You are on page 1of 6

3/9/2015

Infinity (philosophy) - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Infinity (philosophy)
From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

In philosophy, infinity can be attributed to infinite dimensions, as for instance in Kant's first antinomy.
In both theology and philosophy, infinity is explored in articles such as the Ultimate, the Absolute, God,
and Zeno's paradoxes. In Greek philosophy, for example in Anaximander, 'the Boundless' is the origin of
all that is. He took the beginning or rst principle to be an endless, unlimited primordial mass (,
apeiron). In Judeo-Christian theology, for example in the work of theologians such as Duns Scotus, the
infinite nature of God invokes a sense of being without constraint, rather than a sense of being unlimited
in quantity. In ethics infinity plays an important role designating that which cannot be defined or
reduced to knowledge or power.

Contents
1 History
1.1 Early Indian views of infinity
1.2 Early European views of infinity
1.3 Views from the Renaissance to modern times
1.4 Modern philosophical views
1.5 Ethics
2 Three types of infinities
3 Structure of infinity, examples from metaphysics
4 Notes and references
5 Other references

History
Early Indian views of infinity
The Isha Upanishad of the Yajurveda (c. 4th to 3rd century BC) states that "if you remove a part from
infinity [pra] or add a part to infinity, still what remains is infinity".
The Jain mathematical text Surya Prajnapti (c. 400 BC) classifies all numbers into three sets:
enumerable, innumerable, and infinite. Each of these was further subdivided into three orders:
Enumerable: lowest, intermediate and highest
Innumerable: nearly innumerable, truly innumerable and innumerably innumerable
Infinite: nearly infinite, truly infinite, infinitely infinite
The Jains were the first to discard the idea that all infinites were the same or equal. They recognized
different types of infinities: infinite in length (one dimension), infinite in area (two dimensions), infinite
in volume (three dimensions), and infinite perpetually (infinite number of dimensions).

http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Infinity_%28philosophy%29

1/6

3/9/2015

Infinity (philosophy) - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

According to Singh (1987), Joseph (2000) and Agrawal (2000), the highest enumerable number N of the
Jains corresponds to the modern concept of aleph-null
(the cardinal number of the infinite set of
integers 1, 2, ...), the smallest cardinal transfinite number. The Jains also defined a whole system of
infinite cardinal numbers, of which the highest enumerable number N is the smallest.
In the Jaina work on the theory of sets, two basic types of infinite numbers are distinguished. On both
physical and ontological grounds, a distinction was made between asakhyta ("countless,
innumerable") and ananta ("endless, unlimited"), between rigidly bounded and loosely bounded
infinities.

Early European views of infinity


In Europe the traditional view derives from Aristotle:

... It is always possible to think of a larger number: for the number of times a
magnitude can be bisected is infinite. Hence the infinite is potential, never actual; the
number of parts that can be taken always surpasses any assigned number.
Physics 207b8

This is often called potential infinity; however there are two ideas mixed up with this. One is that it is
always possible to find a number of things that surpasses any given number, even if there are not
actually such things. The other is that we may quantify over infinite sets without restriction. For
example,
, which reads, "for any integer n, there exists an
integer m > n such that P(m)". The second view is found in a clearer form by medieval writers such as
William of Ockham:

Sed omne continuum est actualiter existens. Igitur quaelibet pars sua est vere existens
in rerum natura. Sed partes continui sunt infinitae quia non tot quin plures, igitur
partes infinitae sunt actualiter existentes.
But every continuum is actually existent. Therefore any of its parts is really existent in
nature. But the parts of the continuum are infinite because there are not so many that
there are not more, and therefore the infinite parts are actually existent.

The parts are actually there, in some sense. However, on this view, no infinite magnitude can have a
number, for whatever number we can imagine, there is always a larger one: "There are not so many (in
number) that there are no more." Aquinas also argued against the idea that infinity could be in any sense
complete, or a totality.

Views from the Renaissance to modern times


Galileo was the first to notice that we can place an infinite set into one-to-one correspondence with one
of its proper subsets (any part of the set, that is not the whole). For example, we can match up the set of
square numbers {1, 4, 9, 16, ...} with the natural numbers {1, 2, 3, 4, ...} as follows:

http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Infinity_%28philosophy%29

2/6

3/9/2015

Infinity (philosophy) - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

11
24
39
4 16

It appeared, by this reasoning, as though a set which is naturally smaller than the set of which it is a part
(since it does not contain all the members of that set) is in some sense the same "size". Galileo thought
this was one of the difficulties which arise when we try, "with our finite minds," to comprehend the
infinite.

So far as I see we can only infer that the totality of all numbers is infinite, that the
number of squares is infinite, and that the number of their roots is infinite; neither is the
number of squares less than the totality of all numbers, nor the latter greater than the
former; and finally the attributes "equal," "greater," and "less," are not applicable to
infinite, but only to finite, quantities.
On two New Sciences, 1638

The idea that size can be measured by one-to-one correspondence is today known as Hume's principle,
although Hume, like Galileo, believed the principle could not be applied to infinite sets.
(Mathematicians from the time of Georg Cantor do apply the principle to infinite sets, and do have a
notion of some infinite quantities being greater than others.)
Locke, in common with most of the empiricist philosophers, also believed that we can have no proper
idea of the infinite. They believed all our ideas were derived from sense data or "impressions," and since
all sensory impressions are inherently finite, so too are our thoughts and ideas. Our idea of infinity is
merely negative or privative.

Whatever positive ideas we have in our minds of any space, duration, or number, let
them be never so great, they are still finite; but when we suppose an inexhaustible
remainder, from which we remove all bounds, and wherein we allow the mind an
endless progression of thought, without ever completing the idea, there we have our
idea of infinity... yet when we would frame in our minds the idea of an infinite space or
duration, that idea is very obscure and confused, because it is made up of two parts
very different, if not inconsistent. For let a man frame in his mind an idea of any space
or number, as great as he will, it is plain the mind rests and terminates in that idea;
which is contrary to the idea of infinity, which consists in a supposed endless
progression.
Essay, II. xvii. 7., author's emphasis

Famously, the ultra-empiricist Hobbes tried to defend the idea of a potential infinity in light of the
discovery, by Evangelista Torricelli, of a figure (Gabriel's Horn) whose surface area is infinite, but
whose volume is finite. Not reported, this motivation of Hobbes came too late as curves having infinite
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Infinity_%28philosophy%29

3/6

3/9/2015

Infinity (philosophy) - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

length yet bounding finite areas were known much before. Such seeming paradoxes are resolved by
taking any finite figure and stretching its content infinitely in one direction; the magnitude of its content
is unchanged as its divisions drop off geometrically but the magnitude of its bounds increases to infinity
by necessity. Potentiality lies in the definitions of this operation, as well-defined and interconsistent
mathematical axioms. A potential infinity is allowed by letting an infinitely-large quantity be cancelled
out by an infinitely-small quantity.

Modern philosophical views


Modern discussion of the infinite is now regarded as part of set theory and mathematics. This discussion
is generally avoided by philosophers. An exception was Wittgenstein, who made an impassioned attack
upon axiomatic set theory, and upon the idea of the actual infinite, during his "middle period".[1]

Does the relation


correlate the class of all numbers with one of its
subclasses? No. It correlates any arbitrary number with another, and in that way we
arrive at infinitely many pairs of classes, of which one is correlated with the other, but
which are never related as class and subclass. Neither is this infinite process itself in
some sense or other such a pair of classes... In the superstition that
correlates
a class with its subclass, we merely have yet another case of ambiguous grammar.
Philosophical Remarks 141, cf Philosophical Grammar p. 465

Unlike the traditional empiricists, he thought that the infinite was in some way given to sense
experience.

... I can see in space the possibility of any finite experience... we recognise [the]
essential infinity of space in its smallest part." "[Time] is infinite in the same sense as
the three-dimensional space of sight and movement is infinite, even if in fact I can only
see as far as the walls of my room.

... what is infinite about endlessness is only the endlessness itself.

Ethics
The philosopher Emmanuel Levinas uses infinity to designate that which cannot be defined or reduced
to knowledge or power. In Levinas' magnum opus Totality and Infinity he says:

...infinity is produced in the relationship of the same with the other, and how the
particular and the personal, which are unsurpassable, as it were magnetize the very field
in which the production of infinity is enacted...
The idea of infinity is not an incidental notion forged by a subjectivity to reflect the
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Infinity_%28philosophy%29

4/6

3/9/2015

Infinity (philosophy) - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

case of an entity encountering on the outside nothing that limits it, overflowing every
limit, and thereby infinite. The production of the infinite entity is inseparable from the
idea of infinity, for it is precisely in the disproportion between the idea of infinity and
the infinity of which it is the idea that this exceeding of limits is produced. The idea of
infinity is the mode of being, the infinition, of infinity... All knowing qua intentionality
already presupposes the idea of infinity, which is preeminently non-adequation.
p. 26-27

Three types of infinities


Besides the mathematical infinity and the physical infinity, there could also be a philosophical infinity.
There are scientists who hold that all three really exist and there are scientists who hold that none of the
three exists. And in between there are the various possibilities. Rudy Rucker, in his book Infinity and the
Mindthe Science and Philosophy of the Infinite (1982), has worked out a model list of representatives
of each of the eight possible standpoints. The footnote on p.335 of his book suggests the consideration
of the following names: Abraham Robinson, Plato, Thomas Aquinas, L.E.J. Brouwer, David Hilbert,
Bertrand Russell, Kurt Gdel and Georg Cantor.

Structure of infinity, examples from metaphysics


Eternity: linguistically the opposite of finite, having no edges, limits, an end: How deep is the sky?
How can I write down the largest possible number?
Indefinite: How could God be sure that there is no-one greater?
Circularity: The line defining a circle does not have an end.
Recursion: See semantic satiation for instance. Lack of utter reason. Why is that? Apparently, a
relevant question after any answer.

Notes and references


1. ^ See also "Logic of antinomies" (http://projecteuclid.org/euclid.ndjfl/1093891610). Retrieved July 9, 2010.

Other references
D. P. Agrawal (2000). Ancient Jaina Mathematics: an Introduction
(http://www.infinityfoundation.com/mandala/t_es/t_es_agraw_jaina.htm), Infinity Foundation
(http://infinityfoundation.com).
L. C. Jain (1973). "Set theory in the Jaina school of mathematics", Indian Journal of History of
Science.
George G. Joseph (2000). The Crest of the Peacock: Non-European Roots of Mathematics (2nd
edition ed.). Princeton University Press. ISBN0-14-027778-1.
O'Connor, John J.; Robertson, Edmund F., "Jaina mathematics" (http://www-history.mcs.standrews.ac.uk/HistTopics/Jaina_mathematics.html), MacTutor History of Mathematics archive,
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Infinity_%28philosophy%29

5/6

3/9/2015

Infinity (philosophy) - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

University of St Andrews.
Ian Pearce (2002). 'Jainism' (http://www-history.mcs.standrews.ac.uk/history/Projects/Pearce/Chapters/Ch5.html), MacTutor History of Mathematics
archive.
N. Singh (1988). 'Jaina Theory of Actual Infinity and Transfinite Numbers', Journal of Asiatic
Society, Vol. 30.
Retrieved from "http://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Infinity_(philosophy)&oldid=638516096"
Categories: Concepts in metaphysics Infinity
This page was last modified on 17 December 2014, at 17:10.
Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License; additional terms
may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia is a
registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.

http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Infinity_%28philosophy%29

6/6

You might also like