You are on page 1of 12

Ethics, Medicine and Public Health (2016) 2, 523—534

Available online at

ScienceDirect
www.sciencedirect.com

DOSSIER ‘‘PERSONHOOD: INTIMITY AND OTHERNESS’’ /Studies

Narrative, identity and the therapeutic


encounter
Narratif, identité et la rencontre thérapeutique

M.J. Young (Resident Physician, Fellow) a,b,∗,


H.J. Bursztajn (Co-founder) c

a
Massachusetts General Hospital, Harvard Medical School, Boston, MA, USA
b
Department of Philosophy, Harvard University, Cambridge, MA, USA
c
Program in Psychiatry and the Law at BIDMC/MMHC Psychiatry of Harvard Medical School,
Boston, MA, USA

Received 5 June 2016; accepted 25 September 2016


Available online 23 November 2016

KEYWORDS Summary This article explores the place of narrative in the constitution of selfhood, and
Philosophy of through this lens examines its multifaceted role in the clinical encounter. It begins by explaining
medicine and and critically evaluating the recent view advocated by Schachtman and others that narrative
neuropsychiatry; is wholly constitutive of the self. On this view, the role played by narrative is not merely a
Identity; descriptive one, but serves more fundamentally as the ontological substrate upon which identity
Selfhood; is invariably built and sustained. Understood as such, this capacity may distinctively modulate
Mind; the meanings, motivations, and attitudes individuals adopt in reaction to and in anticipation of
Ethics; happenings in their lives. Acts of self-narrative can serve not only to describe meaningful facts
Personhood about a person’s life, but may also serve to reflexively influence the very states of affairs that
they aim to describe. After assessing the theoretical attraction of this view, counter-evidence
to this theory is adduced from clinical neuropsychiatric cases wherein lapses of narrative, such
as those observed in dementia, dissociative identity disorder, autism and amnestic syndromes,
do not entail wholesale losses of selfhood. Analyses of cases such as these reveal that there is
more than narrative that is constitutive of selfhood and identity, and further raises the question
of whether the absence of conveyed self-narrative ought to be interpreted as evidence of a
failure of this capacity versus as evidence that an agent simply is no longer is motivated to
express it. Rather than a monotonic construct, it is argued that narrative is one of a cadre
of crisscrossing capacities sharing some family resemblance and with characteristically open
texture that variably combine to produce selves with no single common denominator, but rather
with dynamic clusters of commonalities. Six other symbiotic dimensions are identified that
contribute to an intact scaffolding of selfhood, and disturbances within each of which might lead

∗ Corresponding author. Department of Medicine, Massachusetts General Hospital, 55, Fruit Street, 02114 Boston, MA, USA.
E-mail address: michael.young@mgh.harvard.edu (M.J. Young).

http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.jemep.2016.10.009
2352-5525/© 2016 Elsevier Masson SAS. All rights reserved.
524 M.J. Young, H.J. Bursztajn

to distinctive pathologies. In particular, the capacities for self-other representation; diachronic


unity; synchronic unity; consciousness (in particular, awareness); ecologic embededdness; and
cognitive unity are explained and evaluated, along with pathologies that may arise in the setting
of disturbances of each. It is contended that avenues of research studying the neural substrates
corresponding to these different dimensions of selfhoold, as well as how these varied neu-
ronal systems coalesce to produce a phenomenologically integrated and unified self is much
needed. Further clarity with respect to these issues can shed further light on how particular
brain lesions may differentially affect elaborations of selfhood. Such research could foresee-
ably include functional neuroimaging studies, non-invasive brain modulation (e.g., transcranial
magnetic stimulation; transcranial direct current stimulation), and targeted neuropsychologi-
cal testing of individuals with apparent disruptions of self stratified according to the different
dimensions elucidated to aid in uncovering the enigmatic neuroanatomy and neurophysiology
of selfhood. The cross-disciplinary nature of each of these avenues underscores the profound
importance of deep and sustained collaborations among philosophers, ethicists, clinicians and
researchers to optimize and advance approaches to the pathologies of the mind and the self.
Neuroethical upshots of the account of selfhood developed are discussed, including implica-
tions for treatment of individuals with neurodegenerative conditions wherein the self itself is
called into question, for the foundation and function living wills, and for approaches to pain
management in individuals with disorders of consciousness. While narrative, when elicited, can
provide a vital window into patient experience, lapses of narrative may be just as central to
the psychoanalysis of the self and to the therapeutic encounter. What is not, and cannot be
spoken, is often as vital as the narrative itself.
© 2016 Elsevier Masson SAS. All rights reserved.

MOTS CLÉS Résumé Cet article explore la place du narratif dans la constitution du Moi et examine, à
Philosophie médicale travers ce prisme, son rôle multifactoriel dans la rencontre clinique. Il commence par expli-
et neuropsychiatrie ; quer et évaluer de façon critique le point de vue récent de Schachtman et al., selon lequel le
Identité ; narratif constituerait entièrement le Moi. Sous cet angle, le rôle que joue le narratif n’est pas
Moi ; simplement descriptif, mais sert plus fondamentalement de sous-strate ontologique sur laque-
Esprit ; lle l’identité est invariablement construite et soutenue. Perçu comme tel, cette capacité peut
Éthique ; typiquement moduler les sens, motivations et attitudes que les individus adoptent en réagis-
Identité individuelle sant et en anticipant les événements de leur vie. Les actes de narration de soi peuvent servir
non seulement à décrire les faits pertinents de la vie de quelqu’un, mais peuvent également
influencer de façon réfléchie l’état des choses qu’ils tentent de décrire. Après avoir consid-
éré l’attrait théorique de cette perspective, nous fournissons des arguments qui réfutent cette
théorie en nous basant sur des cas de neuropsychiatrie clinique dans lesquels les défaillances
du narratif — telles que celles observées dans les cas de démence, de troubles dissociatifs
de l’identité, de l’autisme et du syndrome amnésique — n’entraînent pas une perte systéma-
tique du Moi. L’analyse de ces cas révèle qu’il y a plus que le narratif qui soit constitutif de
l’individualité et de l’identité. Ceci nous porte à nous questionner sur l’absence d’un récit de
soi articulé et si celui-ci doit être interprété comme d’une preuve d’incapacité, ou bien comme
d’une preuve que l’agent n’est plus motivé à l’exprimer. Nous soutiendrons que, plutôt qu’une
construction monotonique, la fonction narrative est celle d’un cadre de capacités croisées à
ressemblance familiale et une texture ouverte caractéristique qui se combine de manière vari-
able pour donner des Moi ne présentant pas un dénominateur commun unique mais plutôt un
groupe dynamique d’ensemble. Nous identifions six autres dimensions symbiotiques qui con-
tribuent à maintenir l’échafaudage du Moi intact et les possibles perturbations pour chacune
de ces dimensions, qui peuvent mener à des pathologies distinctes. En particulier, les capacités
de représentation de soi et de l’autre ; l’unité diachronique ; l’unité synchronique ; la con-
science (notamment la conscientisation) ; l’enchâssement écologique et l’unité cognitive sont
expliqués, évalués, de même que les pathologies qui peuvent émerger dans les contextes de
perturbation pour chacun de ces cas. Nous avançons que les possibilités de recherche portant
sur l’étude des strates neurologiques correspondant à ces différentes dimensions de l’identité
et sur comment ces systèmes neurologiques fusionnent un soi phénoménologiquement intégré
et unifié sont indispensables. Un éclaircissement de ces problématiques pourrait mettre en
lumière la façon dont les lésions cérébrales affectent l’élaboration du Moi. Cette recherche
Selfhood and the therapeutic encounter 525

pourrait inclure des études en neuroimagerie fonctionnelles, une modulation non invasive du
cerveau, (par exemple une stimulation magnétique transcrânienne ; une stimulation transcrâni-
enne à courant direct), et des tests neuropsychologiques ciblés pour les individus ayant des
perturbations apparentes du Moi. Stratifiée en fonction des différentes dimensions élucidées,
cette recherche permettrait de découvrir les énigmatiques neuroanatomie et neurophysiolo-
gie de l’individualité. La nature interdisciplinaire de chacune de ces possibilités réaffirme
l’importance des collaborations profondes et soutenues entre les philosophes, les éthiciens,
les cliniciens et les chercheurs, afin d’optimiser et d’avancer les approches des pathologies
de l’esprit et de l’identité. Nous abordons les développements des résultats neuroéthiques de
la narration du soi. Cette discussion inclut les implications pour le traitement des individus
ayant des conditions neurodégénératives — à travers lesquelles le Moi est remis en question —
pour la fondation et la création des désirs de vie et pour les approches face à la gestion de la
douleur pour les individus ayant des troubles de la conscience. Bien que le narratif, quand il
est exprimé, offre une fenêtre vitale sur l’expérience du patient, les failles du narratif peuvent
être tout aussi centrales pour la psychanalyse du Moi et la rencontre thérapeutique. Ce qui
n’est pas et ne peut pas être dit est souvent tout aussi important que ce qui est narré.
© 2016 Elsevier Masson SAS. Tous droits réservés.

The staggeringly diverse array of experiences encoun- Schechtman [1] offers another illustrative example:
tered directly and indirectly in neuropsychiatric practice
provides illuminating pathways through which to probe ‘‘take an event described neutrally as stepping off of
the nature of identity and selfhood. Such analyses reveal an airplane at a particular airport. For the person leav-
a distinctive porosity and elasticity to the configuration ing the plane, this event will be very different if she is
of personal identity, features that might be easily over- (a) arriving at the country where she will finally pick up
looked when such theorizing proceeds detached from its the child whose adoption she has eagerly anticipated, (b)
nourishing, empirical roots in phenomenology and clinical arriving at the country of her deployment for dangerous
semiology. military duty having left small children behind at home,
Eliciting and entertaining the narratives of patients, a (c) arriving at the place where she will give an academic
centerpiece of virtually all therapeutic encounters, has of address and receive a prestigious reward, or (d) arriving
late received renewed attention among theoreticians and for the funeral of a beloved relative who died unexpect-
practitioners alike. Whereas traditionally narrative has been edly and very young. The same neutrally described event
treated as a purely descriptive portal into the experience will yield a different experience and lead to different
and identity of patients, the view that the identity itself con- actions and decisions in each of these cases because it is
sists in the capacity to weave life events into a coherent and part of a different narrative and it takes its character
characteristic narrative has been described and defended from the story of which it is a part. The Narrative Self-
most recently by Marya Schechtman and others. On this Constitution View claims that all of our experiences are
view, the role played by narrative is not merely a descrip- like this. As persons interact with the world, they carry
tive one, but serves more fundamentally as the ontological with them an implicit awareness of the basic elements of
substrate upon which identity is invariably built and sus- their histories and anticipated trajectories which at each
tained. Understood as such, this capacity may distinctively moment influences both their experience of the present
modulate the meanings, motivations, and attitudes individ- and their deliberations about what to do next. Accord-
uals display in reaction to and in anticipation of happenings ing to this account, persons are able to have the kinds
in their lives. of experiences and engage in the kinds of behaviors they
Acts of self-narrative can serve not only to describe do precisely because they bring their ongoing life stories
meaningful facts about a person’s life, but may also serve to to bear on the present and so structure their experience
reflexively influence the very states of affairs that they aim of the world according to an ongoing autobiographical
to describe. This bears resemblance to J.L. Austin’s view of narrative. The unity of a single person, according to this
language as performative, except it extends it to the inter- view, is the unity of a narrative’’.
nal language, as it were, of the mind. While prima facie
self-narrative is a construct that exists solely to describe This turn from conceptualizing narrative as a descriptive
reality as it is or is imagined to be, deeper analysis reveals tool to an ontological cornerstone of identity is a provocative
that self-narrative may not only to describe facts but can one. Jean-Paul Sartre poignantly highlighted the phenomen-
also establish new facts by representing them as such. In ological implications of self-narrative in earlier terms in his
such settings, meaning is used to create facts that can give exposition of the concept of bad faith. Through this concept,
agents new grounds for acting. In settings of addiction, for Sartre gestures toward the notion that in the construction of
instance, a desire’s motivational influence might be rein- self-narratives individuals are prone to a particularly perni-
forced by an addict’s self-narrative that might pick out and cious tendency to exclude the role of volition in determining
elevate the relevant desire as providing the strongest reason the course of lived events, a tendency which he equates
for acting. to a denial of consciousness which ineluctably governs the
526 M.J. Young, H.J. Bursztajn

interface between the objective world and conscious fact. Identity beyond narrative
Hence, Sartre argues:

‘‘[t]he human being is not only the being by whom In the latter half of his Philosophical Investigations,
négatités are disclosed in the world; he is also the Wittgenstein reminds us of ‘‘a main cause of philosophi-
one who can take negative attitudes with respect cal disease — one-sided diet: one nourishes one’s thinking
to himself. . . there exist more subtle behaviors, the with only one kind of example’’ (§593) [5]. In considering
description of which will lead us further into the inward- the constitution of identity, it is important to relinquish
ness of consciousness. Irony is one of these. In irony a this impulse, and to seek conceptual nourishment from as
man annihilates what he posits within one and the same wide array of examples as possible; while Schechtman’s
act; he leads us to believe in order not to be believed; articulation of the capacity to ‘‘present and structure the
he affirms to deny and denies to affirm; he creates a world according to an ongoing autobiographical narrative’’
positive object but it has no being other than its nothing- is apposite, the position appears to overreach insofar as
ness. Thus attitudes of negation toward the self permit it asserts that narrative alone is constitutive of identity.
us to raise a new question: What are we to say is the Let us consider what is constitutive of identity beyond this
being of man who has the possibility of denying himself? capacity, and the relevance of this issue to the therapeutic
But it is out of the question to discuss the attitude of encounter.
‘self-negation’ in its universality. The kinds of behavior Consider an individual who appears to wholly lack the
which can be ranked under this heading are too diverse; intact capacity to construct a self-narrative, such as may
we risk retaining only the abstract form of them. It is be evident in a patient with advanced Alzheimer’s disease.
best to choose and to examine one determined attitude In such a scenario, selfhood does not altogether vanish in
which is essential to human reality and which is such the absence of this intact capacity; a self remains, albeit
that consciousness instead of directing its negation out- noticeably less robust. It is neither a shadow of selfhood
ward turns it toward itself. This attitude, it seems to nor a mimic of selfhood that one identifies in observing
me, is bad faith (mauvaise foi). . . consciousness affects such an individual, rather, it is a self that is in one, rather
itself with bad faith. There must be an original inten- particular sense, indisposed. The limited extent of the
tion and a project of bad faith; this project implies a explanatory power of this capacity alone in accounting for
comprehension of bad faith as such and a pre-reflective what is constitutive of selfhood will be more fully appreci-
apprehension (of) consciousness as affecting itself with ated in the course of accounting for other key components
bad faith. . . one who practices bad faith is hiding a dis- of this complex scaffolding, and in directing attention to
pleasing truth or presenting as truth a pleasing untruth. a range of clinical examples and thought experiments not
Bad faith then has in appearance the structure of false- ordinarily considered. One might further question whether
hood. Only what changes everything is the fact that in absence of conveyed self-narrative ought to be interpreted
bad faith it is from myself that I am hiding the truth’’ as evidence of a failure of this capacity versus as evidence
(pp. 208—215) [2]. that an agent simply is no longer is motivated to express
it.
Paradigmatic instances of bad faith are not uncommonly Patients with amnestic syndromes arising for instance
encountered in substance use narratives; in such contexts, from lesions to the thalamus, hippocampus, or fornix, in
through denying the possibility of freedom, agents who some forms of epilepsy [6], in forms of dementia, or
have developed addictions to substances or behaviors might in autoimmune conditions such as limbic encephalitis [7]
claim incapacity as rationalizations for continuing substance may, to varying degrees, lose their abilities or motiva-
use. In this manner, denial of consciousness in the original tions to recount or produce coherent narratives of events
construction of self-narratives may powerfully actuate or in their current or past lives; yet, it would be tenden-
perpetuate behavioral patterns, rather than merely serve tious to posit that identity in such patients is perforce
to describe them. In contradistinction to patterns of bad lost. Remaining dimensions of selfhood may remain intact
faith, Sartre incisively contends that ‘‘it would be better to despite the loss of narrative unity or motivation to express
recognize frankly that whatever is going on in consciousness it. Without narrative unity, it is not that identity is lost,
can receive its explanation nowhere but from consciousness but rather that identity has changed; it becomes, in an
itself’’ (pp. 249). Through the affirmation of consciousness important sense, less robust, but it does not altogether
in self-narrative, agents may expand the perceived array recede. The capacity for constructing active narratives
of potential behavioral trajectories and thereby reimagine depends, in turn, on a variety of other important capaci-
the possibility of freedom. Interestingly, these ideas align ties, including memory, motivation, assignment of meaning
well with Gerald Edelman and Arnold Modell’s models of and emotional valence and embededdness in a field of
self-referential consciousness and so-called ‘‘neural Darwin- dynamic relationships as will be explored in following sec-
ism,’’ which posit that the subjective divide between self tions.
and non-self hinges on adaptive neurophysiological systems To further illustrate the scope of problems that arise in
that function to ‘‘determine the relative salience of exter- the course of theorizing about identity and key approaches
nal events according to internal value schemes. It affects the taken toward addressing them, a few central points
selection of goals and action patterns and therefore affects regarding the notion of selfhood and identity in the history
behavior’’ and promote survival [3,4]. of modern philosophy are in order.
Selfhood and the therapeutic encounter 527

Beyond Hume: demystifying the In the view of Descartes, the mere existence of mental
activity analytically entails a thinking self. Accordingly, he
scaffolding of selfhood argues in Meditations on First Philosophy, ‘‘[b]ut what then
In A Treatise of Human Nature, Hume famously casts skep- am I? A thing which thinks. What is a thing which thinks? It
ticism on the foundations of philosophical reflection on the is a thing which doubts, understands, affirms, denies, wills,
self, arguing that since the self is never directly observed, refuses, which also imagines and feels. . . Here I make my
and rather what is observed is only successions of expe- discovery: thought exists; it alone cannot be separated from
riences (never the underlying putative self having those me. I am; I exist — this is certain. But for how long? For as
experiences), to speak of the self is empirically untenable long as I am thinking; for perhaps it could also come to pass
(emphasis added): that if I were to cease all thinking I would then utterly cease
to exist. . . I am therefore precisely nothing but a thinking
‘‘There are some philosophers who imagine we are thing; that is a mind, or intellect, or understanding, or rea-
every moment intimately conscious of what we call son — words of whose meanings I was previously ignorant.
our self; that we feel its existence and its continu- Yet I am a true thing and am truly existing; but what kind
ance in existence; and are certain, beyond the evidence of thing? I have said it already: a thinking thing. . . it is this
of a demonstration, both of its perfect identity and same ‘I’ who senses or who is cognizant of bodily things as
simplicity. . .but self or person is not any one impression, if through the senses. For example, I now see a light, I hear
but that to which our several impressions and ideas are a noise, feel heat. These things are false, since I am asleep.
supposed to have a reference. If any impression gives rise Yet I certainly do seem to see, hear, and feel warmth. This
to the idea of self, that impression must continue invari- cannot be false. Properly speaking, this is what in me is
ably the same, thro’ the whole course of our lives; since called ‘sensing’. But this, precisely taken, is nothing other
self is supposed to exist after that manner. But there than thinking’’ (31—32, emphasis added) [9].
is no impression constant and invariable. Pain and plea- An important upshot of this argument is that it results in
sure, grief and joy, passions and sensations succeed each selfhood being bound up with consciousness. In Descartes’
other, and never all exist at the same time. It cannot, view, then, a thing that does not think cannot be justifi-
therefore, be from any of these impressions, or from any ably called a self, and any thinking thing might be said
other, that the idea of self is derived; and consequently to instantiate some degree of selfhood.1 In the language
there is no such idea. . . [what is experienced is] noth- of contemporary neuroscience, which canonically describes
ing but a bundle or collection of different perceptions, consciousness as the union of wakefulness (i.e., arousal,
which succeed each other with an inconceivable rapid- which is mediated by the reticular activating system and
ity, and are in a perpetual flux and movement. Our eyes its ascending thalamocortical projections treversing the ros-
cannot turn in their sockets without varying our percep- tral brainstem tegmentum) and awareness (mediated by
tions. Our thought is still more variable than our sight; the cerebral cortices, thalami, basal ganglia, and limbic
and all our other senses and faculties contribute to this networks), it is presence or absence of awareness that is
change; nor is there any single power of the soul, which constitutive of the ‘I’. Interestingly, such considerations
remains unalterably the same, perhaps for one moment. intersect with those used in prevailing approaches to dis-
The mind is a kind of theatre, where several perceptions tinguishing brain death from vegetative states, with brain
successively make their appearance; pass, re-pass, glide death hinging on irrecoverable loss of wakefulness and
away, and mingle in an infinite variety of postures and awareness [10].
situations. There is properly no simplicity in it at one In contrast, the Kantian response to Humean skepticism
time, nor identity in different; whatever natural propen- about selfhood focuses not on the logical entailments of con-
sion we may have to imagine that simplicity and identity. sciousness but rather on a subtle yet salient feature of our
The comparison of the theatre must not mislead us. They experiences themselves, namely, the experience of sequen-
are the successive perceptions only, that constitute the tial events as a connected, coherent and synthesized whole,
mind; nor have we the most distant notion of the place, rather than as disjointed series of discrete occurrences. It
where these scenes are represented, or of the materials, is this synthetic unity of experience (what Kant dubs the
of which it is composed’’ [8]. ‘‘transcendental unity of apperception’’) that necessitates
positing an underlying self that enables the phenomenolo-
This variety of empiricism, on which the meaningfulness gical unity of experienced sequences of events that would
of a concept is necessarily grounded in direct experi- otherwise be experienced as disjointed.
ences of the concept, leads Hume not only to reject the Kant thus zigs where Hume zags. While conceding the
meaningfulness of the self but also to reject the mean- Humean point that the self is never empirically observed,
ingfulness of the concept of causation; while sequences rather than concluding that the self does not exist, Kant con-
of events may be observed, inability to directly observe tends that the self is necessarily given a priori as a condition
the causal glue, as it were, that links events in a puta- for the possibility of a unified and coherent phenomenology
tively causal scheme, animates Hume’s skepticism about of experience. It is important to note that this synthetic
causation in a manner similar to his skepticism about self- capacity operates in both diachronic and synchronic modes
hood. [11]; diachronic, in its ability to synthesize temporally dis-
Responses to Humean skepticism about selfhood have
classically assumed one of two forms, one rooted in the tra-
dition of René Descartes and one rooted in the tradition of 1 That selfhood is fundamentally nonmonotonic and may come in
Immanuel Kant. go in degrees is a key point of the present analysis.
528 M.J. Young, H.J. Bursztajn

tinct experiences; and synchronic, in its ability to synthesize attitude its own (p. 171) [13]. Researchers studying this phe-
numerically distinct experiences. nomenon have concluded that ‘‘the fact that objects at the
To illustrate, consider an individual listening to a piece focus of the [other’s] attitudes change in meaning for the
of music while simultaneously playing chess. Such an indi- infant [depending on what the other’s attitudes are, shows
vidual is able to do engage in both of these experiences at how the infant’s attitudes fluctuate in tandem] with the atti-
once; it is not that she oscillates back and forth between tudes of the other. . . such that the world comes to have
playing chess and listening to music, rather, the capacity for meaning according to oneself as identified with the other,
synchronic unity enables one to simultaneously experience and therefore. . . a new meaning for oneself’’ (p. 171) [13].
both of these activities. On the other hand, the capacity for In this way, one’s own representations of objects, events and
diachronic unity grounds the ability to experience the piece concepts are formed through interactions with the repre-
of music as a coherent whole rather than as a series of dis- sentations of others. The interactivity upon which our basic
jointed notes, as well as the ability to play a coherent round abilities to represent the world and our selves as we do
of chess experiences as a unified series of moves in a game, depends is what later allows for more sophisticated styles
rather than as a disunified string of unrelated movements of of collaboration. We tend to think that what we feel and
small physical objects of varying shapes. These two crucial know comes about through processes that are largely inde-
capacities served by the self — diachronic synthesis and syn- pendent of what others feel and know, but the implications
chronic synthesis — are important to consider in appraising of these findings are that our attitudes, concepts, judgments
the varieties of pathologies of selfhood that may emerge. — indeed, our selves — are not independent constructs but
Our analysis thus far has brought to light at least are rather thoroughly inter-relational constructs.
three conceptualizations of what is constitutive of selfhood Kindred themes of intersubjectivity were philosophically
beyond narrative: (A) that which consists in synthesizing probed in Martin Buber’s 1923 Ich und Du (I and Thou),
experiences (diachronically and synchronically); (B) that in which Buber proffers that ‘‘[t]hrough the Thou a man
which consists in conscious awareness/thinking; and (C) that becomes I. That which confronts him comes and disappears,
which consists in differentiating the personal from the for- relational events condense, then are scattered, and in the
eign (i.e., self-other representation, which may operate change consciousness of the unchanging partner, of the I,
doxastically and affectively). In considering this conceptual grows clear, and each time stronger. . . The I is real in virtue
landscape, it is most suitable to regard this cast of capacities of its sharing in reality. The fuller its sharing the more real
as symbiotic elements of selfhood, each illuminated by a dif- it becomes.’’ (pp. 28, 63) [14].
ferent sort of example, rather than as logically competing or This ecological approach to appraising selfhood reca-
mutually exclusive theories. The remainder of this section pitulates an intriguing conceptual turn in the history and
will explore two other capacities to be accounted for in a philosophy of modern immunology, wherein the paradigm
satisfying scaffolding of selfhood: ecological embededdness, of immune identity as predicated on a strict self/non-self
and cognitive unity. dichotomy has been gradually upended by a paradigm of
immune identity that focuses on open and dynamic ecolog-
From ecological embeddedness to selfhood ical integration as an organizing principle. Describing this
shift in theoretical orientation, Tauber describes that this is
Drawing on their anthropological study of self-construal ‘‘a fully ecological perspective (supported by systems biol-
across different cultures as seen through child-rearing ogy more generally) [that] alter[s] the basic postulates of
behaviors and other social norms, Markus and Kitayama [12] immune theory based on an insular self. Instead of a the-
argue that the concept of the self as an independent unit ory grounded on self/non-self distinctions, models of the
distinct from the collective is misleadingly overemphasized immune system would be built on an ‘open’ architecture
in European-American theory. Instead, they develop and to fully represent the dynamic and dialectical relationship
defend a concept of selfhood as intimately bound up in the characterizing an organism engaged in its environment. . .
greater collective: ‘‘[T]he self [should be] viewed not as conceptually, the arguments for and against these com-
an independent entity separate from the collective,’’ they peting views provide the arena for the philosopher’s own
contend, ‘‘but instead as a priori fundamentally interde- discourse, one that has repercussions for philosophy of
pending with others. Individuals do not stand in opposition to biology at large’’ (pp. 233—241) [15].2 The ‘ecological ori-
the confines and constraints of the external collective, nor
do they voluntarily choose to become parts of this external
collective. Instead the self is inherently social — an integral 2 Detailing the relevance of ecological frameworks in immune
part of the collective. This interdepending view grants pri- identity, Tauber importantly points out that ‘‘[w]hile immune cells
macy to the relationship between self and others. The self distribute themselves throughout the body, they are particularly
derives only from the individual’s relationships with specific conspicuous at the interfaces between host tissues and the envi-
others in the collective. There is no self without the collec- ronment: within the skin and underlying muscosal surfaces (e.g.,
tive; the self is a part that becomes whole only in interaction the respiratory tract and gastrointestine). These are the sites
where the body first encounters chemicals and micro-organisms,
with others. . . In this view a type of intersubjectivity, rather
and thereby senses toxins and destroys pathogens. Such interfaces
than a private subjectivity, would be the strongest, most
are obviously open and dynamic, and they possess a complexity
elaborated aspect of self’’ (p. 570) [12]. distinct to themselves. . . the organism adjusts its own identity as
As an example that illustrates how the self may achieve it responds along a continuum of behaviors to adapt to the chal-
elaboration only within a social collective, consider the lenges it faces, and, indeed, ‘identity’ is determined by particular
infant, who, when introduced to something unknown, looks context. Responses are consequently based not on intrinsic for-
toward an adult in its presence and makes the adult’s eignness, but rather on how the immune system sees an ‘alien’ or
Selfhood and the therapeutic encounter 529

entation’ elucidated by Tauber bears relevance beyond temporally unified but nonetheless may exhibit a profound
conceptualization of immune identity to the interdependent logical discrepancy among different beliefs, behaviors and
architecture of selfhood writ large. goals [16]. By analogy, a first-time player of a complicated
This interdependent dimension of selfhood serves as game might be able to experience a round of a game as a
a vital complement to the narrative dimension examined temporally unified whole, but may lack full understanding
above. Insofar as life stories that persons carry invariably or logical execution of the rules governing the game, mak-
feature others in the social fabric (much as immune identity ing moves in successive turns that are, with respect to the
hinges on the landscape of antigens interfaced with), and intended or anticipated outcome, effectively contradictory.
conversely, as roles and relationships that exist in a social The capacity to ensure that items populating one’s mental
schema routinely gain full-form only through life stories space are generally internally consistent (viz., not logically
conferring meaning and emotional valence to an otherwise contradictory) allows for a distinctive unity of experience,
inconsequential array of bare facts, the narrative dimension cognition and action that in part underpins the capacity to
of selfhood is intimately aligned with an ecological orienta- live and communicate effectively.
tion. This capacity of cognitive unity is, however, enigmatic,
An interdependent concept of self-identity carries novel owing in part to a range of philosophical puzzles that emerge
implications for how we think about pathologies of selfhood when aiming to square this capacity of selfhood with a vari-
by shifting the relevant object to include the collective. ety of ordinary phenomena that appear to defy it. Notably,
As such, putative features that may be apparent given a some have argued that making sense of cases of putative
strictly independent self-construal may not be apparent irrationality, self-deception and akrasia (‘weakness of will’)
given an interdependent self-construal. Moreover, miscon- requires positing a model of the mind that is no longer uni-
struing self-concepts at play in human experience may give fied, but is constitutively divided. Sigmund Freud’s extensive
rise to defective approaches to the diagnosis and manage- observations of clinical neuroses, for instance, famously led
ment of relevant disorders of selfhood. him to propose an ‘‘architectonic principle of the mental
apparatus [that] lies in a stratification, a building up of
superimposed agencies’’ (p. 192) [17]. Freud advocated for
Cognitive unity a ‘‘subdivison of the unconscious [as] part of an attempt to
picture the apparatus of the mind as being built up of a num-
A remaining key feature to consider in appraising the archi- ber of agencies or systems whose relations to one another
tecture of identity is that of cognitive unity. ‘Cognitive are expressed in spatial terms. . . without implying any con-
unity’ here refers to a general logical coherence of the nection with the actual anatomy of the brain’’ (XX 32) [17].
attitudes, intentions, motivations, beliefs and volitions that Later theorists, including Donald Davidson and David Pears,
populate one’s mental space and which enables individuals adopted alternative views subdividing the mind to meet the
to effectively deliberate, plan and act in their lives in a man- conceptual challenges of irrationality, or of cases where
ner that is, at least by the agent’s own lights, coherent and individuals appear to act against their own better judgment
reasonable. [18—20].
This capacity encapsulates more than mere diachronic or Although mental partitioning may present as an appealing
synchronic synthesis (which as detailed above, underpins the answer to the problems of irrationality, it raises its own array
phenomenological unity of experience) or that of narrative. of perplexing issues concerning agency, identity, control,
It refers not to an experiential unity but rather refers to a responsibility and the self. Exactly what is it that performs
unity characterized by logical coherence. The role of this and orchestrates the partitioning? When are these partitions
capacity is perhaps best illustrated through observation of formed, and what is the substrate that is partitioned? If
cases in which it breaks down, such as in dissociative identity numerous partitions are independently capable of promp-
disorder wherein an individual might experience events as ting action or belief, is the person to be regarded as a single
agent or as a bundle of multiple agents? If as a single agent,
what serves to unify the multiple partitions that the agent
‘domestic’ antigen in the larger context of the body’s economy. . . contains? If as multiple agents, what implications does this
al. Because such border areas contain species from each habi-
have for holding whole persons, insofar as they are collec-
tat, unique forms of competition may occur, giving rise to unique
dynamic relationships. . .. new opportunities arise in such an envi-
tions of agents, accountable for actions brought about by
ronment [and] ecotones may be seen as engines of biological a single recalcitrant partition? Invoking a unifying mental
innovation. Diversity and dynamism are greatest at the margins principle or overlapping topology to meet these challenges
between habitats, and it is at such interfaces that whole new bio- appears to leave us squarely where we started; viz., having
logical forms probably originated. Far from being places of pure to explain how, in spite of this putative unity, agents can
strife, some ecotones are characterized as much by cooperation and wittingly believe or act inconsistently or against their own
synergism as by cutthroat competition. . . [an] ecological orientation better judgment.
brings issues of communication and information theory directly onto Jean-Paul Sartre echoes this criticism in responding to
notions of immune regulation, where different tiers of bidirectional Freud’s early theory of a mental divide between the con-
cognition between pathogens and immune cells set the balance
scious and unconscious. The problem, Sartre remarks, ‘‘still
of responses and adaptation. Indeed, ‘immune cognition’—–replete
with metaphorical ‘memory’, ‘perception’, and ‘recognition’—–has
remains of accounting for the unity of the total phenomenon
already provided a new scientific lexicon for a variety of converg- (repression of the drive which disguises itself and ‘passes’
ing conceptual orientations. . .’’ (p. 233) [15]. See also Tauber and in symbolic form), to establish comprehensible connections
Podolsky. The generation of diversity: Clonal selection theory and among its different phases. How can the repressed drive
the rise of molecular immunology. Harvard University Press, 2000. ‘disguise itself’ if it does not include (1) the consciousness
530 M.J. Young, H.J. Bursztajn

of being repressed, (2) the consciousness of being pushed Contrary to this standard story according to which all
back because it is what it is, [and] (3) a project of disguise? actions are, perforce, motivated by primary reasons, it
No mechanistic theory. . .can explain these modifications’’ may well be the case that actions are only contingently
(p. 210) [21]. ‘‘By rejecting the conscious unity of the motivated by primary reasons. In cases where they are,
psyche,’’ Sartre proceeds, ‘‘Freud is obliged to imply. . . a such actions could be deemed rational, and in cases where
magic unity linking distant phenomena across obstacles. . . they are not, such actions could be deemed not rational
[yet, this] explanation by magic does not avoid the coex- (arational or irrational). For perhaps what it means to be
istence — on the level of the unconscious, on that of irrational is to act without any primary reason at all, where
the censor [which unifies the parts], and on that of con- one could have acted with a primary reason.
sciousness — of two contradictory, complimentary structures On this view, when an agent acts irrationally, there is
which reciprocally imply and destroy each other. We [thus] no primary reason that needs to be sequestered from the
find that the problem that we had attempted to resolve agent’s better all-things-considered reason. Whereas the
is still untouched’’ (pp. 210—11) [21]. In explaining how standard account designates primary reasons as necessary
partitions unite within one person to dynamically interact, conditions for all actions, this account delegates primary
one is confronted with the same problem motivating the- reasons to the more circumscribed conceptual role as suffi-
oretical efforts to partition the mind in the first place. cient conditions for rational actions. Of course, this account
Pears cites this criticism in Motivated Irrationality, but does not entail that mental partitioning is conceptually
does not explain how his formulation of mental partition- impossible; instead, it explains why mental partitioning is
ing resolves the problem. In Freud’s Anatomies of the Self, not strictly necessary to explain irrationality and that there
Thalberg raises a related host of ‘‘identification problems’’ are alternative ways of viewing action and agency that
with Freud’s treatment of the mind (p. 254) [22], and has do not require a constitutively partitioned mind. Moreover,
us ‘‘[r]ecall Freud’s treatment of our instincts or drives. this account does not rule out the possibility that the irra-
Freud says ‘these processes strive toward gaining pleasure; tional mind only sometimes is partitioned, or that sometimes
psychical activity draws back from any event which might mental partitioning does account for irrational behaviors.
arouse unpleasure’ (1911b, XII, 219). But whose enjoyment Rather, it has sought only to explain why the concepts of
do they ‘strive’ for? Why mine? Surely it is unintelligible agency and action themselves do not conceptually oblige us
to suppose they enjoy escaping from my homeostatic men- to partition the self in accounting for the colorful array of
tal apparatus. . ..[w]hich ‘self’ does my ego have the duty conflicts that populate the economy of action and thought.
of preserving? How is its continued existence related to The tendency to invoke mental partitioning, even when
mine?. . . What exactly do we mean by ‘its own advantage’? not strictly logically necessary, is likely an artifact of what
[The] notion of this prominent actor within us. . .seems quite has been dubbed the seductive allure effect, a term that
elusive’’ (p. 254) [22]. The problems articulated by Sartre encapsulates findings substantiated by recent studies that
and Thalberg are perhaps most pronounced when considered people tend to exhibit ‘‘a general preference for reduc-
through the lens of Freud’s theory of the mind, but it is not tive information, even when it is irrelevant to the logic of
clear whether more contemporary theories of partitioning an explanation’’ [23]. The categorical dichotomy commonly
successfully avoid them. drawn between the cognitive and affective is another likely
A few key points gesturing toward a solution to this prob- byproduct of this pervasive reductive tendency. Overlook-
lem of how to reconcile the conceptual need to posit some ing the interconnectedness of these dimensions can give rise
form of cognitive unity with the range of regular instances of to oversimplified and misleading approaches to the assess-
human action and cognition which seem to defy it should be ment of competence in decision makers, which may become
noted in defense of cognitive unity as a durable dimension dominated by cognitive criteria to the neglect of affective
of selfhood. factors that can powerfully modulate the abilities of agents
Theories of mental partitioning in accounting for irra- to engage in balanced decision-making [24,25].
tionality and akrasia stem from a philosophical impulse
to preserve a certain orthodoxy about action according to
which every action, by virtue of being an action, is per- Pathologies of identity
force caused by a primary reason which stands to explain
The foregoing analysis reveals that our concept of iden-
and to motivate its behavioral effect [18]. On this view,
tity encapsulates a wide repertory of symbiotic capacities.
an agent’s behavior at any point in time constitutes action
To review, seven key capacities that might be said to be
if and only if it is caused intentionally by a certain kind
constitutive of an intact scaffolding of selfhood have been
of reason-oriented mental state. This generates difficulties
elucidated:
when trying to account for irrational action, requiring us to • diachronic unity;
either jettison its conceptual possibility (a view dating back • synchronic unity;
to Socrates, who famously professed, ‘‘no one voluntarily • self-other representation;
pursues that which he judges to be wrong3 ’’) or to pre- • narrative (past, present and future);
serve its possibility by positing mental partitions containing • consciousness (in particular, awareness);
competing sets of potentially motivating reasons. • ecological embededdness;
• cognitive unity.
3 The translation here is in line with Norman Gulley’s in The Inter- Though not meant to be exhaustive of the entire conceptual
pretation of ‘No One Does Wrong Willingly’ in Plato’s Dialogues terrain, these elements might be regarded as key capacities
[44]. that coalesce to form an intact scaffolding of selfhood.
Selfhood and the therapeutic encounter 531

This approach represents a marked departure from pre- not know the year that the games were held. He recog-
vailing approaches to selfhood; rather than reducing the nized all the Korean presidents when given the names
self to a monotonic concept with a single common denom- (10 presidents since 1948); however, he did not know the
inator, the self on this account consists in a network of order of the presidents who were elected after Octo-
crisscrossing symbiotic capacities that share some family ber 1996, although he correctly identified the order of
resemblance and displays a characteristically open texture. the presidents before 1996. Nevertheless, he was able
‘‘[A]s in spinning a thread,’’ to borrow the apt description to accurately identify periods of 10 or 20 seconds and
of family resemblance concepts Wittgenstein develops, ‘‘we had good musical rhythm, suggesting that his internal
twist fibre on fibre. And the strength of the thread does not clock was normal. He had also normal biologic rhythms,
reside in the fact that some one fibre runs through its whole including a normal sleep cycle. In other neuropsychologic
length, but in the overlapping of many fibres’’ (§67) [5,26]. examinations, he had a normal performance in tests of
Substantial alterations of any of these elements could episodic, semantic, and implicit memories, as well as in
foreseeably result in a fracturing, disintegration or trans- tests of attention, praxis, frontal executive functions,
formation of the emergent self, resulting in an array of frontal inhibitory function, visuospatial function, cal-
conditions, from the ordinary to the pathological. For culation, and language. After the symptoms began, he
example, phenomena of thought-insertion delusions in failed to return to his former job. . . Although the patient
schizophrenia and mirror-touch synesthesia are emblematic remembered all events after his stroke, they were reg-
of disturbances in the capacity of self-other representation istered without time information. Thus, although the
[27], and loss or fracturing of cognitive unity may manifest patient seemed to have normal episodic memory, he
in conditions such as dissociative identity disorder. had severe difficulty in remembering the time informa-
Indeed, variable disturbances of each of the capacities tion associated with events and in retrieving them in
enumerated above may result in distinctive clinical presen- the appropriate sequence’’ (supplemental document A1,
tations, furnishing a rich empirical basis for studying the pp. 2—3) [29].
phenomenology and neurobiology of each respective dimen-
sion of the self. Accordingly, conceptualizing and studying Cases such as this reveal the importance of diachronic
such conditions qua disturbances of selfhood may help to unity in maintaining higher order functioning, while at the
reveal novel features of their phenomenology, and accord- same time revealing that its isolated loss does not entail the
ingly illuminate novel areas for future research and guide wholesale loss of selfhood (a conclusion which, it might be
approaches to therapy. argued, may be entailed by a minimalist Kantian conceptu-
With respect to the diachronic dimension of selfhood, alization of the self). It moreover provides insight into the
striking cases to consider are those of chronotaraxis (‘time possible neural underpinnings of this particular dimension
amnesia’) and chronoblindness, pronounced confusion with of selfhood as diachronic unity, narrowing potential local-
respect to time, or inability to perceive the passage of ization to the thalami and parietal lobe. Studying instances
time. In such cases, patients may experience acute or pro- of simultagnosia (inability to perceive more than a single
longed temporal disorientation. These conditions have been object at a time), akinetopsia (inability to perceive motion)
described as being occasioned by thalamic lesions [28—30] [32] and related attentional disturbances can help clarify
or right parietal pathology [31]. In their supplemental data, the neural underpinnings of synchronic unity in a similar
Lee et al. report the fascinating case of this sort [29]: fashion.
Turning our attention to pathologies of the narrative
A 38-year-old gentleman was ‘‘admitted for a sudden dimension of selfhood, it is apt to consider how loss of
somnolence while playing golf [in the fall of 1996]. autobiographical memory in Alzheimer’s disease may char-
When admitted to the hospital, he was in a state of acteristically give way to a distinctive loss of narrative, and
stupor without other focal neurological abnormalities. yet other dimensions of selfhood may remain intact. As such,
After MRI and a full work-up, he was diagnosed with conceptualizing Alzheimer’s disease as an en-bloc loss of self
the bilateral medial thalamic infarction in the area of is misconceived. Delicate care should be taken among clini-
the paramedian thalamic arteries arising from a com- cians and researchers in deciding how to conceptualize and
mon trunk. . . His consciousness returned after a week, explain alterations of self in such common clinical condi-
although he presented a severe impairment of time ori- tions, the communication of which could impact not only
entation. This impairment has continued for more than how patients and families come to make sense of their condi-
13 years. . . he was unaware of the day, month, year, and tion, but may also bear significantly on debates in public
exact time at the interview. He was also unaware of the policy surrounding patient rights and legal norms, as may be
duration of his stay in the clinic room, the time taken gleaned from the recent debate in the Netherlands regarding
from his house to the hospital, and even the ages of euthanasia for patients with dementia [33].
his children. When asked the age of his 21-year-old son, A nuanced approach that carefully delineates capaci-
he answered that he was 7 years old, his age in 1996. ties altered or lost without withdrawing attention from the
He was able to recognize the Vancouver Winter Olympic dimensions of self that are preserved (and may even con-
Games and the name of the national medalists, but failed tinue to be enriched) is imperative. Indeed, alterations
to recognize the month and year (February, 2010) when of some dimensions of self may be accompanied or suc-
the Olympic games were held. He also remembered the ceeded by the emergence of other dimensions of self; Miller
names of the coaches and players of Korea’s national et al. [34] describe a case series of patients who became
football team and even knew the scores of the FIFA visual artists in the early stages of frontotemporal demen-
World Cup held in Korea and Japan in 2002, but he did tia, and explain how such cases provide unique windows into
532 M.J. Young, H.J. Bursztajn

studying creative aspects of selfhood. Cases such as these regarded as a neurogenic dissociation between the ‘sub-
challenge theoretical orientations conceptualizing selfhood jectively felt’ and ‘objectively seen’ body. This recalls
as monotonic or static. the developmental finding that young infants cannot link
Among the cases Miller et al. describe is a 68-year-old their ‘felt body’ with the view of themselves in a mir-
man who ‘‘was seen for a dementing illness of a 12-year ror,’’ implying that there may be multiple neural networks
duration. Previously a successful businessman without inter- at play responsible for simultaneous representations of the
est in art, at age 56 he began to describe ‘open’ and ‘closed’ self from different perspectives, in addition to integrative
periods. When ‘closed,’ he was dysphoric, and experienced network(s) unifying these discrete representations under
lights and sounds as exquisitely intense. When ‘open,’ lights normal circumstances (p. 3946) [41], generating a large
and sounds produced a pleasant feeling that allowed him range of potential pathologies of selfhood that might ensue
to think creatively. He painted images experienced during owing to breakdown at any point within these complex
‘open’ and ‘closed’ periods. At 58 years he became anomic networks.
and disinhibited. Language and memory deteriorated, but he Beyond the range of cases already considered, cases
showed heightened visual and auditory awareness. Odd com- of commisurotomy and the accompanying ‘split-brain syn-
pulsions developed, and despite his considerable wealth, he drome’ [42], disorders of consciousness, schizophrenia,
cajoled his caregivers to walk with him to look for coins. thought-insertion delusions, and related neuropsychiatric
At 56 years he began painting. During the next decade syndromes provide rich and relatively underexplored oppor-
he created paintings with increasing precision and detail. tunities to further expand and crystalize our understanding
The first featured brightly colored ellipses. Soon his work of the profound phenomenology and neurobiology of self-
became realistic, and he drew animals. Later works were hood and its multiform pathologies.
crafted with care, and he took hours to complete single
lines. Between 63 and 66 years his paintings won several art
show awards. . . He displayed heightened interest in his envi-
ronment, commenting extensively on color and sound. . .’’
Future directions
(p. 980) [34]. The emergence of creative capacities has
The analysis offered here illuminates numerous avenues for
more recently been described in cases of other neurologic
future research, some of which have already been ges-
diseases, including verbal creativity in transient epileptic
tured at above. These include fruitful avenues for both
amnesia [35], musical creativity in some forms of cere-
empirical and conceptual work. On an empirical plane,
brovascular disease [36], poetic talent in Parkinson’s disease
further research exploring the neural substrates correspond-
[37], and artistic ability in traumatic brain injury [38].
ing to different components of the scaffolding of identity
Other conditions to consider in evaluating the range of
articulated herein, as well as how these varied neuronal
cases that might inform and be informed by our schemati-
systems/networks coalesce to produce a phenomenologi-
zation of selfhood include transient or persistent amnestic
cally integrated and unified self is much needed. Further
syndromes arising in the context of epilepsy, autoimmune
clarity with respect to these issues can shed further light
neurologic conditions, focal lesions, and in cases of psy-
on how particular brain lesions may differentially affect
chogenic or trauma-induced amnesia and fugue [6,7]. In such
elaborations of selfhood by impacting different dimensions
cases, loss of episodic memories might entail disturbances
of selfhood. Such research could foreseeably include func-
of selfhood insofar as the capacities for diachronic unity
tional neuroimaging studies, non-invasive brain modulation
and narrative are implicated, in addition to possible dis-
(e.g., TMS; tDCS), and targeted neuropsychological testing
turbances in self-other representation. Felt disturbances of
of individuals with apparent disruptions of self stratified
selfhood occasioned in the context of amnesia are reflected
according to the domains of diachronic unity, synchronic
in the phenomenology of some reported cases [39], but most
unity, self-other representation, narrative, awareness and
published accounts lack sufficient phenomenological detail
interdependence to aid in elucidating the enigmatic neu-
to parse out which dimensions of selfhood patients and clini-
roanatomy and neurophysiology of selfhood. Moreover,
cians might be referring to when describing a loss of identity
studies examining the emergence and development of each
or a dwindling away of self.
of these dimensions during key windows of human develop-
Strikingly, apparent disturbances of selfhood in patients
ment can serve to clarify the ontogeny and organization of
with Anton—Babinski syndrome (visual anosognosia wherein
selfhood over the lifespan. In the pursuit of such research,
cortically blind patients do not recognize their visual
it is important to avoid a misleading philosophical impulse
deficit), and other forms of anosognosia (unawareness of
toward mereological reduction4 with respect to the self, and
deficits) and somatoparaphrenia (a sense of alienation
from parts of one’s own body) arising in the context of
4 P.M.S. Hacker and others have famously argued for what is
cerebrovascular accidents, traumatic brain injuries, and
in neurodegenerative disease may manifest not only with dubbed the mereological principle — that psychological properties
disturbances of self-other representation but also with dis- can only be justifiably ascribed to persons as whole beings and
turbances in cognitive unity; interestingly, the therapeutic not to constituent parts of persons. This principle is wielded to
contend that many contemporary neuroscientists and their respec-
technique of presenting the self to the anosognosic or
tive methodologies are guilty of a mereological fallacy in ascribing
somatoparaphrenic patient from a third-person perspec- psychological properties to parts of an individual instead of to the
tive (e.g., through mirrors or videos) has been found to be individual as a whole. This is not to say that components of the
effective at reinstating motor and proprioceptive awareness individual cannot cause or underpin psychological predicates apply-
in some patients [40,41]. On the basis of these findings, ing to a person as a whole, but rather that it is the whole person
Fotopoulou et al. suggest that such conditions ‘‘can be and not a part of the person that instantiates and experiences the
Selfhood and the therapeutic encounter 533

to aim for utmost conceptual clarity in the construction and Post-script: narrative and the neuroethics
operationalization of sound methodologies that effectively
articulate which feature(s) of selfhood or identity are being
of identity
measured and how. On clinical and conceptual planes, there While history matters, history is not to be confused with
is foreseeable utility in future work geared toward devel- identity, authenticity or destiny. The foregoing analysis
oping a quantifiable, multidimensional index of identity to brings to light a diverse array of neuroethical questions and
assess patients’ robustness of self through measurements considerations. The conceptual heterogeneity and Wittgen-
of the various capacities enumerated herein; such a clin- steinian family resemblances entailed by this analysis of
ical tool could help to evaluate and longitudinally track selfhood has vital ethical implications in a variety of clinical
patients’ development through time in settings of distur- and forensic contexts. These include questions which arise
bances of selfhood, according to some of the measures that in the treatment of individuals with dementia and other pro-
might matter most to patients and families. Such a tool gressive neuropsychiatric conditions wherein the self itself is
might be of further utility in future clinical studies evalu- called into question, for the foundation and function of living
ating the natural history of neuropsychiatric diseases and in wills, and for approaches to pain management in individuals
studying novel methods for their diagnosis and prognostica- with disorders of consciousness.
tion. The analysis developed and defended here suggests that
Additionally, future research appraising the adequacy of in such settings the impulse toward mereological reduction
current neuropsychiatric nosologies in capturing the breadth with respect to the self ought to be swiftly eschewed in
and depth of pathologies of selfhood may yield actionable favor of an approach that recognizes and responds to the
insights. Wittgenstein’s family resemblance approach may multiple dimensions in which self-identity might manifest;
serve as an ideal conceptual framework for optimizing cur- this includes situating the self within its attendant interper-
rent taxonomies of neuropsychiatric disease. sonal network, recognizing that the absence of proclaimed
The cross-disciplinary nature of each of these avenues of narrative does not entail the absence of self, and undertak-
future work underscores the profound importance of deep ing on a case-by-case basis careful forensic neuropsychiatric
and sustained collaborations among philosophers, clinicians evaluation, be it a bedside examination or, where too late,
and researchers to optimize and advance approaches to the a post-mortem forensic neuropsychiatric autopsy.
diagnosis, evaluation and treatment of pathologies of the In the case of the advanced directive or living will,
mind and self. questions might be raised in settings of progressive neurode-
generative diseases such as how to proceed if a patient,
after developing new neurocognitive deficit(s), wishes to
alter his or her advanced directive crafted prior to the devel-
opment of that deficit. In such settings, questions regarding
Summary and conclusions the unity of the self across time become particularly salient.
We began by explaining and critically evaluating the recent What are the neuroethical grounds that might substantiate
view advocated by Schechtman and others that narrative or negate the ability of the wishes of the prior self to over-
is wholly constitutive of self-identity. Counter-evidence to ride the wishes of the future self, or of the future self to
this theory was adduced from clinical neuropsychiatric cases override the wishes of the prior self? Is the question as to
wherein lapses of narrative do not obviously entail wholesale which self is authentic or merely as to which wishes are
losses of selfhood. Rather than a monotonic construct, it has authentic? How should questions of culpability and moral
been argued that narrative is one of a cadre of crisscross- responsibility be appraised and operationalized across time
ing capacities sharing some family resemblance and with in individuals with unstable or evolving self-constructs, such
characteristically open texture that variably combine to pro- as in the case of those recovering from addiction, where
duce selves with no single common denominator, but rather claims may be akin to ‘‘it was not me, it was just the sub-
with dynamic clusters of commonalities. Six other capacities stance talking.’’
were delineated and defined that might variably contribute In settings of disorders of consciousness, clinicians
to an intact scaffolding of selfhood, and we examined how responsible for pain management decisions may be tempted
substantial alterations of any of these elements of identity to prematurely withdraw analgesics on the basis of tacit
could result in a fracturing, disintegration or transforma- assumptions about the self that may prove tendentious. For
tion of the emergent self. Future appraisal of how particular instance, if selfhood is presumed to be absent on the basis
lesions may differentially affect elaborations of selfhood of an inability to communicate a narrative, a clinician might
by impacting neural substrates and networks correspond- erroneously judge analgesics to be unnecessary if the pos-
ing to different dimensions of this complex scaffolding was sibility of the persistence of an experiencing self in the
explained. While narrative, when elicited, can provide a absence of the communication or behavioral manifestation
vital window into patient experience, lapses of narrative thereof is not duly considered.
may be just as central to the psychoanalysis of the self and As the analysis here reveals, the tendency to reduce self-
to the therapeutic encounter. What is not, and cannot be hood to a single capacity and thereupon point to the absence
spoken, is often as vital as the narrative itself. of a given capacity as evidence of a wholly incapacitated self
ought to be avoided in such settings. It is vital to reconstruct
our health care budgetary priorities to make it practical for
practitioners to have the time with patients to undertake
psychological predicate of interest (see Hacker and Smith for more to understand the richness of the scaffolding constitutive of
on the mereological fallacy) [43].
534 M.J. Young, H.J. Bursztajn

selfhood as well as its variable expression. It is against this [20] Davidson D. First-person authority. Dialectica 1984;38:101—11.
backdrop that clinical decisions should be situated to avoid [21] Sartre JP. Mauvaise foi and the Unconscious. In: Wollhem R,
compounding the suffering that illness brings with added editor. Philosophical essays on Freud. Cambridge: Cambridge
measures of helplessness. Being able to understand the self University Press; 1982.
[22] Thalberg I. Freud’s anatomies of the self. In: Wollhem R, editor.
as a dynamic process may serve as a useful heuristic for the
Philosophical essays on Freud. Cambridge: Cambridge Univer-
neuroethics of identity.
sity Press; 1982.
Looking forward, the irreducible complexity of the self, [23] Hopkins EJ, Weisberg DS, Taylor JC. The seductive allure is
and of the narratives told by and of it as we continue to a reductive allure: people prefer scientific explanations that
learn evermore about neurodevelopment and neuroplastic- contain logically irrelevant reductive information. Cognition
ity in health and illness, is a developing story in need of 2016;155:67—76.
societal rereading as much as Heraclitus’s reminder that we [24] Bursztajn HJ, Feinbloom RI, Hamm RM, Brodsky A. Medi-
can never step twice in the same stream of consciousness. cal choices, medical chances: how patients, families and
physicians can cope with uncertainty. New York: Routledge;
1990.
[25] Appelbaum PS, Roth LH. Clinical issues in the assessment of
Disclosure of interest competency. Am J Psychiatry 1981;138:1462—7.
[26] Waismann. Verifiability. In: Flew A, editor. Language and logic.
The authors declare that they have no competing interest.
Oxford: Basil Blackwell; 1951.
[27] Young MJ. Pathologies of thought and first person authority.
Philos Psychiatr Psychol [Forthcoming].
References [28] Kumral E, Gulluoglu H, Dramali B. Thalamic chronotaraxis:
isolated time disorientation. J Neurol Neurosurg Psychiatry
[1] Schechtman M. Dissociative identity disorder and narrative. 2007;78(8):880—2.
Springer Netherlands: Handbook of Neuroethics; 2015. p. [29] Lee ST, Chu K, Kim M, Roh JK. Isolated and prolonged loss of
393—405. time orientation. Neurology 2010;75(12):1120.
[2] Sartre JP. Being and nothingness. New York: Open Road Media; [30] Spiegel EA, Wycis HT, Orchinik C, Freed H. Thalamic chrono-
2012 [1943]. taraxis. Am J Psychiatry 1956;113(2):97—105.
[3] Edelman GM. The remembered present: a biological theory of [31] Rocha S, Amorim JM, Machado ÁA, Ferreira CM. Phonag-
consciousness. New York: Perseus Books; 1989. nosia and inability to perceive time passage in right parietal
[4] Modell AH. The private self. Cambridge: Harvard University lobe epilepsy. J Neuropsychiatry Clin Neurosci 2015;27(2):
Press; 1993. e154.
[5] Wittgenstein L. Philosophical investigations. Oxford: Black- [32] Cooper SA, O’Sullivan M. Here, there and everywhere: higher
well; 1953. visual function and the dorsal visual stream. Pract Neurol
[6] Campora N, Kochen S. Subjective and objective characteris- 2015;10:1136.
tics of altered consciousness during epileptic seizures. Epilepsy [33] Hertogh CM, de Boer ME, Dröes RM, Eefsting JA. Would we
Behav 2016;55:128—32. rather lose our life than lose our self? Lessons from the Dutch
[7] Frisch C, et al. Neuropsychological course of voltage gated debate on euthanasia for patients with dementia. Am J Bioeth
potassium channel and glutamic acid decarboxylase antibody 2007;7(4):48—56.
related limbic encephalitis. Eur J Neurol 2013;20(9):1297—304. [34] Miller BL, et al. Emergence of artistic talent in frontotemporal
[8] Hume D, Norton M, Norton D. A treatise of human nature. dementia. Neurology 1998;51(4):978—82.
Oxford: Clarendon Press; 2007. [35] Woollacott, Ione OC, et al. Compulsive versifying after
[9] Descartes R, Haldan ES, Ross GRT. Discourse on method and treatment of transient epileptic amnesia. Neurocase
meditations. Mineola, NY: Dover Publications; 2003. 2015;21(5):548—53.
[10] Wijdicks, Eelco FM. Determining brain death. CONTIN- [36] Zagvazdin Y. Stroke, music, and creative output: Alfred Schnit-
UUM: Lifelong Learning in Neurology. Neurocrit Care tke and other composers. Prog Brain Res 2015;216:149—65.
2015;21(5):1411—24. [37] Inzelberg R. The awakening of artistic creativity and Parkin-
[11] Brook A. Kant and the mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University son’s disease. Behav Neurosci 2013;127:256.
Press; 1994. [38] Midorikawa A, Mitsuru K. The emergence of artistic ability fol-
[12] Markus HR, Shinobu K. A collective fear of the collective: impli- lowing traumatic brain injury. Neurocase 2015;21(1):90—4.
cations for selves and theories of selves. Pers Soc Psychol Bull [39] Nochi M. ‘‘Loss of self’’ in the narratives of people with
1994;20(5):568—79. traumatic brain injuries: a qualitative analysis. Soc Sci Med
[13] Hobson RP. Emotion as personal relatedness. Emotion Rev 1998;46(7):869—78.
2012;4(2):169—75. [40] Fotopoulou A, et al. Self-observation reinstates motor
[14] Buber M. I and thou. London: Continuum; 2004. awareness in anosognosia for hemiplegia. Neuropsychologia
[15] Tauber AI. The immune system and its ecology. Philos Sci 2009;47(5):1256—60.
2008;75:224—45. [41] Fotopoulou A, Jenkinson PM, Tsakiris M, Haggard P, Rudd A,
[16] Itzkowitz S, et al. Exploring dissociation and dissociative iden- Kopelman MD. Mirror-view reverses somatoparaphrenia: dis-
tity disorder: a roundtable discussion. Psychoanal Perspect sociation between first-and third-person perspectives on body
2015;12(1):39—79. ownership. Neuropsychologia 2011;49(14):3946—55.
[17] Freud S. The standard edition of the complete psychological [42] Schechter E. The subject in neuropsychology: individu-
works of Sigmund Freud: (1932—1936). New introductory lec- ating minds in the split. Brain case. Mind Language
tures on psycho-analysis. London: The Hogarth Press; 1991. 2015;30(5):501—25.
[18] Davidson D. Actions, reasons, and causes. Essays on actions and [43] Hacker PMS. An intellectual entertainment: the nature of the
events. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 1980. p. 3—19. mind. Royal Inst Philos Suppl 2015;76:199—223.
[19] Donald D. Paradoxes of irrationality. In: Wollhem R, Hopkins J, [44] Gulley N. The interpretation of ‘No one does wrong willingly’
editors. Philosophical essays on Freud. Cambridge: Cambridge in Plato’s dialogues. Phronesis 1965;1:82—96.
University Press; 1982. p. 289—305.

You might also like