You are on page 1of 17

Morality and Justice

22
Linda J. Skitka, Christopher W. Bauman,
and Elizabeth Mullen

Morality and justice have apparent similarities. Piaget, 1932/1997; Kohlberg, 1981). Others view
Both facilitate social interaction, coordination, morality as one of several possible motivations
and cooperation. Both can feel like external stan- for justice (e.g., Folger, 2001; Skitka, 2003). Still
dards that somehow should carry more weight others argue that justice is merely one component
than individuals’ preferences. That said, morality of morality (e.g., Haidt & Joseph, 2004). The
and justice are not synonymous. Scholars as far goals of this chapter are therefore to (a) review
back as Aristotle have identified ways that moral- these different perspectives on morality and jus-
ity and justice differ (see Konow, 2008). In this tice, and (b) offer constructive critiques and iden-
chapter, we review research programs from the tify ways that these theories might inform each
literatures on moral development, the social psy- other. We conclude that three separate literatures
chology of justice, and the burgeoning social converge on the basic idea that morality and jus-
psychological literature on adult morality and tice are distinct but related constructs. However,
examine how scholars have conceptualized the no consensus exists regarding more specific
relation between morality and justice. We review aspects of the relation between the constructs.
these literatures in roughly chronological order to
illustrate how theorizing and research about
morality and justice has changed over time. 22.1 Moral Development
We find a great deal of variability in how theo- and Justice
rists have approached links between morality and
justice. Some treat them as the same construct 22.1.1 Classic Theories of Moral
(e.g., classic theories of moral development; Development

Justice has had a long and deep connection to


L.J. Skitka (*) theory and research on moral development,
University of Illinois at Chicago, Chicago, IL, USA beginning with Jean Piaget’s focus on the moral
e-mail: lskitka@uic.edu
lives of children as revealed through games and
C.W. Bauman play. He observed that children’s games are dom-
University of California, Irvine, CA, USA
inated by concerns about fairness (Piaget,
e-mail: cwbauman@exchange.uci.edu
1932/1997). In early years, children are very con-
E. Mullen
cerned about following the rules, but they also
San Jose State University,
San Jose, CA, USA begin to understand that rules are relatively arbi-
e-mail: mullen@gwu.edu trary as they develop. Finding ways to coordinate

© Springer Science+Business Media New York 2016 407


C. Sabbagh, M. Schmitt (eds.), Handbook of Social Justice Theory and Research,
DOI 10.1007/978-1-4939-3216-0_22
408 L.J. Skitka et al.

play to facilitate group function becomes more 1982). There also have been many critiques of
important than the rules themselves. Piaget there- the evidence that Kohlberg tried to mount in sup-
fore came to view moral development as the port of the notion that moral development occurs
result of interpersonal interactions through which in universal ordered stages (e.g., Simpson, 1974;
people find solutions all will accept as fair Sullivan, 1977).
(Piaget, 1932/1997).
Kohlberg (1981) embraced and elaborated on
Piaget’s conclusion that moral development is 22.1.2 Contemporary Theories
rooted in justice. Kohlberg described the stages of Moral Development
of moral development in a variety of ways, but
one clear way he thought they differed was in the Contemporary theories of moral development
motivation that drives justice judgments. In have adapted some components of Kohlberg’s
Stages 1 and 2, people do little more than seek to ideas, but have dropped its most controversial
avoid punishment and obtain rewards. Their con- aspects, including normative claims that some
ceptualization of justice is mainly defined by stages of moral development and reasoning are
self-interest. At Stages 3 and 4, people begin to better or worse than others. Ties between moral
consider others’ expectations for their behavior development and justice operations remain, but
and the implications of their behavior for society the emphasis on justice is not as strong in con-
as a whole. They show concern for other people temporary theories of moral development as they
and their feelings, follow rules in an effort to be were in Kohlberg’s writing about the topic. Next,
seen as a good person, and feel an obligation to we review two of these contemporary theories:
contribute to the group, society, or institution. At Moral schema and domain theory.
Stage 5, people define justice in terms of uphold-
ing people’s basic rights, values, and the legal Moral schema theory. Moral schema theory
contracts of society. People at this stage under- reconceived Kohlberg’s stages as cognitive sche-
stand social life is a social contract to abide by mas (Rest, Narvaez, Bebeau, & Thoma, 1999a,
the laws for the good of all and to protect the 1999b). According to this theoretical update,
rights of the individual and the group. Finally, at people use three kinds of schemas to make socio-
Stage 6, people believe that laws or social agree- moral judgments: personal interest, norm mainte-
ments are valid only if they are based on univer- nance, and post-conventional. The personal
sal principles, and their justice judgments are interest schema develops in early childhood, the
motivated by concerns about self-condemnation norm maintenance schema develops during ado-
rather than social approbation. In short, people lescence, and the post-conventional schema
become increasingly able to take into account the develops in late adolescence and adulthood. Once
perspectives of others as they progress through formed, people can use any one of the schemas to
the stages, and the source of moral motivation guide their judgments and behavior, and theoreti-
shifts from outside (i.e., heteronomy) to inside cally can move fluidly between them as a func-
the individual (i.e., autonomy). tion of how well features of situations and social
Although Kohlberg’s theory was enormously relationships map onto and therefore prime the
influential, it nonetheless has a host of problems. activation of one or another core schema.
For example, people seldom give responses to When people apply the personal interest
moral dilemmas that can be completely encapsu- schema, they tend to focus on their own self-
lated or described by any single Kohlbergian interests in a situation or justify the behavior of
stage. The theory also has been criticized for others in terms of their perceptions of others’
championing a Western worldview and being personal interests. The norm maintenance
culturally insensitive (e.g., Simpson, 1974; schema focuses on (a) the needs of cooperative
Sullivan, 1977), and sexist in both its construc- social systems and the group, (b) a belief that
tion and interpretation of morality (Gilligan, living up to these norms and standards will pay-
22 Morality and Justice 409

off in the long run, and (c) a strong duty orienta- create and maintain order within the group.
tion, whereby one should obey and respect Conventions are arbitrary in the sense that they
authorities. Finally, the post-conventional depend on group norms and practices rather than
schema primes a sense of moral obligation based intrinsic features of the actions they govern. For
on the notions that laws, roles, codes, and con- example, greeting someone with a handshake or
tracts facilitate cooperation. However, people by showing them the back of your hand with just
also recognize that these standards are relatively your middle finger extended is only meaningful
arbitrary, and there are a variety of social in a particular society that has established rules
arrangements that can achieve the same ends. about those actions. Other societies have estab-
This schema leads people more toward an orien- lished different practices for greetings that are
tation that duties and rights follow from the equivalent in terms of how they regulate interper-
greater moral purpose behind conventions, not sonal interactions (e.g., kisses on the cheek, flick-
from the conventions themselves. Post- ing your hand under your chin); nothing about
conventional thinking therefore focuses people these actions in-and-of-themselves is inherently
on ideals, conceptions of the ultimate moral right or wrong. In sum, morals and conventions
good or imperative (Rest et al., 1999a). Although both establish permissibility or impermissibility
moral schema theory does not explicitly refer- and create social order, but conventions depend
ence justice or justice operations, Rest et al. on group context whereas morals are viewed as
(1999a, 1999b); Rest, Narvaez, Bebeau, and more universal. In domain theory, as in formalist
Thoma (1999b) nonetheless emphasize that their ethics, morals (a) are not based on established
theory is fundamentally about justice: “We still rules (i.e., rule contingency), (b) prohibit rules
agree with Kohlberg that the aim of the develop- that would sanction undesirable actions (i.e., rule
mental analysis of moral judgment is the rational alterability), and (c) generalize to members of
reconstruction of the ontogenesis of justice oper- other groups and cultures (i.e., rule and act
ations” (Rest et al., 1999b, p. 56). generalizability).
Supporting the notion that there is an impor-
Domain theory. Domain theory was proposed as tant psychological distinction between the moral
an alternative view of moral development as criti- and conventional domains, people judge and pun-
cism of Kohlberg’s theory began to mount. A key ish moral transgressors more severely than those
observation that helped launch domain theory who break conventions (Smetana, 2006; Turiel,
was that people, even young children, differenti- 1998). Additionally, moral rules do not depend
ate between actions that harm innocent people on authorities. Children say that hitting and steal-
and those that break rules but do not harm anyone ing are wrong, even if a teacher says it is okay
(Turiel, 1983; see also Nucci & Turiel, 1978; (Nucci & Turiel, 1978; Smetana, 1981, 1984).
Smetana, 1981). Based on growing support for Similarly, children endorse obedience to moral
the distinction between transgressions that do requests (e.g., to stop fighting) made by any per-
versus do not harm someone, Turiel surmised son, including other children, but they only
that two distinct systems underlie people’s judg- endorse obedience to norms (e.g., seat assign-
ments of social events; a system focused on ments) from legitimate authorities (Laupa, 1994).
morality and another on social convention. Domain theory therefore provides a clear account
Domain theory defines morality as concep- of when and why people sometimes are willing to
tions of rights, fairness, and human welfare that break rules to achieve what is in their view a
depend on inherent features of actions (Turiel, greater good. Moral rules supersede social con-
1983). For example, punching a stranger in the ventions and provide both the motivation and the
face for no reason is wrong because it hurts rationale that attempts to change the system
someone, not because it violates a law, social requirement.
rule, or custom. Social conventions, in contrast, In summary, moral developmental theory
are rules that a particular group has adopted to began with the core assumption that morality and
410 L.J. Skitka et al.

justice operations were functionally the same psy- In the early 1980s, justice theory and research
chological constructs. Although the emphasis on shifted from a dominant focus on distributive
justice operations is less explicit in contemporary justice to consider the role that procedures play
moral developmental theory than it was in Piaget in people’s conceptions of fairness, with a cor-
and Kohlberg’s work, these theories nonetheless responding shift in assumptions about the
continue to assume that justice and morality are motives that drive people’s concern with fair-
either very deeply connected if not the same psy- ness. Procedural justice theorists posited that
chological construct. Integrating the domain the- people’s concern about being fairly treated is
ory distinction between morality and convention driven more by relational motives, such as needs
with social psychological theory and research on to feel valued, respected, and included in impor-
justice, however, suggests the connections are not tant groups, than it is by material self-interests
as deep as these theorists might believe—an issue (e.g., Lind & Tyler, 1988; Tyler & Lind, 1992).
we revisit in the concluding section of this Both the quality of decision-making procedures
chapter. and the quality of interpersonal treatment pro-
vided by decision-making authorities, provide
individuals with important information about
22.2 Morality their status and standing within a group (Blader
from the Perspective & Tyler, 2003).1
of Justice Theory Morality as a consideration or motivation that
and Research shapes people’s justice reasoning is a relatively
new development in justice theorizing and
Justice theory and research evolved almost research. Some of this work connects with the
entirely independently of theory and research in historical focus of justice research on questions
moral development. Moral development theory of distributive and procedural justice, and some
and research was focused on improving child- of it does not, but each of these perspectives
hood education. Justice theory and research, in nonetheless posit that morality—and not only
contrast, was initially motivated by a desire to self-interest or relational needs—plays a role in
understand the factors that affect satisfaction how people think about fairness.
with promotion decisions and wages, and the
implications of just or unjust treatment on worker
productivity (e.g., Adams, 1965; Stouffer,
Suchman, DeVinney, Star, & Williams, 1949).
Early justice theory and research focused largely 1
Some scholars consider interpersonal treatment a dimen-
on questions of distributive justice, that is, how
sion of procedural justice (e.g., Blader & Tyler, 2003),
people believe the benefits and burdens of social others argue that interpersonal treatment from those who
cooperation should be distributed. Theories of implement procedures is a separate construct termed
distributive justice generally assume that people interactional justice (Bies, 2005; Bies & Moag, 1986).
Meta-analyses indicate that interactional justice and pro-
approach life as a series of negotiated exchanges,
cedural justice are highly overlapping but nonetheless dis-
and that human relationships and interactions are tinguishable constructs (Cohen-Charash & Spector, 2001;
best understood by applying subjective cost- Colquitt, Conlon, Wesson, Porter, & Ng, 2001). For exam-
benefit analyses and comparisons of alternatives. ple, people tend to experience higher levels of interac-
tional justice when decision makers provide justifications
Although based on an assumption that people are
and explanations for outcomes compared to when they do
rationally self-interested, these theories also pro- not, irrespective of the decision-making procedures used
pose that properly socialized persons learn that to to generate the outcomes. Although theorists suggested
maximize rewards in the long run, they need to from the outset that poor treatment can prompt moral out-
rage (Bies, 1987), the potentially unique link between
understand and adhere to norms of fairness in
moral motivation and interactional justice has only
their relationships with others (e.g., Walster, recently begun to be emphasized and articulated in detail
Walster, Berscheid, & Austin, 1978). (e.g., Spencer & Rupp, 2009).
22 Morality and Justice 411

22.2.1 Moral Exclusion and the Scope rather than all of morality. In addition, there is
of Justice confusion about whether the scope of justice
should be conceptualized as a dichotomous (in
The scope of justice is defined as the boundary which case targets are either in or out of the scope)
condition on when morality and justice are per- or continuous variable (in which case exclusion
ceived as applicable concerns: Moral rules and can range from mild to severe, Hafer & Olson,
justice considerations only theoretically apply to 2003). The scope of justice concept also implies
those psychologically included in people’s scope that if someone is “inside the scope,” then they get
of justice (Opotow, 1990). Moral exclusion, a positive treatment, whereas if they are outside the
related concept, refers to the entities (e.g., indi- scope, they do not. What this conceptualization
viduals, groups of people, or animals) that are ignores is the possibility that entities—regardless
excluded from people’s scope of justice and of whether they are included or excluded from
therefore not considered as having the right to perceivers’ scope of justice—can vary in whether
fair or moral treatment (Opotow, 1995). they are perceived as deserving positive or nega-
Theory and research on the scope of justice has tive treatment (Hafer & Olson, 2003).
its roots in evidence that people are relatively hard
wired to sort others into categories of “us” versus
“them” (Deutsch, 1990). Categorizing entities in 22.2.2 The Functional Pluralism
this way corresponds with a tendency to see peo- Model of Justice
ple within one’s group (and therefore scope of
justice) as good, and those outside of it as less so The functional pluralism model of justice
(e.g., Tajfel, Billig, Bundy, & Flament, 1971). attempts to integrate moral concerns into how
The consequences of moral exclusion theoreti- people think about questions of procedural and
cally range from mild kinds of micro-aggression distributive justice. According to the functional
(e.g., verbal or behavioral indignities; Sue, pluralism model of justice (Skitka, 2003; Skitka,
Bucceri, Lin, Nadal, & Torino, 2009) to much Aramovich, Lytle, & Sargis, 2009; Skitka &
more harmful forms of exclusion, including exter- Wisneski, 2012), the adaptive challenges people
mination, genocide, slavery, or mass internments confront in their everyday lives require the abil-
(e.g., DeWind, 1990; Nagata, 1990, 1993; Staub, ity to move fluidly between different goal states
1990). Consistent with scope of justice predic- or motives. For example, people have to resolve
tions, people are less likely to support social poli- the problems of (a) competing for scarce
cies designed to help excluded groups (Beaton & resources, such as wages or jobs (the economist),
Tougas, 2001; Opotow, 1994; Singer, 1996), more (b) how to get along with others and secure their
likely to deny excluded groups legal procedures standing in important groups (the politician), and
and rights (Boeckmann & Tyler, 1997), and more (c) building a meaningful sense of existence (the
likely to express apathy when they witness nega- theologian).2 In short, the functional pluralism
tive treatment of excluded than included groups model’s position is that people are intuitive econ-
(Brockner, 1990; Foster & Rusbult, 1999). omists, politicians, and theologians. Which
Although the notion that people maintain a homunculus is piloting the ship at any given time
scope of justice has been generative, it has not (so to speak), depends on the current goal orien-
escaped constructive criticism. Among other tation of the actor and the salience of various
issues, there is not agreement that justice and situational cues that could activate one or another
morality are functional equivalents, or if instead, of these mindsets.
justice is only one aspect of morality or ethics
(Hafer & Olson, 2003). Although Opotow and
others treat these concepts as relatively inter- 2
Other mindsets or perspectives that can influence percep-
changeable, it might be preferable to narrow the tions of fairness are the intuitive scientist and prosecutor
“scope of justice” term to concerns about fairness, (see Skitka & Wisneski, 2012 for a review).
412 L.J. Skitka et al.

The intuitive economist. People take the perspec- one’s life who control valuable resources and
tive of an intuitive economist when situations who have some legitimate right to inquire into the
prime a materialistic mindset. According to the reasons behind one’s opinions or decisions. This
functional pluralism model of justice, material knowledge activates the goal of establishing or
goals and concerns are most likely to be activated preserving a desired social identity vis-à-vis
when (a) there is a possibility of material gain, (b) these constituencies” (Tetlock, 2002, p. 454).
the relational context is defined in market terms, The functional pluralism model predicts that
and (c) other goals are not particularly salient. people are more likely to take the perspective of
Contexts that prime the intuitive economist there- the intuitive politician when: (a) their material
fore include negotiations for goods and services, needs are at least minimally satisfied, (b) their
purchases, investments, and other contexts in needs for belongingness, status, and inclusion are
which the primary goal is material exchange. not being met or are under threat, (c) the potential
When the intuitive economist, or materialistic for significant relational losses or gains are made
mindset is activated, people define equitable out- especially salient, (d) the dominant goal of the
comes as more fair than outcomes distributed social system is to maximize group harmony or
equally or on the basis of need (e.g., Deutsch, solidarity, (e) people’s interdependency concerns
1985), a finding that is robust across cultures are primed, and (f) accountability demands are
(Fiske, 1991). They also become physiologically high (Skitka, 2003; Skitka & Wisneski, 2012).
distressed at either inequitable underpayment or Consistent with the idea that the goals associ-
overpayment, and adjust their level of effort and ated with the intuitive politician perspective
productivity to restore equity (see Walster et al., influence people’s reasoning, people care more
1978 for a review). Although no research to our about procedures and interpersonal treatment
knowledge has studied the degree to which an intu- than material outcomes when (a) social identity
itive economist mindset affects perceptions of pro- needs are particularly strong, (b) perceivers are of
cedural justice, there are some logical possibilities. low rather than high status, (c) status concerns
For example, intuitive economists should be espe- are primed, and (d) they are high rather than low
cially concerned about consistency, for example, in interdependent self-construal and interdepen-
that pricing rules or compensation guidelines are dent self-construal is activated (see Skitka &
applied in the same way irrespective of who is pur- Wisneski, 2012 for a review). In a related vein,
chasing the goods or performing the service. Given people are more likely to accept negative or unfa-
that voice effects on procedural fairness are vorable material outcomes when they are the
explained to some degree by the instrumental ben- result of fair rather than unfair procedures (the
efits of process control (e.g., Lind, Kanfer, & “fair process effect,” e.g., Folger, 1977), in part
Earley, 1990), people in an intuitive economist because these procedures convey information
mindset might also be especially sensitive to oppor- about belongingness (e.g., De Cremer & Alberts,
tunities for voice, but primarily for instrumental 2004) and respect (Lind & Tyler, 1988; Tyler &
rather than noninstrumental reasons. Lind, 1992). In short, people sacrifice material
interests to serve social identity needs and goals,
The intuitive politician. When situations activate when social identity needs are more salient than
an intuitive politician mindset, people are moti- material ones.
vated to achieve and maintain a position to influ- Variables related to social identity also influence
ence others, to accumulate the symbols, status, people’s judgments of distributive justice. For
and prestige associated with influence and power, example, people primed with solidarity and group
and seek approval from the social groups and harmony goals, who are chronically higher in com-
individuals to whom they are accountable munal or interpersonal orientation, or who take a
(Tetlock, 2002). Intuitive politicians’ motivation group rather than an individual level perspective,
is rooted in “the knowledge that one is under the are more likely to allocate material rewards equally
evaluative scrutiny of important constituencies in than equitably, and to rate equal allocations as more
22 Morality and Justice 413

fair than equitable ones. Other research indicates cases, they can simply evaluate whether authori-
conceptions of fairness vary as a function of the ties get it “right.” “Right” decisions indicate that
social role of the perceiver. For example, when authorities are appropriate and work as they
one’s social role as a parent is more highly acti- should. “Wrong” answers signal that the system
vated, one is more likely to perceive allocations is somehow broken and is not working as it
based on need as fairer than those based on equity should. Consistent with these ideas, people’s fair-
or equality (see Skitka & Wisneski, 2012 for a ness reasoning is driven more by whether author-
review). ities get it “right” than by whether authorities
provide opportunities for voice, respect the dig-
The intuitive theologian. People adopt an intui- nity of those involved, or otherwise enact proce-
tive theologian mindset when they are motivated dural fairness when people have a moral
more by concerns about morality and immorality investment in decision outcomes (e.g., Bauman
and questions of the greater good than by either & Skitka, 2009; Skitka, 2002; Skitka & Houston,
their social standing or material self-interest. 2001; Skitka & Mullen, 2002; Skitka, Aramovich
People should be more likely to use a moral et al., 2009; Skitka, Bauman & Lytle, 2009).
frame of reference for evaluating fairness when In summary, theories of procedural and dis-
(a) their material and social needs are minimally tributive justice have emphasized materialistic
satisfied, (b) they have a moral conviction about and social motivations underlying justice and
the outcome being decided (e.g., whether abor- ignored or dismissed the possibility that people’s
tion is or is not legal); (c) moral emotions are conceptions of fairness might connect to underly-
aroused, such as moral outrage, guilt, or shame; ing moral motives. Justice theory and research
(d) there is a real or perceived threat to people’s has been preoccupied with which of these two
conceptions of morality (not just normative con- motives—materialistic/egoistic motivation ver-
ventions), (e) people’s sense of personal moral sus social identity and belongingness—best
authenticity is questioned or undermined, or (f) explains people’s reasoning about procedural and
people are reminded of their mortality (Skitka, distributive fairness. A working definition of jus-
2003; Skitka, Aramovich et al., 2009; Skitka & tice and what it means to people, however, could
Wisneski, 2012). just as reasonably start with morality, righteous-
Consistent with these hypotheses, people are ness, virtues, and ethics rather than with self-
more likely to believe that duties and rights fol- interest, belongingness, or other nonmoral
low from the greater moral purposes underlying motivations. The functional pluralism model of
rules, procedures, and authority dictates, than justice treats materialistic and social identity con-
from the rules, procedures, or authorities them- cerns as valid motivations that can contingently
selves when they have a moral investment in out- influence how people think about fairness
comes (Skitka, Bauman & Lytle, 2009; see also (instead of framing these as competing theoreti-
Kohlberg, 1976). Moral beliefs are not by defini- cal alternatives), but it also recognizes that moral
tion antiestablishment or anti-authority; they just concerns sometimes shape people’s fairness rea-
are not dependent on establishment, convention, soning as well.
rules, or authorities. Instead, when people take a
moral perspective, they focus more on their ide-
als, and the way they believe things “ought” or 22.2.3 Fairness Theory and the
“should” be done, than on a duty to comply with Deonance Approach
authorities. When people have moral certainty
about what outcome authorities and institutions Fairness theory focuses less on questions of pro-
should deliver, they do not need to rely on stand- cedural and distributive fairness, and more on
ing perceptions of legitimacy as proxy informa- people’s reactions to transgressions. Fairness
tion to judge whether the system works—in these theory posits that justice is fundamentally about
414 L.J. Skitka et al.

accountability and the assignment of blame in Rupp, 2010). However, deontic responses also
response to counter-normative outcomes and include opportunities for social reconciliation,
interpersonal conduct (Cropanzano, Byrne, which open the door to future interactions once
Bobocel, & Rupp, 2001; Folger & Cropanzano, a situation has been satisfactorily resolved.
1998, 2001; Folger, Cropanzano, & Goldman, Taken together, these aspects of the deontic
2005). According to the theory, perceived fair- approach highlight a facet of the way people
ness depends on people’s answer to three central experience injustice that has been absent from
questions: (a) Would the situation have turned out many theories of justice.
better if things were done differently? (b) Could In summary, fairness theory attempts to
the actor have behaved differently? (c) Should the integrate and organize theory and research on
actor have behaved differently? That is, “would” moral judgment with justice, and proposes the
judgments assess whether something negative social cognitive and emotional processes that
occurred by considering counterfactual alterna- may underlie when, why, and how people judge
tives as reference points. “Could” judgments and react to unfairness. Empirical research that
determine whether the actor realistically could formulates and tests specific hypotheses
have chosen a different course of action. “Should” derived from fairness theory has recently gath-
judgments ascertain whether the actor violated ered momentum (e.g., Umphress, Simmons,
moral or ethical standards. In short, people judge Folger, Ren, & Bobocel, 2012), but as with any
fairness by comparing aspects of events associ- relatively young theory, there are many areas
ated with accountability to counterfactual of fairness theory that remain untested, unad-
alternatives. dressed, and underspecified. For example, fair-
The “should” component of fairness theory ness theory currently has only addressed
explicitly links justice and morality. It argues negative events, that is, people’s responses to
that perceived transgressions of moral norms perceived transgressions. Although the theory
for interpersonal conduct—the product of may ultimately be extended to explain people’s
“should” judgments—arouse deonance, a moti- reactions to positive events (Folger &
vational state akin to reactance and dissonance Cropanzano, 2001), asymmetries in how peo-
(Folger, 1998, 2001). Deontic responses have at ple process positive and negative events are
least five important attributes that distinguish likely to complicate this effort (e.g.,
them from other responses to unfairness (Folger Baumeister, Bratslavsky, Finkenauer, & Vohs,
et al., 2005). Deontic responses often involve 2001). Therefore, fairness theory provides a
rapid evaluations of situations that alert per- broad framework for understanding justice
ceivers to injustice. Although people can and judgments in the context of transgressions that
do consciously deliberate about justice, initial may provide increasing utility as it continues
appraisals of unfairness can arise from auto- to develop.
matic attribution processes that detect and cat-
egorize stimuli as negative for the perceiver.
Deontic responses do not always serve individ- 22.3 Justice from the Perspective
uals’ self-interest and often include strong of Theory and Research
emotions, especially anger and hostility that on Adult Morality
drive behavioral responses. Furthermore, deon-
tic responses prompt a desire for retribution. Justice theorists are not alone in their recent
Rather than seek compensation for the losses interest in morality; in recent years other social
they incurred, aggrieved persons can be moti- psychologists have also become fascinated by
vated to restore justice through punishment or morality. We turn next to how social psycholo-
other means perceived to decrease the likeli- gists interested in morality have made connec-
hood of future violations (e.g., Skarlicki & tions with psychological concerns with justice.
22 Morality and Justice 415

22.3.1 Moral Foundations Theory To date, however, empirical research on addi-


tional candidates for “foundationhood” has
Moral foundations theory (MFT) incorporates focused mainly on Liberty/oppression, which
concerns with justice as part of a larger pluralist underlies the negative reactions people have to
theory of morality. Drawing on similarities individuals or institutions that meddle in the lives
between works in anthropology (e.g., Fiske, of others (see Iyer, Koleva, Graham, Ditto, &
1992; Shweder, Much, Mahapatra, & Park, Haidt, 2012).
1997), and evolutionary theories of human soci- The harm and fairness foundations are indi-
ality, Haidt and colleagues proposed MFT (Haidt vidualizing foundations (in which individuals are
& Joseph, 2004, 2007; Haidt & Graham, 2007; the locus of moral value, and concerns with
see Graham et al., 2013 for a review) to explain autonomy and protecting individuals’ rights are
variation in morality across (sub)cultures. In par- paramount), whereas in group, authority and
ticular MFT argues that there is a small set of purity are binding foundations (in which the
innate “foundations” upon which cultures con- group is the locus of moral value, and concerns
struct their moral systems. Thus, MFT argues with loyalty, duty, and self-control are para-
some aspects of morality are organized in mount; Graham et al., 2009). Haidt and col-
advance of experience (Marcus, 2004), but never- leagues argue that most research in moral
theless get revised during childhood through cul- psychology has tended to focus on the individual-
tural practices and experiences. The revision izing foundations, and has neglected the other
process accounts for the diversity of moralities foundations.
witnessed across cultures and across groups Much of the research on MFT has been applied
within a culture (Graham, Haidt, & Nosek, 2009). to understanding ideological disagreements
MFT asserts that there are at least five moral between liberals and conservatives (and of late,
foundations: (1) Harm/care, (2) Fairness/reci- libertarians). In particular, Haidt and colleagues
procity, (3) In-group/loyalty, (4) Authority/ have argued that liberals endorse the harm and
respect, and (5) Purity/sanctity (Graham et al., fairness foundations more than the other founda-
2013). The harm/care foundation underlies vir- tions, whereas conservatives tend to endorse all
tues of kindness, generosity, and nurturance and five foundations more equally (Graham et al.,
evolved from our ability to feel the pain of others. 2009; Haidt & Graham, 2007); both groups
The fairness/reciprocity foundation underlies equally endorse liberty (Graham et al., 2013).
ideas of justice, rights, equity, and autonomy and Thus, according to MFT, the root of some ideo-
is related to the process of reciprocal altruism. logical disagreements rests in the fact that con-
The in-group/loyalty foundation underlies the vir- servatives endorse moral principles that liberals
tue of self-sacrifice for the group and values such don’t recognize as moral (Haidt & Graham,
as loyalty and patriotism; it evolved in response to 2007). MFT and moral motives theory (reviewed
our ancestors’ ability to form shifting coalitions. later in this chapter) together suggest that justice
The authority/respect foundation underlies the researchers may have missed an important mod-
virtues of obedience to legitimate authorities and erator of how people judge fairness, specifically,
respect for tradition; it evolved from our history of the political orientation of the perceiver.
hierarchical social interactions. Finally, the purity/ Although MFT has generated a lot of research
sanctity foundation underlies ideas about religios- in the short time since its original formulation, it
ity and how the body can be desecrated by con- has also been subject to criticism (for a review
taminants and impure activities; it evolved from see Graham et al., 2013). In particular, MFT has
disgust mechanisms that protect the body. been criticized for lacking conceptual clarity on
Notably, Haidt and colleagues believe that several what constitutes a foundation and for not provid-
additional foundations may exist, including but ing enough evidence that moral intuitions are in
not limited to Liberty/oppression, Efficiency/ fact innate (Suhler & Churchland, 2011). Some
waste, and Ownership/theft (Graham et al., 2013). scholars reject its pluralist perspective and argue
416 L.J. Skitka et al.

that all morality comes down to the dimension of Social relationships generally fit one of four
harm (Gray, Young, & Waytz, 2012). Others basic relational models: communal sharing,
argue that only the harm and fairness dimensions authority ranking, equality matching, and market
are truly moral, and the other foundations repre- pricing (Fiske, 1991, 1992; see also Haslam,
sent conventional beliefs (e.g., Jost, 2009). Still 2004). How people define fairness and morality
others criticize MFT for missing vital elements therefore depends on the relational system. In
of morality (see Janoff-Bulman’s work reviewed communal sharing relationships, all people within
below) or for not paying enough attention to the a given group (e.g., a family) hold equivalent and
relational context in which concerns about moral- undifferentiated status and can expect equal
ity arise (Rai & Fiske, 2011). The authors of access to resources, but the same is not true for
MFT acknowledge these criticisms in their recent outsiders. The authority ranking model provides
writings and discuss ways that MFT could organization within a group by introducing asym-
address these criticisms in future research metry among members according to ordinal posi-
(Graham et al., 2013). tions that indicate linear patterns of dominance
In summary, MFT argues that concerns about and deference. In equality matching relationships,
harm and justice (which have been the dominant people seek to balance their outcome relative to
focus in the literatures on moral development and others’ in terms of both valence and magnitude
the social psychology of justice) are only two along one dimension at a time (e.g., effort). In
foundations on which morality is built. By draw- market pricing relationships, people take into
ing our attention to other possible foundations of account a wide array of disparate dimensions of
morality (e.g., authority), MFT has highlighted comparison and combine them along a common
that justice and morality are not identical con- metric (often money) into a single ratio that facili-
cepts because concerns about justice and harm tates complex comparisons and exchanges. The
are only part of the larger pie of morality. four basic relational models help people antici-
pate and coordinate behavior, evaluate interac-
tions and exchanges, and identify transgressions.
22.3.2 Relational Models Theory Each relational model prescribes the basis for
and Moral Relationship moral motivation and judgment that people use to
Regulation derive appropriate standards of conduct given the
nature of the relationship between the individuals
The relationship regulation approach to morality involved (Rai & Fiske, 2011). Unity is the princi-
posits that people derive their standards for pal moral motive in communal sharing relation-
morality and justice from their understanding of ships. People in communal sharing situations are
the social relationships within specific situations expected to take care of their own. They ought to
(Rai & Fiske, 2011). According to this perspec- satisfy any in-group members’ unmet needs,
tive, moral principles do not exist independent of experience threats to individual members of the
the social-relational contexts in which they oper- group as a threat to the group as a whole, and
ate. Instead, moral concepts such as harm, equal- protect the integrity of the group from both inter-
ity, or purity are situationally determined as a nal and external disruptions. Hierarchy is the
function of the type of social relationship a given principal moral motive in relationships character-
situation involves. Diversity in moral thought, ized by authority ranking. People expect inequal-
feelings, and actions therefore is not the product ity in these situations; lower ranking individuals
of erroneous recognition of moral facts but a claim fewer resources and have a duty to support
legitimate consequence of how different people and defer to higher ranking individuals. Higher
interpret social situations and implement a finite ranking individuals, in contrast, claim more
set of schema about the nature of a given resources but are obligated to lead and look after
relationship. lower ranking individuals.
22 Morality and Justice 417

Equality is the principal moral motive in the flict that is accompanied by moral outrage
equality matching model. In relationships char- (Fiske & Tetlock, 1997). Tradeoffs that are rel-
acterized by equality matching, people strive to atively easy to make when viewed through the
provide equal opportunities or outcomes lens of one relational model can appear inap-
through processes such as turn taking, in-kind propriate—or even ghastly and unthinkable—
reciprocity, and lotteries in which each person when viewed through the lens of another. Goods
has the same opportunity to be chosen. Finally, and services, for example, are bought and sold
proportionality is the principal moral motive in every day, and the vast majority of these trans-
market pricing relationships. When market actions are acceptable because people apply the
pricing applies, people monitor multiple inputs market pricing model to such exchanges. When
and outputs simultaneously and ensure that it comes to human organs, however, people
rewards and punishments are equitable. Taken often apply the communal sharing model,
together, the relational regulation approach which causes them to view organ markets as
integrates a wide array of perspectives, includ- taboo and morally repugnant. Somewhat simi-
ing prior research on care (e.g., Opotow, 1990), larly, friendships often operate under the equal-
authority (e.g., Tyler & Lind, 1992), and mul- ity matching model. If one couple invites
tiple distributive justice criteria (e.g., Deutsch, another to their home for dinner, the appropri-
1985). By doing so, it provides a comprehen- ate response is to reciprocate at a later date.
sive and contingent theory of when and why Offering to pay a sum that would cover the cost
moral rules and motives vary across situations of dinner would be perfectly acceptable under
and individuals. the market pricing model (e.g., at a restaurant),
From the perspective of relational models but awkward and uncomfortable under the
theory, moral conflict is largely the result of dis- equality matching model in someone’s home.
agreement over implementation rules that spec- In sum, relational models and the moral motives
ify when, how, and to whom each relational that accompany them facilitate social interac-
model applies (Fiske, 1991, 1992; Fiske & tions, but conflict arises when people apply dif-
Tetlock, 1997). The relational models them- ferent implementation rules, or worse, a
selves are universal but abstract. Beliefs about completely different model.
how to operationalize the models to address In summary, relational models theory and the
specific situations and relationships vary across moral relationship regulation approach provide a
cultures, groups, institutions, ideologies, and rich framework for understanding how and why
individuals’ familiarity with possible prece- morality and justice vary across situations, and it
dents. Consider, for example, a situation in also explains when and why people sometimes
which most people agree that the equality moralize conflict and resist the type of tradeoffs
matching model fits. If one person does another that are necessary to resolve disagreements. The
a favor, everyone might agree that reciprocation relational systems model is solidly grounded in
is appropriate. In the absence of more precise interdisciplinary theory and empirical research
implementation rules, however, it remains about how people coordinate social relationships.
unclear how or when the favor should be recip- However, it is presented at a level of abstraction
rocated. Different interpretations of the ways to that may make it difficult to formulate hypothe-
satisfy the requirements of a model can there- ses about how the theory should apply in specific
fore lead to misunderstanding, disagreement, situations. Moreover, the theory allows that any
and conflict. given situation can simultaneously involve parts
Disagreement over which model ought to of each model, which may limit its utility or
apply to a given situation is less common than make it unfalsifiable. Therefore, greater specifi-
disagreement over implementation rules, but it cation of the theory is needed before it can be
tends to generate intense and intractable con- tested cleanly.
418 L.J. Skitka et al.

22.3.3 Moral Motives Model The moral concerns identified by MFT over-
lap to a considerable degree with the moral
Janoff-Bulman and Carnes (2013) moral motives motives model, with one primary exception.
model has been offered as an alternative to MFT MFT defines fairness in individuating terms—it
and the relational models theory. Building on the describes microjustice (i.e., justice from the per-
scaffolding of theory and research on behavioral spective of the individual). In contrast, moral
regulation and motivation (e.g., motives of motives theory differentiates between micro- and
approach and avoidance, and behavioral activa- macrojustice, or justice at the level of the indi-
tion versus inhibition; e.g., Carver & Scheier, vidual versus the collective, respectively.
1998), Janoff-Bulman and Carnes argue that Although the macro- or social justice compo-
morality fundamentally involves behavioral reg- nent of moral motives theory has already proven
ulation to facilitate an optimized social existence. to be somewhat controversial (see Graham, 2013
In particular, proscriptive moral regulation is for a critique), it has strong empirical grounding
focused on avoiding immorality or transgres- in research that has revealed important differ-
sions, and is inhibitory and protection oriented. ences between how people think about justice for
In contrast, prescriptive morality is an approach individuals versus collectives (Brickman, Folger,
motivation oriented toward providing rather than Goode, & Schul, 1981). Individual justice focuses
protecting. on person-specific variables, such as merit.
In addition to arguing that morality engages Macrojustice (or what Janoff-Bulman & Carnes,
these two motivational systems, Janoff-Bulman 2013 called social justice) instead focuses on the
and Carnes (2013) argue that these moral motiva- shape of the outcome distribution writ large, such
tions can play out at three different levels of anal- as the distribution of annual income of a given
ysis, specifically morality of the self, the other, public. Discourse about growing income inequal-
and the group. At the level of the self, proscrip- ity is a concrete example of a macrojustice
tive and prescriptive moral motivations are asso- concern.
ciated with self-restraint and moderation on the MFT also implies that liberals for the most
one hand, and industriousness on the other. Other part do not have a communal moral orientation.
directed moral motivation is interpersonally Moral motives theory challenges this idea, and
directed, and is proscriptively focused on avoid- argues that liberals do have communal moral
ing harm, and prescriptively focused on helping concerns, they just are not captured well by the
and fairness. Finally, the group-based or collec- foundations of in-group, authority, and purity,
tive oriented moral motives are concerned with which are largely described in proscriptive terms,
social order and communal solidarity when they which appeal to conservatives. In contrast, moral
are proscriptively oriented (e.g., status quo main- motives theory proposes that liberals’ communal
tenance), and focused on social justice and com- moral motivations are prescriptively oriented
munity responsibility when they are prescriptively around concerns about social justice and commu-
motivated. Similar to MFT, Janoff-Bulman and nal responsibility, and not in-group, authority or
Carnes (2013) argue that liberals and conserva- purity.
tives differ in their moral motivations. According Strengths of moral motives theory include its
to this model, however, ideological differences explicit grounding in psychological theory and
are not classified around individuating or binding research on motivation, as well as reinvigorating
foundations, but are focused instead on differ- the important distinctions between micro- and
ences in the motivational priorities of liberals and macrojustice. Especially given recent public
conservatives. Political conservatives’ moral debate about issues such as income inequality,
motivations are more likely to be proscriptively social class divisions in access to higher educa-
motivated, whereas political liberals’ moral moti- tion, and various other macrojustice topics, how
vations are prescriptively motivated. people reconcile conflicts between micro- and
22 Morality and Justice 419

macrojustice concerns will be an important area ments (e.g., Brockner et al., 1998; Skitka &
for future research. Mullen, 2002; van den Bos, Wilke, Lind, &
Vermunt, 1998). Furthermore, the claim that jus-
tice rules are more often based on normative con-
22.4 Morality and Justice: ventions than moral imperatives is reinforced by
The Same or Different the degree to which definitions of justice include
Constructs? not only informal norms, but also a host of for-
malized codes and guidelines that can vary across
This review highlights the considerable variabil- organizational structures or communities.
ity in the literature regarding how morality and Homeowners’ associations, for example, gener-
justice are related. For Piaget and Kohlberg, ate very localized versions of their covenants;
morality and justice were viewed as essentially workplaces vary in their pay and benefit policies,
the same thing; more contemporary theories of and so forth. Although all homeowners’ associa-
moral development, however, have de- tions and workplaces (for example) will develop
emphasized the links between morality and jus- their covenants and policies in ways that ensure
tice operations. Contemporary theories of fairness (and therefore increase compliance),
morality differ from theories of justice in the there is no one just set of rules, nor do people
kinds of connections they make between moral- experience these rules as universally generaliz-
ity and justice. Moral foundations and moral able or objective truths.
motives theories, for example, posit that justice is In contrast, people do not generally accept and
merely one aspect among many that define the expect that their conceptions of morality are or
moral domain. Alternatively, recent theories of should be contextually contingent or situationally
justice maintain that morality is one concern that variable, and are offended at the very idea that
underlies why people care about justice. morality could be relative (e.g., Darwell, 1998;
One way to help clarify the similarities and Smith, 1994). Even philosophers who reject the
differences in the psychology of justice and idea of moral objectivism (e.g., Mackie, 1977)
morality may be to integrate the distinction nonetheless accept that people’s commitment to
domain theory makes between normative con- the idea that there are objective moral truths is
ventions and moral imperatives with justice the- central to folk metaethics (i.e., people’s beliefs
ory and research. Specifically, it may be that and assumptions about the nature of morality).
people’s conceptions of justice are often grounded In summary, our review of the rather dis-
more on conventional beliefs than moral impera- jointed literature on morality and justice leads us
tives. Consistent with this assertion, people tend to tentatively conclude that morality and justice
to acknowledge and accept the idea that determi- are distinct, but sometimes overlapping psycho-
nants of fairness can and should vary across situ- logical constructs. Perceptions of justice are typi-
ations, but they experience their moral beliefs cally more negotiable and flexible than moral
and convictions as universally generalizable and beliefs. Justice judgments also are at least as
objective truths (e.g., Goodwin & Darley, 2008; likely to be driven by nonmoral as moral con-
Morgan, Skitka, & Lytle, 2013). Moreover, cerns. That is, justice judgments often are made
researchers have identified a plethora of alloca- using what Rest et al. (1999a, 1999b) referred to
tion norms and standards that are seen as differ- as personal interest or norm maintenance sche-
entially fair and appropriate in different contexts, mas, or what Skitka and Wisneski (2012) labeled
relationships, or situations (e.g., Deutsch, 1985). as the intuitive economist or politician mindsets.
A broad range of factors similarly shape percep- Justice only becomes moralized when it is based
tions of procedural fairness (e.g., Leventhal, on post-conventional beliefs about fundamental
1980; Lind & Tyler, 1988) and the relative weight questions of right and wrong, which unlike nor-
that people place on distributive versus proce- mative conventions, are nonnegotiable, authority
dural considerations when making fairness judg- independent, and autonomous.
420 L.J. Skitka et al.

Future theory and research will need to further Bies, R. J. (1987). The predicament of injustice: The man-
agement of moral outrage. In L. L. Cummings &
develop and refine the ways in which morality
B. M. Staw (Eds.), Research in organizational behav-
and justice are similar and different. Important to ior (Vol. 9, pp. 289–319). Greenwich, CT: JAI.
this refinement will be (a) careful definition of Bies, R. J., & Moag, J. S. (1986). Interactional justice:
terms, (b) deciding whether justice and morality Communication criteria of fairness. In R. J. Lewicki,
B. H. Sheppard, & M. H. Bazerman (Eds.), Research
describe judgments, behaviors, attitudes, motives,
on negotiation in organizations (pp. 43–55).
treatment, or outcomes (or all of the above), and Greenwich, CT: JAI Press.
(c) exploring the ways in which perspective may Bies, R. J. (2005). Are procedural justice and interactional
matter, that is, whether one is the recipient or tar- justice conceptually distinct? In J. Greenberg, J.A.
Colquitt (Eds). Handbook of organizational justice
get, a third-party perceiver, or the allocator or
(pp. 85–112). Mahwah, NJ, US: Lawrence Erlbaum
actor of justice and morality. Associates Publishers.
Blader, S., & Tyler, T. R. (2003). A four-component
model of procedural justice: Defining the meaning of a
“fair” process. Personality and Social Psychology
22.5 Conclusion Bulletin, 29, 747–758.
Boeckmann, R. J., & Tyler, T. R. (1997). Commonsense
In summary, theories of moral development, justice and inclusion within the moral community:
morality, and justice evolved independently but When do people receive procedural justice from oth-
ers? Psychology, Public Policy, and Law, 3, 362–380.
have converged on the idea that justice and
Brickman, P., Folger, R., Goode, E., & Schul, Y. (1981).
morality are inherently linked yet separate con- Microjustice and macrojustice. In M. J. Lerner & S. C.
structs. The relation between justice and moral- Lerner (Eds.), The justice motive in social behavior
ity is almost assuredly conditional; sometimes (pp. 173–202). New York, NY: Plenum.
Brockner, J. (1990). Scope of justice in the workplace:
there is a high degree of overlap between jus-
How survivors react to co-worker lay-offs. Journal of
tice and morality, but there are aspects of moral- Social Issues, 46, 95–106.
ity that have nothing to do with justice and Brockner, J., Heuer, L., Siegel, P. A., Wiesenfeld, B.,
aspects of justice that have nothing to do with Martin, C., Grover, S., … & Bjorgvinsson, S. (1998).
The moderating effect of self-esteem in reaction to
morality. That said, little research has directly
voice: converging evidence from five studies. Journal
examined this space. Future research aimed at of Personality and Social Psychology, 75(2), 394.
doing so has the opportunity to have a big Carver, C. S., & Scheier, M. F. (1998). On the self-
impact because it may inform multiple regulation of behavior. New York, NY: Cambridge
University Press.
literatures.
Cohen-Charash, Y., & Spector, P. E. (2001). The role of
justice in organizations: A meta-analysis.
Acknowledgments All authors contributed equally to Organizational Behavior and Human Decision
the preparation of this chapter. Processes, 86, 278–324.
Colquitt, J. A., Conlon, D. E., Wesson, M. J., Porter, C. O.
L. H., & Ng, K. Y. (2001). Justice at the millennium:
A meta-analysis of 25 years of organizational justice
References research. Journal of Applied Psychology, 86,
425–445.
Adams, J. S. (1965). Inequity in social exchange. In Cropanzano, R., Byrne, Z. S., Bobocel, D. R., & Rupp,
L. Berkowitz (Ed.), Advances in experimental social D. E. (2001). Self-enhancement biases, laboratory
psychology (Vol. 2, pp. 267–299). New York, NY: experiments, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, and the
Academic. increasingly crowded world of organizational justice.
Bauman, C. W., & Skitka, L. J. (2009). Moral conflict and Journal of Vocational Behavior, 58, 260–272.
procedural justice: Moral mandates as constraints to Darwell, S. (1998). Philosophical ethics. Boulder, CO:
voice effects. Australian Journal of Psychology, 61, Westview.
40–49. De Cremer, D., & Alberts, H. J. (2004). When procedural
Baumeister, R. F., Bratslavsky, E., Finkenauer, C., & fairness does not influence how positive I feel: The
Vohs, K. D. (2001). Bad is stronger than good. Review effects of voice and leader selection as a function of
of General Psychology, 5, 323–370. belongingness need. European Journal of Social
Beaton, A. M., & Tougas, F. (2001). Reactions to affirma- Psychology, 34(3), 333–344.
tive action: Group membership and social justice. Deutsch, M. (1985). Distributive justice. Binghamton,
Social Justice Research, 14, 1042–1054. NY: Vail-Ballou Press.
22 Morality and Justice 421

Deutsch, M. (1990). Sixty years of conflict. International Gray, K., Young, L., & Waytz, A. (2012). Mind percep-
Journal of Conflict Management, 1(3), 237–263. tion is the essence of morality. Psychological Inquiry,
DeWind, J. (1990). Alien justice: The exclusion of Haitian 23, 101–124.
refugees. Journal of social issues, 46(1), 121–132. Hafer, C. L., & Olson, J. M. (2003). An analysis of empir-
Fiske, A. P. (1991). Structures of social life: The four ele- ical research on the scope of justice. Personality and
mentary forms of human relations: Communal shar- Social Psychology Review, 7, 311–323.
ing, authority ranking, equality matching, market Haidt, J., & Graham, J. (2007). When morality opposes
pricing. New York, NY: Free Press. justice: Conservatives have moral intuitions that liber-
Fiske, A. P. (1992). The four elementary forms of social- als may not recognize. Social Justice Research, 20,
ity: Framework for a unified theory of social relations. 98–116.
Psychological Review, 99, 689–723. Haidt, J., & Joseph, C. (2004). Intuitive ethics: How
Fiske, A. P., & Tetlock, P. E. (1997). Taboo trade‐offs: innately prepared intuitions generate culturally vari-
reactions to transactions that transgress the spheres of able virtues. Daedalus, 133, 55–66.
justice. Political Psychology, 18, 255–297. Haidt, J., & Joseph, C. (2007). The moral mind: How 5
Folger, R. (1977). Distributive and procedural justice: sets of innate intuitions guide the development of
Combined impact of “voice” and improvement of many culture-specific virtues, and perhaps even mod-
experienced inequity. Journal of Personality and ules. In P. Carruthers, S. Laurence, & S. Stich (Eds.),
Social Psychology, 35, 108–119. The innate mind (Vol. 3, pp. 367–391). New York, NY:
Folger, R. (1998). Fairness as a moral virtue. In Oxford.
M. Schminke (Ed.), Managerial ethics: Moral man- Haslam, S. A. (2004). Psychology in organizations. Sage.
agement of people and processes (pp. 13–34). Iyer, R., Koleva, S., Graham, J., Ditto, P., & Haidt,
Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. J. (2012). Understanding libertarian morality: The
Folger, R. (2001). Fairness as deonance. In S. W. Gilliland, psychological dispositions of self-identified libertari-
D. D. Steiner, & D. P. Skarlicki (Eds.), Research in ans. PloS One, 7(8), e42366. doi:10.1371/journal.
social issues in management (Vol. 1, pp. 3–33). pone.0042366.
New York, NY: Information Age. Janoff-Bulman, R., & Carnes, N. C. (2013). Surveying the
Folger, R., & Cropanzano, R. (1998). Organizational jus- moral landscape. Personality and Social Psychology
tice and human resource management. Thousand Review, 17, 237–241.
Oaks, CA: Sage. Jost, J. T. (2009). Group morality and ideology: Left and
Folger, R., & Cropanzano, R. (2001). Fairness theory: right, right and wrong. Paper presented to the Society
Justice as accountability. In J. Greenberg & for Personality and Social Psychology annual confer-
R. Cropanzano (Eds.), Advances in organizational jus- ence, Tampa, FL.
tice (pp. 1–55). Stanford, CA: Stanford University Kohlberg, L. (1976). Moral stages and moralization: The
Press. cognitive developmental approach. In T. Lickona
Folger, R., Cropanzano, R., & Goldman, B. (2005). (Ed.), Moral development and behavior: Theory,
Justice, accountability, and moral sentiment: The research and social issues. New York, NY: Holt,
deontic response to “foul play” at work. In J. Greenberg Rinehart, & Winston.
& J. Colquitt (Eds.), Handbook of organizational jus- Kohlberg, L. (1981). The philosophy of moral develop-
tice (pp. 215–245). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. ment: Moral stages and the idea of justice. San
Foster, C. A., & Rusbult, C. E. (1999). Injustice and Francisco, CA: Harper & Row.
powerseeking. Personality and Social Psychology Konow, J. (2008). Distributive justice. In M. A. Genovese
Bulletin, 25, 834–849. & L. C. Han (Eds.), Encyclopedia of American gov-
Gilligan, C. (1982). In a different voice: Psychological ernment and civics. New York, NY: Facts-on-File.
theory and women’s development. Cambridge: Laupa, M. (1994). Who’s in charge? Preschool children’s
Harvard University Press. concepts of authority. Early Childhood Research
Goodwin, G. P. & Darley, J. M. (2008). The psychology of Quarterly, 9, 1–17.
meta-ethics: Exploring objectivism. Cognition, 106, Leventhal, G. S. (1980). What should be done with equity
1139–1366. theory? New approaches to the study of fairness in
Graham, J. (2013). Mapping the moral maps: From alter- social relationships. In K. J. Gergen, M. S. Greenberg,
nate taxonomies to competing predictions. Personality & R. H. White (Eds.), Social exchange: Advances in
and Social Psychology Review, 17, 237–241. theory and research (pp. 27–55). New York, NY:
Graham, J., Haidt, J., Koleva, S., Motyl, M., Iyer, R., Plenum.
Wojcik, S., & Ditto, P. H. (2013). Moral foundations Lind, E. A., Kanfer, R., & Earley, P. C. (1990). Voice, con-
theory: The pragmatic validity of moral pluralism. trol, and procedural justice: Instrumental and nonin-
Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, 47, strumental concerns in fairness judgments. Journal of
55–130. Personality and Social Psychology, 59, 952.
Graham, J., Haidt, J., & Nosek, B. A. (2009). Liberals and Lind, E. A., & Tyler, T. R. (1988). The social psychology
conservatives rely on different sets of moral founda- of procedural fairness. New York, NY: Plenum.
tions. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, Mackie, J. L. (1977). Ethics: Inventing right and wrong.
96, 1029–1046. New York, NY: Penguin.
422 L.J. Skitka et al.

Marcus, G. (2004). The birth of the mind. New York, NY: protection model of justice reasoning. Personality and
Basic. Social Psychology Bulletin, 28, 588–597.
Morgan, G. S., Skitka, L. J., & Lytle, B. L. (2013). Skitka, L. J. (2003). Of different minds: An accessible
Universally and objectively true: Psychological foun- identity model of justice reasoning. Personality and
dations of moral conviction. Manuscript submitted for Social Psychology Review, 7, 286–297.
publication. Skitka, L. J., Aramovich, N., Lytle, B. L., & Sargis, E.
Nagata, D. K. (1990). The Japanese-American intern- (2009). Knitting together an elephant: An integrative
ment: Perceptions of moral community, fairness, and approach to understanding the psychology of justice
redress. Journal of Social Issues, 46(1), 133–146. reasoning. In D. R. Bobocel, A. C. Kay, M. P. Zanna,
Nagata, D. K. (1993). Moral exclusion and nonviolence: & J. M. Olson (Eds.), The psychology of justice and
The Japanese American Internment. In V. K. Kool legitimacy: The Ontario symposium (Vol. 11,
(Ed.), Nonviolence: Social and psychological issues pp. 1–26). Philadelphia, PA: Psychology Press.
(pp. 85–93). Lanham, MD: University Press of Skitka, L. J., Bauman, C. W., & Lytle, B. L. (2009). The
America. limits of legitimacy: Moral and religious convictions
Nucci, L. P., & Turiel, E. (1978). Social interactions and as constraints on deference to authority. Journal of
the development of social concepts in pre-school chil- Personality and Social Psychology, 97, 567–578.
dren. Child Development, 49, 400–407. Skitka, L. J., & Houston, D. (2001). When due process is
Opotow, S. (1990). Moral exclusion and injustice. Journal of no consequence: Moral mandates and presumed
of Social Issues, 46, 1–20. defendant guilt or innocence. Social Justice Research,
Opotow, S. (1994). Predicting protection: Scope of justice 14, 305–326.
and the natural world. Journal of Social Issues, 50, Skitka, L. J., & Mullen, E. (2002). Understanding judgments
49–63. of fairness in a real-world political context: A test of the
Opotow, S. (1995). Drawing the line: Social categoriza- value protection model of justice reasoning. Personality
tion, moral exclusion, and the scope of justice. In B.B. and Social Psychology Bulletin, 28, 1419–1429.
Bunker, J. Z. Rubin (Eds), Conflict, cooperation, and Skitka, L. J., & Wisneski, D. (2012). Justice theory and
justice: Essays inspired by the work of Morton research: A social functionalist perspective. In J. Suls
Deutsch, (pp. 347–369). San Francisco, CA, US: & H. Tennen (Eds.), The handbook of psychology (2nd
Jossey-Bass. ed., pp. 420–428). Hoboken, NJ: Wiley.
Piaget, J. (1997). The moral judgment of the child. New York, Smetana, J. G. (1981). Preschool children’s conceptions
NY: Free Press (Original work published 1932). of moral and social rules. Child Development, 52,
Rai, T. S., & Fiske, A. P. (2011). Moral psychology is rela- 1333–1336.
tionship regulation: Moral motives for unity, hierar- Smetana, J. G. (1984). Toddlers’ social interactions
chy, equality, and proportionality. Psychological regarding moral and conventional transgressions.
Review, 118, 57–75. Child Development, 55, 1767–1776.
Rest, J., Narvaez, D., Bebeau, M. J., & Thoma, S. J. (1999a). Smetana, J. G. (2006). Social-cognitive domain theory:
A neo-Kohlbergian approach: The DIT and schema Consistencies and variations in children’s moral and
theory. Educational Psychology Review, 11, 291–324. social judgments. In M. Millen & J. G. Smetana
Rest, J. R., Narvaez, D., Bebeau, M. J., & Thoma, S. J. (Eds.), Handbook of moral development (pp. 119–
(1999b). Postconventional moral thinking. A neo- 153). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
Kohlbergian approach. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Smith, M. (1994). The moral problem. Oxford: Blackwell.
Erlbaum. CedarEthics Online. Paper 36. Retrieved May 17,
Shweder, R. A., Much, N. C., Mahapatra, M., & Park, L. 2013 from http://digitalcommons.cedarville.edu/
(1997). The “big three” of morality (autonomy, com- cedar_ethics_online/36/
munity, and divinity), and the “big three” explanations Spencer, S., & Rupp, D. E. (2009). Angry, guilty, and con-
of suffering. In A. Brandt & P. Rozin (Eds.), Morality flicted: Injustice toward coworkers heightens emotional
and health (pp. 119–169). New York, NY: Routledge. labor through cognitive and emotional mechanisms.
Simpson, E. L. (1974). Moral development research: A Journal of Applied Psychology, 94, 429–444.
case of scientific cultural bias. Human Development, Staub, E. (1990). Moral exclusion, personal goal theory,
17, 81–106. and extreme destructiveness. Journal of Social Issues,
Singer, M. S. (1996). Effects of scope of justice, infor- 46, 47–64.
mant ethnicity, and information frame on attitudes Stouffer, S. A., Suchman, E. A., DeVinney, L. C., Star,
towards ethnicity-based selection. International S. A., & Williams, R. M., Jr. (1949). The American
Journal of Psychology, 31, 191–205. soldier: Adjustment during army life (Vol. 1).
Skarlicki, D., & Rupp, D. (2010). Dual processing and Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
organizational justice: The role of rational versus Sue, D., Bucceri, J., Lin, A. I., Nadal, K. L., & Torino,
experiential processing in third-party reactions to G. C. (2009). Racial microaggressions and the Asian
workplace mistreatment. Journal of Applied American experience. Asian American Journal of
Psychology, 95, 944–952. Psychology, 1, 88–101.
Skitka, L. J. (2002). Do the means always justify the ends Suhler, C. L., & Churchland, P. (2011). Can innate, modu-
or do the ends sometimes justify the means? A value lar “foundations” explain morality? Challenges for
22 Morality and Justice 423

Haidt’s moral foundations theory. Journal of Cognitive Tyler, T. R., & Lind, E. A. (1992). A relational model of
Neuroscience, 23, 2103–2116. authority in groups. In M. P. Zanna (Ed.), Advances in
Sullivan, E. V. (1977). Kohlberg’s structuralism: A criti- experimental social psychology (Vol. 25, pp. 115–
cal appraisal. Toronto, Ontario, Canada: Ontario 191). San Diego, CA: Academic.
Institute for Studies in Education. Umphress, E. E., Simmons, A. L., Folger, R., Ren, R., &
Tajfel, H., Billig, M. G., Bundy, R. P., & Flament, C. Bobocel, R. (2012). Observer reactions to interper-
(1971). Social categorization and intergroup behaviour. sonal injustice: The role of perpetrator intent and vic-
European Journal of Social Psychology, 1, 149–178. tim perception. Journal of Organizational Behavior,
Tetlock, P. E. (2002). Social functionalist frameworks for 34, 327–349.
judgment and choice: Intuitive politicians, theologians, van den Bos, K., Wilke, H. A. M., Lind, E. A., & Vermunt,
and prosecutors. Psychological Review, 109, 451–471. R. (1998). Evaluating outcomes by means of the fair
Turiel, E. (1983). The development of social knowledge: process effect: Evidence for different processes in fair-
Morality and convention. Cambridge, England: ness and satisfaction judgments. Journal of Personality
Cambridge University Press. and Social Psychology, 74, 1493–1503.
Turiel, E. (1998). The development of morality. In Walster, E., Walster, G. W., Berscheid, E., & Austin, W.
W. Damon (Ed.), Handbook of child psychology. (1978). Equity: Theory and research. Boston, MA:
Hoboken, NJ: Wiley. Allyn & Bacon.

You might also like