You are on page 1of 13

Richard Rorty, Liberalism and the Politics of Redescription

Author(s): Keith Topper


Source: The American Political Science Review, Vol. 89, No. 4 (Dec., 1995), pp. 954-965
Published by: American Political Science Association
Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/2082520
Accessed: 14-02-2020 13:28 UTC

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms

American Political Science Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and
extend access to The American Political Science Review

This content downloaded from 137.222.114.241 on Fri, 14 Feb 2020 13:28:57 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
American Political Science Review Vol. 89, No. 4 December 1995

RICHARD RORTY, LIBERALISM AND THE POLITICS OF REDESCRIPTION


KEITH TOPPER California State University, Long Beach

Tn recent years Richard Rorty has sought to develop an alternative to the familiar rationalist and
f natural rights "vocabularies" of liberalism. Unlike most critics of classical liberalism, however,
v Rorty eschews attempts to argue against these vocabularies, and instead seeks to persuade his
readers by redescribing the aspirations of a liberal society in a more "attractive" way. I assess Rorty's
redescriptive practice through an analysis of his ideal liberal polity. I contend that although Rorty
defends redescription as an alternative to "normal" philosophical and theoretical argument, his
redescriptive efforts fail on their own terms: not only does it appear that there is no redescription in
his descriptions, but he proves incapable of offering any insights into or exits from pressing problems
in contemporary liberal societies. This, I submit, can be traced back to his unwillingness to investigate
and redescribe power and power relations.

In the essay "Method, Social Science, and Social redescription is an intellectual practice employed
Hope," Richard Rorty (1983) contends that per- specifically for the purpose of radically transforming
haps the most important challenge facing social or replacing a calcified but well-entrenched vocabu-
scientists today is that of reinvigorating the long lary. Such a practice is necessary because, following
dormant Deweyan ideal of social science. This ideal, from his neo-Wittgensteinian account of alternative
which flourished in America for a period prior to the vocabularies and language games, in cases where
advent of behavioralism, accents above all "the moral one's aim is to uproot a well-established and "time-
importance of the social sciences-their role in wid- honored" vocabulary, standard forms of argument
ening and deepening our sense of community and of prove invariably to be "inconclusive or question-
the possibilities open to that community" (pp. 203-4). begging" (Rorty 1989a, 9). This, he says, is because
Rorty urges pragmatists not to follow the path of the proponents of the time-honored vocabulary al-
figures such as Michel Foucault (who, Rorty claims, ways demand that any arguments against it be
adopts the "pragmatist line" but, unlike Dewey, phrased in their vocabulary. And this implies that
emphasizes the darker aspects of the social sciences, their opponents must show that certain features of
the ways they "have served as instruments of 'the the entrenched vocabulary are internally incoherent
disciplinary society"' [p 204]) but to devote their or inconsistent or that they "deconstruct themselves"
energies to the positive task of enlarging human (p. 8). But these demands, Rorty holds, can never be
solidarity, that is, the task of expanding the scope met, for the current vocabulary defines what is co-
and depth of our liberal democratic community by herent, consistent, and meaningful speech in the first
showing us how others who do not share our partic- place (p. 9). Thus the attempt to uproot an en-
ular cultural practices or form of life or who look trenched vocabulary through argument is always at
strange or who act differently are ultimately also "one best inconclusive, simply because there are no non-
of us" (p. 203). This transformation of both our invidious common criteria of evaluation or compari-
sensibilities and our sense of community is accom- son. For this reason, Rorty maintains that "interest-
plished, Rorty says, not by locating something uni- ing philosophy is rarely an examination of the pros
versal that binds us all together but by describing and cons of a thesis. Usually it is ... a contest
what unfamiliar people are like and redescribing between an entrenched vocabulary which has be-
what we ourselves are like (1989a, xvi). By interpret- come a nuisance and a half-formed new vocabulary
ing people, cultures, institutions, and practices in which vaguely promises great things" (ibid.).
ways that make us more sensitive to the details of In these instances, what is required is not careful
human pain, suffering, and humiliation; by promot- argument but an ability to show how things might
ing an appreciation of the cardinal liberal values of look when rearranged and placed in a different light.
tolerance, diversity, and freedom; and by fostering an As Rorty explains, this "method" of philosophy
awareness of the contingency of all communities-
pragmatists contribute to both a "strengthening of is the same as the "method" of utopian politics or
liberal institutions" and "a renewed sense of commu- revolutionary science (as opposed to parliamentary pol-
itics or normal science). The method is to redescribe lots
nity" (Rorty 1983, 166; idem 1986b, 13).
and lots of things in new ways, until you have created a
Now if the principal aim of this Deweyan/Rortyian
pattern of linguistic behavior which will tempt the rising
vision of social science is the widening and deepen-
generation to adopt it, thereby causing them to look for
ing of a flexible, pluralistic, open and tolerant "bour- appropriate new forms of nonlinguistic behavior, for
geois liberalism,"' then the means to this end lies inexample, the adoption of new scientific equipment of
the somewhat vague interpretive practice which new social institutions. This sort of philosophy does not
Rorty labels "redescription." As conceived by Rorty, work piece by piece, analyzing concept after concept, or

954

This content downloaded from 137.222.114.241 on Fri, 14 Feb 2020 13:28:57 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
American Political Science Review Vol. 89, No. 4

testing thesis after thesis. Rather, it works holistically REDESCRIPTION APPLIED:


and pragmatically. It says things like "try thinking of it
RORTY'S LIBERAL UTOPIA
this way" . . . It does not try to pretend to have a better
candidate for doing the same things which we did when
Rorty's postmetaphysical redescription of liberalism
we spoke in the old way. Rather, it suggests that we
is, among other things, an attempt to offer a way out
might want to stop doing those things and do something
of what he sees as a prototypical case of philosophical
else. But it does not argue for this suggestion on the basis
of antecedent criteria common to the old and new deadlock in contemporary social and political theory,
language games. For just insofar as the new language namely the stalemate regarding the relation between
really is new, there will be no such criteria. (1989a, 9) the private and public domains of life, or, as Rorty
redescribes it, the conflict between the desire for
In short, redescription is not an attempt to enunciate private autonomy and self-creation and the desire for
"the right description" but an attempt to avoid or solidarity and social justice. Rorty contends that these
dissolve intractable problems, conflicts, or anomalies conflicting impulses constitute the principal tension
by reweaving the fabric of our current ways of speak- between two distinct and ultimately irreconcilable
ing into a new vocabulary, one "that cuts across the types of thinkers, each with its own philosophical
vocabulary we have so far used in our . . . delibera- vision, as well as its own understanding of language,
tions" (Rorty 1989a, 99; idem 1990b, 638-39). The aim selfhood, community, and freedom: ironists, such as
of the redescriber is not to offer arguments against the Nietzsche, Proust, Heidegger, and Nabokov and lib-
erals, such as Marx, Mill, Dewey, Habermas, and
currently familiar vocabulary, but to "make the vo-
Rawls (1989a, xiv).
cabulary I favor look attractive by showing how it
Rorty begins by noting that in at least one respect
may be used to describe a variety of topics" (Rorty
both kinds of writers are quite similar: both are
1989a, 9). If successful, the redescriber will contribute
"historicist" in the sense that they reject any and all
to intellectual progress by creating new metaphors
attempts at theoretically, theologically, or metaphys-
and modes of speech that over time succeed in
ically grounding our "most central beliefs and de-
becoming literalized (p. 44).
sires" (1989a, xv). Like Rorty, both types repudiate
Because the practice of redescription is resolutely
the idea "that there is any such thing as 'human
not an attempt to engage in, but to avoid, "normal"
nature' or the 'deepest level of the self'," as well as
philosophical and conceptual argumentation, efforts
the notion that there is "an order beyond time and
to evaluate it on these grounds are in Rorty's view
change which determines the point of human exis-
fundamentally misconceived. They are misconceived
tence and establishes a hierarchy of responsibilities"
for the obvious reason that they presuppose precisely
(pp. xiii, xv). To the contrary, they both "insist that
the normal vocabulary and practices of justification
socialization, and thus historical circumstance, go all
that the redescriber seeks to circumvent and replace.
the way down-that there is nothing 'beneath' social-
As one commentator has noted, to ask Rorty "for
ization or prior to history which is definitory of the
a conceptually adequate account of redescription
human" (p. xiii). In this respect, both have helped
would be to demand a philosophically responsible
release us from the grip of "theology and metaphys-
account of irresponsibility" (McCumber 1990, 8).
ics" and have prepared the way for a future, "post-
While I would maintain that there are indeed cases in
metaphysical culture," one organized around "an
which it is possible to argue for or against the intro-
endless, proliferating realization of Freedom, rather
duction of a new vocabulary,2 here I am primarily
than a convergence toward an already existing
interested in examining Rorty's redescriptive practice
Truth" (pp. xiii, xvi).
in its own pragmatic terms-that is, I want to see to
However, apart from their common animus to the
what extent his redescriptive efforts promise to pre-
idea of metaphysical grounding, these two types of
serve and extend freedom and pluralism, help us to historicist writers are motivated by dramatically dif-
determine which social and political traditions and ferent desires. For ironists like Nietzsche, Heidegger,
practices should endure and be extended and which and Foucault, "the desire for self-creation, for private
may need reconstruction or abandonment, and pro- autonomy, dominates" (1989a, xiii). These writers are
vide us with an attractive and promising exit from interested primarily in the quest for "private perfec-
particular conflicts and dilemmas. In what follows, tion," in the self-creation of a distinctive, autono-
therefore, I will explore what is perhaps Rorty's most mous life, one that is not, as Harold Bloom says,
ambitious effort at redescription, his attempt to rede- either "a copy or a replica" (quoted on p. 24). As
scribe liberalism by sketching a picture of what he such, they are exemplars of "what private perfection
calls a "liberal utopia." By examining some of the ... can be like"; but at the same time they distrust
problems implicit in this particular exemplar of rede- processes of socialization, which they tend to view as
scription, I hope to identify some of the limits of "antithetical to something deep within us" (p. xiv)-
Rorty's redescriptive practice. However, before ex- such as the will to power, libidinal impulses, or
amining these questions, it is first necessary to de- Being. By contrast, liberal authors like Mill, Dewey,
scribe in more detail Rorty's understanding of current Habermas, Rawls, and Isaiah Berlin are inspired
impasses in social and political thought, as well as his primarily by "the desire for a more just and free
vision of a postmetaphysical liberal utopia. human community" (ibid.). They see their work not

955

This content downloaded from 137.222.114.241 on Fri, 14 Feb 2020 13:28:57 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Rorty, Liberalism, and Redescription December 1995

as a personal quest for autonomy, but as "a shared, ways in which these institutions and practices fall
social effort-the effort to make our institutions and short of our implicit commitments, these writers help
practices more just and less cruel" (ibid.). Indeed, give focus to our "sense of obligation to other human
Rorty (borrowing Judith Shklar's definition of "liber- beings" (p. 68).
al") calls these figures liberals precisely because they As a way of preserving what is most valuable in
"think that cruelty is the worst thing we do" (p. xv, both types of writers, Rorty advocates not a theoret-
see Shklar 1984, 8; idem 1989). However, this over- ical solution but, rather, a satisfactory practical "com-
riding regard for social justice and the cessation of promise." In this compromise, each party is recog-
cruelty places them deeply at odds with their ironist nized as being "right" but only within a particular
counterparts, whose pursuit of private perfection domain (Rorty 1989a, xiv-xv, 68). The challenge,
seems frequently imbued with a decidedly antiliberal Rorty believes, is to reconcile ourselves to the fact
proclivity for "'irrationalism' and 'aestheticism"' that our "final vocabulary" (i.e., those fully contin-
(Rorty 1989a, xv). For this reason, liberals like Rawls gent and foundationless but nevertheless irreducible
(in his early writings) and Habermas continue to search and authoritative words that constitute the linguistic
for a postmetaphysical anchor for their politics, hoping ground for all of our claims about knowledge, moral-
in this way to harness the threat of unbridled ironism. ity, and the good life [1989a, 73; idem 1992, 216])
In discussing this oftentimes acrimonious conflict contains "two independent parts," one crucial for the
between "writers on autonomy" and "writers on private project of self-creation, the other indispens-
justice," Rorty holds that the standard philosophical able for the public project of human solidarity (1989a,
solutions all seek to reconcile these antagonistic 68). Our imperative, he emphasizes, is not to unify but
stances by uniting them under a single, more syn- to accommodate practically these two "equally valid, yet
thetic theoretical or philosophical view, one that forever incommensurable" parts (p. xv; see also p. 68).
"would let us hold self-creation and justice, private For Rorty, the most suitable modus vivendi is one
perfection and human solidarity, in a single vision" that grants the ironist's demand for autonomy and
(1989a, xv). Hence, we find debates among neo- self-creation yet insists that the pursuit of this goal be
Kantian rationalists like Habermas, neo-Nietzschean strictly a private affair. Ironists, Rorty writes, are
anarchists like Foucault, communitarians like Michael figures who are defined in part by their acute aware-
Sandel, and philosophically oriented liberals like ness of the arbitrariness and contingency of their own
Rawls and Ronald Dworkin-all seeking to commen- final vocabulary. Unlike nihilists, ironists have com-
surate opposing claims by bringing them under a mitments, but unlike metaphysicians, their commit-
more synoptic philosophical view. Rorty maintains, ments are wedded to "a sense of the contingency of
however, that these manifold proposals are plausible their own commitment" (Rorty 1989a, 61). Indeed,
only if one first assumes that the ironist and liberal precisely because ironists are "never quite able to
visions are not fundamentally "incommensurable" take themselves seriously," they continually enter-
but are merely opposed. But, he insists, they are tain and experiment with other vocabularies, hoping
incommensurable: "The vocabulary of self-creation is through this ongoing process to fashion an increas-
necessarily private, unshared, unsuited to argument. ingly self-made self, one that is not simply a reflection
The vocabulary of justice is necessarily public and or effect of one's predecessors, historical circum-
shared, a medium for argumentative exchange" stances, or local culture (p. 73). However, while this
(ibid.). Because of this basic and ineradicable incom- unending process of questioning, redescribing, and
mensurability, there "is no way to bring self-creation reweaving one's inherited vocabularies and exploring
together with justice at the level of theory" (ibid.). and creating new ones is central to the ironist's quest
Rather than endeavoring to unify these forever for an ever more autonomous, self-created final vo-
incommensurable stances in a single philosophical cabulary, Rorty denies emphatically that this activity
vision or to terminate the conflict by granting priority plays any positive role in public life. "Irony," he
to the demands of one side over those of the other, states, "seems inherently a private matter," some-
Rorty instead recommends that we look at the rela- thing that "is of little public use" (pp. 83, 120). More
tion between these two types of writers "as being like importantly, Rorty warns that when nonliberal
the relation between two kinds of tools-as little in ironists such as Nietzsche, Heidegger, and Foucault
need of synthesis as paintbrushes and crowbars" seek to bring their redescriptive practices into the
(1989a, xv). One kind of writer, the ironist, teaches us public domain, they typically abandon their ironic
that there are indeed legitimate virtues other than appreciation of the contingency of their own vocab-
social virtues, that some people do succeed "in re- ulary and instead become convinced that they have
creating themselves" (ibid.). These writers serve us hit upon some deep truth about the way in which
by bringing to light our own "half-articulate need" public institutions repress inherently the desire for
for self-transformation and by encouraging us to autonomy. Failing to recognize that autonomy "is not
become "one whom we as yet lack the words to the sort of thing that could ever be embodied in social
describe" (ibid.). Conversely, liberal writers prompt institutions," ironist public philosophers are led to
us to recognize the gap between the commitments dismiss too easily both liberalism and its attendant
embodied in "the public, shared vocabulary we use institutions (p. 65). When this happens, public
in daily life" and the actual character of our current ironists become "at best useless and at worst danger-
institutions and practices (ibid.). By pointing out the ous" (p. 68).

956

This content downloaded from 137.222.114.241 on Fri, 14 Feb 2020 13:28:57 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
American Political Science Review Vol. 89, No. 4

In order to circumvent these potential hazards of no persuasive force. This absence of ultimate ground,
public ironism, Rorty offers an elegantly clear and however, is in Rorty's view no cause for despair not
simple prescription: we should "privatize the Nie- only because the demand for a "noncircular" justifi-
tzschean-Sartrean-Foucauldian attempt at authentic- cation of our social practices is itself incoherent but,
ity and purity" and enforce this by insisting upon "a more notably, because our own ungrounded ground
firm distinction between the public and the private" is all we need for our social deliberations.4
(1989a, 65, 83). On this view, the ironist's desire for While at first reading this resolutely nominalist,
autonomy and self-creation, as well as the utopian historicist, and "postmodernist" conception of liber-
vision of a culture characterized by an endless prolif- alism might appear to be hopelessly at odds with the
eration of alternative descriptions (what Rorty calls a standard canon of liberal thought, Rorty contends
"poeticized culture"), are all to be welcomed as that in fact it remains in tune with the basic commit-
legitimate and even exemplary private ideals. As long ments both of J. S. Mill's liberalism and Jeffersonian
as they "do it on their own time-causing no harm to democracy (1991a, 175-96). For example, he tells us
others and using no resources needed by those less that although the practical tasks of reducing cruelty
advantaged," ironists are free to be "as privatistic, and of balancing public and private commitments
'irrational' and aestheticist as they please" (p. xiv). require perpetual deliberation, discussion, and social
Such freedom from coercion is not only tolerable but experimentation, his "hunch" is that "Western social
is, Rorty claims, "the aim of a just and free society" and political thought may have had the last conceptual
(p. xiv). In the public realm, however, things are revolution that it needs. J. S. Mill's suggestion that
altogether different. This is the realm of what Wilfred governments devote themselves to optimizing the
Sellars calls "we-intentions," of shared practices and balance between leaving people's private lives alone
self-interpretations that define us not as individuals and preventing suffering seems to me pretty much
but as part of a larger moral community (quoted in the last word" (1989a, 63). On the question of how
Rorty 1989a, 59-60). Here our paramount concern is best to close the divide between liberal ideals and the
with public issues of social justice, and in public oftentimes depressing (and cruel) realities of life in
matters of this sort, discourse must begin necessarily contemporary liberal states, Rorty rejects the idea
from within a common vocabulary, one that permits that what we need is a "radical critique" of liberal
both argument and rational consensus. This, of thought and instead urges that "contemporary liberal
course, does not imply that public vocabularies must society already contains the institutions for its own
remain forever immune from criticism, expansion, improvement" (1989a, 63; idem 1990b, 633-43; idem
and transformation but it does entail a "mild ethno- 1991b, 129-39). Indeed, the "only way to avoid per-
centrism," one based on the idea that public dis- petuating cruelty within social institutions" is simply
course must start from "the way we live now" and to continue extending those institutions emblematic
that "people [and communities] can rationally change of liberalism, that is, to continue "maximizing the
their beliefs and desires only by holding most of quality of education, freedom of the press, educa-
those beliefs and desires constant" (Rorty 1989a, 197, tional opportunity, opportunities to exert political
idem 1991a, 29, 212). influence, and the like" (idem 1989a, 66-67).
For "us" citizens of "the secular modern West," Seen in this light, Rorty's fully developed ideal
this shared and public vocabulary is unavoidably that polity (i.e., his "liberal utopia") is a clear repudiation
of liberal democracy, with its characteristic accent on of both Habermas' (1987) attempt to eradicate all
averting cruelty and "the humiliation of human be- ironism and ground social democratic practices in a
ings" (Rorty 1989a, xv; idem 1991a, 29).3 Rorty openly universalist, "communicative reason" and Foucault's
accepts the idea that these core commitments can putative hope for a "total revolution" that would
never be buttressed by appeals to transcendental or embody our autonomy in our institutions (Rorty
ontological arguments but maintains that such philo- 1989a, 65). Rather, what emerges is a dualistic, com-
sophical reinforcements are not needed in the first partmentalized vision not only of the self but also of
place. All that is required to sustain a commitment to the relation between the public and private spheres.
liberal democracy is a comparative historical narrative On the private side of this divide is the ironist's
about the way in which its customs and institutions preoccupation with autonomy and passion for con-
have, on the whole, made these societies less cruel tinual redescription-both esteemed as exemplary
and more free (i.e., tolerant of a greater range of impulses in the quest to achieve private perfection.
self-expression and providing more leeway for peo- Here we find the realm of negative freedom and the
ple to pursue what private projects they wish) than absence of other-regarding obligations and hence also
other, nonliberal societies (Rorty 1989a, 68; idem the realm of fantasy, play, incommensurate meta-
1991a, 29). Such an account could not, he acknowl- phors, and self-creation. On the public side of the
edges, rationally convince just anyone of liberalism's divide is the liberal's commitment to the minimiza-
superiority, for unless one already shares our moral tion of pain, cruelty, and humiliation through the
sensitivity to acts of cruelty and humiliation, as wellexpansion and refinement of "the insViAuoiuns of
as our appreciation of the pleasures devolving from bourgeois liberal society" (ibid., 84). This is the realm
freedom, diversity, and toleration (i.e., unless one not of idiosyncrasy and aesthetic invention but of
already accepts some of the "words" in liberalism's "solidarity" and "we-intentions." Here the highest
"final vocabulary"), such comparative accounts have virtues are those of the public citizen, the person

957

This content downloaded from 137.222.114.241 on Fri, 14 Feb 2020 13:28:57 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Rorty, Liberalism, and Redescription December 1995

engaged in common public discourse about ways to tive to foundationalist liberalism, one based on a clear
minimize cruelty, achieve social justice, and extend understanding of "the patterns of the past and the
human solidarity. As a polity populated by citizens needs of the present" (Rorty 1987, 11)? Or, by con-
who have dispensed with attempts to unify or syn- trast, does the very way in which he seeks to escape
thesize philosophically the public and private spheres, from the pathologies of conventional foundationalist
Rorty's utopia stands as a picture of a transformed philosophy leave him without the resources required
culture freed of such Enlightenment neuroses, one for expanding and ultimately realizing liberalism's
that seeks only to devise various practical and polit- most admired ideals?
ical measures to balance these "equally valid" yet
dualistic commitments (p. xv). Likewise, the ideal
resident of this polity, the "liberal ironist" (an un- CONTINGENCY, SELF-CREATION
likely combination of the private ironism of Proust AND CHANGE
and Derrida and the public liberalism of figures such
as Dewey and George Orwell) is one who abjures the Perhaps these issues can be defined more sharply if
Enlightenment-induced longing for a unified and we begin by examining what is clearly the connecting
centered self and instead strives merely to negotiate thread running throughout Rorty's narrative, the
the irreconcilable demands between "a private ethic rather elusive but frequently invoked notion of con-
of self-creation and a public ethic of mutual accom- tingency.5 In its broadest sense, Rorty construes con-
modation" (Rorty 1986a, 12). tingency as the idea that things and events "might
For Rorty, this redescription of Enlightenment lib- have been otherwise" (Dreyfus and Hall 1992, 18).
eralism terminates in a new and more compelling Understood in this way, the term contingency typically
vision both of liberal politics and of the relation stands at one end of a set of oppositions whose other
between the public and private spheres. By abandon- term is variously necessary, essential, intrinsic, or un-
ing the now-outdated vocabularies of theology, meta- conditional. These latter terms, (as I have indicated)
physics, and foundationalist philosophy, Rorty be- are themselves tightly intertwined with notions of a
lieves that we provide the conditions for a revitalized common "human nature," a telos, a divine order or
public and private life, one that consists of an "intri- some other principle of legitimacy that is privileged
cately textured collage of private narcissism and pub- precisely because its status is independent of our
lic pragmatism" (1991a, 210). Moreover, he insists particular historical location and social practices. At a
that the absence of such vocabularies does not leave minimum, then, Rorty's accent on contingency is tied
us without the tools necessary for defending liberal closely to his denial of the idea that there is anything
commitments to freedom, tolerance, pluralism, and "'beneath' socialization or prior to history which is
the like (as some critics maintain it does) but rather definatory of the human" (1989a, xiii).
reinvigorates those commitments precisely by under- Unfortunately, this in itself is not highly informa-
scoring in detail both their practical advantages and tive, for it is at best an extremely general and purely
their historical contingency. Such a story may lack the negative construal. When Rorty speaks of contin-
sense of epic drama found in the "grand" treatises of gency in a more specific manner, however, he typi-
Enlightenment philosophy, but it is no less capable of cally uses the term in one of two ways. First, he uses
engendering a commitment to human solidarity. it in a way that links it to notions of novelty, innova-
This vision of a liberal society founded entirely tion, originality, and creativity. In these instances
upon "our loyalty to other human beings clinging (common in his chapter "The Contingency of Self-
together against the dark, not our hope of getting hood"), contingency is meant to pinpoint some do-
things right" (Rorty 1983, 166) is unquestionably one main or space that is devoid of any immanent nature
of the more ambitious efforts to rejuvenate liberal- or logic and therefore also open to innovation, trans-
ism's most attractive ideals-namely, its moral com- formation, and redescription. Here contingency repre-
mitment to toleration, pluralism, and the avoidance sents the abundant possibilities inherent in the rec-
of cruelty and its preoccupation with developing a ognition of historicity: because our inherited practices
mix of rights, liberties, and institutions that protects and forms of life are not ontologically fixed but are
individuals and minorities against the all-too-familiar culturally and historically constituted, they can (al-
dangers of absolutism, totalitarianism, and other though never all at once) be questioned, transformed,
forms of unrestrained statism. By detaching these and redescribed. Understood in this way, Rorty's
aspirations from the abstract and rigid philosophical invocation of contingency moves between a restate-
structures in which they have frequently been en- ment of the undeniable fact that human beings and
cased, Rorty proposes a vision of liberalism that human history are something more than the com-
departs both from classical social contract and natural bined effects of culture and nature and a voluntarist
rights versions and from those offered by contempo- notion that the only impediments to human change
rary foundationalist liberals like Ronald Dworkin and transformation are those set by the human will
(1977), Robert Nozick (1974), and the early John itself.
Rawls (1971). However, apart from the evident orig- On the other hand, Rorty frequently uses the term
inality of Rorty's liberal utopia, one must still pose contingency in a quite different manner, identifying it
the basic pragmatist questions: What is the cash value not with the powers and possibilities of human
of this redescription? Does it offer us a useful alterna- innovation but with notions of chance, luck, accident,

958

This content downloaded from 137.222.114.241 on Fri, 14 Feb 2020 13:28:57 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
American Political Science Review Vol. 89, No. 4

randomness, and fortuitousness. This connection is problems. He acknowledges at times that our creative
made explicit in a number of different passages: capacities are not unlimited and that even purely
"Poetic, artistic, philosophical, scientific, or political chance events can be understood and confronted in
progress results from the accidental coincidence of a different ways. He tells us, for example, that there are
private obsession with a public need" (1989a, 37); "no fully Nietzschean lives, . . . no lives which are
Galileo "just lucked out" (1983, 193); "The idea of not largely parasitical on an un-redescribed past and
human solidarity is simply the fortunate happen- dependent on the charity of as yet unborn genera-
stance creation of modern times" (1989a, 68); the tions" (1989a, 42). Unfortunately, Rorty fails fully to
mention of "random factors" and constellations (p. appreciate the social and political implications of this
17; 1986a, 12); and the use of Philip Larkin's meta- insight. For if novelty and imagination are them-
phor of the "blind impress" (1989a, 141).6 The con- selves partly constituted by language and social prac-
nection is also implicit in Rorty's radically decentered tice and if (as I have indicated) language and social
conception of human subjectivity, as well as in the practice place flexible and contestable but neverthe-
recurrence of haunting and despondent passages on less real boundaries upon what is and is not intelli-
the theme of human powerlessness. Whether explicit gible, who has the right to speak, whose speech and
or implicit, however, the meaning of contingency in what forms of speech are taken seriously, what
all of these passages is essentially the same: it impliescounts as a problem and what counts as a legitimate
uncontrollable and unpredictable forces or events solution to some problem, then questions about the
that shape our lives in decisive ways. pursuit of and capacity for self-creation and change
What is significant about these construals of con- are not just personal and private questions, nor are
tingency is the way in which they accent Rorty's own they just questions about whether we should "drop"
equivocations regarding the potentialities and limits worn-out vocabularies and metaphors in favor of
of individual and collective action. As we can see newer, more useful ones. Indeed, precisely because
from his dual use of the term, Rorty vacillates be- what counts as a "worn-out" or "useful" vocabulary
tween an "anything goes" vision of human agency in is itself partly constituted by the social and linguistic
which our capacities for personal or social transfor- practices of our communities, questions about self-
mation are limited only by the powers of our individ- creation, change, and the usefulness of vocabularies
ual or collective imaginations and a vision in which all presuppose a specific social, political, and ideolog-
efforts to shape one's self and one's world are every ical context that cannot be erased even if it goes
bit as uncontrollable as in the most deterministic and unnoticed.
totalizing philosophical systems. Here Rorty finds This discussion of contingency and the public/
himself locked in the same dichotomy between vol- private dichotomy suggests a profound and unre-
untarism and determinism that he associates with solved tension in Rorty's redescriptive efforts. Al-
metaphysical and foundationalist enterprises.7 though his accent on contingency, along with his
In fact, neither of these construals are typical of the
rigid separation of the public and the private, are
situations that characterize the better part of every- both intended to open up spaces for increased plu-
day life. Our capacity for self-creation or imagination ralism, novelty, play, self-creation, and human soli-
is not unlimited; it is instead partly constituted, and darity, they tend instead to pass over or mask just
therefore also partly constrained, by past and present those forces which not only limit the range of possible
social, cultural, and linguistic practices. These practices
projects but also structure the level, quality, and
not only privilege certain imaginative and creative ef- possibility of participation in cultural and political
forts over others but also partly constitute the categories
conversations. If we ask what features within Rorty's
of "novelty" and "originality," thus distinguishing narrative encourage these problematic construals, we
them both from "the old" and from eccentricity, find at least two interrelated sources of significance,
insanity, silliness, the quixotic, and so on. Indeed, as one deriving from Rorty's understanding of politics
many commentators have pointed out, the absence of and the political and one (which is more "method-
any "great" women artists or philosophers in the ological") concerning the relation, or absence of rela-
standard canon of Western culture reveals more tion, between theories and narratives and the prac-
about the ways in which categories like originality tices that they seek to inform.
and genius have been constructed than about the Starting with the second, one of the most puzzling
artistic or intellectual talents of women.8 Conversely, features of Rorty's redescriptive practice is the con-
it may be true that there are countless unanticipated spicuous gap between his formal pronouncements
and uncontrollable events that in one way or another regarding the heuristic value of particular genres, and
shape the course of our lives, but precisely what effect the content of his own writings. Formally, Rorty tells
they have on us and how we respond to them is us that certain sorts of books are particularly "rele-
neither fully predetermined nor entirely a matter of vant to our relations with others, to helping us to
"chance." Rather, these things are delimited both by notice the effects of our actions on other people"
material forces and by the horizons of our individual (1989a, 141). These are, first, books that "help us to
and social self-understandings-horizons that, im- see the effects of social practices and institutions on
portantly, simultaneously make meaning possible others" and, second, "those which help us see the
and limit the possible domain of meaning. effects of our private idiosyncrasies on others" (ibid.).
Rorty, of course, is not entirely unaware of these Beyond these very general categories Rorty places

959

This content downloaded from 137.222.114.241 on Fri, 14 Feb 2020 13:28:57 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Rorty, Liberalism, and Redescription December 1995

few restrictions (apart from the stipulation that theo- and comments on the written and oral work of students
ries and treatises are not well suited for these tasks) of different social origins, Bourdieu found "a simple
upon the types of books that might illuminate these and clearly visible relation" between a hierarchy of epi-
issues. Apparently anything from "the reports ... of thets (evaluative comments ranging from "simplistic,"
government commissions" to novels like Sister Carrie "silly," and "insipid" to "lively," "cultivated," and
and Black Boy are possible candidates for moral and "masterly") and a hierarchy of social origins, a ranking
political edification (ibid.). In accord with his antithe- based on "the importance of the cultural capital" that
oretical, antiuniversalist posture, however, he em- students inherited from their parents (determined by,
phasizes the import of narratives that focus upon e.g., the residence and profession of the pupils' par-
particular exemplars or offer what Clifford Geertz ents) (p. 197). Students from the middle classes (there
calls "thick description." He observes, for example, were no students from the lower classes, nor any male
that "ethnography," "concrete examples," "detailed students, since the files were taken from an all girls'
historical narratives" and "detailed description of school) and the provinces "were the prime target of
what unfamiliar people are like and . .. redescription negative judgments-and of the most negative
of what we ourselves are like" are all particularly among them, such as simplistic, servile or vulgar....
effective ways of enlarging our moral sympathies and Even the virtues which are attributed to them are
political understanding (p. xvi; idem 1991b, 175). negative too: academic, painstaking, careful, consci-
What is significant here is not just the observation entious" (pp. 198-99). By contrast, students from the
itself (which is, after all, common among those who class with the most cultural capital "almost entirely
question the practical benefits of transcendental the- avoid the most negative judgments, even in their
orizing) but rather the extraordinary disjunction be- euphemistic forms, as they do the petty-bourgeois
tween these recommendations and Rorty's own nar- virtues, and they most often find themselves granted
rative practice. For within the corpus of Rorty's the most sophisticated qualities" (p. 199). Moreover,
writings there is almost no "detailed description" of he found that in those instances where students from
"the effects of our social practices and institutions on different social origins received equivalent grades,
others" and there are no "detailed historical narra- the remarks were "all the more severe and more
tives" mapping the genesis and effects of those brutally expressed, less euphemistic, as the social
practices. In fact, it is striking that while Rorty ac- origins of the pupils decrease" (ibid.).
knowledges the existence of deep and disturbing As Bourdieu notes, not only technical aptitudes,
social problems (e.g., "the unending hopelessness such as the capacity to construct an argument or to
and misery of the lives of the young blacks in Amer- grasp the specialized vocabulary of particular au-
ican cities" [1989a, 191]), he never describes in any thors, but also personal and physical qualities consti-
detail the broader context or "social field" in which tute part of the disparate criteria of professorial
those problems are embedded, nor does he locate judgment. Especially in students' oral work, these
particular social practices that contribute to and sus- latter "'external' criteria" become prominent, and
tain these problems. here too there is a tight connection between students'
This failure to offer any detailed description of the social origins (as expressed in accent, body language,
social field or particular social practices leads inevita- and style of speaking) and the professor's remarks on
bly to a number of difficulties. It sustains, for exam- their work and talents:
ple, Rorty's problematic construal of contingency. As
The "external" criteria, most often implicit and even
we have seen, when he asserts that "man is always rejected by the institution, have even greater importance
free to choose new descriptions (for, among other in the remarks on oral work, since the criteria already
things, himself)" (Rorty 1979, 362, n. 7) or when he mentioned are compounded with all those concerning
speaks of poets and other original thinkers inventing speech, and, more specifically, accent, elocution and dic-
radically novel and incommensurate metaphors that tion, which are the surest, because the most indelible,
eventually become literalized, he verges on the adop- marks of social and geographical origins, the style of the
tion of an extreme form of voluntarism-one in spoken language, which can differ radically from written
style, and finally and above all the bodily 'hexis', manners
which, as Roy Bhaskar puts it, we are "always free to
and behavior, which are often designated, very directly,
choose any description" (1989, 176-77). This stance
in the remarks. (Bourdieu 1988, 200)
appears credible if we examine only the most palpa-
ble and formal types of social constraints. But once Bourdieu's point is clearly not that philosophy
we observe in narrative detail the role that linguistic professors or professors from other disciplines self-
and social practices play in constraining, disposing, and consciously conspire to reproduce in the academic
directing (even if not determining and compelling) our field the social hierarchies characteristic of the society
descriptions and redescriptions, Rorty's voluntaristic in which they live. Indeed, if this were the case, the
understanding of contingency and choice appears process could hardly be sustained in the way that it is
both facile and complacent. (Bourdieu 1988, 207-8). Rather, he claims that it is the
To take one example, the sociologist Pierre Bour- very way in which the academic field itself is struc-
dieu, in a study of modes of classification in French tured that "makes it unthinkable" for both professors
academic institutions, examined the individual files and their pupils to recognize "the social significance
of a professor of philosophy at a premiere superieure in of the judgments" (p. 205). Hence, both the mani-
Paris (1988, 194-225). Through the inspection of grades festly brutal epithets used to describe pupils' work

960

This content downloaded from 137.222.114.241 on Fri, 14 Feb 2020 13:28:57 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
American Political Science Review Vol. 89, No. 4

(epithets that, Bourdieu rightly observes, "would not argue, the evidence of history and everyday life
be permissible in ordinary usage") and the "compla- shows that these two spheres have never been simply
cency and freedom of symbolic aggression" are pos- divided but have always been intimately and "inex-
sible only because they operate in such a way as to tricably interrelated" as well (Pateman 1989, 121-22),
appear to be something other than they are (ibid.). As then the proper starting point for deliberating about
Bourdieu remarks, these spheres would seem to be precisely this evi-
It is because they think that they are operating a purely dence, rather than the artificial and abstract separa-
academic or even a specifically "philosophical" classifi- tion that Rorty defends. Indeed, it appears that in
cation . . . that the system is able to perform a genuine Rorty's effort to correct those writers who seek to unify
distortion of the meaning of their practices, persuading the public and private spheres via an abstract theoreti-
them to do what they would not do deliberately for "all cal synthesis, he simply inverts the problem by positing
the money in the world." It is also because they believe an equally misleading and abstract separation-one
that they are making a strictly academic judgment that
that, far from being a redescription of the public and
the social judgment which is masked by the euphemistic
private spheres, merely follows the time-honored lib-
implications of academic (or more specifically, philo-
eral practice of insisting solely on a division of these
sophical) language can produce its characteristic ef-
fect.... The transmutation of social truth into academic spheres, while ignoring their historical and conceptual
truth (from "you are a petty bourgeois" to "you work interrelations. The result is a description that is not in
hard but lack brilliance" [vous etes travailleur mais pas any substantive way a redescription and a proposed
brillant]) is not a simple game of writing which has no solution/compromise that remains detached from the
consequence but an operation of social alchemy which political realities that it seeks to inform.
confers on words their symbolic efficiency, their power This, of course, does not imply that the public/
to have a lasting effect on practice. (pp. 207-8) private distinction has no meaningful social or polit-
This example shows that although Rorty would like ical purpose but rather that philosophical solutions or
to separate clearly private projects of self-creation pragmatic redescriptions that clearly contravene the
from public projects of social justice, in the realm of lessons of history and everyday experience should be
everyday life these projects inevitably spill over received with skepticism. This is especially the case
and causally intermix with one another. For the when those solutions or redescriptions are ones that
middle-class student from the provinces whose reenshrine patterns of thinking that have historically
project of self-creation includes the desire to teach preserved and legitimated patriarchical or other op-
philosophy, these concerns are neither abstract nor pressively hierarchical forms of social relations. As
trivial nor easily eradicable. Indeed, they are the sort many feminists have observed, however, the classical
of thing of which deep personal conflicts are made, liberal dichotomy between the public and the private
for in this case it may involve either disavowing or spheres (founded on the idea that these two spheres
eradicating aspects of her identity or history or- are ontologically separate and unrelated, "but equally
having come to believe that she genuinely is "lacking important and valuable" [Pateman 1989, 120]) has
philosophical talent"-deciding that her preferred served historically as a mainstay of patriarchical rela-
project is not one for which she is suited (Bourdieu tions in both the public and private spheres.9 More-
1988, 206; see also p. 208). In either instance, how- over, to the extent that this philosophical separation
ever, the private project of self-creation cannot be eventually became internalized in individual and
neatly distilled from the social practices, mecha- social bodies, it had, as Pateman points out, the
nisms, hierarchies, and power relationships that op- mystifying and ideological effect of delegitimizing
erate, sometimes inconspicuously and sometimes those aspects of experience which denied the separa-
quite nakedly, in the public domain. To the contrary, tion (p. 131). For these reasons, many feminists have
private projects are always and unavoidably struc- advocated a conception or ideal of the social order
tured by public forces. that is markedly different from the classical liberal
Rorty would no doubt agree that in practice the line and Rortyian versions. This conception
between the private pursuit of self-creation and the
looks toward a differentiated social order within which
public pursuit of social justice is often fuzzy and that the various dimensions are distinct but not separate or
one of the principal aims of social science is to clarify opposed, and which rests on a social conception of
this fuzziness by identifying previously unrecognized individuality, which includes both women and men as
forms of cruelty in public institutions that constrain biologically differentiated but not unequal creatures.
the private pursuit of self-creation. Nevertheless, he Nevertheless, women and men, and the private and the
would-and does-insist that it is important to think public, are not necessarily in harmony. Given the social
of these two spheres as distinct and "forever incom- implications of women's reproductive capacities, it is
mensurable" universes and to make this the basis of surely utopian to suppose that tension between the
personal and the political, between love and justice,
our political deliberations. This response, however,
between individuality and community will disappear
fails to address the crucial question of why the public
with patriarchical-liberalism. (p. 136)
and private spheres should be viewed as linguistically
and conceptually exclusive and incommensurable The preceding analysis demonstrates the way in
categories if, as Rorty himself recognizes, history and which Rorty's reluctance to examine the complicated
human experience clearly indicates that they are not? interweavings of past and present social practices
In other words, if, as writers such as Carole Pateman leaves him without any analytic resources for either

961

This content downloaded from 137.222.114.241 on Fri, 14 Feb 2020 13:28:57 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Rorty, Liberalism, and Redescription December 1995

assessing the costs of those practices or indicating through the application of neutral, context-indepen-
how we might preserve, extend, criticize, or chal- dent criteria or theories? Here Rorty's pragmatic
lenge them. All of these endeavors presuppose that liberalism is at its weakest. For although his claims
we first have some understanding of how social and about the impossibility of philosophically or theoret-
linguistic practices interact; of the various privileges, ically synthesizing "Nietzsche with Marx or Hei-
distinctions, and distortions that they enshrine; and degger with Habermas" may be convincing (1989a,
of the role they play in constituting our individual xiv), it is difficult to see how Rorty's description of a
and collective self-interpretations. This, of course, liberal utopia could operate as a starting point or
does not necessarily imply a return to grand theory provocative heuristic device for coming to grips with
or, a fortiori, to totalizing conceptions of society, but it current social and political dilemmas. For instance,
does imply an empiricism of sorts, namely, a willing- Rorty's insistence on a firm distinction between the
ness to examine closely how these practices devel- public and private spheres may usefully remind us of
oped, what their effects are, and how their benefits the obvious dangers of eradicating the distinction
and burdens are parsed among different individuals altogether, but it does nothing to answer the truly
and groups in society. In this regard, the recurring difficult question of how that distinction is to be
theme of powerlessness, along with the correspond- negotiated in practice. In current political debates
ing admission that we "have no clear idea of what to about abortion rights, prayer in the school, family
work for" (Rorty 1989a, 182), should not be construed leave, governmental regulation of the economy, wel-
as being out of tune with the more celebratory temper fare payments to the poor, domestic violence, and so
of Rorty's narrative. Rather, both motifs should be on, the issue under dispute isn't whether some
seen as natural consequences flowing from the type distinction should be drawn between those aspects of
of narrative that Rorty constructs, one that-ironical- life that are immune from governmental regulation
ly-implicitly shares the theorist's and traditional and those which are not (this is instead the common
philosopher's animus toward all forms of empiricism starting point of the debate) but where, how, and on
and detailed historical and sociological description.10 what basis that distinction is to be drawn.
Indeed, if we examine current ideological conflicts
in the United States, what is striking is the way in
REDESCRIPTION AND POLITICS which conservatives and liberals seek to defend dia-
metrically opposed agendas through appeals to
Let us turn now to Rorty's postmetaphysical vision of Rorty-like distinctions between the public and private
liberalism. Rorty's redescription of classical liberal spheres.'1 Broadly speaking, conservatives view mar-
thought proceeds, as we have seen, through a nonra- kets and economic affairs generally as the realm of
tionalist, nonuniversalist redescription of the hopes freedom, autonomy, innovation, and self-creation.
and aims of a liberal society. The key maneuver in They accept economic inequality as an unfortunate
this redescription is his recommendation that philos- but inevitable effect of free markets, arguing that
ophers and political theorists drop their efforts to fuse whatever cruelties the market may inflict on individ-
theoretically the impulses for self-creation and jus- uals, such cruelties are still less severe than those that
tice. Instead, they should be content to recognize the would result from governmental efforts to regulate
import and legitimacy of both impulses, while care- economic affairs and redistribute wealth. On the
fully circumscribing the domain in which each is other hand, they argue that cultural, moral, educa-
allowed to flourish. By insisting on a firm distinction tional, and lifestyle issues are issues of public con-
between the public and private spheres, Rorty con- cern; for without a consensus on basic moral and
tends that hopelessly irreconcilable philosophical dis- cultural questions, civility, decency, and public life
putes can be transformed into concrete practical ques- in general cannot be sustained. Conversely, liberals
tions about how best to balance the incommensurable contend that these same cultural, moral, educational
demands for self-creation and human solidarity. and lifestyle issues belong in the private sphere, the
Striking adequate compromises between these two sphere of negative freedom, autonomy, irony, and
demands is, Rorty inveighs, the most important self-creation. They maintain that questions of moral
practical issue in liberal societies, but the skills re- belief, lifestyle choice, and the like are quintessen-
quired to negotiate such compromises are quite dif- tially private questions and thus should remain free
ferent from those of the theorist or traditional philos- from state control, regulation, and coercion. By con-
opher. trast, the demands of justice and the obligation to
In examining this redescription, we might begin by minimize cruelty requires more control over eco-
posing the sort of instrumental, pragmatist questions nomic affairs and the distribution of wealth than an
that Rorty himself encourages us to ask: What is the unregulated market provides. Moreover, they argue
practical benefit of this redescription? Does it illumi- that civility, decency, and civic-mindedness are best
nate or help us to resolve concrete social or political preserved not through the institution of moral and
questions? Does it, in the spirit of Dewey, help us to cultural orthodoxy but by ensuring humane living
determine or usefully consider which social practices conditions and attenuating extreme economic in-
we must preserve, cultivate, or extend and which we equalities.
must refashion or jettison-especially, once we have This brief sketch of current political conflict illus-
dispensed with the hope of solving these questions trates the severe practical limits of Rorty's redescrip-

962

This content downloaded from 137.222.114.241 on Fri, 14 Feb 2020 13:28:57 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
American Political Science Review Vol. 89, No. 4

tion of classical liberalism. Not only does his pro- influence, and the like" (1989a, 63, 66-67). Such
posed separation of the public and private spheres statements may, as far as they go, be true, but they
fail to provide a clear alternative to or exit from elide all the troublesome questions about the partic-
current ideological combat, but it fails even to be a ular measures required to realize these abstract aims.
redescription in the strict sense of the word. As we Can one, for instance, seriously hope to maximize the
have seen, both conservatives and liberals already quality of education and educational opportunities
appeal to distinctions identical to Rorty's own, yet without improving teacher-to-student ratios, without
they make these appeals in defense of diametrically paying teachers salaries comparable to those in other
opposed social and political policies. Hence, Rorty's respected professions, without increasing the num-
distinctions between autonomy and justice, self-cre- ber of days a year that children are sent to school and
ation and human solidarity, private narcissism and without providing the necessary equipment for in-
public pragmatism are better understood as restate- struction?12 And if not, how does one finance these
ments of positions that both conservatives and liber- reforms in an age of fiscal crisis and increasing voter
als endorse, the difference being that they interpret distrust of government generally? In short, Rorty's
these distinctions in very different ways. utopian dream of "building new and magnificently
Rorty would surely reply that only someone still equipped schools in the inner cities" may be an
under the spell of metaphysics and theology could honorable one (p. 7); but this only raises further and
demand something more than the narrative that he considerably more contentious questions about the
provides, for only such a person believes that there types of political, economic, cultural, and institu-
are things like a special method or general a priori tional transformations that might be required to make
principles that determine what counts as rational or this utopia a reality and about the forms of collective
moral action in particular circumstances. As a prag- action that are likely to be the most effective instru-
matist, however, he cannot-and need not-appeal ments of such changes.
to any neutral, context-independent principles or These, of course, are only a few of the many issues
criteria for determining the outcome of specific con- that arise as soon as one moves from the level of
flicts. At most, he can recommend a possible locus of abstract sentiments to the terrain of social and polit-
public deliberation while supplementing this recom- ical action, yet Rorty's narrative repeatedly stops
mendation with a narrative describing its potential short of any serious or systematic exploration of
benefits and the potential dangers of competing al- them. In place of a detailed interpretation of the social
ternatives. In politics, as in other areas of inquiry, the context and genesis of problems like the "crisis in
loyal pragmatist construes "rational" or "just" poli- education," Rorty offers sweeping and unsupported
cies as those which emerge as a result of "undistorted generalizations about "an increasingly greedy and
communication" or "free and open encounters of heartless American middle-class" that lets "the qual-
present linguistic practices and other practices with ity of education a child receives become proportional
suggestions for new practices" (Rorty 1989a, 60, 67). to the assessed value of its' parents real estate,"3 or
The actual resolution of particular conflicts can thus that "is unwilling to pay the taxes necessary to give
occur only through free-and-open public delibera- poor blacks a decent education and a chance in life"
tions, not through the development of ahistorical (1989b, 7; idem 1990b, 642). Such claims are them-
theories of morality, politics, or justice. selves deeply contentious, yet even if one grants that
This response might be credible if Rorty either middle-class greed and racism are indeed part of the
convincingly demonstrated that "undistorted com- problem, this too would seem to require further
munication" or "free-and-open encounters" were in- analysis and interpretation: Is the American middle
deed accurate descriptions of current political dis- class as fully unitary as Rorty assumes, or is it a
course in America or if he offered detailed analyses of complex collection of different social groups and
current impediments to such encounters, along with communities (white, African-American, Asian-Amer-
proposals for curbing or remedying them. But Rorty ican, urban and rural, northern and southern, male
rejects both of these options. He concedes openly and female, white-collar and blue-collar, Christian,
that for all of American liberalism's virtues, there is Jew, and Muslim) with disparate and frequently
still a clear and undeniable gulf between the ideal of conflicting interests, sensibilities, and social sympa-
free-and-open encounters and current political reali- thies? Was it just a matter of "chance" or "accident"
ties. Yet he also fails to examine those social practices that this class, or segments of this class, became
and institutions that inhibit the development of a increasingly greedy, selfish, and racist during the
more free, open, inclusive, and democratic public past 15 years? Was this a matter of "choice"? And if
discourse. Instead, he offers vague suggestions that not, what are the social, political, economic, institu-
circumvent entirely the difficult practical issues. For tional, and historical sources of this shift in social
example, he says that "discoveries about who is sensibilities? Unfortunately, Rorty never pursues
being made to suffer can be left to the workings of a these questions. Instead, he quickly closes off the
free press, free universities, and enlightened public conversation by declaring that "it seems to me a fact
opinion" and that "the only way to avoid perpetuat- [that] we need no fancier theoretical notions than
ing cruelty within social institutions is by maximizing 'greed', 'selfishness', and 'racial prejudice' to explain
the quality of education, freedom of the press, edu- these phenomena. .. . When I am told that to appre-
cational opportunity, opportunities to exert political ciate the significance of these facts I need a deeper

963

This content downloaded from 137.222.114.241 on Fri, 14 Feb 2020 13:28:57 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Rorty, Liberalism, and Redescription December 1995

understanding of, for example, ernist bourgeois


the liberalism"
discourses (1991a, 197-202) and,
ofmore re-
power
cently, as a "liberal utopia." In a recent essay, however, he
of late capitalism, I am incredulous" (1990b, 642).
expresses regrets about his use of the term postmodern (which,
Here again, Rorty's legitimate suggestion (that
following Jean-Franqois Lyotard, he defines as "distrust of
there is a point at which further analysis of pressing metanarratives"), primarily because it is now "so over-used
social problems can become an evasion of, or substi- that it is causing more trouble than it is worth" (1991b, 1).
tute for, rather than a supplement to, political action) 2. Using case studies from the history of science, I have
obscures the larger question of whether his remark- offered such an argument (Topper 1994, chap. 1). It should be
noted that if (pace Rorty) it is sometimes possible to argue for
ably vague proposals, along with his global claims
or against the introduction of a new vocabulary, then the
about the causes of current social dilemmas, are crucial question becomes one of deciding when, in the course
accurate, compelling, or pragmatically useful (in Ror- of an ongoing exchange, it may become unreasonable or
ty's own sense of identifying a "pressure point for absurd to continue arguing. As Jacques Bouveresse has
initiating change" [1990b, 643]). As I have argued, rightly stated: "II nest pas contestable qu'il arrive en philos-
ophie, comme d'ailleurs 6galement dans n'importe quelle
Rorty's recommendations not only fail to help iden-
autre entreprise intellectuelle, un moment oa il est deraison-
tify pressure points for change, they represent a flight nable et absurd de vouloir continuer a argumenter.... Mais
from that very task. In this respect, his original la difficulty est, comme toujours, de reconnaitre le point oil
Deweyan ambition of transforming philosophy into l'on doit s'arrfter" (1992, 47).
3. As Rorty explains, humiliation is a particularly devas-
an instrument of moral and political change-of
tating form of nonphysical cruelty, one that is tied closely to
bringing it back into "the conversation of man- the ironist's preoccupation with redescription. Here, too,
kind"-is abrogated by his own reluctance and inabil- Rorty borrows from Judith Shklar's (1984) discussion in Ordi-
ity to explore precisely those questions which are nary Vices. For his account of humiliation and especially his
morally and politically urgent. Oddly, Rorty's preoc- reasons for thinking that irony and redescription must be kept
private (in part because they have the potential of humiliating
cupation with avoiding a return to foundationalism,
others), see Rorty 1989a, 90.
metaphysics, and Truth have left him so resistant to 4. Although Rorty himself never appeals to such argu-
all forms of systematic analysis that his alternative to ments, nonfoundationalists have also sought to answer the
foundationalism is in many ways every bit as aloof charge of relativism by pointing out that today many of the
tenets of liberal democracy are almost universally accepted as
from the complexities of ongoing social and political
principles of political legitimation, even if they are violated
issues as the foundationalist philosophy which he frequently in practice. This, they claim, makes the charge of
sought to replace. radical relativism moot as a practical issue. See, e.g., Taylor
1992, 38.
5. The first three chapters of Contingency, Irony, and Soli-
darity are "The Contingency of Language," "The Contingency
CONCLUSION
of Selfhood," and "The Contingency of a Liberal Communi-
ty."
To return to the questions I posed at the outset, I 6. For an even more explicit link between contingency and
hope to have shown that "redescription," as well as "chance events," see the "possible world" sketch of Heideg-
the broader Deweyan aim of reinvigorating social ger's life in Rorty 1990a. It should be emphasized that there is
an important difference between asserting, for example, that
science and philosophy, must involve something there was "no particular reason why this ocular metaphor
more than just overcoming foundationalism or theo- seized the imagination of the founders of Western thought"
retical hegemony. It also means creating a space for (Rorty 1979, 38) and simply declining to offer any reason(s).
the development of detailed portraits of our institu- 7. This dichotomy between voluntarism and determinism
has a corollary in Rorty's attempt to defend (1) the physicalist
tions and practices, of how they develop, of the
idea that "one day we will be able, 'in principle', to predict
effects they produce, and of the issues to which they every movement of a person's body . . . by reference to the
give form. In addition, this means recognizing that microstructures within his body" and (2) the existentialist
the absence of an Archimedean point implies that commitment to the idea of radical freedom (1979, 354, 376-
issues of power are always potentially at stake in 79). Interestingly, Rorty's effort to preserve both freedom and
determinism by claiming that these are different descriptions
constituting, sustaining, or transforming our social of a single event or bodily movement is remarkably similar to
practices. Rorty's own work is a testament to the fact Kant's attempt to reconcile moral freedom and natural neces-
that one can all too easily fuse sophisticated views sity by viewing them as both true under different aspects of
about epistemology and philosophical foundational- reality. See Bhaskar 1989, 164-65.
8. For a relevant discussion of this issue from the stand-
ism with political positions that are, however well
point of art history, see Parker and Pollock 1981. In political
intentioned, at best misconceived and at times self- theory, writers such as Carole Pateman have appropriately
stultifying. If we hope to avoid these problems, asked, "Why is Paine's reply to Burke's polemic against the
perhaps the approach to take would be to combine French revolution studied, but not Mary Wollestonecraft's
postmetaphysical insights on the status of knowledge earlier reply? Why have the early socialists, who were con-
cerned with relations between the sexes and new modes of
not simply with "thin," global stories about the past household organization, been dismissed as 'utopian'? Why,
but with detailed histories of practices and power. more generally, are none of the feminist theorists' writing
from the seventeenth century onward discussed, when the
most minor male figures are given their due?" (Pateman 1987,
2-3).
Notes 9. It should be emphasized that Rorty's intent is not to
preserve patriarchical or sexist social relations or modes of
I would like to thank Richard Ashcraft, Carole Pateman, Lyle behavior. On his account, cruelty is by definition a public
Massey. and Bert Dreyfus for helpful comments on an earlier affair, whether it occurs in the home, workplace, or anywhere
version of this essay. else. Nevertheless, his failure to examine the ways in which
1. Rorty describes his desired polity as both "postmod- the public/private distinction has operated historically as a

964

This content downloaded from 137.222.114.241 on Fri, 14 Feb 2020 13:28:57 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
American Political Science Review Vol. 89, No. 4

bulwark against not only against sexual (and hence civic) sirables du pragmatisme." In Lire Rorty, ed. Jean-Pierre
equality but also against gays, lesbians, and other minorities Cometti. Combas: Editions de lftclat.
raises the question of whether his version of the distinction Dreyfus, Hubert, and Harrison Hall. 1992. Introduction to
(which in its formal features is almost identical to the classical Heidegger: A Critical Reader, ed. Hubert L. Dreyfus and
distinction) is the most useful tool for advancing the ideals of Harrison Hall. Cambridge, MA: Basil Blackwell.
liberal democracy. Given the historical record, it would seem Dworkin, Ronald. 1977. Taking Rights Seriously. Cambridge:
incumbent on Rorty to show how his construal of the distinc- Harvard University Press.
tion would operate in practice to reduce sexual and gender Gutmann, Amy. 1987. Democratic Education. Princeton: Prince-
inequalities and to explain why this construal would be more ton University Press.
useful than the alternative versions proposed by recent fem- Habermas, Jurgen. 1987. The Philosophical Discourse of Moder-
inist writers. Compare Will Kymlicka's (1991) recent attempt nity. Cambridge: Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press.
to apply an interpretation of liberalism to current conflicts King, Jeff. 1990. "Ontology, Reflexivity, and Policy: Toward a
regarding the rights of minority cultures. Post-Cartesian Politics." Presented at the annual meeting of
10. In recent writings, Cornel West (1993a, 1993b) makes the New York State Political Science Association, Albany.
similar criticisms of Rorty. West contends, for example, that Kymlicka, Will. 1991. Liberalism, Community, and Culture. New
Rorty embraces "an aestheticized version of historicism in York: Oxford University Press.
which the provisional and variable are celebrated at the McCumber, John. 1990. "Reconnecting Rorty: The Situation
expense of highlighting who gains, loses or bears what costs" of Discourse in Richard Rorty's Contingency, Irony, and
and that he offers "'thin' historical narratives which rarely dip Solidarity." Diacritics 20:2-19.
into the complex world of politics and culture" (1993a, 23, 127; Nozick, Robert. 1974. Anarchy, State, and Utopia. New York:
see also West 1993b, 177). While the preceding analysis Basic Books.
strongly underscores these remarks, I would perhaps differ Parker, Rozsika, and Griselda Pollock. 1981. Old Mistresses.
with West on two issues. First, West implies that Rorty's New York: Pantheon Books.
errors are chiefly (contingent) ones of omission, that is, he Pateman, Carole. 1987. Introduction to Feminist Challenges, ed.
neglects thick, politically engaged historical description and Carole Pateman and Elizabeth Gross. Boston: Northeastern
fails to articulate the social and political implications of University Press.
specific social practices and institutional arrangements (for Pateman, Carole. 1989. The Disorder of Women. Stanford:
hints of stronger objections, see West 1993b, 177). I argue, Stanford University Press.
however, that Rorty not only fails to engage in detailed social, Rawls, John. 1971. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge: Harvard
historical and institutional analysis but lacks the conceptual University Press.
resources for such analysis. At a minimum, such an under- Rorty, Richard. 1979. Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature.
taking would require, if not a theory in Rorty's sense, at least Princeton: Princeton University Press.
a satisfactory (or prudent and plausible) account or (re)de- Rorty, Richard. 1983. Consequences of Pragmatism. Minneapo-
scription of power and power relations, something Rorty (like lis; University of Minnesota Press.
the classical pragmatists) not only omits but cannot develop Rorty, Richard. 1986a. The Contingency of Selfhood." London
without also revising considerably his understanding of con- Review of Books, 8 May, pp. 11-14.
tingency. Second, West, like other critics, tends to accent the Rorty, Richard. 1986b. "The Contingency of Community."
celebratory aspects of Rorty's narrative, criticizing it for its London Review of Books, 24 July, pp. 10-14.
inattentiveness to the everyday miseries and cruelties that Rorty, Richard. 1987. "Posties." London Review of Books, 3
punctuate the lives of so many Americans. I would maintain, September, pp. 11-12.
however, that such criticisms are incomplete, for they over- Rorty, Richard. 1989a. Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity. New
look the fact that Rorty's narratives contain both an effusive York: Cambridge University Press.
optimism and a deep and often fatalistic pessimism. Indeed, I Rorty, Richard. 1989b. "Education, Socialization, and Individ-
take it that any adequate assessment of Rorty's political uation." Liberal Education 75:2-9.
thought must account for the disconcerting shifts between Rorty, Richard. 1990a. "Diary." London Review of Books, 8
these binary poles. February, p. 21.
11. My sketch of ideological conflict is indebted to Jeff Rorty, Richard. 1990b. "Truth and Freedom: A Reply to
King's discussion (1990, 8-9). While King's analysis accents Thomas McCarthy." Critical Inquiry 16:633-43.
"the problem of the mutual intrusion or colonization of the Rorty, Richard. 1991a. Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth: Philo-
public and private spheres" (p. 7), my concern is to show the sophical Papers, Vol. 1. New York: Cambridge University
practical limitations of Rorty's redescriptive efforts, as well as Press.
his conceptual inability to deal with concrete social problems. Rorty, Richard. 1991b. Essays on Heidegger and Others: Philo-
12. For some recent efforts to discuss difficult and contro- sophical Papers, Vol. 2. New York: Cambridge University
versial issues of educational reform, see Gutmann 1987 and Press.
Barber 1992. Rorty, Richard. 1992. "Heidegger, Contingency, and Pragma-
13. The claim that current social ills in the United States are tism." In Heidegger: A Critical Reader, ed. Hubert L. Dreyfus
due primarily to an increasingly greedy middle class is a and Harrison Hall. Cambridge, MA: Basil Blackwell.
recurring theme in Rorty's recent work. See Rorty 1990b, 642; Shklar, Judith. 1984. Ordinary Vices. Cambridge: Harvard
idem 1991a, 15, n. 29. University Press.
Shklar, Judith. 1989. "The Liberalism of Fear." In Liberalism
and the Moral Life, ed. Nancy Rosenbloom. Cambridge:
References Harvard University Press.
Taylor, Charles. 1992. "The Politics of Recognition." In Mul-
ticulturalism and "The Politics of Recognition," ed. Amy Gut-
Barber, Benjamin. 1992. An Aristocracy of Everyone: The Politics mann. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
of Education and the Future of America. New York: Ballantine Topper, Keith. 1994. Sciences of Uncertainty: Perspectives on
Books. Naturalism, Politics, and Power. Ph.D. diss. University of
Bhaskar, Roy. 1989. Reclaiming Reality. London: Verso. California, Los Angeles.
Bourdieu, Pierre. 1988. Homo Academicus. Stanford: Stanford West, Cornel. 1993a. Keeping Faith. New York: Routledge.
University Press. West, Cornel. 1993b. Prophetic Thought in Postmodern Times.
Bouveresse, Jacques. 1992. "Sur quelques consequences ind6- Monroe, ME: Common Courage.

Keith Topper is Visting Lecturer of Political Science, California State University,


Long Beach, Long Beach, CA 90840-4605.

965

This content downloaded from 137.222.114.241 on Fri, 14 Feb 2020 13:28:57 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms

You might also like