You are on page 1of 6

Dark Posthumanism

David Roden

Billions of years in the future, the Time Traveller stands before a dark ocean, beneath a
bloated red sun. The beach is dappled with lichen and ice. The huge crabs and insects
which menaced him on his visit millions of years in its past are gone. Apart from the lapping
of red-peaked waves on the distant shore, everything is utterly still. Nonetheless, a churning
weakness and fear deters him from leaving the saddle of the time machine.

He thinks he sees something black flop awkwardly over a nearby sandbar; but when he
looks again, all is still. That must be a rock, he tells himself.

Studying the unknown constellations, he feels an enveloping chill. Then twilight segues to
black. The old sun is being eclipsed by the moon or some other massive body.

The wind moans out of utter darkness and cold. A deep nausea hammers his belly. He is on
the edge of nothing.

The object passes and an an arc of blood opens the sky. By this light he sees what moves in
the water. Wells writes: “It was a round thing, the size of a football perhaps, or, it may be,
bigger, and tentacles trailed down from it. It seemed black against the weltering blood-red
water, and it was hopping fitfully about.”.

During the Traveller’s acquaintance with it, the creature gives no indication of purpose. Its
“flopping” might be due to the action of the waves. It might lack a nervous system, let alone
a mind replete with thoughts, beliefs or desires. In contrast, we learn much of the Traveller’s
state. He feels horror at the awful blackness of the eclipse; pain breathing in the cold; “a
terrible dread of lying helpless in that remote and awful twilight”.

It is as if Wells’ text edges around what cannot be carried from that shore. There is no heroic
saga of discovery, cosmic exploration or “first contact”; no extended reflection on time and
human finitude. There is just a traumatic, pain-filled encounter.

When viewed against the backdrop of “Weird” literature, however, the event on the shoreline
seems more consequential. As China Miéville has argued, the Weird is defined by its
preoccupation with the radically alien. This is in stark opposition to the Gothic specter, that
always signifies a representation in play between an excluded past and an uncertain future
(Miéville 2012).

Monsters like H P Lovecraft’s Cthulhu do not put representation in play. They shred it. As
Mieville writes:

1
For Cthulhu, in its creator’s words, “there is no language.” “The Thing cannot be
described.” Even its figurine “resembled nothing familiar to geology or
mineralogy” (Lovecraft, “Call”). The Color Out of Space “obeyed laws that are not of
our cosmos” (“Colour”). The Dunwich Horror was “an impossibility in a normal
world” (“Dunwich”).(Miéville 2012, 379)

The monstrous reality is indicated by grotesque avatars and transformations whose causes
erode political order and sanity itself. In Jeff VanderMeer’s recent Southern Reach trilogy a
fractious bureaucracy in a looking-glass USA is charged with managing a coastline that has
been lost to some unearthly power. This proves inimical to human minds and bodies even as
it transforms “Area X” into a lush Edenic wilderness. As we might expect, bureaucratic
abstraction falters in its uncertain borders. The Reach’s attempts to define, test and explore
Area X are comically inappropriate - from herding terrified rabbits across the mysterious
barrier that encloses it, to instituting “round-the-clock” surveillance of an immortal plant
specimen from an unsanctioned expedition (VanderMeer 2014a, b, c). All that remains to
VanderMeer’s damaged protagonists is a misanthropic acceptance of something always too
distant and strange to be understood, too near not to leave in them the deepest scars and
ecstasies.

This misanthropy is implied in Wells’ earlier shoreline encounter. An unstory from a far future
that is perhaps not alive or unalive. A moment of suspense and inconsequence that can
reveal nothing because it inscribes the limits of stories.

Yet this alien is not the “gaseous invertebrate” of negative theology – but an immanent other,
or as Miéville puts it, “a bad numinous, manifesting often at a much closer scale, right up
tentacular in your face, and casually apocalyptic” (Miéville 2012, 381). It is this combination
of inaccessibility and intimacy, I will argue, that makes the Weird apt for thinking about the
temporally complex politics of posthuman becoming.1

In Posthuman Life I argue for a position I call “Speculative posthumanism” (SP). SP claims,
baldly, that there could be posthumans: that is, powerful nonhuman agents arising through
some human-instigated technological process.

I’ve argued that the best way to conceptualize the posthuman here is in terms of agential
independence – or disconnection. Roughly, an agent is posthuman if it can act outside of the
“Wide Human” - the system of institutions, cultures, and techniques which reciprocally
depend on us biological (“narrow”) humans (Roden 2012; Roden 2014: 109-113).

Now, as Ray Brassier usefully remind us in the context of the realism debate, mind-
independence does not entail unintelligibility (“concept-independence”). This applies also to

2
the agential independence specified by the Disconnection Thesis (Brassier 2011, 58).
However, I think there are reasons to allow that posthumans could be effectively
uninterpretable. That is, among the class of possible posthumans – we have reason to
believe that there might be radical aliens.

But here we seem to confront an aporia. For in entertaining the possibility of uninterpretable
agents we claim a concept of agency that could not be applied to certain of its instances,
even in principle.

This can be stated as a three-way paradox.

1) The behavior of radical aliens would not be interpretable as actions.

2) Radical alien would be agents.

3) An entity whose behaviors could not be interpreted as actions would not be an agent.

Each of these statements is incompatible with the conjunction of the other two; each seems
independently plausible.

Something has to give here. We might start with proposition 3.

3) implies a local correlationism for agency. That is to say: the only agents are those
amenable to “our” practices of interpretative understanding. 3) denies that there could be
evidence-transcendent agency such procedures might never uncover.

Have we good reason to drop 3?

I think we do. 3) entails that the set of agents would correspond to those beings who are
interpretable in principle by some appropriate “we” – humans, persons, etc. But in-principle
interpretability is ill defined unless we know who is doing the interpreting.

That is, we would need to comprehend the set of interpreting subjects relevantly similar to
humans by specifying minimal conditions for interpreterhood. This would require some kind
of a priori insight presumably, since we’re interested in the space of possible interpreters and
not just actual ones.

How might we achieve this? Well, we might seek guidance from a phenomenology of
interpreting subjectivity to specify its invariants (Roden 2014: Ch 3). 2 However, it is very
doubtful that any phenomenological method can even tell us what its putative subject matter
(“phenomenology”) is. I’ve argued that much of our phenomenology is “dark”; having dark
phenomenology yields minimal insight into its nature or possibilities (Roden 2013; Roden
2014 Ch4).

3
If transcendental phenomenology and allied post-Kantian projects (see Roden Forthcoming)
fail to specify the necessary conditions for be an interpreter or an agent, we should embrace
an Anthropologically Unbounded Posthumanism which rejects a priori constraints on the
space of posthuman possibility. For example, Unbounded Posthumanism gives no warrant
for claiming that a serious agent must be a "subject of discourse" able to measure its
performances against shared norms.3

Thus the future we are making could exceed curent models of mutual intelligibility, or
democratic decision making (Roden 2014 Ch8). Unbounded posthumanism recognizes no a
priori limit on posthuman possibility. Thus posthumans could be weird. Cthulhu-weird. Area X
weird. Unbounded Posthumanism is Dark Posthumanism – it circumscribes an epistemic
void into which we are being pulled by planetary scale technologies over which we have little
long run control (Roden 2014: ch7).

To put some bones on this: it is conceivable that there might be agents far more capable of
altering their physical structure than current humans. I call an agent “hyperplastic” if it can
make arbitrarily fine changes to its structure without compromising its agency or its capacity
for hyperplasticity (Roden 2014, 101-2; Roden Unpublished).

A modest anti-reductionist materialism of the kind embraced by Davidson and fellow


pragmatists in the left-Sellarsian camp implies that such agents would be uninterpretable
using an intentional idiom because intentional discourse could have no predictive utility for
agents who must predict the effects of arbitrarily fine-grained self-interventions upon future
activity. However, the stricture on auto-interpretation would equally apply to
heterointerpretation. Hyperplastic agents would fall outside the scope of linguistic
interpretative practices. So, allowing this speculative posit, anti-reductionism ironically
implies the dispensability of folk thinking about thought rather than its ineliminability.

Hyperplastics (H-Pats) would be unreadable in linguistic terms or intentional terms, but this
is not to say that they would be wholly illegible. It’s just that we lack future proof information
about the appropriate level of interpretation for such beings – which is consonant with the
claim that there is no class of interpretables or agents as such.

Encountering H-Pats might induce the mental or physical derangements that Lovecraft and
VanderMeer detail lovingly. To read them might have to become more radically plastic
ourselves – more like the amorphous, disgusting Shoggoths of Lovecraft’s At the Mountains
of Madness. Shoggothic hermeneutics is currently beyond us – for want of such flexible or
protean interlocutors. But the idea of an encounter that shakes and desolates us,
transforming us in ways that may be incommunicable to outsiders, is not. It is the

4
unnarratable that the Weird tells in broken analogies,4 agonies and elisions. This is why the
Weird Aesthetic is more serviceable as a model for our relationship to the speculative
posthuman than any totalizing conception of agency or interpretation.

In confronting the posthuman future, then, we are more like Wells’ broken time traveller than
a voyager through the space of reasons. Our understanding of the posthuman - including the
interpretation of what even counts as Disconnection – must be interpreted aesthetically;
operating without criteria or pre-specified systems of evaluation. It begins, instead, with
xeno-affects, xeno-aesthetics, and a subject lost for words on a “forgotten coast” (See
VanderMeer 2014c).

References

Brassier, R., 2011. Concepts and objects. The Speculative Turn: Continental Materialism
and Realism, pp.47-65.

Bakker, R.S., 2009. Neuropath. Macmillan.

Colebrook, C., 2014. Sex after life: Essays on extinction, Vol. 2. Open Humanities Press.

Derrida, J. and Moore, F.C.T., 1974. White mythology: Metaphor in the text of philosophy.
New Literary History, 6(1), pp.5-74.

Harman, G., 2012. Weird realism: Lovecraft and philosophy. John Hunt Publishing.

Malpas, J. E. 1992. Donald Davidson and the Mirror of Meaning: Holism, Truth,
Interpretation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Miéville, C., 2012. On Monsters: Or, Nine or More (Monstrous) Not Cannies. Journal of the
Fantastic in the Arts, 23(3 (86), pp.377-392.

Roden, David. (2012), “The Disconnection Thesis”. In A. Eden, J. Søraker, J. Moor & E.
Steinhart (eds), The Singularity Hypothesis: A Scientific and Philosophical Assessment,
London: Springer.

Roden, David. 2013. “Nature’s Dark Domain: An Argument for a Naturalised


Phenomenology”. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplements 72: 169–88.

Roden, David (2014), Posthuman Life: Philosophy at the Edge of the Human. London:
Routledge.

5
Roden, David (Forthcoming). “On Reason and Spectral Machines: an Anti-Normativist
Response to Bounded Posthumanism”. To appear in Philosophy After Nature edited by
Rosie Braidotti and Rick Dolphijn.

Roden (Unpublished). “Reduction, Elimination and Radical Uninterpretability: the case of


hyperplastic agents”

https://www.academia.edu/15054582/Reduction_Elimination_and_Radical_Uninterpretability

O’Sullivan, S., 2010. From aesthetics to the abstract machine: Deleuze, Guattari and
contemporary art practice. Deleuze and contemporary art, pp.189-207.

Thacker, E., 2015. Tentacles Longer Than Night: Horror of Philosophy. John Hunt
Publishing.

VanderMeer, J., 2014a. Annihilation: A Novel. Macmillan.

VanderMeer, J., 2014b. Authority: A Novel. Macmillan

VanderMeer, J., 2014c. Acceptance: A Novel. Macmillan.


1 One of the things that binds the otherwise fissiparous speculative realist movement is an appreciation of Weird
writers like Lovecraft and Thomas Ligotti. For in marking the transcendence of the monstrous, the Weird evokes
the “great outdoors” that subsists beyond any human experience of the world. Realists of a more rationalist bent,
however, can object that the Weird provides a hyperbolic model of the independence of reality from our
representations of it.

2 For example, one that supports pragmatic accounts like Davidsons’s with an ontology of shared worlds and
temporal horizons. See, for example, Malpas 1992 and Roden 2014 Ch3.

3 I’ve given reasons to generalize this argument against hermeneutic a priori’s. Analytic Kantian accounts, of the
kind championed by neo-Sellarsians like Brassier, cannot explain agency and concept-use without regressing to
claims about ideal interpreters whose scope they are incapable of delimiting (Roden Forthcoming).

4 In Lovecraft’s “The Dreams in the Witch House” we are told that the demonic entity called “Azathoth” lies “at the
center of ultimate Chaos where the thin flutes pip mindlessly”. The description undermines its metaphorical
aptness, however, since ultimate chaos would also lack the consistency of a center. The flute metaphor only
advertises the absence of analogy; relinquishing the constraints on interpretation that might give it sense. We
know only that terms like “thin flutes” designate something for which we have no concept. Commenting on his
passage in his book Weird Realism: Lovecraft and Philosophy, Graham Harman suggests that the “thin and
mindless flutes” should be understood as “dark allusions to real properties of the throne of Chaos, rather than
literal descriptions of what one would experience there in person” (Harman 2012: 36-7)

View publication stats

You might also like