You are on page 1of 5

Book review

Jean-Pierre Vigier and the Stochastic


Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics
selected and edited by Stanley Jeffers, Bo Lehnert, Nils Abramson,
and Leve Chebotarev. Montreal: Apeiron, 2000. vi + 291 pp. $25.00
(p). ISBN 0-9683689-5-6.

(Published in the Journal of Scientific Exploration, vol. 16, no. 2, pp. 283-7, 2002)

This book serves as a useful reminder that the widespread belief that the quantum
world is irreducibly weird, indeterministic, unvisualizable, and dependent on human
observation, is not required by experimental results, and that a causal, more rational
and intuitive interpretation is possible.

The book was compiled as a tribute to Jean-Pierre Vigier on the occasion of his 80th
birthday. It begins with a preface by Stanley Jeffers outlining Vigier’s life. He worked
closely with Louis de Broglie and David Bohm, and helped to pioneer the de Broglie-
Bohm-Vigier approach to quantum physics, also known as the causal stochastic
interpretation. The main features of this approach and how it evolved are explained in
an introduction by Lev Chebotarev. The bulk of the book consists of 22 facsimile reprints
of papers on quantum mechanics authored or coauthored by J.P. Vigier. There is also a
biography of Vigier’s works. Most of the papers are, at least in part, highly technical, but
much of the discussion and analysis of the contending interpretations of quantum
physics can be readily understood by nonspecialists.

As Chebotarev points out, while quantum mechanics works impeccably as a


mathematical tool, ‘the conceptual situation in quantum mechanics appears to be the
most disturbing in modern physics’. Seventy years after the advent of quantum theory,
‘there is still no clear idea as to what its mathematics is actually telling us’ (p. 1).

A central tenet of the standard Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics, as


developed by Bohr, Heisenberg, Born, and Pauli, is that ‘There is no quantum world,
there is only an abstract quantum physical description’. But what does the mathematical
formalism actually describe? It is hard to believe that the quantum world underlying our
material, macroscopic world consists of nothing but abstract ‘probability waves’ that
somehow ‘collapse’ into particle-like objectivity whenever a measurement is made (or,
according to some theorists, whenever a measurement is registered by a conscious
human mind).

Each time the position of, say, an electron is measured, it is found in only one place.
In between measurements we do not know exactly where the electron is, but the wave
function can be used to calculate the probability of it being found in any particular region
of space. On the assumption that the wave function provides a complete description of
quantum objects, many physicists believe that a particle does not follow a definite
trajectory in between measurements, but dissolves into ‘superposed probability waves’,
which then ‘collapse’ instantaneously, discontinuously, and quite inexplicably when the
next measurement is made.

This probabilistic approach was strongly opposed by Einstein, Planck, and


Schrödinger, but it was de Broglie and later Bohm and Vigier who played the main role
in developing an alternative. Chebotarev writes:

The central idea of the Stochastic Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics


consists in treating a microscopic object exhibiting a dual wave-particle
nature as composed of a particle in the proper sense of the word (a small
region in space with a high concentration of energy), and of an associated
wave that guides the particle’s motion. Both the particle and the wave are
considered to be real, physically observable, and objectively existing entities.
(p. 2)

Particles are pictured as oscillators (or solitons) beating in phase with their surrounding
pilot waves, which in turn result from the superposition of superluminal phase waves
carried by a subquantal etheric medium subject to constant stochastic fluctuations. The
force, or quantum potential, determining particle motions therefore carries information
from the entire environment, accounting for the ‘wholeness’ of quantum phenomena.

The causal stochastic approach can account for all the quantum properties of matter,
including all the so-called paradoxes. It therefore disproves the claim that the quantum
formalism requires us to abandon not only the quest for an explanation of quantum
phenomena but also the concepts of causality, continuity, and the objective reality of
individual microobjects. In Vigier’s view, the Copenhagen interpretation is based on
‘arbitrary philosophical assumptions’, and its insistence on the absolute and final
character of indeterminacy is dogmatic.

The causal stochastic approach is ‘the only known interpretation of quantum


mechanics in terms of which all quantum effects can be explained on the basis of
causal continuous motions in space and time’ (p. 142). It has no place for the ill-defined
notion of wave-packet collapse. There is only a ‘pseudo-collapse’, which ‘simply
represents a change of our knowledge and does not correspond to any real physical
changes in the state of the system’ (p. 147). Vigier says that even if the quantum-
potential approach ‘is not taken as a fully satisfactory description of quantum
mechanical reality, it at least shows in a clear way the features that such a description
must entail’ (p. 169).

In the causal approach, therefore, ‘the material world has an existence independent
of the knowledge of observers’ (p. 170). Vigier does not discuss possible explanations
for genuine psychokinesis (‘mind over matter’). However, invoking the abstract notion of
wave-function collapse certainly contributes nothing to a concrete understanding of
such phenomena (see Pratt, 1997). Bohm believed that the causal interpretation
opened the door to the creative operation of deeper, subtler, more mindlike levels of
reality. Like Bohm, Vigier stresses that it is by no means a return to the classical
mechanistic worldview. Some of his statements, however, seem to deny the existence
of free will (pp. 50-51, 99-100), though he acknowledges that, given the fundamental
complexity of nature, ‘The ghost cannot be exorcized from the machine’ (p. 169).

Vigier shows how, in stark contrast to the Copenhagen interpretation, the causal
interpretation is able to provide an intelligible and visualizable explanation of key
experiments such as the double-slit experiment and neutron-interferometry experiments
(pp. 137-72). In the double-slit experiment, if both slits are open an interference pattern
builds up on the screen even if electrons approach the slits one at a time. In the
Copenhagen interpretation, a single particle supposedly passes in some indefinable
sense through both slits and interferes with itself, whereas in the causal approach each
particle passes through only one slit whereas the pilot wave passes through both. If a
device is used to detect through which slit each particle travels, the interference pattern
disappears. In the Copenhagen interpretation, the measurement collapses the wave
function, whereas in the causal approach it affects the real pilot wave. The Copenhagen
interpretation claims that any path-determining measurement will destroy the
interference pattern, whereas the causal interpretation predicts that interference will
persist if future techniques allow a sufficiently subtle, nondemolition measurement to be
performed.

Neutron-interferometry experiments reproduce the double-slit configuration with


massive particles and introduce new interaction possibilities through neutron spin. In
these experiments, something exchanges energy with the spin-flip coils in the two arms
of the interferometer, and this interaction almost certainly involves real neutrons rather
than nebulous probability waves. Although such experiments cannot yet determine the
path of each individual neutron, they prove ‘the incompleteness of the quantum-
mechanical Copenhagen description because the persistence of an interference pattern
is combined with the existence of a definite trajectory for each particle, a fact forbidden
in the Copenhagen interpretation’ (p. 257). In other words, the wave and particle
aspects of matter can manifest simultaneously in the same experimental setup, thereby
contradicting the complementarity principle.

Vigier argues that quantum entanglement (EPR-type) experiments leave no doubt


that quantum mechanics is a nonlocal theory, i.e. that quantum systems can show
correlations that cannot be explained in terms of classical forces or signals propagating
at or slower than the speed of light. However, the EPR experiments conducted to date
still contain loopholes, and Chebotarev puts the probability of nonlocal connections at
about 90% (for a dissident view, see Thompson, 1998). Vigier proposes that nonlocal
interactions are not absolutely instantaneous but causal and superluminal; they are
mediated by the quantum potential, carried by superluminal phase waves in a Dirac-
type ether consisting of superfluid states of particle-antiparticle pairs. (If superluminal
connections were brought about by individual particles rather than phase waves, this
would contradict relativity theory, which Vigier upholds.)

Vigier writes:

In my opinion the most important development to be expected in the near


future concerning the foundations of quantum physics is a revival, in modern
covariant form, of the ether concept of the founding fathers of the theory of
light . . . [I]t now appears that the vacuum is a real physical medium which
presents some surprising properties . . . (p. 272)

In several places he refers to the ‘negative result’ of the Michelson-Morley ether-drift


experiment of 1887 (pp. 63, 192). However, contrary to what numerous textbooks and
popular science books claim, this famous experiment did not give a null result.

Vigier (1997a) himself acknowledges this in an article not included in the book, or
even mentioned in the bibliography. In it he states: ‘the observed effect was not zero in
Michelson’s famous experiment, as later confirmed by a (presently almost forgotten) set
of very detailed and very careful experiments by Morley and Miller [Miller, 1933].’ He
presents a brief overview of the ‘long set of remarkable experiments’ conducted from
1881 to 1926, which ‘are now completely ignored in the physics community’. These
experiments detected a small but consistent and systematic ether drift of about 9 km/s.

Although relativity theory assumed a zero ether drift (and a constant velocity of light),
Vigier (1997b) argues that a positive ether drift is compatible with special relativity if
photons are assumed to have a very small mass. He also argues that Sagnac’s
discovery in 1910 of fringe shifts in rotating interferometers (the Sagnac effect) can be
reconciled with general relativity on the same assumption. Whether the results of ether-
drift experiments, including more recent ones (e.g. Silvertooth & Whitney, 1992), are
best understood in terms of standard relativity theory is hotly contested (e.g. Galeczki,
1995; Hazelett & Turner, 1979; Múnera, 1997; Spolter, 1993).

Vigier points out the radical implications of non-zero-mass photons, as originally


proposed by Einstein, Schrödinger, and de Broglie:

If confirmed by experiment, it would necessitate a complete revision of


present cosmological views. The associated tired-light models could possibly
replace the so-called expanding Universe models. Non-velocity redshifts
could explain the anomalous quasar-galaxy associations, etc., and the
Universe would possibly be infinite in time (p. 273).

Vigier’s book is an important contribution to the debate on fundamental aspects of


quantum physics.

David Pratt

References

Galeczki, G. (1995). From Lorentz to Einstein and then back to Newton. Physics
Essays, 8, 591-593.

Hazelett, R., & Turner, D. (Eds.) (1979). The Einstein Myth and the Ives Papers: A
Counter-Revolution in Physics. Old Greenwich, CT: The Devin-Adair Company.

Miller, D. C. (1933). The ether-drift experiment and the determination of the absolute
motion of the earth. Reviews of Modern Physics, 5, 203-242.

Múnera, H. A. (1997). An absolute space interpretation (with non-zero photon mass) of


the non-null results of Michelson-Morley and similar experiments: An extension of
Vigier’s proposal. Apeiron, 4, 77-79.
Pratt, D. (1997). Consciousness, causality, and quantum physics. Journal of Scientific
Exploration, 11, 69-78.

Silvertooth, E. W., & Whitney, C. K. (1992). A new Michelson-Morley experiment.


Physics Essays, 5, 82-89.

Spolter, P. (1993). Gravitational Force of the Sun. Granada Hills, CA: Orb Publishing.

Thompson, C. H. (1998). Behind the scenes at the EPR magic show. In Selleri, F. (Ed.),
Open Questions in Relativistic Physics. Montreal: Apeiron (pp. 351-359).

Vigier, J. P. (1997a). Relativistic interpretation (with non-zero photon mass) of the small
ether drift velocity detected by Michelson, Morley and Miller. Apeiron, 4, 71-76.

Vigier, J. P. (1997b). New non-zero photon mass interpretation of the Sagnac effect as
direct experimental justification of the Langevin paradox. Physics Letters A, 234, 75-85.

Consciousness, causality, and quantum physics

Space, time, and relativity

Homepage

You might also like