You are on page 1of 18

姝 Academy of Management Learning & Education, 2005, Vol. 4, No. 1, 75–91.

........................................................................................................................................................................

Bad Management Theories Are


Destroying Good Management
Practices
SUMANTRA GHOSHAL
Advanced Institute of Management Research (AIM), UK and London Business School

The corporate scandals in the United States have vested interests, which are dangerous for good or
stimulated a frenzy of activities in business evil” Keynes (1953: 306).
schools around the world. Deans are extolling how This is precisely what has happened to manage-
much their curricula focus on business ethics. New ment. Obsessed as they are with the “real world”
courses are being developed on corporate social and sceptical as most of them are of all theories,
responsibility. Old, highly laudatory cases on En- managers are no exception to the intellectual sla-
ron and Tyco are being hurriedly rewritten. “What very of the “practical men” to which Keynes re-
more must we do?”, the faculty are asking them- ferred. Many of the worst excesses of recent man-
selves in grave seminars and over lunch tables agement practices have their roots in a set of ideas
(Bartunek, 2002). that have emerged from business school academ-
Business schools do not need to do a great deal ics over the last 30 years.
more to help prevent future Enrons; they need only In courses on corporate governance grounded in
to stop doing a lot they currently do. They do not agency theory (Jensen & Meckling, 1976) we have
need to create new courses; they need to simply taught our students that managers cannot be
stop teaching some old ones. But, before doing any trusted to do their jobs—which, of course, is to
of this, we—as business school faculty—need to maximize shareholder value—and that to over-
own up to our own role in creating Enrons. Our come “agency problems,” managers’ interests and
theories and ideas have done much to strengthen incentives must be aligned with those of the share-
the management practices that we are all now so holders by, for example, making stock options a
loudly condemning. significant part of their pay. In courses on organi-
zation design, grounded in transaction cost eco-
Our theories and ideas have done much nomics, we have preached the need for tight mon-
to strengthen the management practices itoring and control of people to prevent
“opportunistic behavior” (Williamson, 1975). In
that we are all now so loudly
strategy courses, we have presented the “five
condemning. forces” framework (Porter, 1980) to suggest that
companies must compete not only with their com-
“The ideas of economists and political philoso- petitors but also with their suppliers, customers,
phers, both when they are right and when they are employees, and regulators.
wrong, are more powerful than is commonly under- MBA students are not alone in having learned,
stood,” wrote John Maynard Keynes (1953: 306). “In- for decades, these theories of management. Thou-
deed the world is run by little else. Practical men, sands—indeed, hundreds of thousands— of execu-
who believe themselves to be quite exempt from tives who attended business courses have learned
any intellectual influences are usually the slaves the same lessons, although the actual theories
of some defunct economist. . . . It is ideas, not were often not presented to them quite so directly.
Even those who never attended a business school
have learned to think in these ways because these
Editor’s Note. Sumantra Ghoshal died unexpectedly after draft- theories have been in the air, legitimizing some
ing this manuscript. Our gratitude belongs to his son, Ananda actions and behaviors of managers, delegitimizing
Ghoshal, his secretary, Sharon Wilson, and his student, Felipe
Monteiro, all of whom were instrumental in bringing this work
others, and generally shaping the intellectual and
to publication. For a more detailed account of the genesis of this normative order within which all day-to-day deci-
paper, see the From the Editor column. sions were made.
75
76 Academy of Management Learning & Education March

Why then do we feel surprised by the fact that practice of management. These influences have
executives in Enron, Global Crossing, Tyco, and been less at the level of adoption of a particular
scores of other companies granted themselves ex- theory and more at the incorporation, within the
cessive stock options, treated their employees very worldview of managers, of a set of ideas and as-
badly, and took their customers for a ride when sumptions that have come to dominate much of
they could? Besides, the criminal misconduct of management research. More specifically, I suggest
managers in a few companies is really not the that by propagating ideologically inspired amoral
critical issue. Of far greater concern is the general theories, business schools have actively freed their
delegitimization of companies as institutions and students from any sense of moral responsibility.
of management as a profession (The Economist:
25–31 October, 2003) caused, at least in part, by the
adoption of these ideas as taken-for-granted ele- By propagating ideologically inspired
ments of management practice. amoral theories, business schools have
Several scholars have recently voiced their con- actively freed their students from any
cerns about the current state of management re- sense of moral responsibility.
search and pedagogy (e.g., Porter & McKibbin,
1988; Leavitt, 1989; Hambrick, 1994; Mintzberg &
Gosling, 2002; Donaldson, 2002; Pfeffer & Fong, Figure 1 provides a roadmap of the arguments
2002). In the main, their arguments have focused on that follow. As has been extensively documented
the lack of impact of management research on in the literature (e.g., Friga, Bettis, & Sullivan,
management practice and the lack of effectiveness 2003), over the last 50 years business school re-
of management education for business perfor- search has increasingly adopted the “scientific”
mance of students. model—an approach that Hayek (1989) described
In this article, I raise a very different concern: I as “the pretense of knowledge.” This pretense has
argue that academic research related to the con- demanded theorizing based on partialization of
duct of business and management has had some analysis, the exclusion of any role for human in-
very significant and negative influences on the tentionality or choice, and the use of sharp as-

FIGURE 1
The Process of Bad Theories Destroying Good Practice
2005 Ghoshal 77

sumptions and deductive reasoning (Bailey & Ford, THE PRETENSE OF KNOWLEDGE
1996). Since morality, or ethics, is inseparable from
Our primary endeavor as business school academ-
human intentionality, a precondition for making
ics over the last half century has been to make
business studies a science has been the denial of
business studies a branch of the social sciences
any moral or ethical considerations in our theories
(Schlossman, Sedlak, & Wechsler, 1998). Rejecting
and, therefore, in our prescriptions for manage-
what we saw as the “romanticism” of analyzing
ment practice.
corporate behaviors in terms of the choices, ac-
At the same time, a particular ideology has in-
tions, and achievements of individuals (e.g., An-
creasingly penetrated most of the disciplines in
drews, 1980), we have adopted the “scientific” ap-
which management theories are rooted. Described
by Milton Friedman (2002) as “liberalism,” this ide- proach of trying to discover patterns and laws, and
ology is essentially grounded in a set of pessimis- have replaced all notions of human intentionality
tic assumptions about both individuals and insti- with a firm belief in causal determinism for ex-
tutions—a “gloomy vision” (Hirschman, 1970) that plaining all aspects of corporate performance. In
views the primary purpose of social theory as one effect, we have professed that business is reduc-
of solving the “negative problem” of restricting the ible to a kind of physics in which even if individual
social costs arising from human imperfections. managers do play a role, it can safely be taken as
Combined with the pretense of knowledge, this determined by the economic, social, and psycho-
ideology has led management research increas- logical laws that inevitably shape peoples’ ac-
ingly in the direction of making excessive truth- tions. Legitimized by a set of influential reports
claims based on partial analysis and both unreal- (such as Gordon & Howell, 1959) and supported by
istic and biased assumptions. significant investments by, among others, the Ford
All of this would still not lead to any negative Foundation (about $250 million, in 2003 dollars),
consequences for management practice but for the these beliefs have become dominant in business
distinctive feature of double hermeneutic that schools in the United States and around the world
characterizes the link between theory and practice (Clegg & Ross-Smith, 2003).
in social domains. Unlike theories in the physical Adoption of scientific methods has undoubtedly
sciences, theories in the social sciences tend to be yielded some significant benefits for both our re-
self-fulfilling (Gergen, 1973). search and our pedagogy, but the costs too have
A theory of subatomic particles or of the uni- been high. Unfortunately, as philosophy of science
verse—right or wrong— does not change the be- makes clear, it is an error to pretend that the methods
haviors of those particles or of the universe. If a of the physical sciences can be indiscriminately ap-
theory assumes that the sun goes round the earth, plied to business studies because such a pretension
it does not change what the sun actually does. So, ignores some fundamental differences that exist be-
if the theory is wrong, the truth is preserved for tween the different academic disciplines.
discovery by someone else. In contrast, a manage- Figure 2, reproduced from Elster (1983), provides
ment theory—if it gains sufficient currency— one way of understanding these differences. As
changes the behaviors of managers who start act- Elster argued, from the perspective of philosophy
ing in accordance with the theory. A theory that of science, one must first distinguish between the
assumes that people can behave opportunistically natural sciences and the humanities. Within the
and draws its conclusions for managing people natural sciences, there is a need to distinguish the
based on that assumption can induce managerial study of inorganic nature, such as physics, and the
actions that are likely to enhance opportunistic study of organic nature, such as biology. Within
behavior among people (Ghoshal & Moran, 1996). A the humanities, similarly, a distinction needs to be
theory that draws prescriptions on corporate gov- made between the social sciences, such as eco-
ernance on the assumption that managers cannot nomics and psychology, and aesthetic disciplines,
be trusted can make managers less trustworthy such as art. Eschewing for the moment the argu-
(Osterloh & Frey, 2003). Whether right or wrong to ments of those who would classify management as a
begin with, the theory can become right as man- practicing art (e.g., Eccles & Nohria, 1992), let us ac-
agers—who are both its subjects and the consum- cept the more common view and consider manage-
ers—adapt their behaviors to conform with the ment-related theories as part of the social sciences.
doctrine. As I will demonstrate here, this is pre- His interests limited to the academic concerns of
cisely what has happened to management practice scholarship, Elster argued that the fundamental
over the last several decades, converting our col- difference between these different fields lies nei-
lective pessimism about managers into realized ther in the method of inquiry nor in the interests
pathologies in management behaviors. they serve; it lies instead in the mode of explana-
78 Academy of Management Learning & Education March

FIGURE 2
The Different Modes of Explanation for the Different Sciences.
Note. From Explaining Technical Change, by J. Elster, 1983, Cambridge, England: Cambridge University
Press. Adapted with permission.

tion and theorizing that is appropriate for each. action guided by some intention. In the presence of
Categorizing such modes as causal, functional, such intentionality, functional theories are sus-
and intentional, Elster demonstrated why for the pect, except under some special and relatively rare
sciences of inorganic matter, such as physics, the circumstances, because there is no general law in
only acceptable mode of explanation is the causal the social sciences comparable to the law of natu-
mode. Functional explanations, based on notions ral selection in biology. As Elster explained, inten-
such as benefits, evolution, or progress have no tional adaptation differs from functional adapta-
role in physics, nor is there any room for inten- tion
tional or teleological explanations, such as those
based on some notion of actor imagination or will. in that the former can be directed to the dis-
Functional explanations, however, play an im- tant future, whereas the latter is typically my-
portant role in the sciences of organic matter, such opic and opportunistic. Intentional beings
as biology. All one has to do to explain a particular can employ such strategies as “one step back-
feature of an organism, or some aspect of its be- ward, two steps forward,” which are realized
havior, is to demonstrate that the feature or behav- only by accident in biological evolution (1983:
ior enhances its reproductive fitness. The reason 36).
such functional explanations are adequate, how-
ever, lies in the availability of an overarching There is, of course, a role for causal theories in
causal theory: that of natural selection. There is no the social sciences, but it is a relatively limited
role of intentionality within biology because the one, suitable, for example, for the analysis of phe-
process of evolution is driven by random error or nomena involving the interplay among a very
mutation, over which the sources of variation or large number of diverse actors (e.g., capital mar-
the units of selection have no influence. kets), where the intentions of individual actors can
The basic building block in the social sciences, be ignored (similar to the analytical underpin-
the elementary unit of explanation, is individual nings of statistical quantum mechanics that does
2005 Ghoshal 79

not intend to explain the outcomes for individual face of external forces, it is to the dehumanization
particles but makes statistical estimates of aggre- of practice that they resort. When they claim that
gate outcomes). However, for a vast range of issues competition or capital markets are relentless in
relevant to the study of management, such condi- their demands, and that individual companies and
tions are not attained. For these issues, human managers have no scope for choices, it is on the
intentions matter. And, intentions are mental strength of the false premise of determinism that
states; so to say that a particular action of an they free themselves from any sense of moral or
individual was caused by a particular intention is ethical responsibility for their actions.
not a causal explanation. To quote Elster, “using It is not only morality, however, that has been a
causal explanation, we can talk about all there is, victim of this endeavor of business academics to
including mental phenomena, but we shall not be make management a science; common sense, too,
able to single out mental phenomena from what has suffered a toll. It is to this cost of losing the
else there is” (1983). wisdom of common sense that Donald Campbell
Management theories at present are overwhelm- (1988) referred when he provided numerous exam-
ingly causal or functional in their modes of expla- ples of how the application of social theories had
nation. Ethics, or morality, however, are mental led to poor public policy decisions in the United
phenomena. As a result, they have had to be ex- States. As he wrote, referring to the application of
cluded from our theory, and from the practices that scientific methods for the assessment of public
such theories have shaped. In other words, a pre- programs, “if we present our resulting improved
condition for making business studies a science as truth-claims as though they were definitive
well as a consequence of the resulting belief in achievements comparable to those in the physical
determinism has been the explicit denial of any sciences, and thus deserving to override ordinary
role of moral or ethical considerations in the prac- wisdom when they disagree, we can be socially
tice of management. No one has voiced this denial destructive.”
more strongly than Milton Friedman: “Few trends Friedrich von Hayek dedicated his entire Nobel
could so thoroughly undermine the very founda- Memorial Lecture to the danger posed by scientific
tions of our free society as the acceptance by cor- pretensions in the analysis of social phenomena.
porate officials of a social responsibility other than Speaking as an economist and acknowledging
to make as much money for their stockholders as that “as a profession we have made a mess of
possible” (2002: 133). things,” he placed the blame on “the pretense of
To both the managers and the management ac- knowledge,” which is how he titled his talk (1989:
ademics who profess these beliefs, I refer the 3–7). “It seems to me that this failure of economists
words of Isiah Berlin: “One may argue about the to guide public policy more successfully is clearly
degree of difference that the influence of this or connected with their propensity to imitate as
that individual made in shaping events. But to try closely as possible the procedures of the brilliantly
to reduce the behaviours of individuals to that of successful physical sciences,” said Hayek. Be-
impersonal social forces not further analyzable cause of the very nature of social phenomena,
into the conduct of men who. . . make history. . . is a which Hayek described as “phenomena of orga-
form of false consciousness of bureaucrats and nized complexity,” the application of scientific
administrators who close their eyes to all that methods to such phenomena “are often the most
proves incapable of quantification, and thereby unscientific, and, beyond this, in these fields there
perpetrate absurdities in theory and dehumanisa- are definite limits to what we can expect science to
tion in practice” (2002: 26). achieve.”
When Richard Posner claims that justice is im- As an example of how this pretense of science
portant only because it leads to the avoidance of affects management practice, consider the dictum
waste, he perpetrates absurdities in theory, as in- of Milton Friedman that few managers today can
deed pointed out by Todd Buchholtz (1999) when he publicly question, that their job is to maximize
described that claim as a “dim observation by a shareholder value. Where did the enormous cer-
brilliant man” (p. 199). When Gary Becker (1993) tainty that this assertion seems to carry come
asserts that theft is harmful only because it dimin- from?
ishes productivity, he closes his eyes to all that After all, we know that shareholders do not own
proves incapable of quantification and falls victim the company—not in the sense that they own their
to the “false consciousness” to which Isiah Berlin homes or their cars. They merely own a right to the
refers. residual cash flows of the company, which is not at
Similarly, when managers, including CEOs, jus- all the same thing as owning the company. They
tify their actions by pleading powerlessness in the have no ownership rights on the actual assets or
80 Academy of Management Learning & Education March

businesses of the company, which are owned by contributions of capital by shareholders, a pure
the company itself, as a “legal person.” Indeed, it is commodity that is perhaps in excess supply
this fundamental separation between ownership (Quinn, 1992). As Grossman and Hart (1986)
of stocks and ownership of the assets, resources, showed, once we admit incomplete contracts, re-
and the associated liabilities of a company that sidual rights of control are optimally held by the
distinguishes public corporations from proprietor- party whose investments matter more in terms of
ships or partnerships. The notion of actual owner- creating value. If these truths are acknowledged,
ship of the company is simply not compatible with there can be no basis for asserting the principle of
the responsibility avoidance of “limited liability.” shareholder value maximization. There just aren’t
We also know that the value a company creates any supporting arguments.
is produced through a combination of resources
contributed by different constituencies: Employ-
ees, including managers, contribute their human The truth is, of course, exactly the
capital, for example, while shareholders contrib- opposite. Most shareholders can sell their
ute financial capital. If the value creation is stocks far more easily than most
achieved by combining the resources of both em- employees can find another job.
ployees and shareholders, why should the value
distribution favor only the latter? Why must the
mainstream of our theory be premised on maximiz- Once again, Milton Friedman (1953) has pro-
ing the returns to just one of these various contrib- vided a compelling counterargument: Don’t worry
utors? if the assumptions of our theories do not reflect
The answer—the only answer that is really val- reality; what matters is that these theories can
id—is that this assumption helps in structuring accurately predict the outcomes. The theories are
and solving nice mathematical models. Casting valid because of their explanatory and predictive
shareholders in the role of “principals” who are power, irrespective of how absurd the assumptions
equivalent to owners or proprietors, and managers may look from the perspective of common sense.
as “agents” who are self-centered and are only What is interesting is that agency theory, which
interested in using company resources to their own underlies the entire intellectual edifice in support
advantage is justified simply because, with this of shareholder value maximization, has little ex-
assumption, the elegant mathematics of principal– planatory or predictive power. Its solution to the
agent models can be applied to the enormously agency model yields some relatively straightfor-
complex economic, social, and moral issues re- ward prescriptions: Expand the number and influ-
lated to the governance of giant public corpora- ence of independent directors on corporate boards
tions that have such enormous influence on the so that they can effectively police management;
lives of thousands— often millions— of people. split the roles of the chairman of the board and the
But then, to make the model yield a solution, chief executive officer so as to reduce the power of
some more assumptions have to be made. So, the the latter; create markets for corporate control, that
theory assumes that labor markets are perfectly is, for hostile takeovers, so that raiders can get rid
efficient—in other words, the wages of every em- of wasteful managers; and pay managers in stock
ployee fully represent the value of his or her con- options to ensure that they relentlessly pursue the
tributions to the company and, if they didn’t, the interests of the shareholders. The facts are that
employee could immediately and costlessly move none of these factors have the predicted effects on
to another job. With this assumption, the share- corporate performance.
holders can be assumed as carrying the greater A review of 54 studies on the performance effects
risk, thus making their contribution of capital more of board composition shows that the proportion of
important than the contribution of human capital independent directors on the board has no signif-
provided by managers and other employees and, icant effect on corporate performance. A similar
therefore, it is their returns that must be maxi- review of 31 studies on the effects of separating
mized (Jensen & Meckling, 1976). leadership roles demonstrates that whether the
The truth is, of course, exactly the opposite. Most same or different individuals occupy the positions
shareholders can sell their stocks far more easily of chairman and CEO does not affect corporate
than most employees can find another job. In every performance in any way. These studies cover com-
substantive sense, employees of a company carry panies based in different countries, and the con-
more risks than do the shareholders. Also, their clusions are valid irrespective of whether perfor-
contributions of knowledge, skills, and entrepre- mance is assessed in terms of market value of the
neurship are typically more important than the company or accounting measures, such as return
2005 Ghoshal 81

on capital employed (Dalton, Daily, Ellstrand, &


Johnson, 1998). Why do we not fundamentally rethink
Empirical evidence on the effects of a market for the corporate governance issue?
corporate control is highly ambiguous. And even
Michael Jensen, the proponent of the theory, has
been forced to admit that stock options have not The honest answer is because such a perspec-
worked quite the same way as he had hoped (The tive cannot be elegantly modeled—the math does
Economist, November 16, 2002: 66). not exist. Such a theory would not readily yield
Unrealistic assumptions and invalid prescrip- sharp, testable propositions, nor would it provide
tions—yet, the theory and the dictum it leads to simple, reductionist prescriptions. With such a
remain absolute. As Margaret Blair (1995) has premise, the pretense of knowledge could not be
shown, it is this theory, amplified by the power of protected. Business could not be treated as a sci-
institutional investors and their political and aca- ence, and we would have to fall back on the wis-
demic supporters, that influenced both regulatory dom of common sense that combines information
changes and court decisions in the United States, on “what is” with the imagination of “what ought
ultimately yielding to the argument a level of le- to be” to develop both a practical understanding of
gitimacy and certainty that few managers or aca- and some pragmatic prescriptions for “phenomena
demics now dare question. At the same time, as of organized complexity” that the issue of corpo-
Thomas Kochan has observed, the root cause of the rate governance represents.
recent corporate scandals in the United States lies This too is scholarship, but it yields theory that
in this “over-emphasis American corporations does not pretend to be scientific laws but merely
have been forced to give in recent years to maxi- serves as temporary “walking sticks”—in Fritz Ro-
mizing shareholder value without regard for the ethlisberger’s (1977) terms—to aid sense making as
effects of their actions on other stakeholders” (2002: we go along, to be used only until a better walking
139). stick can be found. And, if the association of schol-
What is most curious is that despite the lack of arship with common sense seems like an oxymo-
both face validity and empirical support, agency ron, it is only because of the extremely restrictive
theory continues to dominate academic research definition of the term scholarship that the pretense
on corporate governance (Daily, Dalton, & Can- of knowledge has straight-jacketed us into.
nella, 2003). At the same time, despite the aberra- In describing himself and his work, Sigmund
tions that have occurred in companies that fully Freud wrote: “[Y]ou often estimate me too highly. I
conformed to the prescriptions of this theory—such am not really a man of science, not an experi-
as in Enron that had loaded its board with many menter, and not a thinker. I am nothing but by
(80%) high-profile independent directors who temperament a conquistador—an adventurer, if
chaired most key committees, separated the chair- you want to translate the term—with the curiosity,
man and chief executive roles, granted generous the boldness, and the tenacity that belong to that
stock options to its senior managers, and operated type of being” (In Jones, 1964: 171).
in the economy with the most advanced market for Freud’s inductive and iterative approach to
corporate control—all regulatory reviews of corpo- sense making, often criticized for being ad hoc and
rate governance, such as by the SEC in the United unscientific, was scholarship of common sense. So
States, by Derek Higgs in the United Kingdom, and indeed was Darwin’s, who too practiced a model of
by the Narayanamurthy Committee in India, are research as the work of a detective, not of an ex-
relying even more strongly on rigorous implemen- perimenter, who was driven by the passions of an
tation of the same discredited prescriptions! adventurer, not those of a mathematician. Scholar-
Why do we not fundamentally rethink the corpo- ship of common sense is the epistemology of dis-
rate governance issue? Why don’t we actually ac- ciplined imagination, as advocated by Karl Weick
knowledge in our theories that companies survive (1989), and not the epistemology of formalized fal-
and prosper when they simultaneously pay atten- sification that was the doctrine of Karl Popper
tion to the interests of customers, employees, (1968).
shareholders, and perhaps even the communities To protect the pretense of knowledge, we have
in which they operate? Such a perspective is avail- created conditions under which this kind of schol-
able, in stewardship theory for example (Davis, arship can no longer flourish in our community.
Schoorman, & Donaldson, 1997); why then do we so This is true of all social science disciplines but,
overwhelmingly adopt the agency model in our curiously, perhaps it is most intensely true in busi-
research on corporate governance, ignoring this ness schools where, in our desire for respect from
much more sensible proposition? scholars in other fields, we have become even
82 Academy of Management Learning & Education March

more intolerant of the scholarship of common simistic view of human nature, on the role of
sense than those whose respect we seek (Bailey & companies in society, and of the processes of cor-
Ford, 1996). “We ask the reader to consider whether porate adaptation and change. These negative as-
the evidence provided by people such as Freud, sumptions are manifest in the strong form of deter-
Marx or Darwin would meet the empirical stan- minism in both ecological (e.g., Hannan &
dards of the top journals in organizational re- Freeman, 1977) and institutional (e.g., DiMaggio &
search,” asked Robert Sutton and Barry Staw (1995: Powell, 1983) analysis of organizations; in the de-
371–384). In the same vein one can ask, “Would the nial of the possibility of purposeful and goal-
arguments of a Hayek, a McGregor, or a Barnard directed adaptation in behavioral theories of the
meet the standards by which these journals eval- firm (e.g., Cyert & March, 1963); in the focus on
uate theory?” value appropriation rather than value creation in
In his book Scholarship Reconsidered, Ernest most theories of strategy (e.g., Porter, 1980); and in
Boyer (1990) described four different kinds of schol- the assumptions about shirking, opportunism, and
arship: the scholarship of discovery (research), the inertia in economic analysis of companies (e.g.,
scholarship of integration (synthesis), the scholar- Alchian & Demsetz, 1972; Williamson, 1975).
ship of practice (application), and the scholarship In his article “The Search for Paradigms as a
of teaching (pedagogy). Historically, business Hindrance to Understanding,” Albert Hirschman
schools have celebrated and accommodated as (1970) has traced the source of this pessimism to
equals the practitioners of all four kinds of schol- what he calls a “paradigm-based gloomy vision”
arship. Over the last 30 years, we have lost this that, as the title of his article suggests, he views as
taste for pluralism. What started off as an entirely a critical barrier to developing effective under-
justified effort for introducing the scholarship of standing of complex social phenomena. Based es-
discovery to the study of business has ended up in sentially on an ideology, this gloomy vision is
the excess of eliminating all other forms of schol- deeply embedded within the theories as starting
arship from the world of business schools. Those assumptions—which, therefore, are exempt from
with primary interests in synthesis, application, or the need for conforming either to common sense or
pedagogy have been eliminated from our milieu to empirical evidence—and it is these pessimistic
or, at best, accommodated at the periphery and assumptions which have, through the self-fulfill-
insulated from the academic high table that is now ing process we have described, curbed managers’
reserved only for the scientists. ability to play out a more positive role in society.
What would happen if we reversed this trend so Consider, for example, the assumptions regard-
as to provide some space to these people? They ing human nature. As Herbert Simon observed,
exist— often outside the academic mainstream— “Nothing is more fundamental in setting our re-
and it is on their work that we primarily rely for search agenda and informing our research meth-
meeting our teaching demands. What if we in- ods than our view of the nature of human beings
cluded them again in the mainstream, as equal whose behaviours we are studying. . . It makes a
members—judging them not on their scientific cre- difference to research, but it also makes a differ-
dentials but on their practical knowledge? What if ence for the proper design of . . . institutions” (1985:
in acknowledgment of the “research benefit to gen- 293).
eralists and generalism” (Pfeffer & Fong, 2002: 88), Mainstream economics has, in the main, always
we granted the generalists tenure, allowed them to worked on the assumption of Homo Economicus—a
groom others like them, and to interact with the model of people as rational self-interest maximiz-
scientists at the high table? It would compromise ers. Although recently, primarily in the field of
the pretense of knowledge, but would it not create behavioral economics, attention has been paid to
a richer environment for knowledge creation? systematic deviations from rationality in human
Would it not help us weed out each other’s absur- behavior, such attention has largely been limited
dities in theory and, thereby, reduce the chances of to “foolishness” and not to any aspect of other-
dehumanization of practice? than-self-interested preferences of individuals
(e.g., Kahneman, Slovic, & Tversky, 1982).
Even practitioners of sociology and psychology,
IDEOLOGY-BASED GLOOMY VISION
the starting points of which as academic fields
Currently influential theories of business and were defined by the recognition that human be-
management span diverse academic disciplines havior can be shaped by factors other than con-
including psychology, sociology, and, of course— scious, rational self-interest, have increasingly
preeminent of all— economics. Collectively, how- adopted the notion of behavior as being self-seek-
ever, they have increasingly converged on a pes- ing as their foundational assumption. Friendship
2005 Ghoshal 83

ties of people are now analyzed by sociologists as “self-regarding preferences concern the individu-
means for individuals to use social networks to al’s own consumption and other outcomes, other-
enhance their personal influence, power, or pay regarding preferences concern the consumption
(e.g., Burt, 1997). And social psychologists increas- and outcomes of others, and process-regarding
ingly resort to the same assumption about human preferences concern the manner in which the indi-
nature when studying how people interact with vidual in question and others behave, including
others (e.g., Homans, 1961; Thibaut & Kelley, 1959). the ways in which they attain outcomes of interest”
Common sense has, of course, always recog- (p. 7). Also, these preferences do not stand in a
nized that human behavior can be influenced by hierarchy but represent independent human
other motives. Increasingly, empirical evidence needs. As Amartya Sen notes, “in acknowledging
provides overwhelming support to what common the possibility of prudential explanation of appar-
sense suggests. It is not only in behaviors such as ently moral conduct, we should not fall into the
mothers taking care of their children, people leav- trap of presuming that the assumption of pure self-
ing a tip after a meal in restaurants they are un- interest is, in any sense, more elementary than
likely to visit again, or Peace Corps volunteers assuming other values. Moral or social concerns
toiling amid the depravations of impoverished can be just as basic or elementary” (1998: xii).
countries that the limitations of the self-interest James Q. Wilson (1993) goes even further: “On bal-
model become clear—they become manifest even ance, I think other-regarding features of human
in careful experiments devised by economists to nature outweigh the self-regarding ones.”
test their theories under controlled conditions in If both common sense and empirical evidence
which “aberrations,” such as altruism or love are suggest the contrary, why does the pessimistic
strictly excluded. model of people as purely self-interested beings
Consider, for example, the “ultimatum game” in still so dominate management-related theories?
which one player, designated as the proposer, is The answer lies not in evidence but in ideology.
given the opportunity to propose a division of a Theories of social phenomena are, and have to be,
certain sum—a gift— between herself and another ideologically motivated. Despite the pretense to be
player, designated as the responder. If the re- values-free, no social theory can be values-free.
sponder accepts the proposal, the sum is divided And, while no social science discipline makes a
as proposed. If he rejects the proposal, neither stronger claim to objectivity than economics, no
player receives anything. In any variant of the domain of the social sciences is more values-laden
self-interest-based model of human behavior, the in both its assumptions and its language than eco-
proposer ought to offer only a token sum to the nomics and all its derivatives, including much of
responder, keeping the bulk of the amount for her- modern finance and management theories (Frank-
self, and the responder ought to accept the pro- furter & McGoun, 1999). As Robert Nelson (2001) has
posal, since even a token sum is more than noth- observed, “[t]he closest predecessors for the cur-
ing, which is the only alternative available to him. rent members of the economics profession are not
Much to the dismay of all ardent supporters of scientists such as Albert Einstein or Issac Newton;
the Homo Economicus model, including those who rather, we economists are more truly the heirs of
have proposed some relatively more sophisticated Thomas Acquinas and Martin Luther.”
versions of the model (e.g., Jensen & Meckling, But what is the connection between ideology and
1994), this outcome almost never materializes in pessimism? Why is the ideology pessimistic?
experiments (Camerer & Thaler, 1995). Token offers Again, Milton Friedman (2002) has provided the
are rarely made, and even more rarely accepted. most honest and direct answer. He labeled the
Often proposers offer a 60:40 division, taking ad- ideology as “liberalism,” cautioning at the same
vantage of their position as first mover, but not time, however, that his use of the term referred not
exploiting that advantage fully because of their to its corrupted association with concepts such as
concerns for the responder. Most frequently, how- social welfare or equality, but to its earlier empha-
ever, they propose a 50:50 split, out of a notion of sis on “freedom as the ultimate goal and the indi-
fairness, which suggests that windfalls, that is, vidual as the ultimate entity in the society.” He
gains not merited through contributions but by also recognized that the ideology was more com-
chance, should be distributed equally among monly referred to as “conservatism,” but he pre-
those involved in the event. ferred “liberalism” because it sounded more “rad-
In other words, people have preferences that, in ical” (p. 6).
the language of Avner Ben-Ner and Louis Putter- At the heart of this ideology lies two convictions.
man (1998), can be classified as self-regarding, other- First, in Friedman’s words, “a major aim of the
regarding, and process-regarding. As they wrote, liberal is to leave the ethical problem for the indi-
84 Academy of Management Learning & Education March

vidual to wrestle with.” In other words, it can and, ence on management research has been largely
indeed, must be excluded from social theory. The mediated by the University of Chicago. It is in and
way to do so is to base all theories on the assump- through this institution that “liberalism,” as Fried-
tion of homogeneous human behavior based on man called it, has penetrated economics, law, so-
self-interest. And, second, “the liberal conceives of ciology, social psychology and most other core dis-
men as imperfect beings . . . and regards the prob- ciplines, yielding theories such as agency theory,
lem of social organization to be as much a nega- transaction cost economics, game theory, social
tive problem of preventing bad people from doing network analysis, theories of social dilemmas, and
harm as of enabling good people to do good. . .” (p. so on, that we now routinely draw on both, radical
12). And, given that much of social science until individualism and Friedman’s liberalism, to frame
then had focused on the second part of the prob- our research and to guide our teaching.
lem, the agenda of social scientists thereon, that is, In their analysis of the development of manage-
for the last 40 years has focused on the first part, ment theory in terms of what they described as the
that is, the “negative problem.” Hence the pessi- “fact-value antinomy,” Eastman and Bailey (1998)
mism, the ideology-based gloomy vision. have identified the rise of value-partisan ap-
Jeffrey Pfeffer (1993), among others, has criticized proaches in theory in the late 20th century. While
management scholars for proliferating theories in- they correctly identified the polarization of theory
stead of seeking consensus on a particular para- around different sets of values, they perhaps un-
digm. He is right about the proliferation of diverse derestimated the extent to which the “Chicago
theories, but wrong in assuming that a dominant agenda” has gradually crept into all the different
paradigm is not emerging. While within individual disciplines—an observation that has also been
fields, such as organization theory or strategic made by Donaldson (1990). Nietzche distinguished
management, authors can and do publish research between scholars and scholarly laborers; increas-
grounded in very different assumptions and tradi- ingly most of us serve the latter role, carrying the
tions, Friedman’s version of liberalism has indeed ideology-based gloomy vision from field to field,
been colonizing all the management-related disci- and from applied area to applied area.
plines over the last half century (see Fig. 3). Combine ideology-based gloomy vision with the
The roots of the ideology lie in the philosophy of process of self-fulfilling prophecy and it is easy to
radical individualism articulated, among others, see how theories can induce some of the manage-
by Hume, Bentham, and Locke (Berlin, 2002). While ment behaviors and their associated problems we
the philosophy has influenced the work of many have witnessed. Consider, for example, the case of
scholars in many different institutions, its influ- transaction cost economics to which I referred at

FIGURE 3
The Creeping Spread of an Ideology in Management-Related Theories
2005 Ghoshal 85

the beginning of this article. Oliver Williamson Surveillants come to distrust their targets as a
(1975), the most ardent champion of this theory, result of their own surveillance and targets in
started from the Friedman position: Some people fact become unmotivated and untrustworthy.
are opportunistic—not just self-interested, but The target is now demonstrably untrustwor-
worse. They make promises knowing full well that, thy and requires more intensive surveillance,
should the benefits from breaking them exceed the and the increased surveillance further dam-
costs, they would do so in an instant. They lie and ages the target. Trust and trustworthiness both
cheat. While most people may not be like that, some deteriorate.
are, and it is not possible to separate, ex-ante, those
who are from those who are not. The “negative prob- Combine agency theory with transaction costs
lem” this theory then focuses on is how organizations economics, add in standard versions of game the-
need to be managed so as to prevent these “bad” ory and negotiation analysis, and the picture of the
people from doing harm to others. manager that emerges is one that is now very
What follows from the theory is quite straightfor- familiar in practice: the ruthlessly hard-driving,
ward. The manager’s task is to use hierarchical strictly top-down, command-and-control focused,
authority to prevent the opportunists from benefit- shareholder-value-obsessed, win-at-any-cost busi-
ing at the cost of others. To ensure effective coor- ness leader of which Scott Paper’s “Chainsaw” Al
dination, managers must know what everyone Dunlap and Tyco’s Dennis Kozlowski are only the
ought to be doing, give them strict instructions to most extreme examples. This is what Isaiah Berlin
do those things, and use their ability to monitor implied when he wrote about absurdities in theory
and control and to reward and punish to ensure leading to dehumanization of practice.
that everyone does what he or she is told to do. “As there is a degree of depravity in mankind
This is the exercise of “fiat.” which requires a certain degree of circumspection
and distrust, so there are other qualities in human
What is the outcome of such a management ap-
nature which justify a certain portion of esteem
proach? It is likely to be—and there is significant
and confidence,” wrote James Madison in the Fed-
evidence that it indeed is— exactly the opposite of
eralist Papers (No. 55). What would happen if we
what Williamson’s theory predicts: Instead of con-
acknowledged this complexity of human nature in
trolling and reducing opportunistic behavior of
our theories, this combination of good and evil,
people, it is likely to actually create and enhance
instead of focusing only on Friedman’s “negative
such behaviors (Ghoshal & Moran, 1996).
problem”? What would happen if we acknowl-
For managers, the net consequence of adopting
edged the existence of other and process-regard-
Williamson’s advice is what Strickland (1958) has ing preferences, together with the self-regarding
described as “the dilemma of the supervisor”: The ones, in our assumptions about human nature? It
situation when the use of surveillance, monitoring, would vastly change our theory.
and authority leads to management’s distrust of The good news is that the endeavor appears to
employees and perception of an increased need for have already commenced. In the field of psychol-
more surveillance and control. Because all behav- ogy, Martin Seligman—in his capacity as the pres-
ior is seen by managers as motivated by the con- ident of the American Psychological Association in
trols in place, they develop a jaundiced view of 1998 —sponsored a new initiative that he referred
their people. to as positive psychology. Seligman argued that
For the employees, the use of hierarchical con- since World War II, research in psychology had
trols signals that they are neither trusted nor trust- been grounded in what he described as “a disease
worthy to behave appropriately without such con- model of human nature.” Human beings were seen
trols. Surveillance that is perceived as controlling as “flawed and fragile, casualties of cruel environ-
threatens peoples’ personal sense of autonomy ments or bad genetics, and if not in denial then at
and decreases their intrinsic motivation. It dam- best in recovery.” Indeed, for psychologists, any-
ages their self-perception. One of the likely conse- thing positive about people— hope, optimism, al-
quences of eroding attitudes is a shift from con- truism, courage, joy, and fulfillment— had become
summate and voluntary cooperation to perfunctory suspect. While this focus on pathologies had pro-
compliance. duced important progress in understanding, treat-
The outcome of these negative feelings of both ing, and preventing psychological discords, Selig-
managers and employees is a pathological spiral- man argued that the progress had come at some
ing relationship, which has been described by psy- significant costs. It neglected human strengths
chologists Michael Enzle and Samuel Anderson and ignored what could go right with people
(1993) as follows: (Peterson & Seligman, 2003).
86 Academy of Management Learning & Education March

Positive psychology, as framed by Seligman and thing, the dominance is becoming stronger as the
his associates, proposes that it is time to correct intellectual influence of the “Chicago agenda” is
this imbalance and to challenge the pervasive as- spreading to all the main areas of business school
sumptions of the disease model. “Positive psychol- research. The positive perspective will not
ogy calls for as much focus on strength as on weak- progress unless many scholars, including younger
ness, as much interest in building the best things scholars, redirect their work, at considerable risk
in life as in repairing the worst, and as much to their careers. For them to take such risks, much
attention to fulfilling the lives of healthy people as has to be done by many so as to reverse the overall
to healing the wounds of the distressed.” trend of the last 50 years.
In the field of economics, too, such an endeavor
appears to be in progress as evidenced, for exam-
REVERSING THE TREND
ple, by the Conference on Economics, Values and
Organization that took place at Yale University in Kurt Lewin argued that “nothing is as practical as
April, 1996. The collected volume of conference pa- a good theory” (1945: 129). The obverse is also true:
pers, together with a foreword by Amartya Sen and Nothing is as dangerous as a bad theory. I have so
an epilogue by Douglass North, explores “the two- far developed the proposition that bad manage-
way interaction between economic arrangements ment theories are, at present, destroying good
or institutions and preferences, including those re- management practices. I have traced the source of
garding social status, the well-being of others, and the “badness” to two trends that have powerfully
ethical principles” (Ben-Ner & Putterman, 1998). As influenced the nature of business school-based re-
the volume editors argue, the time has arrived search over several decades. On the one hand,
“when the questions of values and institutions can what Clegg and Ross-Smith (2003) have described
begin to be attacked using available and emerg- as “the hubris of physics envy” has led us to in-
ing analytical tools, without loss of rigour, but with creasingly adopt a narrow version of positivism
much gain in relevance and generality.” together with relatively unsophisticated scientific
Not only in the fields of psychology and econom- methods to develop causal and testable theories.
ics is the dominance of the “negative problem” On the other hand, the growing dominance of a
being challenged. In December, 2001, under the particular ideology has focused us on solving the
championship of Kim Cameron, Jane Dutton, and “negative problem” of containing the costs of hu-
Robert Quinn, a conference was held at the Uni- man imperfections. These two features of our re-
versity of Michigan Business School entitled “Pos- search, combined with the process of double her-
itive Organizational Scholarship.” As these schol- meneutic, have led to our pessimism becoming a
ars described in the edited volume of the self-fulfilling prophecy.
conference papers (Cameron, Dutton, & Quinn, I must emphasize, however, that by this analysis
2003), I do not at all intend to imply either that we should
abandon the effort to develop systematic theory in
Positive Organizational Scholarship (POS) is the field of management or that we should not
concerned primarily with the study of espe- study some of the more distasteful aspects of indi-
cially positive outcomes, processes and at- vidual and organizational behavior. My distinction
tributes of organizations and their members. between good and bad theory must not be taken to
POS does not represent a single theory, but it mean that the normative implications of a theory
focuses on dynamics that are typically de- stand in isolation of its positive merits. A theory
scribed by words such as excellence, thriving, must illuminate and explain and, if it cannot do
flourishing, abundance, resilience, or virtu- those things, it is not a theory—neither good nor
ousness” (emphasis in original). bad. Wishes and hopes are not theory. Sermons
and preaching are not theory either.
With contributions from 38 well-known academics But the trouble with the social sciences is that
from diverse disciplines and a wide range of institu- the logic of falsification, which is so very essential
tions, this conference and the edited volume clearly for the epistemology of positivism, is very hard to
represent a major step forward in reversing the trend apply with any degree of rigor and ruthlessness in
by rebuilding a balance between positive and neg- the domain of social theories. Typically, no theo-
ative assumptions in the analysis of business-, or- ry—which are all, by definition, partial— explains
ganization-, and management-related issues. a “phenomenon of organized complexity” fully,
But these are, as yet, the nascent efforts of a few. and many different and mutually inconsistent the-
The mainstream of management theory is still ories explain the same phenomenon, often to very
dominated by the gloomy vision—indeed, if any- similar extents. As a result, nothing can be weeded
2005 Ghoshal 87

out nor, given the very different framings, can any- make progress by independently investigating
thing be combined with anything else, except in a both the characters of light, so too must we make
very synthetic and ad hoc manner. progress on both the negative and the positive
The choice among theories, then, falls very much problems described by Friedman. My contention is
on a scholar’s personal preferences rather than on that the pretense of knowledge has led us to in-
either the discipline of empirical estimation or the creasingly focus on only the negative problem as a
rigor of formal, deductive logic. Combined with the result of which we have made little analytical
possibility of self-fulfilling prophecy, it is this am- progress in the last 30 years on the positive prob-
biguity that, in the social sciences, gives life to the lem, at considerable cost to our students, to com-
distinction between good and bad theories. panies, and to society. I also suggest that to ad-
Excessive truth-claims based on extreme as- dress the positive problem, we need to temper the
sumptions and partial analysis of complex phe- pretense of knowledge and reengage with the
nomena can be bad even when they are not alto- scholarships of integration, application, and ped-
gether wrong. In essence, social scientists carry an agogy to build management theories that are
even greater social and moral responsibility than broader and richer than the reductionist and par-
those who work in the physical sciences because, tial theories we have been developing over the last
if they hide ideology in the pretense of science, 30 years.
they can cause much more harm. Ultimately if the trend in management theory is
to be reversed, only business school academics
can do so. This is not going to be easy. The nature
In essence, social scientists carry an even of the academic process naturally favors building
greater social and moral responsibility on the existing edifice of theory instead of starting
than those who work in the physical over, on fresh ground. The currently dominant the-
sciences because, if they hide ideology in ories have so much commitment vested in them
the pretense of science, they can cause that the temptation of most scholars would be to
incrementally adapt these theories, if and as nec-
much more harm. essary, rather than to start afresh on the more
positive agenda.
My contention here is that this is precisely what The barriers to a fresh start are almost too high
business school academics have done over the last (Pfeffer & Fong, 2002). All the way from the struc-
30 years. ture of PhD training to the requirements for pub-
Similarly, the criticism of negative assumptions lishing in top journals, from the criteria of faculty
does not in any way relate to what theorists choose recruitment to the processes for granting tenure,
to study or the conclusions they arrive at; I am not the institutional structures within and around
suggesting that business school academics should business schools are rigidly built around the dom-
restrict themselves in any way from the spirit of inant model. Yet, if we are to have an influence in
free enquiry. My concern relates only to the prac- building a better world for the future, adapting the
tice of considering the premises as basic assump- pessimistic, deterministic theories will not get us
tions— often not even explicitly stated—instead of there. If we really wish to reinstitute ethical or
treating them as testable propositions. By treating moral concerns in the practice of management, we
them as assumptions, theorists exempt their own have to first reinstitute them in our mainstream
ideological biases from the need for either theoret- theory. If we wish our students to contribute to
ical justification or empirical validation, and yet building what Warren Bennis (2000) has described
the same assumptions, through the self-fulfilling as “delightful organizations,” we will have to
process of the double hermeneutic, influence the teach them the theories that describe how they can
social and moral behaviors of people. do so. In spite of all the individual and institutional
The ultimate goal must be to go from the pre- pressures that drive us to paradigmatic confor-
tense to the substance of knowledge. Physicists mity, as both researchers and teachers we have to
continue to seek a unifying grand theory that define and adopt a different path.
would combine both the particle and the wave Thomas Kuhn (1962) was right in arguing that
nature of light. We too must seek the same with mere disconfirmation or challenge never dislodges
regard to the different and contradictory facets of a dominant paradigm; only a better alternative
human nature and organizational behavior. But, does. It would not, therefore, be entirely inappro-
just as such a grand unification has eluded phys- priate to dismiss my concerns as an irrelevant rant
ics so far, so it is likely to elude us for a long time. because I present no such alternative (although,
In the meantime, just as physics has continued to together with colleagues, I have tried to present
88 Academy of Management Learning & Education March

some modest proposals elsewhere—see, e.g., Na- pated in a tenure committee meeting. The chal-
hapiet & Ghoshal, 1998; Moran & Ghoshal, 1999; lenge for the deans is to reinstate this taste—not
and Ghoshal, Bartlett, & Moran, 1999). I suggest, only in terms of theory and methodology but also
however, that such an alternative theory can only in terms of what research questions are asked and
emerge from the collective efforts of many, and where the answers are published.
that the first step in stimulating that collective As a business school academic, I have always
effort lies in reshaping the structure and context staunchly believed that the role of the governors of
within which business school faculty work. The a school should be strictly limited to fund-raising
current paradigm is deeply embedded in the con- and ceremonial activities. In particular, I could
text that surrounds us; for a significant shift in our never conceive of advocating a role of the govern-
priorities, some significant support, resources, and ing board that would even remotely touch on the
reassurances are needed to change that context sanctity of academic freedom. But I do not feel so
(Pfeffer & Fong, 2002; Friga, Bettis, & Sullivan, 2003). sure any more. I believe that as academics, we
In part, this support must come from the leader- may have been guilty of overexploiting our free-
ship of business schools. If deans really intend to dom.
infuse a concern for ethics and for responsible
management in the research and teaching that are
carried out in their institutions, they have to ac- I believe that as academics, we may
knowledge that the tokenism of adding a course on have been guilty of overexploiting our
ethics will not achieve their goals. As long as all freedom.
the other courses continue as they are, a single,
stand-alone course on corporate social responsi-
bility will not change the situation in any way. In the desire to create and protect the pretense of
knowledge—in our venture to make business stud-
Deans have to take leadership—perhaps even at
ies a science—we may have gone too far in ignor-
the cost of some displeasure of some of the senior
ing the consequences not only for our students but
faculty who are most embedded in the currently
also for society. Given the almost absolute power
dominant perspective—in adapting the recruit-
that particularly those of us in the tenured faculty
ment and promotion processes in their schools. To
have over all academic matters, a powerful coun-
the extent that they have any discretion over re-
tervailing force would be necessary for any signif-
search and other resources, they have to allocate a
icant redirection in our research and teaching. Per-
part of those resources for building the positive
haps the boards of governors of the different
agenda, not only in creating courses on ethics and schools represent the only possible source of such
corporate social responsibilities, but also for sup- a countervailing force.
porting a broader range of scholarship in the tra- For most business schools, the governing
ditional fields of strategy, organization behavior, board— by whatever name—represents perhaps
marketing, and others—perhaps even in econom- the worst caricature of ineffective corporate
ics and finance. boards. Most members are irregular in their atten-
The task is not one of delegitimizing existing dance; those who attend tend to see the board
research approaches, but one of relegitimizing plu- meetings as essentially social occasions. The ac-
ralism (Clegg & Ross-Smith, 2003). The ideology tual realities of the school are rarely revealed in
that Milton Friedman described as “liberalism” is the board meetings. The agenda typically focuses
yet another manifestation of the enduring human on fund-raising, external relations, or on vacuous
quest for utopia. The problem with any version of vision statements and the like.
utopia is that the concept itself fails to recognize Perhaps business school governors need to get
the dilemmas that are posed because of the con- more involved in ensuring that the external rheto-
flicts among different desired values and prefer- ric of the institutions are actually reflected in their
ences, and among different desired outcomes. The internal decisions and choices. This does not mean
only alternative to any form of ideological absolut- that the governors should set the research or teach-
ism lies in intellectual pluralism, which is likely to ing agenda for individual faculty or departments
lead both to better research (Weick, 1989) and to nor that they should have a direct influence on
broadened usefulness (Lawrence, 1992). As I have academic recruitment or promotion processes. I am
argued earlier in this article, the social sciences, in not suggesting that they play the policing role that
general, and business schools, in particular, have agency theory reserves for members of corporate
lost their taste for pluralism—as would be mani- boards. The role I see business school governors
fest to any reader of this article who has partici- play is more one of stewardship—involved, sup-
2005 Ghoshal 89

porting, and challenging rather than detached and REFERENCES


controlling. As senior representatives of the exter- Alchian, A. A., & Demsetz, H. 1972. Production, information costs
nal (and, sometimes, internal) communities busi- and economic organization. American Economic Review,
ness schools serve, they can forcefully bring in 62(5): 777–795.
different perspectives and external information Andrews, K. R. 1980. The concept of corporate strategy. Home-
into the highly insular world of business school land, IL: Irwin.
faculty. Given the extremely limited influence of Bailey, J., & Ford, C. 1996. Management as science versus man-
students, staff, and other groups directly connected agement as practice in postgraduate business education.
Business Strategy Review, 7(4): 7–12.
with business schools, it is only the governors who
may have the legitimacy and power to challenge Bartunek, J. 2002. Corporate scandals: How should Academy of
Management members respond? Academy of Management
the dominant dogma with disconfirming informa- Executive, 16: 138.
tion and perspective, and thereby to strengthen the
Becker, G. 1993. The economic way of looking at behaviour,
hands of the deans. (Nobel Lecture). Journal of Political Economy, 101 (3) June:
Companies and managers at large can also get 385– 409.
into the act. After all, the venture of making busi- Ben-Ner, A., & Putterman, L. (Eds.). 1998. Economics, values, and
ness studies a science has made the progress it organization: 7. Cambridge, England: Cambridge Univer-
has only because of the significant amount of re- sity Press.
sources business schools have received through Bennis, W. 2000. Managing the dream: Reflections on leadership
corporate and individual gifts. Without the slack and change. New York: Perseus.
created by generous endowments, business school Berlin, I. 2002. Liberty: 26. (Henry Hardy, Ed.). Oxford, England:
academics would not have been able to separate Oxford University Press.

their research from the practical needs of their Blair, M. 1995. Ownership and control. Washington, DC: The
Brookings Institution.
students or the positive needs of society quite as
completely as many have done. If managers care Boyer, E. L. 1990. Scholarship reconsidered: Priorities of the pro-
fessoriate. Princeton, NJ: The Carnegie Foundation for the
about the conduct of their companies and about Advancement of Teaching.
the legitimacy of their own roles in society—which
Buchholtz, T. 1999. New ideas from dead economists. New York:
is clearly a major issue in most countries around Plume.
the world—perhaps they need to become a bit
Burt, R. 1997. The contingent value of social capital. Adminis-
more discerning about their giving. Both as indi- trative Science Quarterly, 42: 340.
viduals and collectively, business school alumni
Camerer, C., & Thaler, R. H. 1995. Ultimatums, dictators and
and corporate leaders can exert significant pres- manners. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 9(2): 209 –219.
sures to realign the perspectives and priorities of Cameron, K. S., Dutton, J. E., & Quinn, R. E. (Eds.). 2003. Positive
the institutions they support. organizational scholarship. San Francisco: Berrett-Koehler.
Institutions such as the Academy of Manage- Campbell, D. T. 1988. Can we be scientific in applied social
ment will also have to play a key role. While the science? In D. T. Campbell, Methodology and epistemology
leaders of the Academy have duly expressed their for social science: Selected papers: 315–333. [Originally pub-
concerns about the corporate scandals, they can do lished in Evaluation Studies Review Annual (1984): 26 – 48.]
Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
much more to create a new intellectual agenda
Clegg, S. R., & Ross-Smith, A. 2003. Revising the boundaries:
that would support James Coleman’s (1992) vision
Management education and learning in a postpositivist
of the social sciences providing actual help in world. Academy of Management Learning & Education, 2(1):
what he described as “the rational reconstruction 85–98.
of society.” Martin Seligman, through his actions in Coleman, J. S. 1992. The rational reconstruction of society. Amer-
the American Psychological Association, has al- ican Sociological Review, 58:
ready shown what some of these actions can be. Cyert, R. M., & March, J. G. 1963. A behavioural theory of the firm.
The Academy can create a steering committee of Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.
senior people to lead the endeavor and provide Daily, C. M., Dalton, D. R., & Cannella, A. A., Jr. 2003. Corporate
“air cover” for the junior faculty who choose to join governance: Decades of dialogue and data. Academy of
in. Leaders of the Academy can ensure that all the Management Review, 28(3): 371–382.

Academy journals dedicate special issues to legit- Dalton, D. R., Daily, C. M., Ellstrand, A. E., & Johnson, J. L. 1998.
Meta-analytic reviews of board composition, leadership
imize the new intellectual agenda. Indeed, per-
structure, and financial performance. Strategic Manage-
haps they can make this topic the core theme of a ment Journal, 19: 269 –290.
forthcoming annual meeting so as to include the Davis, J. H., Schoorman, F. D., & Donaldson, L. 1997. Toward a
collective wisdom of all members in shaping the stewardship theory of management. Academy of Manage-
journey ahead. ment Review, 22: 20 – 47.
90 Academy of Management Learning & Education March

DiMaggio, P. J., & Powell, W. W. 1983. The iron cage revisited: Jensen, M. E., & Meckling, W. H. 1994. The nature of man. Journal
Institutional isomorphism and collective rationality in or- of Applied Corporate Finance, Summer.
ganizational fields. American Sociological Review, 48: 147–
Jones, E. 1964. The life and work of Sigmund Freud. London:
160.
Penguin Books.
Donaldson, L. 1990. The ethereal hand: Organizational econom- Kahneman, D., Slovic, P., & Tversky, A. (Eds.). 1982. Judgement
ics and management theory. Academy of Management Re- under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases. Cambridge, En-
view, 15(3): 369 –381. gland: Cambridge University Press.
Donaldson, L. 2002. Damned by our own theories: Contradic- Keynes, J. M. 1953. The general theory of employment, interest
tions between theories and management education. Acad- and money. New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich.
emy of Management Learning & Education, 1(1): 96 –106.
Kochan, T. A. 2002. Addressing the crisis in confidence in cor-
Eastman, W., & Bailey, J. 1998. Mediating the fact-value anti- porations: Root causes, victims and strategies for reform.
mony: Patterns in managerial and legal rhetoric, 1890 –1990. Academy of Management Executive, 16: 139 –141.
Organization Science, 9(2): 232–245.
Kuhn, T. S. 1962. The structure of scientific revolution. Chicago,
Eccles, R. G., & Nohria, N. 1992. Beyond the hype: Rediscovering IL: University of Chicago Press.
the essence of management. Boston: Harvard Business
Lawrence, P. R. 1992. The challenge of problem-oriented re-
School Press.
search. Journal of Management Inquiry, 1: 139 –142.
Elster, J. 1983. Explaining technical change. Cambridge, En-
Leavitt, H. J. 1989. Educating our MBAs: On teaching what we
gland: Cambridge University Press.
haven’t taught. California Management Review, 31(3): 38 –
Enzle, M. E., & Anderson, S. C. 1993. Surveillant intentions and 50.
intrinsic motivation. Journal of Personality and Social Psy-
Lewin, K. 1945. The research centre for group dynamics at Mas-
chology, 64: 257–266.
sachusetts Institute of Technology. Sociometry, 8:126 –135.
Frankfurter, G. M., & McGoun, E. G. 1999. Ideology and the Mintzberg, H., & Gosling, J. 2002. Educating managers beyond
theory of financial economics. Journal of Economic Behav- borders. Academy of Management Learning & Education,
ior and Organization, 39: 159 –177. 1(1): 64 –76.
Friedman, M. 1953. Essays in positive economics. Chicago: Uni- Moran, P., & Ghoshal, S. 1999. Markets, firms and the process of
versity of Chicago Press. economic development. Academy of Management Review,
Friedman, M. 2002. Capitalism and freedom (40th Anniversary 24(3): 390 – 412.
Edition). Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. Nahapiet, J., & Ghoshal, S. 1998. Social capital, intellectual
Friga, P. N., Bettis, R. A., & Sullivan, R. S. 2003. Changes in capital, and the organizational advantage. Academy of
graduate management education and new business school Management Review, 23(2): 242–266.
strategies for the 21st century, Academy of Management Nelson, R. H. 2001. Economics as religion. PA: The Pennsylvania
Learning & Education, 2(3): 233–249. State University.
Gergen, K. J. 1973. Social psychology as history. Journal of Per- Osterloh, M., & Frey, B. S. 2003. Corporate governance for
sonality and Social Psychology, 26(2): 309 –320. crooks? The case for corporate virtue. Unpublished working
Ghoshal, S., Bartlett, C., & Moran, P. 1999. A new manifesto for paper, University of Zurich,
management. Sloan Management Review, 40(3): 9 –20. Peterson, C. M., & Seligman, M. E. P. 2003. Positive Organiza-
tional Studies: Lessons from positive psychology. In K. S.
Ghoshal, S., & Moran, P. 1996. Bad for practice: A critique of the
Cameron, J. E. Dutton, & R. E Quinn (Eds.). Positive organi-
transaction cost theory. Academy of Management Review,
zational scholarship. San Francisco, CA: Berrett-Koehler.
21(1): 13– 47.
Pfeffer, J. 1993. Barriers to the advance of organizational sci-
Gordon, R., & Howell, J. 1959. Higher education for business. New
ence: Paradigm development as a dependent variable.
York, NY: Columbia University Press.
Academy of Management Review, 18: 599 – 620.
Grossman, S., & Hart, O. 1986. The costs of benefits of owner-
Pfeffer, J., & Fong, C. T. 2002. The end of business schools? Less
ship: A theory of lateral and vertical integration. Journal of
success than meets the eye. Academy of Management
Political Economy, 94: 691–719.
Learning & Education, 1(1):78 –95.
Hambrick, D.C. 1994. What if the Academy actually mattered? Popper, K. R. 1968. The logic of scientific discovery. New York:
Academy of Management Review, 19: 11–16. Harper and Row.
Hannan, M. J., & Freeman, J. 1977. The population ecology of Porter, M. E. 1980. Competitive strategy: Techniques for analyz-
organizations. American Journal of Sociology, 82: 929 –964. ing industries and firms. New York: Free Press.
Hayek, F. A. Von. 1989. The pretence of knowledge (Nobel Lec- Porter, L. W., & McKibbin, L. E. 1988. Management education and
ture). American Economic Review, December: 3–7. development: Drift or thrust into the 21st century. New York:
Hirschman, A. O. 1970. The search for paradigms as a hindrance McGraw Hill.
to understanding. World Politics, March. Quinn, J. B. 1992. Intelligent enterprise. New York: Free Press.
Homans, C. G. 1961. Social behaviour: Its elementary forms. New Roethlisberger, F. J. 1977. The elusive phenomena. Boston, MA:
York: Harcourt, Brace, & World. Harvard University Press.
Jensen, M., & Meckling, W. 1976. Theory of the firm: Managerial Schlossman, S., Sedlak, M., & Wechsler, H. 1998. The new look:
behaviour, agency costs and ownership structure. Journal The Ford Foundation and the revolution in business edu-
of Financial Economics, 3: 305–360. cation. Selections, 14(3): 8 –27.
2005 Ghoshal 91

Sen, A. 1998. Foreword. In A. Ben-Ner & L. Putterman (Eds.), Sumantra Ghoshal was profes-
Economics, values and organization: xii. Cambridge: Cam- sor of strategic and interna-
bridge University Press. tional management at the Lon-
don Business School (LBS). He
Simon, H. 1985. Human nature in politics: The dialogue of psy- also served as the founding
chology with political science. American Political Science dean of the Indian School of
Review, 79: 293–304. Business in Hyderabad, of
which LBS is a partner, and as a
Strickland, L. H. 1958. Surveillance and trust. Journal of Person-
member of the Committee of
ality, 26: 200 –215.
Overseers of the Harvard Busi-
Sutton, R. I., & Staw, B. M. 1995. What theory is not. Administra- ness School. Managing Across
tive Science Quarterly, 40: 371–384. Borders: The Transnational So-
lution, a book he coauthored
Thibaut, J., & Kelley, H. H. 1959. The social psychology of groups. with Christopher Bartlett, has
New York: Wiley. been listed in the Financial
Times as one of the 50 most in-
Weick, K. E. 1989. Theory construction as disciplined imagina- fluential management books
tion. Academy of Management Review, 14: 516 –531. and has been translated into
Williamson, O. E. 1975. Markets and hierarchies: Analysis and nine languages. The Differenti-
antitrust implications. New York: Free Press. ated Network: Organizing the
Multinational Corporation for
Wilson, J. Q. 1993. The moral sense. New York: Free Press. Value Creation, a book he coau-
thored with Nitin Nohria, won
the George Terry Book Award in
1997. The Individualized Corpo-
ration, coauthored with Chris-
topher Bartlett, won the Igor An-
soff Award in 1997, and has
been translated into seven lan-
guages. Dr. Ghoshal’s last
book, Managing Radical
Change, won the Management
Book of the Year award in India.
With doctoral degrees from
both the MIT School of Manage-
ment and the Harvard Business
School, Sumantra served on the
editorial boards of several aca-
demic journals and had been
nominated to the Fellowships
at the Academy of Manage-
ment, the Academy of Interna-
tional Business, and the World
Economic Forum.

You might also like