You are on page 1of 7

Downloaded from http://jme.bmj.com/ on March 30, 2016 - Published by group.bmj.

com
JME Online First, published on March 1, 2016 as 10.1136/medethics-2015-103226
Extended essay

Knowing-how to care
Darlei Dall’Agnol

Correspondence to ABSTRACT finally illustrate how respectful care may transform


Professor Darlei Dall’Agnol, This paper advances a new moral epistemology and some of our current clinical bioethical practices.
Department of Filosofia,
Universidade Federal de Santa
explores some of its normative and practical, especially
Catarina, Processo 6671/2014- bioethical, implications. In the first part, it shows that A new moral epistemology
09, Florinopolis, Santa there is moral knowledge and that it is best understood To start with, consider this real-life bioethical case:
Catarina 88036001, Brazil; in terms of knowing-how. Thus, moral knowledge
ddarlei@yahoo.com cannot be analysed purely in the traditional terms of Baby X was born on 1 March 2009 at the
midwife-led maternity unity Y in the UK. Two
Received 5 November 2015 knowing-that. The fundamental idea is that one knows-
weeks before, the mother complained that her
Revised 26 January 2016 how to act morally only if she is capable of following the baby was not moving as much. She also said that
Accepted 8 February 2016 right normative standards. In the second part, the paper she was feeling unwell. She was checked, but
discusses ways of integrating two expressions of moral nothing was identified. At this point, it would have
knowing-how, namely caring and respecting into a been normal for care professionals to discuss
coherent normative theory. It builds up the concept of whether she should continue with the plan to give
respectful care as the central ingredient of such a birth at a midwife-led unit. There is no evidence,
normative theory. Finally, it illustrates how respectful however, that any risk assessment took place.
care may transform some of our current clinical When the baby was born, she was cold and floppy
bioethical practices. and needed medical attention, yet the midwife
placed her into a cold cot. It was only after 2 h
that an ambulance was called. She was transferred
to a hospital to be reviewed by a paediatrician. It
was later revealed that baby X had suffered from
INTRODUCTION anaemia caused by a substantial fetomaternal
We humans are, as social beings, care-dependent crea- haemorrhage. Baby X would have had a chance of
tures. Caring may, however, go wrong in many ways. surviving had she been delivered in a hospital
where she could have had blood transfusion or any
For one thing, the care may be insufficient to fulfil
other experimental procedure or treatment.
basic needs of the cared-for. It may even be a cause of
negligence or malpractice. Moreover, it may degener- These are the basic facts of the case. Some
ate into forms of paternalism when the one-caring ethical questions are: did baby X receive the care
imposes her own views of the good on a vulnerable she was entitled to? If not, is this not disrespectful
individual, for instance, a parent on a teenager learn- to her as a human being? How may one deliver the
ing how to be independent; a scientist on a research proper care baby X was entitled to? Did baby X
subject; a doctor or a nurse on a patient in need of wrongly die an avoidable death?
medical attention, and so forth. Besides, caring may One of the main problems underlying insuffi-
generate anxiety, that is, be accompanied by negative cient, negligent care, or even supercare, that is, a
feelings that compromise the well-being of the one- paternalistic form of ‘caring’, is, most likely, a mis-
caring. An important question then arises: under understanding regarding the very kind of knowl-
which conditions can we say that the one-caring edge that is required to look after a vulnerable
knows-how to care in a proper way, for instance, being properly. An incompetent carer, we might
respectfully? say, must know better. I believe this is the case not
In this paper, I would like to advance a only in the technical sense, for instance,
meta-ethical theory, particularly to outline the main knowing-how to make a reliable diagnosis, but also
tenets of a new moral epistemology, which I call in the moral sense. In this section, then, I will
‘practical cognitivism’, and to explore some of its argue that caring presupposes a practical kind of
normative and practical, especially bioethical, knowledge, namely knowing-how and not only
implications. Thus, in the first part, I will argue for knowing-that. Now, even in philosophy, knowledge
the thesis that there is moral knowledge (pace is sometimes defined in reductivistic ways obfuscat-
ethical scepticism and non-cognitivism) and that it ing the nature of practical ways of understanding
is best understood in terms of knowing-how. That and acting. As Gilbert Ryle pointed out, this is a
is to say, moral knowledge cannot be analysed prejudice of the ‘intellectualist doctrine’,1 which
purely in the traditional terms of knowing-that. tries to define intelligence in terms of apprehension
The fundamental idea is that one knows-how to act of truths instead of apprehension of truth in terms
morally or knows-how to be a certain kind of of intelligence. We need, in order to avoid this
person, and so on, only if she is capable of follow- inversion, to sort out a new kind of moral
ing the right normative standards (shortly, norms). epistemology.
To cite: Dall’Agnol D. J
In the second part, I will look for ways of integrat- Practical cognitivism is the epistemic thesis that
Med Ethics Published Online ing two expressions of moral knowing-how, namely there is moral knowledge and that it is best under-
First: [ please include Day caring and respecting into a coherent normative stood in terms of knowing-how and not only in
Month Year] doi:10.1136/ theory. I will show that respectful care must be a terms of knowing-that. The central idea is that a
medethics-2015-103226 central ingredient of such a normative theory. I will sound moral epistemology reveals that moral
Dall’Agnol D. J Med Ethics 2016;0:1–6. doi:10.1136/medethics-2015-103226 1
Copyright Article author (or their employer) 2016. Produced by BMJ Publishing Group Ltd under licence.
Downloaded from http://jme.bmj.com/ on March 30, 2016 - Published by group.bmj.com

Extended essay

knowledge is mainly a matter of knowing-how to follow norma- just skills that are quick in operation, but virtues require deliber-
tive standards. Thus, a practical cognitivist does not deny that ation and choice. Unfortunately, I cannot pursue this issue here
there is also moral knowing-that, for instance, that one must (cf. Bengson & Moffett’s excellent collection of essays for
care for her daughter’s well-being (there are, as we will see, further discussion on kinds of knowing-how).4 Other differ-
many moral ‘language-games’), but rather argues that something ences between moral knowledge and the other sorts of
else is needed: one must also know-how to do that. That is to knowing-how will become apparent in the next section.
say, practical cognitivism points out that there is more than one Professional knowledge may involve all sorts of knowledge.
kind of knowledge and does not try to reduce moral The exercise of modern medicine, for instance, requires differ-
knowing-how to knowing-that. Moral knowledge needs also to ent kinds of expertise. It certainly needs factual knowledge,
be clearly distinguished from other kinds of knowing-how, for especially scientific knowledge such as provided by chemistry,
instance, artisan skills, mere prudence, and so on. Thus, let me biology, and so on, for example, knowing that the blood is
sort out the main features of this new moral epistemology. pumped by the heart to the arteries, the arterioles and the capil-
Hopefully, it will help us to understand what went wrong in the laries, and returns in the venous system to be oxygenated in the
case of baby X and to avoid similar cases happening again. I will lungs. However, since healthcare professions also have a prac-
discuss in a more detailed way this bioethical case later, after tical component, their goal is doing and not just knowing.
establishing the basic ingredients of practical cognitivism. Doing something involves knowing-how, for instance, bypassing
To start with, let me sort out a provisory analysis of coronary arteries, which is a technical kind of knowledge. They
knowing-how. In order to do so, I will use Wittgenstein’s need practical skills too, which may improve upon new proce-
project of a philosophical grammar, that is, his remarks on the dures for bypassing arteries. Moral knowledge is also required
rules for using the word ‘know’ as being closely related to that since what can be done, perhaps must not be done. Medicine
of ‘can’ and ‘be able to’ and, especially, his rule-following con- can even be considered a form of wisdom, that is, it requires
siderations.2 I will explore some implications of his rule- practical rationality and not only scientific knowledge. This is
following remarks for ethics, but I will not commit myself to why, as was recently pointed out by Savulescu,5 philosophy is
the view that moral life exclusively comprises rules. A moral important for bioethics.
system may indeed also include sentiments, rights, emotions, From this analysis, we may derive a definition of explicit
obligations, traits of character, values, and so on, as we will see knowing-how in these terms: it is ‘an acquired capacity to
regarding respectful care. Not all these elements need to be follow normative standards’. This definition establishes a rule
explained by referring to rules or be reduced to them. But for using the expression ‘she knows-how’ distinguishing its right
moral rules do play a fundamental role in guiding a person’s from wrong uses. The above definition contains elements that
behaviour, in discriminating right from wrong, in justifying or in clearly show that knowing-how is irreducible to knowing-that. I
giving reasons for actions, and so on. Consequently, they are a believe that people like Jason Stanley are mistaken in claiming
necessary condition for holding persons accountable. the reducibility of knowing-how to knowing-that. Recently, he
What is knowledge after all? Is knowledge always related to a has argued, even against the strong evidence from neuroscience,
propositional attitude, that is, having a justified belief? This that procedural knowledge is a kind of knowing-that.6 This is
seems not to be the case. In Wittgenstein’s own words: “But not the case since procedural knowledge, that is, knowing-how
there is also this use of the word ‘to know’: we say ‘Now I to perform a task well, involves above all the mastering of
know!’ –and similarly ‘Now I can do it!’ and ‘Now I under- norms. Imagine you are going to learn a new game. You need
stand!’”.3 Thus, to have knowledge is not simply a matter of certainly to practice how to follow the constitutive rules. That is
having justified true beliefs, but, more importantly, in the prac- to say, knowing-how is not just a matter of having beliefs in true
tical sense, of being capable of effectively doing something, for propositions; it is a matter of mastering the norms necessary to
instance, mastering a technique such as handwriting, playing perform activities, that is, being able to follow them effectively
chess, and so on. to get the desired results. It does not follow, however, that there
Despite the fact that providing a comprehensive taxonomy of is no need for knowing-that or that one is, pace Ryle, more fun-
all sorts of knowledge is beyond the limits of this work, I would damental than the other. On the contrary, knowing-how
like now to make some further distinctions, especially between involves knowing-that. The basic point is just that they represent
tacit and explicit knowing-how. On the one hand, a person has two different kinds of knowledge, which may well be charac-
implicit, non-codified, knowing-how when she performs an terised in terms of the distinction between practical and theoret-
activity without having reflected on the norms involved. On the ical philosophy: the former deals with what ought to be; the
other hand, explicit knowing-how requires mastering the princi- latter is an inquiry into what is the case. And this is arguably the
ples and rules constitutive of such activity. Now, procedural most important advantage of explaining moral knowledge in
knowledge, most skills, moral knowledge, and so on, are sub- terms of knowing-how, namely ‘the problem of normativity’
types of explicit knowing-how. Procedural knowledge or (the way ‘ought-ness’ is sui generis and yet compatible with the
knowing-how to perform a task well, which is also sometimes natural world) is solved by introducing it right inside our analyt-
referred to as ‘imperative knowledge’, involves mastering expli- ical model. That is to say, it shows that norms are irreducible to
cit norms, for instance, a child learning how to count using her facts.
fingers. Moreover, skills are also an expression of a special kind If this is the case, then there is an important implication for
of knowledge, which is not only propositional. If we understand current meta-ethical debates: we must, so to speak, turn the
a skill as a learned ability with predefined goals, then it is best tables. Most present-day discussions are contaminated by the
defined as a subspecies of knowing-know. There are, of course, single (and false) presupposition that either there is moral
all sorts of skills: psychological, social, and so on. To illustrate: knowledge or there is not; however, both sides, most cogniti-
professional interaction with patients requires learning effective vists and non-cognitivists alike, think exclusively in terms of
rules for communication. It is crucial, however, to distinguish knowing-that. For instance, an intuitionist such as G.E. Moore
skills from moral knowledge as the latter manifests itself in the (and many present-day intuitionists) has many problems in
virtues. In an Aristotelian spirit, we may say that virtues are not showing us how such knowledge is possible, so he finds himself
2 Dall’Agnol D. J Med Ethics 2016;0:1–6. doi:10.1136/medethics-2015-103226
Downloaded from http://jme.bmj.com/ on March 30, 2016 - Published by group.bmj.com

Extended essay

postulating strange faculties or subscribing to queer entities.7 themselves express actions we do, for instance, a person at her
Many cognitivists follow the same path by trying to reduce wedding saying ‘I promise to ….’); these sentences can be said
ethics to empirical investigations naturalising morality and thus to be true in a pragmatic sense. Consequently, there are count-
committing the naturalistic fallacy (a category mistake in my less moral language-games.
interpretation). But, on the other hand, non-cognitivists do not The main theoretical advantage of applying the concept of
come out with better solutions despite the fact that they are suc- language-games in ethics is to get us to realise that particular
cessful in showing us that not all moral judgements are proposi- words do not have a moral meaning in themselves, but they
tions in the strictest sense. The shared mistake is to assume just may function as such, for instance, the word ‘no’ can be used in
one kind of knowledge either in affirming (cognitivists) or a normative-language-game as a moral imperative. That is to say,
denying it (non-cognitivists). Therefore, what we need is to the atomistic investigation of the meanings of ‘good’, ‘right’,
twist the debate in the direction of knowing-how. and so on, considered in isolation is misleading and we are
Let me then go back to practical cognitivism and deal with better off with a systemic approach to moral language using the
more epistemic issues surrounding it. First, there is the question notion of language-games.
of objectivity. Since norms are the basic ingredient of explicit Let me now make clear why the acceptance of this multipli-
knowing-how (as propositions are for knowing-that), it seems city of moral language-games does not imply radical relativism.
clear that the discussion of whether moral judgements are First, I was using different meanings of ‘true’, relating it to dif-
objective or not, according to a practical cognitivist, must be ferent kinds of language-games. Thus, it is important to stress
related to the kind of entity norms ( principles, rules, etc) are. In that Wittgenstein rejects a theory of truth, but not that moral
this sense, it is not difficult to recognise that norms are objective judgements cannot be true or false. Thus, if we accept the prima
in their own way, that is, if they are clearly formulated they facie principle of non-maleficence ‘do no harm’, then we must
coordinate the behaviour of all agents. To say ‘persons must also follow particular rules such as ‘do not cause pain’, ‘do not
keep their promises’ does not express subjective feelings, but cause suffering’, and so on. In this sense, norms form a coherent
objectively prescribes a specific kind of behaviour. That is why a web of guiding directives for our actions. In a minimalist sense,
non-cognitivist is wrong: following a rule (not merely acting in they can be said to be true, just as it may well be true that an
accordance with it) is a cognitive state. A norm presents a stand- evaluative moral judgement is in accordance with what is stated.
ard for agents to act accordingly. Thus, objectivity in ethics has Norms are, then, objective and may even be said to be true,
nothing to do with finding queer objects ‘out there’, which sup- but that is not to argue that norms are not revisable. A practical
posedly must correspond to moral terms or concepts. On the cognitivist may well be a fallibilist, and she may not be founda-
contrary, it is a matter of recognising that moral norms direct tionist about the justification of accepting norms. As for beliefs,
behaviour. Thus, moral norms such as the fundamental princi- we may constantly revise our norms, correcting them, perfecting
ples of bioethics (eg, first, do no harm) are objective in this them. For instance, the principle of non-maleficence can be
sense and once they are internalised they convert into attitudes, rewritten in terms of ‘do no more harm than benefit’, asking a
for instance, a caring one, which are not subjective either. subject of scientific research or a patient herself to say what
The question relating to the philosophical problem of truth counts as harm. The rules related to it may also be rewritten
may have a similar (dis)solution. What we must mainly be con- and improved. This adjustment is an ongoing project. Does that
cerned with, from a cognitivist point of view, is not whether all imply radical relativism? I will try to show now that this is not
our moral judgements correspond to facts in the world, but the case.
whether a system of norms is coherent and helps us achieve our A practical cognitivist may be considered a realist in the rela-
goals. That is to say, we may assume here a minimalist approach tional sense. That is to say, it is compatible with what Peter
to moral truths. As Wittgenstein noted while commenting on Railton calls ‘an objectified subjective interest’ for an individual
Broad’s threefold classification of theories of truth as corres- A+. Railton describes A+ in this way: “give to an actual individ-
pondence, coherence and pragmatic: “We can say that the word ual A unqualified cognitive and imaginative powers, and full
[‘truth’] has at least three different meanings; but it is mistaken factual and nomological information about his physical and psy-
to assume that any one of these theories can give the whole chological constitution, capacities, circumstances, history, and so
grammar of how we use the word, or endeavour to fit into a on.”9 I would like to add, complementing Railton, A+ must also
single theory cases which do not seem to agree with it.”8 I have knowing-how in a high, excellent degree. In other words,
believe that contemporary philosophy has overlooked the knowing-how presupposes the exercise of full capacities in
importance of this remark. The truth of moral sentences order to act morally or have the appropriate attitudes. What
depends on the language-game in which they occur. counts as real (eg, the ingredients of one’s welfare), then, is
To recognise this point, let me examine more deeply what is established from the point of view of A+ and not from
Wittgenstein’s notion of language-games applying it to moral an independent realm of values ‘out there’.
language. A moral system may comprise the following language- Let me, now, if this conclusion is right, show which path we
games: (i) imperative moral language-games (comprising sen- may follow to construct a normative ethics based on
tences enunciating principles—general guides for action—such knowing-how to care. There are certainly different kinds of
as ‘do no harm’ and particular rules that prescribe or make per- knowing-how and also different kinds of care, for instance,
missible specific acts, for instance, ‘do not cause physical injury’, natural care and moral care. There are, perhaps, only family
‘do not cause offence’, etc); particular rules may be said to be resemblances between them. Thus, it is important to distinguish
true if we accept principles and they cohere with them; (ii) moral knowing-how (eg, to care for someone for her own sake)
evaluative moral language-games (sentences to assess certain from non-moral knowing-how (eg, caring for a particular book).
forms of behaviour, attitudes or qualities of an agent’s character In this sense, I would like to adopt here a specific use of the
such as ‘Peter is a good fellow’); these sentences may be true in word ‘moral’, which is after all a common sense use that is also
the correspondent sense if they describe accurately what a assumed in many empirical studies of morality, namely as a
person is, for instance, whether an agent is an honest person; synonym for altruistic behaviour. To be more precise, and given
and (iii) performative moral language-games (sentences that that there is also the morally relevant case of self-care, I would
Dall’Agnol D. J Med Ethics 2016;0:1–6. doi:10.1136/medethics-2015-103226 3
Downloaded from http://jme.bmj.com/ on March 30, 2016 - Published by group.bmj.com

Extended essay

like to use the following criteria to distinguish moral from non- consent),12 we need to integrate both care and respect to create
moral kinds of knowing-how: in the former case, it presupposes the main core of a common morality. This is not the idea of the
a special kind of valuation, namely the ascription of intrinsic morality as some bioethicists hold is necessary. In their book
value; in the latter, there is no such assumption. This is the Bioethics,13 Gert, Culver and Clouser present, as an alternative
domain of morality: from Aristotle’s conception of praxis, to the predominant bioethical theory, common morality as a
through Kant’s definition of a categorical imperative, to public system for all, which manifests itself in different cultures.
Wittgenstein’s notion of absolute values, morality is a domain Such morality comprises several moral rules such as ‘Don’t
composed of intrinsic values. Self-care or caring for others are, deceive’, ‘Don’t kill’, ‘Keep your promises’, and so on, which
consequently, expressions of the intrinsic valuing of a vulnerable supposedly are part of all existent moral systems. This idea was
being. incorporated into principlism by Beauchamp and Childress,
I will use now this criterion to distinguish moral norms from who describe it in these terms: “It is not merely a morality, in
non-moral ones. For this purpose, I will refer to Wittgenstein’s contrast to other moralities. The common morality is applicable
Tractatus. He wrote: “When an ethical law of the form, ‘Thou to all persons in all places, and we rightly judge all human
shalt …’, is laid down, one’s first thought is, ‘And what if I do conduct by its standards.”14 Grounding principlism in common
not do it?’ … There must be indeed some kind of ethical morality seems to be a remedy for many meta-ethical problems;
reward and ethical punishment, but they must reside in the however, it may bring new ones. Consider, for instance, the
action itself ”.10 The distinctive feature of a moral law is, then, issues involved in the end-of-life processes, the problems sur-
that it commands an action as good in itself. In other words, a rounding the euthanasia debate: either in prolonging life or
moral rule is a categorical not a hypothetical norm. In his shortening it. When futility of any treatment is the case (a cure
Lecture of Ethics, Wittgenstein makes the distinction between a is not possible), a person has the moral right to refuse extraor-
relative and an absolute use of moral words. His example is dinary means to keep her alive. In order to respect her as a
this: suppose I had told somebody here a preposterous lie and person, this right must be granted, but it does not follow that
he came up to me and said ‘You’re behaving like a beast’ and she must not be cared for. How then to provide her with real
then I said ‘I know I’m behaving badly, but I don’t want to respectful care? For one asking for it, palliative care is the way
behave any better’, could he then say ‘Ah, then that’s all right’? to value her for her own sake and to show respectful care and
Certainly not; he would say ‘Well, you ought to want to behave caring respect. For those asking for assistance to die, the only
better’. It seems clear that moral knowledge relates to an intrin- way to value them intrinsically is to provide a dignified way of
sic valuation: the ascription of what is good in itself or right in passing away, but this is something the proponents of the
itself. In this sense, there is no priority between right and good common morality argued was against the rule ‘don’t kill’ in
because both may be defined in terms of value. This is import- medical contexts. Medicine is, however, a social practice and its
ant in realising how we can overcome the dichotomy between goals may change. Thus, it seems clear that we should look for
deontology and teleology/consequentialism in normative ethics: better ways of integrating care and respect. Let me then ask:
both rightness and goodness are instantiations of intrinsic value. under what conditions does one know-how to care for a vulner-
I will argue for this in the next section, showing how care and able individual respectfully?
respect can be integrated into normative ethics, for instance, The knowledge implicit in caring for a vulnerable individual
when one knows-how to care respectfully. (a human being or even a sentient non-human animal) is
knowing-how to increase her well-being and also prevent loss of
Respectful care in bioethics well-being, not just in the technical sense of doing what must be
Let me now illustrate in a more detailed way how practical cog- done to cure her if she is a patient/subject of research, but it is
nitivism, that is, the epistemic theory that says that moral knowl- also in the moral sense, which presupposes an intrinsic valu-
edge is knowing-how, interprets two important moral attitudes, ation: the person’s welfare must be fostered because it is good
namely caring and respecting. These notions are the foundations for her own sake. If there is no such evaluative attitude, there is
of bioethics, the field with which I am most concerned here, no moral worth in caring for her. Here, we must also remember
and are the basic building blocks of a common morality. Just to that there is a distinction between natural and moral care. Thus,
be clear: I am not assuming that respecting and caring are the knowing-how to act morally involves an intrinsic valuation: a
only intrinsic valuations, but there is no doubt that they repre- person knows-how to care if she answers in the appropriate
sent the kind of knowledge a practical cognitivist holds to be way, for instance, sympathetically, to an individual’s well-being
central to morality. In this section, however, I will particularly and acts accordingly protecting it, fostering it, and so on, doing
look for the conditions required for knowing-how to care in a whatever is necessary for the vulnerable’s own sake. An ethics of
respectful manner. care (as represented by the works of Gilligan,15 Noddings,16
To start with, consider the predominant bioethical approach, Lindemann,17 etc.) is arguably a consequence of practical cogni-
namely the theory called ‘principlism’ based on the prima facie tivism. I am not assuming here, however, the particularist
norms of respect for autonomy (a person’s choices must be con- assumptions generally subscribed to by most defenders of an
sidered), non-maleficence (harm must be avoided), beneficence ethics of care. In fact, a norm such as the non-maleficence prin-
(more benefits than otherwise must result from our actions) and ciple mentioned above is always applicable in any case where
justice (a distribution is a fair one if it gives equally to equals caring is at stake. No one knows-how to care if she produces
and differently to non-equals). This approach is, meta-ethically more harm than benefit and, if the above criterion is the right
speaking, intuitionist (there are several principles and no way of one, no one knows-how to care, in the moral sense, if she does
ranking them), and this may lead to arbitrary applications, as not increase an individual’s welfare or prevent loss of welfare
perhaps baby X shows. On the other hand, if we want to avoid for cared-for own sake.
both paternalism (eg, Pellegrino’s model of beneficence-in-trust, As we saw in the previous section, professional medical
which still gives more weight to the traditional Hippocratic knowledge involves all sorts of expertise. Now, regarding
principles)11 and individualism or indifference (eg, Engelhardt’s knowing-how to care, we may also distinguish between common
autonomism, which gives absolute priority to personal moral knowledge and professional moral knowledge. For this
4 Dall’Agnol D. J Med Ethics 2016;0:1–6. doi:10.1136/medethics-2015-103226
Downloaded from http://jme.bmj.com/ on March 30, 2016 - Published by group.bmj.com

Extended essay

proposal, it is crucial, for instance, to bear in mind the differ- contractualism) and consequentialism. For instance, Derek
ences between general and specific beneficence. According to Parfit, in On What Matters, proposes a Triple Theory in norma-
Beauchamp and Childress,18 specific beneficence rests on special tive ethics holding that “an act is wrong just when such acts are
relations, contracts or particular commitments and it is directed disallowed by the principles that are optimific, uniquely univer-
at specific parties such as children, patients, and so on; on the sally willable, and not reasonably rejectable”.23 I believe that we
other hand, general beneficence is directed beyond special rela- can amend Parfit’s Triple Theory to include virtue ethics, the
tionships to all persons. In this sense, healthcare professionals other major normative ethics in contemporary philosophy.
have specific obligations of beneficence through taking on a According to virtue ethics, an agent is always obligated to, as
role. Consequently, moral knowing-how to care professionally Roger Crisp puts it,24 act as the virtuous person would act. This
is, in some sense, agent-relative despite the fact that, as Darwall is also a purely formal criterion as it is ‘optimific’, ‘universally
has correctly pointed out, reasons to care are agent-neutral.19 willable’, and so on, and can be incorporated into a renewed
Before developing further other normative implications of Triple Theory in this way: act under norms that are optimific,
practical cognitivism, let me give one more example of moral universally williable and would not be rejected by a virtuous
knowing-how: a person knows-how to respect another person person. Now, respectful care is the kind of moral attitude that is
only if she is capable of deferring to her rights. In other words, based on norms that are optimific, universally willable and
in order to respect another person, one needs to recognise her would, certainly, not be rejected by a virtuous character.
as a person (a free agent and a holder of rights and a bearer of Therefore, the amended Triple Theory seems to provide the
obligations) and to revere to her rights for her own sake. The right balance between caring and respecting.
so-called ‘respect for autonomy’ in bioethics that amounts to I believe, however, that we are still far from having a clear
self-determination may here be a particular right a person has, understanding of what respectful care actually requires. This is
but there are many others. A patient, as a person, has many perhaps one reason why some of our practices may go wrong
rights: to advocacy services, to meet with clergy, to information, and we fail to deliver proper care as the case of baby X clearly
and so on, and not just to receive the necessary and basic care. shows. I hope here to make a small contribution to this topic by
Thus, instead of respect for autonomy at the foundations of bio- calling attention to some elements we need to consider in order
ethics, one must think in terms of respect for persons, which is to build this new bioethical concept, namely that of respectful
another fundamental norm. An ethics of universal respect (as care. There is little doubt that baby X should not have been
represented by the works of Tugendhat,20 Dworkin,21 delivered at a midwife-led unit. This was disrespectful to the
Darwall,22 etc) may also be seen as a consequence of practical baby herself. True care needs not only good intentions or nice
cognitivism. That is to say: a person knows-how to respect only feelings (sympathy), but also real conditions to benefit a vulner-
if she recognises the other person’s rights and has the relevant able individual at risk of losing her life. The attention needed to
moral attitude of deferring, protecting, fostering, and so on, improve a patient’s well-being, to restore her health or simply to
them because they are their rights. If such intrinsic valuation is protect her from further harm must be accompanied by effective
not implicit, there is no moral value in her actions even if rights knowledge, both scientifically and morally speaking, and by
are not directly infringed. material conditions. There are many mistakes that care is subject
If we now ask what kind of moral system we can build from to. Technical errors, for instance, in diagnosis, are not the only
practical cognitivism, one possible answer is this: on the one ones that may occur. There can also be moral failures.
hand, since there is not just one single conception of well-being As we have seen in the first part, knowing-how to care is not
or even a single consensual set of claim rights, then we are just a question of having justified true beliefs, but requires the
bound to accept some sort of pluralism; on the other hand, if effective capacity of following some normative standards.
we want at the same time to avoid an extreme form of ethical Practices such as playing chess, diagnosing diseases, and so on,
relativism, then we must build up a common sharable morality require the development of relevant skills. In the same way,
(henceforth, CS-Morality), which has, so to speak, a ‘transcen- acting morally requires acquiring knowing-how, for instance, to
dental’ function: it makes possible the pacific and cooperative care for a vulnerable individual for her own sake. Thus, caring
coexistence of persons even if they belong to different moral and respecting are mastered by training/practicing in order to
systems (Christians, Agnostics, Buddhists, Atheists, etc). Thus, a develop the necessary capabilities to benefit a person’s well-
CS-Morality allows for a limited kind of pluralism, although it being and not with informational knowledge only. Moral train-
restricts unreasonable axiological systems. Now, respectful care ing consists in teaching normative standards by given examples,
and caring respect are the core of this minimalist public system inculcating rules and principles, punishing wrong doings, and so
of morality. As we have seen, both caring and respecting are on, so that the apprentice internalises them up to the point they
expressions of intrinsically valuing an individual and/or a person are part of her own character. Moral education also involves
and that is why they are moral attitudes. Despite the fact that learning-how to respond appropriately to the special value
there is no space here to argue for this in a more detailed way, I persons have. Only then one knows-how to act morally and will
am assuming that care and respect are complementary aspects of develop the relevant moral attitudes.
moral life at the foundations of what I have called ‘a Moral sentiments such as sympathetic concern are also a con-
CS-Morality.’ Moreover, in this system, care and respect limit dition of proper care. Sympathy is just a natural sharing of feel-
each other avoiding both paternalism and individualism in bio- ings and emotions, both negative and positive, any social animal
ethics and in other domains of life. This remark applies to an is capable of. It is immediate and involuntary rising out of our
intersubjective or social sphere, but it is also true of self- intersubjective interactions. In the human case, it is sometimes
regarding concerns. That is to say, both self-respect and self-care accompanied by empathy, that is, by imaginatively placing
are expressions of moral attitudes in the above defined sense. oneself in another person’s shoes and simulating how she feels.
How then can we now integrate care and respect into a solid Although they are certainly essential for proper caring, sym-
normative ethics? Apart from principlism, there are currently pathy and empathy may not be sufficient. Moreover, feelings are
important projects being carried out that are trying to overcome sometimes misleading and may even compromise proper care. If
the dichotomy between kinds of deontology (Kantianism, one allows oneself to be guided just by anxiety, one may end up
Dall’Agnol D. J Med Ethics 2016;0:1–6. doi:10.1136/medethics-2015-103226 5
Downloaded from http://jme.bmj.com/ on March 30, 2016 - Published by group.bmj.com

Extended essay

acting wrongly. Thus, empathy must be tempered with reflection a CS-Morality guarantees mutual respect among persons, limit-
on what is really best to benefit the patient’s well-being, for ing doctrines (eg, traditional practices, religions, etc), which are
instance, to effectively improve her health. Recalling the case incompatible with the above-mentioned moral attitudes.
mentioned, midwives were probably very sensitive, but perhaps
lacked the material conditions to effectively benefit baby X’s FINAL REMARKS
well-being. To finish, let me go back to the baby X case once more. As has
There is another necessary ingredient for proper care. Apart become clear, baby X’s ‘care’ was disrespectful in many ways, for
from sentiments such as sympathetic concern and empathy, the example, a second opinion should have been sought, the baby
recognition of the patient as a person is essential. Without should not have been delivered in a midwife unit, and so on. The
making here a detailed analysis of what a person is, let us conclusion cannot be otherwise: poor care, as provided in this
assume that a person is a bearer of rights and/or obligations. case, is very disrespectful indeed. I believe that baby X died an
Thus, a patient has not only the basic right to health assistance, avoidable and wrongful death. Apparently, both parents and
but other rights as well, such as to give informed consent, to midwife professionals did not care for the baby’s own sake. That
call for a second opinion, to have her privacy protected, and so is to say, this case clearly shows a lack of respect as an expression
on. To respect a person is not only to fulfil our obligations of an intrinsic valuation, that is, of not knowing-how profes-
regarding improving health, but to be careful not to violate sionals ought to behave for the patient’s own sake. As the health
other rights as well. Consequently, it seems clear that in the case ombudsman report now reveals, the baby’s records are of a poor
of baby X proper care was not delivered because not all rights standard and even inaccurate in some places. There is no doubt
were respected. If the mother was complaining before giving that the midwife missed key signs that the baby was unwell, so she
birth, a second opinion should have been sought. Both parents did not care for the patient’s best interest. If we are to avoid such
and midwives should have remembered this and requested an cases occurring again, we have not only to improve the material
obstetrician’s review. and the scientific conditions to provide proper care, but we need
There is another condition necessary to give caring a full moral also to add a moral dimension to caring: delivering it respectfully.
sense. The one-caring must benefit the cared-for because this is
good for the patient’s own sake. This is the right thing to do. Acknowledgements A previous version of this paper was presented at the
University of Hull in the Department of Politics, Philosophy and International Studies
Thus, morality requires evaluating intrinsically a vulnerable indi-
on 3 November 2015. I would like to thank Professor Nick Zangwill for the
vidual or a person. If the one-caring ‘cares’ for the vulnerable out invitation and the audience for the lively and interesting discussion. I would also like
of self-interest only, then ‘caring’ has no moral meaning. If the to thank CAPES, a Brazilian federal agency, for supporting my research project
one-caring is only concerned with earning money or not losing “Care & Respect: Re-thinking the meta-ethical and normative basis of bioethics” at
her job, then caring may not only go wrong from a technical the Oxford Uehiro Centre for Practical Ethics throughout 2015.
point of view, but could also represent a moral failure. Health Funding Coordenação de Aperfeiçoamento de Pessoal de Nível Superior.
sciences and practices, as many philosophers have argued, are Competing interests None declared.
moral enterprises. Therefore, to achieve its moral goal, caring Provenance and peer review Not commissioned; externally peer reviewed.
needs to proceed with an intrinsic valuation.
Taking into account the results of the two sections, we may REFERENCES
now say that W knows-how to care for X respectfully iff: 1 Ryle G. The concept of mind. London/New York: Routledge, 2009:9.
1. W sympathises with X, but also recognises her as a p 2 Wittgenstein L. Werkausgabe in 8 Banden. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp. (PI, §185-243) See
( person); also: Elliott C. ed. (2001). Slow cures and bad philosophers. Essays on
Wittgenstein, Medicine and Bioethics. Durham: Duke University Press, 1993.
2. X’s well-being needs attention and p has, among others, a
3 Wittgenstein L. Werkausgabe in 8 Banden. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1993, (PI, §151).
basic right to health assistance; 4 Bengson J, Moffett MA. eds. Knowing how. Essays on knowledge, mind, and
3. W fulfils her obligations benefiting X for her own sake. action. New York: OUP, 2011.
By definition, then, respectful care causes an increase in one’s 5 Savulescu J. Bioethics: why philosophy is essential for progress. J Med Ethics
well-being or prevents a fall in welfare for one’s own sake 2015;41:28.
6 Stanley J. Know how. Oxford: OUP, 2011:150f.
without violating other rights. 7 Moore GE. Principia Ethica. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993.
A CS-Morality (granted, not the eternal and immutable mor- 8 Apud Monk R. Ludwig Wittgenstein. The duty of genius. London: Vintage,
ality), based on respectful care, is greatly needed nowadays for 1991:322.
bioethics in our globalised society. It is also the best candidate to 9 Railton P. Facts, values, and norms. New York: Cambridge University Press,
2003:11.
provide the political foundation for justifying a State and its
10 Wittgenstein L. Werkausgabe in 8 Banden. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1993, Remark:
institutional policies enforcing many forms of caring. Thus, a 6.422.
CS-Morality may adopt the following political principle: “indi- 11 Pellegrino E, Thomasma D. For the patient’s good. Oxford: OUP, 1988.
viduals have a right to equal concern and respect in the design 12 Engelhardt T. The foundations of bioethics. Oxford: OUP, 1996.
and administration of the political institutions that govern 13 Gert B, Culver C, Clouser D. Bioethics. A return to fundamentals. New York/Oxford:
OUP, 1997.
them”.25 That is to say, caring and respecting requires: health- 14 Beauchamp TL, Childress J. Principles of biomedical ethics. Oxford: OUP, 2013:3.
care policies ( preventive care, primary and acute care, social ser- 15 Gilligan C. In a different voice. Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 2003.
vices for those with disabilities, etc), basic education for all 16 Noddings N. Caring. 2nd edn. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1984.
(teaching useful skills, cultivating artistic talents, giving physical 17 Lindemann H. An invitation to feminist ethics. Langua: McGraw-Hill, 2005.
18 Beauchamp TL, Childress J. Principles of biomedical ethics. Oxford: OUP, 2013:205.
training, etc, and enforcing one’s own sense of responsibility),
19 Darwall S. Welfare and rational care. Princeton/Oxford: Princeton University Press,
public safety ( protection from different kinds of harm), and so 2002:4.
on, for all vulnerable human beings. In this sense, a 20 Tugendhat E. Vorlesungen über Ethik. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1994.
CS-Morality may be based on egalitarian and universal norms. 21 Dworkin R. Taking rights seriously. Cam./Mass: Harvard University Press, 1978.
It is also the best candidate for providing the juridical founda- 22 Darwall S. Welfare and rational care. Princeton/Oxford: Princeton University Press,
2002.
tion to guarantee the respect for other basic rights such as the 23 Parfit D. On what matters. Oxford: OUP, 2011:413.
freedom to pursue one’s ideals, life projects, and so on, and 24 Crisp R. Reasons & the Good. Oxford: OUP, 2008:33.
other fundamental liberties such as property. Last but not least, 25 Dworkin R. Taking rights seriously. Cam./Mass: Harvard University Press, 1978:180.

6 Dall’Agnol D. J Med Ethics 2016;0:1–6. doi:10.1136/medethics-2015-103226


Downloaded from http://jme.bmj.com/ on March 30, 2016 - Published by group.bmj.com

Knowing-how to care

Darlei Dall'Agnol

J Med Ethics published online March 1, 2016

Updated information and services can be found at:


http://jme.bmj.com/content/early/2016/03/01/medethics-2015-103226

These include:

References This article cites 1 articles, 1 of which you can access for free at:
http://jme.bmj.com/content/early/2016/03/01/medethics-2015-103226
#BIBL
Email alerting Receive free email alerts when new articles cite this article. Sign up in the
service box at the top right corner of the online article.

Topic Articles on similar topics can be found in the following collections


Collections Bioethics (168)

Notes

To request permissions go to:


http://group.bmj.com/group/rights-licensing/permissions

To order reprints go to:


http://journals.bmj.com/cgi/reprintform

To subscribe to BMJ go to:


http://group.bmj.com/subscribe/

You might also like