You are on page 1of 21

Venn Diagram Technique for testing

syllogisms
We have used two-circle Venn diagrams
to represent standard-form categorical
propositions. In order to test a
categorical syllogism by the method of
Venn diagrams, one must first represent
both of its premises in one diagram.
That will require drawing three
overlapping circles, for the two premises
of a standard-form syllogism contain
three different terms-minor term, major
term, and middle term.

Lets start with this example:


No doctors are professional wrestlers.
All cardiologists are doctors.
No cardiologists are professional wrestlers.
Since this argument, like all standard-form
categorical syllogisms, has three category-terms
(in this case, cardiologists, professional
wrestlers, and doctors), we need three
interlocking circles rather than two to represent
the three categories. The minor term will go on
the top left, the major term will go on the the top
right, and the middle term will be the bottom
circle.

The diagram for our example is as follows:

The first premise states that no doctors are


professional wrestlers. To represent this claim, we
shade that part of the Doctors circle that overlaps
with the Professional wrestlers circle, as follows:

The second premise states that all cardiologists are


doctors. To represent this claim, we shade that
part of the Cardiologists circle that does not
overlap with the Doctors circle:

We now have all the information we need to see


whether the argument is valid. The conclusion
tells us that no cardiologists are professional
wrestlers. This means that the area where the
Cardiologists and Professional wrestlers circles
overlap is shaded, that is, empty. We look at the
diagram to see if the area is shaded, and we see
that it is indeed shaded. That means that the
conclusion is implicitly contained in (i.e.
follows logically from) the premises. Thus, the
argument is shown to be valid.

Lets look at a second example:


All snakes are reptiles.
All reptiles are cold-blooded animals.
All snakes are cold-blooded animals.

Next, we diagram the first premise. The premise


states that all snakes are reptiles. We represent
this information by shading the area of the Snakes
circle that does not overlap with the Reptiles
circle.

Next, we diagram the second premise. The second


premise states that all reptiles are cold-blooded
animals. We represent this claim by shading that
part of the Reptiles circle that does not overlap
with the Cold-blooded animals circle.

Finally, we look to see if the information


contained in the conclusion is depicted in the
diagram. The conclusion tells us that all snakes
are cold-blooded animals. This means that the
part of the Snakes circle that does not overlap with
the Cold-blooded animals circle should be
completely shaded. Inspection of the diagram
shows that this is indeed the case. So, the
argument is valid.

Lets look at a third example:


Some Baptists are coffee-lovers.
All Baptists are Protestants.
Some Protestants are coffee-lovers.
Notice that this example includes two some
statements. Diagramming some statements is a
little trickier than diagramming all or no
statements. As we have seen, some statements
are diagrammed by placing Xs rather than by
shading. Most mistakes in Venn diagramming
involve incorrect placement of an X.

To avoid such mistakes, remember the following


rules:
1. If the argument contains one all or no
statement, this statement should be diagrammed
first. In other words, always do any necessary
shading before placing an X. If the argument
contains two all or no statements, either
statement can be done first.
2. When placing an X in the area, if one part of the
area has been shaded, place the X in the unshaded
part. Examples:
x

3. When placing an X in an area, if one part of the


area has not been shaded, place the X precisely
on the line separating the two parts. Example:

Back to the third example:


Some Baptists are coffee-lovers
All Baptists are Protestants.
Some Protestants are coffee-lovers.
First, we draw and label our three circles:

Next, we need to decide which premise to diagram


first. Should it be the some premise or the all
premise? Rule one states that we should start with
the all premise:

Now we can diagram the first premise, which


states that some Baptists are coffee-lovers. To
represent this claim, we place an X in the area of
the Baptists circle that overlaps with the Coffeelovers circle. Part of this area, however, is shaded.
This means that there is nothing in that area. For
that reason, we place the X in the unshaded
portion of the Baptists circle that overlaps with the
Coffee-lovers circle, as follows:

Finally, we inspect the completed diagram to see if


the information contained in the conclusion is
represented in the diagram. The conclusion states
that some Protestants are coffee-lovers. This
means that there should be an X in the area of the
Protestants circle that overlaps with the Coffeelovers circle. A glance at the diagram show that
there is an X in this area. Thus, the argument is
valid.

So far, all the categorical syllogisms we have


looked at have been valid. But Venn diagrams can
also show when a categorical syllogism is invalid.
Here is one example:
All painters are artists.
Some magicians are artists.
Some magicians are painters.
First, we draw and label our three circles:

Since the premise begins with all and the second


premise begins with some, we diagram the first
premise first. The first premise states that all
painters are artists. To depict this claim, we shade
that part of the Painters circle that does not
overlap with the Artists circle:

Next, we enter the information of the second


premise, the claim that some magicians are artists.
To represent this claim, we place an X in that
portion of the Magicians circle that overlaps with
the Artists circle. That area, however, is divided
into two parts (the areas here marked 1 and 2),
and we have no information that warrants placing
the X in one of these areas rather than the other.
In such cases, we place the X precisely on the line
between the two sections, as follows:

The X on the line means that we have no way of


knowing from the information given whether the
magician-who-is-an-artist is also a magician-whois-a-painter.
The conclusion states that some magicians are
painters. This means that there should be an X
that is definitely in the area where the Magicians
and Painters overlap. There is an X in the
Magicians circle, but it dangles on the line
between the Artists circle and the Painters circle.
We dont know whether it is inside or outside the
Painters circle. For that reason, the argument is
invalid.

You might also like