You are on page 1of 7

This article was originally published in the Encyclopedia of Animal Behavior

published by Elsevier, and the attached copy is provided by Elsevier for the
author's benefit and for the benefit of the author's institution, for non-
commercial research and educational use including without limitation use in
instruction at your institution, sending it to specific colleagues who you know,
and providing a copy to your institution’s administrator.

All other uses, reproduction and distribution, including without limitation


commercial reprints, selling or licensing copies or access, or posting on open
internet sites, your personal or institution’s website or repository, are
prohibited. For exceptions, permission may be sought for such use through
Elsevier's permissions site at:

http://www.elsevier.com/locate/permissionusematerial

McAuliffe K. and Hauser M. (2010) Morality and Evolution. In: Breed M.D. and
Moore J., (eds.) Encyclopedia of Animal Behavior, volume 2, pp. 483-488
Oxford: Academic Press.

© 2010 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.


Author's personal copy

Morality and Evolution


K. McAuliffe and M. Hauser, Harvard University, Cambridge, MA, USA
ã 2010 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.

. . . of all the differences between man and the lower In this essay, we further explore the evolutionary ori-
animals, the moral sense or conscience is by far the most gins of our moral sense, providing a synopsis of the cur-
important. This sense. . . has a rightful supremacy over rent state of empirical play and the issues raised by the
every other principle of human action; it is summed up in experiments and observations of animals. Like Darwin, we
that short but imperious word ought, so full of high distinguish questions of proximate and ultimate cause, and
significance. It is the most noble of all the attributes of specifically, separate out the issues of phylogeny, adapta-
man, leading him without a moment’s hesitation to risk tion, and psychological mechanism. Like Darwin, we also
his life for that of a fellow-creature; or after due delibera- distinguish between the psychological mechanisms that
tion, impelled simply by the deep feeling of right or duty, guide our intuitive and rather automatic sense of right or
to sacrifice it in some great cause. wrong, from those that underpin our contemplative reflec-
tion of what ought to be. From the perspective of psycho-
Darwin C (1871) The Descent of Man and Selection in Relation logical mechanisms and adaptive function, we can explore
to Sex, pp. 70–71. Princeton: Princeton University Press. the building blocks of our capacity to decide what is right
and what is wrong, and the conditions under which partic-
ular actions are permissible or forbidden. This perspective
seeks an understanding of the core psychological mechan-
Introduction
isms that enable organisms, both human and non-human,
to decide what is fair, when harms are permissible, and
In the Descent of Man, Darwin explored the evolutionary
when social contracts may be broken.
origins of our moral sense, and as the quotation above
To this end, we review two distinct sets of literatures.
emphasizes, highlighted what we see as three essential
The first explores studies that fall within the general area
points. First, to understand the origins of our sense of
of behavioral economics, and in particular, the processes
right and wrong, we must adopt a comparative perspec-
that guide cooperation, resource distribution, and a broad
tive, drawing on studies of animals, to reveal what is
sense of fairness. We focus here on results that relate to
uniquely human as opposed to what is shared across
some of the critical features of human cooperation and
species. Second, understanding the moral sense is funda-
altruistic behavior, specifically, attention to inequities,
mentally a problem about the power of our conscience to
reputation, punishment, and reciprocity. Second, we
guide what we ought to do. It is, in Darwin’s terms, the
explore the mechanisms of action perception and produc-
highest of virtues, giving humans a sense of nobility, and
tion, and in particular, the extent to which animals distin-
fundamentally distinguishing them from other animals.
guish intentional from accidental consequences, as well
Third, our sense of ought, of what should or could be
as the cues they use to decide goal-directed actions.
done, can lead to either instinctive action (‘without a
Together, these processes comprise some of the funda-
moment’s hesitation’) or to a more contemplative stance
mental building blocks that are evolutionarily ancient,
(‘after due deliberation’) where we reflect upon par-
appear early in human ontogeny, and ultimately lead to
ticular principles of justice, and then based on this
a full-fledged moral sense in healthy human adults. We
analysis, act in such a way that we support some great
then conclude with our current and personal sense of
moral cause, often at personal cost (‘sacrifice’). These
what makes human morality fundamentally different
three points target aspects of phylogeny and proximate
from what is observed in other animals, focusing specifi-
cause, that is, the patterns of evolutionary change and
cally on how we evolved a brain that conceives of that
the psychological mechanisms that either facilitate or
imperious word ought.
constrain their appearance. Darwin also discussed the
adaptive significance of morality, and in particular, the
selective pressures that may have led to its appearance in
our species. Characteristic of his thinking at the time, Cooperation and Moral Judgment in
Darwin perceived a strong role for group-level pressure, Humans
such that individuals in groups acting in particularly
altruistic ways would ultimately outcompete groups act- A great deal of moral philosophy has been devoted to an
ing less cooperatively. exploration of our capacity to cooperate with others,

483
Encyclopedia of Animal Behavior (2010), vol. 2, pp. 483-488
Author's personal copy
484 Morality and Evolution

sacrifice personal gains for the benefit of others, maintain However, these conditions demand consideration of the
social contracts, and appreciate that a sense of justice is requisite psychological mechanisms, including recall of
premised on a sense of fairness. This rich tradition is prior outcomes to evaluate reputation, quantification
generally aimed at understanding the guiding principles and tracking of the payoff matrices to evaluate fair dis-
that appear to underpin not only our intuitive sense of tributions, and assessment of whether the resources were
cooperative action and distributive justice, but also the distributed intentionally or as a byproduct of otherwise
principles that ought to guide our decisions. Thus, for selfish behavior.
example, we observe in Rawls’ thinking on justice a clear While reciprocal altruism and indirect reciprocity can
distinction between the intuitive principles that may explain the evolution of cooperation in small social
guide our spontaneous judgments of fairness, and those groups where individuals know each other, these mechan-
that percolate up during a period of considered reflection, isms cannot account for the fact that modern humans
where we consciously divorce ourselves from the poten- often live in large groups of unrelated others, where
tially powerful and biasing influences of in-versus out- reputation tracking is not possible, and where repeated
group partiality (e.g., favoring kin over nonkin). The and stable relationships are unreliable, thus making reci-
question of interest here is how human cooperation, procity difficult or impossible. In these situations, cooper-
including the psychological mechanisms that support it, ation nonetheless evolves, demanding a different kind of
as well as the selective pressures that led to its particular account that can accommodate the fact that the optimal
design features, evolved. strategy is to defect and free ride on the contributions of
When biologists have discussed the evolution of coop- others. Here, Boyd and Richerson pointed out that it
eration, they have often focused on behavior and fitness appears that punishment evolved to crack down on the
consequences, without Taking into account psychological defector problem, and bring about stable cooperation. On
mechanisms that may be relevant or even required. Thus, an ultimate level, focused on evolutionary consequences,
Darwin puzzled over the possibility of altruism by asking punishment is a behavior that reduces the fitness of a
how such a costly behavior could evolve, given that his recipient at a temporary cost, but ultimate benefit to an
theory of natural selection favored self-beneficial actions. actor (see the reading by Clutton-Brock and Parker for
This puzzle vanished when Hamilton, and later Williams, more on this topic). However, from a proximate perspec-
pointed the way to a different level of analysis, one that tive, punishment requires specific psychological mechan-
focused on genes as opposed to either individuals or isms including the recruitment of motivating emotions
groups. That is, we can explain why an animal engages (e.g., Trivers’ moral outrage), the ability to determine when
in self-sacrifice for the benefit of another by the fact that a norm has been violated, the assessment of just deserts,
the ‘other’ is a close genetic relative. As such, altruism and a mechanism to distinguish whether the outcome
evolves by benefiting genes shared in common. Where (e.g., failure to cooperate) was intended or accidental.
puzzles remain today is in explaining the evolution of Recent work on the evolution of fairness provides a
cooperation among genetically unrelated individuals, good example of how proximate and ultimate concerns
and especially the kind of large-scale cooperation often have come together. Specifically, using a combination of
observed among human societies. well-defined bargaining games from behavioral econom-
A partial answer to these puzzles emerged, interest- ics, together with rich psychological analysis and cross-
ingly enough, when Trivers proposed his theory of recip- cultural data, we can see that humans evolved a distinctive
rocal altruism, blending issues of adaptive function sense of fairness, one shared by all members of our spe-
with psychological constraints. Specifically, and unlike cies, but open to cross-cultural variation, and constrained
Hamilton and Williams, Trivers’ theory included not by sensitivity to inequities and the ability to punish those
only a set of evolutionary conditions for the emergence who violate norms of distributive justice. Consider, as an
of cooperation among unrelated individuals, but also a example, the well studied, one-shot, anonymous Ultima-
discussion of requisite psychological mechanisms includ- tum Game. An experimenter first informs two individuals,
ing recognition of individuals, memory of past inte- a donor and a recipient, about the three rules of the game.
ractions, and strong emotional responses to defection, Rule 1: the bank allocates a sum of money to the donor
including moralistic aggression. Thus, Trivers’ analysis who has the option of allocating some proportion of
paved the way for what has now become a major focus this sum to the recipient. Rule 2: whatever amount the
in the field: a consideration of both proximate and ulti- donor gives to the recipient, the recipient keeps, and
mate concerns related to the evolution of cooperation. the donor keeps the remainder. Rule 3: if the recipient
More specifically, and as many have argued, cooperation chooses to reject the donor’s offer, then neither donor nor
among unrelated others can evolve if it takes place within recipient keeps any money. According to the rational
stable groups with opportunities for repeated interactions economic model, the recipient should accept any offer
(reciprocal altruism), or in groups where cooperative deci- from the donor as some money is surely better than no
sions can be based on reputation (indirect reciprocity). money. However, results from this game show that people

Encyclopedia of Animal Behavior (2010), vol. 2, pp. 483-488


Author's personal copy
Morality and Evolution 485

across cultures consistently reject some offers, licensing Specifically, there are at least two reasons why reciprocity
the conclusion that humans approach this problem with a might be rare among animals. First, the demographics of
sense of what constitutes an unfair offer. Further, when most animal populations may provide a sufficiently high
subjects learn that the donor is a computer or random density of kin to eliminate the pressure for nonkin based
number generator, they are more likely to accept unfair relationships. Despite these issues, we suggest that recent
offers. These results show that humans not only attend work on cooperation, including reciprocity, has provided
to the distribution of resources (i.e., outcomes), but also to new insights into some of the psychological mechanisms
the means by which resources are distributed. Returning that are shared among human and non-human animals,
to the ultimatum game, there is a fundamental (moral) and leads to one of our primary conclusions: though we
difference between a human donor offering 1 out of 20 share with other animals some of the core building blocks
possible dollars to a recipient, and a computer program of morality, only one species – our species – has combined
that uses a random number generator to offer $1 out of these core elements into a truly moral system that not
$20. Computers are not intentional agents, and thus, don’t only considers how we distinguish moral rights from
enter the moral domain. Regardless of how upset we are at wrongs, but also what ought to be the foundation for
the computer’s offering, we can’t hold them responsible. On such decisions.
the other hand, we do hold other humans responsible for
their actions. Pushing the point further, if we forced a
A Sense of Fairness in Animals?
human to roll a die to pick the donation, and the die
landed with a 1 facing up for $1, we would also not hold Recent comparative work on primates and dogs has
the human responsible for this outcome; this game func- explored the problem of inequity aversion as an important
tionally strips the human agent of his intentional control – component of the more general sense of fairness. One of
of his free will. What is critical, then, is a combination of the earliest treatments of this problem was Brosnan and de
both the actual outcome and whether the agent was Waal’s study of brown capuchin monkeys (Cebus apella).
responsible for this decision. In this experiment, subjects that had been trained to trade
Thus, a sense of fairness, together with an ability to tokens for food rewards watched a conspecific acquire and
discriminate between intentional and accidental actions, eat a high-value food item and then were given the
is critical to cooperation, and more generally, to our moral opportunity to acquire and eat a lower-value food item.
judgments about others’ actions. Given the importance of Subjects consistently refused to trade the token for the
these abilities, they raise the crucial question of whether lower-value food, and this result was interpreted as evi-
these traits are unique to humans or whether they also dence for inequity aversion and a sense of fairness. This
play a role in governing behavior in non-human animals experiment was heavily criticized because the authors
(hereafter animals). could not rule out the effect of frustration as the driving
force behind rejections. That is to say, subjects may have
rejected unfair offers not because the other individual was
Cooperation, Fairness and Action getting a better deal, but because they were frustrated at
Perception in Animals not being able to obtain the higher-value food item that
was right in front of them. Though subsequent experi-
Cooperation in animals is taxonomically widespread, with ments confirmed the validity of these critiques, Brosnan,
numerous examples of individuals engaging in costly de Waal, and their colleagues, have since replicated the
altruistic behavior for the benefit of others. In the early original findings with relevant controls, and found that
literature, most of the examples were consistent with the their results cannot be explained by frustration, or further
theory of kin selection and with optimization of inclusive extended to parallel findings with chimpanzees (Pan tro-
fitness. That is, most altruistic acts of cooperation evolved glodytes). Adding to the comparative scope of this work,
to benefit close genetic relatives. Following on the heels of a recent experiment by Range and colleagues shows
Trivers’ conceptual work on reciprocity, however, several that domestic dogs are sensitive to inequities in reward
cases of reciprocal altruism emerged in the literature. distribution. In this experiment, subjects were given a
These cases, as well as several more recent studies have, command to perform an action (paw shake) in a social
for the most part, been dismissed, either because of a situation where one individual received a food reward for
failure to replicate, the weakness of the effects, alternative its performance while the other did not. Subjects that did
explanations (e.g., byproduct mutualism), or the highly not receive the reward were more reluctant to perform the
artificial conditions under which the evidence has been action and displayed more stress behavior in the social
obtained. At best, we argue, reciprocity is an uncommon condition compared to an asocial control.
form of social interaction among animals. We further In sum, although there is still much controversy sur-
argue, however, that consideration of both proximate rounding the results on inequity aversion in animals, mini-
and ultimate factors makes this conclusion unsurprising. mally, it appears that animals are sensitive to the distribution

Encyclopedia of Animal Behavior (2010), vol. 2, pp. 483-488


Author's personal copy
486 Morality and Evolution

of rewards, in both social and nonsocial contexts, responding then they should selectively approach the coconut con-
negatively when an outcome appears unfair. tacted, as this maximizes the odds of obtaining food.
Another approach to studying fairness in animals Results revealed that when the experimenter grasped
comes from a series of experiments investigating prosocial the coconut with his hand, foot, or a precision grip involving
behavior, specifically, the tendency to help another in a the pointer finger and thumb, rhesus selectively approached
situation where there are no personal gains, and little or this coconut over the other; in contrast, they approa-
no personal cost. In these experiments, subjects are given ched the two coconuts at chance levels when the experi-
the option of acquiring a reward for themselves or for menter flopped the back of his hand on the coconut
themselves as well as for another individual. The impor- [accidental], touched or grasped the coconut with a tool,
tant difference between prosociality tasks and inequity or grasped the coconut with his hand for balance while
aversion tasks is that a preference for equity is costless standing up. These results rule out low-level association
in the former (actors receive a payoff either way) and accounts; many of these individuals have experience see-
costly in the latter (actors receive nothing if they reject ing humans perform goal-directed actions with tools, and
an unfair offer). Studies of common marmosets (Callithrix yet they did not perceive tool-related actions as goal-
jacchus) and brown capuchin monkeys have shown that directed, and none of these individuals have experience
subjects consistently choose the prosocial option. Studies seeing humans perform grasping actions with their feet,
of chimpanzees, on the other hand, have shown that and yet they did perceive foot-related actions as goal-
individuals are indifferent to the welfare of conspecifics directed. Further, these data show that when assessing
and will choose indiscriminately between the two options. the meaning of actions, rhesus are highly sensitive to the
Interestingly, when chimpanzees are tested in a spontane- means used to achieve a goal – for example, perceiving a
ous altruism task, where subjects are given the opportu- hand grasp action as goal-directed but a hand flop action
nity to help another individual in the absence of a food as accidental, despite the fact that the experimenter’s body
reward, they do exhibit prosocial behavior. At present, it is position, eye gaze, and duration of contact with the coco-
not clear whether the difference in prosociality between nut were identical across the two conditions. These stud-
these studies is due to the nature of the reward (i.e., food ies, together with research on other species, suggest that
versus nonfood), or to specific details of the task demands. non-human animals infer the meaning of an action by
Together, studies of inequity aversion and prosociality evaluating the actor’s goals in relation to the environmen-
suggest that the ability to both detect and react to unfair tal constraints on achieving such goals.
outcomes, together with a preference for fair resource Given that some animal species are able to draw infer-
distributions, are not uniquely human traits. However, ences about others’ intentions and goals, we can ask
these experiments focus exclusively on outcomes and do whether this ability influences their social interactions.
not explore the means by which they are achieved. In the That is, are animals completely outcome-oriented or do
next section, we discuss experiments that tap into the they attend to the means by which outcomes are achieved?
psychological mechanisms involved in discriminating One of the first studies to explore this problem was Call
between intentional versus accidental actions. and colleagues’ experimental study of captive chimpanzees.
In this study, a human experimenter faced a chimpanzee,
seated on the opposite side of a Plexiglas partition. In each
Going Beyond Outcomes to Intentions
of several conditions, varying the nature of the experimen-
and Goals
ter’s action, a grape was presented near the opening of the
In this section we explore two questions: (1) Can animals partition; the opening was large enough for the chimpanzee
draw inferences about an individual’s intentions and goals, to reach and grab the grape. In one condition, the experi-
and (2) if so, does this capacity influence social behavior? menter brought the grape within grasping distance, but
Recent studies of rhesus monkeys on Cayo Santiago then rapidly retracted it as soon as the subject reached.
have explored their ability to use subtle details of an action This action was defined as teasing. In a second, and highly
sequence to draw inferences about the actor’s goal. In the parallel condition, the experimenter brought the grape
basic design, Wood and colleagues presented two potential forward, but then dropped it as soon as the subject reached.
food sources (overturned coconut shells) to a subject, acts This action was defined as clumsiness. Chimpanzees
on one, and then walks away, allowing the subject to selec- showed much greater signs of frustration in the teasing
tively approach. Although coconuts are native to the island than clumsy conditions, leaving the test chamber earlier,
on which these animals live, rhesus cannot open the hard and acting aggressively toward the experimenter (i.e., bang-
outer shells themselves, and therefore, only obtain the ing on the Plexiglas partition). Thus, as Call and colleagues
desired inner fruit when the coconuts open on their own suggest, chimpanzees appear to make a distinction between
or have been opened and discarded by a human. It, thus, unwilling (teasing) and unable (clumsy), thereby showing
logically follows that if subjects perceive the experimenter’s sensitivity to more than the mere outcome of an event, as in
action as goal-directed and potentially communicative, both of these cases, the subject failed to obtain the grape.

Encyclopedia of Animal Behavior (2010), vol. 2, pp. 483-488


Author's personal copy
Morality and Evolution 487

In the aforementioned study of reciprocity in tamarins, stages, and there are currently several noticeable gaps in
Hauser and colleagues showed that individuals were more our understanding of these phenomena. First, while there
likely to cooperate in situations in which a conspecfic’s is an emerging body of evidence suggesting that these
actions were truly altruistic, than when the same amount capacities are present in some species of non-human
of food (outcome) was delivered as an accidental bypro- primates and domestic dogs, little is known about its
duct of an otherwise selfishly motivated action. Specifi- taxonomic distribution or the evolutionary pressures
cally, a game was set up such that the individual playing that may select for this capacity in different species. For
the actor-1 position was offered an opportunity to pull a example, given the increasing evidence that some food-
tool, delivering one piece of food to self and three pieces caching jays are sensitive to where others are looking,
to an unrelated partner. For the partner, or actor-2, pull- what others have seen, and how such information guides
ing the tool resulted in no food for self, but two pieces for cooperation and cheating, it would not be surprising to
the partner (actor-1). A session was defined as 12 trials find that at least these birds, and possibly other animals,
each for actor-1 and -2, alternating turns. If both actor-1 are sensitive to inequities, and to the distinction between
and -2 pulled on their respective turns, they would maxi- means and outcomes. Second, it is unclear whether the
mize the overall returns, with three pieces each, after an capacities discussed here are specific to the social domain
alternating round. This is what would be expected if or are important in other domains as well. For example, do
actor-2 perceives actor-1’s pull as altruistic, that is, moti- animals appreciate that some properties of artifacts such
vated by the goal of giving food. In contrast, if actor-2 per- as tools are intentionally designed whereas others are
ceives actor-1’s pull as selfish, with the three pieces simple byproducts of physical constraints or accidents?
obtained as a byproduct, then actor-2 should not pull. Third, the majority of studies that have investigated
Results showed that actor-2 rarely pulled. This condition, these capacities in animals have focused on captive indi-
combined with another showing that individuals will viduals. Similar studies of wild populations will be crucial
altruistically give food (i.e., paralleling the actor-2 posi- to understanding whether these abilities are expressed in
tion) when a partner altruistically reciprocates, reinforces nature or are only elicited under controlled laboratory
the conclusion that tamarins attend to both the outcomes conditions that often set up situations that would never
and the means by which they are obtained. arise in the wild. For example, though capuchin monkeys
A final experiment adds to this literature by showing can work with a token economy and detect inequities, and
not only sensitivity to the means by which outcomes arise, though they can solve a joint action task, these situations
but the agent responsible for such outcomes. Jensen and never arise in the wild. It is, thus, essential to distinguish
colleagues first presented one chimpanzee, A, with an between the capacity to solve various cooperative tasks
apparatus involving a sliding tray full of food. Subject and the social and ecological pressures that might demand
B was then introduced into an adjacent enclosure that that such abilities be used to cooperate.
contained a rope. By pulling on the rope, B moved the Despite these limitations, we believe the work on the
sliding tray away from A, thereby stealing A’s food. How- foundations of morality reviewed here (and elsewhere;
ever, subject A’s enclosure also contained a rope that, if Hauser’s 2006 book, Moral Minds: How Nature Designed
pulled, would collapse the sliding tray, thereby taking the Our Universal Sense of Right and Wrong, for a more extensive
food away from B. In conditions where B pulled the tray discussion) lead to at least two conclusions. First, we share
away from A, A frequently became agitated and collapsed with other animals several core psychological capacities
the sliding tray. However, in a similar condition where, that were most likely necessary for the evolution of our
instead of B pulling the tray, the experimenter pushed the moral sense. Like other animals, a sense of justice as
tray away from A to B, A rarely collapsed the tray. This fairness is premised on an ability to take the perspective
result is interesting because it shows that chimpanzees not of another individual, show concern for others, detect
only respond to unfair outcomes, but that they distinguish inequities, and inhibit the temptation to feed self-interest.
between human and chimpanzee agents; a parallel set of Though humans certainly show highly elaborated forms
findings was presented by Hauser and colleagues in their of these abilities, there are significant precursors in other
reciprocity study, showing that cooperation increased in species. Second, there are two ways in which human moral
the face of a unilateral tamarin cooperator, but not a game behavior, and the psychology that supports it, are unique.
in which the payoffs remained the same, but a human Animals show virtually no evidence of reciprocity and
cooperator delivered the rewards for another tamarin. large-scale cooperation, and as far as we can tell, never
engage in the problem of considering not only what is the
moral state of play, but what could or should be – our
Conclusion sense of ought. Though a brief essay like this is not the
place to develop these issues, we end with a speculative
Research on inequity aversion, prosociality and action consideration. What allows humans to uniquely engage
perception in non-human animals is still in its nascent with the thought of the ought is our ability to combine

Encyclopedia of Animal Behavior (2010), vol. 2, pp. 483-488


Author's personal copy
488 Morality and Evolution

different modular representations into new representa- Brosnan SF and de Waal FBM (2003) Monkeys reject unequal pay.
Nature 425: 297–299.
tions. Whereas other animals have evolved highly adap- Call J, Hare B, Carpenter M, and Tomasello M (2004) ‘Unwilling’ versus
tive, modular, and informationally encapsulated domains ‘unable’: Chimpanzees’ understanding of human intentional action.
of thought, targeted at single problems, humans evolved Developmental Science 7: 488–498.
Clutton-Brock TH and Parker GA (1995) Punishment in animal societies.
the capacity to create interfaces between these domains to Nature 373: 209–216.
create entirely new systems of thought. Thus, we alone Dugatkin LA (1997) Cooperation Among Animals. Oxford: Oxford
can consider how we typically distribute resources, often University Press.
Hamilton WD (1964) The genetical evolution of social behavior, I. Journal
based on matters of effort and need, step back from such of Theoretical Biology 7: 1–16.
norms, and consider a more enlightened perspective that Hauser MD (2006) Moral Minds: How Nature Designed Our Universal
not only considers matters of fairness but also individual Sense of Right and Wrong. New York: Ecco.
Hauser MD, Chen MK, Chen F, and Chuang E (2003) Give unto others:
welfare. And we can do this because we can prospectively Genetically unrelated cotton-top tamarin monkeys preferentially give
evaluate the future, sideline current needs and tempta- food to those who altruistically give food back. Proceedings of the
tions, and realize that progress is made by dissent as Royal Society, London, B 270: 2363–2370.
Jensen K, Call J, and Tomasello M (2007) Chimpanzees are vengeful
opposed to consent. What fuels the ought is the realiza- but not spiteful. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences
tion that we can, and often should, entertain a different 104: 13046–13050.
moral landscape. Range F, Horn L, Viranyi ZS, and Huber L (2009) Absence of reward
induced aversion to inequity in dogs. Proceedings of the National
Academy of Sciences 106: 340–345.
See also: Cooperation and Sociality; Empathetic Behav- Rawls J (1971) A Theory of Justice. Cambridge: Harvard University
ior; Mental Time Travel: Can Animals Recall the Past and Press.
Stevens JR and Hauser MD (2004) Why be nice? Psychological
Plan for the Future?; Punishment; Social Cognition and
constraints on the evolution of cooperation. Trends in Cognitive
Theory of Mind. Sciences 8: 60–65.
Trivers RL (1971) The evolution of reciprocal altruism. The Quarterly
Review of Biology 46: 35–57.
Williams GC (1966) Adaptation and Natural Selection. Princeton, NJ:
Further Reading Princeton University Press.
Wood JN, Glynn DD, Phillips BC, and Hauser MD (2007) The perception
of rational, goal-directed action in non-human primates. Science
Boyd R and Richerson PJ (1992) Punishment allows the evolution of
317: 1402–1405.
cooperation (or anything else) in sizeable groups. Ethology and
Sociobiology 13: 171–195.

Encyclopedia of Animal Behavior (2010), vol. 2, pp. 483-488

You might also like