also consider that, as this is a
historical system: what happens once political evolution occurs? The new
"initial conditions" are not only matriliny and warfare, but the presence of
canoes, long-distance exchange and chiefs. If the new technology is used to
migrate, thus removing the factor of environmental circumscription, will the
chiefs lose their power?
My point is not to describe "what if" (for we
certainly cannot use a systems model for prediction) but to explain "what
for" and "from what" certain institutions developed, and to understand the
processes by which this might occur.
I will turn now to an examination of the consequences of a historical
perspective on social evolution to one of the key problems in the study of
state formation: the distinction between primary (or pristine) and secondary
states. Most authors make a strong distinction between the two types of
state. Jonathan Haas claims that in every known ethnographic case of state
formation, the situation has been "contaminated" by the presence of outside

complex societies (Haas 1982: 51). Anatolii Khazanov notes that "the states
founded as a consequence of the expansion or colonial policies of more
developed states - which hence represented a kind of secondary developed
states - were definitely not early ones, even at the time of their origin"
(Khazanov 1978: 79). Jerome Rousseau, in discussing the prerequisites of
inequality, asserts that "societies transformed by more developed modes of
production (and this applies eminently to the colonial situation) cannot be
expected to follow this sequence" (1985: 45).
One would certainly have to concede that the distinction between
primary and secondary states is a meaningful one at least with regards to
its basic definition. There is no apparent reason, however, to sharply
divide episodes of state formation on these lines any more than along the
axis of circumscribed vs. non-circumscribed states, or distinguishing the
presence or absence of long-distance trade. Two reasons come to mind
immediately as to why the primary-secondary distinction might come to assume
a logically prior position in the description of states. Firstly, many
early researchers were seeking "prime movers" rather than considering a
multivariant scheme. An inevitable consequence of this quest would be that
secondary states had to be relegated to "impure" status in order to study
the single cause which resulted in primary state formation. Inevitably,
cultural diffusionism came to be looked down upon as a secondary process,
unworthy of study. A second reason might be cultural arrogance; we do not,
for instance, often think of Anglo-Saxon state formation as a secondary
process, or somehow "contaminated". Just because the processes of state
formation among the Iroquois or the Zulus were relatively recent does not
deny their validity.
An important issue which most scholars have not raised is why, given
contact between large centralized states and smaller, non-state societies,
certain societies developed into states and others did not. Why did the
Zulus and Polynesians respond as they did, by evolving centralized political
institutions of their own? Why did other societies such as the Iroquois,
who were at the same "level" of evolution as the first two, not do so until
much later? And why did other areas, such as the Pacific Northwest, not
evolve states at all? It seems ridiculous to claim that all instances where
diffusion occurred should fall under the rubric of "secondary states". The
number of truly "pristine" formations is very small, perhaps as low as two
(see Wright and Johnson 1975). Why, then, do we insist on making much ado
about nothing by continuing to ignore the processes of state formation right
on our historical doorstep?
It is already very well-known among anthropologists that various
institutions and structures may take different forms when imposed on or
borrowed by societies to which those institutions are not native. Alan
Macfarlane discusses capitalist economics as a cultural creation of the
West, specifically England, in The Culture of Capitalism (Macfarlane 1992).
The creation of pseudo-Christian cargo cults in New Guinea is welldocumented, as are various forms of syncretic religion which derive from
contact between organized religions and the religious beliefs and traditions
of conquered and colonized peoples. There is no reason, then, other than
blind insistence on the existence of "pure" political forms, to argue that
the diffusion and/or imposition of state structures occurred in a pure, noncontested form.
The position taken by Barbara Price regarding secondary state
formation is quite close to my own. Price argues that secondary state

formation depends on a dialectic approach in which the relationship is not


simply one of the more complex society "imposing" the state upon the
simpler, but upon careful consideration of the conditions of both the state
and the non-state society, and the degree of contact between the two (Price
1978). However, where Price and I diverge is in her materialist assertion
that it is the amount of energy use of each society alone which determines
the resultant secondary state structure. For reasons I will detail below, I
believe that the situation in many secondary states is far more complex than
the expression of material factors. I will do so by considering two cases:
the Iroquois of the Great Lakes region of North America, and the Zulu of
southeastern Africa.
The evolution (or, more accurately, the homeostasis) of the Iroquois
has been well-documented by Bruce Trigger in a manner generally consistent
with a systems-information theory perspective. He notes that immediately
prior to and at the time of contact with Europeans, Iroquois society
possessed many of the necessary conditions for statehood: a great potential
for agricultural surplus production, the presence of warfare, long-distance
trade with and borrowing from more complex Mississippian peoples, and
concentrated villages under the control of chiefs (Trigger 1990: 124-127).
However, despite material conditions and stresses similar to those creating
states elsewhere, Iroquois society did not become significantly
differentiated during this period. Trigger attributes the non-emergence of
state structures to a concerted effort to maintain social equality through
censure of those seeking political gain, and through rewarding generosity
(1990: 136). The fact that "[t]he material benefits of chiefly office were
more than counter-balanced by its expenses" which included dispensing goods
ensured that those seeking political gain were discouraged from doing so
(Trigger 1990: 133). Only much later, when colonial rule was at its height
and the Iroquois found themselves under more circumscribed conditions and
engaged in large-scale wars, did state formation occur.(5)
From a systems perspective, it is evident that many factors ensured
homeostasis in the resultant political structure by means of negative
feedback. Trigger thus concludes that egalitarianism is not merely a
"default" option for societies, but must be explained, just as the creation
of states which result from the uncoupling or dissolution of such factors
require analysis (1990: 145). The example of the Iroquois is also
instructive in that ideological and cultural factors, presumably retained
from an earlier period, take precedence over material and ecological factors
which provide impetus towards social inequality into the system. It is
evident, then, that human social systems are not merely slaves to their
environment but have the potential to organize themselves along a variety of
ideological principles which help in determining the course of social
change.
In the case of Zulu state formation, a "successful" instance (meaning
only that a state was actually formed), the situation is quite different,
and yet the systemic principles involved are very much the same. Service
discusses the Zulu case briefly, noting that the personal traits of its
first ruler, Shaka Zulu, were of secondary importance to the more gradual
transformations in the politico-legal system (1975: 116). Stuart Romm, a
political scientist, re-examines the Zulu data in a systems-oriented light,
tracking the responses of various actors to changing military and political
conditions, culminating in the end of homeostasis and the formation of the
Zulu state. He argues that the eventual stabilization of Zulu rule under
Mpande, its third king, was a result of his willingness to compromise with

traditional chiefs, whereas his predecessors required brutal force and


coercion to maintain their positions (Romm 1986: 637).
The fundamental difference between the Iroquois and Zulu situation can
be equated directly with the question of positive and negative feedback.
Romm argues forcefully that pre-state polities "will be most subject to
these disequilibrating tendencies when economic, social, and military
conditions are such that actors of this nature are able to attract followers
and mobilize resources" (1986: 611). Since the Zulu kings Shaka, Dingane
and Mpande were able to revise the traditional chiefly ideologies in order
to gain power, the constraints on state formation were removed. The two
factors of personal military might and ideological considerations,
previously holding each other in check, become coupled and positive feedback
is the result. The conclusion that Romm reaches is inevitable: "one cannot
have 'just a little' sociopolitical change" (1986: 641). Of course, not all
instances of state formation are as rapid as the Zulu case, which was
hastened by other factors such as the British and Boer colonizers.
Although both the Iroquois and Zulu cases of political evolution (or
its absence) are "secondary" formations, both show the remarkable properties
of systems in the same way as detailed by systems theorists such as
Flannery. Furthermore, with the cumbersome requirement of a single prime
mover discarded, it is possible to re-integrate diffusion as a legitimate
source of cultural evolution. My proposition, therefore, is this: The
distinction between primary and secondary states, if it is to be retained,
must be reduced in importance and its weight considered in all cases of
state formation. In systemic terms, diffusion from states or responses to
contact with states provide impetus for structural change to the initial
conditions of the system. Whether there is positive feedback (probably
leading to a state) or negative feedback (inertial forces preventing state
formation) depends on the initial system under consideration, the nature and
degree of unbalancing forces, and the interaction of the two. The
structural change which occurs may then be considered a new set of "initial
conditions" so to speak, upon which the evolutionary process may work.(6)

VI.

Conclusion:

Implications for Future State Research

Time is a sort of river of passing events, and strong is


the current; no sooner is a thing brought to sight than it is
swept by and another takes its place, and this too will be swept
away.
Marcus Aurelius, Meditations IV, 43
Throughout this paper, I have traced the construction of four
fundamental illusions regarding state formation. I have also, I hope, shown
that despite these illusions, there is a process of social evolution which
exists at the core of them all. If I have succeeded, the illusions should
be stripped away, bringing us closer to an understanding of the processes
that have constrained and governed the evolution of all societies, and which
still continue to act upon them today. It would, of course be overly
arrogant to claim that I have not at the same time constructed my own
illusions; much work needs to be done before state formation can be
resuscitated from its dormant state.

I have indicated that the fundamental complexity of all political


systems prohibits their reduction to a small number of categories in which
one or a few scenarios lead to the development of the state as the
"pinnacle" of human political evolution. Instead, we should recognize that
the same processes that occurred in the past continue to operate now, both
upon small-scale and industrial states, albeit in a greatly modified form.
Is it possible that we will someday refer to the state as just one of many
stages in the evolution of societies? The question of what such a future
"post-state" might look like is one for the astrologer, not the
anthropologist. Nevertheless, Western societies should recognize that they
too are embedded in these historical processes.
I am certainly not the first to suggest that all universal models of
state formation are grossly oversimplified; most scholars, I suspect, regard
this sort of theoretical simplicity as wrong. Nevertheless, the trend among
some scholars to consider only what can be found in the archaeological
record as potential causes has led to a sort of "methodological"
simplification that I contend is entirely unnecessary. Rather than
searching for "pure" or "pristine" states in the earth, I offer that it may
be equally profitable (albeit in a different manner) to study the "messy"
states of the historical and ethnographic record. While the situation
thereby becomes muddled with regards to state formation, we should avoid
oversimplifying a topic simply due to an outdated notion of the purity of
earlier times. Historical events, "Great Men" (and Great Women), kinship
structures, and other elements may all have played important roles in
determining the course of any particular society's political evolution. If
we are to reject any of these, it should not be because we cannot find them
in the earth but because we cannot find room for them in our model of state
formation.
It may be that ethnographic study of modern states is no longer a
viable alternative to archaeology, inasmuch as all human social systems are
now under the control of Western-style state structures. However, it is
inevitable, insofar as archaeologists recognize prehistoric states as human
systems, that some degree of analogy will always be required between living
human societies and the archaeological record. In this respect, I am in
agreement with Gledhill (1988: 24), who asserts that the problems inherent
in creating such comparisons "may not preclude archaeologists from
continuing to draw insights about process from ethnographic and
ethnohistorical cases, if we handle such analogies with greater care". I
would go further and suggest that the invisibility of certain elements in
the archaeological record has caused their role in societies to be
overlooked, emphasizing instead what has survived the tests of time. If
this is the case, then it is essential that we examine modern societies of
all degrees of political complexity in an attempt to create meaningful
dialogue between the sub-disciplines of archaeology and ethnology on the
nature of the state.
While there have certainly been many errors committed by early state
theorists, many of these do not pose insurmountable barriers to the
discernment of patterns of long-term directional social change. We must
gain a clearer understanding, not only of the descriptive characteristics of
complex polities, but also of the interrelated causal factors - ecology,
warfare, trade, ritual, kinship, cultural diffusion, personal achievement,
and others - which lead to their creation. Anthropologists should come to
recognize the systemic features of societies so that the process of their

evolution can be understood more fully. Above all, however, human systems
must be recognized as historical systems, in which the initial conditions of
the system play a key role in constraining its structural change. We must
cease our search for the "pristine" or "pure" state of the past, which
probably never existed, and look at the real examples around us. It is
essential to examine societies of particular examples of these constraints
in action, so that we may not fall off the thin ledge between excessive
particularism and radical determinism. Rather than rejecting the
evolutionary paradigm altogether, a critical examination of its failures and
shortcomings can thus lead to a greater understanding of its relevance for
contemporary theory.

Notes
(1) Unlike Service (1975: 23), I do not regard Machiavelli
solely as an early "coercion theorist", for he does recognize
the need for the prince to have the consent of his subjects in
many circumstances.
(2) Such insistence on the creation of state "templates" which
are imposed upon and eliminate earlier settlement patterns has
been successfully refuted by Nocete (1994) with regards to
locational analysis such as Central Place Theory.
(3) Of course, social evolution in no way negates the
possibility of no change in complexity - "stagnation", for lack
of a better term, or societal collapse or "devolution". As I
show later, these instances are useful in the study of the
evolutionary process and, in fact, the exceptions prove the
rule that societies tend to increase in complexity.
(4) I do not include the "structural Marxists" such as
Friedman and Godelier in this camp, for many scholars
influenced by Marxist thought emphasize material factors along
with ideological and cultural factors in state formation.
(5) This occurrence would be an instance of negative feedback,
since the newly introduced structure would tend to reduce the
deviation caused by the initial condition of circumscription.
(6) The reader may note certain similarities between this
approach and the Hegelian dialectic (thesis + antithesis =
synthesis), with each instance of change producing a new set of
initial conditions.

Works Cited

Athens, J. Stephen
1977
Theory Building and the Study of Evolutionary Process

in Complex Societies. In For Theory Building in


Archaeology, edited by Lewis R. Binford, 353-384.
New York: Academic Press.
Boserup, Ester
1965
The Conditions of Agricultural Growth. Chicago: Aldine.
Buckley, Walter
1967
Sociology and Modern Systems Theory.
NJ: Prentice-Hall.

Englewood Cliffs,

Carneiro, Robert
1967
"On the Relationship Between Size of Population and
Complexity of Social Organization", Southwestern Journal
of Anthropology, 23: 234-243.
Carneiro, Robert
1970
"A Theory of the Origin of the State", Science 169:
733-738.
Carneiro, Robert
1978
Political Expansion as an Expression of the Principle of
Competitive Exclusion. In Origins of the State: The
Anthropology of Political Evolution, edited by Ronald
Cohen and Elman R. Service, 205-233. Philadelphia:
Institute for the Study of Human Issues.
Claessen, Henri J.M.
1978
The Early State: A Structural Approach. In The Early
State, edited by Henri J.M. Claessen and Peter Skalnk,
533-596. The Hague: Mouton.
Cohen, Ronald
1978

State Origins: A Reappraisal. In The Early State, edited


by Henri J.M. Claessen and Peter Skalnk, 31-76. The
Hague: Mouton.

Flannery, Kent
1972
"The Cultural Evolution of Civilizations", Annual Review
of Ecology and Systematics 3: 399-426.
Fried, Morton
1967

The Evolution of Political Society: An Essay in


Political Anthropology. New York: Random House.

Friedman, Jonathan
1975
Tribes, States and Transformations. In Marxist Analyses
and Social Anthropology, edited by Maurice Bloch, 161202. London: Tavistock.
Gall, Patricia and Arthur A. Saxe
1977
The Ecological Evolution of Culture. In Exchange
Systems in Prehistory, edited by Timothy Earle and
Jonathon E. Ericson, 255-268. New York: Academic
Press.
Gledhill, John

1988

Introduction: the comparative analysis of social and


political transitions. In State and Society, edited
by John Gledhill, Barbara Bender and Mogens Trolle
Larsen, 1-32. London: Unwin Hyman.

Gould, Stephen Jay


1980
The Panda's Thumb.

New York: W.W. Norton.

Gould, Stephen Jay


1992
Bully for Brontosaurus.

New York: W.W. Norton.

Haas, Jonathan
1982
The Evolution of the Prehistoric State.
Columbia University Press.

New York:

Harris, Marvin
1977
Cannibals and Kings: The Origins of Cultures.
Random House.
Hill, Jack
1994

New York:

"Biology, Prestige and the Origin of States", Journal of


Social and Evolutionary Systems 17(2): 213-225.

Hutterer, Karl L.
1991
Losing Track of the Tribes: Evolutionary Sequences in
Southeast Asia. In Profiles in Cultural Evolution,
edited by A. Terry Rambo and Kathleen Gillogly, 219-246.
Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.
Keegan, William F. and Morgan
1989
"The Evolution
Reconstruction
Anthropologist

D. Maclachlan
of Avunculocal Chiefdoms: A
of Taino Politics and Kinship", American
91: 613-630.

Khazanov, Anatolii
1978
Some Theoretical Problems of the Study of the Early
State. In The Early State, edited by H.J.M. Claessen and
Peter Skalnk, 77-92. The Hague: Mouton.
Khazanov, Anatolii
1985
Rank Society or Rank Societies: Processes, Stages and
Types of Evolution. In Development and Decline, edited
by H.J.M. Claessen et al., 82-96. South Hadley, MA:
Bergin & Garvey.
Kristiansen, Kristian
1991
Chiefdoms, States and Systems of Social Evolution. In
Chiefdoms: Power, Economy and Ideology, edited by
Timothy K. Earle, 16-43. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Macfarlane, Alan
1987
The Culture of Capitalism.

Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

Maisels, Charles Keith


1987
"Models of Social Evolution: Trajectories from the
Neolithic to the State", Man (NS) 22: 331-359.

Masters, Roger D.
1982
"Evolutionary biology, political theory and the state",
Journal of Social and Biological Structures 5: 439-450.
Naroll, Raoul and William T. Divale
1976
"Natural selection in cultural evolution: warfare versus
peaceful diffusion", American Ethnologist 3: 97-128.
Nocete, Francisco
1994
"Space as Coercion: The Transition to the State in the
Social Formations of La Campina, Upper Guadalquivir
Valley, Spain, ca. 1900-1600 B.C.", Journal of
Anthropological Archaeology 13: 171-200.
Patterson, Thomas C.
1991
The Inca Empire: The Formation and Disintegration of a
Pre-Capitalist State. New York: Berg.
Price, Barbara J.
1978
Secondary State Formation: An Explanatory Model. In
Origins of the State: The Anthropology of Political
Evolution, edited by Ronald Cohen and Elman R. Service.
Philadelphia: Institute for the Study of Human Issues.
Rambo, A. Terry
1991
The Study of Cultural Evolution. In Profiles in Cultural
Evolution, edited by A. T. Rambo and Kathleen Gillogly,
23-112. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.
Rappaport, Roy A.
1977
Maladaptation in Social Systems. In The Evolution of
Social Systems, edited by J. Friedman and M.J. Rowlands,
49-72. London: Duckworth.
Romm, Stuart
1986

"Political conflict, role differentiation and state


formation: a case study of the Zulus", Social Science
Information 25(3): 607-645.

Rousseau, Jerome
1985
The Ideological Prerequisites of Inequality. In
Development and Decline, edited by H.J.M. Claessen
et al., 36-45. South Hadley, MA: Bergin & Garvey.
Service, Elman R.
1962
Primitive Social Organization: An Evolutionary
Perspective. New York: Random House.
Service, Elman R.
1975
Origins of the State and Civilization.
W.W. Norton.

New York:

Spencer, Charles
1990
"On the Tempo and Mode of State Formation: NeoEvolutionism Reconsidered", Journal of Anthropological
Archaeology 9(1): 1-30.

Tosi, Maurizio
1976
"The Dialectics of State Formation in Mesopotamia,
Iran and Central Asia", Dialectical Anthropology 1:
173-185.
Trigger, Bruce
1985
Generalized Coercion and Inequality: The Basis of State
Power in the Early Civilizations. In Development and
Decline, edited by H.J.M. Claessen et al., 46-61.
South Hadley, MA: Bergin & Garvey.
Trigger, Bruce
1990
Maintaining Economic Equality in Opposition to
Complexity: An Iroquoian Case Study. In The Evolution
of Political Systems, edited by Steadman Upham, 119-145.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Upham, Steadman
1990
Analog Or Digital? In The Evolution of Political
Systems, edited by Steadman Upham, 87-115. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Webster, David
1975
"Warfare and the Evolution of the State: A
Reconsideration", American Antiquity 40(4): 464-470.
Wright, Henry T. and Gregory A. Johnson
1975
"Population, Exchange and Early State Formation in
Southwestern Iran", American Anthropologist 77: 267-289.

Copyright 1997 Steve Chrisomalis. This paper may be copied for personal
use and evaluation only, and may not be retransmitted or published without
the author's permission. Links to this page may be made freely. Any
comments made on this paper may be posted here in whole or in part with
the commenter's name and e-mail address.
Return to the Phrontistery

You might also like