You are on page 1of 16

Journal of Economic Literature

Vol. XLI (December 2003) pp. 12401255

Sraffa, Wittgenstein, and Gramsci


AMARTYA SEN1

1. Introduction philosophy, namely Ludwig Wittgensteins


momentous movement from his early
When, in February this year, the Acca-
position in Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus
demia Nazionale dei Lincei had a large con-
(Wittgenstein 1921) to the later Philosophical
ference in Rome on the twentieth
Investigations (Wittgenstein 1951).4
anniversary of the death of Piero Sraffa,2
The economist Sraffa is often separated
they were celebrating the memory of an
out from his other roles. This is partly
extraordinary intellectual, one who published
because Sraffa was professionally an econo-
remarkably little but significantly influenced
mist, but also because his economic contri-
contemporary economics, philosophy, and the
butions seem, at least superficially, to stand
social sciences. Sraffas intellectual impact
apart from his philosophical ideas. Even
includes several new explorations in econ-
though he published only a few articles and
omic theory, including a reassessment of the
one book, apart from editing David
history of political economy (starting with the
Ricardos works, Sraffa is also a much-cited
work of David Ricardo).3 He also had a criti-
author in economics. 5 His economic contri-
cally important influence in bringing about
butions, particularly his one book,
one of the major departures in contemporary
Production of Commodities by Means of
Commodities: Prelude to a Critique of
1
2
Sen: Trinity College. Economic Theory (Sraffa 1960), have gener-
Piero Sraffa: Convegno Internazionale, Accademia ated major controversies in economics.
Nazionale dei Lincei, February 1112, 2003. This essay
draws on a longer essay (Piero Sraffa: A Students Sraffas works initiated a substantial school
Perspective) presented there, which will be published by of thought in economic theory, and yet other
the Accademia. For helpful discussions over many years, I economists have argued that there is nothing
am greatly indebted to Kenneth Arrow, Kaushik Basu,
Christopher Bliss, Nick Denyer, Maurice Dobb, much of substance in his writings, and still
Pierangelo Garegnani, Frank Hahn, Geoff Harcourt, John others (most notably Paul Samuelson) have
Hicks, Heinz Kurz, Brian McGuinness, James Mirrlees,
Robert Nozick, Luigi Pasinetti, Suzy Payne, Hilary
4
Putnam, Joan Robinson, Emma Rothschild, Robert Solow, See also Wittgenstein (1953, 1958) for issues related
Luigi Spaventa, and Stefano Zamagni, and of course to to this transition.
5
Piero Sraffa himself. I am also grateful to the editor and See, for example, the widely used The New Palgrave:
referees of this journal for useful suggestions. A Dictionary of Economics (Eatwell, Milgate, and
3
On this see Pierangelo Garegnani (1960, 1998); Newman 1987). Books in English on Sraffas life and con-
Alessandro Roncaglia (1978, 1999); Luigi Pasinetti (1979, tributions include, among others, Ian Steedman (1977,
1988); Nicholas Kaldor (1984, 1985); John Eatwell and 1988); Roncaglia (1978); Jean-Pierre Potier (1987);
Carlo Panico (1987); Paul Samuelson (1987, 2000a,b); Schefold (1989); Krishna Bharadwaj and Bertram Schefold
Paolo Sylos Labini (1990); and Bertram Schefold (1996), (1990); Terenzio Cozzi and Roberto Marchionatti (2000);
among other writings. and Heinz Kurz (2000).

1240
Sen: Sraffa, Wittgenstein, and Gramsci 1241

argued that Sraffa is partly profound and Sraffa demonstrated that the foundations of
partly just wrong.6 ongoing price theory developed by Alfred
The temptation to examine the econo- Marshall (the leader of the then-dominant
mist Sraffa separately has certainly been Cambridge school) were incurably defec-
strong. And yet there is something to be tive. A significant extension of this essay in
gained from seeing Sraffas different contri- English appeared the next year in the
butions together. No less importantly for the Economic Journal (Sraffa 1926) and was
history of philosophical thought, it may be extremely influential.
important to reexamine Sraffas interactions Sraffa also had deep political interests
with Wittgenstein, whom Sraffa strongly and commitments, was active in the
influenced, in the light of Sraffas relation- Socialist Students Group, and joined the
ship with Antonio Gramsci, the Marxist theo- editorial team of LOrdine Nuovo, a leftist
rist, who had a strong influence on Sraffa. journal founded and edited by Antonio
Indeed, these dual relations also provide an Gramsci in 1919 (it would later be banned
opportunity to explore a possible Gramsci by the fascist government). Indeed, by the
connection in the transformation of early time Sraffa moved to Britain in 1927, he had
Wittgenstein into later Wittgenstein. become a substantial figure among Italian
leftist intellectuals, and was close tobut
not a member ofthe Italian Communist
2. Wittgenstein and Sraffa
Party, founded in 1921 and led by Gramsci.
Ludwig Wittgenstein returned to Trinity While Sraffa had obtained the position of
College, Cambridge, in January 1929, after lecturer at the University of Perugia in
having left Cambridge in 1913, where he 1923, and a professorship in Cagliari in
had been a student of Bertrand Russell. Sardinia in 1926, he considered a move to
Wittgensteins return was quite an event, Britain, as fascist persecution became
given his already established reputation as stronger in Italy.
a genius philosopher. John Maynard Already in 1922, Piero Sraffas father,
Keynes wrote to his wife, Lydia Lopokova: Angelo, who was the Rector of Bucconi
Well, God has arrived. I met him on the University, had received two telegrams from
5:15 train. Mussolini, demanding that Piero should
Piero Sraffa, who did not know Wittgen- retract a critical account of Italian financial
stein earlier, had moved to Cambridge from policies he had published in the Manchester
Italy a little over a year before Wittgensteins Guardian (as it happens, on John Maynard
return. Even though Sraffa was only 29 years Keyness invitation). It was spreading mis-
old at that time (he was born in Turin on trust and was an act of true and real sabo-
August 5th, 1898), he was already well- tage, Mussolini complained. Angelo Sraffa,
known in Britain and Italy as a highly origi- a courageous and resolute academic, replied
nal economist. He had obtained a research that the article stated only known facts and
degree, (testi de Laurea) from the University there was nothing in particular to be retract-
of Turin in late 1920, with a thesis on mone- ed. Piero Sraffa had several other alterca-
tary economics, but it was an article on the tions with the Italian government in the
foundations of price theory which he pub- years following, and warmed to an invitation
lished in 1925 in Annali di Economia (a jour- conveyed in a letter from John Maynard
nal based in Milan) that made him a major Keynes in January 1927 to take up a lecture-
celebrity in Italy and Britain. In this essay ship in Cambridge. He moved to Cambridge
in September that year. By the time
6
See Samuelson (1987, 2000a,b). See also Frank Hahn Wittgenstein returned to Cambridge in
(1982). January 1929, Sraffa had already established
1242 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XLI (December 2003)

a legendary reputation in Cambridge as one contribute to the meaning of our utterances


of the cleverest intellectuals around. and gestures.
The influence that Sraffa had on The conversations that Wittgenstein had
Wittgensteins thinking came through a with Sraffa were evidently quite momentous
series of regular conversations between the for Wittgenstein. He would later describe to
two.7 What form did the influence take? It Henrik von Wright, the distinguished
concerned a change in Wittgensteins philo- Finnish philosopher, that these conversa-
sophical approach in the years following tions made him feel like a tree from which
1929a change in which conversations with all branches have been cut. It is conven-
Sraffa evidently played a pivotal role. In his tional to divide Wittgensteins work between
early work (particularly in the Tractatus the early Wittgenstein and the later
Logico-Philosophicus), Wittgenstein used an Wittgenstein, and the year 1929 was clearly
approach that is sometimes called the pic- the dividing line separating the two phases.
ture theory of meaning, which sees a sen- Sraffa was not, in fact, the only critic with
tence as representing a state of affairs by whom Wittgenstein had to reckon. Frank
being a kind of a picture of it, mirroring the Ramsey, the youthful mathematical prodigy
structure of the state of affairs it portrays. in Cambridge, was another. Wittgenstein
There is an insistence hereit can be said at (1953, p. xe) thanked Ramsey, but recorded
the risk of some oversimplificationthat a that he was even more indebted to the crit-
proposition and what it describes must have icism that a teacher of this university, Mr. P.
the same logical form. Sraffa found this Sraffa, for many years unceasingly practised
philosophical position to be altogether erro- on my thoughts, adding that he was indebt-
neous, and argued with Wittgenstein on the ed to this stimulus for the most consequen-
need for him to rethink his position. tial ideas of this book.
According to a famous anecdote, Sraffa Wittgenstein told a friend (Rush Rhees,
responded to Wittgensteins claim by brush- another Cambridge philosopher) that the
ing his chin with his fingertips, which is most important thing that Sraffa taught him
apparently readily understood as a was an anthropological way of seeing
Neapolitan gesture of skepticism, and then philosophical problems. In his insightful
asked, What is the logical form of this? analysis of the influence of Sraffa and Freud,
Sraffa (whom, later on, I had the privilege Brian McGuinness (1982) discusses the
of knowing wellfirst as a student and then impact on Wittgenstein of the ethnological
as a colleagueat Trinity College, or anthropological way of looking at things
Cambridge) insisted that this account, if not that came to him from the economist Sraffa
entirely apocryphal (I cant remember such (pp. 3639). While the Tractatus tries to see
a specific occasion), was more of a tale with language in isolation from the social circum-
a moral than an actual event (I argued with stances in which it is used, the Philosophical
Wittgenstein so often and so much that my Investigations emphasizes the conventions
fingertips did not need to do much talk- and rules that give the utterances particular
ing). But the story does illustrate graphi- meaning. The connection of this perspective
cally the nature of Sraffas skepticism of the with what came to be known as ordinary
philosophy outlined in the Tractatus, and in language philosophy is easy to see.
particular how social conventions could The skepticism that is conveyed by the
Neapolitan brushing of chin with fingertips
7 (even when done by a Tuscan boy from Pisa,
On this see Brian McGuinness (1982); Ray Monk
(1991); Paolo Albani (1998); and John Davis (2002), among born in Turin) can be interpreted only in
other writings. terms of established rules and conventions
Sen: Sraffa, Wittgenstein, and Gramsci 1243

indeed the stream of lifein the philosopher. When I arrived in Trinity in the
Neapolitan world. Wittgenstein (1953, p. 5e) early fifties as a student, shortly after
used the expression language-game to Wittgensteins death, I was aware that there
illustrate how people learn the use of lan- had been something of a rift between the
guage and the meaning of words and ges- two. In response to my questions, Sraffa was
tures (even though, ultimately, there is much most reluctant to go into what actually hap-
more in any actual language than what can pened. I had to stop our regular conversa-
be seen as just language-games). tionsI was somewhat bored, was the
closest to an account I ever obtained. The
We can also think of the whole process of using events were described, however, by Ray
word as one of those games by means of
Monk (1991), in rather greater detail, in his
which children learn their native language. I will
call these games language games and will biography of Wittgenstein (p. 487):
sometimes speak of a primitive language as a
language game. In May 1946 Piero Sraffa decided he no longer
wished to have conversations with Wittgenstein,
saying that he could no longer give his time and
attention to the matters Wittgenstein wished to
3. Reservation and Rift discuss. This came as a great blow to
Wittgenstein. He pleaded with Sraffa to contin-
Was Sraffa thrilled by the impact that his ue their weekly conversations, even if it meant
ideas had on, arguably, the leading philoso- staying away from philosophical subjects. I will
pher of our times (the God whom Keynes talk about anything, he told him. Yes, Sraffa
met on the 5:15 train)? Also, how did Sraffa replied, but in your way.
arrive at those momentous ideas in the first
place? I asked Sraffa those questions more There are many puzzling things in the
than once in the regular afternoon walks I Sraffa-Wittgenstein relations. How could
had the opportunity to share with him Sraffa, who loved dialogues and arguments,
between 1958 and 1963. I got somewhat become so reluctant to talk with one of the
puzzling answers. No, he was not particu- finest minds of the twentieth century? Even
larly thrilled, since the point he was making initially, how could the conversations that
was rather obvious. No, he did not know were clearly so consequential for
precisely how he arrived at those argu- Wittgenstein, which made him feel like a
ments, sinceagainthe point he was tree from which all branches have been cut,
making was rather obvious. seem rather obvious to this economist
Sraffa was very fond of Wittgenstein and from Tuscany? I doubt that we shall ever be
admired him greatly.8 But it was clear that sure of knowing the answers to these ques-
he was not convinced of the fruitfulness of tions. As far as the later rift is concerned,
conversing ceaselessly with the genius Sraffa might have been put off by
Wittgensteins domineering manners (carica-
8
Wittgenstein not only admired Sraffa, but also relied tured in a poem of a student, Julian Bell, the
on Sraffa for the safekeeping of some of his philosophical son of Clive Bell: who, on any issue, ever
papers. Sraffa wrote to von Wright, on August 27, 1958
(copy of letter in Sraffas handwriting in the Wren Library saw/ Ludwig refrain from laying down the
of Trinity College): law?/ In every company he shouts us down,/
On comparing my copy of the Blue Book [of And stops our sentence stuttering his own).
Wittgenstein] with the recently published edition
[Wittgenstein 1958] I find that it contains a number of Sraffa might have also been exasperated
small corrections in Wittgensteins handwriting which by Wittgensteins political naivete. Sraffa
have not been taken into account in the printed ver- had to restrain Wittgensteinwith his
sion. I suppose that he made these corrections when he
gave me the book which was shortly after the death of Jewish background and his constitutive out-
Skinner [in 1941], to whom it had originally belonged. spokennessfrom going to Vienna in 1938,
1244 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XLI (December 2003)

just as Hitler was holding his triumphant would later be famous as his Prison
procession through the city. Also, even Notebooks (Gramsci 1971, 1975).
though both had left-wing political convic- These notes give us considerable under-
tions, Sraffa (as a seasoned political realist) standing of what Gramsci and his circle
could see little merit in the odd eccentrici- were interested in. Sraffa was very keen that
ties of Wittgensteins social beliefs, which Gramsci should write down his thoughts,
combined a romantic longing for the ardu- and to help him, Sraffa opened an unlimit-
ous life of a hard-working manual laborer ed account with a Milan bookshop (Sperling
with the hope that the communist revolu- and Kupfer) in the name of Gramsci, to be
tion would lead to a rejection of the adora- settled by Sraffa. As was mentioned earlier,
tion of science, which Wittgenstein saw as a Sraffa was a part of the editorial team, led
corrupting influence on contemporary life. by Gramsci, of LOrdine Nuovo. Sraffa
There remains, however, the question of joined the team in 1921, but he had known
why Sraffa was so reserved about the depth Gramsci from earlier on, and was writing
and novelty of his conversations with for LOrdine Nuovo from 1919 onwards
Wittgenstein even at the beginning (in 1929 (mainly translating works from English,
and soon thereafter), and why the ideas that French, and German). Working together on
so influenced Wittgenstein would have this distinguished journal had brought
seemed to Sraffa to be rather straight- Sraffa and Gramsci even closer together
forward. Sraffa himself did not publish any- than they already had been, and they had
thing whatsoever on this subject, but there is intense discussions over the years. 9 Even
considerable evidence that what appeared to though they disagreed from time to time,
Wittgenstein as new wisdom was a common for example in 1924 when Sraffa criticized
subject of discussion in the intellectual circle the party line (the Communist Party makes
in Italy to which Sraffa and Gramsci both a terrible mistake when it gives the impres-
belonged. That issue I take up next. sion it is sabotaging an alliance of opposi-
tion movements), there can be no doubt
about the intensely productive nature of
4. The Gramsci Connection
their interactions.
Antonio Gramsci was less reticent than Since the Prison Notebooks were, in many
Sraffa about writing down his philosophical ways, a continuation of Gramscis long-
ideas. When John Maynard Keynes wrote to standing intellectual pursuits and reflected
Sraffa in January 1927 communicating the the kind of ideas that the circle of friends
willingness of Cambridge University to offer were involved in, it is useful to see how
him a lecturing position, Gramsci had just Gramscis notes relate to the subject matter
been arrested (on November 8, 1926, to be of Sraffas conversations with Wittgenstein,
precise). After some harrowing experiences including the part played by rules and con-
of imprisonment, not least in Milan, Gramsci ventions and the reach of what became
faced a trial, along with a number of other
political prisoners, in Rome in the summer 9
On the friendship between Gramsci and Sraffa, see
of 1928. Gramsci received a sentence of Nerio Naldi (2000). Their intellectual interactions involved
twenty years in gaol (for twenty years we a great variety of subjects, and John Davis (1993, 2002) has
must stop this brain from functioning, said illuminatingly investigated the impact of Gramscian notions
of hegemony, caesarism and praxis on Sraffas think-
the public prosecutor in a statement that ing, and how these ideas may have, through Sraffa, influ-
achieved some fame of its own), and was enced Wittgenstein. These possible connections are more
sent to a prison in Turi, about twenty miles complicated than the interactions considered in this essay,
which are concerned with the most elementary issues of
from Bari. From February 1929 Gramsci meaning and communication which lie at the foundation of
was engaged in writing essays and notes that mainstream philosophy.
Sen: Sraffa, Wittgenstein, and Gramsci 1245

known as ordinary language philosophy. In seen more clearly from the fact that these terms
an essay on the study of philosophy have crystallized not from the point of view of a
hypothetical melancholic man in general but
Gramsci discusses some preliminary points from the point of view of the European cultured
of reference, which include the bold claim classes who, as a result of their world-wide hege-
that it is essential to destroy the widespread mony, have caused them to be accepted every-
prejudice that philosophy is a strange and where. Japan is the Far East not only for Europe
difficult thing just because it is the specific but also perhaps for the American from
California and even for the Japanese himself,
intellectual activity of a particular category who, through English political culture, may then
of specialists or of professional and system- call Egypt the Near East.
atic philosophers. Rather, argued Gramsci,
it must first be shown that all men are How exactly Sraffas ideas linked with
philosophers, by defining the limits and char- Gramscis, and how they influenced each
acteristics of the spontaneous philosophy other, are subjects for further research. 10 But
which is proper to everybody. it is plausible to argue that, in one way or
What kind of an object, then, is this another, Sraffa was quite familiar with the
spontaneous philosophy? The first item themes that engaged Gramsci in the twenties
that Gramsci lists under this heading is lan- and early thirties. It is not very hard to under-
guage itself, which is a totality of deter- stand why the program of Wittgensteins
mined notions and concepts and not just of Tractatus would have seemed deeply mis-
words grammatically devoid of content. guided to Sraffa, coming from the intellectual
The role of conventions and rules, including circle to which he belonged. Nor is it difficult
what Wittgenstein came to call language- to see why the fruitfulness of the anthropo-
games, and the relevance of what has been logical waynovel and momentous as it was
called the anthropological way which to Wittgensteinwould have appeared to
Sraffa championed to Wittgenstein, all seem Sraffa to be not altogether unobvious.
to figure quite prominently in the Prison
Notebooks (Gramsci 1975, p. 324): 5. Capital Valuation and Social
Communication
In acquiring ones conception of the world one
always belongs to a particular grouping which is What bearing do these philosophical ideas
that of all the social elements which share the (including the so-called anthropological
same mode of thinking and acting. We are all
conformists of some conformism or other,
always man-in-the-mass or collective man. 10
I should, however, point briefly at two issues on
which the correspondenceor dissonancebetween
Gramscis and Sraffas ideas deserve much further investi-
The role of linguistic convention was dis- gation. The first concerns what Saul Kripke (1982) calls
cussed by Gramsci with various illustrations. the Wittgensteinian paradox, citing Wittgensteins claim
Here is one example (Gramsci 1975, p. 447): that no course of action could be determined by a rule,
because every course of action can be made to accord with
the rule. Since the later Wittgenstein is so focused on
One can also recall the example contained in a relating meaning and communication to following rules,
little book by Bertrand Russell [The Problems of Kripke identifies this paradox as perhaps the central
Philosophy]. Russell says approximately this: problem of [Wittgensteins] Philosophical Investigations
We cannot, without the existence of man on the (p. 7). The second issue concerns how far one should
earth, think of the existence of London or stretch the anthropological way of seeing philosophical
Edinburgh, but we can think of the existence of issues, in particular whether custom has to be invoked
two points in space, one to the North and one to only to understand how language is used, or also to go as
far as David Hume did when he argued, in a passage quot-
the South, where London and Edinburgh now
ed approvingly by Keynes and Sraffa (1938), that the
are. East and West are arbitrary and con- guide of life was not reason but custom (p. xxx). Further
ventional, that is, historical constructions, since discussion of these two issues can be found in my longer
outside of real history every point on the earth is paper, cited earlier, Piero Sraffa: A Students Perspective,
East and West at the same time. This can be to be published by the Accademia Nazionale dei Lincei.
1246 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XLI (December 2003)

way) discussed by Sraffa, Gramsci, and Sraffas critique disputes these claims. He
Wittgenstein have on Sraffas work in eco- shows that capital as a surrogate factor of
nomic theory? In his early work, particularly production cannot be defined, in general,
the much-acclaimed essay published in independently of the rate of interest, and
Italian in 1925 and in its English variant in the so-called marginal productivity of capi-
the Economic Journal in 1926, which initial- tal can hardly be seen as governing the
ly established Sraffas reputation, he demon- interest rate. Indeed, techniques of produc-
strated that the tendency in ongoing tion cannot even be ranked in terms of
economic theory, led by Alfred Marshall, being more or less capital intensive, since
to interpret market outcomes as having their capital intensities, which are depend-
resulted from pure competition involves an ent on the interest rate, can repeatedly
internal contradiction when there are reverse their relative ranking as the interest
economies of large scale in the production of rate is lowered.11
individual firms. Sraffas analysis led to con- This is a powerful technical result. We can
siderable follow-up work about the nature ask: what difference does it make?
of economies of scale as well as the working Aggregative neoclassical models with capital
of not fully competitive market forms, as a factor of production are irreparably
beginning with Joan Robinson (1933) and damaged. But neoclassical economic theory
Edward Chamberlin (1933). These early need not be expounded in an aggregative
economic contributions do not appear to form. It is possible to see production in
turn critically on the kind of philosophical terms of distinct capital goods and leave it at
issues addressed later by Wittgenstein, or by that. Also, the kind of practical insight for
Sraffa or Gramsci. policy that one may try to get from arguing in
However, in Sraffas book, Production of aggregative terms (such as the case for using
Commodities by Means of Commodities: less capital-intensive techniques when labor
Prelude to a Critique of Economic Theory is cheap and the cost of capital is high) is nei-
(Sraffa 1960), the interpretational issues ther dependent on how interest rates are
are centrally important. Let me try to illus- actually determined, nor conditional on any
trate this with two issues discussed in this very specific model of capital valuation.12
elegant book. The first of these two con- Yet, at the level of pure theory, the idea
cerns the aggregation of capital and the that interest is the reward of the productiv-
idea of capital as a factor of production. ity of capital rather than, say, the result of
Mainstream economic theory, often called exploiting labor (or simply the passive
neoclassical economics, can be formulat- residual that is left over between the output
ed at different levels of aggregation. Capital value and input costs, including wage pay-
goods such as machinery and equipment ments) can playand has often been made
are, of course, quite diverse, and any to playquite a major part in political and
aggregative account that invokes capital
as a general factor of production must
11
involve some aggregative modelling There have been substantial controversies on the
exact significance and reach of these and related results;
which is comprehensible and discussable in see, among others, Robinson (195354); Robert Solow
social communication. Also, there is a (195556); Garegnani (1960, 1970, 1990); Samuelson
much-discussed claim that it is the produc- (1962, 1966); Pasinetti (1966, 1974); Harcourt (1972);
Dobb (1973); Christopher Bliss (1975); Steedman (1977,
tivity of incremental capital (called the 1988); Edwin Burmeister (1980); Vivian Walsh and Harvey
marginal product of capital) that can be Gram (1980); Bharadwaj (1990); Bharadwaj and Schefold
seen as governing the value of the rate (1990); Mauro Baranzini and Geoffrey Harcourt (1993);
Cozzi and Marchionatti (2000);, Kurz (1990); and Avi
of return on capital (such as the rate of Cohen and Geoffrey Harcourt (2002).
interest or profit). 12
Discussed in Sen (1974), reprinted in Sen (1984).
Sen: Sraffa, Wittgenstein, and Gramsci 1247

social debates about the nature of the capi- then the wage rate will be consistently lower
talist system. Thus, the political and social and lower. We can, thus, get a downward-
context of Sraffas demolitional critique of sloping wage-profit relationship (an almost
capital as a factor of production is not hard tranquil portrayal of a stationary class war),
to see once the subject matter of the cri- for that given production situation, and the
tique is fully seized and interpreted in line specification of either the interest (or profit)
with a classical debate stretching over sev- rate or the wage rate will allow us to calcu-
eral centuries. Sraffas findings have to be late all the commodity prices.
seen as a response to a particular descrip- The dog that does not bark at all in this
tive accountwith normative relevance exercise is the demand side: we go directly
of the capitalist system of production, and from production information to prices.
that is where the potential social relevance There is no need, in this mathematical exer-
of these technical results lies. cise, to invoke the demand conditions for the
I must confess that I find it altogether different commodities, which are, for this
difficult to be convinced that ones skepti- particular analytical exercise, redundant. In
cism of unrestrained capitalism must turn interpreting this very neat result, the philo-
on such matters as the usefulness of aggre- sophical foundation of meaning and commu-
gate capital as a factor of production and nication comes fully into its own. It is
the productivity attributed to it, rather than extremely important to understand what is
on the mean streets and strained lives that meant by determination in the mathemat-
capitalism can generate, unless it is ical context (or, to put it in the anthropolog-
restrained and supplemented by other ical way, how it would be understood in a
often nonmarketinstitutions. And yet it mathematical community), and we must not
is not hard to see the broad social and confound the different senses in which the
political vision of Sraffas analysis and its term could be used. There has been a strong
argumentative relevance for debates temptation on the part of the critics of main-
about taking the productivity of capital as stream economic theory to take Sraffas cri-
explication of profits. tique as showing the redundancy of
demand conditions in the causal determina-
6. Prices and Two Senses of Determination tion of prices, thereby undermining that
theory since it makes so much of demands
I turn now to a second example. Sraffa and utilities. Robinson (1961) is not the only
considers an economy in equilibrium to the commentator to display some fascination
extent of having a uniform profit (or interest) towards taking that route (p. 57):
rate. He shows that if we take a snapshot of
the economy with a comprehensive descrip-
when we are provided with a set of technical
tion of all production activities, with
equations for production and a real wage rate
observed inputs and outputs, and a given which is uniform throughout the economy, there
interest rate, from this information alone we is no room for demand equations in the deter-
can determine (in the sense of figuring out) mination of equilibrium prices.
the prices of all the commodities as well as
distribution of income between wages and However, since the entire calculation is
interest (or profit).13 And, if we consider a done for a given and observed picture of
higher and higher interestor profitrate, production (with inputs and outputs all
fixed, as in a snapshot of production oper-
13
The result holds in this simple form in the case in ations in the economy), the question as to
which there is no joint production, the presence of which
would make the relationship more complex but not in fact what would happen if demand conditions
untractable. See Bertram Schefold (1989). changewhich could of course lead to
1248 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XLI (December 2003)

different amounts of productionis not at philosopher at some level, and perhaps an


all addressed in this exercise. 14 The ten- exactly similar thing can be said about the
dency to interpret mathematical determi- fact that analyticaland even mathemati-
nation as causal determination can, thus, calcuriosity is widespread, and influ-
cause a major misunderstanding. 15 ences our social thinking. The idea that it is
possible to find out what the commodity
7. Value and Descriptive Importance prices are merely by looking at the given
production side (inputs and outputs),
If Sraffas results do not have anything along with the interest rate, is a powerful
much to say on causal determination, then analytical result.
what gives them interest? That question A second reason for being interested in
can be answered by considering the nature Sraffas results is to understand them in
of social communication to which Sraffas terms of the idea of value and the political
work contributes. First, analytical determi- content of that concept. In classical thought,
nationnot only causal determinationis value has been seen not merely as a way of
a subject that interests people a good deal. getting at prices (Smith, Ricardo, and Marx
Sraffas demonstration that a snapshot pic- all discussed problems in going from values
ture of just the production conditions of the to prices), but also at making a descriptive
economy can tell us so much about possible statement of some social importance. To
prices is not only a remarkable analytical many economists the idea of value appears
diagnosis, it is also a finding of considerable to be thoroughly wrongheaded. For exam-
intellectual interest to people who want to ple, Robinson invoked positivist method-
think about the correspondence between ology (she could be described as a left-wing
quantities produced and prices charged. Popperian) to dismiss any real relevance of
Gramsci has argued that everyone is a the idea of value in general and its invoking
in Marxian economics in particular. In her
14
I have discussed the distinctions involved in Sen Economic Philosophy, Robinson (1964) put
(1978). See also Salvadori (2000) for a textual analysis of her denunciation thus (p. 39):
what Sraffa doesand does notclaim regarding the
role of demand. Given the nature of Sraffas exercise
(with given commodity production), it is also clear why On this plane the whole argument appears to be
Sraffa (1960, preface) claimsrightlythat there is no metaphysical; it provides a typical example of
specific assumption of constant returns to scale that
the way metaphysical ideas operate. Logically it
needs to be invoked for his analysis. The internal charac-
teristics of the observed snapshot picture may, of course, is a mere rigmarole of words, but for Marx it was
themselves reflect particular market relations (and even a flood of illumination and for latter-day
some underlying equilibriation), especially for the Marxists, a source of inspiration.16
observed uniform profit rate and universal wage rate to
have come about. But Sraffa is undoubtedly right that no
further assumption (for example, of constant returns to Value will not help, Robinson conclud-
scale) need be added to what is already entailed by the ed. It has no operational content. It is just
observed snapshot picture (without any counterfactual
changes being considered).
a word.
15
Sraffa discusses a corresponding distinction in an The philosophical issues raised by
unpublished note (D3/12/15:2 in the Sraffa collection, Gramsci and Sraffa, and of course by
Wren Library, Trinity College, italics added) written in
1942 (I am very grateful to Heinz Kurz for drawing my
Wittgenstein, have considerable bearing on
attention to it): this question. Just as positivist method-
This paper [the forthcoming book] deals with an ology pronounces some statements mean-
extremely elementary problem; so elementary indeed
that its solution is generally taken for granted. The
ingless when they do not fit the narrow
problem is that of ascertaining the conditions of equi- sense of meaning in the limited terms of
librium of a system of prices & the rate of profits,
independently of the study of the forces which may
16
bring about such a state of equilibrium. Robinson (1964), p. 39.
Sen: Sraffa, Wittgenstein, and Gramsci 1249

verification or falsification, the Tractatus (within a snapshot picture of the economy),


too saw little of content in statements that while different from a labor-based descrip-
did not represent or mirror a state of affairs tion in the Marxian mould, is also an
in the same logical form. This has the attempt to express social relations with a
implication, as Simon Blackburn (1994) put focus on the production side, rather than on
it, of denying factual or cognitive meaning utility and mental conditions. We can
to sentences whose function does not fit debate how profound that perspective is,
into its conception of representation, such but it is important to see that the subject
as those concerned with ethics, or mean- matter of Sraffas analysis is enlightening
ing, or the self (p. 401). In contrast, the description of prices and income distribu-
philosophical approach pursued by the tion, invoking only the interrelations on the
later Wittgenstein, partly influenced by production side.
Sraffa himself, sees meaning in much Closely related to this perspective, there is
broader terms. 17 a further issue which involves addressing the
The interpretation of value and its classical dichotomy between use-value and
descriptive relevance have been well dis- exchange-value, as it was formulated by
cussed by Maurice Dobb (1937, 1973), the the founders of modern economics, in par-
Marxist economist, who was a close friend of ticular Adam Smith and David Ricardo.
Sraffa and his long-term collaborator in edit- Sraffa and Dobb, who collaborated in the
ing David Ricardos collected works. Dobb editing of Ricardos collected works, had sig-
pointed to the social and political interest in nificant interest in this question,18 and to
a significant description of economic rela- that issue, I now turn.
tions between people. Even such notions as
exploitation which have appeared to some 8. Use, Exchange and Counterfactuals
(including Robinson) as metaphysical, can
David Ricardos foundational book, On the
be seen to be an attempt to reflect, in com-
Principles of Political Economy and
municative language, a common public con-
Taxation, published in 1817, begins with the
cern about social asymmetries in economic
following opening passage:
relations. As Dobb (1973) put it (p. 45):
It has been observed by Adam Smith, that the
exploitation is neither something metaphysical word Value has two different meanings, and
nor simply an ethical judgement (still less just sometimes expresses the utility of some particu-
a noise) as has sometimes been depicted: it is a lar object, and sometimes the power of purchas-
factual description of a socio-economic relation- ing other goods which the possession of that
ship, as much as is Marc Blochs apt characteri- object conveys. The one may be called value in
sation of Feudalism as a system where feudal
use; the other value in exchange. The things,
lords lived on labor of other men. he continues, which have the greatest value in
use, have frequently little or no value in
Sraffas analysis of production relations exchange; and on the contrary, those which have
and the coherence between costs and prices the greatest value in exchange, have little or no
value in use. Water and air are abundantly use-
ful; they are indeed indispensable to existence,
17 yet, under ordinary circumstances, nothing can
There is a related issue in epistemology as to the
extent of precision that would be needed for a putative sci- be obtained in exchange for them. Gold, on the
entific claim to be accepted as appropriate. For this issue contrary, though of little use compared with air
too, the nature of Sraffas analysis has a direct bearing, in or water, will exchange for a great quantity of
line with Aristotles claim, in the Nicomachean Ethics, that other goods.
we have to look for precision in each class of things just so
far as the nature of the subject admits. On this issue, see
Sen (1982), essay 20 (Description as Choice), and Coates
18
(1996), along with the references cited there. I shall not, See particularly Ricardo (195173), edited by Sraffa
however, pursue this question further here. with the collaboration of Dobb, and Dobb (1973).
1250 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XLI (December 2003)

There is a puzzle here that is of some only as a mechanical device that has mere-
interest of its own, and can also tell us ly instrumental use in price theory. Even as
something about how we may think about theories of value address the Smith-
prices and values in general. There are two Ricardo question regarding a coherent
alternative ways of perspicuously explain- understanding of the dual structure of
ing how gold can come to command a value in use and value in exchange, they
higher price than water, despite being so attempt to make important social state-
much less important for human life. One ments of their own on the nature of the
answer, based on the utility side of the pic- economic world by focusing respectively
ture, is that given the large amount of on such matters as the incremental useful-
water that is generally available and the ness of commodities, the satisfaction they
shortage of gold, the so-called marginal can generate, the labor that is used in mak-
utility of water (the incremental benefit ing them, or the costs that have to be
that a consumer gets from an additional incurred in their production.
unit of water) is small, compared with the The inclination of classical political
marginal utility of gold. The other answer is econ-omy, including classical Marxian eco-
that the cost of productionor of min- nomics, to expect from a theory of value
ingof gold is much higher than that of something much more than a purely
water, in the situation in which we examine mechanical intermediate product in
the economy. price theory is, of course, well-known.
Neither explanation is an attempt at causal- Indeed, this inclination is often taken to be
ly explaining why and how the prices and special pleading, for largely political rea-
quantities that exist have actually emerged. sons, in a contrived justification of the rel-
They are, rather, answers to the Smith- evance of labor theory of value. However,
Ricardo question: How can people under- this diagnosis does the classical perspective
stand why gold though of little use less than justice, since the importance of
compared with air or water exchanges for a perspicacious explanation and communica-
great quantity of other goods? The cost- tion is part and parcel of the classical
based explanation and the utility-based expla- approach. Indeed, it is important to recol-
nation are, thus, alternative ways of lect, in this context, the significance that
explicating what we observe, by invoking has typically been attached, in the perspec-
ideas like costs of production and marginal tives of classical political economy and
usefulness, which can serve as means of social Marxian economics, not just to labor and
communication and public comprehension. production, but also to the idea of use
While Sraffa himself did not publish value (and to its successor concept in the
much that relates directly to this interpre- form of satisfactionor utilitythat
tational question (except to comment on a commodities may generate). The compari-
distinction involving the use of counter- son between the two rival value theories in
factual concepts, on which more present- the form of labor theory and utility theory
ly), we can get some insight into the issues was taken to be of interest precisely
involved from the writings of Maurice because both made socially engaging state-
Dobb, Sraffas friend, collaborator and ments; there is no attempt here to deny the
exponent. Indeed, in a classic paper on nature of social interest in utility theory as
the requirements of a theory of value, a theory of value.
included in his book, Political Economy Indeed, in 1929, in a prescient early cri-
and Capitalism, Dobb (1937) had argued tique of what would later develop into the
that a theory of value must not be seen revealed preference approach (led by
Sen: Sraffa, Wittgenstein, and Gramsci 1251

Samuelson 1938), Dobb (1929) regretted opting for a cost-based explanation (in line
the tendency of modern economics to down- with Sraffa 1960), we can rely entirely on
play the psychological aspects of utility in observed facts, such as inputs and outputs
favor of just choice behavior (p. 32): and a given interest rate, without having to
invoke any counterfactuals (that is, with-
Actually the whole tendency of modern theory is out having to presume what would have
to abandon psychological conceptions: to
happened had things been different).20 This
make utility and disutility coincident with
observed offers on the market; to abandon a is not the case with the utility-based expla-
theory of value in pursuit of a theory of nation, since marginal utility inescapably
price. But that is to surrender, not to solve the involves counterfactual reasoning, since it
problem.19 reflects how much extra utility one would
have if one had one more unit of the
Indeed, the problem to which Dobb commodity.
refers, and to which utility theory of value, The philosophical status of counterfactu-
like the labor theory, caters, is to make an als has been the subject of considerable
important qualitative statement about the debating in epistemology. I see little merit
nature of the economic problem (Dobb in trying to exclude counterfactuals in trying
1937, pp. 2122). Dobb went on to distin- to understand the world.21 But I do know
guish between these two social explanations from extensive conversations with Sraffa
by noting that the qualitative statement that he did find that the use of
[utility theory] made was of a quite different counterfactuals involved difficulties that
order, being concerned not with the rela- purely observational propositions did not. It
tions of production, but with the relation is not that he never used counterfactual
of commodities to the psychology of con- concepts (life would have been unbearable
sumers (p. 21). In contrast, the picture of with such abstinence) but he did think there
the economy presented by Sraffa concen- was a big methodological divide here.
trates precisely on the relations of pro- Whether or not one agrees with Sraffas
duction, and in explicating Sraffas judgement on the unreliability of counter-
contributions, Dobb (1973) pursues exactly factuals, it is indeed remarkable that there is
this contrast. such a methodological contrast between the
There is much evidence that this contrast utility-based and cost-based stories (in the
was of particular interest to Sraffa himself. Sraffian form). The difference between
But in this comparison, Sraffa saw another them lies not merely in the fact that the for-
big difference which was methodologically mer focuses on mental conditions in the
important for him (though I know of little form of utility while the latter concentrates
evidence that it interested Dobb much), on material conditions of production (a con-
given Sraffas philosophical suspicion of the trast that is easily seen and has been much
invoking of counterfactual magnitudes in discussed), but also in the less-recognized
factual descriptions. Sraffa noted that in distinction that the former has to invoke
counterfactuals, whereas the latterin the
Sraffian formulationhas no such need.
19
Dobb (1929), p. 32. It is also of interest to note that
in a letter to R. P. Dutt, another Marxist intellectual, Dobb
20
wrote on May 20, 1925 (as it happens, shortly after his first See Sraffa (1960), pp. vvi.
21
meeting with Piero Sraffa): the theory of marginal utility Indeed, the reach of economics as a discipline would
seems to me to be perfectly sound, & as explanation of be incredibly limited had all counterfactual reasoning been
prices & price changes quite a helpful advance on the clas- disallowed, as I have tried to discuss in Sen (2002); see also
sical doctrine, framing it more precisely & forging a more Sen (1982), essay 20 (Description as Choice), pp.
exact tool of analysis. On this see Pollit (1990). 43249.
1252 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XLI (December 2003)

9. Concluding Remarks argued in this essay that it is possible to


interpret Sraffas departures in terms of
The critical role of Piero Sraffa in con- the communicational role of economic
tributing to profound directional changes in theory in matters of general descriptive
contemporary philosophy, through helping interest (rather than seeing them as
to persuade Wittgenstein to move from the attempts at constructing an alternative
Tractatus to the theory that later found causal theory of the determination of
expression in Philosophical Investigations, is prices and distribution).22
plentifully acknowledged by Wittgenstein Sraffa used analytical reasoning to throw
himself (as well as by his biographers). What light on subjects of public discussion in polit-
may, however, appear puzzling is the fact ical and social contexts. In particular, he
that Sraffa remained rather unexcited about demonstrated the unviability of the view that
the momentous nature of this influence and profits can be seen as reflecting the produc-
the novelty of the ideas underlying it. tivity of capital. More constructively, Sraffas
However, the sharpness of the puzzle is, to a work throws light on the importance of value
great extent, lessened by the recognition theory in perspicacious description. The
that these issues had been a part of the stan- contrast between utility-based and cost-
dard discussions in the intellectual circle in based interpretation of prices belongs to the
Italy to which Sraffa belonged, which also world of pertinent description and social dis-
included Gramsci. cussion, and the rival descriptions are of
As a result, the weakness of Wittgensteins general interest; these have been invoked in
view of meaning and language in Tractatus the past and remain relevant today. The
would have come as no surprise to Sraffa, inquiry into alternative descriptions differs
nor the need to invoke considerations that from the subject of causal determination of
later came to be known as the anthropolog- prices, in which both demand and supply
ical way of understanding meaning and the sides would tend to be simultaneously
use of language. There appears to be an evi- involved.
dent Gramsci connection in the shift from There is an obvious similarity here with
the early Wittgenstein to the later John Hickss (1940, 1981) classic clarifica-
Wittgenstein, though much more research tion that while utility and costs are both
would be needed to separate out, if that is needed in a theory of price determination,
possible at all, the respective contributions when it comes to the valuation of social
of Sraffa and Gramsci to the ideas that income, utility and costs provide two alter-
emerged in their common intellectual circle. native ways of interpreting prices, with
Turning to Sraffas economic contribu- respectively different implications on the
tions, they cannot, in general, be divorced understanding of social or national income.
from his philosophical understanding. The measurement of social income in real
After his early writings on the theory of the
firm (and his demonstration of the need to 22
Since Sraffas (1960) classic book has the subtitle
consider competition in imperfect or Prelude to a Critique of Economic Theory, there has
monopolistic circumstances), his later been some temptation to presume that once the cri-
work did not take the form of finding dif- tiqueto which that book is a preludeis completed,
Sraffa would have expected it to yield an alternative theo-
ferent answers to the standard questions in ry of prices and distribution. If the arguments presented
mainstream economics, but that of alter- in this essay are correct, this presumption is mistaken.
ingand in some ways broadeningthe Sraffa was, in this view, trying to broaden the reach and
scope of economic inquiries, not just trying to find differ-
nature of the inquiries in which main- ent answers to the questions standardly asked in main-
stream economics was engaged. I have stream economic theory.
Sen: Sraffa, Wittgenstein, and Gramsci 1253

terms may mean valuation in terms of utili- (managing, mysteriously, without giving any
ty, or in respect of cost, and that these two role to demand conditions) must be resisted.
meanings are in principle different (Hicks Everything here turns on the meaning of
1981, p. 142). 23 determination and the usage of that term
In pursuing the descriptive distinction on which Sraffa draws. The sense of deter-
between utility and costs, Sraffa attached mination invoked by Sraffa concerns the
importance to the demonstration that his mathematical determination of one set of
account of the cost-based story (as in Sraffa facts from another set. To illustrate the point
1960) draws exclusively on observed infor- (with a rather extreme example) a sundial
mation, rather than having to invoke any may allow us to determine what time it is
counterfactual presumptions. This differs by looking at the shadow of the indicator
from the utility-based picture, since the (gnomon), but it is not the case that the
concept of marginal utility is constitutively shadow of the indicator causally deter-
counterfactual. How methodologically sig- mines what time it is. The value of a clock
nificant this distinctionbetween descrip- does not lie in its ability to fixrather than
tions with or without counterfactualsin tellthe time of day.
fact is remains an open question (I confess It would have been very surprising if, in
to having remained a skeptic), but it is a his economic analysis, Piero Sraffa were not
subject to which Sraffa himself attached influenced by his own philosophical position,
very great importance. It also relates to and had stayed within the rather limited
other methodological features of Sraffas boundaries of positivist or representational
analysis, including his strenuousbut reasoning commonly invoked in contempo-
entirely correctinsistence that his analysis rary mainstream economics. In addressing
does not need any assumption of constant foundational economic issues of general
returns to scale.24 social and political interest (some of which
The temptation to see Sraffas contribu- have been discussed over two hundred
tion as a causal theory of price determination years), Sraffa went significantly beyond
those narrow barriers. It is, I suppose, com-
23
The extensive reach of the Hicksian contrast forting to know that there were not many
between the two alternative perspectives are among the Piero Sraffas, but one.
subjects explored in Sen (1979). In commenting on his
earlier 1940 paper, Hicks (1981) remarks that I now think
that in my 1940 article I claimed too little for the cost REFERENCES
measure (p. 143). A pioneering exploration of the pro- Albani, Paolo. 1998. Sraffa and Wittgenstein: Profile
duction-based, rather than utility-based, evaluation of of an Intellectual Friendship, Hist. Econ. Ideas 6:3,
national income can be found in James Mirrlees (1969). pp. 15173.
Since that evaluation involves investigation of production Baranzini, Mauro and Geoffrey C. Harcourt, eds. 1993.
possibility for real income comparisons (a quintessentially The Dynamics of the Wealth of Nations: Growth,
counterfactual exercise), Mirrleess analysis goes in a very Distribution and Structural Change: Essays in
different direction from Sraffas investigation of the inter- Honour of Luigi Pasinetti. NY: St. Matins Presss.
nal relations on the cost side, for a given production situa- Bharadwaj, Krishna. 1988. Sraffas Ricardo,
tion. The point of similarity lies only in (1) the fact that a Cambridge J. Econ. 12:1, pp. 6784.
complete theory of causal determination of prices is not . 1990. Sraffas Return to Classical Theory, in
needed either for evaluation of social income or for using Bharadwaj and Schefold (1990). pp. 5381.
value theory for social description of utility or costs, and Bharadwaj, Krishna and Bertram Schefold, eds. 1990.
(2) the fact that the separation of the cost story from the Essays on Piero Sraffa: Critical Perspectives on the
utility story is involved in both the exercises. Revival of Classical Theory. London: Routledge.
24
See Sraffa (1960), pp. vvi. Sraffa notes that when in Blackburn, Simon. 1994. Dictionary of Philosophy. NY:
1928 Lord Keynes read a draft of this paper, he recom- Oxford U. Press.
mended that, if constant returns were not to be assumed, Bliss, Christopher J. 1975. Capital Theory and the
an emphatic warning to that effect should be given (p. vi). Distribution of Income. Amsterdam: North-Holland.
That emphatic warning can be found in the preface to Burmeister, Edwin. 1980. Capital Theory and
Sraffa (1960). Dynamics. Cambridge: Cambridge U. Press.
1254 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XLI (December 2003)

Chamberlin, Edward H. 1933. The Theory of . 1985. Piero Sraffa (18981983), Proceedings
Monopolistic Competition. Cambridge, MA: British Academy 71, pp. 61540.
Harvard U. Press. Keynes, Johan Maynard and Piero Sraffa. 1938.
Coates, John. 1996. The Claims of Common Sense: Introduction, in An Abstract of a Treatise of
Moore, Wittgenstein, Keynes and the Social Sciences. Human Nature 1740, A Pamphlet Hitherto Unknown
Cambridge: Cambridge U. Press. Digital ed., 2001. by David Hume. John M. Keynes and Piero Sraffa,
Cohen, Avi and Geoffrey C. Harcourt. 2002. eds. Cambridge: Cambridge U. Press.
Whatever Happened to the Cambridge Capital Kripke, Saul A. 1982. Wittgenstein on Rules and Private
Theory Controversies, J. Econ. Perspect. 17:1, pp. Language. Cambridge, MA: Harvard U. Press.
199214. Kurz, Heinz D. 1990. Capital, Distribution and
Cozzi, Terrenzio and Roberto Marchionatti, eds. 2000. Effective Demand: Studies in the Classical Approach
Piero Sraffas Political Economy: A Centenary to Economic Theory. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Estimate. London: Routledge. , ed. 2000. Critical Essays on Piero Sraffas
Davis, John B. 1993. Sraffa, Interdependence and Legacy in Economics. Cambridge: Cambridge U.
Demand: The Gramscian Influence, Rev. Polit. Press.
Econ. 5:1, pp. 2239. Kurz, Heinz D. and Neri Salvadori. 2000. Piero
. 2002. Garmsci, Sraffa, and Wittgenstein: Sraffas Contributions to Economics: A Brief
Philosophical Linkages, Europ. J. Hist. Econ. Survey, in Kurz op. cit., pp. 324.
Thought 9:3, pp. 384401. McGuinness, Brian, ed. 1982. Wittgenstein and His
Dobb, Maurice H. 1929. A Sceptical View of the Times. Oxford: Blackwell.
Theory of Wages, Econ. J. 39:156, pp. 50619. Mirrlees, James A. 1969. The Evaluation of National
. 1937. Political Economy and Capitalism. Income and an Imperfect Economy, Pakistan
London: Routledge. Devel. Rev. 9:1, pp. 113.
. 1955. On Economic Theory and Socialism: Monk, Ray. 1991. Ludwig Wittgenstein: The Duty of
Collected Papers. London: Routledge. Genius. London: Vintage.
. 1973. Theories of Value and Distribution since Naldi, Nerio. 2000. Piero Sraffa and Antonio Gramsci:
Adam Smith: Ideology and Economic Theory. The Friendship Between 1999 and 1927, Europ. J.
Cambridge: Cambridge U. Press. Hist. Econ. Thought 7:1, pp. 79114.
Eatwell, John; Murray Milgate and Peter Newman, Pasinetti, Luigi L. 1966. Changes in the Rate of Profit
eds. 1987. The New Palgrave: A Dictionary of and Switching of Techniques, Quart. J. Econ. 80:4,
Economics. London: Macmillan. pp. 50317.
. 1990. Capital Theory. London: Macmillan. . 1969. Switches of Techniques and the Rate
Eatwell, John and Carlo Panico. 1987. Sraffa, Piero of Return in Capital Theory, Econ. J. 79, pp.
(18981983), in Eatwell, Milgate and Newman op. 50825.
cit., pp. 44552. . 1974. Growth and Income Distribution.
Garegnani, Pierangelo. 1960. Il capitale nelle teorie Cambridge: Cambridge U. Press.
della distribuzione. Milan: Giuffr. . 1977. Lectures on the Theory of Production.
. 1970. Heterogeneous Capital, the Production London: Macmillan.
Function and the Theory of Distribution, Rev. . 1979. Sraffa, Piero, Int. Encyclopaedia
Econ. Stud. 37:3, pp. 40736. Social Sciences vol. 18. NY: Macmillan.
. 1990. Quantity of Capital, in Eatwell, . 1988. Sraffa on Income Distribution,
Milgate and Newman op. cit. Cambridge J. Econ. 12:1, pp. 13538.
. 1998. Sraffa: The Theoretical World of the Pollit, Brian H. 1990. Clearing the Path for
Old Classical Economists, Europ. J. Hist. Econ. Production of Commodities by Means of
Thought 5:3, pp. 41529. Commodities: Notes on the Collaboration of
Gramsci, Antonio. 1957. The Modern Prince and Other Maurice Dobb in Piero Sraffas edition of the Works
Writings. London: Lawrence Wishart. and Correspondence of David Ricardo, in
. 1971. Selections from the Prison Notebooks of Bharadwaj and Schefold op. cit.
Antonio Gramsci. Quintin Hoare and Geoffrey Potier, Jean-Pierre. 1987. Piero SraffaUnorthodox
Nowell Smith, eds. London: Lawrence Wishart. Economist (18981983): A Biographical Essay.
. 1975. Letters from Prison. Lynne Lawner, London and NY: Routledge.
trans. and ed. London: Jonathan Cape. Ricardo, David. 195173. The Works and
Hahn, Frank H. 1982. The Neo-Ricardians, Correspondence of David Ricardo. 11 vols. Piero
Cambridge J. Econ. 6:4, pp. 35374. Sraffa, ed. with Maurice H. Dobb. Cambridge:
Harcourt, Geoffrey C. 1972. Some Cambridge Cambridge U. Press.
Controversies in the Theory of Capital. Cambridge: Robinson, Joan. 1933. The Economics of Imperfect
Cambridge U. Press. Competition. London: Macmillan.
Hicks, John. 1940. The Valuation of Social Income, . 195354. The Production Function and the
Economica 7, pp. 10424. Theory of Capital, Rev. Econ. Stud. 21:2, pp.
. 1981. Wealth and Welfare: Collected Essays on 81106.
Economic Theory, vol. 1. Oxford: Blackwell. . 1961. Prelude to a Critique of Economic
Kaldor, Nicholas. 1984. Piero Sraffa, Cambridge J. Theory, Oxford Econ. Pap. 13:1, pp. 5358.
Econ. 8:1, pp. 15. . 1964. Economic Philosophy. Harmondsworth:
Sen: Sraffa, Wittgenstein, and Gramsci 1255

Penguin. Smith, Adam. 1776. An Inquiry into the Nature and


Roncaglia, Alessandro. 1978. Sraffa and the Theory of Causes of the Wealth of Nations. Repub., Oxford:
Prices. NY: Wiley. 2nd ed., 1981. Oxford U. Press, 1976.
. 1999. Sraffa: la biografia, lopera, le scoule. Solow, Robert M. 195556. The Production Function
Bari: Laterza. and the Theory of Capital, Rev. Econ. Stud. 23:2,
Salvadori, Neri. 2000. Sraffa on Demand: A Textual pp. 101108.
Analysis, in Kurz op. cit., pp. 18197. . 1963. Capital Theory and the Rate of Return.
Samuelson, Paul A. 1938. A Note on the Pure Theory Amsterdam: North-Holland.
of Consumers Behaviour, Economica 5, pp. 6171. Sraffa, Piero. 1925. Sulle relazioni fra costo e quanti-
. 1962. Parable and Realism in Capital Theory: ta prodotta, Annali di Econ. 2, pp. 277328.
The Surrogate Production Function, Rev. Econ. English trans. by John Eatwell and Alessandro
Stud. 29:3, pp. 193206. Roncaglia in Luigi L. Pasinetti, ed., Italian Econ.
. 1966. A Summing Up, Quart. J. Econ. 80:4, Papers vol. 3. Bologna: Il Mulino, and Oxford:
56883. Oxford U. Press, 1998.
. 1987. Sraffian Economics, in Eatwell, . 1926. The Laws of Return under Competitive
Milgate and Newman op. cit. Conditions, Econ. J. 36:144, pp. 53550.
. 2000a. Revisionist Findings on Sraffa, in . 1951. Introduction, in Ricardo (195173) op.
Kurz op. cit, pp. 2545. cit., vol. I, pp. xiiilxii.
. 2000b. Sraffas Hits and Misses, in Kurz op. . 1960. Production of Commodities by Means of
cit., pp. 11152. Commodities: Prelude to a Critique of Economic
Schefold, Bertram. 1989. Mr. Sraffa on Joint Production Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge U. Press.
and Other Essays. London: Unwin Hyman. Steedman, Ian. 1977. Marx After Sraffa. London: New
. 1996. Piero Sraffa 18981983, Econ. J. Left Books. Repub., London: Verso, 1981.
106:438, pp. 131425. . 1988. Sraffian Economics. 2 vols. Aldershot:
Sen, Amartya K. 1974. On Some Debates in Capital Elgar.
Theory, Economica 41, pp. 32535. Sylos Labini, Paolo. 1990. Sraffas Critique of the
. 1978. On the Labour Theory of Value: Some Marshallian Theory of Prices, in Bharadwaj and
Methodological Issues, Cambridge J. Econ. 2, pp. Schefold op. cit., pp. 319.
17590. Walsh, Vivian; and Harvey Gram. 1980. Classical and
. 1979. The Welfare Basis of Real Income Neoclassical Theories of General Equilibrium. NY:
Comparisons: A Survey, J. Econ. Lit. 17, pp. 145. Oxford U. Press.
. 1982. Choice, Welfare and Measurement. Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1921. Tractatus Logico-
Oxford: Blackwell. Repub., Cambridge, MA: Philosophicus. Trans. David Pears and Brian
Harvard U. Press, 1997. McGuinness. NY: Routledge, 1961.
. 1984. Resources, Values and Development. . 1953. Philosophical Investigations. Oxford:
Cambridge, MA: Harvard U. Press. Blackwell. 2nd ed. 1958.
. 2002. Rationality and Freedom. Cambridge. . 1958. The Blue and Brown Books. Oxford:
MA: Harvard U. Press. Blackwell.

You might also like