You are on page 1of 3

Bethany Besteman. 1st draft. Alternate Assignment for Compare and Contrast.

May 12, 2016

Alternate Assignment 3: Compare and Contrast

Read the following passages about Friendship

From Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics Book VIII

Now these reasons differ from each other in kind; so, therefore, do the corresponding forms of
love and friendship. There are therefore three kinds of friendship, equal in number to the things that are
lovable; for with respect to each there is a mutual and recognized love, and those who love each other
wish well to each other in that respect in which they love one another. Now those who love each other for
their utility do not love each other for themselves but in virtue of some good which they get from each
other. So too with those who love for the sake of pleasure; it is not for their character that men love ready-
witted people, but because they find them pleasant. Therefore those who love for the sake of utility love
for the sake of what is good for themselves, and those who love for the sake of pleasure do so for the sake
of what is pleasant to themselves, and not in so far as the other is the person loved but in so far as he is
useful or pleasant. And thus these friendships are only incidental; for it is not as being the man he is that
the loved person is loved, but as providing some good or pleasure. Such friendships, then, are easily
dissolved, if the parties do not remain like themselves; for if the one party is no longer pleasant or useful
the other ceases to love him.
….
Perfect friendship is the friendship of men who are good, and alike in virtue; for these wish well
alike to each other qua good, and they are good themselves. Now those who wish well to their friends for
their sake are most truly friends; for they do this by reason of own nature and not incidentally; therefore
their friendship lasts as long as they are good-and goodness is an enduring thing. And each is good
without qualification and to his friend, for the good are both good without qualification and useful to each
other. So too they are pleasant; for the good are pleasant both without qualification and to each other,
since to each his own activities and others like them are pleasurable, and the actions of the good are the
same or like. And such a friendship is as might be expected permanent, since there meet in it all the
qualities that friends should have. For all friendship is for the sake of good or of pleasure-good or
pleasure either in the abstract or such as will be enjoyed by him who has the friendly feeling-and is based
on a certain resemblance; and to a friendship of good men all the qualities we have named belong in
virtue of the nature of the friends themselves; for in the case of this kind of friendship the other qualities
also are alike in both friends, and that which is good without qualification is also without qualification
pleasant, and these are the most lovable qualities. Love and friendship therefore are found most and in
their best form between such men.
But it is natural that such friendships should be infrequent; for such men are rare. Further, such
friendship requires time and familiarity; as the proverb says, men cannot know each other till they have
'eaten salt together'; nor can they admit each other to friendship or be friends till each has been found
lovable and been trusted by each. Those who quickly show the marks of friendship to each other wish to
be friends, but are not friends unless they both are lovable and know the fact; for a wish for friendship
may arise quickly, but friendship does not.

Translated by W.D. Ross from classics.mit.edu


Bethany Besteman. 1st draft. Alternate Assignment for Compare and Contrast. May 12, 2016

From “Friendship” by Ralph Waldo Emerson

Our friendships hurry to short and poor conclusions, because we have made them a texture of
wine and dreams, instead of the tough fibre of the human heart. The laws of friendship are austere and
eternal, of one web with the laws of nature and of morals. But we have aimed at a swift and petty benefit,
to suck a sudden sweetness. We snatch at the slowest fruit in the whole garden of God, which many
summers and many winters must ripen. We seek our friend not sacredly, but with an adulterate passion
which would appropriate him to ourselves. In vain. We are armed all over with subtle antagonisms,
which, as soon as we meet, begin to play, and translate all poetry into stale prose. Almost all people
descend to meet. All association must be a compromise, and, what is worst, the very flower and aroma of
the flower of each of the beautiful natures disappears as they approach each other. What a perpetual
disappointment is actual society, even of the virtuous and gifted! After interviews have been compassed
with long foresight, we must be tormented presently by baffled blows, by sudden, unseasonable apathies,
by epilepsies of wit and of animal spirits, in the heyday of friendship and thought. Our faculties do not
play us true, and both parties are relieved by solitude.

The attractions of this subject are not to be resisted, and I leave, for the time, all account of
subordinate social benefit, to speak of that select and sacred relation which is a kind of absolute, and
which even leaves the language of love suspicious and common, so much is this purer, and nothing is so
much divine.
I do not wish to treat friendships daintily, but with roughest courage. When they are real, they are
not glass threads or frostwork, but the solidest thing we know. For now, after so many ages of experience,
what do we know of nature, or of ourselves? Not one step has man taken toward the solution of the
problem of his destiny. In one condemnation of folly stand the whole universe of men. But the sweet
sincerity of joy and peace, which I draw from this alliance with my brother's soul, is the nut itself,
whereof all nature and all thought is but the husk and shell. Happy is the house that shelters a friend! It
might well be built, like a festal bower or arch, to entertain him a single day. Happier, if he know the
solemnity of that relation, and honor its law! He who offers himself a candidate for that covenant comes
up, like an Olympian, to the great games, where the first-born of the world are the competitors. He
proposes himself for contests where Time, Want, Danger, are in the lists, and he alone is victor who has
truth enough in his constitution to preserve the delicacy of his beauty from the wear and tear of all these.
The gifts of fortune may be present or absent, but all the speed in that contest depends on intrinsic
nobleness, and the contempt of trifles.

From Ralph Waldo Emerson Texts at emersoncentral.com


Bethany Besteman. 1st draft. Alternate Assignment for Compare and Contrast. May 12, 2016

Using the passages above, respond to the following prompts by writing a 3-paragraph 2-3 page
essay. Each paragraph should produce an argument supported by evidence (quotations from the
above excerpts) and explanation (a discussion of the implications of that evidence).

Paragraph 1: How does Aristotle use compare and contrast to make an argument about friendship?
Paragraph 2: Discuss significant differences and similarities about the ways Aristotle and Emerson use
compare and contrast to make their different arguments about friendship.
Paragraph 3: Drawing on your analyses in Parts one and two, make a thoughtful argument about what are
in general the advantages and limitations of using compare and contrast to make an argument?

You might also like