You are on page 1of 202

Encyclopedia of

ETHICS
Board of Consulting Editors

Harold Alderman Raymond Geuss Onora O’Neill


Julia E. Annas Alan Gewirth Derek L. Phillips
Annette C. Baier Mary Gibson Tom Regan
Kurt Baier Kenneth E. Goodpaster Abdulaziz Sachedina
Marcia W. Baron Russell Hardin John Sallis
Sissela Bok R. M. Hare Thomas M. Scanlon, Jr.
R. B. Brandt Virginia Held Samuel Scheffler
David Braybrooke Paul Helm J. B. Schneewind
Hsueh-li Cheng Terence Irwin Robert L. Simon
Antonio S. Cua Joseph J. Kockelmans Holly M. Smith
Eliot Deutsch Christine M. Korsgaard Hillel Steiner
Cora Diamond Norman Kretzmann Jeffrey Stout
Alan Donagan David Lyons Laurence Thomas
Gerald Dworkin Henry John McCloskey Susan Wolf
Abraham Edel Howard McGary David B. Wong
William K. Frankena Martha Nussbaum Allen W. Wood
Encyclopedia of
ETHICS
Second Edition

Lawrence C. Becker and Charlotte B. Becker


Editors

Volume I
A–G

Routledge
New York and London
To G.S.K.

Published in 2001 by
Routledge
711 Third Avenue,
New York, NY 10017

Published in Great Britain by


Routledge
2 Park Square, Milton Park,
Abingdon, Oxon, OX14 4RN

Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business

All other content and compilation, copyright © 2001 by Lawrence C. Becker and
Charlotte B. Becker.

All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilized in
any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter
invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or
retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publisher.

First edition published by Garland Publishing, New York, 1992.

Portions of Derk Pereboom’s “free will” were drawn from his introduction to Free Will,
edited by Derk Pereboom, Indianapolis: Hackett, ©1997, all rights reserved.
“deceit” © 2001 by Sissela Bok
“etiquette” © 2001 by Judith Martin and Gunther Stent
“moral terms,” “prescriptivism,” “slavery,” “universalizability,” and “weakness of will”
© 2001 by R. M. Hare

10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1

Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data

Encyclopedia of ethics / Lawrence C. Becker and Charlotte B. Becker, editors. — 2nd ed.
p. cm.
Includes bibliographical references and index.
ISBN 0-415-93672-1 (set : alk. paper) — ISBN 0-415-93673-X (vol. 1 : alk. paper) —
ISBN 0-415-93674-8 (vol. 2 : alk. paper) — ISBN 0-415-93675-6 (vol. 3 : alk. paper)
1. Ethics — Encyclopedias. I. Becker, Lawrence C. II. Becker, Charlotte B., 1944 –

BJ63 .E45 2001


170'.3 — dc21
2001019657
Contents

Volume I

Introduction and Acknowledgments vii


Note on Use ix
List of Entries xi
Contributors and Editors xix

A–G Entries 1

Volume II

H–O Entries 643

Volume III

P–W Entries 1267

Subject Index 1833


Citation Index 1955
This page intentionally left blank
Introduction and Acknowledgments

In this new edition, the Encyclopedia of Ethics has been substantially revised, and it
has been expanded by more than 30 percent. Its intended audience remains the same:
scholars, university students, and readers with a serious interest in philosophy. Its aims
with respect to subject matter remain the same: coverage of ethical theory as pursued
among English-speaking philosophers. Its 326 distinguished contributors (see the list
of Contributors and Editors) are authorities in their fields. The Encyclopedia’s content
(see List of Entries) was again designed through wide consultation, and its 581 signed
entries were peer reviewed. In addition, the encyclopedic apparatus has been improved
in various ways, most notably by the inclusion of references to other entries, set in
SMALL CAPITAL LETTERS, within the text of each entry. There are two indexes: a subject
index and a citation index.
The emphasis in this edition, as in the first, is on ethical theory. But as before, there
are entries on metaethics, applied ethics, and ethical issues that are especially important
to theory, as well as biographical entries on figures who have made significant contri-
butions to theory. There are thus entries on abortion, animals, blackmail, homicide, the
Holocaust, racism, rape, sexuality, slavery, and many other contemporary moral issues
that have become crucial test cases for theory, but not on the whole panoply of topics
one might find in a work devoted to applied ethics. There are entries on various religious
traditions, and survey entries on the history of ethics, but again these entries were
commissioned and written with an eye to themes that are especially important to ethical
theory.
Since the publication of the first edition in 1992, the number of new reference works
in philosophy has grown exponentially. There is now a large assortment of dictionaries,
companions, and even encyclopedias devoted to various areas of philosophy, and of
course there is now the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. However, the original
aims and coverage of the Encyclopedia of Ethics have not been duplicated in any of
those new works. The treatment of ethical theory in this work, for example, is densely
populated with rather narrowly focused entries (e.g., pride, humility), many of which
are accompanied by broadly conceived surveys (e.g., virtue ethics, virtues).
As before, however, the scope of this encyclopedia is considerably broader than the
term “ethical theory” might suggest. Readers will find lengthy survey entries on the
history and current status of philosophical ethics in other areas of the world; major
traditions in religious ethics; the relation of philosophical ethics to technology, religion,
law, literature, and social, political, and economic systems and theories; the relation of
philosophical ethics to important contemporary social/political movements and prob-
lems; and the relation of philosophical ethics to other fields of philosophy. Moreover,
the editors have given careful attention to theories of rational choice and economic
analysis; feminist ethics; virtue theory; and moral psychology. The encyclopedia also

vii
Introduction and Acknowledgments

includes a twelve-part, multi-authored, 60,000-word history of ethics from the pre-


Socratics through the twentieth century.
Our aims in producing this new edition were not to expand the scope of the work,
but rather to deepen and otherwise improve its original design. In doing this, the editors
once again had the assistance of an outstanding Board of Consulting Editors. In con-
structing the new table of entries, we surveyed the authors who contributed to the first
edition and incorporated suggestions about the second edition from correspondence
and reviews concerning the first.
Almost all of the 435 entries from the first edition have been retained, but many
have been substantially revised, and all of them have been reviewed for needed revi-
sions. A few entries from the first edition have been dropped, but only because coverage
of their topics has been reorganized by a set of newly commissioned entries. Most of
the original entries have been revised in at least minor ways, and, where appropriate
and possible, their bibliographies have been updated. Peer reviewing of these revised
entries was done by the editors, and in a few cases where the authors are now deceased,
the editors have supplied updated bibliographies.
For the 150 new entries, the process of selecting topics and authors began with a
circular to the contributors to the first edition, asking for judgments about the list of
additional entries proposed by the editors, as well as suggestions for other entries and
authors. A strong consensus was reached fairly quickly. Once again the most serious
divergence of opinion concerned which living philosophers should have biographical
entries, and once again there was virtually no support for the editors’ view (no doubt
a selfish one) that the best policy would be to include no such entries. All new entries
were peer reviewed, either by one of the editors, by one or more of the consulting
editors, or by a larger pool of critics. In one case, on the author’s initiative, an entry
was circulated to several hundred specialists for comment.
The idea for this new edition, as for the first one, came from Gary Kuris, then of
Garland Publishing. He has since moved on to a grander position, Garland has been
acquired by Taylor & Francis and subsequently merged with Routledge, and the En-
cyclopedia of Ethics now appears under their distinguished imprint, much revised and
much expanded.
As they did with the first edition of the Encyclopedia of Ethics, the contributors,
peer reviewers, and consulting editors have made these volumes possible. We owe them
all a debt of gratitude. We handled the remainder of the pre-production work, assisted
by the cheerful and efficient efforts of Sharon Durham. The detailed, perceptive, and
elegant subject index was prepared by Cynthia Crippen.
All of us who have worked on this project hope for astute readers. They will under-
stand that no encyclopedia in philosophy can be complete or definitive, nor should it
try to be, for that would mean trying to stop the philosophical enterprise itself. They
will understand that no encyclopedia in philosophy should be used as a substitute for
philosophy, or as a substitute for a direct encounter with the work it describes. And
they will not fail, at the end of the first entry they read, to follow the references into
the labyrinth.
Charlotte B. Becker
Lawrence C. Becker

viii
Note on Use

Unlike the first edition, the entries in this revised edition are listed in word-by-word
alphabetical order. Spaces between the words in titles matter. Thus, for example, the
entry on Mo Tzu appears before the entry on motives. The List of Entries gives a con-
venient overview of the arrangement.
The dates given for people and events have been checked against standard biograph-
ical and bibliographical sources. Where standard sources differ from each other or from
the results of more recent scholarship, however, we have followed what appears to be
the prevailing view in recent sources, unless advised otherwise by our authors. This is
especially applicable to the entries on Greek and Chinese antiquity, where we have often
used approximate dates even though precise dates are listed in some sources. For the
modern era, such problems are fewer, but even here the reader should be wary. Sources
differ in minor ways. We are reliably informed, for example, that Richard Cumberland’s
year of birth was 1632, as we have given it, and not 1631 as many sources report.
We have not given birth dates for living figures, except in the titles of entries devoted
to them. But otherwise it has been our policy to insert birth and death dates at the first
mention of a historical person’s name in each entry. For works we have typically sup-
plied the date of first publication or, where that is not applicable, the date of composition
for nonrecent works. Some authors have naturally protested the resulting typographical
clutter, but we think readers will find the information worth the added reading effort.
Following general practice for encyclopedias, there are no footnotes, and parentheti-
cal references in the text have been kept to a minimum. In those few places where
citations are necessary, the page references are given in the relevant listing in the bib-
liography.
Within the text of an entry, a word or phrase set in SMALL CAPITAL LETTERS indicates
that there is an entry of that title elsewhere in the Encyclopedia. It does not constitute
a claim that the referenced entry is directly relevant to the topic under discussion. See
also references are included in a paragraph immediately following the entry’s text, prior
to the bibliography.
The choice of headwords for both topical and biographical entries is often problem-
atic. Where there is cause for confusion, the editors have provided appropriate cross-
references. In reference works, consistency in choosing headwords and then adhering
to them is of the utmost importance. Unfortunately, the consistent implementation of
one such choice fell through the safety net: the entry for Ibn Sı̄nā is listed under the
Anglicized form of his name (Avicenna), with a cross-reference from the transliterated
Arabic form, while the reverse is true of his fellow Islamic philosophers. The reader is
directed to the List of Entries for an overview of headwords and cross-references.
The Subject Index is an analytical index of topics and persons discussed in the text
of the entries. The Citation Index gives an author-by-author listing of writers, and some
editors, cited in the bibliographies of all 581 entries.

ix
This page intentionally left blank
List of Entries

Abelard, Peter Aquinas, see Thomas Aquinas


abortion Arendt, Hannah
absolutes, see moral absolutes arete, see excellence; virtues
absurd, the Aristotelian ethics
Abunaser, see Farabi, al- Aristotle
academic ethics atheism
academic freedom attention, see moral attention; moral perception
action Augustine, Saint
acts, see voluntary acts authenticity
acts and omissions authority
additivity problems autonomy of ethics
Adler, Felix autonomy of moral agents
aesthetics Averroes, see Ibn Rushd
Africa Avicenna
agency and disability Ayer, A. J.
agent-centered morality bad faith
agents, see autonomy of moral agents; idealized Baier, Kurt E. M.
agents Balguy, John
agnosticism bargaining
agricultural ethics Barry, Brian (M.)
akrasia, see weakness of will Beauvoir, see de Beauvoir
al-Farabi, see Farabi, al- Beccaria, Cesar [Bonesana], Marchesi di
alienation beneficence
altruism benefit-cost analysis, see cost-benefit analysis
American moral philosophy benevolence
amnesty and pardon Bentham, Jeremy
analogical arguments bioethics
analytic philosophy and ethics biological theory
anger blackmail
animals, treatment of Bradley, F[rancis] H[erbert]
Anscombe, G. E. M. Brandt, Richard B.
Anselm, Saint Brentano, Franz Clemens
anthropology bribery
anti-realism, see metaphysics and epistemology; Buber, Martin
moral realism; moral relativism Buddha
applied ethics Buddhist ethics

Note: Cross-references are in italics.

xi
List of Entries

Burke, Edmund consequentialism


business ethics conservation ethics
Butler, Joseph conservatism
Calvin, John constructivism
Cambridge Platonists contraception, see reproductive technologies
Camus, Albert contractarianism
capital punishment contracts
care conventions
casuistry cooperation, conflict and coordination
categorical and hypothetical imperatives cooperative surplus
causation and responsibility coordination, see cooperation, conflict and
censorship coordination
character correctional ethics
charity corruption
cheating cosmopolitan ethics
children and ethical theory cost-benefit analysis
China courage
choice, see deliberation and choice; rational choice cradle arguments
Christian ethics critical theory
Chu Hsi cruelty
Chuang Tzu Crusius, Christian August
Cicero, Marcus Tullius Cudworth, Ralph
circumstances of justice, see justice, circumstances cultural studies
of Cumberland, Richard
civic duties, see civil rights and civic duties Cynics
civic good and virtue Cyrenaics
civil disobedience Darwin, Charles
civil rights and civic duties de Beauvoir, Simone
civility death
Clarke, Samuel deceit
coercion definition, see persuasive definition
cognitive science deliberation and choice
coherentism democracy
collective responsibility Democritus
commensurability deontology
common good Descartes, René
common sense moralists desert, see merit and desert
communitarianism desire
community, see moral community, boundaries of determinism, see freedom and determinism
comparative ethics deterrence, threats and retaliation
competition Dewey, John
compromise dignity
computers dilemmas, see moral dilemmas
confidentiality, see secrecy and confidentiality dirty hands
conflict, see cooperation, conflict and coordination; disability, see agency and disability
international justice: conflict discounting the future
Confucian ethics discrimination
Confucius distributive justice, see justice, distributive
conscience Donagan, Alan
consent double effect

xii
List of Entries

Duns Scotus, John fittingness


Durkheim, Émile Foot, Philippa
duty and obligation forgery
Dworkin, Ronald forgiveness
economic analysis formalism
economic liberty, see liberty, economic forms of consciousness
economic systems Foucault, Michel
education, see moral education Frankena, William Klaas
Edwards, Jonathan free will
egoism freedom and determinism
elite, concept of, freedom of the press
Emerson, Ralph Waldo friendship
emotion Fuller, Lon
emotivism future generations
Engels, Frederick Gadamer, Hans-Georg
engineering ethics game theory
entitlements Gandhi, Mohandas Kamarchand
environmental ethics Gassendi, Pierre
envy gay ethics
Epictetus generosity
Epicureanism genetic engineering
Epicurus genocide
epistemology, see metaphysics and epistemology Gert, Bernard
equality Gewirth, Alan
ethical egoism, see egoism Godwin, William
ethical naturalism, see naturalism golden rule
ethics, see autonomy of ethics; history of Western good, theories of the
ethics government, ethics in
ethics and morality gratitude
etiquette Green, Thomas Hill
eudaimonia, -ism Grotius, Hugo
euthanasia groups, moral status of
evil guilt and shame
evolution Habermas, Jürgen
excellence happiness
excuses Hare, R. M.
existential ethics harm and offense
exploitation Hart, H. L. A.
externalism and internalism Hartmann, Nicolai
fairness hate
family hedonism
Farabi, al- Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich
fate and fatalism Heidegger, Martin
feminist ethics Hindu ethics
Fénelon, François historiography
Feuerbach, Ludwig history of Western ethics: 1. presocratic Greek
Fichte, Johann Gottlieb history of Western ethics: 2. classical Greek
fidelity history of Western ethics: 3. Hellenistic
fiduciary relationships history of Western ethics: 4. Roman
final good history of Western ethics: 5. early Medieval

xiii
List of Entries

history of Western ethics: 6. later Medieval intention


history of Western ethics: 7. Renaissance interests
history of Western ethics: 8. seventeenth and internalism, see externalism and internalism
eighteenth centuries international justice: conflict
history of Western ethics: 9. nineteenth-century international justice: distribution
British intolerance, see toleration
history of Western ethics: 10. nineteenth-century intransitivity
Continental intuitionism
history of Western ethics: 11. twentieth-century Islam
Continental Islamic business ethics
history of Western ethics: 12. twentieth-century Islamic ethics
Anglo-American Islamic medical ethics
Hobbes, Thomas Jainism
Holbach, Paul Henri Thiry James, William
Holocaust Japan
homicide Jefferson, Thomas
homosexuality Jesus of Nazareth
honor Jewish ethics
hope journalism
Hsün Tzu justice, circumstances of
human rights justice, distributive
humanism justice, international, see international justice:
Hume, David conflict; international justice: distribution
humility justice, rectificatory
Husserl, Edmund Kant, Immanuel
Hutcheson, Francis Kantian ethics
hypocrisy karma
hypothetical imperative, see categorical and Kierkegaard, Søren
hypothetical imperatives killing and letting die
Ibn Rushd King, Martin Luther, Jr.
Ibn Sı̄nā, see Avicenna land ethics
Ibn Tufayl Lao Tzu
ideal observer law and ethics, see legal ethics; legal philosophy
idealist ethics legal ethics
idealized agents legal philosophy
imagination, see moral imagination legitimacy
immoralism Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm
impartiality Leopold, Aldo
imperative, see categorical and hypothetical lesbian ethics
imperatives Levinas, Emmanuel
incontinence, see weakness of will Lewis, Clarence Irving
India liberalism
individualism libertarianism
inequality liberty
infanticide liberty, economic
information professions, see library and library and information professions
information professions life and death
innocence life, meaning of
institutions life, right to
integrity literature and ethics

xiv
List of Entries

Locke, John moral psychology


logic and ethics moral purity
love moral realism
loyalty moral reasoning
luck, see moral luck moral relativism
Lucretius moral rules
Luther, Martin moral saints
lying, see deceit moral sense theorists
Machiavelli, Niccolò moral status of groups, see groups, moral status of
MacIntyre, Alasdair C. moral terms
Maimonides, Moses morality, see ethics and morality
Malebranche, Nicolas mortality
Mandeville, Bernard motives
Marcus Aurelius Antoninus multiculturalism
marriage, see children and ethical theory; family; murder, see homicide
love; personal relationships Murdoch, Iris
Marx, Karl Murphy, Arthur Edward
Marxism mysticism
Marxism and Soviet communism, see Soviet ethics Nāgārjuna
mass media narrative ethics
materialism natural law
Mead, George Herbert naturalism
medical ethics naturalistic fallacy
medical ethics, historical nature and ethics
Mencius needs
mercy negligence
merit and desert neo-Kantian ethics
metaethics neo-Stoicism
metaphysics and epistemology neutral principles
military ethics Niebuhr, Reinhold
Mill, James Nietzsche, Friedrich
Mill, John Stuart nihilism
Mo Tzu non-human animals, see animals, treatment of
Montaigne, Michel de non-violence, see pacifism; violence and non-
Montesquieu, baron de violence
Moore, G. E. norms
moral absolutes Nozick, Robert
moral agents, see autonomy of moral agents; nuclear ethics
idealized agents nursing ethics
moral attention obedience to law
moral community, boundaries of Objectivism
moral development obligation, see duty and obligation
moral dilemmas Ockham, see William of Ockham
moral education offense, see harm and offense
moral imagination omissions, see acts and omissions
moral luck oppression
moral norms, see norms organic unity
moral perception ought implies can
moral pluralism pacifism
moral point of view pain and suffering

xv
List of Entries

Paine, Thomas proportionality


Paley, William Protagoras of Abdera
pardon, see amnesty and pardon prudence
partiality psychoanalysis
Pascal, Blaise psychology
passion public and private morality
paternalism public goods
Paul, Saint public health policy
peace, see war and peace public policy
Peirce, C. S. public policy analysis
perception, see moral perception Pufendorf, Samuel
perfectionism punishment
Perry, Ralph Barton puritanism
person, concept of purity, see moral purity
personal relationships racism and related issues
persuasive definition racism, concepts of
phenomenology Rand, Ayn
philosophical anthropology rape
philosophy of law, see legal philosophy rational choice
philosophy of religion rationality vs. reasonableness
phronesis Rawls, John
plagiarism realism, see moral realism
Plato reasonableness, see rationality vs. reasonableness
pleasure reason[ing], see moral reasoning; practical
Plotinus reason[ing]; rationality vs. reasonableness
pluralism, see moral pluralism reasons for action
police ethics reciprocity
political correctness rectificatory justice, see justice, rectificatory
political philosophy, see social and political reflective equilibrium
philosophy Reid, Thomas
political systems, evaluation of relationships, see friendship; personal relationships
pornography relativism, see moral relativism
possibilism religion
postmodernism religion, philosophy of, see philosophy of religion
power reproductive technologies
practical reason[ing] resentment
practical wisdom responsibility
pragmatism responsibility, collective, see collective
praxis responsibility
precedent retaliation, see deterrence, threats and retaliation
prescriptivism retributive justice, see justice, rectificatory
Price, Richard revenge
Prichard, H. A. revolution
pride Ricoeur, Paul
principlism right, concepts of
privacy right holders
private morality, see public and private morality rights
professional ethics rights, human, see human rights
promises risk
property risk analysis

xvi
List of Entries

risk aversion sport


Ross, W. D. Staël, Madame de
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques stakeholder analysis
Royce, Josiah Stevenson, Charles L.
Russell, Bertrand Stewart, Dugald
saints, moral, see moral saints Stoicism
Santayana, George strategic interaction
Sartre, Jean-Paul Suarez, Francisco
scepticism, see skepticism in ethics; skepticism in subjectivism
ancient ethics suffering, see pain and suffering
Scheler, Max suicide
Schelling, Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph von Sunnism
Schiller, Friedrich von supererogation
Schopenhauer, Arthur sympathy
Schweitzer, Albert Taoist ethics
Scotus, John Duns, see Duns Scotus, John Taylor, Charles
secrecy and confidentiality technology
self and social self technology and nature
self-control teleological ethics
self-deception temperance
self-defense terrorism
self-esteem theism
self-knowledge theological ethics
self-ownership theory and practice
self-respect Thomas Aquinas, Saint
Seneca Thomasius, Christian
sexual abuse and harassment Thomson, Judith Jarvis
sexuality and sexual ethics Thoreau, Henry David
Shaftesbury, 3rd Earl of threats, see deterrence, threats and retaliation
shame, see guilt and shame toleration
Shi’ism torture
Sidgwick, Henry tragedy
Singer, Marcus G. transcendentalism
situation ethics transitivity, see intransitivity
skepticism in ancient ethics trust
skepticism in ethics Tufts, James Hayden
slavery universalizability
slippery slope arguments utilitarianism
Smith, Adam value, concept of
social and political philosophy value, theory of
social contract vices, see virtues
social psychology violence and non-violence
social self, see self and social self virtue ethics
sociobiology, see biological theory virtues
sociology Vitoria, Francisco de
Socrates Voltaire
Sophists voluntarism
Soviet ethical theory voluntary acts
Spencer, Herbert Walzer, Michael
Spinoza, Baruch de Wang Yang-ming

xvii
List of Entries

war and peace Williams, Bernard


weakness of will wisdom
Weber, Max Wittgenstein, Ludwig
Weil, Simone Wittgensteinian ethics
welfare rights and social policy Wolff, Christian
Westermarck, Edward Wollaston, William
Whewell, William Wollstonecraft, Mary
wickedness women moral philosophers
William of Ockham work

xviii
Contributors and Editors

Mitchell Aboulafia. Professor and Chair of Philosophy, in Modern Medicine (5th ed.); editor of Bringing the
University of Colorado at Denver. Author, The Medi- Hospital Home. NARRATIVE ETHICS; SLIPPERY SLOPE
ating Self: Mead, Sartre, and Self-Determination, and ARGUMENTS.
other works in social theory and American and Conti-
John E. Atwell (1934–1995). Late Professor of Philoso-
nental philosophy. Editor, Philosophy, Social Theory
phy, Temple University. Author, Ends and Principles in
and the Thought of George Herbert Mead. MEAD.
Kant’s Moral Thought; Schopenhauer: The Human
E. M. Adams. Kenan Professor of Philosophy Emeritus, Character; Schopenhauer on the Character of the
University of North Carolina, Chapel Hill. Author, Eth- World: The Metaphysics of Will. General editor, Series
ical Naturalism and the Modern World-View; Philos- in Occupational Ethics. BRADLEY.
ophy and the Modern Mind; The Metaphysics of Self
Annette C. Baier. Professor of Philosophy Emerita, Uni-
and World; and A Society Fit for Human Beings. AU-
versity of Pittsburgh. Author, Postures of the Mind; A
TONOMY OF ETHICS; LEWIS; NATURALISM.
Progress of Sentiments: Reflections on Hume’s “Trea-
Harold Alderman. Professor of Philosophy Emeritus, tise”; Moral Prejudices: Essays on Ethics; and The
Sonoma State University. Author, Nietzsche’s Gift, and Commons of the Mind: The Paul Carus Lecture Series
other works in ethics, aesthetics, and continental phi- 19. Consulting editor. HUME; PASSION.
losophy. Consulting editor. ELITE, CONCEPT OF; LIFE,
Kurt Baier. Distinguished Service Professor of Philoso-
RIGHT TO; MACINTYRE; NIETZSCHE.
phy Emeritus, University of Pittsburgh. Author, The
Ernest Alleva. Philosophy, Smith College and Hampshire Moral Point of View; The Rational and the Moral Or-
College. MORAL DEVELOPMENT. der; and Problems of Life and Death. Consulting editor.
MORAL REASONING.
Roger T. Ames. Professor of Philosophy, University of
Hawaii. Author, books in Chinese and comparative Marcia W. Baron. Philosophy, Indiana University. Author,
philosophy; translator of classical texts; editor, Philos- Kantian Ethics Almost Without Apology; and articles
ophy East and West. CHUANG TZU; LAO TZU; TAOIST on crime and culpability, Kantian ethics and Hume’s
ETHICS. ethics. Consulting editor. LOYALTY; SUPEREROGATION.
Julia Elizabeth Annas. Regents Professor, Department of Brian Barry. Arnold A. Saltzman Professor of Philosophy
Philosophy, University of Arizona. Recent works in- and Political Science, Columbia University. Works in-
clude Hellenistic Philosophy of Mind; The Morality of clude Political Argument; Theories of Justice; Justice as
Happiness; Platonic Ethics Old and New. Consulting Impartiality; and Culture and Equality. EQUALITY; PO-
editor. ETHICS AND MORALITY; FINAL GOOD; SKEPTICISM LITICAL SYSTEMS.
IN ANCIENT ETHICS.
Margaret P. Battin. Distinguished Professor of Philoso-
Kwame A. Appiah. Professor of Afro-American Studies phy, University of Utah. Author, Ethical Issues in Sui-
and Philosophy, Harvard University. Author, Assertion cide; Ethics in the Sanctuary; The Least Worst Death.
and Conditionals; For Truth in Semantics; Necessary Co-author, Puzzles About Art and Ethical Issues in the
Questions; and In My Father’s House: Essays in the Professions. Co-editor, John Donne’s Biathanatos. SUI-
Philosophy of African Cultures. AFRICA; ANTHROPOL- CIDE.
OGY.
Charlotte B. Becker. Former music, catalog, and biblio-
Richard J. Arneson. Professor of Philosophy, University graphic instruction librarian. Author of general interest
of California, San Diego. Author of works on political articles and reviews. Co-editor.
philosophy. EXPLOITATION.
Lawrence C. Becker. Kenan Professor in the Humanities
John D. Arras. Porterfield Professor of Bioethics and Pro- and Professor of Philosophy Emeritus, College of Wil-
fessor of Philosophy at the University of Virginia. Au- liam and Mary; Fellow, Hollins University. Works in-
thor of articles on bioethics; co-editor of Ethical Issues clude Property Rights: Philosophic Foundations; Reci-

xix
Contributors and Editors

procity; A New Stoicism. Co-editor. GODWIN; MORAL RIGHTS AND CIVIC DUTIES; KING; RACISM AND RELATED
LUCK; NOZICK; PRIDE; PROPERTY; RECIPROCITY; SOCIAL ISSUES.
CONTRACT; WOLLSTONECRAFT.
R. B. Brandt (1910–1997). Late Professor of Philosophy
Hugo Adam Bedau. Austin Fletcher Professor of Philos- Emeritus, University of Michigan. Works include Eth-
ophy Emeritus, Tufts University. Author, Making Mor- ical Theory; A Theory of the Good and the Right; and
tal Choices; Thinking and Writing About Philosophy; Hopi Ethics. Consulting editor. IDEAL OBSERVER.
Death is Different. Editor, The Death Penalty in Amer-
David Braybrooke. Centennial Commission Professor in
ica: Current Controversies; Civil Disobedience. APPLIED
the Liberal Arts, Professor of Government and Profes-
ETHICS; BECCARIA; CAPITAL PUNISHMENT; CASUISTRY;
sor of Philosophy, University of Texas. Fellow, Royal
CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE.
Society of Canada. Works include Philosophy of Social
Charles R. Beitz. Professor of Government and Legal Science; Meeting Needs; Moral Objectives, Rules, and
Studies, Bowdoin College. Works include Political the Forms of Social Change; Natural Law Modernized.
Theory and International Relations; Political Equality: Co-author, Logic on the Track of Social Change. Con-
An Essay in Democratic Theory. Editor, International sulting editor. COMMON GOOD; CORRUPTION; INTER-
Ethics. Editor of the journal, Philosophy & Public Af- ESTS; NEEDS.
fairs. INTERNATIONAL JUSTICE: CONFLICT. Richard Bronaugh. Professor of Philosophy Emeritus and
Martin Benjamin. Professor of Philosophy, Michigan Adjunct Professor of Law, University of Western On-
State University. Author, Splitting the Difference: Com- tario. Co-founder and Senior Editor, Canadian Journal
promise and Integrity in Ethics and Politics. Co-author, of Law and Jurisprudence. CONTRACTS; PROMISES.
Ethics in Nursing. COMPROMISE; NURSING ETHICS. John Broome. White’s Professor of Moral Philosophy,
Robert Benne. Jordan-Trexler Professor of Religion, Ro- University of Oxford. Author, Weighing Goods; Ethics
anoke College. Author, The Paradoxical Vision: A Pub- Out of Economics; Counting the Cost of Global Warm-
lic Theology; Ordinary Saints: An Introduction to the ing. DISCOUNTING THE FUTURE; ECONOMIC ANALYSIS.
Christian Life. LUTHER; NIEBUHR. Taft Broome, Jr. Professor of Engineering, Howard Uni-
Robert Bernasconi. Moss Professor of Philosophy, The versity. Works include “Engineering the Philosophy of
University of Memphis. Author, The Question of Lan- Science” and “Engineering Responsibility for Hazard-
guage in Heidegger’s History of Being; Heidegger in ous Technologies.” ENGINEERING ETHICS.
Question. Co-editor, The Idea of Race; The Provoca- Charlotte Brown. Associate Professor of Philosophy, Il-
tion of Levinas; and Rereading Levinas. HUMANISM; linois Wesleyan University. Author of articles on David
LEVINAS. Hume’s Ethics and on the British moralists. BALGUY;
Lawrence Blum. Professor of Philosophy, Distinguished MORAL SENSE THEORISTS; PALEY; STEVENSON; WOL-

Professor of Liberal Arts and Education, University of LASTON.

Massachusetts, Boston. Author, Friendship, Altruism, Jacques Brunschwig. Professor Emeritus, University of
and Morality; Moral Perception and Particularity. Co- Paris—I. Author, Papers in Hellenistic Philosophy. Co-
author, A Truer Liberty: Simone Weil and Marxism. editor, Le Savoir grec and Passions and Perceptions.
ALTRUISM; CARE; PERSONAL RELATIONSHIPS; WEIL. CRADLE ARGUMENTS.

James Bohman. Danforth Professor of Philosophy at Allen Buchanan. Professor of Philosophy, University of
Saint Louis University. Author, Public Deliberation: Arizona. Author, Marx and Justice; Ethics, Efficiency
Pluralism, Complexity and Democracy; New Philoso- and the Market; Secession: The Morality of Political
phy of Social Science: Problems of Indeterminacy; Divorce. Co-author, The Ethics of Surrogate Decision
other work in critical theory, the philosophy of social Making; From Chance to Choice: Genetics and Justice.
science, and political philosophy. CRITICAL THEORY. JUSTICE, DISTRIBUTIVE.

Sissela Bok. Formerly, Professor of Philosophy, Brandeis Ann Bumpus. Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Dart-
University. Author, Lying; Secrets; A Strategy for Peace; mouth College. Author of “Actors Without Intentions:
Common Values; Mayhem; and Alva Myrdal: A The Double Phenomenon View” and “Aiming and In-
Daughter’s Memoir. Consulting editor. DECEIT. tending.” INTENTION.
E. J. Bond. Emeritus Professor of Philosophy, Queen’s Charles Butterworth. Professor of Government and Poli-
University, Kingston, Ontario. Author, Reason and tics, University of Maryland. Author, Between the State
Value and other works in ethics, value theory, aesthet- and Islam; “The Political Teaching of Avicenna.” Edi-
ics, and epistemology. GOOD, THEORIES OF THE; MA- tor and translator, Averroës’ Middle Commentary on
TERIALISM; PURITANISM; VALUE, CONCEPT OF. Aristotle’s Poetics. AVICENNA; FARABI, AL-; IBN RUSHD;
IBN TUFAYL.
Bernard R. Boxill. Professor of Philosophy, University of
North Carolina, Chapel Hill. Author, Blacks and Social Steven M. Cahn. Professor of Philosophy, City University
Justice and other works in moral philosophy. CIVIL of New York Graduate School. Works include Saints

xx
Contributors and Editors

and Scamps: Ethics in Academia. Editor, Morality, Re- theories of justice, democratic theory, and foundations
sponsibility, and the University: Studies in Academic of moral philosophy. DEMOCRACY.
Ethics. General editor, Issues in Academic Ethics. AC-
Maudemarie Clark. George Carleton, Jr., Professor of
ADEMIC ETHICS.
Philosophy, Colgate University. Author, Nietzsche on
Cheshire Calhoun. Professor of Philosophy, Colby Col- Truth and Philosophy. Co-editor, Nietzsche’s Day-
lege. Author, Feminism, the Family, and the Politics of break; Co-editor and co-translator, Nietzsche’s On the
the Closet: Lesbian and Gay Displacement. Editor, Genealogy of Morality. IMMORALISM.
What is an Emotion? POLITICAL CORRECTNESS. S. R. L. Clark. Professor of Philosophy, University of Liv-
J. Baird Callicott. Professor of Philosophy and Religious erpool. Author, The Political Animal; Biology and
Studies, University of North Texas. Works include In Christian Ethics; Civil Peace and Sacred Order; and
Defense of the Land Ethic; Beyond the Land Ethic; other works on Aristotle, animals, philosophy of reli-
Earth’s Insights; and book chapters and journal arti- gion, philosophical psychology, and neo-Platonism.
cles. CONSERVATION ETHICS; ENVIRONMENTAL ETHICS; PHILOSOPHICAL ANTHROPOLOGY.
LEOPOLD. C. A. J. (Tony) Coady. Gibson Professor of Philosophy
James Campbell. Professor of Philosophy, University of and Deputy Director of the Centre for Applied Philos-
Toledo (Ohio). Author, Understanding John Dewey; ophy and Public Ethics, University of Melbourne. Au-
Recovering Benjamin Franklin; and other works in thor, Testimony: A Philosophical Study, and other
social philosophy and the history of American Philos- works on political philosophy, ethics, philosophy of
ophy. TUFTS. mind, epistemology. DIRTY HANDS; TERRORISM.

Richmond Campbell. Professor of Philosophy, Dalhousie John M. Cooper. Stuart Professor of Philosophy, Prince-
University (Nova Scotia). Author, Illusions of Paradox; ton University. Author, Reason and Human Good in
Self-Love and Self-Respect. Co-editor, Paradoxes of Aristotle; Reason and Emotion: Essays on Ancient
Rationality and Cooperation. An editor of Canadian Moral Psychology and Ethical Theory. Editor, Plato:
Journal of Philosophy. EGOISM. Complete Works. FRIENDSHIP; HISTORY 2: CLASSICAL
GREEK.
Claudia Card. Professor of Philosophy, University of Wis-
David Copp. Professor of Philosophy, Bowling Green
consin, Madison. Author, Lesbian Choices and The
State University (Ohio). Author, Morality, Normativ-
Unnatural Lottery: Character and Moral Luck. Editor
ity, and Society. Co-editor, The Idea of Democracy;
of Feminist Ethics; Adventures in Lesbian Philosophy;
Morality, Reason and Truth; and Pornography and
On Feminist Ethics and Politics; and the forthcoming
Censorship. METAETHICS; SKEPTICISM IN ETHICS.
Cambridge Companion to Simone de Beauvoir. FIDEL-
ITY; LESBIAN ETHICS; MERCY. John Cottingham. Professor of Philosophy, University of
Reading. Author, Philosophy and the Good Life; Des-
Thomas L. Carson. Professor of Philosophy, Loyola Uni- cartes; The Rationalists; “Varieties of Retribution”;
versity of Chicago. Author, The Status of Morality; and “Partiality and the Virtues”; “The Ethical Credentials
Value and the Good Life. Co-Editor of Morality and of Partiality”; and other works on history of philosophy,
the Good Life; and Moral Relativism. BRIBERY. ethics, and philosophy of law. JUSTICE, RECTIFICATORY.
Hsueh-li Cheng. Professor of Philosophy, University of Antonio S. Cua. Professor Emeritus of Philosophy, Cath-
Hawaii, Hilo. Author, Empty Logic and Exploring Zen. olic University of America. Author, Dimensions of
Translator and commentator, Nagarjuna’s Twelve Gate Moral Creativity; Ethical Argumentation: A Study in
Treatise. Co-editor, New Essays in Chinese Philosophy. Hsun Tzu’s Moral Epistemology; Moral Vision and
Editor-in-chief, International Review of Chinese Reli- Tradition: Essays in Chinese Ethics. Co-editor, Journal
gion and Philosophy. Consulting editor. BUDDHA; BUD- of Chinese Philosophy. Consulting editor. CONFUCIAN
DHIST ETHICS; JAINISM; NAGARJUNA. ETHICS; HSUN TZU; WANG YANG-MING.
James F. Childress. Kyle Professor of Religious Studies Garrett Cullity. Lecturer in Moral Philosophy, University
and Professor of Medical Education, University of Vir- of St. Andrews. Author of essays in normative and
ginia. Author, Practical Reasoning in Bioethics. Co- meta-ethics. Co-editor, Ethics and Practical Reason.
author, Principles of Biomedical Ethics. PRINCIPLISM. PUBLIC GOODS.

Roderick M. Chisholm (1916–1999). Late Professor of Randall Curren. Associate Professor, Philosophy and
Philosophy Emeritus, Brown University. Author, Franz Education, University of Rochester. Author, Aristotle
Brentano and Intrinsic Value; Theory of Knowledge; on the Necessity of Public Education, and other works
Perceiving; Person and Object; The First Person; and in ancient, moral, legal, political, and educational phi-
On Metaphysics. Translator of Brentano. BRENTANO. losophy. Editor, A Companion to the Philosophy of
Education (forthcoming). MORAL EDUCATION.
Thomas Christiano. Associate Professor of Philosophy,
University of Arizona. Author, Rule of the Many: Fun- Norman Daniels. Professor of Philosophy, Tufts Univer-
damental Issues in Democratic Theory, and articles on sity. Author of Just Health Care; Am I My Parents’

xxi
Contributors and Editors

Keeper?; Justice and Justification: Reflective Equilib- Alan Donagan (1925–1991). Late Doris and Henry
rium in Theory and Practice; and other works on ethics Dreyfuss Professor of Philosophy, California Institute
and public policy. PUBLIC HEALTH POLICY; REFLECTIVE of Technology. Works include Choice: The Essential
EQUILIBRIUM. Element in Human Action and Spinoza. Consulting
editor. CONSCIENCE; DELIBERATION AND CHOICE; HIS-
Stephen L. Darwall. Professor of Philosophy, University
TORY 12: 20TH CENTURY ANGLO-AMERICAN; SPINOZA;
of Michigan. Author, Impartial Reason; The British
WHEWELL.
Moralists and the Internal ‘Ought’; and other works on
moral theory and on the foundations and history of Thomas Donaldson. Mark O. Winkleman Professor, Pro-
ethics. CAMBRIDGE PLATONISTS; CUDWORTH; HUTCH- fessor of Legal Studies, and Director, Wharton Ethics
ESON; SHAFTESBURY. Program, The Wharton School, University of Pennsyl-
vania. Co-author, Ties That Bind. JUSTICE, CIRCUM-
G. Scott Davis. Booker Professor of Religion and Ethics, STANCES OF.
University of Richmond. Author, works on medieval
and early modern ethics, ethics and religion, and the John Doris. Assistant Professor of Philosophy, University
just war tradition. HISTORY 5: EARLY MEDIEVAL; MYS- of California, Santa Cruz. SOCIAL PSYCHOLOGY.
TICISM. Gerald Dworkin. Professor of Philosophy, University of
N. Ann Davis. Professor of Philosophy, Pomona College. California, Davis. Author, The Theory and Practice of
Works include articles on abortion and self-defense, Autonomy; Euthanasia and Physician-Assisted Sui-
the doctrine of double effect, deontology, utilitarian- cide. Editor, Mill’s ‘On Liberty’. Consulting editor.
ism, and rights. ABORTION. PATERNALISM.

John Deigh. Associate Professor of Philosophy, North- Abulfadl Mohsin Ebrahim. Professor of Islamic Studies,
western University. Author, The Sources of Moral School of Religion and Culture, University of Durban-
Agency; and articles on moral and political philosophy. Westville (South Africa). Author, Abortion, Birth Con-
Editor, Ethics. GUILT AND SHAME; INNOCENCE. trol and Surrogate Parenting: An Islamic Perspective;
Organ Transplantation: Islamic Ethico-Legal Perspec-
Maurizio Passerin d’Entrèves. Chair of Philosophy, Uni- tives. ISLAMIC MEDICAL ETHICS.
versity of Cape Town. Author, Modernity, Justice and
Abraham Edel. Research Professor of Philosophy, Uni-
Community and The Political Philosophy of Hannah
versity of Pennsylvania; Distinguished Professor of Phi-
Arendt. Co-editor, Habermas and the Unfinished Pro-
losophy Emeritus, City University of New York. Works
ject of Modernity and Public and Private. COMMUNI-
include Method in Ethical Theory; Science, Ideology,
TARIANISM.
and Value; Aristotle and His Philosophy. Consulting
Ronald de Sousa. Professor of Philosophy, University of editor. NATURE AND ETHICS; PERRY; VALUE, THEORY OF.
Toronto. Author, The Rationality of Emotion. Interests Paul Edwards. New School University; Professor of Phi-
include Greek philosophy, cognitive science, ethics, losophy Emeritus, Brooklyn College. Author, The Logic
philosophy of biology. EMOTION. of Moral Discourse; Heidegger and Death; Reincar-
Eliot Deutsch. Professor of Philosophy, University of Ha- nation: A Critical Examination. Editor-in-Chief, The
waii, Manoa. Editor, Philosophy East and West. Works Encyclopedia of Philosophy (1967). Editor, Voltaire’s
include Personhood, Creativity and Freedom and Stud- Philosophical Writing and Immortality. RUSSELL; VOL-
ies in Comparative Aesthetics. Translator of the Bha- TAIRE.
gavad Gita. Consulting editor. Rem B. Edwards. Lindsay Young Professor of Humani-
Lewis Anthony Dexter (1915–1995). Held Visiting Pro- ties Emeritus, University of Tennessee. Author, Bio
fessorships at several universities and state government Ethics; Religious Values and Valuations; What Caused
positions in Massachusetts. Author, “Scandals and the Big Bang? EDWARDS; JEFFERSON.
Scandalization” (Encyclopedia of American Political Gerard Elfstrom. Professor of Philosophy, Auburn Uni-
History). CORRUPTION. versity. Author, Moral Issues and Multinational Cor-
Cora Diamond. William R. Kenan, Jr. Professor of Phi- porations; New Challenges for Political Philosophy;
losophy, University of Virginia. Author, The Realistic and International Ethics: A Reference Handbook. Co-
Spirit: Wittgenstein, Philosophy, and the Mind. Editor, author, Military Ethics. COSMOPOLITAN ETHICS; HONOR;
MILITARY ETHICS.
Wittgenstein’s Lectures on the Foundations of Mathe-
matics. Consulting editor. ANSCOMBE; INTEGRITY; Anthony Ellis. Professor of Philosophy, Virginia Com-
WITTGENSTEIN; WITTGENSTEINIAN ETHICS. monwealth University. Author of articles in a wide area
of philosophy, including political philosophy and phi-
Mary G. Dietz. Professor, Political Science, University of
losophy of law. PUNISHMENT.
Minnesota. Works include, Between the Human and
the Divine: The Political Thought of Simone Weil. Ed- Eyjólfur Kjalar Emilsson. Lecturer in Philosophy, Uni-
itor, Thomas Hobbes and Political Theory. CIVIC GOOD versity of Iceland. Author, Plotinus on Sense-
AND VIRTUE. Perception: A Philosophical Study. PLOTINUS.

xxii
Contributors and Editors

Gertrude Ezorsky. Brooklyn College, City University of books and papers in moral and educational philosophy,
New York, Emerita. Author, Racism and Justice: The including Ethics; Thinking about Morality; and Per-
Case for Affirmative Action, and other publications in spectives on Morality. Consulting editor.
ethics and social philosophy. Editor, Philosophical Per-
spectives on Punishment and Moral Rights in the Allie M. Frazier. Professor of Philosophy and Religion
Workplace. DISCRIMINATION. Emeritus, Hollins University. Past President, Associa-
tion of Graduate Liberal Studies Programs. Editor,
Joel Feinberg. Regents Professor of Philosophy and Law Eastern Religious Thought. FEUERBACH; KARMA.
Emeritus, University of Arizona. Author of The Moral
Limits of the Criminal Law. HARM AND OFFENSE. Alfred J. Freddoso. Professor of Philosophy, University of
Notre Dame. Translator, Ockham’s Quodlibeta sep-
Fred Feldman. Professor of Philosophy, University of
tem; Part II of Ockham’s Summa logicae; Francisco
Massachusetts, Amherst. Author, Utilitarianism, He-
Suarez, On Creation, Conservation, and Concurrence;
donism, and Desert; Doing the Best We Can: An Essay
Francisco Suarez, On Efficient Causality. Author, ar-
in Informal Deontic Logic; and Confrontations With
ticles on Ockham. WILLIAM OF OCKHAM.
the Reaper. HEDONISM; LOGIC AND ETHICS.
John Martin Fischer. Professor of Philosophy, University Michael Freeman. Reader in Government, and Associate
of California, Riverside. Author, The Metaphysics of Director, Human Rights Centre, University of Essex.
Free Will: An Essay on Control. Co-author, Responsi- Author, Edmund Burke and the Critique of Political
bility and Control: A Theory of Moral Responsibility. Radicalism and other works on democratic theory, rev-
Editor, Moral Responsibility and God, Foreknowledge, olutions, human rights, and genocide. BURKE; OPPRES-
SION.
and Freedom. Co-editor, Ethics: Problems and Princi-
ples. DEATH; FATE AND FATALISM; FREEDOM AND DE- Samuel Freeman. Professor of Philosophy and Law, Uni-
TERMINISM.
versity of Pennsylvania. Editor and contributor, The
James Fishkin. Professor and Chair, Department of Gov- Cambridge Companion to John Rawls (forthcoming);
ernment, and Darrell K. Royal Regents Chair in Ethics Editor, John Rawls’s Collected Papers. Author, articles
and American Society, University of Texas at Austin. in political and legal philosophy. DEONTOLOGY; RAWLS.
Director, Center for Deliberative Polling. Author of
R. G. Frey. Professor of Philosophy, Bowling Green State
“Tyranny and Legitimacy”; “Democracy and Delibera-
University. Author, Interests and Rights; Rights, Killing,
tion”; “The Dialogue of Justice”; and other works in
and Suffering. Co-author, Euthanasia and Physician-
political theory and political behavior. BARRY.
Assisted Suicide. Editor, Utility and Rights and Liabil-
Richard E. Flathman. George Armstrong Kelly Memorial ity and Responsibility. ACTS AND OMISSIONS; HARE;
Professor of Political Science, The Johns Hopkins Uni- MANDEVILLE; TORTURE.
versity. Works include Willful Liberalism; Thomas
Hobbes, Skepticism, Individuality and Chastened Poli- Marilyn Friedman. Professor of Philosophy, Washington
tics; Reflections of a Would-Be Anarchist; The Philos- University. Author, What Are Friends For? Feminist
ophy and Politics of Freedom; and Toward a Liberal- Perspectives on Personal Relationships and Moral The-
ism. LIBERALISM. ory; Autonomy, Gender, Politics (forthcoming). Co-
author, Political Correctness: For and Against. PARTI-
Elizabeth Flower (1913–1995). Late Professor Emerita ALITY.
of Philosophy, University of Pennsylvania. Author of
works in moral and legal philosophy. Co-author, A His- Manfred S. Frings. Emeritus Professor of Philosophy,
tory of Philosophy in America and Morality, Philoso- DePaul University. Works include: Max Scheler; The
phy and Practice. STEWART. Mind of Max Scheler: The First Comprehensive Guide
Based on the Complete Works. Editor, The Collected
Thomas R. Flynn. Samuel Candler Dobbs Professor of
Works of Max Scheler. Co-editor, The Collected Works
Philosophy, Emory University. Author of Sartre and
of M. Heidegger. SCHELER.
Marxist Existentialism; Sartre, Foucault and Historical
Reason; and other works on contemporary continental Thomas J. Froehlich. Professor, Library and Information
philosophy. ABSURD, THE; AUTHENTICITY; BAD FAITH; Science, Kent State University. Author, Survey and
DE BEAUVOIR; SARTRE. Analysis of the Major Ethical and Legal Issues Facing
Nicholas Fotion. Professor of Philosophy, Emory Univer- Library and Information Services. LIBRARY AND INFOR-
sity. Author, Military Ethics: Looking Toward the Fu- MATION PROFESSIONS.

ture, and works in medical ethics, ethical theory, and


Jack Fruchtman, Jr. Professor of Political Science, Tow-
philosophy of language. Co-author, Military Ethics:
son University. Author, Thomas Paine and the Religion
Guidelines for Peace and War. HONOR; MILITARY
of Nature; Thomas Paine: Apostle of Freedom; studies
ETHICS.
of Joseph Priestley, Richard Price, Thomas Reid,
William K. Frankena (1908–1994). Late Professor Emer- Thomas Hardy, Thomas Spence, and Helen Maria Wil-
itus of Philosophy, University of Michigan. Author of liams. PAINE.

xxiii
Contributors and Editors

Dwight Furrow. Philosophy, San Diego Mesa College. Have a Conscience?”; “Business Ethics and Stake-
Author, Against Theory: Continental and Analytic holder Analysis”; “Conscience and its Counterfeits in
Challenges in Moral Philosophy. POSTMODERNISM. Organizational Life.” Consulting editor. BUSINESS ETH-
ICS; STAKEHOLDER ANALYSIS.
J. L. A. Garcia. Professor, Philosophy Department, Rut-
gers University, New Brunswick. MORAL ABSOLUTES; Samuel Gorovitz. Professor of Philosophy and of Public
PROPORTIONALITY; RACISM, CONCEPTS OF. Administration, Syracuse University, and Faculty
Newton Garver. Distinguished Service Professor of Phi- Scholar in Bioethics, State University of New York
losophy, State University of New York at Buffalo. Au- Upstate Medical University. Works include Doctors’
thor, This Complicated Form of Life and Derrida and Dilemmas and Drawing the Line: Life, Death, and Eth-
Wittgenstein. Co-editor, Naturalism and Rationality ical Choices in an American Hospital. BIOETHICS.
and Justice, Law and Violence. CIVILITY; GANDHI; PAC- J. C. B. Gosling. Retired Principal, St. Edmund Hall, Uni-
IFISM; SCHWEITZER. versity of Oxford. Works include Pleasure and Desire;
Bernard Gert. Stone Professor of Intellectual and Moral Plato; Plato’s Philebus; The Greeks on Pleasure; and
Philosophy, Dartmouth College. Author, Morality: Its Weakness of the Will. PLEASURE.
Nature and Justification. Co-author, Bioethics and Mo- James Gouinlock. Emeritus Professor of Philosophy,
rality and the New Genetics. ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY Emory University. Works include John Dewey’s Phi-
AND ETHICS; CHEATING; GENETIC ENGINEERING; IMPAR- losophy of Value; Excellence in Public Discourse: John
TIALITY; MORAL RULES. Stuart Mill, John Dewey, and Social Intelligence; and
Joshua Gert. Visiting Assistant Professor, University of Rediscovering the Moral Life. Past President, Society
Missouri at Columbia. Author of articles on rationality for the Advancement of American Philosophy. DEWEY.
and reasons. REASONS FOR ACTION. Carol C. Gould. Professor of Philosophy, Stevens Insti-
Raymond Geuss. Professor of Political Science, Colum- tute of Technology, and Adjunct Professor of Interna-
bia University. Author, The Idea of a Critical Theory tional Affairs, Columbia University. Author, Marx’s
and other works on ethics and political and social phi- Social Ontology and Rethinking Democracy. Editor,
losophy. Consulting editor. Beyond Domination and The Information Web. Co-
editor, Women and Philosophy. SELF AND SOCIAL SELF.
Alan Gewirth. Edward Carson Waller Distinguished Ser-
vice Professor of Philosophy, University of Chicago. Timothy Gould. Philosophy, Metropolitan State College
Fellow, American Academy of Arts and Sciences. Works of Denver. Works include essays on Kant’s ethics and
include Reason and Morality; Human Rights; The Com- aesthetics; on Romantic and feminist accounts of cul-
munity of Rights; and Self-Fulfillment. Consulting editor. ture; on Mill, Emerson, and Nietzsche; and Hearing
RATIONALITY VS. REASONABLENESS; RIGHTS. Things: Voice and Method in the Writing of Stanley
Cavell. EMERSON; THOREAU; TRANSCENDENTALISM.
Mary Gibson. Associate Professor of Philosophy, Rutgers
University. Author, Workers’ Rights; “Contract Moth- James M. Gustafson. Professor Emeritus, Emory Univer-
erhood: Social Practice in Social Context.” Editor, To sity. Works include Ethics from a Theocentric Perspec-
Breathe Freely: Risk, Consent, and Air. Consulting ed- tive; Intersections: Science, Theology, Ethics; Protes-
itor. RISK. tant and Roman Catholic Ethics. CHRISTIAN ETHICS;
Joseph J. Godfrey. Associate Professor of Philosophy, JESUS OF NAZARETH; SITUATION ETHICS.
Saint Joseph’s University. Author, A Philosophy of Hu- Paul Guyer. Florence R.C. Murray Professor in the Hu-
man Hope, and works on hope and trust. HOPE. manities, University of Pennsylvania. Author, Kant and
Alan H. Goldman. Professor of Philosophy, University of the Claims of Taste; Kant and the Claims of Knowl-
Miami. Author, Moral Knowledge; The Moral Foun- edge; Kant and the Experience of Freedom; and Kant
dations of Professional Ethics; Justice and Reverse Dis- on Freedom, Law, and Happiness. Editor, Cambridge
crimination; Empirical Knowledge; Aesthetic Value; Companion to Kant and Kant’s Groundwork of the
and Practical Rules. PRECEDENT; PROFESSIONAL ETHICS. Metaphysics of Morals: Critical Essays. Co-translator
of Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason and Critique of the
Alvin Goldman. Regents’ Professor of Philosophy, Uni- Power of Judgment. SCHILLER; WOLFF.
versity of Arizona. Author, A Theory of Human Action;
Epistemology and Cognition; Liaisons: Philosophy Knud Haakonssen. Professor of Philosophy, Boston Uni-
Meets the Cognitive and Social Sciences; and Knowl- versity. Author, The Science of a Legislator and Natural
edge and the Social World. Co-editor, Values and Mor- Law and Moral Philosophy. Editor, Thomas Reid’s
als. ACTION. Practical Ethics; Enlightenment and Religion; and Tra-
ditions of Liberalism. CUMBERLAND; GROTIUS; NATU-
Kenneth E. Goodpaster. Koch Professor of Business
RAL LAW.
Ethics, University of St. Thomas. Works include, Per-
spectives on Morality; Ethics and Problems of the 21st Philip P. Hallie (1922–1994). Late Griffin Professor,
Century; Policies and Persons; “Can a Corporation Emeritus, of Philosophy and Humanities, Wesleyan

xxiv
Contributors and Editors

University. Works include Cruelty and Lest Innocent Moral Judgment, and other works in ethics and Kan-
Blood be Shed. CRUELTY. tian moral theory. DESIRE; MOTIVES.
Alan Hamlin. Professor of Economics, University of Steven Hetcher. Assistant Professor, Vanderbilt Univer-
Southampton (England). Author, Ethics, Economics sity School of Law. Works include “Creating Safe So-
and the State. Co-author, Democratic Devices and De- cial Norms in a Dangerous World” and “Burning
sires. Co-editor, The Good Polity. ECONOMIC SYSTEMS. Chrome from the One-way Mirror: The Emergence of
Jean Hampton (1954–1996). Late Professor of Philoso- Website Privacy Norms.” NORMS.
phy, University of Arizona. Author, Hobbes and the Thomas E. Hill, Jr. Professor of Philosophy, University of
Social Contract Tradition, and articles on social con- North Carolina, Chapel Hill. Works include Autonomy
tract theory, punishment, moral culpability, and liber- and Self-Respect and Dignity and Practical Reason.
alism. Co-author, Forgiveness and Mercy. HOBBES. AUTONOMY OF MORAL AGENTS; SELF-RESPECT.
Russell Hardin. Professor of Politics, New York Univer-
Margaret Holland. Associate Professor of Philosophy,
sity. Author, Collective Action; Morality Within the
University of Northern Iowa. Author of “Touching the
Limits Of Reason; One For All: The Logic Of Group
Weights: Moral Perception and Attention” and “What’s
Conflict; and Liberalism, Constitutionalism, and De-
Wrong with Telling the Truth? An Analysis of Gossip.”
mocracy. Consulting editor. COOPERATION, CONFLICT
MORAL ATTENTION; MORAL PERCEPTION; MURDOCH.
AND COORDINATION; GAME THEORY; RATIONAL CHOICE;
STRATEGIC INTERACTION; TRUST. Helen Bequaert Holmes. Independent scholar. Research
interests include assessment of new technology in re-
John E. Hare. Professor of Philosophy, Calvin College.
productive medicine. Editor, Feminist Perspectives in
Author, Plato’s Euthyphro; The Moral Gap. Co-author,
Medical Ethics; Issues in Reproductive Technology.
Ethics and International Affairs. Congressional Fellow,
REPRODUCTIVE TECHNOLOGIES.
American Philosophical Association, 1981–83. GOV-
ERNMENT, ETHICS IN. Sarah Holtman. Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Uni-
R. M. Hare. Emeritus Professor of Philosophy, University versity of Minnesota, Twin Cities. Works include articles
of Florida, Gainesville. Formerly White’s Professor of on moral, legal, and political philosophy, in particular
Moral Philosophy, Oxford. Works include The Lan- on Kant’s theory of justice. FIDUCIARY RELATIONSHIPS.
guage of Morals; Freedom and Reason; Moral Think- Brad Hooker. Philosophy, University of Reading (En-
ing; Sorting Out Ethics; and Objective Prescriptions. gland). Author, Ideal Code, Real World: A Rule-
Consulting editor. MORAL TERMS; PRESCRIPTIVISM; SLAV- Consequentialist Theory of Morality. SUBJECTIVISM.
ERY; UNIVERSALIZABILITY; WEAKNESS OF WILL.
Jasper Hopkins. Professor of Philosophy, University of
George W. Harris. Chancellor Professor of Philosophy,
Minnesota. Co-translator and commentator, Anselm’s
College of William and Mary. Author, Dignity and Vul-
works; translator of Nicholas of Cusa’s works. Au-
nerability: Strength and Quality of Character; Agent-
thored works include Hermeneutical and Textual Prob-
Centered Morality: An Aristotelian Alternative to Kan-
lems in the Complete Treatises of St. Anselm and A
tian Internalism. ARISTOTELIAN ETHICS; SELF-ESTEEM;
Companion to the Study of St. Anselm. ANSELM.
SELF-KNOWLEDGE.

Ross Harrison. Reader in Philosophy, University of Cam- Laurence D. Houlgate. Professor of Philosophy, Califor-
bridge. Author, Democracy; Bentham. WILLIAMS. nia Polytechnic State University, San Luis Obispo. Au-
thor, Family and State: The Philosophy of Family Law;
Joseph Heath. Professor of Philosophy, University of To- The Child and the State: A Normative Theory of Juve-
ronto. Author, Communicative Action and Rational nile Rights; Morals, Marriage and Parenthood: An In-
Choice. TAYLOR. troduction to Family Ethics. CHILDREN AND ETHICAL
Virginia Held. Distinguished Professor of Philosophy at THEORY.

the City University of New York, Graduate School and John Howes. President, Learningguild (Brunswick, Vic-
Hunter College. Works include Feminist Morality: toria, Australia). Formerly, Senior Lecturer in Philos-
Transforming Culture, Society, and Politics; Rights and ophy, University of Melbourne, and Professor of Phi-
Goods: Justifying Social Action; The Public Interest losophy, Cape Town. Works include Making Up
and Individual Interests. Consulting editor. MASS ME- Sentences and articles on Plato and Mill. CICERO;
DIA; MORAL PLURALISM.
GREEN; SENECA.
Paul Helm. Reader in Philosophy, University of Liver-
Donald C. Hubin. Associate Professor of Philosophy,
pool. Author, The Varieties of Belief; Eternal God;
Ohio State University. Works include “Parental Rights
other works in the philosophy of religion and episte-
and Due Process”; “The Moral Justification of Benefit/
mology. Consulting editor. CALVIN; RELIGION.
Cost Analysis”; “What’s Special About Humeanism”;
Barbara Herman. Professor of Philosophy, University of and “Hypothetical Motivation”. COST-BENEFIT ANALY-
California at Los Angeles. Author, The Practice of SIS.

xxv
Contributors and Editors

Paul M. Hughes. Associate Professor of Philosophy, in the Holocaust and other works in ethics and philos-
and Chair, Department of Humanities, University of ophy of mind. HOLOCAUST; HOMICIDE; INFANTICIDE.
Michigan-Dearborn. Author, “Temptation and the Ma-
Albert R. Jonsen. Department of Medical History and
nipulation of Desire”; “Paternalism, Battered Women,
Ethics, School of Medicine, University of Washington.
and the Law”; “Moral Anger, Forgiving, and Condon-
MEDICAL ETHICS, HISTORICAL.
ing.” ANGER; HATE.
Robert Welsh Jordan. Associate Professor of Philosophy,
Lester H. Hunt. Professor of Philosophy, University of
Colorado State University. Author of essays on phe-
Wisconsin. Author, Nietzsche and the Origin of Virtue;
nomenological value theory, Kafka’s and Brentano’s
Character and Culture; and articles on ethics, philos-
ethics, historicality in Husserl’s works, and philosophy
ophy of law, and philosophy in literature. ENVY; GEN-
of social sciences. HARTMANN.
EROSITY.
Lynn S. Joy. Professor of Philosophy, University of Notre
Thomas Hurka. Professor of Philosophy, University of Dame. Author, Gassendi the Atomist and articles in the
Calgary. Author, Perfectionism; Virtue, Vice, and philosophy of science and the history of ethics. GAS-
Value; and articles on punishment, future generations, SENDI.
and value theory. FUTURE GENERATIONS; PERFECTION-
ISM. Charles H. Kahn. Professor of Philosophy, University of
Pennsylvania. Author, Anaximander and the Origins of
Kenneth K. Inada. Emeritus Professor of Philosophy, Greek Cosmology; The Verb ‘Be’ in Ancient Greek; The
State University of New York, Buffalo. Author, Nagar- Art and Thought of Heraclitus; Plato and the Socratic
juna, and other works on Asian and comparative phi- Dialogue. HISTORY 1: PRESOCRATIC GREEK.
losophy. Translator, The Logic of Unity. General editor,
Guide to Buddhist Philosophy. JAPAN. Morris B. Kaplan. Associate Professor of Philosophy,
Purchase College in the State University of New York.
Terence Irwin. Susan Linn Sage Professor of Philosophy Author, Sexual Justice: Democratic Citizenship and the
and Humane Letters, Cornell University. Works in- Politics of Desire; “Intimacy and Equality: The Ques-
clude Aristotle’s First Principles; Classical Thought; tions of Lesbian and Gay Marriage”; and Sodom on the
Plato’s Ethics; translations with notes of Plato’s Gor- Thames: Policing Male Desire in Late Victorian Lon-
gias and Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. Consulting don (forthcoming). GAY ETHICS.
editor. ARISTOTLE; PLATO; SOCRATES.
Gregory S. Kavka (1947–1994). Late Professor of Phi-
John Claiborne Isbell. Department of French and Italian, losophy, University of California, Irvine. Author, works
Indiana University, Bloomington. Author, The Birth of on Hobbes, nuclear ethics. BRANDT; DETERRENCE,
European Romanticism. STAEL. THREATS AND RETALIATION; NUCLEAR ETHICS.

Alison M. Jaggar. Professor of Philosophy and Women’s John Kekes. Professor of Philosophy, State University of
Studies, University of Colorado at Boulder. Author, New York, Albany. Author, Against Liberalism; A Case
Feminist Politics and Human Nature; Living With for Conservatism; Pluralism in Philosophy: Changing
Contradictions: Controversies In Feminist Ethics. Co- the Subject. BENEVOLENCE; CONSERVATISM; HAPPINESS;
editor, Feminist Frameworks. FEMINIST ETHICS. LIFE, MEANING OF; MORAL IMAGINATION; WISDOM.

Deborah G. Johnson. Professor, Director of the Program Douglas Kellner. George Kneller Chair in Philosophy of
in Philosophy, Science and Technology, School of Pub- Education, University of California at Los Angeles. Au-
lic Policy, Georgia Institute of Technology. Author, thor, Critical Theory, Marxism and Modernity; Televi-
Computer Ethics. Co-editor, Computers, Ethics and So- sion and the Crisis of Democracy; Media Culture. Co-
cial Values; editor, Ethical Issues in Engineering. COM- author, Camera Politica. CULTURAL STUDIES.
PUTERS.
John Kelsay. Professor, Department of Religion, Florida
Edward Johnson. Professor of Philosophy, University of State University. Author, Islam and War. Co-editor and
New Orleans. Author, “Treating the Dirt: Environmen- contributor, Just War and Jihad and Cross, Crescent,
tal Ethics and Moral Theory”; “Inscrutable Desires”; and Sword. ISLAMIC ETHICS.
“Media Ownership”; other works on environmental
Kenneth Kipnis. Professor of Philosophy, University of
ethics, philosophy of technology, philosophy of edu-
Hawaii. Author, Legal Ethics; “Confessions of an Ex-
cation, and philosophy of sex and love. AGENT-
pert Ethics Witness”; and other works in practical
CENTERED MORALITY.
ethics. Co-editor, Property: Cases, Concepts, Critiques.
Mark L. Johnson. Professor of Philosophy, University of Editor of various works in legal and social philosophy.
Oregon. Author, The Body in the Mind and Moral BARGAINING.
Imagination. Co-author, Metaphors We Live By and
Eva Feder Kittay. Professor of Philosophy, State Univer-
Philosophy in the Flesh. COGNITIVE SCIENCE.
sity of New York, Stony Brook. Author, Metaphor;
David H. Jones. Emeritus Professor of Philosophy, Col- Love’s Labor: Essays on Women; Equality and Depen-
lege of William and Mary. Author, Moral Responsibility dency; and other works on philosophy of language, nor-

xxvi
Contributors and Editors

mative ethics, and feminist theory. Co-editor, Frames, John Lachs. Centennial Professor of Philosophy, Vander-
Fields, and Contrasts and Women and Moral Theory. bilt University. Author, Intermediate Man; The Rele-
HYPOCRISY. vance of Philosophy to Life; In Love with Life. AMER-
ICAN MORAL PHILOSOPHY.
Ted Klein. Professor of Philosophy, Texas Christian Uni-
versity. Co-translator of works by Husserl and Heideg- Berel Lang. Professor of Humanities, Trinity College
ger. Author, articles on Kant, Husserl, Heidegger, Ri- (Connecticut). Works include Act and Idea in the Nazi
coeur, hermeneutical ethics, legal reasoning and analogy. Genocide; The Future of the Holocaust; Holocaust
ANALOGICAL ARGUMENT. Representation: Art Within the Limits of History and
Ethics. GENOCIDE; MAIMONIDES.
John Kleinig. Professor of Philosophy, John Jay College of
Criminal Justice, City University of New York. Works Judith Lichtenberg. Associate Professor of Philosophy,
include Punishment and Desert; Paternalism; and Val- and Research Scholar, Institute for Philosophy and
uing Life. CONSENT. Public Policy, University of Maryland. Editor, Democ-
racy and the Mass Media. Author of essays in moral
George L. Kline. Milton C. Nahm Professor Emeritus of theory, media ethics, and international ethics. FREEDOM
Philosophy, Bryn Mawr College. Works include, Spi- OF THE PRESS; JOURNALISM.
noza in Soviet Philosophy and Religious and Anti-
Religious Thought in Russia. SOVIET ETHICAL THEORY. Ralph Lindgren. William Wilson Selfridge Professor of
Philosophy Emeritus, Lehigh University. Editor, The
Charles H. Koch, Jr. Dudley Warner Woodbridge Profes- Early Writings of Adam Smith. Author, The Social Phi-
sor of Law, College of William and Mary. Works in- losophy of Adam Smith. Co-author, The Law of Sex
clude: Administrative Law and Practice, second; Ad- Discrimination. SMITH.
ministrative Law: Cases and Materials; and law journal
articles. COOPERATIVE SURPLUS. Shu-hsien Liu. Research Fellow, Institute of Chinese Lit-
erature and Philosophy, Academia Sinica, Taipei.
Joseph J. Kockelmans. Distinguished Professor of Philos- Emeritus Professor, The Chinese University of Hong
ophy, Emeritus, Pennsylvania State University. Works Kong. Author, Understanding Confucian Philosophy:
include, On the Truth of Being and Heidegger on Art Classical and Sung-Ming, and works on Chu Hsi and
and Art Works. Editor, books on European philosophy. Huang Tsung-hsi. Editor, Harmony and Strife: Contem-
Consulting editor. CAMUS; HUSSERL; PHENOMENOL- porary Perspectives, East & West. CHU HSI.
OGY.
Loren E. Lomasky. Professor of Philosophy, Bowling
Marvin Kohl. Professor of Philosophy Emeritus, State Green State University (Ohio). Author, Persons, Rights,
University of New York, College at Fredonia. Author, and the Moral Community. PERSON, CONCEPT OF.
The Morality of Killing. Editor, Beneficent Euthanasia A. A. Long. Professor of Classics, and Irving Stone Pro-
and Infanticide and the Value of Life. BENEFICENCE; fessor of Literature, University of California, Berkeley.
EUTHANASIA; LIFE AND DEATH.
Author, Hellenistic Philosophy and other works on
Christine M. Korsgaard. Arthur Kingsley Porter Profes- Greek philosophy and literature. CYNICS; CYRENAICS;
sor of Philosophy, Harvard University. Author of The HISTORY 3: HELLENISTIC; HISTORY 4: ROMAN.
Sources of Normativity; Creating the Kingdom of Ends; David Luban. Frederick Haas Professor of Law and Phi-
and articles on practical reason and the self in ethics losophy, Georgetown University Law Center. Author,
and the history of ethics. Consulting editor. KANT; Lawyers and Justice: An Ethical Study, and other
PRICE; RAWLS. works on political and legal philosophy and on law.
Jill Kraye. Reader in the History of Renaissance Philos- ARENDT; LEGAL ETHICS; SECRECY AND CONFIDENTIAL-
ITY.
ophy, Warburg Institute (London). Editor, Cambridge
Translations of Renaissance Philosophical Texts. Co- Steven Lukes. Professor of Sociology, New York Univer-
editor, Humanism and Early Modern Philosophy. Ed- sity. Author, Émile Durkheim, His Life and Work: A
itor, Cambridge Companion to Renaissance Human- Historical and Critical Study; Essays in Social Theory;
ism. HISTORY 7: RENAISSANCE; NEO-STOICISM. Individualism; and Marxism and Morality. DURKHEIM;
INDIVIDUALISM; POWER.
David Farrell Krell. Professor of Philosophy, DePaul Uni-
versity. Author, Contagion; Archeticture; The Good Eu- David Lyons. Professor of Law and of Philosophy, Boston
ropean; Lunar Voices; Infectious Nietzsche; and Dai- University. Works include Forms and Limits of Utili-
mon Life. MORTALITY; NIHILISM; SCHELLING. tarianism; Ethics and the Rule of Law; Moral Aspects
of Legal Theory; and Rights, Welfare, and Mill’s Moral
Norman Kretzmann (1928–1998). Late Susan Linn Sage
Theory. Consulting editor. UTILITARIANISM.
Professor of Philosophy, Cornell University. Principal
editor, The Cambridge History of Later Medieval Phi- Jim MacAdam. Professor Emeritus, Philosophy, Trent
losophy. Editor, The Philosophical Review. Consulting University. Works include “What is Prichard’s Intui-
editor. tionism?”; “Obligations: From Common to Uncommon

xxvii
Contributors and Editors

Morality, The Latimer Case”; Prichard, Harold Arthur, sibility; The Socially Responsive Self; Masculinity and
(Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy). PRICHARD. Morality. Co-author, Praying for a Cure. Co-editor,
Collective Responsibility. COLLECTIVE RESPONSIBILITY;
Scott MacDonald. Professor of Philosophy, Cornell Uni-
PUBLIC AND PRIVATE MORALITY.
versity. Author of articles on ancient and medieval
ethics, metaphysics, and theory of knowledge. Editor, William L. McBride. Professor of Philosophy, Purdue
Being and Goodness and Aquinas’s Moral Theory. HIS- University. Co-founder of the Sartre Society of North
TORY 6: LATER MEDIEVAL. America. Works include The Philosophy of Marx; So-
cial Theory at a Crossroads; Sartre’s Political Theory;
Alasdair MacIntyre. Research Professor of Philosophy,
Philosophical Reflections on the Changes in Eastern
University of Notre Dame. Works include A Short His-
Europe. PRAXIS.
tory of Ethics and After Virtue. VIRTUE ETHICS.
Thomas McCarthy. Professor of Philosophy, Northwest-
Eric Mack. Professor of Philosophy, Tulane University.
ern University. Works include The Critical Theory of
Author, “Deontic Restrictions are not Agent-Relative
Jürgen Habermas and Ideals and Illusions: On Recon-
Restrictions” and “In Defence of the Jurisdiction The-
struction and Deconstruction in Contemporary Critical
ory of Rights.” Editor, Spencer’s The Man Versus the
Theory. Series editor, Studies in Contemporary Ger-
State. LIBERTY, ECONOMIC; SPENCER.
man Social Thought. HABERMAS.
Douglas MacLean. Professor of Philosophy, University of
Henry John McCloskey (1925–2000). Late Emeritus
Maryland, Baltimore County. Editor, Values at Risk.
Professor, La Trobe University. Works include Meta-
RISK ANALYSIS; RISK AVERSION.
Ethics and Normative Ethics; John Stuart Mill; God
Jeffery E. Malpas. Professor of Philosophy, University of and Evil; Derechos y sociedad en la filosófica analı́tica;
Tasmania. Author, Place and Experience; Donald Da- and Ecological Ethics and Politics. Consulting editor.
vidson and the Mirror of Meaning. Editor, Philosoph- PAIN AND SUFFERING.
ical Papers of Alan Donagan. DONAGAN.
Mary A. McCloskey. Senior Associate in Philosophy, Mel-
Rudolf Malter (1937–1994). Late Professor of Philoso- bourne University. Works include Kant’s Aesthetic.
phy, University of Mainz. Author of works on theory GRATITUDE.
of knowledge, metaphysics, aesthetics, Luther, Kant,
Howard McGary. Professor of Philosophy, Rutgers, The
and Schopenhauer. SCHOPENHAUER.
State University of New Jersey, New Brunswick. Au-
William E. Mann. Professor of Philosophy, University of thor, Race and Social Justice. Co-author, Between Slav-
Vermont. Author of articles in the philosophy of reli- ery and Freedom: Philosophy and American Slavery.
gion and medieval philosophy. EVIL; PHILOSOPHY OF Consulting editor. GROUPS, MORAL STATUS OF.
RELIGION; VOLUNTARISM.
Ralph M. McInerny. Director, Jacques Maritain Center,
Joseph Margolis. Laura H. Carnell Professor of Philoso- and Grace Professor of Medieval Studies, University of
phy, Temple University. Works include The Truth about Notre Dame. Works include Boethius and Aquinas
Relativism and The Persistence of Reality. PSYCHO- and First Glance at St. Thomas Aquinas. ABELARD;
ANALYSIS; PSYCHOLOGY. THOMAS AQUINAS.
John Marshall. Professor of Philosophy Emeritus, Uni- Dennis McKerlie. Professor of Philosophy, University of
versity of Virginia. Author, Descartes’s Moral Theory. Calgary. INEQUALITY.
FENELON; KANTIAN ETHICS.
Chrisopher McMahon. Professor of Philosophy, Univer-
Judith Martin. Works include the “Miss Manners” books sity of California, Santa Barbara. Author of works on
and syndicated column; the novels, Gilbert and Style moral, political, and social philosophy. AUTHORITY.
and Substance; and the essay, “Common Courtesy”.
John McMurtry. Professor of Philosophy, University of
ETIQUETTE.
Guelph. Author, The Structure of Marx’s World-View;
Mike W. Martin. Professor of Philosophy, Chapman Uni- Understanding War; Unequal Freedoms: The Global
versity. Works include Self-Deception and Morality; Market as an Ethical System; The Cancer Stage of
Love’s Virtues; Meaningful Work: Rethinking Profes- Capitalism; and other works in value theory and social
sional Ethics. SELF-DECEPTION. philosophy. COMPETITION; FORMS OF CONSCIOUSNESS.
Gareth B. Matthews. Professor of Philosophy, University Alfred R. Mele. Professor of Philosophy, Florida State
of Massachusetts at Amherst. Author, Thought’s Ego University. Works include Irrationality; Springs of
in Augustine and Descartes; The Philosophy of Child- Action; Autonomous Agents; and Self-Deception Un-
hood; Socratic Perplexity and the Nature of Philoso- masked. SELF-CONTROL; TEMPERANCE.
phy. Co-translator of Ammonius’s On Aristotle’s Cate-
Susan Mendus. Professor of Political Philosophy, and Di-
gories. AUGUSTINE; MORAL DEVELOPMENT.
rector of the Morrell Studies in Toleration Program,
Larry May. Professor of Philosophy, Washington Univer- University of York. Works include Toleration and the
sity. Author, The Morality of Groups; Sharing Respon- Limits of Liberalism. Editor, Justifying Toleration. Co-

xxviii
Contributors and Editors

editor, John Locke’s Letter on Toleration in Focus. TOL- Christopher Morris. Professor of Philosophy, Bowling
ERATION. Green State University. Author, An Essay on the Mod-
ern State and essays on contractarian ethics and other
Michael J. Meyer. Associate Professor of Philosophy, topics. Editor, The Social Contract Theorists: Critical
Santa Clara University. Co-editor, The Constitution of Essays on Hobbes, Locke, and Rousseau. CONTRAC-
Rights: Human Dignity and American Values. Author TARIANISM.
of works in ethics and political philosophy. DIGNITY.
Mary Mothersill. Professor of Philosophy, Barnard Col-
Mary Midgley. Formerly Senior Lecturer, University of lege, Columbia University. Author, Beauty Restored.
Newcastle-on-Tyne. Author, Beast and Man; Wicked- FITTINGNESS.
ness; Heart and Mind; Wisdom, Information and Won-
der; Animals and Why They Matter; Can’t We Make Janice Moulton. Philosophy, Smith College. Co-author,
Moral Judgements? WICKEDNESS. Ethical Problems in Higher Education; Scaling the
Dragon; and The Organization of Language. ACADEMIC
Richard W. Miller. Professor of Philosophy, Cornell Uni- FREEDOM; PLAGIARISM.
versity. Works include Fact and Method; Analyzing
Amy Mullin. Associate Professor of Philosophy, Univer-
Marx; Moral Differences; and articles on justice, moral
sity of Toronto. Author of works in feminist philoso-
realism, Marx, and explanation and confirmation in the
phy, the history of philosophy, and aesthetics. MORAL
sciences. MARXISM; MORAL REALISM.
PURITY.
Seumas Miller. Professor of Social Philosophy, and Di- Jeffrie G. Murphy. Regents Professor of Law and Philos-
rector, Special Research Centre in Applied Philosophy ophy, Arizona State University. Author, Retribution,
and Public Ethics, Charles Sturt University, Canberra, Justice and Therapy; Character, Liberty and Law. Co-
Australia. Author, Social Action. Co-author, Police author, The Philosophy of Law and Forgiveness and
Ethics. CONVENTIONS. Mercy. FORGIVENESS; LEGAL PHILOSOPHY.
Phillip Mitsis. Professor of Classics, and Director, Alex- Steven Nadler. Professor of Philosophy, University of
ander S. Onassis Program in Hellenic Studies, New Wisconsin, Madison. Author, books and articles in the
York University. Works include Epicurus’ Ethical The- history of early modern philosophy, including Spinoza:
ory: The Pleasures of Invulnerability. EPICUREANISM; A Life. MALEBRANCHE.
EPICURUS; LUCRETIUS.
Jan Narveson. Professor of Philosophy, University of Wa-
Richard D. Mohr. Professor of Philosophy, University of terloo (Ontario). Author, Morality and Utility; The Lib-
Illinois, Urbana. Works include The Platonic Cosmol- ertarian Idea; and Moral Matters. ENTITLEMENTS.
ogy and Gays/Justice: A Study of Ethics, Society, and Daniel Nelson. Senior Associate Dean of the College,
Law. HOMOSEXUALITY. Dartmouth College. Author of works on virtue theory
Arthur P. Monahan. Professor of Philosophy Emeritus, and on Thomas Aquinas. PRUDENCE.
Saint Mary’s University (Halifax, Nova Scotia). Au- Mark T. Nelson. Senior Lecturer in Philosophy, Univer-
thor, Consent, Coercion and Limit and From Personal sity of Leeds. Co-editor, Christian Theism and Moral
Duties Towards Personal Rights. Translator of medie- Philosophy. Author of works in ethics, philosophy of
val political works. COMMON GOOD. religion, epistemology and philosophy of mind. THE-
ISM.
Edward F. Mooney. Professor of Philosophy, Sonoma State
University. Author, Selves in Discord and Resolve: Kier- James W. Nickel. Professor of Philosophy, University of
kegaard’s Moral-Religious Psychology; Knights of Faith Colorado, Boulder. Author, Making Sense of Human
and Resignation: Reading Kierkegaard’s “Fear and Rights; “Group Agency and Group Rights”; “Economic
Trembling.” Editor, Wilderness and the Heart; other Liberties.” HUMAN RIGHTS.
works on Kierkegaard, ethics, and philosophy in litera- Kai E. Nielsen. Professor of Philosophy Emeritus, Uni-
ture. SYMPATHY. versity of Calgary. Works include Marxism and the
Kathleen Dean Moore. Professor of Philosophy, Oregon Moral Point of View; Philosophy and Atheism; Ethics
State University. Author, Pardons: Justice, Mercy, and Without God; and After the Demise of the Tradition.
the Public Interest; Reasoning and Writing; and Hold- ATHEISM; ENGELS; MORAL POINT OF VIEW; MURPHY;

fast. AMNESTY AND PARDON. REVOLUTION.

Michael Nill. Head of School, Brooklyn Friends School


Ebrahim Moosa. Professor of Islamic Thought, Stanford
(Brooklyn). Author, Morality and Self-Interest in Pro-
University and the University of Cape Town. Author,
tagoras, Antiphon, and Democritus. DEMOCRITUS;
“Languages of Change in Islamic Law: Redefining
PROTAGORAS; SOPHISTS.
Death in Modernity”; “Allegory of the Rule (Hukm):
Law as Simulacrum in Islam.” Editor, Revival and Re- Martha Nussbaum. Ernst Freund Distinguished Service
form in Islam: A Study of Islamic Fundamentalism. Professor of Law and Ethics at the University of Chi-
SHI-ISM; SUNNISM. cago. Works include The Fragility of Goodness; Love’s

xxix
Contributors and Editors

Knowledge; The Therapy of Desire; Poetic Justice; Cul- Gerald J. Postema. Cary C. Boshamer Professor of Phi-
tivating Humanity; Sex and Social Justice; and Women losophy, University of North Carolina, Chapel Hill. Ed-
and Human Development. Consulting editor. CHAR- itor, Cambridge Studies in Philosophy and Law; former
ACTER; LITERATURE AND ETHICS; TRAGEDY. Fellow, Netherlands Institute for Advanced Study. Au-
thor, Bentham and the Common Law Tradition; and
Timothy O’Connor. Associate Professor of Philosophy, Jeremy Bentham: Moral, Political and Legal Philoso-
Indiana University. Author, Persons and Causes: The phy. BENTHAM.
Metaphysics of Free Will, and articles in metaphysics,
philosophy of mind, and philosophy of religion. CAU- George Proctor. Emeritus Professor of Philosophy, Son-
SATION AND RESPONSIBILITY. oma State University. Author of works on the history
and philosophy of science. DUNS SCOTUS.
Onora O’Neill. Newnham College, Cambridge. Author,
Faces of Hunger: An Essay on Poverty, Justice, and De- Susan M. Purviance. Associate Professor of Philosophy,
velopment; Constructions of Reason: Explorations of University of Toledo (Ohio). Works include “The
Kant’s Practical Philosophy; Towards Justice and Vir- Moral Self and the Indirect Passions”; “The Facticity of
tue; Bounds of Justice. Consulting editor. CHARITY; Kant’s Fact of Reason”; “Social Meliorism, Virtue, and
DUTY AND OBLIGATION; FORMALISM; INTERNATIONAL
Vice: Bernard Mandeville”; and other articles on ethi-
JUSTICE: DISTRIBUTION.
cal theory, the history of ethics, and health care ethics.
JAMES MILL.
Gene Outka. Dwight Professor of Philosophy and Chris- Ruth Anna Putnam. Professor of Philosophy, Emerita,
tian Ethics, Yale University. Author, Agape: An Ethical Wellesley College. Works include “Perceiving Facts
Analysis. Co-editor, Prospects for a Common Morality; and Values”; “Some of Life’s Ideals”; “Why Not a Femi-
Norm and Context in Christian Ethics; Religion and nist theory of Justice?”; Neither A Beast Nor a God.
Morality. KIERKEGAARD; LOVE. Editor, The Cambridge Companion to William James.
Richard D. Parry. Fuller E. Callaway Professor of Philos- JAMES; PRAGMATISM.
ophy, Agnes Scott College. Works include, Plato’s Craft Andrew Pyle. Lecturer, Department of Philosophy, Uni-
of Justice; “The Unique World of the Timaeus”; “The versity of Bristol. Author, Atomism and Its Critics. Ed-
Uniqueness Proof of Forms in Republic X”; “Morality itor, Agnosticism: Contemporary Responses to Spencer
and Happiness: Book IV of Plato’s Republic”; and “The and Huxley. General Editor, Dictionary of Seventeenth
Craft of Justice.” EUDAIMONIA, -ISM. Century British Philosophers. AGNOSTICISM.
Terence Penelhum. Professor Emeritus of Religious Stud- Philip L. Quinn. O’Brien Professor of Philosophy, Uni-
ies, University of Calgary. Author, God and Skepticism; versity of Notre Dame. Author, Divine Commands and
Themes in Hume; Survival and Disembodied Exis- Moral Requirements. Co-editor, A Companion to Phi-
tence; Religion and Rationality; Butler. BUTLER. losophy of Religion and The Philosophical Challenge
of Religious Diversity. THEOLOGICAL ETHICS.
Derk Pereboom. Professor and Chair, Department of Phi-
losophy, University of Vermont. Author of Living With- James Rachels. University Professor of Philosophy, Uni-
out Free Will. FREE WILL. versity of Alabama at Birmingham. Works include The
End of Life: Euthanasia and Morality and Created
Philip Pettit. Professor of Social and Political Theory, The From Animals: The Moral Implications of Darwinism.
Australian National University. Author, The Common KILLING AND LETTING DIE; THEORY AND PRACTICE.
Mind: From Intentional Psychology to Social and Po-
litical Theory; Republicanism; The Fundamentals of Stuart Rachels. Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Uni-
Freedom. Co-author, Not Just Deserts: A Republican versity of Alabama. Articles include “Counterexamples
Theory of Criminal Justice. INSTITUTIONS. to the Transitivity of Better Than”, “Is it Good to Make
Happy People?”, and “Is Unpleasantness Intrinsic to
Derek L. Phillips. Professor Emeritus of Sociology, Univ- Unpleasant Experiences?” INTRANSITIVITY.
ersiteit van Amsterdam. Works include Toward a Just Diane C. Raymond. Professor of Philosophy and Women’s
Social Order and Looking Backward. Consulting edi- Studies, Simmons College. Author, Existentialism and
tor. SOCIOLOGY; WEBER. the Philosophical Tradition; Looking at Gay and Les-
Roger Pilon. Vice President for Legal Affairs, B. Kenneth bian Life. Editor, Sexual Politics and Popular Culture.
Simon Chair in Constitutional Studies, and Director, WORK.
Center for Constitutional Studies, Cato Institute. Au- Andrews Reath. Professor of Philosophy, University of
thor of works in law and legal theory. GEWIRTH. California at Riverside. Works include articles on the
history of ethics, in particular on Kant’s moral philos-
Edmund L. Pincoffs (1919–1991). Late Professor Emer-
ophy. CATEGORICAL AND HYPOTHETICAL IMPERATIVES;
itus of Philosophy, University of Texas at Austin. Works
CONSTRUCTIVISM; ROUSSEAU.
include The Rationale of Legal Punishment and Quan-
daries and Virtues: Against Reductivism in Ethics. Tom Regan. Professor of Philosophy, North Carolina
MORAL COMMUNITY, BOUNDARIES OF; VIRTUES. State University. Works include: The Case for Animal

xxx
Contributors and Editors

Rights; Bloomsbury’s Prophet: G. E. Moore and the Children: Philosophical and Legal Reflections on Par-
Development of his Moral Philosophy; and The Thee enthood. FAMILY; MEDICAL ETHICS.
Generation. Consulting editor. ANIMALS, TREATMENT
Michael Ruse. Lucyle T. Werkmeister Professor of Phi-
OF; MOORE; ROSS.
losophy. Florida State University. Works include Mo-
Frank Reynolds. Professor of History of Religious and nad to Man; Sociobiology: Sense or Nonsense?; Taking
Buddhist Studies, the Divinity School and the Depart- Darwin Seriously: A Naturalistic Approach to Philos-
ment of South Asian Languages and Civilizations, Uni- ophy. DARWIN; EVOLUTION.
versity of Chicago. Co-editor, Cosmogony and Ethical
Abdulaziz Sachedina. Professor of Religious Studies,
Order. HINDU ETHICS.
University of Virginia. Author, The Islamic Roots of
David A. J. Richards. Edwin D. Webb Professor of Law, Democratic Pluralism; The Just Ruler in Shı̄ite Islam;
New York University School of Law. Works include: and Islamic Messianism. Co-author, Human Rights
Identity and the Case for Gay Rights; Italian American: and the Conflict of Cultures: Western and Islamic Per-
The Racializing of an Ethnic Identity; Free Speech and spectives on Religious Liberty. Consulting editor. IS-
the Politics of Identity; A Theory of Reasons for Action; LAM; ISLAMIC BUSINESS ETHICS.
Toleration and the Constitution; and Foundations of
Mark Sagoff. Institute for Philosophy and Public Policy,
American Constitutionalism. CENSORSHIP.
University of Maryland. Author, The Economy of the
Norvin Richards. Professor of Philosophy, University of Earth. PUBLIC POLICY ANALYSIS.
Alabama. Works include Humility; “Forgiveness”;
John Sallis. Edwin Erle Sparks Professor of Philosophy
“Luck and Desert”; and “Criminal Children.” HUMIL-
at The Pennsylvania State University. Author of Force
ITY.
of Imagination; Chorology: On Beginning in Plato’s
Henry Richardson. Associate Professor of Philosophy, “Timaeus”; Shades—Of Painting at the Limit; and
Georgetown University. Author, Practical Reasoning other books on continental philosophy, philosophy of
about Final Ends; “Specifying Norms as a Way to Re- art, and history of philosophy. Consulting editor.
solve Concrete Ethical Problems”; “Beyond Good and FICHTE; GADAMER.
Right: Towards a Constructive Ethical Pragmatism.”
Geoffrey Sayre-McCord. Bowman and Gordon Gray Pro-
COMMENSURABILITY.
fessor of Philosophy, University of North Carolina at
John Robertson. Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Syr- Chapel Hill. Author of a variety of papers on metaeth-
acuse University. Works include “Internalism about ics, moral theory, the history of ethics and epistemol-
Moral Reasons” and “Hume on Practical Reason”. EX- ogy. COHERENTISM.
TERNALISM AND INTERNALISM.
Thomas M. Scanlon, Jr. Alford Professor of Natural Re-
George Robinson. Psychology, Smith College. Co-author, ligion, Harvard University. Author, What We Owe to
Ethical Problems in Higher Education; Scaling the Each Other. Consulting editor.
Dragon; and The Organization of Language. ACADEMIC
Richard Schacht. Professor of Philosophy, University of
FREEDOM; PLAGIARISM.
Illinois, Urbana-Champaign. Author, Alienation; Hegel
Sandra B. Rosenthal. Provost Distinguished Professor of and After; Nietzsche; Making Sense of Nietzsche; and
Philosophy, Loyola University, New Orleans. Author, The Future of Alienation. ALIENATION; HISTORY 10:
Speculative Pragmatism; Charles Peirce’s Pragmatic 19TH CENTURY CONTINENTAL.
Pluralism; Time, Continuity, and Indeterminacy; and
Samuel Scheffler. Class of 1941 World War II Memorial
other works on pragmatism and on the relation be-
Professor of Philosophy and Law, University of Cali-
tween pragmatism and phenomenology. PEIRCE.
fornia, Berkeley. Author, The Rejection of Consequen-
William L. Rowe. Professor of Philosophy, Purdue Uni- tialism; Human Morality. Editor, Consequentialism
versity. Author, Thomas Reid on Freedom and Moral- and its Critics. Consulting editor.
ity. CLARKE; REID.
Naomi Scheman. Professor of Philosophy and Women’s
Sara Ruddick. Faculty emerita, Eugene Lang College, Studies, University of Minnesota. Author of Engender-
New School for Social Research. Works include Ma- ings: Constructions of Knowledge, Authority, and Privi-
ternal Thinking: Toward a Politics of Peace, and arti- lege; and editor of the forthcoming Feminist Interpre-
cles in ethics and social and political philosophy. VIO- tations of Wittgenstein: Re-Reading the Canon. RAPE;
LENCE AND NON-VIOLENCE; WAR AND PEACE. SEXUAL ABUSE AND HARASSMENT.

William Ruddick. Professor of Philosophy and Adjunct J. B. Schneewind. Professor of Philosophy, The Johns
Professor of Psychiatry, New York University. Author: Hopkins University. Author, Sidgwick’s Ethics and Vic-
“Parenthood: Three Concepts and a Principle”; “Hope torian Moral Philosophy and The Invention of Auton-
and Deception”; “Do Doctors Undertreat Pain?”; and omy. Editor, Moral Philosophy from Montaigne to
other essays on parenthood and medical ethics. Editor: Kant, and other studies in the history of ethics. Con-
Philosophers in Medical Centers. Co-editor, Having sulting editor. COMMON SENSE MORALISTS; CRUSIUS;

xxxi
Contributors and Editors

HISTORY8: 17TH AND 18TH CENTURIES; MONTAIGNE; sessment. AGRICULTURAL ETHICS; LAND ETHICS; TECH-
THOMASIUS. NOLOGY.

Ferdinand D. Schoeman (1945–1992). Late Professor of Henry Shue. Professor of Ethics and Public Life, Cornell
Philosophy, University of South Carolina. Author, Pri- University. Works include Basic Rights. Editor, Nuclear
vacy and Social Freedom and other studies in respon- Deterrence and Moral Restraint. PUBLIC POLICY; WEL-
sibility and privacy. PRIVACY. FARE RIGHTS AND SOCIAL POLICY.

William R. Schroeder. Associate Professor of Philosophy, Kwong-loi Shun. Professor of Philosophy, University of
University of Illinois, Urbana-Champaign. Author, Sar- California, Berkeley. Author of works on Chinese ethics
tre and his Predecessors: The Self and the Other; “Con- and contemporary Anglo-American moral philosophy.
tinental Ethics”; and other works on continental ethics CHINA; CONFUCIUS; MENCIUS.
and philosophy of mind. Editor, The Blackwell Com-
panion to Continental Philosophy. HISTORY 11: 20TH Anita Silvers. Professor of Philosophy, San Francisco
CENTURY CONTINENTAL; RESENTMENT.
State University. Co-author, Disability, Difference,
Discrimination: Perspectives on Justice in Bioethics
Chris Matthew Sciabarra. Visiting Scholar, Department and Public Policy; and Puzzles About Art. Co-Editor,
of Politics, New York University. Author, Total Free- Americans With Disabilities: Exploring Implications of
dom: Toward A Dialectical Libertarianism; Ayn Rand: the Law for Individuals and Institutions; Physician-
The Russian Radical; Marx, Hayek, and Utopia. Co- Assisted Suicide; and Health Care and Social Justice
editor of Feminist Interpretations of Ayn Rand and of (forthcoming). AGENCY AND DISABILITY.
The Journal of Ayn Rand Studies. OBJECTIVISM; RAND.
A. John Simmons. Commonwealth Professor of Philoso-
Jorge Secada. Associate Professor of Philosophy, Univer- phy, University of Virginia. Author, Moral Principles
sity of Virginia, and regularly Visiting Professor at the and Political Obligations; The Lockean Theory of
Graduate School of the Universidad Catolica del Peru Rights; On the Edge of Anarchy; and Justification and
in Lima. Author, Cartesian Metaphysics: The Scholas- Legitimacy. FAIRNESS; LEGITIMACY; OBEDIENCE TO
tic Origins of Modern Philosophy; “Berkeley y el ideal- LAW.
ismo”; “Ontologia de la obra de arte”; and other arti-
cles. HISTORIOGRAPHY; SUAREZ; VITORIA. Robert L. Simon. Professor of Philosophy, Hamilton Col-
lege. Author, Neutrality and The Academic Ethic;
Michael Seidler. Professor of Philosophy, Western Ken- Sports and Social Values; and other works on ethics,
tucky University. Author of articles on German natural philosophy of sport, and political and social philoso-
law theory and other early modern topics. Translator, phy. Co-author, The Individual and the Political Order.
The Political Writings of Samuel Pufendorf; editor and Consulting editor. SOCIAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY;
translator, Samuel Pufendorf’s “On the Natural State SPORT.
of Men.” PUFENDORF.
Marcus G. Singer. Professor of Philosophy Emeritus,
George Sher. Herbert S. Autrey Professor of Philosophy, University of Wisconsin, Madison. Author, Generaliza-
Rice University. Author of Desert; Beyond Neutrality: tion in Ethics. Editor, Morals and Values and Reason,
Perfectionism and Politics; Approximate Justice: Stud- Reality, and Speculative Philosophy. ADLER; GOLDEN
ies in Non-Ideal Theory; and essays in metaphysics, RULE; HISTORY 9: 19TH CENTURY BRITISH; SIDGWICK.
ethics, and social and political philosophy. MERIT AND
DESERT; NEUTRAL PRINCIPLES. Walter Sinnott-Armstrong. Professor of Philosophy, Dart-
mouth College. Author, Moral Dilemmas. Co-author,
Nancy Sherman. Professor of Philosophy, Georgetown Understanding Arguments: An Introduction to Infor-
University. Author, The Fabric of Character; Making a mal Logic. Co-editor, Moral Knowledge? New Read-
Necessity of Virtue; and other works on the history of ings in Moral Epistemology. GERT; INTUITIONISM;
moral philosophy, the emotions, and moral psychology. MORAL DILEMMAS; OUGHT IMPLIES CAN.
Editor, Aristotle’s Ethics: Critical Essays. EXCELLENCE;
PRACTICAL WISDOM. John E. Sisko. Assistant Professor of Philosophy, College
of William and Mary. Author of articles on Ancient
Charles M. Sherover. Professor Emeritus of Philosophy,
Greek Philosophy. PHRONESIS.
Hunter College, City University of New York. Works
include Heidegger, Kant and Time; Time, Freedom, and Quentin Skinner. Regius Professor of Modern History,
the Common Good; The Human Experience of Time; University of Cambridge. Works include The Founda-
and “Royce’s Pragmatic Idealism and Existential Phe- tions of Modern Political Thought; Machiavelli; Rea-
nomenology”. HEIDEGGER; ROYCE. son and Rhetoric in the Philosophy of Hobbes; Liberty
Before Liberalism. MACHIAVELLI.
Kristin Shrader-Frechette. O’Neill Family Professor of
Philosophy and Concurrent Professor of Biological Sci- R. C. Sleigh, Jr. Professor of Philosophy, University of
ences, University of Notre Dame. Author of books and Massachusetts. Author, Leibniz and Arnauld: A Com-
articles on philosophy of science, environmental ethics, mentary on Their Correspondence. Co-editor, The Yale
and ethical/scientific problems in quantitative risk as- Leibniz. LEIBNIZ.

xxxii
Contributors and Editors

Michael A. Slote. Professor of Philosophy, University of Robert M. Stewart. Professor of Philosophy, California
Maryland, College Park. Author, Goods and Virtues; State University, Chico. Co-author, Moral Philosophy:
From Morality to Virtue; Morals from Motives; A Comprehensive Introduction. Editor, Readings in So-
Common-Sense Morality and Consequentialism; and cial and Political Philosophy; Philosophical Perspec-
Beyond Optimizing. CONSEQUENTIALISM; TELEOLOGI- tives on Sex and Love. FRANKENA.
CAL ETHICS.
Michael Stocker. Professor of Philosophy, Syracuse Uni-
Saul Smilansky. Professor of Philosophy, University of versity. Works include Plural and Conflicting Values.
Haifa, Israel. Author of Free Will and Illusion. BLACK- EXTERNALISM AND INTERNALISM.
MAIL.
Jeffrey Stout. Andrew W. Mellon Professor of Religion,
Holly M. Smith. Professor of Philosophy, and Dean, So- Princeton University. President, editorial board, Jour-
cial and Behavioral Sciences, University of Arizona. nal of Religious Ethics. Works include, The Flight from
Author of articles on moral theory, utilitarianism, and Authority and Ethics after Babel. Consulting editor.
medical ethics. Consulting editor. ACTION; EXCUSES;
Gisela Striker. Professor of Classical Philosophy, Harvard
IDEALIZED AGENTS; NEGLIGENCE; POSSIBILISM.
University. Author, Essays on Hellenistic Epistemology
Alan Soble. University Research Professor and Professor and Ethics. EPICTETUS; MARCUS AURELIUS; STOICISM.
of Philosophy, University of New Orleans. Author, Por- Timothy Stroup. Professor of Philosophy, John Jay Col-
nography; The Structure of Love; Sexual Investiga- lege of Criminal Justice, City University of New York.
tions; The Philosophy of Sex and Love. Editor, Sex, Author, Westermarck’s Ethics. Editor, Edward Wester-
Love, and Friendship; The Philosophy of Sex; Eros, marck; co-editor, Police Ethics. Co-founder, Criminal
Agape, and Philia. SEXUALITY AND SEXUAL ETHICS. Justice Ethics. CORRECTIONAL ETHICS; POLICE ETHICS;
Moshe Z. Sokol. Professor and Chairman, Philosophy WESTERMARCK.
Department, Touro College. Author, works on Jewish Nicholas L. Sturgeon. Professor of Philosophy, Cornell
ethics and philosophy. Editor, Personal Autonomy and University. Author of works on the metaphysical and
Rabbinic Authority and Tolerance, Dissent and De- epistemological foundations of morality. METAPHYSICS
mocracy. JEWISH ETHICS. AND EPISTEMOLOGY.

Wm. David Solomon. Professor of Philosophy, University John A. Taber. Associate Professor of Philosophy, Uni-
of Notre Dame. Co-author, The Synoptic Vision: The versity of New Mexico. Author, Transformative Philos-
Philosophy of Wilfrid Sellars. Co-editor, Abortion and ophy: A Study of Sankara, Fichte, and Heidegger; and
Social Policy. DOUBLE EFFECT. other works in Asian and comparative philosophy.
André Spies. Associate Professor of History, Hollins Uni- INDIA.
versity. Author, Opera, State and Society in the Third Larry S. Temkin. Professor of Philosophy, Rutgers Uni-
Republic, 1875-1914. MONTESQUIEU. versity. Author, Inequality and other works on equality,
T. L. S. Sprigge. Professor Emeritus and Endowment Fel- rationality, transitivity, additivity, and the good. ADDI-
TIVITY PROBLEMS.
low, University of Edinburgh. Works include Santay-
ana; The Vindication of Absolute Idealism; Theories of Laurence Thomas. Professor of Philosophy and Professor
Existence; The Rational Foundations of Ethics; and of Political Science, Syracuse University. Author, Liv-
James and Bradley: American Truth and British Real- ing Morally: A Psychology of Moral Character; Vessels
ity. AYER; IDEALIST ETHICS; NATURALISTIC FALLACY; of Evil: American Slavery and the Holocaust; and other
ORGANIC UNITY; SANTAYANA. works in moral and social philosophy. Consulting edi-
tor. BAIER; MORAL PSYCHOLOGY.
Hillel Steiner. Professor of Political Philosophy, Univer-
sity of Manchester. Author, An Essay on Rights; A De- Mark Timmons. Professor of Philosophy, University of
bate Over Rights: Philosophical Enquiries; and other Memphis. Author, Morality without Foundations: A
works on rights, justice, and liberty. Editor, Left- Defense of Ethical Contextualism. Co-editor, Moral
Libertarianism and Its Critics. Consulting editor. LIB- Knowledge? New Readings in Moral Epistemology.
ERTARIANISM; LIBERTY. Editor, Kant’s Metaphysics of Morals: Interpretive Es-
says (forthcoming). SINGER.
Gunther S. Stent. Professor Emeritus of Neurobiology,
University of California, Berkeley. Works include Na- James Tully. Professor and Chair, Department of Political
zis, Women and Molecular Biology; Paradoxes of Pro- Science, University of Victoria (Canada). Author,
gress. Editor, Norton Critical Edition of J. D. Watson’s Strange Multiplicity: Constitutionalism in an Age of
The Double Helix: Morality as a Biological Phenome- Diversity; An Approach to Political Philosophy: Locke
non. ETIQUETTE. in Contexts. FOUCAULT; LOCKE.
Calvin Stewart. Philosophy, Santa Clara University. THOM- Suzanne Uniacke. Associate Professor of Philosophy,
SON. University of Wollongong. Author, Permissible Killing:

xxxiii
Contributors and Editors

The Self-Defense Justification of Homicide. REVENGE; Metaphysics. DESCARTES; PASCAL; TECHNOLOGY AND
SELF-DEFENSE. NATURE.

J. O. Urmson. Emeritus Professor, Stanford University; Stephen H. Watson. Professor of Philosophy, University
Emeritus Fellow, Corpus Christi College, Oxford. Au- of Notre Dame. Works include articles on continental
thor, Philosophical Analysis; Emotive Theory of Ethics; philosophy. RICOEUR.
Berkeley; and Aristotle’s Ethics. EMOTIVISM.
Carl Wellman. Hortense and Tobias Lewin Distinguished
Peter Vallentyne. Professor of Philosophy, Virginia Com- Professor Emeritus, Washington University. Works in-
monwealth University. Author of works on consequen- clude Welfare Rights; A Theory of Rights; Real Rights;
tialism, moral dilemmas, egalitarian theories of justice, An Approach to Rights. RIGHT, CONCEPTS OF; RIGHT
and left-libertarianism. SELF-OWNERSHIP. HOLDERS.
Harry van der Linden. Professor of Philosophy, Butler
Alan Wertheimer. McCullough Professor of Political Sci-
University. Author, Kantian Ethics and Socialism and
ence, University of Vermont. Author, Coercion; Ex-
articles on Kant, Marx, Marburg neo-Kantianism, and
ploitation. Co-editor, Majorities and Minorities. CO-
international relations. NEO-KANTIAN ETHICS.
ERCION.
Donald VanDeVeer. Professor of Philosophy, North Caro-
lina State University. Author, Paternalistic Intervention. Henry R. West. Professor of Philosophy, Macalester Col-
Co-editor of works including Health Care Ethics; AIDS: lege. Author, “Utilitarianism” (Encyclopaedia Britan-
Ethics and Public Policy; People, Penguins, and Plastic nica); “Mill’s ‘Proof’ of the Principle of Utility”; and
Trees; And Justice for All; The Environmental Ethics and other works on Mill’s utilitarianism. Co-editor, Moral
Policy Book. PORNOGRAPHY. Philosophy. JOHN STUART MILL.

Aram Vartanian (1922–1997). Late Kenan Professor of Forrest Williams. Professor of Philosophy Emeritus, Uni-
French Literature, Emeritus, University of Virginia. versity of Colorado, Boulder. Associate Editor, Conti-
Author, Diderot and Descartes: A Study of Scientific nental Philosophy. Author of essays on twentieth cen-
Naturalism in the Enlightenment and Lamettrie’s tury French and German philosophers; translator of
‘L’Homme Machine’: A Study in the Origins of an Idea. writings by Sartre, Merleau-Ponty, and Foucault. EX-
HOLBACH. ISTENTIAL ETHICS.

Allen D. Verhey. Blekkink Professor of Religion, Hope Patricia A. Williams. Independent Scholar. Author, Do-
College. Works include The Great Reversal: Ethics and ing without Adam and Eve: Sociobiology and Original
the New Testament. PAUL. Sin. Co-editor, Evolution and Human Values. BIO-
LOGICAL THEORY.
Candace Vogler. Philosophy, University of Chicago. Au-
thor of Reason in Action; John Stuart Mill’s Delibera- Kenneth Winston. Lecturer in Ethics and Assistant to the
tive Landscape; and articles on ethics, social and po- Dean for Special Projects on International Ethics and
litical philosophy, feminism, sex, gender and culture Diversity, Kennedy School of Government, Harvard
studies. FOOT. University. DWORKIN; FULLER; HART.
Mary Ellen Waithe. Professor of Philosophy, and Direc-
Susan Wolf. Duane Peterson Professor of Ethics, The
tor, Bioethics Program, Cleveland State University.
Johns Hopkins University. Author, Freedom Within
Founder, Project on the History of Women in Philoso-
Reason and other works on ethics and the philosophy
phy. Author of A History of Women Philosophers.
of mind. Consulting editor. MORAL SAINTS.
WOMEN MORAL PHILOSOPHERS.

Douglas N. Walton. Professor of Philosophy, University David B. Wong. Professor of Philosophy, Duke Univer-
of Winnipeg. Author, Courage: A Philosophical Inves- sity. Author, Moral Relativity and other works in ethi-
tigation; Informal Logic. Co-author, Commitment in cal theory, Chinese philosophy, and the history of phi-
Dialogue: Basic Concepts of Interpersonal Reasoning. losophy. Consulting editor. COMPARATIVE ETHICS; MO
COURAGE; PERSUASIVE DEFINITION; PRACTICAL REA-
TZU; MORAL RELATIVISM.
SON[ING].
Allen W. Wood. Professor of Philosophy, Stanford Uni-
Georgia Warnke. Professor of Philosophy, University of versity. Author, Karl Marx; Hegel’s Ethical Thought;
California, Riverside. Author, Gadamer: Hermeneu- Kant’s Ethical Thought. Translations include Kant’s
tics, Tradition and Reason; Justice and Interpretation; writings on religion and rational theology, and Critique
and Legitimate Differences: Interpretation in the Abor- of Pure Reason. Editor: Hegel’s Elements of the Phi-
tion Controversy and other Public Debates. MULTICUL- losophy of Right. Consulting editor. HEGEL; MARX.
TURALISM; WALZER.
Robert E. Wood. Professor and Chair, Department of Phi-
Richard A. Watson. Professor of Philosophy, Washington losophy, University of Dallas. Author, Martin Buber’s
University. Works include The Breakdown of Cartesian Ontology; A Path into Metaphysics; Placing Aesthetics:

xxxiv
Contributors and Editors

Reflections on the Philosophic Tradition. Editor, Amer- Michael J. Zimmerman. Professor of Philosophy, Univer-
ican Catholic Philosophical Quarterly. BUBER. sity of North Carolina, Greensboro. Author, An Essay
on Human Action; The Concept of Moral Obligation;
Michael Wreen. Professor of Philosophy, Marquette Uni-
An Essay on Moral Responsibility; The Nature of In-
versity. Author, works in ethics, aesthetics, argumen-
trinsic Value; and other works on ethics. RESPONSIBIL-
tation theory, philosophy of language, metaphysics, and
ITY; VOLUNTARY ACTS.
action theory. AESTHETICS; FORGERY.

xxxv
This page intentionally left blank
Encyclopedia of
ETHICS
This page intentionally left blank
A

Abelard, Peter (1079–1142) theological discourse. What we shall call Abelard’s


ethics is clearly the work of a Christian who is con-
Peter Abelard lived a life which could be called in
cerned with the precise nature of sin, that is, with
its entirety what he called a portion of it: the story
moral fault as an offense against God. The Nico-
of his calamities. From the moment of his arrival in
machean Ethics would be translated into Latin
the logic schools of Paris, he was a figure of contro-
shortly after Abelard’s death and exercised no influ-
versy. He successfully challenged the doctrines of his ence on his thought. Far more relevant to under-
teacher William of Champeaux (1071–1121) and, standing his approach are contemporary manuals
when he turned to the study of theology, almost im- for confessors. And indeed his book ends—it would
mediately challenged his teacher Anselm of Laon (d. be better to say that it stops, since it is an unfinished
1117). Abelard reached the apex of his career in his work—with discussions of reconciliation and sac-
late thirties when he was master of the cathedral ramental confession. Nonetheless, the work has in-
school of Notre Dame. It was then that he met He- terest for moral philosophers and moral theologians,
loise (1101–1164), became a boarder in her uncle’s not least because of its suggestion as to precisely
house, where she lived, and seduced her under the what makes an action wrong.
guise of tutoring her in logic. When she became Abelard spends some time distinguishing willing
pregnant, he took her to Brittany, where she bore from willing sinfully, and evil DESIRE from CONSENT,
him a son. Against her wishes—self-effacingly, she and a very long time establishing that PLEASURE is
feared what marriage would do to his career—they not as such sinful. The principal interest in Abelard’s
married, but secretly. Her uncle’s attempts to pub- discussion lies in what he has to say about the rela-
licize the marriage ended in an attack on Abelard tion between desire and consent, on the one hand,
during which he was castrated. Eventually, Heloise and the external act, on the other. His aim is to locate
repaired to a convent and Abelard became a monk. the source of moral wrong in the INTENTION with
In the course of his career, he was twice condemned which the act is done and to reject the notion that it
for heresy, and attempts on his life were made by his is the external act as externally described, without
monks when he was abbot. He ended his life in an attention to the intention of the agent, that is suffi-
edifying way at Cluny, having fallen ill on his way to cient. This leads him to say that the prohibitions of
Rome to appeal his second condemnation for heresy. the Decalogue bear on internal consent and not on
Among the writings of Abelard is an ethical work the objective deed. His reason is that the same ex-
called Nosce teipsum (Know Thyself ). Abelard did ternal act can be performed by a good agent and a
not clearly distinguish between philosophical and bad agent. Their difference as morally good and bad

1
Abelard, Peter

cannot then lie in the deed they both do, but rather Epistle to the Romans (2:13). He also looked for
in the intention with which they do it. The examples evidence of Trinitarian beliefs in the pagans, how-
he uses suggest why he attracted censure. Christ was ever, which got him into rough waters theologically.
delivered up by Judas to be crucified, but also by See also: AGENT CENTERED MORALITY; AUTONOMY
God the Father. In the former case it is unjust, in the OF MORAL AGENTS; CHRISTIAN ETHICS; CONSENT;
latter just, so the deed done cannot decide the moral DESIRE; EVIL; EXTERNALISM AND INTERNALISM; FIT-
matter. The position toward which Abelard moves TINGNESS; FREE WILL; KANT; NATURAL LAW; PHILOS-
is that moral worth lies in the intention of the agent OPHY OF RELIGION; SELF-KNOWLEDGE; THEOLOGI-
and not in the deed done. CAL ETHICS; VOLUNTARISM.
While he is not at all consistent in this, sometimes
speaking of deeds themselves as unfitting, what he
Bibliography
seems clearly to want to say is that intention is the
sole source of moral value, a bad intention making
Works by Abelard
an act bad, a good intention making it good.
That what would otherwise be a good act can be Historia calamitatum. Translated by J. T. Muckle. P.I.M.S.:
Toronto, 1954.
morally vitiated by the intention with which it is
Peter Abelard’s Ethics. Translated by D. E. Luscombe. Ox-
done is clear enough. One might help another in or-
ford: Clarendon Press, 1971. Contains useful introduc-
der to lull him into a condition in which he can more tion and notes.
easily be exploited. Then helping him is no longer
praiseworthy. Moreover, there are what will come to Works about Abelard
be called indifferent acts (e.g., waggling one’s fin-
Luscombe, David. The School of Peter Abelard. Cam-
gers), which when performed are either good or bad
bridge, 1969.
because of the intent with which they are done. To
Proceedings of the International Conference, 1971. Peter
waggle one’s fingers in order to signal to an assassin Abelard. The Hague, 1974.
that his victim is approaching is considerably differ- Williams, Paul. The Moral Philosophy of Peter Abelard.
ent from waving good-bye to one’s spouse or bid- Washington, DC: University Press of America, 1980.
ding at an auction. In all these cases we have to
know the intent with which the deed is done in order Ralph McInerny
to know whether it is morally good or bad. But just
when Abelard’s position shows its value, its spong-
iness also reveals itself.
abortion
If it is a bad intention that makes the doing of the Abortion can be defined as the intentional termina-
deed bad, in what does a bad intention consist? tion of in utero fetal life after conception and before
There are reasons to think Abelard might have an- birth. The question of when, if ever, abortion is per-
swered, when the intention is to disobey God it is missible has been widely discussed and fiercely de-
wrong. This would put him securely in the Divine bated in academic circles, in the media, and on side-
Command camp. The truth is, Abelard has taken walks outside abortion clinics across the United
away the only thing that finally can make an inten- States. The 1973 Supreme Court decision that le-
tion bad. A bad intention has to be the intention to galized abortion, Roe v. Wade, increased both the
perform a bad action, to do a deed that is reprehen- volume and the heat of this discussion, and more
sible. But if there are no criteria for a bad action recent Court decisions that have clarified or re-
other than intention, the account becomes vacuous. stricted abortion rights have added fuel to an already
An unsurprising corollary of his position is the de- roaring fire. Both debates about the morality of
nial that the actual doing of the external deed adds abortion and discussions of PUBLIC POLICY have
to the good or EVIL of the intention. been polarized, notoriously acrimonious, and, some
Although we do not find a clear-cut distinction would say, futile. Perhaps the only point of agree-
between philosophy and theology in Abelard, he was ment among the various factions lies in the recog-
a champion of pagan philosophers. He was able to nition that abortion is one of the least tractable is-
argue for the justification of pagans by appeal to sues in applied ethics and one of the most troubling
NATURAL LAW, relying on PAUL’s (C.E. 5?–67?) public policy issues of the late twentieth century.

2
abortion

morally permissible and sometimes not. Moderates


The Views Characterized
differ widely in their views, both normatively and
Those who discuss the morality of abortion can theoretically. Some take the permissibility of abor-
be divided into three groups: Restrictives (who are tion to turn on the stage of fetal development, and
often characterized as Conservatives or as ‘Pro-life’); would thus allow abortion only in the earlier stages
Permissives (who are often characterized as Liberals of pregnancy. Others regard the future or potential
or as ‘Pro-choice’); and Moderates. child’s health or welfare prospects as critical, and
Restrictives believe that abortion is rarely if ever thus would permit the abortion of a severely dam-
morally permissible. Most Restrictives regard the fe- aged fetus in circumstances in which they might dis-
tus as a full moral person from very early on in its allow the abortion of a normal fetus. Some focus on
development (perhaps as early as conception) and the projected effects of the continued pregnancy and
believe that it is entitled to the same sorts of moral birth on the woman, her FAMILY, and the community
protections that postfetal persons enjoy, most nota- of which she is a part. And some hold the permis-
bly the stringent protections against being killed that sibility of abortion to turn on assessments of how
many take to be conferred by persons’ possession of much RESPONSIBILITY the woman bears for becom-
rights to life. Extreme Restrictives allow no excep- ing pregnant, or assessments of how good or bad her
tions, but most Restrictives permit abortion when it reasons are for seeking an abortion. If, for example,
is deemed necessary to save the pregnant woman’s a woman is pregnant owing to RAPE, fraud, or con-
life or when the continuation of the pregnancy pre- traceptive failure, then she bears less responsibility
sents a serious and immediate threat to her health. for becoming pregnant than she would if she had
In such cases, Restrictives think, although the killing become pregnant owing to a reckless failure to em-
of the fetus is indeed the killing of a person, it may ploy contraception in the first place, and her deci-
be a permissible form of killing in SELF-DEFENSE. sion to abort may be seen in a different light. Mod-
Permissives hold the view that abortion is rarely erates may also assess differently an indigent
if ever morally impermissible. Many of the Permis- fifteen-year-old’s desire not to continue with a preg-
sives who describe themselves as feminists maintain nancy that is the result of intercourse with her uncle,
that recognition of female EQUALITY requires ac- and an affluent married twenty-five-year-old’s desire
knowledgment of substantive reproductive rights, to postpone childbearing to a more opportune time.
including a woman’s right to decide whether or not Public opinion polls indicate that most Americans
her pregnancy will be brought to term. Other Per- regard themselves as Moderates, and that it is a
missives focus more on the issue of personal auton- woman’s reasons for seeking abortion, the stage of
omy or self-determination: overruling a woman’s re- fetal development, and a fetus’s prospects for future
productive choices is seen as inconsistent with well-being that most strongly affect their views of
respect for her as an autonomous or full moral per- abortion’s permissibility. A significant majority of
son. Though most Permissives acknowledge some Americans regard abortion as morally defensible in
moral constraints on the termination of fetal life in case of a threat to the woman’s life or health, rape,
utero, all believe that there are morally relevant incest, or severe fetal deformity.
asymmetries between the fetus and the pregnant Discussions about the morality of abortion have
woman. Because a fetus lacks at least some of the usually focused on two connected issues: the ques-
psychological and affective properties that Permis- tion of when (or whether) the fetus becomes a per-
sives take to be essential to moral personhood (for son, and the nature and scope of the moral protec-
example, the capacities for self-consciousness, self- tions, obligations, and liberties that members of the
initiated activity, communication, or interaction), moral community possess.
Permissives regard the fetus as less a person than
the pregnant woman or—if personhood is an all-or-
Personhood
nothing matter—as not a person at all. They thus
maintain that, although abortion involves the ter- Questions about fetal personhood—perhaps
mination of fetal life, it does not involve the killing most notably the question of when a developing hu-
of a full moral person. man being becomes a person, and hence a full mem-
Moderates believe that abortion is sometimes ber of the moral community—are notoriously slip-

3
abortion

pery and contentious ones. As observation of possessed a psychology, intellect, and social organi-
discussions of the issue makes clear, disagreements zation comparable to ours, would indeed be moral
about when one becomes a person generally reflect persons.
radically different understandings of what it is to be Permissives who emphasize social, interactive, or
a person, and disagreements about what it is to be conventional aspects of personhood may regard a
a person are quite intractable. Restrictives who lo- neonate’s potential for social interaction with a va-
cate the onset of personhood very early in fetal riety of other members of the community as critical.
development tend to see personhood as an all-or- They may thus be quite willing to attribute person-
nothing matter, and to understand personhood hood to a premature neonate while denying it to the
largely in biological or structural terms. They tend nine-month fetus that remains in utero. For the child
to stress both the fact that the fetus is a unique hu- who is born prematurely at eight months is in a po-
man being and the fact that human biological de- sition to interact with other individuals, and hence,
velopment is a continuous process. Because there is even though their physical development may be com-
no point in fetal development that is importantly dis- parable, the ‘younger’ neonate and ‘older’ fetus have
continuous with any other, there is no ‘magic mo- relevantly different relationships to other individuals,
ment’ at which a fetus who was not already a person as well as an altogether different sort of relationship
can be said to turn into one. Birth is rejected as an to the woman who is the biological mother.
implausible dividing line between persons and not- Finally, those who think that the psychological ca-
yet-persons, for it is thought to allow us to attribute pacities that are essential to being a self-conscious
personhood to the premature neonate who is born individual are ones that do not develop until later in
after eight months’ gestation while denying that infancy (or early childhood) may think that even a
status to the fetus who is still in utero at nine normal neonate is not properly counted as a person.
months. Since there may be no relevant develop- Usually, those who espouse such a view maintain
mental or structural differences between an eight- either that personhood is a matter of degree, rather
month-old fetus who is still in utero and one who than an all-or-nothing matter, or that neonates pos-
has just been born, those who understand person- sess some important properties that distinguish
hood largely in biological or structural terms regard them morally from fetuses. Either supposition al-
birth as too late and too arbitrary a dividing line lows them to assert that it may be wrong to kill neo-
between persons and not-yet-persons. natal proto-persons even though they are not yet
Those who locate the onset of personhood later (full) persons.
in fetal development tend to have a very different Most Moderates are not content with either Re-
understanding of personhood. Permissives who see strictive or Permissive conceptions of personhood.
personhood as less a matter of biological humanity Many people believe that there are points in fetal
or structural development and more a matter of the development that are importantly morally discontin-
development of the psychological capacities that en- uous with others: some believe that the end of the
able one to be a self-conscious, and eventually, at embryonic stage—when all the organ systems are
least minimally self-determining, individual tend to present in the developing organism—marks a mor-
locate the onset of personhood at birth, or later. ally significant boundary; others think that neuro-
Though a fetus that belongs to the species Homo logical developments, and in particular, those asso-
sapiens (rather than to any other) is biologically hu- ciated with the beginnings of sentience, are what is
man, Permissives do not think that this is sufficient critical (though there is disagreement about when
or perhaps even necessary for personhood. If it is sentience occurs). Still others hold that the onset of
the possession of psychological, social, or moral ca- viability, the point at which the fetus could survive
pacities that is critical to personhood, then there on its own if born prematurely, is what marks the
may be Homo sapiens who are not persons, and per- all-important moral boundary.
sons who are not Homo sapiens. Neonates who are
anencephalic (lacking an upper brain) and individ-
The Moral Community
uals who are profoundly mentally retarded may all
count as humans who are not persons, while extra- Though much of the discussion of the morality of
terrestrial beings who were not Homo sapiens, but abortion has centered on the question of fetal per-

4
abortion

sonhood, people have increasingly come to believe woman has reproductive rights and is entitled to re-
that issues about the morality of abortion cannot be spect as an autonomous individual, the fetus has in-
resolved by arguing about the personhood of the fe- terests that are morally considerable. Those inter-
tus; any hope of progress requires a change of strat- ests—in the avoidance of pain, or the continuation
egy. Some people arrive at this position as a prag- of life, for example—may be thought to counter-
matic matter. They believe that disagreements about balance the pregnant woman’s interest in personal
the nature of moral personhood, and the methods or reproductive autonomy except in quite extreme
by which it can be discovered or conferred, are log- circumstances.
ically irresolvable, and hence futile. Some of the peo- There are also other grounds for thinking that
ple who draw this conclusion regard it as showing the issue of fetal personhood cannot be decisive. The
that hopes for resolution of conflict about the mo- relationship between the pregnant woman and the
rality of abortion lie in shifting the discussion to developing fetus, and the nature of the dependency
other moral issues, while others take it to show that of the fetus upon the woman are, in many important
discussions about the morality of abortion should be respects, unique: they do not have clear analogues
suspended in favor of discussions about public in the relationships—even the closest, and most
policy. one-sided, dependencies—between postfetal per-
Some people favor a change of strategy not be- sons. Because of this, one may be unhappy with ei-
cause they suppose that disagreement about the na- ther the assertion of fetal personhood or its denial.
ture of personhood must be intractable, but because For the uniqueness of the fetus/woman relationship
they believe that the issue is largely moot: the rights may be thought to undermine one of abortion dis-
and protections that go along with personhood are cussants’ favorite strategies, that of attempting to
not as strong, or as important, as discussants of determine the morality of abortion by modeling po-
abortion have generally supposed them to be. On the tential conflicts of interest between the fetus and the
one hand, even if the fetus is deemed a person and pregnant woman on those that occur between post-
thus the bearer of strong rights, including rights to fetal persons. Though many of those who believe
life, killing may be permissible in a wide range of that the morality of abortion does not turn on the
circumstances. Judith THOMSON has forcefully ar- ascription (or denial) of fetal personhood are Mod-
gued that rights to life cannot be intelligibly re- erates, this belief can be consistent with Permissive
garded as absolute protections against ever being or Restrictive views as well.
killed, but must instead be seen as protections If the killing of the fetus may often be permissible
against being unjustly killed, and she presents a even if it is a person from the point of conception,
number of cases in which it would not be obviously or impermissible even if personhood is seen as be-
unjust to kill someone, even when the individual in ginning at birth or later, then the question of fetal
question is incontrovertibly a person. If—as Thom- personhood is indeed moot. But how, then, should
son argues—there are many different sorts of cir- issues concerning the morality of abortion be ap-
cumstances in which killing the fetus would not be proached? It is tempting to suppose that discussions
unjust, then abortion may not violate a fetus’s rights, of fetal personhood can be gainfully bypassed in fa-
even if it is regarded as the killing of a person. vor of incursions into moral theory, in particular, di-
On the other hand, even if the fetus is deemed a rect discussion about the nature and scope of the
nonperson, it does not follow that it is usually per- rights, liberties, and obligations that members of the
missible to kill it. Many of those who have discussed moral community possess. But this strategy may
the moral claims of nonhuman animals have argued prove to possess many of the defects that the focus
persuasively that creatures who are not (and may on fetal personhood does. For reflection on the in-
never be) persons may nevertheless have INTERESTS, tractability of discussions of fetal personhood sug-
and are thus entitled to some moral protection. De- gests that disagreements about the morality of abor-
pending on what sorts of interests a fetus is taken to tion are both deeper and broader than much of the
possess, and what weight those interests are thought polarized, black-or-white discussion suggests. It
to carry, one might maintain that the fetus is not a seems plausible to suppose that disagreements about
person and yet think that abortion is often wrong. what it is to be a person are not isolated metaphys-
For one might believe that, although the pregnant ical disagreements, but rather ones that reflect dif-

5
abortion

ferent understandings of moral community and hu- Among them: “Abortion and the Concept of a Person”
man relationship, and hence different views of by Jane English argues that the concept of a person
cannot take the weight that the abortion controversy
individuals’ obligations to and responsibilities for has put on it. “A Defense of Abortion” by Judith Jarvis
each other. But if this is so, then disagreements Thomson (orig. pub. Philosophy and Public Affairs,
about the morality of abortion may be less local vol. 1, 1971) is a classic and widely cited paper criti-
normative disagreements about when the life of cizing the restrictive view. “On the Moral and Legal
a person begins, or comes to merit special protec- Status of Abortion” by Mary Anne Warren defends the
permissive view.
tion, than broad and pervasive differences in world
Garfield, Jay L., and Patricia Hennessey, eds. Abortion:
view. Though moral theory may be able to help us
Moral and Legal Perspectives. Amherst: University of
articulate these differences, and spell out their im- Massachusetts Press, 1984. Includes a summary of
plications, it is doubtful whether it can provide a relevant legal decisions. See especially “Abortion and
basis for resolving—or even harmonizing—such Self-Defense” by Nancy Davis (orig. pub. Philosophy
differences. and Public Affairs, vol. 13, 1984), which discusses
some of the difficulties of applying self-defense argu-
See also: ANIMALS, TREATMENT OF; AUTONOMY OF ments to the abortion context.
MORAL AGENTS; DEATH; DOUBLE EFFECT; ENTITLE- Luker, Kristin. Abortion and the Politics of Motherhood.
MENTS; EUTHANASIA; FAMILY; FEMINIST ETHICS; GE- Berkeley: University of California Press, 1984. Socio-
NETIC ENGINEERING; HOMICIDE; HUMAN RIGHTS; IN- logical analysis of the abortion debate in the United
States.
FANTICIDE; INNOCENCE; KILLING/LETTING DIE; LIFE
Mohr, James C. Abortion in America. Oxford: Oxford Uni-
AND DEATH; LIFE, RIGHT TO; MEDICAL ETHICS;
versity Press, 1978. Classic historical sourcebook.
MORAL COMMUNITY, BOUNDARIES OF; PERSON, CON-
Petchesky, Rosalind Pollack. Abortion and Woman’s
CEPT OF; PUBLIC AND PRIVATE MORALITY; PUBLIC Choice. Boston: Northeastern University Press, 1985.
HEALTH POLICY; PUBLIC POLICY; RAPE; REPRODUC- Comprehensive discussion of abortion in the context
TIVE TECHNOLOGY; RIGHT HOLDERS; SELF-DEFENSE; of reproductive rights.
SEXUALITY AND SEXUAL ETHICS; SLIPPERY SLOPE AR- Sachdev, Paul. International Handbook on Abortion. New
GUMENTS; THOMSON; WELFARE RIGHTS AND SOCIAL York: Greenwood, 1988. Comprehensive assembly of
demographic data relating to abortion.
POLICY.
Sumner, Wayne. Abortion and Moral Theory. Princeton:
Princeton University Press, 1981. Defense of a mod-
Bibliography erate view.
Tooley, Michael. Abortion and Infanticide. Oxford: Ox-
Bondesman, William B., et al., eds. Abortion and the ford University Press, 1983. Comprehensive defense of
Status of the Fetus. Dordrecht: Reidel, 1983. Essays on a permissive view.
moral, legal, medical, and religious issues about
personhood. (Nancy) Ann Davis
Brody, Baruch. Abortion and the Sanctity of Human Life:
A Philosophical View. Cambridge: MIT Press, 1975.
Defense of a restrictive view. absolutes
Butler, J. Douglas, and David F. Walbert. Abortion, Med-
icine, and the Law. 3d ed. New York: Facts on File, See moral absolutes.
1986. Medical, legal, and ethical questions.
Callahan, Sidney, and Daniel Callahan, eds. Abortion: Un-
derstanding Differences. New York: Plenum, 1984. absurd, the
Philosophical, social science, and social services
perspectives. The classic formulation of the “philosophy of the
Devine, Phillip E. The Ethics of Homicide. Ithaca, NY: absurd” is found in Camus’s The Myth of Sisyphus
Cornell University Press, 1978. Restrictive view de- (1942), where he writes: “I don’t know whether this
fended in the larger context of a discussion of the mo-
world has a meaning that transcends it. But I know
rality of killing.
that I do not know that meaning and that it is im-
Feinberg, Joel. “Abortion.” In Matters of Life and Death,
edited by Tom Regan. 2d ed. New York: Random possible for me just now to know it. I can under-
House, 1986. An overview. stand only in human terms. What I touch, what re-
———, ed. The Problem of Abortion. 2d ed. Belmont, sists me—that is what I understand. And these two
CA: Wadsworth, 1984. Broad spectrum of views. certainties—my appetite for the absolute and for

6
absurd, the

unity and the impossibility of reducing this world to serious as arbitrary or open to doubt.” Though this
a rational and reasonable principle—I also know thesis seems close to that of Camus, it differs by fo-
that I cannot reconcile them.” This necessary but cusing entirely on the “collision within ourselves” of
futile search for ultimate meaning constitutes absurd two attitudes rather than on the tension between our
existence in its fundamental form. It finds imagina- attitude and the world. Nagel likens the absurdist
tive expression in the Theater of the Absurd with belief to epistemological skepticism in that both po-
works of authors like Samuel Beckett (1906–1989) sitions, on his account, recognize the futility of seek-
and Eugene Ionesco (1912–1994) and it enters ing a noncircular defense of our system of beliefs. In
theological discourse with the negative theologies of the case of absurdism, “we continue to take life
the mystics and the theology of paradox of Søren largely for granted while seeing that all our decisions
KIERKEGAARD (1813–1855) as well as in the works and certainties are possible only because there is a
of authors from the voluntarist and fideist traditions. great deal we do not bother to rule out.” (“The Ab-
In other words, the absurd need not be synonymous surd.”) What results in either case, he concludes, is
with NIHILISM, even if the two terms have been a new attitude toward knowledge and life, namely, a
closely associated since the nineteenth century. certain resignation mixed with irony.
The philosophy of the absurd has become syn- Perhaps the difference between these approaches
onymous with atheistic existentialism beginning to the absurd is best reflected emotionally in the con-
with Friedrich NIETZSCHE (1844–1900) and cul- trast between irony and anguish (Angst). The French
minating in the writings of Albert CAMUS (1913– existentialist supports a chastened hope that has
1960). Camus translated Nietzsche’s famous “death fallen away from the utopian dream of a Revolution
of God” proclamation into the premise of a philos- that had assumed mythic proportions, whereas the
ophy of life that is neo-Stoic in tone and anticipates American philosopher counsels a more pragmatic
a thesis of many postmodernist thinkers with its way of dealing with life’s pressing but unanswerable
counsel to persevere in living despite the abandon- mysteries.
ment of HOPE for ultimate meaning in life. “The only Absurdist theater, of which Beckett’s Waiting for
hope is to know there is no [ultimate] hope.” (Myth Godot (1952) is the paradigm, articulates this at-
of Sisyphus.) As the narrator in his novel The Plague mosphere of abandonment and ultimate hopeless-
(1947) observes, it is only those who seek limited ness in which one cries “I can’t go on, I’ll go on.”
HAPPINESS who can be satisfied; the idealist in search (The Unnamable [1953].) Like Camus’s Sisyphus,
of the absolute is condemned to a lifelong futile condemned for eternity to push the stone repeatedly
quest. Correspondingly, moral values are to be cre- up the hill only to see it roll back again, Beckett’s
ated, not discovered in some metaphysical system. characters are making the best of what might other-
This Nietzschean theme is echoed by Jean-Paul SAR- wise be called a “bad deal,” except that there is no
TRE (1905–1980) in his prescription from Existen- possibility of a better deal in the offing. If the only
tialism Is a Humanism (1946): “You are free, there- serious problem in our day, consequently, is SUICIDE,
fore choose, that is, invent!” Although he too denies that too becomes an absurd decision. As Camus ex-
an absolute meaning prior to human existence, Sar- plains: “The final conclusion of absurdist reasoning
tre avoids nihilism by his commitment to human is, in fact, the repudiation of suicide and the accep-
freedom as itself the supreme value and source of all tance of the desperate encounter between human in-
other values. And he does not subscribe to the “lim- quiry and the silence of the universe. . . . But it is
ited happiness” thesis that, many Marxist critics obvious that absurdism hereby admits that human
claim, seems to align Camus (and Michel FOUCAULT life is the only necessary good since it is precisely life
[1926–1984], so it has been argued by Jürgen HA- that makes this encounter possible and since, with-
BERMAS and others) with a reformist, if not a neo- out life, the absurdist wager would have no basis.”
conservative camp. (The Rebel [1951].)
From a nonexistentialist perspective, Thomas Na- Mystics, negative theologians, and fideists of vari-
gel argues that our philosophical sense of absurdity ous stripes have profited from the absurdity of our
arises from “the collision between the seriousness condition which the shipwreck of total rationality
with which we take our lives and the perpetual pos- seems to entail in order to direct our attention toward
sibility of regarding everything about which we are an entirely other dimension of meaning and/or

7
absurd, the

existence. This is the point of Tertullian’s (c. C.E. Crosby, Donald A. The Specter of the Absurd: Sources and
160–220) credo quia absurdum est (I believe be- Criticisms of Modern Nihilism. Albany, NY: State Uni-
versity of New York Press, 1988.
cause it is absurd), which Kierkegaard cites when
Lyotard, Jean-François. “The Sign of History.” In his The
appealing to the “paradox” of the Christian’s belief Differend: Phrases in Dispute, translated by Georges
in the divinity of Christ. Such theological “absurd- Van Den Abbeele, 151–81. Minneapolis, MN: Univer-
ism” resembles much philosophical skepticism: a sity of Minnesota Press, 1988.
strategic move to disarm the power of a destroying Nagel, Thomas. Mortal Questions. Cambridge: Cam-
rationality in defense of traditional values or NORMS. bridge University Press, 1979. Chapter 2, “The Ab-
Where philosophy and theology overlap on the surd,” 11–23.
matter of absurdity is in the problem of moral EVIL. Sartre, Jean-Paul. Being and Nothingness. Translated by
Hazel E. Barnes. New York: Humanities Press, Philo-
The questions—which cannot be answered ade-
sophical Library, 1956. Tr. of L’Être et le néant [1943].
quately—“Why do bad things happen to good peo-
———. “Existentialism Is a Humanism.” In Existentialism
ple?” and more specifically, “Why do good people from Dostoevsky to Sartre, edited by Walter Kaufmann,
suffer at the hands of others?” have been common 287–311. Cleveland, OH: World Publishing, Meridian
objections to the idea of a God that cares (Provi- Books, 1956. Tr. of L’Existentialism est un humanisme
dence). Though this need not lead to the conclusion [1946].
that the universe is not only indifferent but mean- Thomas R. Flynn
ingless, it often does—so close, in the eyes of many,
is the conceptual link between “it all making sense”
and the existence of a personal God.
In the wake of postmodernist critiques of a mono- Abunaser
lithic “Enlightenment Reason” and the concomitant See Fārābı̄, al-.
claim that “the fission of meaning” is the philosoph-
ical “sign of our times”, much as the revolutionary
enthusiasm for freedom was the sign (die Begeben-
heit) of history in KANT’s (1724–1804) day, a cer-
academic ethics
tain absurdist specter seems to linger on the horizon Academic life generates a variety of moral issues.
of contemporary thought. These issues may be faced by students, staff, admin-
istrators, trustees, or even alumni, but most often
See also: ATHEISM; CAMUS; EVIL; EXISTENTIAL
revolve around the obligations of the faculty. Its in-
ETHICS; FREEDOM AND DETERMINISM; KIERKE-
formed judgments lie at the heart of the educational
GAARD; LIFE, MEANING OF; METAPHYSICS AND EPIS-
process, and the study of its critical role is the central
TEMOLOGY; MORAL IMAGINATION; MYSTICISM; NEO-
focus of academic ethics.
STOICISM; NIETZSCHE; NIHILISM; POSTMODERNISM;
The essence of the professor’s life is the pursuit
RATIONALITY AND REASONABLENESS; SARTRE; SKEP-
of knowledge. To ensure that this search is not ob-
TICISM IN ETHICS; SUICIDE; THEOLOGICAL ETHICS;
structed on political, religious, or any other grounds,
VOLUNTARISM.
faculty members are protected by ACADEMIC FREE-
DOM, the right of professionally qualified persons to
Bibliography seek, teach, and publish the truth as they see it
Beckett, Samuel. The Unnamable. New York: Alfred A. within their fields of competence.
Knopf, 1997. Tr. of L’Innommable [1953]. Academic freedom is imperiled whenever an
———. Waiting for Godot. New York: Grove Press, 1954. ideological test is imposed to determine who will be
Tr. of En attendant Godot [1952]. appointed to the faculty, whenever a school adopts
Camus, Albert. The Myth of Sisyphus and Other Essays. an official stance on issues unrelated to its educa-
Translated by Justin O’Brien. New York: Alfred A. tional mission, or whenever a presentation by some
Knopf, 1995.
campus speaker is interfered with on the grounds
———. The Plague. Translated by Stuart Gilbert. New
York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1948. Tr. of La peste [1947]. that the views expressed are unpalatable. Some have
———. The Rebel. Translated by Anthony Bower. New argued that such actions may occasionally be justi-
York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1954. Tr. of L’Homme révolté fied on the grounds that they achieve a greater good,
[1951]. such as preventing the spread of racial or religious

8
academic ethics

bigotry, but it is generally accepted that the onus lies student views be solicited without exposing the
on those who would subordinate academic freedom teacher to intimidation?
to a supposedly higher end. Faculty autonomy, how-
ever, does not imply the absence of RESPONSIBILITY.
Scholarship
Teaching, scholarship, and service all have an ethical
dimension. Professors profess the worth of their subjects, and
no subject can thrive in the absence of new contri-
butions. Publications, then, ought to result from a
Teaching
faculty member’s commitment to the advance of a
Professors are authorities, experts in their fields, discipline. In addition, those instructors expected to
and in virtue of superior knowledge they are as- provide original perspectives in the classroom ought
signed AUTHORITY to guide the educational process. to have their abilities to do so evaluated periodically
Mishandled, however, the use of authority can de- in accordance with rigorous standards set and main-
generate into authoritarianism, guidance can be- tained by peers who referee works for publication
come domination, and education can turn into in- and comment on materials when they appear.
doctrination. These crucial distinctions need to be Yet it has been argued that emphasis on publish-
drawn with care. ing can lead to neglect of teaching. To what extent
Professors are expected to judge fairly the extent are the two activities complementary, and what is the
of each student’s accomplishment. Examinations appropriate balance between them?
and grades are traditionally used to achieve this goal. All researchers are bound by common ethical
Yet examinations have been criticized for stifling principles. Chief among these is the axiom that in-
students’ creativity, and grades, it has been said, are dividuals should not claim credit for work they have
inherently inaccurate devices which, in attempting not done. In addition, they are obligated to study
to measure people, succeed only in traumatizing and available literature carefully, provide accurate cita-
dehumanizing them. A critical challenge is to for- tions, not distort opposing views, and not overstate
mulate methods of evaluation that can withstand their own conclusions.
such criticisms. It seems to follow directly that research findings
Fair evaluation requires the absence of PARTIAL- should be made public, so that they are available for
ITY. But FRIENDSHIP, unlike friendliness or goodwill, use by the community of scholars. But suppose a
implies favoritism. How, then, can professors be funding agency insists that it will finance a study
friends with those they are supposed to evaluate? only if the results are kept confidential or remain
If friendship between professor and student is in- entirely under its control. Given a university’s com-
appropriate, so, a fortiori, is romance. Furthermore, mitment to an open atmosphere of unrestricted in-
given the POWER and prestige of the faculty, students quiry, when, if ever, is a researcher justified in ac-
are especially vulnerable to sexual EXPLOITATION. cepting support under conditions of secrecy?
When an unscrupulous professor is known to have
used cajolery or COERCION to take advantage of a
Service
student, faculty colleagues are thereby challenged to
make an appropriate ethical judgment and take suit- Scholars are engaged in a cooperative enterprise
able action. and ought to treat each other with amity and INTEG-
RITY. In offering evaluations of research they should
not indulge in captious criticism; in providing letters
Evaluating Teaching
of recommendation they should not offer exagger-
Virtually every empirical study of alternative ated praise.
methods of judging teachers has concluded that peer An additional professorial duty is to take on a fair
review is a major component of any sound evalua- share of the sundry, day-to-day tasks that are an in-
tion. Yet many schools rely almost entirely on stu- escapable part of the institution’s life. Failure to join
dent opinion. What are the appropriate limits to this in this work unfairly burdens colleagues.
practice, given that students, by definition, do not Faculty members are also obliged to ensure that
know the subjects they are studying? And how can individuals deserve the degrees they are awarded.

9
academic ethics

For example, students granted liberal arts degrees ———, gen. ed. Issues in Academic Ethics. Lanham, MD:
should actually have obtained the essentials of a lib- Rowman and Littlefield, 1993–. Ten volumes have
been published; ten are in preparation.
eral education. Suitable requirements should be es-
Robinson, George M., and Janice Moulton. Ethical Prob-
tablished to guarantee the worth of a diploma, and lems in Higher Education. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Pren-
these should be examined regularly and modified tice Hall, 1985.
appropriately. Shils, Edward. The Calling of Education. Chicago and
London: University of Chicago Press, 1997.
Personnel Decisions Steven M. Cahn
Appointments to a faculty ought to be made only
after a widespread search has been carried out with
scrupulous attention to proper procedures. At every academic freedom
stage of the process, ethical issues may arise. These The freedom to teach and do research in any schol-
frequently call for balancing an applicant’s RIGHTS arly discipline without constraint; to discover and
and an institution’s INTERESTS. For example, to what promulgate new ideas no matter how controversial.
extent is it appropriate to ask candidates questions Like other accepted freedoms, academic freedom re-
about their personal life? quires individuals, authorities, and governments not
Other issues relate to decision procedures in mat- only to allow scholars to work without restraint but
ters of appointment or promotion. Who is entitled also to prevent any interference with this freedom.
to vote, and should individual judgments be kept In addition, academic freedom seems to require
secret? something more: that society provide conditions in
The most crucial personnel decision is the award- which new ideas can be generated, nurtured, and
ing of tenure. This prerogative protects academic freely exchanged.
freedom by providing professors an extraordinary Historical examples show the need for academic
degree of latitude and security. Yet such privilege freedom. SOCRATES (c. 470–399 B.C.E.) was put to
leads into an ethical thicket, for how can unprofes- death for corrupting the youth of Athens with his
sional conduct be deterred without undermining ideas. Galileo (1564–1642) was sentenced to life
faculty autonomy? imprisonment for advocating the Copernican view
A university is morally committed to harbor dis- of the solar system. DESCARTES (1596–1650) sup-
sent, nonconformity, and even the most unpopular pressed his own writing to avoid similar trouble.
of heresies. What ought never be tolerated is pro- Teachers were fired for telling their students about
fessorial malfeasance. DARWIN’s (1809–1882) views. The ideas of these
See also: ACADEMIC FREEDOM; AUTHORITY; COER- great thinkers have survived, but we will never know
CION; EXPLOITATION; FAIRNESS; FRIENDSHIP; IMPAR- how many others were completely suppressed. Rec-
TIALITY; INSTITUTIONS; PATERNALISM; PERSONAL RE- ognizing the need to protect controversial ideas,
LATIONSHIPS; PLAGIARISM; POWER; PROFESSIONAL nineteenth-century German universities affirmed the
ETHICS; RESPONSIBILITY; SEXUAL ABUSE AND HA- ideal of academic freedom. During the modern era,
RASSMENT. the United States Supreme Court reaffirmed aca-
demic freedom in Sweezey v. New Hampshire
(1957): “to impose any straitjacket upon the intel-
Bibliography
lectual leaders in our colleges and universities would
American Association of University Professors. “State- imperil the future of the nation.”
ment on Professional Ethics.” Academe 73 (1987): 49. Academic freedom can be justified in two ways.
Brown, William R. Academic Politics. Birmingham: Uni- First, one can appeal to a higher value—the pursuit
versity of Alabama Press, 1982. of truth—to argue that we must protect ideas that
Cahn, Steven M. Saints and Scamps: Ethics in Academia.
may be unpopular, controversial, or without imme-
Rev. ed. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 1994
[1986]. diate practical benefit in order to support truth. Sec-
———, ed. Morality, Responsibility, and the University: ond, one can argue that academic freedom is nec-
Essays in Academic Ethics. Philadelphia: Temple Uni- essary to benefit human welfare, which depends on
versity Press, 1990. the discovery and propagation of new knowledge.

10
academic freedom

Since we cannot predict which knowledge will be requires access to students; research requires librar-
helpful in the future, all new knowledge should be ies, laboratories, and other facilities. Modern schol-
protected. ars need access to photocopy machines, computer
The first justification seems to be the simpler. If databases, colleagues to consult, journal and book
we take the pursuit of truth as a higher value, then editors willing to publish their work. These re-
no knowledge should be suppressed. Even harmful sources are limited. Not everyone can be accom-
truths are truths nonetheless. But there is a problem. modated. The difficulty of deciding how to distrib-
If the discovery and promulgation of truth is our ute these limited resources raises serious questions
primary aim, it might be acceptable or even desirable about academic freedom.
to suppress false information that threatens to dis- Educational institutions are the primary provid-
place true information. The problem is the difficulty ers of scholarly resources. Therefore the protection
in determining what new information is true. Who of academic freedom is usually thought to be the
decides what is true and what is false? Historically, responsibility of colleges and universities. However,
those who tried to suppress new information usually academic institutions are meritocracies, not democ-
believed they were trying to preserve the truth. Now racies. They make no attempt to distribute their re-
we know that they were mistaken. We might assume sources to everyone. Instead, they try to reserve
that, given enough intellectual scrutiny, true infor- these resources for people who they judge can best
mation will eventually defeat false information. make use of them. But how do educational institu-
Then we can decide the best policy is to suppress no tions judge who is most suitable?
information. However, there is no guarantee that The freedom to develop and teach new ideas can
true information will always displace false or that be encouraged or discouraged in many ways. The
this system is an efficient way to establish truth. most prominent way that educational institutions
Consider now the second justification: that hu- encourage academic freedom is the granting of ten-
man welfare is primary. This justification seems to ure. Tenure provides job security for teachers and
allow limits on academic freedom. Some things that scholars. It is usually granted after a period of pro-
are discovered and taught might be harmful, might bation, as a symbol of merit. This reinforces the idea
even endanger the future of our species. False infor-
that academic freedom is a privilege.
mation is more likely to be harmful, but true infor-
The tenure system has been criticized because it
mation might also be harmful. Some argue that ac-
can be easily abused. People with tenure can hold
ademic freedom must be limited when there is a
their positions and do very little work. They cannot
serious threat to human welfare. They cite examples
be fired for being lazy teachers, poor researchers, or
such as the danger caused by radioactivity from nu-
uncooperative employees. Defenders of the tenure
clear weapons research or the danger of biological
system, like defenders of other protective systems,
“wildfire” from accidents in recombinant genetic
argue that protecting the work of original, unpopu-
engineering.
lar thinkers is more important than preventing the
Even if we take human welfare to be primary, we
“deadwood” in academic departments from slack-
can still defend the principle of academic freedom.
ing off.
It is too difficult to anticipate what knowledge will
Tenure has also been criticized because its pro-
turn out to be harmful. It is too dangerous to allow
tection of academic freedom is withheld from the
some people to decide what may be studied and
people who may need it the most—younger scholars
what may not, what information should be available
and what should be suppressed. In general, the who are more likely to innovate and to challenge
larger benefit of supporting the principle of uncon- established paradigms. Unless their senior col-
strained research and teaching seems to be worth the leagues support them enthusiastically, untenured
risk of occasional harmful effects. Therefore, we scholars may be fired no matter how excellent or
should support the principle of academic freedom. original their teaching or research. Junior scholars
may lose their jobs because their senior colleagues
do not approve of their research or the material they
Academic Freedom: Privilege or Right
teach, regardless of its quality.
The exercise of academic freedom depends on re- There is usually a six-year probationary period be-
sources that are not available to everyone. Teaching fore tenure is granted at the university level; it is

11
academic freedom

often shorter for secondary school teachers. In guarantee the ability to teach or study freely. Ten-
higher education the average period a junior scholar ured faculty members have been fired for their po-
must work before receiving tenure is increasing in litical beliefs or private indiscretions. Tenured fac-
length as the supply of academic jobs decreases. ulty members with controversial ideas have been
Many scholars go from one untenured position to given undesirable teaching assignments, burdened
another. Scholars who do get tenure may wait twelve with tedious administrative jobs, or denied research
or more years. During this time they work under facilities. While tenure is the main formal protection
conditions of restricted academic freedom. They for academic freedom offered by educational insti-
must be cautious about expressing scholarly or per- tutions, not all institutions offer it. Educational in-
sonal views that may offend senior faculty members stitutions have the power to foster academic free-
and cost them their jobs. The pressure to “publish dom in many ways besides tenure: for example,
or perish” also discourages innovation because in- reducing teaching loads, or granting travel funds
novation requires taking chances that may not result and sabbatical leaves so that faculty members can
in publication. Many of those who are finally granted develop new ideas and exchange ideas with col-
tenure after this long period have learned to avoid leagues at other institutions. Many institutions ex-
daring or controversial research and teaching. Ironi- tend the academic freedom of their students by al-
cally, those who finally receive tenure’s protection of lowing a wide choice of courses. They extend
academic freedom may be the ones who need it least. academic freedom outside the institution by giving
Some hold that tenure should be restricted, that members of the public access to their libraries and
full academic freedom is a privilege to be granted some research facilities.
only after the new scholar demonstrates a record of In some fields, other resources are more impor-
extraordinary contributions. Untenured status is an tant to academic freedom than tenure—access to ar-
apprenticeship that allows the university to identify tifacts, special libraries, private collections, labora-
the most talented scholars. The more untenured tory space, and equipment. These resources can be
scholars an institution has, the more easily it can denied to scholars whose views threaten the people
replace them with people who have new ideas. Un- who control access. And even if the research is suc-
fortunately, this view offers no protection to unten- cessfully completed, it still needs to be made public.
ured scholars who have new ideas that displease se- Journal editors and referees are less likely to rec-
nior colleagues or that fall outside established ommend publication of articles that challenge their
paradigms. own ideas. Publishing houses have been pressured
Others believe that it is young scholars with new by academics not to produce certain books. Librar-
ideas who are most in need of protection. They see ies and bookstores have been pressured to withdraw
scholars who do original work being dismissed for offending books from circulation. Government and
irrelevant reasons and want junior scholars to have industry keep secret the results of research done un-
the same job security as their seniors. They argue der their auspices, even when conducted in institu-
that the quality of research and teaching would be tions of higher education.
improved if working conditions were more secure Teachers, especially those whose evaluations are
and the POWER differences between tenured and un- based on class size and student opinion surveys, feel
tenured faculty members were lessened. This system pressure to please their audiences, sometimes at the
is generally followed in Great Britain and some other expense of educational goals. Teaching curricula are
countries. Opponents point out that in countries affected by ideology, politics, and current intellec-
where job security is granted to new scholars, there tual fashions. Researchers feel pressure to focus on
are fewer academic jobs available and fewer scholars subjects supported by grants from government, in-
can find any academic employment. To compromise, dustry, and foundations.
institutions might give longer contracts to all schol- Research and teaching will always be constrained
ars but eliminate tenure. by outside pressures. The means for exercising aca-
Many who have discussed academic freedom demic freedom—tenure, research support, and pub-
equate it with tenure. Yet the job security that tenure lication space—will always be relatively scarce re-
provides is not enough. Tenure may increase the ac- sources. We should evaluate how these resources are
ademic freedom of some scholars, but it does not distributed. We must consider who should choose

12
action

the recipients of these resources. It may seem that 360–70. Political and personal factors affect judg-
those who have demonstrated competence in a ments of who deserves tenure.
Robinson, G. M., and J. Moulton. Ethical Problems in
scholarly discipline are best able to make the deci-
Higher Education. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall,
sions. However established scholars are intellectu- 1985. Chapter 3 treats the hiring and evaluation of fac-
ally, emotionally, and financially invested in certain ulty; chapter 5 covers ethical problems in teaching.
theories, approaches, and dogma. Given human na- Schneewind, Jerome. “On ‘On Tenure’.” Philosophical Fo-
ture, it is difficult for judges to accept a new idea rum 10 (1979): 353–59. A defense of the tenure
that challenges what they themselves believe, espe- system.
cially when they know that their views are shared by George Robinson
other leading scholars in a field. We should recog- Janice Moulton
nize the dangers of self-perpetuating paradigms and
try to discover ways of overcoming them.
We can look beyond tenure for means of preserv- action
ing academic freedom and ask whether the resources
Moral judgments ostensibly presuppose that there
for academic freedom should be distributed more
are actions, or acts, since it is precisely acts, or
widely or more narrowly; whether these resources
deeds, that are frequently called right or wrong.
should be distributed to encourage merit, diversity,
While the existence of acts remains slightly contro-
or some other property; and whether the creative
versial among metaphysicians, more intense contro-
thinking and hard work that results in new knowl-
versy concerns what they are.
edge is more likely to be inspired by the pressure of
regular evaluation or by freedom from job insecurity.
Types and Tokens
See also: ACADEMIC ETHICS; AUTHORITY; CENSOR-
SHIP; DESCARTES; ELITE, CONCEPT OF; GOVERNMENT, First, we must distinguish act types from act to-
ETHICS IN; LIBERTY; LIBRARY AND INFORMATION PRO- kens. An act type is a kind of action, like whistling
FESSIONS; MERIT AND DESERT; POLITICAL CORRECT- or mailing a letter. An act token is a particular ac-
NESS; PROFESSIONAL ETHICS; SOCRATES. tion, performed by a particular person, at a partic-
ular time. When speaking of acts as right or wrong,
usually act tokens are in question; the specific deed
Bibliography done by Jones in a particular context is said to be
Atherton, M., S. Morgenbesser, and R. Schwartz. “On wrong, even if other deeds of the same type might
Tenure.” Philosophical Forum 10 (1979): 341–52. not be wrong. It is also possible to hold, however,
Junior scholars need protection, too. that an act type is wrong, meaning perhaps that any
Brubacher, J. S. On the Philosophy of Higher Education. token of the type is wrong.
San Francisco: Jossey-Bass, 1977. Chapter 3 presents
a thorough discussion of academic freedom, its justi-
fication, limits, and relation to other rights. Act Individuation
Cahn, S. M. Education and the Democratic Ideal. Chi- The main controversies in action theory concern
cago: Nelson-Hall, 1979. Argues that tenure is neces- act tokens. Suppose that Sally opens her hand,
sary to protect academic freedom but that it should be
granted less often and terminated more frequently.
thereby releasing a plastic cup, thereby littering the
Hook, Sidney. In Defense of Academic Freedom. New
highway, and thereby violating a statute. Presumably
York: Pegasus, 1971. Student challenges to university each of the following is an act token: (a) Sally’s
traditions in the 1960s are seen as a threat to academic opening her hand; (b) her releasing the cup; (c) her
freedom. littering the highway; and (d) her violating a statute.
Hook, Sidney, P. Kurtz, and M. Todorovich. The Ethics of Are these one and the same act token, or four dis-
Teaching and Scientific Research. Buffalo, NY: Pro- tinct act tokens?
metheus, 1977. Hook argues that academic freedom
The first answer, that they are the same act token,
(which he equates with tenure) is a privilege. Kurtz
examines claims that some scientific research should has been defended by G. E. M. ANSCOMBE (1919–
not be done because of dangers or possible misuses. 2001) and Donald Davidson, the latter’s defense be-
Jaggar, Alison. “Tenure, Academic Freedom and Profes- ing partly based on his account of the logical form
sional Competence.” Philosophical Forum 10 (1979): of action sentences. According to Davidson’s ac-

13
action

count, the sentence “Sally opened her hand” is


Doing versus Undergoing
(roughly) equivalent to: “There was an event E such
that E was a hand opening and E was performed by When you are “seized” by a sneeze or cough, or
Sally.” The same event can also be described in terms when you sweat, you do not act; you do not do any-
of its effects, namely, the release of the plastic cup, thing. What is the difference? One theory here is
litter being on the highway, and a statute being vi- causalism: a piece of behavior qualifies as action if
olated. Hence, this event was the releasing (by Sally) it is caused by an appropriate mental event, such as
of the cup, and was the littering of the highway and an INTENTION, a volition, a trying, or a set of desires
was the violating of a statute. Call this the unity ap- and beliefs. This is related to theories claiming that
proach to act individuation. reasons explanations are causal explanations. It goes
Although intuitively appealing, the unity ap- a bit further in claiming a “reduction” of the notion
proach faces ostensibly damaging problems. Some of action to the notions of behavior, event causation,
of these concern causal properties of the act(s). As and selected mental events. A principal difficulty for
Alvin Goldman observes, it looks true to say that this view is the existence of “deviant” causal chains
Sally’s opening her hand caused the release of the between inner events and behavior, chains that don’t
cup, but false to say that Sally’s littering the highway render the resulting behavior an action. Opposed to
caused the release of the cup. How does this square causalism are two views. The agency theory (of
with the alleged fact that the highway littering is the Richard Taylor and Roderick Chisholm [1916–
hand opening? A second problem, posed by Judith 1999], for example) claims that an action is some-
THOMSON and others, involves temporal properties. thing produced by a particular kind of subject, an
Booth killed Lincoln by shooting him. Can the kill- agent, who is something like an unmoved mover.
ing be identical with the shooting, as the unity ap- The exact nature of such a being, however, and its
proach claims? The time of the killing surely mode of operation are obscure. A second and com-
stretches until the time of death, which in this case plementary approach, teleologism, claims that doing
occurred well after the shooting. If the shooting were something for a purpose, or in order to achieve an
the killing, however, they would occupy the same end, is a primitive and irreducible notion.
time interval.
Unity theorists try to reply to these problems, but
other theorists opt for a pluralist approach. In each
Basic and Nonbasic Acts
example, they claim, there is a multiplicity of distinct
(though possibly overlapping) acts. One version It seems natural to distinguish acts that are “di-
construes each causative act as a sequence or fusion rectly” versus only “indirectly” within our power.
of events: an initial act plus a chain of its causal Curling a finger and smiling fall in the first category;
consequences. Booth’s killing Lincoln is a whole of starting a revolution falls in the second. Members of
which his shooting is just a part (a view endorsed by the first category are basic acts. A basic act type
Thomson, Irving Thalberg, Lawrence Davis, and might be explained as a property that a person can
Fred Dretske). A second variant of pluralism has exemplify at will, even without specialized means-
been advanced by Jaegwon Kim for events generally ends knowledge (or belief).
and by Goldman for actions. This is the property With respect to act tokens, the unity theorist has
exemplification approach, which in the action case no need to distinguish basic from nonbasic, because
identifies an act token with the exemplifying of an all act tokens would be (identical to) basic ones. The
act type (a property) by an agent at a specific time pluralist, by contrast, standardly insists on this dis-
(cf. Jonathan Bennett’s “trope” theory). Exemplify- tinction. Every act token is either basic or arises
ings of distinct act types are distinct act tokens, even from a basic act token via the “by” relation. In Gold-
if their agent and time are the same. How does this man’s theory, the “by” relation (dubbed level gen-
approach accommodate the intuition that groups of eration) spawns an action “tree” from each basic act
such acts are intimately related? They are related, it token. A token on such a tree is intentional if the
says, via the “by” relation, the relation holding be- agent has a plan featuring that token (either as a goal
tween action pairs when one is done by doing the or a means) and the plan causes (in the “right” way)
other. its own realization, or at least partial realization.

14
acts and omissions

Chisholm, Roderick. “Freedom and Action.” In Freedom


Sources and Plans of Action and Determinism, edited by Keith Lehrer. New York:
Random House, 1966.
There are many theories about the springs of ac-
Davidson, Donald. Essays on Actions and Events. Oxford:
tion. One controversy is whether all sources of ac- Oxford University Press, 1980.
tion include desire-like elements (the Humean ap- Davis, Lawrence. Theory of Action. Englewood Cliffs, NJ:
proach), or whether there are REASONS FOR ACTION, Prentice Hall, 1979.
such as respect for duty, that have a different char- Dretske, Fred. Explaining Behavior. Cambridge: MIT
acter (the Kantian approach). A second controversy Press, 1988.
concerns the logical and temporal structure of PRAC- Goldman, Alvin. A Theory of Human Action. Englewood
TICAL REASONING. How do intentions and plans for Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall, 1970.
action change in response to new MOTIVES and in- Hornsby, Jennifer. Actions. London: Routledge and Kegan
formation, and how is it rational for these to Paul, 1980.
change? Kim, Jaegwon. “Events as Property Exemplifications.” In
Action Theory, edited by Myles Brand and Douglas
Walton. Dordrecht: Reidel, 1976.
The Moral Status of Actions Taylor, Richard. Action and Purpose. Englewood Cliffs,
NJ: Prentice Hall, 1966.
How does moral status attach to acts? In the lan-
Thalberg, Irving. Perception, Emotion and Action. New
guage of the unity theory, does it attach to whole Haven: Yale University Press, 1977.
“concrete” actions or only to some descriptions Thomson, Judith Jarvis. Acts and Other Events. Ithaca,
thereof? In pluralist terms, must all acts on an act NY: Cornell University Press, 1977.
tree have the same moral status, or can their status
differ? Differences seem possible. If X does Y a fa- Alvin Goldman
vor, but in a fashion that causes Z harm, the first Holly Smith
act, but not the second, seems meritorious. How-
ever, there may be a principle of “inheritance” dic-
tating that whenever one act on an act tree has a acts
certain moral status, lower acts on the tree inherit
See voluntary acts.
that status. Or perhaps acts on the same tree can
differ in prima facie rightness or wrongness but not
in overall rightness or wrongness. A satisfactory the-
ory of moral status should address this issue. acts and omissions
See also: ACTS AND OMISSIONS; ANSCOMBE; AUTON- Very broadly, the act/omission distinction is that
OMY OF MORAL AGENTS; CAUSATION AND RESPON- between acting and failing to act, between a doing
SIBILITY; CONSEQUENTIALISM; DELIBERATION AND or a doing-something and a not-doing or a doing-
CHOICE; DESIRE; DOUBLE EFFECT; FREEDOM AND DE- nothing. Further refinement is clearly necessary,
TERMINISM; INTENTION; INTRANSITIVITY; METAETH- however, since not all failures to act are omissions.
ICS; MORAL ABSOLUTES; MOTIVES; PRACTICAL REA- A nonsurgeon who fails to save a child who can be
SON[ING]; RATIONAL CHOICE; REASONS FOR ACTION; saved only through surgery would seem a case in
RESPONSIBILITY; THOMSON; VOLUNTARY ACTS; point. Moreover, when one is doing something, e.g.,
WEAKNESS OF WILL. reading a book, one is not doing a number of other
things, e.g., mowing the lawn or cooking a meal, and
Bibliography some way is needed of telling which of those things
one is not doing counts as an omission.
Anscombe, G. E. M. Intention. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, At a minimum, three conditions are necessary for
1957.
turning a failure to act into an omission. First, one
Bennett, Jonathan. Events and Their Names. Indianapolis,
IN: Hackett, 1988.
must have the ability to do whatever is in question.
Brand, Myles. Intending and Acting. Cambridge: MIT A nonsurgeon lacks the ability to save the child, just
Press, 1984. as a nonswimmer lacks the ability to swim out and
Bratman, Michael. Intention, Plans, and Practical Reason. save a drowning person. Second, one must have the
Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1987. opportunity to do whatever is in question. If a swim-

15
acts and omissions

mer never comes across a drowning person or if a ers who fail to discharge these duties can be held,
firefighter never encounters people trapped in a absent some excusing condition, to be guilty of an
burning building, then they do not omit to save immoral/illegal omission.
someone. To this second condition, a restriction Of course, something other than duty can explain
might be appended, namely, that the opportunity to why one is expected to act in the situation, though
save a life must occur in circumstances that are not the line of argument to an immoral/illegal omission
themselves life threatening or otherwise represent may be less clear. Is a man who habitually mows his
catastrophic loss to the agent. A firefighter who can neighbor’s lawn guilty of an immoral omission, if he
save someone only by going into an out-of-control, does not mow it this time? Certainly, his past be-
raging inferno would seem to fall under this restric- havior has led his neighbor to expect him to mow.
tion. Third, one is or will be expected to do whatever But is his failure to meet his neighbor’s expectations
is in question. When we say that surgeons or fire- in this regard a moral matter? Whereas, if he is un-
fighters “omitted” to save someone, we in part allude der a duty, say, as the result of promising to mow
to the fact that they are or may be expected to save throughout the summer, the neighbor’s expectations
them. This helps to deal with the many things sur- arise as the result of a moral undertaking on the
geons and firefighters do not do (at a time when they agent’s part.
are doing something), things which we do not treat If a lifeguard walks past a drowning person, then,
as omissions on their parts. At a minimum, then, absent some excusing condition, she is guilty of an
ability, opportunity, and expectation are elements re- immoral omission. If the child of the drowning per-
quired in order to turn a failure to act into an son walks past, some might want to claim that there
omission. is a moral duty of RECIPROCITY or of GRATITUDE be-
Each of these elements can be controversial. tween children and parents and so claim that the
Thus, ability can take the form, not of having a kind child is guilty of an immoral omission. What if a
of technical expertise, but of having a resource, such stranger walks past? Here, some have wanted to ap-
as a dollar. Suppose one buys a newspaper: are all peal to a general moral duty of rescue (there may no
the other things one does not do with one’s dollar prescribed general legal duty of rescue in the legal
omissions? If so, then it is comparatively easy to code in question) or to a moral duty to render mu-
charge people with a great number of omissions at tual aid in order to hold the stranger guilty of an
every moment of their lives. This in turn seems to immoral omission. Precisely because the moral cases
drain the notion of its significance: it merely refers for these last alleged duties are still contested, it is
to all the things one is not doing, when one is doing not clear how persuasive general moral claims for
something. Again, over opportunity, it can be un- rescue are. Moreover, if there is such a general moral
clear what represents catastrophic loss to agents. duty, then one’s liberty to spend one’s dollar on a
Loss of life clearly counts; but what about loss of newspaper constantly runs up against one’s duty to
dollars to spend? Can one deny that one has omitted feed the starving poor. Do duties always trump lib-
to save famine victims by arguing that loss of these erties? Or can some of one’s liberties defy a duty,
dollars would, though not severely, nevertheless sig- say, to aid others?
nificantly affect how one lives? (More on the expec- If the duty view enables us to identify which fail-
tation condition follows below.) ures to act on the agent’s part are immoral/illegal
Plainly, not all omissions are immoral/illegal omissions, it also enables us to characterize an omis-
ones: in failing to turn out the light upon leaving the sion as the failure of the discharge of the duty to
room, one is not usually held to be guilty of an im- occur, where the discharge of the duty would be, so
moral/illegal omission. To obtain this result, we to speak, the completed act. In other words, once
need to add, for instance, that the agent is under a we know what the completed act would be, i.e.,
moral and/or legal duty to do whatever is in ques- what the discharge of the duty would be, we know
tion. (Our knowledge that the agent is under such a what an omission or failure to achieve the completed
duty helps explain why we expect the agent to do act would be; we then construe the latter in terms
something in the situation.) Jobs such as surgeon, of the former. If the lifeguard jumps in, she dis-
firefighter, and lifeguard are in part defined in terms charges her duty and saves a person from drowning;
of the duties they impose on their holders, and hold- if she does not jump in, she fails to discharge her

16
acts and omissions

duty and so fails to save a person from drowning. they are attempts to capture and support. This
We understand her omission—not saving a life—by claim—that, if we think of the act/omission distinc-
first understanding what the completed act—saving tion in terms of that between killing and letting die,
a life—would be, if she discharged her duty. killing is morally worse than letting die—is strongly
With this duty view of immoral/illegal omissions, disputed by consequentialists and on a number of
of course, complications can arise and, on occasions, counts. Yet its defense is of the utmost importance
of a peculiar kind. What if the drowning man’s son to the character of the deontological positions that
is required by some duty to aid or to show gratitude many of their opponents espouse and find compat-
to jump in after his father but is required as a doctor, ible with (what they take to be) “ordinary” or “com-
at the same time, to perform the serious operation monsense” morality.
he is scheduled to perform? Since he cannot do In short, current controversies over the KILLING/
both, is he guilty of an immoral omission, whichever LETTING DIE distinction and over the doctrine of
act he fails to perform? The mere claim that the son DOUBLE EFFECT have brought the act/omission dis-
is confronted with a conflict of duties and must de- tinction to great prominence in ethics and have
cide in the circumstances which is more stringent made it, and the issues that surround it, one source
provides no answer. For this simply tells us how the of major disagreement between consequentialists
son is to decide what to do; it does not show that, and their opponents.
should he decide to save his father, he is under no One of these surrounding issues that has proved
duty to operate. If, then, the decision of stringency absorbing and important in its own right is whether
does not extinguish the other duty, is the son guilty omissions are causes. If one omits to save a drown-
of an immoral omission, whichever way he decides? ing man, and if the man dies, then it is not only
Certainly, even though the conditions of the duty consequentialists to whom it may well appear that
view have been satisfied, it seems harsh to suggest one’s omission plays a causal role in the man’s death.
that he is; equally, however, those conditions are sat- Deontologists have generally rejected any such sug-
isfied, and life, it might be thought, often has a way gestion, insisting, among other things, that killing
of making us “damned if we do and damned if we and letting die have different causal structures as-
don’t.” sociated with them. In killing, one is the direct agent
Is the act/omission distinction morally signifi- of death; in “allowing” or “permitting” to die, one is
cant? On the whole, consequentialists deny that it not the direct agent of death. In medical cases, e.g.,
is, since so many of the consequences of, say, killing it will be the underlying illness or disease that is said
a man and of omitting to feed him and letting him to kill the patient. So, are omissions causes?
starve to death are the same. Others, including vir- The question “What caused the fire?” can be bro-
tually all deontologists, typically find a moral differ- ken down into other, more specific questions. For
ence between acting and omitting, which in contem- example, it can be construed as asking “How did the
porary moral debate is often construed as the fire come to start?” Construed this way, the answer
distinction between killing and letting die, though we give focuses upon Jack’s playing with matches; it
deontologists differ on what this difference is. Sug- was his dropping lighted matches on the porch that
gestions include distinguishing between: (1) intend- began the fire. The question can also be construed,
ing a death, and “allowing” or “permitting” a death; however, as asking “How did the fire, given matches
(2) actively intervening and killing, and passively let- were struck, spread?” Here, we might mention the
ting “nature” or some causal sequence run its course; high winds. Equally, though, the question can also
(3) causing a death, and not preventing a death; be construed as asking “How did the house, given
(4) positing a negative duty to avoid harm and a that matches were struck and that high winds were
positive duty to aid, and claiming that the former is present, come to be consumed by the flames?” Here,
more stringent than the latter; and (5) trying to sepa- we might mention the sprinkler system’s failure to
rate the moral guilt of an agent for an outcome from operate and Jill’s failure to act in alerting the fire
his (guiltless) presence in a situation of tragic cir- department.
cumstances. These distinctions themselves are con- Any one of these three construals would be an
troversial, in how they are drawn, in their implica- appropriate answer to the question “What caused
tions, morally, and in the fundamental claim that the fire?” Which one we choose to give depends

17
acts and omissions

upon how narrowly or how broadly we want to treat with to help produce or bring about the outcome.
the question, and how we treat the question de- We regard and treat omissions as causes just because
pends, among other things, upon our purpose in they can and do combine with active agency to help
raising the question in the first place. A board of bring about outcomes, and a person who operates
inquiry will not be satisfied with a narrow construal with a billiard ball view of causality, who maintains
of the question, since that construal may not pick that omissions do not share in active agency, does
out significant, distinctive features present in the not rebut this point.
case that contributed to or helped to produce or Are, then, omissions causes? No, they are not, if
bring about the destruction of the house. In other billiard ball causality is the only view of causality one
words, the board is going to construe the question will accept; yes, they are, if we focus upon what
“What caused the fire?” to be asking “What brought brought about the outcomes that interest us.
about the destruction of the house by the flames?”,
and it would be wrong to give as the answer to this See also: ACTION; AGENCY AND DISABILITY; CAUSA-
question only Jack’s playing with matches. TION AND RESPONSIBILITY; CONSEQUENTIALISM; DE-
Thus, while the three construals are all appropri- ONTOLOGY; DOUBLE EFFECT; DUTY AND OBLIGATION;
ate construals of the question “What caused the KILLING/LETTING DIE; OBEDIENCE TO LAW; RESPON-
fire?”, it is not true that the answer to any specific SIBILITY; SITUATION ETHICS; SUPEREROGATION.
construal is the same in all three cases. If asked what
brought about the spreading of the fire, the answer
that Jack was playing with matches would not be
right; for it would not take into account the high Bibliography
winds that were present, even though it did account
D’Arcy, Eric. Human Acts. Oxford: Clarendon Press,
for how the flames initially got started. Similarly, if
1963.
asked what brought about the destruction of the en-
Denton, F. E. “The Case Against a Duty to Rescue.” Ca-
tire house, it would not be right to mention only
nadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 4 (1991):
Jack’s playing with matches and the high winds; for 101–32.
significant, distinctive features of the case are the
Dworkin, G., R. G. Frey, S. Bok. Euthanasia and Physician-
failure of the sprinkler system and Jill’s failure to act. Assisted Suicide. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Which of the construals we adopt depends upon our Press, 1998.
purpose in asking the causal question, and if one’s Feinberg, Joel. Harm to Others. Chapter 4. Oxford: Clar-
purpose, in retrospect, is that of a board of inquiry, endon Press, 1984.
i.e., to cast a broad net over the factors that helped Frey, R. G. “Killing and the Doctrine of Double Effect.”
to bring about the destruction of the house by the In his Rights, Killing, and Suffering. Oxford: Claren-
flames, then narrow construals of the question are don Press, 1983. Pp. 118–40.
clearly not going to be selected. Kamm, Frances. “Actions, Omissions, and the Stringency
When we ask the question “What caused the of Duties.” University of Pennsylvania Law Review
fire?”, one of the things we are often interested in is 142 (1994): 1493–1512.
outcomes and what produced them. In the above Leavens, Arthur. “A Causation Approach to Criminal
case, the outcome is that the house is entirely de- Omissions.” University of California Law Review 76
(1988): 547–91.
stroyed by fire, so that what we are in fact asking
about is what factors helped to bring about this out- Moore, Michael. Act and Crime. Chapters 2, 4, and 5.
Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1993.
come. This is why it can be misleading, on a billiard
ball view of causality, to speak of the fire as cause Simester, A. P. “Why Omissions Are Special?” Legal The-
ory 1 (1995): 311–35.
and the destruction of the house as effect; for there
is no straight line of active agency that runs from Steinbock, Bonnie, ed. Killing and Letting Die. Engle-
Jack’s playing with matches to the destruction of the wood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall, 1980.
house. Rather, certain factors which do not share in Williams, Bernard. “Acts and Omissions, Doing and Not
active agency are present, viz., the sprinkler’s system Doing.” In his Making Sense of Humanity. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1995. Pp. 56–64.
failure to operate and Jill’s failure to act, that Jack’s
playing with matches and the high winds combine R. G. Frey

18
additivity problems

additivity problems many accept that utility (or BENEFICENCE)


is one ideal, among others, of moral signif-
Additivity has long been associated with UTILITARI-
icance. Accordingly, in assessing outcomes
ANISM, and has often been thought to underlie some
many accept that how good a situation is
of its deepest problems. Yet additivity is not a spe-
regarding utility is an additive function of
cific concept peculiar to utilitarianism; rather it is a
its individual utilities.
cluster or “family” of concepts which frequently play
2. Additive principles involve two natural and
an integral role in nonutilitarian views. Additive as-
plausible assumptions: (a) given any two
sumptions are natural and plausible, but unfortu-
situations, the best situation regarding
nately their importance and pervasiveness is largely
some factor F will be the one in which the
unrecognized, and it is far from clear to what extent
most F obtains if F is desirable, and where
they are justified.
the least F obtains if F is undesirable, and
(b) to determine how much F obtains in a
Utilitarianism and Additivity situation one need only sum the magnitude
Classical utilitarians and their modern descen- of the individual instances of F. Hence, non-
dants believe in maximizing total utility where this utilitarians may invoke additive principles
is determined by adding together individual utilities. for ideals besides utility. For example, it is
At the core of this view is an additive assumption likely additive assumptions underlie the
regarding the goodness of outcomes. claims that, ceteris paribus, it is better to
Many standard objections to utilitarianism in- prevent as much injustice or INEQUALITY as
volve its additive assumption, including problems of possible, or to minimize infractions of basic
RIGHTS or liberties.
aggregation, distribution, incommensurability, and
interpersonal utility comparisons. For example, on 3. Many arguments—named contrast argu-
total utilitarianism the best outcome has the greatest ments by Shelly Kagan—assess the moral
aggregate utility. Correspondingly, no matter how relevance of a given factor by constructing
large or well-off a population might be, there must two cases alike in all relevant respects ex-
be some possible population, sufficiently large, cept the one at issue. Our judgments about
which would be better even though all its members such cases are then taken to be evidence
had lives barely worth living (cf., Derek Parfit’s Re- regarding the intrinsic moral relevance of
pugnant Conclusion). Similarly, since utilitarianism the factor in question. Intuitively, people as-
focuses on how much utility obtains rather than its sume that since everything else is held con-
distribution, it would approve large inequalities for stant, any preference in such cases must be
slight gains in utility. Moreover, utilitarianism’s ad- due to the additional reason provided by
ditivity assumes that all values can be put on a com- the factor in question; while indifference
mon scale. Yet many believe some values—like the must show the factor lacks intrinsic signif-
pain of TORTURE and the PLEASURE of eating cake— icance, as it does not add any reason for
are incommensurable. Finally, since utilitarianism choosing even between (otherwise) equiv-
adds different people’s utilities, it requires mean- alent alternatives. Here, as elsewhere, the
ingful interpersonal utility comparisons. Yet many assumption is that how good a situation is,
argue these are both conceptually and practically im- all things considered, is an additive func-
possible (intrapersonal intertemporal utility com- tion of how good it is regarding each mor-
parisons raise analogous worries). ally relevant factor.
4. Philosophers often construct simple, “pure”
examples which purposely abstract from
Nonutilitarianism and Additivity the world’s messy complexity in order to
Nonutilitarians implicitly invoke additivity in nu- test the moral significance of particular
merous ways, including the following. factors. In doing this, they assume their re-
sults can be legitimately employed to shed
1. Nonutilitarians deny that only utility mat- light on complex real situations. Such an
ters. But, like W. D. ROSS (1877–1971), approach implicitly assumes that morally

19
additivity problems

relevant factors can be understood and as- equality is (intrinsically) bad depends on whether it
sessed independently and additively com- benefits the worse-off. In addition, where the value
bined, after giving each its due weight, to of human lives is concerned, some—such as Kant
yield an overall judgment about outcomes. and John Taurek—reject the notion that numbers
(Note, the methodology of “transporting” count. While even those who generally believe that,
results from simple experiments or models ceteris paribus, it is better to save more lives rather
to complex situations is a staple of the so- than fewer may resist the additive model’s implica-
cial sciences.) tion that saving five lives would be five times better
5. Additivity also underlies many standard as- than saving one, or that the difference between an
sumptions about rationality. The very met- outcome where 7 million and one die and one where
aphors of “weighing” or “balancing” rea- 7 million die is as great as the difference between an
sons suggest an additive model. Reasons, outcome where one dies and an outcome where
like stones, are thought to contribute a fixed none dies.
weight to any situations where they occur. In conclusion, additive assumptions are perva-
For example, suppose increasing Daniel’s sive, but they raise many worries. It is unclear when,
wealth is a reason for doing A, then if doing if ever, additive assumptions are defensible. But how
B would increase Daniel’s wealth the same to think about morality and rationality in the ab-
amount there would be an equally strong sence of such assumptions is even less clear.
reason for doing B whatever other reasons
See also: CASUISTRY; COMMENSURABILITY; CONSE-
favor A or B. Similarly, people assume if the
QUENTIALISM; EQUALITY; INTRANSITIVITY; LOGIC
reasons supporting A and B are identical ex-
AND ETHICS; MOORE; MORAL REASONING; ORGANIC
cept for one extra (or stronger) reason sup-
UNITY; PROPORTIONALITY; ROSS; UTILITARIANISM.
porting A, then A would be more rational
than B, and, moreover, the extent to which
this was so would be exactly proportional Bibliography
to the strength of the extra (or differential) Anscombe, G. E. M. “Who Is Wronged?” Oxford Review
reason supporting A. Here, again, the 5 (1967). Denies the additive model for the value of
model is additive. human lives.
———. “Modern Moral Philosophy.” Philosophy 33/124
(1958): 1–19. Challenges the additivity of utilitarian
Questions about Additivity thinking.
Bennett, Jonathan. “Morality and Consequences.” In vol.
Additive assumptions are natural and plausible,
2 of The Tanner Lectures on Human Values, edited by
and they underlie many views about morality and Sterling McMurrin, 45–116. Cambridge: Cambridge
rationality. But in addition to the standard objections University Press, 1981. Many examples of contrast
usually leveled against utilitarianism, serious ques- arguments.
tions abound as to whether factors can be treated Bentham, Jeremy. An Introduction to the Principles of
and valued independently and then added together Morals and Legislation. 1780. Bentham’s “hedonic cal-
culus” has been the subject of much discussion. See
in overall judgments. The view in question is op-
especially chapters 1, 4, and 5.
posed by G. E. MOORE’s (1873–1958) doctrine of
Dreyfus, Hubert L. “Holism and Hermeneutics.” Review
ORGANIC UNITY, by gestalt PSYCHOLOGY, and by the
of Metaphysics 34, no. 1 (1980): 3–23.
Hegelian and hermeneutic traditions (which see Hegel, G. W. F. Logic: Being Part One of the Encyclopedia
each part as inextricably connected with the whole’s of the Philosophical Sciences. Translated by William
totality). Wallace. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975 [1830]. See,
On more particular issues, there is a sense in for example, paragraph 15, one of many places where
which many would claim (even) the (intrinsic) bad- Hegel discusses the relation of part to totality, and phi-
losophy as a “circle of circles.”
ness of pain is context-dependent. For example, Im-
———. The Philosophy of Right. Translated by T. M.
manuel KANT (1724–1804) and G. W. F. HEGEL Knox. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1969 [1821].
(1770–1831) would contend pain is bad when un- Kagan, Shelly. “The Additive Fallacy.” Ethics 99, no. 1
deserved, but good when meted out proportionally (1988): 5–31. A germinal article; the best direct dis-
to guilt. Similarly, some contend that whether in- cussion of additivity.

20
Adler, Felix

Kamm, Frances Myrna. “Killing and Letting Die: Meth- 138–87. Parts 2 and 3 raise many questions relevant
odology and Substance.” Pacific Philosophical Quar- to additivity.
terly (Winter 1983): 297–312. Interesting and useful ———. “Inequality.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 15,
discussion of contrast arguments. no. 2 (1986): 99–121. An additive principle of equality
Kant, Immanuel. Foundations of the Metaphysics of Mor- is discussed.
als. 1785. Kant’s theory is deeply nonadditive; his
views regarding the infinite value of persons are a no- Larry S. Temkin
table manifestation of this.
———. The Philosophy of Law. Translated by W. Hastie,
T. T. Clark. Edinburgh, 1887 [1797]. Translation of
“Metaphysische Anfangsgrunde der Rechtslehre” (part Adler, Felix (1851–1933)
1 of Die Metaphysik der Sitten).
American moralist, ethical philosopher, social phi-
Katz, David. Gestalt Psychology: Its Nature and Signifi-
losopher and reformer, philosopher of education,
cance. Translated by Robert Tyson. New York, 1950.
A useful introductory text. and ethical leader. Adler’s greatest accomplishment
was his founding of the Ethical Culture Movement,
Kohler, Wolfgang. The Place of Value in a World of Facts.
New York: Live Right, 1966 [1938]. A standard work a humanistic-secular religion founded on ethical
in gestalt psychology; chapter 8 contains a discussion principles, a movement that spread rapidly through-
of organic fitness. out the United States and Europe and attracted a
Mill, John Stuart. Utilitarianism. 1861. number of outstanding moral philosophers, such as
Moore, G. E. Principia Ethica. 1903. William JAMES (1842–1910), Josiah ROYCE (1855–
Nozick, Robert. Philosophical Explanations. Cambridge: 1916), and Henry SIDGWICK (1838–1900), as lead-
Harvard University Press, 1981. See parts 1 and 3 of ers of local ethical societies. This movement, inter-
chapter 5 for discussions of organic unity, and the national in scope, with branches in England, Ger-
weighing and balancing of moral reasons. many, France, Japan, New Zealand, and elsewhere,
Parfit, Derek. Reasons and Persons. Oxford: Clarendon continued expanding until the advent of World War
Press, 1984. Part 4 raises many fascinating issues rele-
I; even today there are Ethical Culture Schools and
vant to additivity.
Societies in various places in the United States. Ad-
Philips, Michael. “Weighing Moral Reasons.” Mind 96
(1987): 367–76. ler was an active ethical reformer, leader of an in-
Rawls, John. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge: Harvard
ternational ethical movement, and also a consider-
University Press, 1971. See his discussion of the dif- able philosopher who had profound original ideas
ference principle for a view in which the (intrinsic) about ethics, MORAL EDUCATION, and social reform.
value of equality seems to depend on whether it bene- Adler regarded the practical or applied side of ethics
fits the worst-off. as of the greatest importance, and his discussions of
Ross, W. D. The Right and the Good. Oxford: Clarendon these matters inevitably led him to develop an ethi-
Press, 1930. See the discussion of prima facie reasons. cal philosophy, though he viewed theoretical ethics
Sen, Amartya, and Bernard Williams, eds. Utilitarianism as having as its overriding object improvements in
and Beyond. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
human life and well-being.
1982. Contains discussions of many objections to util-
itarianism; extensive bibliography. Adler was born in Germany and brought to the
Sidgwick, Henry. The Methods of Ethics. 7th ed. London: United States in 1857. He studied at Columbia Uni-
Macmillan, 1907 [1st ed., 1874]. See book 2, chapters versity and at the Universities of Berlin and Heidel-
2, 3; book 3, chapter 14; book 4. berg, receiving a Ph.D. from Heidelberg in 1873. In
Smart, J. J. C., and Bernard Williams. Utilitarianism: For 1874–1876 he was Professor of Hebrew and Ori-
and Against. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, ental Literature at Cornell University, but, despite
1973. See the last paragraphs of section 2 in Williams’s his popularity as a lecturer, he was forced to leave
“A Critique of Utilitarianism.”
that post because his rationalistic interpretation and
Taurek, John. “Should the Numbers Count?” Philosophy criticism of the Bible generated so much controversy,
and Public Affairs 6, no. 4 (1977): 293–316. A classic
which has spawned a cottage industry of articles re-
especially among the trustees. He then founded the
garding the moral appropriateness of adding human New York Society for Ethical Culture, on the invi-
lives. tation of a number of civic leaders, at which point
Temkin, Larry. “Intransitivity and the Mere Addition Par- the ethical culture movement spread rapidly. In
adox.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 16, no. 2 (1987): 1902 Adler was appointed Professor of Social Ethics

21
Adler, Felix

at Columbia University and in this capacity he came moral principle something like Kant’s with an ideal
into contact with a number of extraordinary students of self-realization that he worked out in considerable
and protégés, as well as a number of distinguished detail. He constantly emphasized the free develop-
colleagues, such as John DEWEY (1859–1952). ment of the human person in relation to communal
Adler lectured constantly at the regular meetings concerns and human fellowship. Well before Dewey,
of the ethical societies, wrote about 1,500 lectures Adler concerned himself with the “problems of men”
and essays in addition to thirteen books. His philo- rather than with the technical problems of philoso-
sophically most important work is An Ethical Phi- phers. Although Adler’s thought had certain affini-
losophy of Life (1919). Morris Cohen (1880–1947), ties to PRAGMATISM, he was not a pragmatist; he was
once one of Adler’s protégés, recorded these obser- rather an ethical idealist with great practical reform-
vations on it: “The appearance of a book which for- ing zeal, and he advanced an idealistic form of moral
mulates a distinct philosophy of life is a rare and PERFECTIONISM. Yet he was also realistic and not in
noteworthy event. . . . Professor Adler has shown us the least a sentimentalist, holding that “many a man
anew that it is possible to combine the insight of has done . . . evil, and done it most deliberately,
practical experience with the discipline of philo- knowing evil as evil.” Little could he know in 1918
sophical reflection, to mix with one’s fellow citizens how far this would extend to the rest of the century,
in the market place in such activities as tenement- and how much evil would be committed in it.
house reform and child-labor committees, and yet In Adler’s ethics we find an unusual combination
retire at times to the mountain to pray and survey of appeal to universal principles with moral particu-
one’s work, the needs of the multitudes, and our larism, which emphasizes the uniqueness of each
cosmic background, with that time-conquering vi- person and each set of circumstances and under-
sion which is the essence of all genuine philoso- standing the situation as a whole. Thus Adler em-
phy. . . . Professor Adler’s conception of ethical life phasized the importance and indispensability of gen-
as an exercise of human energy provides a basis for eral principles and also of careful consideration of
a truly emancipating philosophy of conduct.” And concrete circumstances in their full particularity. For
Cohen went on to speak of “the radical and revolu- Adler, since everyone is unique, no moral law can
tionary character of . . . Adler’s contribution to apply identically to different persons, even though
ethics.” moral principles apply to all. “Kant,” he said, “at-
Adler’s thought was stimulated by such concrete tempts to deduce out of an empty formula a worth
and widespread evils as poverty, misery, OPPRESSION, while object. Kant’s formula is: Treat man never
and injustice, and in this respect he was the polar merely as a means, but also as an end per se. But
opposite of such philosophers as G. E. MOORE how far man may be treated as a means, and what
(1873–1958), whose philosophical thought was the relation of the means to the end may be is un-
stimulated only by the writings of other philoso- determined.” Adler set out to determine this: “For
phers. He was unusual among moral philosophers the formula ‘not merely as a means but also as an
in both generating fundamental criticisms of estab- end’ I would substitute: Treat every [person] as a
lished INSTITUTIONS and devising programs for im- spiritual means to thine own spiritual end and con-
proving or reconstructing these institutions and the versely.” This formula is elaborated and explained in
wider society. For Adler philosophy was to be not his writings.
just the guide of life but also instrumental in im- Adler maintained that “a genuine philosophy of
proving society and the human condition in accord life can only be reached by the ethical approach to
with essential human DIGNITY. Starting from a solid the problems of life,” thus insisting on the primacy
foundation in the philosophies of Immanuel KANT of ethics. He defined “an ultimate principle . . . as
(1724–1804) and G. W. F. HEGEL (1770–1831), one which is presupposed in every attempt to ac-
Adler formulated an original and stimulating moral count for it.” His first principle of ethics he formu-
philosophy which both developed and transformed lated thus: “Act as a member of the ethical manifold
his starting points. (the infinite spiritual universe); Act so as to achieve
Adler rejected Kant’s metaphysics while accept- uniqueness (complete individualization . . .); [and]
ing Kant’s emphasis on the dignity and intrinsic Act so as to elicit in another the distinctive, unique
worth of the person, and he combined a supreme quality characteristic of him as a fellow-member of

22
Adler, Felix

the infinite whole.” “The ethical end [is] the main- MATISM; PUBLIC AND PRIVATE MORALITY; ROYCE;
tenance and development of personality” and “a rule SITUATION ETHICS; UTILITARIANISM; WELFARE
is ethical when the conduct prescribed is instrumen- RIGHTS AND SOCIAL POLICY.
tal to the development of personality.” “The supreme
ethical rule” is “So act as to elicit the unique per-
Bibliography
sonality in others, and thereby in thyself,” or “Act so
as to elicit the best in others and thereby in thyself.”
Works by Adler
By this means “both egoism and altruism are tran-
scended.” Adler held that “the ethical principle must The Moral Instruction of Children. New York: Appleton,
1892.
run like a golden thread through the whole of a [per-
The World Crisis and its Meaning. New York: Appleton,
son’s] life,” and since he took his ethical principles
1915.
seriously, Adler applied them in his own life and
An Ethical Philosophy of Life. New York: Appleton, 1919.
teachings. He argued that virtue is and must be its Quotations are from pp. 172, 100, 139, 132, 112, 117,
own reward, else it is not virtue, and characterized 185, 197, 208, 220, 56, 214, 317, 180, 337.
a virtuous act as one “in which the ends of self and The Reconstruction of the Spiritual Ideal. New York. Ap-
of the other are respected and promoted jointly.” pleton, 1924. Hibbert Lectures delivered at Oxford in
Thus Adler attempted to coordinate a Kantian uni- 1923. Second in importance only to An Ethical Philos-
versalistic imperative ethics with a form of PERFEC- ophy of Life.
TIONISM. But, despite his emphasis on a self-reali-
“Ethics and Culture.” The Ethical Record 1 (1888): 1–12.
zation that must also enhance the self-realization of “The Problem of Teleology.” International Journal of
Ethics 14 (1904): 265–80.
others, Adler was no consequentialist. He regarded
“The Relation of the Moral Ideal to Reality.” International
CONSEQUENTIALISM, in the form of UTILITARIANISM,
Journal of Ethics 22 (1922): 118.
as an attempt to impose a totally inappropriate “A Critique of Kant’s Ethics.” Mind n.s. 11 (1902): 162–
quantitative measure on that which is essentially 95.
qualitative. “The quantitative standard implied in “Personality: How to Develop it in the Family, the School,
such phrases as ‘the greatest good of the greatest and Society.” In Essays in Honor of John Dewey on the
number’ is out of place [in] ethical relations, which Occasion of his Seventieth Birthday, October 20, 1929.
in their very nature are qualitative.” New York: Holt, 1929. Reprinted, New York: Octagon,
1970.
Adler’s contemporary judgments still have rele-
vance today. His assessment of the evils and future
consequences of colonialism was acute and turned Works about Adler
out to be prescient. He argued that moral progress Cohen, Morris Raphael. “An Ethical Philosophy of Life.”
lies in “extending the sense of responsibility so as to In his The Faith of a Liberal, 78–84. New York: Henry
cover the indirect taking of life. . . . [and that] the Holt, 1946. Reprinted, Freeport, NY: Books for Li-
use of poisonous substances in industry, bad sani- braries, 1970. Originally appeared in The New Repub-
lic, 1919. Quotations from pages 78–79, 83.
tation, and inadequate fire protection must be stig-
matized as indirect murder.” This was quite pene- Fite, Warner. “Felix Adler’s Philosophy of Life.” Journal
of Philosophy Psychology and Scientific Methods 16
trating for the time, and still is. And his claim that (1919): 141–51.
“The root disease that afflicts the world at the pres- Friess, Horace L. “Adler, Felix.” Dictionary of American
ent day is the supremacy of the commercial point of Biography, vol. 21, supp. 1, 13–14. New York: Charles
view,” if true at beginning of the twentieth century, Scribner’s Sons, 1944. The best brief biographical
was no less true at its end. account.
———. Felix Adler and Ethical Culture. New York: Co-
See also: AUTONOMY OF ETHICS; AUTONOMY OF lumbia University Press, 1981. A biography, and a
good one, with a bibliography of Adler’s books and
MORAL AGENTS; CHILDREN AND ETHICAL THEORY;
pamphlets.
COMMUNITARIANISM; CONSEQUENTIALISM; DEWEY;
Guttchen, Robert S. “Felix Adler’s Concept of Worth.”
EXPLOITATION; FAMILY; GOLDEN RULE; HUMANISM;
Journal of the History of Philosophy 11 (1973): 213–
IDEALIST ETHICS; INDIVIDUALISM; JAMES; LIBERAL- 27. An excellent paper, by far the best on Adler’s moral
ISM; LIFE, MEANING OF; MORAL EDUCATION; OPPRES- philosophy.
SION; PERFECTIONISM; PRACTICAL REASONING; PRAG- ———. Felix Adler. New York: Twayne, 1974. Unfortu-

23
Adler, Felix

nately a posthumous work. Guttchen had much to one hand, some have contended that moral values
contribute. rest, at base, on ideals, ultimate decisions, or fun-
Radest, Howard B. Toward Common Ground: The Story
damental commitments that are aesthetic or at least
of the Ethical Societies in the United States. New York.
Frederick Ungar, 1969. Contains a useful chronology aesthetic-like in nature. Somewhat less extreme (or
and a good bibliography. perhaps somewhat more extreme) is a view, some-
———. “Work and Worth: Felix Adler.” Journal of the times called aestheticism, which does recognize a
History of Philosophy 16 (1978): 71–81. basic difference between aesthetic and moral values,
Singer, Marcus G. “The Place of Felix Adler in American but claims that artworks and people’s actions
Philosophy.” Journal of Humanism and Ethical Reli- shouldn’t be appraised from the MORAL POINT OF
gion 1 (1988): 13–36. Contains a number of citations.
VIEW but only from the aesthetic one, or that aes-
This whole issue is devoted to Adler.
thetic values always override moral values. At times
Sleeper, R. W. “Felix Adler and John Dewey: From Ideal-
ism to Pragmatism.” Journal of Humanism and Ethical Friedrich NIETZSCHE (1844–1900) seems to advo-
Religion 1 (1988): 65–82. cate the first of these “less extreme” views, and
Thilly, Frank. “The Kantian Ethics and its Critics.” The Theophile Gautier (1811–1872), Walter Pater
Philosophical Review 27 (1918): 646–50. (1839–1894), and Oscar Wilde (1854–1900)
———. Review of An Ethical Philosophy of Life. The Phil- sometimes give voice to the second. Nietzschean
osophical Review 27 (1918): 651–59. aestheticism, however, is an inchoate theory and one
Marcus G. Singer difficult to interpret, and no other form of aestheti-
cism has been systematically worked out or de-
fended. Many of the nonphilosophical expressions
aesthetics of aestheticism—for instance, in the passionate de-
scription of the “beauty” of a bomb exploding in a
The relations between aesthetics and ethics are
crowd of unarmed civilians (a description tendered
many and mysterious. One useful way to get at sim-
by Mussolini’s son-in-law)—are not just without
ilarities and differences between them is to distin-
philosophical substance but, more importantly,
guish three different “levels” of value theory—sub-
blood-curdling.
stantive issues, normative theory, and meta-theory—
On the other hand—at the other extreme—are
and to see how the two work in concert, or are in
the view that all or some aesthetic values rest upon
conflict, or interrelate in some other way on each
or are reducible to moral values, and the somewhat
level.
less extreme set of views, sometimes called moral-
ism, which does recognize a definite difference be-
Substantive Issues tween the two sorts of values, but claims that art-
Prima facie, it would seem that although many works and people’s actions shouldn’t be appraised,
substantive ethical issues have no aesthetic dimen- or primarily appraised, from the aesthetic point of
sion at all (e.g., ABORTION), and many aesthetic is- view, or that moral values always override aesthetic
sues likewise no ethical dimension (e.g., criteria for ones. Late in his life, Leo Tolstoy (1828–1910)
judgments of elegance), some issues are naturally seems to have advocated the first of these views, par-
given to both kinds of evaluation. Among prominent ticularly in the form that aesthetic values simply re-
issues of this sort are PORNOGRAPHY, CENSORSHIP, duce to moral ones, and many Marxists subscribe to
and the FORGERY of works of art. Since these issues one of the “less extreme” views. In contrast to ex-
and others of a like sort, e.g., PLAGIARISM, are cov- treme forms of aestheticism, both forms of moralism
ered elsewhere in this Encyclopedia, they need not have attracted adherents and been systematically
be discussed here. worked out and defended.
Tolstoy. Vehemently rejecting the view that art
has to do with beauty (a quality defined in terms of
Normative Theory
PLEASURE), Tolstoy defines art as “a human activity
While at first glance “many substantive ethical is- consisting in this, that one man consciously by
sues have no aesthetic dimension at all, and many means of certain external signs, hands on to others
aesthetic issues likewise no ethical dimension,” both feelings he has lived through, and that others are
of these propositions have been challenged. On the infected bv these feelings and also experience them.”

24
aesthetics

Art, then, is essentially the successful communica- is determined historically, and especially by the eco-
tion of feeling from one person to another by means nomic relations between the classes that compose it.
of an external object, the artwork. “In the limited Since the nature, and thus the value, of an artwork
sense,” though, art does “not mean all human activ- is inextricably tied to the socioeconomic conditions
ity transmitting feelings but only that . . . which we under which it was produced, an artwork cannot be
for some reason select . . . and to which we attach understood and properly evaluated until its socio-
special importance.” The “special importance,” he economic and historical place is fixed. Art is thus
says, comes from “feelings flowing from . . . reli- always a reflection of reality—which is to say that it
gious perceptions.” Even if, in the broad sense and is always a reflection of socioeconomic, historical re-
in general, “the stronger the infection, the better the ality—and so art cannot be devoid of ideological
art” regardless of the kind of feeling conveyed, in content.
the narrow sense of the term, art is necessarily reli- Although Karl MARX’s (1818–1883) own view
gious in nature, and the “infectiousness” of religious of art allowed for the production of great art in so-
feeling of an artwork an “indubitable sign” that it is cieties in which the “general [level of societal] de-
“real art” (good art) as opposed to “counterfeit” art velopment” was not high—he mentions ancient
(bad art). Finally, since the “purpose of art” is to Greece as an example—many later Marxists weren’t
replace “feelings less kind and less necessary for the as flexible. Proper political content—meaning the
well-being of mankind . . . by others kinder and promotion of revolutionary goals—increasingly
more needful for that end,” and since “religions have came to be regarded as the sole criterion of the ac-
always furnished [a] guide” for moral progress of ceptability of an artwork, with aesthetic values
just that sort, a moral-cum-religious criterion of ar- brushed aside as unimportant or denigrated as the
tistic or aesthetic value is arrived at. Good art is art lingering effects of bourgeois capitalism. Eventually,
that transmits the best moral feelings with a high a simple and rigid “socialist realism” became the of-
degree of infectiousness, with religion telling us ficial creed of the Soviet Union and other countries
what the best moral feelings are. In our own age, of “real socialism.” But that’s now largely a thing of
Christianity provides the moral beacon to guide us the past. Artistic experimentation and art criticism
and details the moral ideal we should strive for, viz., which view art as something more than mere prop-
the brotherhood of man. Good art is thus Christian aganda with decorative trimmings are tolerated, and
and moral in nature, and unites men with each other even encouraged (within limits), in virtually all
and with God. Art that does not do that, either be- countries today.
cause it conveys the wrong feelings or conveys the In fact, sophisticated Marxists—Marx, Vladimir
right ones with a very low degree of infectiousness, Lenin (1870–1924), Frederick ENGELS (1820–
is bad art. It is on this basis that Tolstoy condemns 1895), and Leon Trotsky (1879–1940), among
the bulk of Western art, including the plays of many others—have always allowed the aesthetic
Shakespeare, the symphonies of Beethoven, and al- value of an artwork to be relatively independent of
most all of his own work. its ideological content (Marx himself thought very
Obviously this view has its problems. highly of Shakespeare, Balzac, and Goethe, none of
Marxism. In its simplest form, a Marxist theory whom waved a red flag, or even a pink one), and
of aesthetic value identifies, in a way similar to Tol- have accounted for the fact in a number of ways.
stoy’s theory, aesthetic value with values that pro- Among them are: (1) By arguing that the superstruc-
mote certain political and moral ideals, such as the ture (which includes art) interacts dialectically with
overthrow of the bourgeois state. More commonly, the historicoeconomic base, and so art, and its aes-
however, Marxist theories don’t begin, or even end, thetic value, aren’t simply epiphenomena of the
with such a reduction, but see artistic activity in the base; (2) by recognizing that art, perhaps more than
context of, and ultimately based on, production and other parts of the superstructure, develops at least
productive relations in society in general, and take in part in accordance with laws of its own, that is,
art to be a historically located product of a certain with some degree of autonomy, and so has to be
social class. Art, like the great majority of social ac- judged accordingly; (3) by embracing, as one crite-
tivities, is part of a culture’s superstructure and re- rion of aesthetic value, a realism that emphasizes
flects a class ideology, while the superstructure itself “typicality” and “reflectivity,” that is, the accurate

25
aesthetics

depiction of historically realistic and typical mem- an act to be one of SUPEREROGATION, or in judging
bers of a social class, regardless of the work’s po- Mother Teresa to be a beautiful person) and/or
litical leanings; (4) by drawing a distinction between seemingly moral criteria used in the aesthetic as-
the “conscious” and “unconscious” dimensions of an sessment of artworks (e.g., in judging a novel to be
artwork, the former having to do with the work’s aesthetically bad because its main thesis is the eu-
explicit ideological content, the latter with what it genic necessity of exterminating people with an IQ
actually reveals, perhaps despite itself. In this way, less than 85).
typical Marxists have avoided reductionism and al-
lowed art and aesthetics some private property of
Meta-theory
their own, even if they haven’t allowed them to own
or control the means of production. And that they Questions of substantive issues and normative
certainly haven’t allowed, for when revolutionary theory would be easier to resolve if answers on the
push comes to counterrevolutionary shove, it is level of meta-theory were available. On this level,
dulce which yields to utile. Aesthetic value is dear the central questions are, What is an aesthetic judg-
to Marxists, but dearer still is the REVOLUTION — ment? and What is a moral judgment? If we knew
that is, their political, social, and ethical values. what made a moral judgment a moral judgment, and
Thus even sophisticated Marxists hold that artworks what made an aesthetic judgment an aesthetic judg-
shouldn’t be primarily appraised—and, in some ment, we could tell how independent the realms are.
cases, shouldn’t be appraised at all—from the aes- One complication that sets in at the start is that
thetic point of view. In the long run, the aesthetic is the term “moral,” more accurately “ethical,” is used
subservient to the political, even if the leash it’s kept in at least two very different ways, and thus delimits
on is very long. The possibility of an intrusive mor- two realms of value, realms which are not co-
alism, and perhaps even censorship, is part and par- extensive. In one sense (a sense that dates back to
cel of even the most sophisticated forms of ancient Greece), the term circumscribes what might
MARXISM. be called all-things-considered value: the ethically
Other Views. On the level of normative theory, right (to focus on a central concept) is what ought to
the central question is simply how independent be done all things, all points of view, considered. Eth-
moral and aesthetic values are or should be. Between ical value is simply the sum of all values, properly
the two extreme positions discussed above are any weighted, and so by definition is overriding value.
number of others. Two which merit consideration The question, Why ought I to be ethical? is self-
are that the two realms are wholly independent— answering on this conception of morality, and the
neither kind of value is reducible to or overlaps with view that ethical (moral) values always override aes-
the other, and perhaps in addition, neither automat- thetic ones similarly an analytic truth. On the other
ically takes precedence over the other (“art for art’s hand, the question isn’t self-answering and the view
sake,” the slogan of the artistic movement some- not analytically true if “ethical” or “moral” is con-
times called aestheticism, is sometimes interpreted strued, as it more commonly is, as delimiting (at least
this way)—and that there is a partial, but only a prima facie) a distinct kind of value that, logically
partial, overlap between the two—aesthetic criteria speaking (again, prima facie), is on a par with other
have some, but only some, place in moral assess- kinds of value, such as legal, economic, or prudential
ment, and/or moral criteria have some, but only value. It is when “moral” is used in this way that some
some, place in aesthetic assessment. A staunch val- of the more puzzling questions about the relations
uational separatism of the first sort might be argued between ethics and aesthetics arise.
for on the basis of the desirability of the indepen- Hampshire. A radical view that some have ad-
dence and autonomy of a plurality of realms of vanced is that there are no relations between them,
value. In a sense, the argument here would parallel, because there is no such subject as aesthetics. There
on a different plane, that for the separation of is ethics, the philosophical study of problems of
church and state. The second view could marshal human conduct, according to Stuart Hampshire, a
evidence of a more direct sort, drawing on, for ex- proponent of this position, but there can be no phil-
ample, seemingly aesthetic criteria used in the moral osophical study of art and beauty, aesthetics. “Aes-
assessment of acts of certain sorts (e.g., in judging thetic judgments,” Hampshire thinks, “are not com-

26
aesthetics

parable in purpose with moral judgments, and . . . moral and aesthetic judgments. Let me briefly dis-
there are no problems of aesthetics comparable with cuss problems on the moral side.
the problems of ethics”; hence the systematic study Moral evaluation is not only of actions, but of
known as ethics is possible, while that known as aes- desires, intentions, tendencies, emotions, beliefs,
thetics is not. Hampshire advances a number of ar- character traits, states of affairs, and people, none
guments for a sharp contrast between moral and aes- of which are chosen in any simple sense; and even
thetic judgments, with most of them resting on an when we judge actions, no problem of real or imag-
alleged difference of practical necessity between the ined immediacy need be present. We can judge
two. His argument is basically as follows. purely hypothetical actions, or actions in the distant
No matter what situation a person is in, he must past or in situations which we know we could never
act; choices always confront us. Choice is thus im- be in, and we can judge another’s actions in terms
posed; and choice is the solution to a practical prob- of moral problems (e.g., the deep disgrace to her
lem, itself imposed. Now human life being what it family that her action would occasion) that wouldn’t
is, the problems of human conduct are recurring or couldn’t occur to her. In fact, it may not even be
problems, and rational people seek a general method that all moral judgments in situations of immediacy
to solve recurring problems. But a method inevitably are practical, in Hampshire’s sense of calling for ac-
yields rules and principles; thus to moralize—to cite tion. Judgments of supererogation in such circum-
reasons in support of a line of conduct—is neces- stances don’t seem to be. In addition, the question
sarily to generalize. System, generality, and reason- arises why the practical problems that never stop
giving in a situation of forced choice characterize confronting us are to be labeled “moral problems.”
morality. (I assume that Hampshire doesn’t mean “moral” in
But they certainly don’t characterize aesthetics. A the broad sense indicated a few paragraphs back.)
Why are they moral rather than, say, prudential? For
work of art is gratuitous; “it is not essentially the
that matter, why is talk of “problems” even in place?
answer to a question or the solution of a presented
I, for one, don’t seem to be constantly confronting
problem.” Moreover, “if something is made or done
problems of any sort, or even sorts. The applicability
gratuitously, and not in response to a problem posed,
of the concept of a problem, a linchpin notion in
there can be no question of preferring one solution
Hampshire’s argument, thus needs to be explained
to another.” Aesthetic judgments need not be
and justified. But that just points up the deepest
made—no one need choose between artworks—
problem with the argument: the question of what a
and any judgments that are made needn’t be sup-
moral and aesthetic judgment is, what makes a judg-
ported with reasons, that is, justified on the basis of
ment one or the other or neither, is never clearly
general principles. Not the general but the particu-
addressed by Hampshire. What we’re told is what
lar—this unique object—is the proper object of the such judgments—or rather one sort of them, moral
critic’s scrutiny. The critic’s job is to direct attention judgments—are used for, namely, to solve practical
on particular features of the object, features that problems. That doesn’t tell us what their nature is
make it beautiful, sublime, ugly, harmonious, or even if their nature is solely a function of their use
whatever, and the purpose of doing so is to make (something Hampshire doesn’t argue for or even
others see those features, “not simply to lead them mention), for it doesn’t distinguish moral judgments
to say: ‘That’s good.’” Ultimately, then, “everyone from other judgments respecting the solution of
needs a morality to make exclusions in conduct; but practical problems, such as prudential judgments.
neither an artist nor a critical spectator unavoidably Thus Hampshire’s argument is, at best, incomplete.
needs an aesthetic; and when in Aesthetics one Kant. In order to know the exact relations be-
moves from the particular to the general, one is trav- tween ethics and aesthetics, we need to know the
elling in the wrong direction.” nature of moral and aesthetic judgments. Unfortu-
A detailed discussion of this provocative argu- nately, although theories of both are rife—especially
ment isn’t possible here (but see Zemach), but, as theories of moral judgment—there is no consensus
might be expected, aestheticians haven’t been con- on either. A number of philosophers have discussed
vinced. Specifics aside, Hampshire seems to have an both, however, usually in an attempt to construct a
unduly restrictive, and even a distorted, view of both unified and comprehensive theory of value, or a uni-

27
aesthetics

fied and comprehensive philosophical system. One “This is a square”) and practical judgments (e.g.,
very prominent example is Immanuel KANT (1724– “This is good”), cognitive, since they don’t formulate
1804). or connect concepts at all. Granted, we speak as
KANT and KANTIAN ETHICS need not be discussed though such judgments were cognitive—that is, in-
here. His much less well-known aesthetics is both a volve subsumption under a concept—and beauty a
distinct and important branch of his critical philos- property; that can be accounted for by noting the
ophy (of which his moral philosophy also forms a disinterested character of such judgments and their
major part) as well as a completion, of sorts, of it. transcendental ground. For the power of judgment,
In his third critique, the Critique of Judgment in trying to find a concept to subsume the particular
(1790), he considers the nature and status of aes- (“this flower”) under, and no determinate concept
thetic judgments. Aesthetic judgments can concern (e.g., “red”) being available, we make use of an in-
the merely agreeable, the beautiful, or the sublime, determinate concept, an indeterminate concept
according to Kant, but judgments of the first sort which, of necessity, is supplied by the power of judg-
(such as “This is pleasant”), since they make no ment itself. This is the concept of “nature’s subjec-
claim to universal validity, are relatively unimpor- tive purposiveness,” or nature’s purposiveness for
tant, philosophically speaking. Judgments of the sec- the power of judgment. In essence, this is the inde-
ond and third sorts do make a claim to universal terminate concept of nature’s lending itself to judg-
validity, however, but since judgments of the sub- ment, so far as its empirical particulars (individual
lime, though both important and importantly differ- objects) are concerned. What constitutes this con-
ent in some respects from those of the beautiful, cept is the idea of lawfulness in general (not in
don’t add anything distinctive to judgments of particular, for that would make it a determinate con-
taste—that is, judgments of the beautiful—as far as cept). As such, it is a concept that exactly corre-
our present purposes are concerned, they won’t be sponds to the understanding as such (that is, the
considered here. understanding as indeterminate, considered inde-
Judgments of taste are logically singular (in pendently of any particular concept), and so also ex-
proper form, they take a singular term, and perhaps actly corresponds to the imagination as such, since
a demonstrative singular term, as their subject) and, the imagination must harmonize with the under-
at the level of grammar, attribute a property, beauty, standing in order to “produce” cognition. In judg-
to an object. A typical judgment of taste would be ments of taste, then, there is purposiveness, but it is
“This flower is beautiful.” But beauty isn’t a prop- not based on a concept; hence the idea of purpo-
erty, Kant thinks, for it doesn’t exist independently siveness without a purpose characterizes such judg-
of a relation to a subject’s feelings. Since judgments ments, in fact is the nature of such judgments. Imag-
of taste make a claim to universal validity, how- ination and understanding harmonize without the
ever—that is, to everyone’s considered assent—the usual constraint of a determinate concept; they play
particular feeling in question, though undoubtedly with each other, so to speak, rather than work with
one of pleasure, must not be the pleasure of the another. Aesthetic awareness (in the case of judg-
merely agreeable, i.e., pleasure that, logically speak- ments of taste) thus doesn’t involve a cognition—
ing, is a function of a subjective make-up that may the requisite determinate concept is absent—and so
not be universally shared. “Beautiful is what, with- can only be experienced in nonconceptual or “felt”
out a concept, is liked universally”—which isn’t an form, as pleasure. This awareness/feeling is precisely
empirical claim, and doesn’t entail that everyone a nonconceptual awareness of the apprehended
will, as a matter of fact, like any particular object. form’s purposiveness for cognition as such. Beauty,
The universal validity of judgments of taste is sub- then, though not a property, is given an analysis that,
jective, not objective, in nature, according to Kant, though not a cognitive one, essentially involves the
but such judgments are distinguished from judg- productive faculties of cognition as such, and thus
ments of agreeableness by being disinterested, that can claim a universal validity in application, even
is, not informed with an interest in the existence of though it is a subjective determination.
the object as related to sense. Rather, they are re- But Kant’s aesthetic goes beyond this to forge an
flective judgments and are contemplative, but they explicit link with morality. Although the details of
are not, in contrast to “logical” judgments (e.g., Kant’s conception of moral judgment cannot be pur-

28
aesthetics

sued here, suffice it to say that morality is conceptual have essentially both sensuous and rational im-
on his account, and thus fully cognitive (though pulses—he attempts to reconcile the duality and re-
linked to PRACTICAL REASON, not pure reason). Now, integrate the human being. This has to be done,
grounding the universality of judgments of taste is Schiller thinks, in the aesthetic, and through aes-
the idea of an intelligible—that is, a supersensible— thetic education.
underlying nature’s purposiveness for our cognitive The sensuous impulse binds us to nature and the
powers; taste has this supersensible “in view” in continuing passage of time, according to Schiller,
judging as it does, and reference to such a supersen- and presses for the “reality of existence, for some
sible is needed in order to resolve the antinomy of content in our perceptions and for purposes in our
taste. (The antinomy of taste is roughly the paradox actions.” The formal or rational impulse is basically
that judgments of taste aren’t based on concepts the demand of the free rational self “to bring har-
[since if they were, disputes about taste would be mony into the diversity of manifestations [appear-
possible; but there is no disputing about taste], and ances].” The former is associated with our empirical
judgments of taste are based on concepts [since if and embodied nature, the latter with our rational
they weren’t, quarreling about judgments of taste and moral nature. In effect, Schiller’s entire aes-
wouldn’t be possible, because general assent thetic theory turns on a number of dualities system-
couldn’t be demanded].) The supersensible that the atically related to the sensuous impulse-formal im-
idea in question points to has various aspects, and pulse duality: material-spiritual, multiplicity-unity,
thus can be “identified” in various ways: (1) as the content-form, inclination-duty, phenomena-nou-
supersensible as just described, namely, the super- mena, subjective-objective, passive-active, contin-
sensible underlying nature’s purposiveness for our gent-necessary. All such dualities characterize the
cognitive powers; (2) as the substrate of objects and fractured condition of modern humanity, and all are
of ourselves as subjects; and (3) as the supersensible basically derived from the more fundamental sen-
that the concept of freedom “contains practically.” suous impulse-formal impulse duality. The problem
The first aspect is needed to resolve the antinomy of is how to keep the dualities from splitting us apart;
taste, but the last is more important for our pur- the problem is how to integrate fragmented human-
poses. Conceived under this last aspect, the super- kind.
sensible in question, concerned as it is with practical Schiller’s answer is that the sensuous and formal
reason, links the “morally good” and “moral feel- impulses can be overcome or reconciled by being
ings” with beauty and taste, and thus unites ethics lifted to a higher plane in a synthesis he calls the
and aesthetics, integrates the two into a comprehen- play impulse. Since the sensuous impulse seeks out
sive whole. That said, it must be admitted that the life as its object, and the formal impulse shape, the
whole in question is rather loosely jointed, and, in- play impulse seeks out and responds to living shape.
deed, must be rather loosely jointed, since the bridge This Schiller identifies with beauty. So construed,
from beauty to morality must be through an aspect beauty is, in contrast with Kant, an objective quality.
of the supersensible that does not resolve the antin- Like Kant, however, Schiller evidently thinks of play
omy of taste, else, contrary to Kant’s repeated as the harmonious working of our cognitive facul-
claims, judgments of taste would be practical, and ties. Unlike Kant once again, though, he gives the
thus cognitive and conceptual. Beauty is the “sym- notion much more content in stressing, in play, a
bol” of morality, Kant says, and morality can, at best, blend of freedom and necessity in voluntary submis-
provide taste with guidance—not standards of jus- sion to rules for the sheer joy of it, something which
tification or criteria. In the end, then, despite the surely characterizes play in the ordinary sense of the
linkage between the two, beauty doesn’t borrow term. Such play is a meeting ground for the ra-
from morality, nor morality from beauty, and the do- tional—there are clear echoes of Kant’s views on
mains remain relatively autonomous. practical reason in the play impulse—and the sen-
Schiller. Not satisfied with this conclusion, but suous—again, there are clear echoes of Kant’s views
nonetheless very influenced by Kant, Friedrich on sensation, pleasure, and beauty in the play im-
SCHILLER (1759–1805) tried to draw aesthetics and pulse. Play is thus the essence of fully developed hu-
ethics closer together. Accepting what is basically a man behavior; the play impulse is the impulse to be
Kantian conception of dual human nature—people fully human. As Schiller says in a famous passage:

29
aesthetics

“Man plays only when he is in the full sense of the using the aesthetic to unite the human being in a
word a man, and he is only wholly Man when he is quest for “the higher self,” the rational self. The aes-
playing.” thetic is simply the means for passing from the sen-
This special sort of play is itself characterized by suous condition to the moral condition, and in the
Schiller as a condition of “utter rest and extreme final analysis the two conditions have to remain dis-
movement . . . at the same time a relaxing and a tinct if that’s to be effected. The moral and aesthetic
tightening effect.” Some “play” tends to invoke a are thus not united in any meaningful, ultimate way,
“melting” effect, while other “play” is more “ener- even if there is a necessary connection between
gizing.” Aesthetic experience itself is “the highest en- the two.
joyment . . . freedom of spirit in the vivacious play There is, however, a different strand of argument
of all its powers.” In short, the aesthetic is more than that’s also developed by Schiller, that of the aesthetic
the symbol of the moral; it’s also what makes us not as a step toward a higher state but as a constit-
whole as human beings, what unites the moral or uent of it, as a final value. According to this line of
rational—freedom and the supersensible realm— argument, the aesthetic is itself the, or at least a,
with the worldly and empirical—nature and the sen- condition of the higher self. The FINAL GOOD is the
suous realm. whole human being, and a human being “is only
But more than that, only beauty or the aesthetic wholly man when he is playing.” Here the moral and
makes social life possible, in the highest sense of the aesthetic are truly inextricably united, with the aes-
term: “Beauty alone can confer on [man] a social thetic as the dominant valuation mode, even if con-
character,” Schiller says. “Taste alone brings har- ceptually and ontologically dependent on the moral.
mony into society, because it establishes harmony in It’s worth noting that as far as the sense of the eth-
the individual. All other forms of perception divide ical as all-in-value, as that which conduces to or con-
a man, because they are exclusively based on the stitutes human flourishing is concerned, Schiller’s
sensuous or on the intellectual part of his being; only second aesthetic project identifies the ethical and the
the perception of Beauty makes something whole of aesthetic, even if, in the other sense of the term “eth-
him, because both his natures must accord with it.” ical,” it subordinates the ethical to the aesthetic. In
Aesthetic education is thus necessary for social life, any case, this ambivalence of purpose is never re-
and is, in a sense, the most basic of all forms of solved by Schiller.
education. Beardsley. Much more empirical and less theory-
Eloquent and provocative as Schiller’s philoso- dependent in his approach is Monroe Beardsley. Tak-
phy is, there are problems with it. Not the least im- ing works of art to be essentially “aesthetic objects,”
portant difficulty is the elaborate but undeveloped Beardsley asks whether “aesthetic objects have in-
and undefended transcendental machinery that herent effects that are themselves of great worth.”
Schiller borrows from Kant, together with the large His slightly tentative answer is that they do, for four
number of associated dualities that that machinery distinct reasons: aesthetic experience (1) “relieves
pulls in train. If the Kantian apparatus is questioned tensions and quiets destructive impulses” (a reason
or called into doubt, many of Schiller’s views would that dates back to ARISTOTLE [384–322 B.C.E.], as
be as well (as would Kant’s, of course). Beardsley notes), (2) “resolves lesser conflicts within
That rather large problem aside, there is also a the self, and helps to create an integration, or har-
crucial ambivalence in the development of Schiller’s mony” (a reason reminiscent of Schiller, but without
thought. Schiller’s initial question is, How can man the metaphysical or transcendental baggage), (3) “re-
pass from the sensuous to the rational or moral con- fines perception and discrimination” (a reason that
dition? He argues that art makes this possible by philosophers who embrace cognitive theories of
providing an intermediate condition in which the art—Nelson Goodman being prominent among
two are combined. In the intermediate condition, the them—have stressed), and (4) “develops the imag-
play impulse is given free rein, and there is delight ination, and along with it the ability to put oneself
in appearance but detachment from the world of in the place of others” (a reason that, in a less meta-
sense: both the sensuous and the rational are given physical and transcendental way, is once again rem-
their due in a single experience. This, however, isn’t iniscent of Schiller). Moreover, if aesthetic experi-
so much uniting the aesthetic and the moral as it is ence does have inherent effects of the four sorts

30
aesthetics

noted, three other, more remote effects might also servations even seem to count against some of them;
be expected. It might well also (5) be “an aid to men- (2) even if all six were empirically well supported,
tal health,” (6) “foster mutual sympathy and under- similar effects are more easily attained by other
standing,” and (7) “offer an ideal for human life” means, means having nothing to do with art or the
(all three reasons here once more having echoes in aesthetic. If, in reply to this second objection, it’s
Schiller). said that the aesthetic alone can bring about all six
As Beardsley is attempting to justify the aesthetic effects, the correct response is, Why is that impor-
by invoking something outside it, something con- tant, philosophically speaking? If a single wonder
cerning the whole canvas of human life, his is an pill could accomplish all six effects, it would have
ethical justification of the aesthetic, in the broader little philosophical significance, and there would be
sense of the term “ethical,” and a justification that no felt need to explore the relations between the
integrates the aesthetic with the ethical. His first realm of pill-values and the realm of ethical values,
four reasons, however, stand or fall on whether cer- much less to integrate the two. In fact, as the analogy
tain causal connections obtain, and the evidence, as makes clear, there aren’t really two realms of value
Beardsley himself knows, might not be with him. present at all: aesthetic value, as a distinct kind of
Indeed, the cathartic effect of art, reason (1), seems value, has dropped out of Beardsley’s account. His
rather minimal, and in general, stronger and more first six reasons integrate aesthetics and ethics and
effective tension-relievers are readily available in the provide a justification for the aesthetic, by subsum-
form of exercise, drugs, conversation with friends, ing it under ethics, as means to end. In brief, there
and therapy. One wonders why the aesthetic would is nothing distinctly and irreducibly aesthetic about
be necessary or very useful, given the alternatives. any of the six causal effects Beardsley claims for aes-
Similar considerations apply to the second reason, thetic objects.
concerning the resolution of conflicts, and even, mu- Not so with his seventh reason, the aesthetic as
tatis mutandis, to the third and fourth reasons. an ideal of human life. The connection between the
There are more direct and effective ways to refine aesthetic and the moral isn’t contingent or causal,
perception and discrimination and to improve the according to this reason, but much closer, concep-
imagination than studying and appreciating art, even tually speaking. Kant expresses a similar sentiment
a lot of art. In fact, it might even be wondered in calling beauty the symbol of morality, as does
whether art refines the perception and discrimina- Nietzsche in speaking of a life as a work of art, and
tion of anything other than art. The experiences of Schiller in speaking of man being fully man—which
auto mechanics and laboratory technicians, for ex- includes being fully ethical—only when engaged in
ample, refine their perception and discrimination of the aesthetic. Even if there’s a shared root in these
engines, cells, tissues, and the like, but have little and other philosophers, what direction such a com-
carry-over into the other areas of life. Why should it mon element will grow in very much depends on
be any different with art? The same holds for the how it’s integrated into a more comprehensive phi-
imagination. The cultivation of a vivid and active losophy, including not just ethics and aesthetics but
scientific imagination seems to have little or no ef- METAPHYSICS AND EPISTEMOLOGY as well. This is
fect on the imagination in other areas of life, or to evident in Kant and Schiller (and also Nietzsche,
make a person more able and willing to put herself whose philosophy hasn’t been discussed here), but
in the place of others. Worse still as far as this con- it’s also true of Beardsley. Influenced by John DEWEY
sideration is concerned, many Nazis had a keen ap- (1859–1952), he stresses the integration of means
preciation of art and a developed aesthetic imagi- and end. “If some of the satisfyingness of the end
nation, but were extremely insensitive and cruel. could be brought into the means,” he says, “and the
Their moral imagination was severely lacking. means at every stage felt as carrying the significance
Many of the points of the preceding paragraph of the end, we should have in life something more
also bear on Beardsley’s fifth and sixth reasons (the of the quality of aesthetic experience itself.”
aesthetic as an aid to mental health, and the aesthetic Other philosophers, however, develop the idea of
as fostering SYMPATHY and understanding), with all art as a model for, ideal for, symbol of, or full reali-
six facing two general objections: (1) empirical sup- zation of the ethical in very different directions, and
port is lacking in each case, and commonsense ob- no detailed answer can be given to how ethics and

31
aesthetics

aesthetics are related without an even more detailed in Kant’s Aesthetics. Pittsburgh: University of Pitts-
examination of each such philosophy. In short, there burgh Press, 1974.
is no very complete, satisfying, or enlightening an- Crawford, Donald W. Kant’s Aesthetic Theory. Madison:
University of Wisconsin Press, 1974.
swer to the question of the relation of aesthetics and
Eagleton, Terry. Marxism and Literary Criticism. Berkeley:
ethics, or art and morality, outside of the context of
University of California Press, 1976. Short and
a comprehensive view of people and their relation readable.
to the world. On what some may consider a more Eaton, Marcia Muelder. Aesthetics and the Good Life.
positive or cheerful note, though, it can also be said Rutherford, NJ: Associated University Presses, 1980.
that any truly comprehensive view of people and Chapter 7.
their relation to the world will have something to Foot, Philippa. “Nietzsche: The Revaluation of Values.” In
say about both aesthetics and ethics, will probably Nietzsche: A Collection of Critical Essays, edited by
Robert Solomon. South Bend, IN: University of Notre
bring the two together, and may well express and
Dame Press, 1980.
develop the sentiment common to Kant, Schiller,
Gautier, Theophile. “Preface to Mademoiselle de
Nietzsche, and Beardsley. Maunin.” Translated by A. Sumichrast. In Paths to the
Present: Aspects of European Thought from Romanti-
See also: AUTONOMY OF ETHICS; CENSORSHIP; CRITI-
cism to Existentialism, edited by Eugen Weber. New
CAL THEORY; DEWEY; EMOTION; EMOTIVISM; ETHICS
York: Dodd, Mead, 1960. A biting statement of Gau-
AND MORALITY; ETIQUETTE; FITTINGNESS; FORGERY; tier’s aestheticism.
FORMALISM; HISTORIOGRAPHY; HUMANISM; IDEAL Goldmann, Lucien. The Hidden God: A Study of Tragic
OBSERVER; IDEALIST ETHICS; INTUITIONISM; KANT; Vision in the Pensées of Pascal and the Tragedies of
KANTIAN ETHICS; LITERATURE AND ETHICS; MARX; Racine. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1964. A
MARXISM; METAETHICS; METAPHYSICS AND EPISTE- major Marxist critical work.
MOLOGY; MORAL PERCEPTION; MORAL REALISM; Guyer, Paul. Kant and the Claims of Taste. Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press, 1979.
MORAL REASONING; MORAL TERMS; MYSTICISM; NAT-
Hampshire, Stuart. “Logic and Appreciation.” Originally
URALISM; NATURE AND ETHICS; NIETZSCHE; PLAGIA-
published in The World Review (1952). In Art and Phi-
RISM; PLEASURE; PORNOGRAPHY; PRACTICAL REA- losophy, 2d ed., edited by William Kennick. New York:
SON[ING]; PRESCRIPTIVISM; RELIGION; SCHILLER; St. Martin’s Press, 1979.
SKEPTICISM IN ETHICS; SPORT; SYMPATHY; TRAGEDY; Kant, Immanuel. Critique of Judgment. Translated by Wer-
VALUE, THEORY OF. ner Pluhar. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 1987. Part One
is on aesthetic judgments. An excellent translation, in-
troduction, bibliography, and index.
Bibliography Lenin, Vladimir Ilyich. Articles on Tolstoy. Moscow: For-
eign Languages Publishing House, 1951.
Avron, Henri. Marxist Aesthetics. Ithaca, NY: Cornell Lukács, Georg. Studies in European Realism: A Socio-
University Press, 1970. A short and clear general logical Survey of the Writings of Balzac, Stendhal,
survey. Zola, Tolstoy, Gorki, and Others. New York: Howard
Bates, Stanley. “Tolstoy Evaluated: Tolstoy’s Theory of Fertig, 1998 [1964]. An important work by a leading
Art.” In Aesthetics: A Critical Anthology, edited by Marxist critic.
George Dickie and Richard Sclafani. New York: St. Marx, Karl, and Fredrick Engels. On Literature and Art.
Martin’s Press, 1977. Edited by Lee Baxandall and Stefan Morawski. New
Beardsley, Monroe. Aesthetics: Problems in the Philoso- York: International General, 1973. A full collection of
phy of Criticism. 2d ed. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, Marx and Engels’s writings on art.
1981. See chapters 11 and 12 for a discussion of aes- Morawski, Stefan. Inquiries into the Fundamentals of
thetic value and art and morality. Aesthetics. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1974. A col-
———. “The Aesthetic Point of View.” In his The Aes- lection of essays by a leading Marxist aesthetician.
thetic Point of View. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Mothersill, Mary. Beauty Restored. Oxford: Oxford Uni-
Press, 1983. Grounding the aesthetic. versity Press, 1984. Contains interesting discussions of
Beardsmore, R. W. Art and Morality. London: Macmillan a number of philosophers, including Hume, Kant, and
Press, 1971. Short and suggestive. Hampshire.
Cohen, Ted, and Paul Guyer, eds. Essays in Kant’s Aes- Nehamas, Alexander. Nietzsche: Life as Literature. Cam-
thetics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1982. bridge: Harvard University Press, 1985.
Important papers and a full bibliography. Nietzsche, Friedrich. Beyond Good and Evil. Translated
Coleman, Francis X. J. The Harmony of Reason: A Study by Walter Kaufmann. New York: Vintage Press, 1966.

32
Africa

Nietzsche’s aestheticism is actually scattered through- ical theory in the Maghreb, however, which has been
out a number of his writings. part of the literate Islamic world for more than a
Parsons, Kathryn Pyne. “Nietzsche and Moral Change.” In millennium, needs to be considered as part of Is-
Nietzsche: A Collection of Critical Essays, edited by
Robert Solomon. South Bend, IN: University of Notre
lamic ethics. Similar reasons rule out consideration
Dame Press, 1980. here of Ethiopia’s literate philosophical traditions,
Pater, Walter. The Renaissance. Chicago: Academy Press, which are also quite distinctive, and those of South
1978. The “Conclusion” is many times taken to be a Africa’s white population, whose moral ideas are a
classic statement of aestheticism. European legacy. This article consequently deals
Plato. Ion. The Republic, Books II, III, and X. Many trans- with sub-Saharan Africa, excluding Ethiopia and
lations. Plato’s views on art and its effects on morality. [white] South Africa.) If we start with traditional
Some of the earliest arguments for extensive
cultures, we may say that ethnography suggests a
censorship.
number of broad generalizations about the ethical
Schaper, Eva. Studies in Kant’s Aesthetics. Edinburgh:
Edinburgh University Press, 1979. dimensions of such systems (in that generous sense
Schiller, Friedrich. On the Aesthetic Education of Man. of “ethical” that takes in all the central features of
Translated by Reginald Snell. New York: Fredrick Un- PRACTICAL REASON). We may begin with a number
gar, 1974. of formal features.
Sircello, Guy. A New Theory of Beauty. Princeton: Prince-
ton University Press, 1975. Sections 23–26 discuss
beauty and morality. Formal Features
Tolstoy, Leo. What Is Art? Translated by Aylmer Maude.
First of all, it is widely agreed that these tradi-
Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1960.
tional societies were essentially communitarian or
Trotsky, Leon. Literature and Revolution. Ann Arbor:
University of Michigan Press, 1971. An important and communalistic in their ethical ideas, holding both
intelligent discussion. that RIGHTS of many sorts inhere not in individuals
Wilde, Oscar. The Artist as Critic. Edited by Richard Ell- but in various corporate groups—families, lineages,
mann. New York: Vintage Books, 1968. See especially villages, societies; and that what is good is the flour-
“Intentions” and “Preface to The Picture of Dorian ishing of certain corporate interests, to which the
Gray” for Wilde’s aestheticism.
projects of individuals ought to be subsidiary. Thus,
Williams, Raymond. Marxism and Literature. Oxford: Ox-
in many cultures PROPERTY rights—the claim for
ford University Press, 1977.
some period to exclusive use of an area of land for
Zemach, Eddy. “Thirteen Ways of Looking at the Ethics-
Aesthetics Parallelism.” The Journal of Aesthetics and farming, say—were assigned by chiefs to lineages,
Art Criticism (1971): 391–98. A sustained critique of with the head and senior members of each such
Hampshire. group allocating both responsibilities and crops to
members of the group and managing profits from
Michael J. Wreen
any sales to cover the needs of individual members.
In many cultures marriage (and what is seen as the
attendant obligation to raise and support children)
Africa is a relationship between families, in which control
Africa is extremely culturally diverse; linguists sug- of children (and their correlative obligation to obe-
gest that well over a thousand languages are spoken dience) belongs to the family of one spouse, a fact
on the continent. Africa’s fifty modern states include which is symbolically acknowledged by payments of
peoples descended from literally hundreds of pre- bride-price or dowry.
colonial societies, ranging in their degree of political A second significant feature of traditional ethical
organization from the acephalous hunter-gathering thought is an effect of taking FAMILY or clan as a
!Kung of central southern Africa, through the hier- basis for practical reflection. This produces a struc-
archical states of Buganda—in the east—or the Yo- ture of thought that is anti-universalizing: “because
ruba—in the west—to the Islamic emirates and she’s my kinswoman” is an essentially indexical rea-
monarchies of the Sahel and northwest Africa. son—referring back in its essence to a historical re-
Sub-Saharan African cultures can be seen as the lation to the agent—and is not consonant with the
product of the interaction of so-called traditional Kantian demand for universality. (It is a familiar idea
systems of thought with Islam and Christianity. (Eth- that obligations to family members do not depend

33
Africa

on their general qualities; we are not supposed to


Ethical Education
care more for our siblings than for strangers for
some extrinsic reason.) The transfer of ethical ideas between generations
Third, traditional religious ideas were largely nat- in preliterate societies was accomplished not only by
uralistic—conceiving of gods, spirits, and ancestors admonition and correction but also by the following
as continuous with and continually operative within means: recounting the history of one’s own people
the natural world. These beings were supposed to be in terms that underwrote current social arrange-
concerned to varying degrees with the flourishing of ments (“history” rather than myth, because in con-
certain specific groups: again, often the people of temporary usage “myth” connotes fictional status,
certain places or lineages. Ritual practice in associ- and these narrations are usually told as true); ritual
ation with cult for spirits and ancestors very gener- enactment of these histories; performing folk tales—
ally involved the observance of taboos, for which the stories told as fictions, often with an “Aesopian”
sanctions were usually misfortunes—a hunting ac- moral; and proverbs (which are themselves often
cident, disease, failed crop—visited upon the indi- shorthand references back to history and folk tale).
vidual (or, as likely, some group to which he or she In some cultures young people undergo special pe-
belonged). Questions of avoiding harm of this sort riods of education prior to the transition to adult
loomed large in PRACTICAL REASONING; and there status, often removed from the community; and in
was rarely an articulated notion of doing right that these periods of training religious and ethical ideas
was distinct from doing what conformed to custom may be a central object of study.
and PRUDENCE (and thus, in particular, violated no
taboos) or was distinct from what was “seemly.” In-
Contrasts with Contemporary Euro-American
deed, one of the highest terms of commendation for
Ethical Theories
conduct in many African societies was also used to
describe physical beauty or “aesthetic” appeal in ar- At the level of content, there is, as one would
tifacts. (This notion can perhaps be understood by expect, less detailed similarity among African tra-
analogy with Greek notions of kalokagathia, a vir- ditions than at the level of the rather abstract formal
tue that unites beauty and goodness.) features catalogued above. But the basically com-
In this sense, fourthly, there is often no clearly munitarian and anti-universalist character of ethical
differentiated and distinctively moral vocabulary, as thought means that, in most traditional African sys-
opposed to a vocabulary of aesthetic or technical tems of ideas, public questions of practical reason—
commendation, a fact that is itself reflective of the as they arise, for example, in courts or in family de-
relatively low degree of linguistic division of labor cision making—rarely focus on the enforcement of
within most preliterate communities. individual rights, concentrating rather on individual
A further consequence of regular involvement needs and a concern for corporate harmony. This is,
with lineage spirits and spirits of place is that, in that of course, in striking contrast to formal juridical
overwhelming majority of cultures which recognize practice in contemporary literate societies.
a high God, associated with the heavens, it is usually Another major item of contrast is that in tradi-
a deus remotus, whose interest in the detailed every- tional African systems of thought, propriety, repu-
day affairs of men and women is minimal. The no- tation, and status are central to practical reasoning.
tion that conduct should be aimed at affecting one’s This is striking because in Euro-American culture
state in an afterlife is unusual, and concern for af- these questions are all usually seen as having to do
fairs after one’s death seems usually to focus on only with the surface of ACTION, and a concern with
questions of having descendants to do cult for one them is generally seen as shallow or superficial, in
as an ancestor and having a reputation that “lives ways that contrast with genuinely moral concerns.
on.” In that sense, such systems of thought are often Anyone familiar with European or Asian moral
profoundly—this is a fifth, broadly formal charac- philosophy will want to ask how such public ethical
teristic—anthropocentric or humanistic, centered discourse relates to the “inner” language of private
on the contemporary concerns of human beings (in- decision; but there is a major difficulty in under-
cluding ancestors) rather than on otherworldly standing this relationship since our access to such
considerations. information in those cultures is a consequence of

34
Africa

literacy. Not only, in preliterate societies, is there no is best seen as arising, in part, from the fact that state
recording of ethical views except through the collec- officials in the modern sector are paid salaries that
tive sphere of oral traditions, but there are also no are intended to support a family unit closer to a
generic conventions—such as that of the confession Euro-American “nuclear” model, while inheriting—
(on the model of St. AUGUSTINE [354–430]) or the or, at least, believing that they inherit—obligations
Protestant diary (as the record of an individual CON- to corporate groups—lineages, hometowns, and so
SCIENCE)—to provide models of organized reflec- on—that they cannot sustain. The question of “nep-
tion on questions outside the public sphere. More otism” or “tribalism” should be seen in the context
than this, such central genres as the novel provide of a conflict between formal rights-based notions of
us with models of interiority in moral life that do not the role of state agents, on the one hand, and tra-
occur in the major genres of orature. To the extent ditional corporate obligations, on the other.
that a nuanced language of private moral reflection, When we come to consider contemporary sub-
distinct from the discourse of collective decision Saharan ethical discourse, the influence of Islamic
making, is the product of the kind of PRIVACY made and Christian theory is very evident, as are Marxist
possible through the conventions that constitute and liberal political and moral ideas introduced
genres of writing such as autobiography and novel, through European colonial education. These latter
we may say that there is no such private morality in secular traditions are not distinctively different from
the largely preliterate cultures of precolonial Africa. their Euro-American counterparts. So far as these
It is facts such as these that lead anthropologists major religious traditions are concerned, the con-
to speak of cultures of (external) shame as opposed trast between traditional and contemporary ideas is,
to (internal) guilt. In using such a classification, one perhaps, less striking in Islamic areas. This is be-
should remember that shame, like guilt, requires one cause, in many parts of sub-Saharan Africa, Islam
to share the values that one has failed to live up to— was well established before the period of European
it is not just a question of embarrassment; so that it colonialism and existed for a long period as a literate
would be quite misleading to think of African cul- tradition alongside the popular culture of a largely
tures without developed discourses of individualized nonliterate populace. There was, in consequence, a
“private” morality as being governed by the notion fairly substantial mutual accommodation of Islamic
that only what is publicly known is of any real ethical ideas and the ethical thought of the pre-Islamic cul-
significance. tures into which they were introduced. Nevertheless,
It should be stressed, finally, that there is little just as Islam in other parts of the contemporary
reason to think that the features we have identified Muslim world has developed both new secularizing
in contrasting African ethical ideas and those of traditions and new forms of “fundamentalism,” so
Euro-America distinguish African ethical ideas from this has happened in Africa. Secularization has
those of many other traditional peoples from outside tended to be the response of a literate intelligentsia
the areas of influence of the literate ethical culture with substantial familiarity with European culture,
of the monotheistic world religions. while fundamentalism has had a more popular—
though usually also literate—base. One conse-
quence of the increasing flow of information,
Contemporary Trends
through broadcast media as well as through literacy,
Against this background, it is possible to under- is that public ethical discourse in sub-Saharan Is-
stand the very substantial ethical crises associated, lamic Africa may now be closer to that in the rest of
on the one hand, with the growth of literacy, the the Muslim world than it has been since the early
development of the African novel, and access to period of African Islam.
Western literary forms; and, on the other, with ur- The effect of Christianity has been to challenge
banization and the growth of commodity production the content of traditional ethical thought in many
and wage labor. Each of these changes contributes places—for example, through objections to polyg-
to undermining the fit between traditional ethical amy, to caste-like hereditary status systems, and to
ideas—of kinship and community—and contem- appeal to the ancestors and other spirits. Further-
porary practical life. The problem of political cor- more, Christian otherworldliness and individualistic
ruption in many modern African states, for example, notions of merit and RESPONSIBILITY (the latter

35
Africa

probably deriving as much from contemporary eco- abled from voting, owning PROPERTY, and retaining
nomic relations) have penetrated many cultures. custody of their own children because they were
Nevertheless it is fair to say that the ethical thought imagined to be too biologically fragile and emo-
of most contemporary African Christians is closer to tional, and consequently too dependent, to bear the
that of the precolonial period—especially in its com- RESPONSIBILITY of doing so. Feminist emancipatory
munalism—than it may sometimes appear. And, of politics explicitly pursued legislation to eliminate
course, to the extent that African Christians partici- such “women’s disabilities.” In a similar vein, to ab-
pate in formal literate ethical discourse, they do so— rogate the bans racist disparagement of their civic
with the significant exception of Coptic churches in and commercial competence constructed against
Egypt and Ethiopia—largely within contemporary them, African Americans embraced juridical strate-
traditions that belong to European Christianity. gies to establish that race and color are not disabil-
ities under the law.
See also: ANTHROPOLOGY; CHILDREN AND ETHICAL
Today, having a physical, sensory or cognitive im-
THEORY; COMMUNITARIANISM; CULTURAL STUDIES;
pairment is the condition most commonly equated
FAMILY; GUILT AND SHAME; INDIVIDUALISM; ISLAMIC
with disability. In this recent narrower usage, and in
ETHICS; MORAL EDUCATION; NARRATIVE ETHICS; PUB-
its broader original meaning as well, disability raises
LIC AND PRIVATE MORALITY.
a number of issues for moral theory, especially in
respect to equitability and inclusiveness. Theories
Bibliography that emphasize dependency rather than agency are
challenged to explain how individuals whose bio-
Floistad, Guttorm, ed. Contemporary Philosophy: A New
Survey. Vol. 5. Amsterdam: Martinus Nijhoff, 1987. logical differences appear to limit their powers can
Contains useful articles. be of equal status with fully capable persons. The-
Forde, Daryll, ed. African Worlds: Studies in the Cosmo- ories that accentuate agency are challenged to em-
logical Ideas and Social Values of African Peoples. brace people whose biological differences impede
London, New York: Published for the International Af- their executing the activities through which moral
rican Institute by Oxford University Press, 1954. Ox- agency is exercised.
ford University Press, 1954.
Gyekye, Kwame. An Essay on African Philosophical
Thought: The Akan Conceptual Scheme. Cambridge: Agency
Cambridge University Press, 1987.
Mbiti, John S. African Religions and Philosophy. New Who counts as a person for purposes of com-
York: Praeger, 1969. manding equitable treatment and respect? John
p’Bitek, Okot. African Religions in Western Scholarship. RAWLS proposes that “a person is someone who can
Nairobi: Kenya Literature Bureau, 1970. be a citizen, that is, a fully cooperating member of
Wright, Richard A., ed. African Philosophy: An Introduc- society over a complete life” but adds that “for our
tion. Washington, D.C.: University Press of America, purposes . . . I leave aside permanent physical dis-
1977. Contains useful articles.
abilities or mental disorders so severe as to prevent
Kwame A. Appiah persons from being normal and fully cooperating
members of society in the usual sense.” In response
to Rawls’s conceptualization, Ruth Anna Putnam
asks, “are we to conclude that a permanently dis-
agency and disability abled human being is not a person, or at any rate
not a citizen?” From an agency-focused moral per-
Disability
spective, such an individual’s status will be relativ-
In its original usage, a disability is a limitation ized to whatever physical, sensory, or cognitive per-
suffered by individuals because they belong to a formances are designated as crucial expressions of
class regarded as incompetent to exercise at least moral activity. The less replete and flexible the rep-
some of the RIGHTS people normally enjoy. Children, ertoire of instrumentally valuable performances, the
for instance, are disabled in respect to entering into less inclusive the theory will be in attributing full
CONTRACTS, purchasing alcoholic beverages, and moral agency to individuals whose powers to per-
protecting their PRIVACY. Women once were dis- form differ from the normal or customary range.

36
agency and disability

We can see why this is so by way of an example. norities. Whether doing so isolates, or instead ele-
Seyla Benhabib urges that humans capable of speech vates, those who sign rather than speak remains a
and action are to be considered equal from a MORAL subject of considerable controversy. For whether the
POINT OF VIEW. In the context of this or similar di- inability to speak to the majority of other people, and
alogical accounts of morality, what is the status of not just to a minority similar to one’s self, compro-
deaf individuals who communicate through sign lan- mises an individual’s moral agency turns on whether
guage rather than speech? In practice, whether such the spoken word is theorized as being essential, or
individuals are afforded fully equitable treatment instead as serendipitous, to whatever dialogical
and respect turns on whether they can communicate functions are crucial to human flourishing.
with whomever the theory takes to be the morally Similar considerations pertain to most other mor-
significant interlocutor(s). ally relevant physical, sensory, and cognitive func-
When sign language was developed in the eigh- tioning. For example, the theologian John Hull di-
teenth century, manual signing was believed to be agnoses the isolation his blindness occasions by
based on natural, self-interpreting symbols that en- explaining that “the main point about [sighted peo-
gaged the intelligence directly and lucidly and facili- ple’s practice in relating to the blind] is its lack of
tated the moral sense. For this reason, deaf people reciprocity.” What prompts this remark is his reflec-
who signed rather than spoke were considered to be tion on the difference between the ways in which
insulated from the transient fashions of conven- blind and sighted people are aware of each others’
tional conversation, and therefore to be less cor- presence and, consequently, in how they attend to
ruptible. Signing thus was considered a respectable, one another: “a common deterioration of mutuality
effective activity conducive to the purest communi- takes place when a blind . . . person believes . . . they
cation with, and about, God, whose significant role are in a face-to-face situation but in fact you, the
in moral conversation was a given. sighted one, are looking out of the window.” Hull
But, by the late nineteenth century, relationships observes that “the mere fact that blind and sighted
among humans had become more significant for the people cannot watch things together . . . deprives
propitious ordering of society than ties between hu- them of a major field of togetherness.”
mans and God were made out to be. Where once So it is not the inferiority of personal powers, but
language’s highest function had been to engage in- rather the nonmutuality of social practice, that
dividuals with transcendent sources of right belief erodes EQUALITY between individuals who cannot
and right conduct, it now most importantly engaged see and those who can at the level of personal con-
people with one another in productive commercial nectedness. In this regard, the Americans With Dis-
and civic interaction. Furthermore, as priority abilities Act (1990) traces disablement to social ar-
shifted from personal to social improvement, the rangements intolerant of physical, sensory, or
ideal of communal participation by people who cognitive difference rather than to the functional in-
functioned in a common dialogical mode in the pub- adequacies of individuals. From the viewpoint rep-
lic sphere superseded that of individualized moral resented by this “social” model of disability, when-
perfection. Eventually, individuals who signed in- ever having such differences diminishes a person’s
stead of speaking were diagnosed as being in deficit agency, injustice, not incompetence or biological def-
of the powers that distinguish humans and their so- icit, is most likely at blame.
cieties from lesser primates. On account of their di- Despite its increasing political influence, how-
alogical difference, deaf individuals were made le- ever, this model of disability is susceptible to a lim-
gally inferior and vulnerable by being decreed iting case, namely, that in which no reform of social
incompetent to own property and to retain custody practice, nor improvement in environment or situ-
of their children (especially of their hearing ation, can enable an impaired individual to become
children). self-determining. Robert Veatch, for one, holds that
In response, deaf rights advocates now urge that some people whom justice urges be compensated
sign language be recognized as the language of a mi- for their disabilities “are not competent, rational
nority community with its own identifiable history decision-makers,” so, for them, the equality implicit
and culture, and that deaf people be accorded the in the principle of self-determination is not an
same moral and political status as other cultural mi- achievable component of justice. The literature of-

37
agency and disability

fers at least two competing ways of addressing their kinds of impairments, are forestalled from assuming
circumstance. The first argues that dependency trusting relationships by a social environment hos-
rather than agency is a definitive attribute of morally tile to, unreliable for, or dismissive of individuals
engaged individuals, while the second expands how like themselves.
agency is recognized so as to increase the number of It is often assumed that those free of impairment
those who are considered capable of being morally have an obligation to care for the disabled, regard-
engaged. less of whether the latter can reciprocate. This claim
is a commonplace of social welfare theory, but it is
not so commonly implemented, and with good rea-
Dependency
son, for what it appears to call for is a moral econ-
Some feminists and some communitarians insist omy that privileges neediness. Such schemes noto-
that the importance of agency has been magnified riously call for determining who is better and who
misleadingly, promoted by a parochial paradigm of worse off, so as to decide whose private assets to
self-determination. Feminists associate self-deter- transform into common resources, and whom to
mination with self-sufficiency and independence and supply from the latter.
then condemn it for being nothing more than an ex- Further, the price extracted to be eligible for such
trapolation from the paradigmatic male relationship benefits makes them of dubious advantage, for the
between nonintimate equals that disregards the social NORMS that shape our patterns of obligation
common female circumstance of being intimately to those classified as unable to care for themselves
connected to others of very different POWER or can be harmfully confining to whoever finds herself
status. Communitarians associate self-determination occupying the dependent’s role. If the respect ac-
with INDIVIDUALISM, complaining that it invites in- corded able-bodied individuals is influenced by oth-
dividuals to operate as idiosyncratic atomistic arbi- ers’ perceptions of the extent of their caring, people
ters of value who abjure traditional understandings with disabilities face being coerced into dependence
about the COMMON GOOD. so as to permit unimpaired associates to display how
A criticism commonly levied from both these well they care. Similarly, if a community’s virtue is
camps is that self-determination constitutes a hope- advanced when ill and disabled people are cared for
less and therefore an unfairly imposed goal for peo- in it, community members viewed as weak must put
ple who are powerless and vulnerable, and especially themselves in the hands of those who seem strong
so for the disabled. To be inclusive of individuals too so as to facilitate the community’s collective pro-
frail or otherwise compromised to conform to this gression toward virtue. But surely no one should be
paradigm, they argue, moral theory should promote obligated to receive whatever benefits are thrust
relationships that bond powerless to more powerful upon her. Nor is it liberating to position individuals
people. Annette Baier, for example, contends that whose social options are unusually limited so that
the INEQUALITY manifested in dependence connects their choosing to disconnect from someone else is
care giver and care recipient morally by exposing condemned as disruptive because it obstructs the so-
them to mutual RISK. For the relationship to work, ciety’s prospects for being virtuous.
each gives up control because each is, figuratively, a
hostage to the other’s role; this mutuality of depen-
Interdependence and Self-Determination
dence constitutes the paradigmatic moral bond.
But modeling moral connectedness on how de- Those who would benefit from assistance should
pendence links people of greatly differing powers not lose this autonomy. Immanuel KANT (1724–
still fails to be responsive to some of the perfor- 1804) advises any prospective benefactor to “show
mance limitations that impairment can occasion. For that he is himself put under the obligation by the
example, people with autism and people with cog- other’s acceptance or honored by it” so as to fore-
nitive deficits such as those characteristic of certain bear from placing the recipient of help in an inferior
stages of senile dementia are individuals whose im- position. Kant’s example illustrates how, in the con-
pairment compromises their empathizing and trust- text of reciprocally constraining practice, individuals
ing, and thereby limits their ability to rely on others. can be interdependent, yet self-determining. Inter-
And many more people, evidencing very different dependence thus can be accepted as integral to hu-

38
agency and disability

man life without being magnified into a social ideal that the relevant mutuality has been achieved. Safe-
that imposes heteronomy on people whose physical guarding humans with disabilities because they are
or cognitive functioning is not species-typical. human entails no duties to extend moral respect or
As Kant suggests, drawing individuals of differ- social inclusion to them.
ent powers together in a mutually binding moral Whether individuals whose execution of major
space is facilitated when, regardless of how needy life activities is compromised can command these
one is for assistance by the other, social practice latter duties (as distinct from being the objects of
maintains RECIPROCITY between them. Of course, duty) turns on whether social practice permits them
where practice divides humanity into the weak and to be perceived as mutually engaged with others in
the strong—those who can’t climb a flight of stairs morally important enterprises. Charles TAYLOR sees
and those who can, those who can’t see printed text the development of liberal morality as being an ex-
and those who can, those who can’t hear a telephone pansion of our views about who can do so and in-
and those who can—such mutuality either does not terprets the claim to equal status as having been
happen or is curtailed. This indicates why inflating extended even to “people who through some circum-
their dependency, and discounting their agency, at- stance that has befallen them are incapable of real-
tenuates the moral connectedness people with dis- izing their potential in the normal way—handi-
abilities can achieve. capped people . . . for instance.” Unfortunately, this
way of putting things deconstructs the egalitarian
project by intimating that all “handicapped” people
Moral Status
are equal only derivatively or fictionally because they
Some people question assigning full moral status do not function normally.
to individuals incapable of agency as, for instance, According to data collected in 1994/95 by the
the most severely retarded and demented humans United States Department of Commerce for the Sur-
seem to be. Peter Singer, for one, draws the moral vey of Income and Program Participation, more than
line at sentience, arguing that anencephalic neonates 50 million Americans reported being so seriously
are of lower moral rank than smart nonhuman ani- impaired as to be precluded from one or more nor-
mals. Singer assigns similar moral standing to hu- mal modes of functioning. So centering agency, or
mans and any other animals positioned alike in re- the potential for it, on normal performance of social
spect to the line established by the capacity for activities forestalls acknowledging the DIGNITY of a
responsiveness. vastly greater number of people than just the most
Doubting whether very severely impaired hu- profoundly intellectually impaired. For this reason,
mans have full moral status may appear to run advocates for individuals with physical, sensory, or
counter to our strong intuition that we have a higher cognitive impairments now adopt strategies reminis-
duty to safeguard humans, whatever their deficits cent of the previous liberatory movements that ad-
may be, than to protect the cleverest nonhuman ani- vanced women and people of color. They declare
mals. But one need not be obligated to an individual that equating competent agency with modes of per-
to be obligated in regard to that individual. Human formance typical of or familiar to the current socially
neonates lack agency but are linked by history and dominant class is itself disabling.
affection to adults on whom they are dependent.
When an individual’s extended dependency imposes See also: AUTONOMY OF MORAL AGENTS; BENEFI-
an unfairly heavy burden of care giving on which- CENCE; BENEVOLENCE; CARE; CHARITY; CHILDREN
ever capable agent is closest, our duty to distribute AND ETHICAL THEORY; CIVIL RIGHTS AND CIVIC DU-
burdens as well as benefits equitably obligates us to TIES; COERCION; COMMUNITARIANISM; CONTRACTS;
provide relief to the unfairly encumbered care DIGNITY; DISCRIMINATION; EQUALITY; EUDAIMONIA,
givers. Discharging this duty to care givers is imple- -ISM; EUTHANASIA; FAMILY; FEMINIST ETHICS; GEN-
mented through taking positive action toward those EROSITY; GRATITUDE; INEQUALITY; INFANTICIDE; IN-
for whom they care. Hence, our duty to care for hu- TERESTS; JUSTICE [entries]; NEEDS; PATERNALISM;
mans incapable of agency exhibits the character of PERSONAL RELATIONSHIPS; PRIDE; PRIVACY; PUBLIC
an obligation to persons with full moral status, but AND PRIVATE MORALITY; PUBLIC HEALTH POLICY;
it is with their care givers rather than themselves PUBLIC POLICY; RACISM AND RELATED ISSUES; RAWLS;

39
agency and disability

RECIPROCITY; RESPONSIBILITY; RIGHT HOLDERS; ical.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 14 (1985): 223–
RIGHTS; SELF AND SOCIAL SELF; SELF-OWNERSHIP;
51. Quotation from pp. 233–34.
SOCIAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY; SUICIDE; THE-
Silvers, Anita. “Disability Rights.” In The Encyclopedia of
Applied Ethics, edited by Ruth Chadwick. San Diego:
ORY AND PRACTICE; WELFARE RIGHTS AND SOCIAL
Academic Press, 1997.
POLICY.
———. “Reconciling Equality to Difference: Caring (F)or
Justice for People with Disabilities.” Hypatia 10, no. 1
Bibliography (1995): 30–55. Argues that substituting care ethics for
justice ethics marginalizes people with disabilities;
Baier, Annette. “The Need for More than Justice.” In Sci- shows how justice ethics should respond to people with
ence, Morality and Feminist Theory, edited by Marsha physical, sensory, and cognitive differences.
Hanen and Kai Nielson. Calgary: University of Calgary ———. “Rights of People with Disabilities.” In The Ox-
Press, 1987. Why the concept of justice doesn’t do jus- ford Handbook of Practical Ethics, edited by Hugh
tice to the nuances of moral connectedness. LaFollette. Oxford: Oxford University Press, forthcom-
Baynton, Douglas. Forbidden Signs: American Culture ing. Reviews and evaluates various philosophical ap-
and the Campaign against Sign Language. Chicago: proaches to justice for people with disabilities.
University of Chicago Press, 1996. Silvers, Anita, David Wasserman, and Mary Mahowald.
Becker, Lawrence C. “The Good of Agency.” In Americans Disability, Difference, Discrimination: Perspectives on
with Disabilities: Exploring Implications of the Law for Justice in Bioethics and Public Policy. Point/Counter-
Individuals and Institutions, edited by Leslie Francis point. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 1998.
and Anita Silvers. New York: Routledge, 2000. Argues Explores how formal, distributive, and feminist ap-
that disability rights are implicit in long-held, funda- proaches to justice address issues raised by disability
mental commitments about the value of human life, in the fields of bioethics and public policy. Afterword
especially our acknowledgment of the value of human by Lawrence C. Becker.
agency. Singer, Peter. Rethinking Life and Death: The Collapse of
Benhabib, Seyla. “In the Shadow of Aristotle and Hegel: Our Traditional Ethics. New York: St. Martin’s, 1996.
Communicative Ethics and Current Controversies in A bio-utilitarian approach to disability, focusing on suf-
Practical Philosophy.” Philosophical Forum 21 (1989): fering and other quality of life issues.
77–95. Moral agency and its applications in the con- Taylor, Charles. Multiculturalism and “The Politics of
text of dialogical theory. Recognition”: An Essay by Charles Taylor with Com-
Francis, Leslie Pickering, and Anita Silvers, eds. Ameri- mentary. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1992.
cans with Disabilities: Exploring Implications of the Commentary by Amy Gutmann (editor), Stephen
Law for Individuals and Institutions. New York: Rout- Rockefeller, Michael Walzer, and Susan Wolf.
ledge, 2000. United States Department of Commerce, Census Bureau.
Funk, Robert. “Disability Rights: From Caste to Class in “Americans with Disabilities: 1994–95,” by John
the Context of Civil Rights.” In Images of the Disabled, McNeil. Household Economic Studies. Current Popu-
Disabling Images, edited by Alan Gartner and Tom Joe, lation Reports, P70–61, August 1997.
7–30. New York: Praeger, 1987. Emergence of social Veatch, Robert. The Foundation of Justice: Why the Re-
model of disability in United States case law and im- tarded and the Rest of Us Have Claims to Equality.
plications for jurisprudence, especially civil rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986.
Hull, John. On Sight and Insight: A Journey into the World Wendell, Susan. The Rejected Body: Feminist Philosoph-
of Blindness. Oxford: One-World Publications, 1997. ical Reflections on Disability. London: Routledge,
Quoted from p. 107. 1996. Introduces disability perspective to feminist
Kant, Immanuel. The Metaphysics of Morals. Part 2, The theory.
Doctrine of Virtue. Translated and edited by Mary
Gregor. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1991 Anita Silvers
[1797]. See sections 31 and 32.
Morris, Jenny. Pride Against Prejudice. Philadelphia: New
Society Publishers, 1991. Introduces feminist perspec-
tives to disability studies. agent-centered morality
Putnam, Ruth Anna. “Why Not a Feminist Theory of
Morality is called agent-centered, or agent-relative,
Justice?” In Women, Culture and Development: A
Study of Human Capabilities, edited by Martha Nuss- insofar as it appeals to moral considerations whose
baum and Jonathan Glover. Oxford: Clarendon Press, force is tied to the projects, values, relationships, or
1995. Pp. 298–331. Quoted from p. 304. perspectives of the moral agent. Commonsense
Rawls, John. “Justice as Fairness: Political not Metaphys- moral practice is often thought to embody agent-

40
agent-centered morality

relative considerations, though much traditional


Intrinsic versus Instrumental Relativity
moral theory has required agents to (try to) act from
a purely impartial, even impersonal, point of view. Are agent-relative considerations intrinsically
“I would have the dearest friend I have to know,” relative, or are they to be taken as instrumentally
said Jeremy BENTHAM (1748–1832), the architect of subordinate to higher-level agent-neutral consider-
classical UTILITARIANISM, “that his interests, if they ations? An instrumentalist analysis, as found in con-
come in competition with that of the public, are as sequentialist apologists such as R. M. HARE, deflates
nothing to me.” Though such a remark would speak the significance of agent-relative moral considera-
well for the integrity of a public official, it might call tions as objections to CONSEQUENTIALISM —which is
into question the speaker’s INTEGRITY as a friend. of course the point of such an analysis.
Some philosophers, most influentially Bernard WIL-
LIAMS, have attacked the adequacy of utilitarianism
Prerogatives versus Restrictions
precisely because it seems to compromise the integ-
rity of the moral agent’s CHARACTER in regard to Do agent-relative considerations merely permit
PERSONAL RELATIONSHIPS and to other values and moral agents, under certain circumstances, to ignore
projects which give the agent’s life meaning. Wil- the impersonal demands of morality? Or do they re-
liams’s sustained critique began in the early 1970s, quire that such demands be ignored? Samuel Schef-
shortly after John RAWLS had argued that utilitari- fler has defended a “hybrid view” which recognizes
anism fails to take the difference between people se- an agent-centered prerogative—permitting agents,
riously, and shortly before Robert NOZICK was to within limits, to pursue their own projects even
introduce the notion of nonutilitarian “side con- when this would not produce the best overall out-
straints,” suggesting that though utilitarianism might come (as defined by impersonal considerations)—
be a good enough moral theory for nonhuman ani- but resists recognizing agent-centered restrictions
mals, people require some form of DEONTOLOGY. which would require agents to act on agent-centered
considerations rather than produce the best state of
affairs. Scheffler’s critics have questioned the via-
bility of this “hybrid,” wondering whether the pre-
Varieties of Agent-Relativity
rogatives and the restrictions do not stand or fall
How are such agent-relative considerations to be together.
characterized? A variety of ordinary intuitions have
appeared to be in tension with the demands of agent-
Alternatives to Agent-Relativity
neutral morality. Thomas Nagel, for example, iden-
tifies three kinds of agent-relativity: “Common sense Which moral views do agent-relative considera-
suggests that each of us should live his own life (au- tions call into question? Bernard Williams’s original
tonomy), give special consideration to certain others target was utilitarianism. But he, and others, have
(obligation), have some significant concern for the gone on to question the impersonal demands of Kan-
general good (neutral values), and treat the people he tian theories of moral duty as well. Thus, the issues
deals with decently (deontology).” Amartya Sen— about agent-centered morality may be deeper than
distinguishing among “doer-relativity”, “viewer- the debate between consequentialism and deontol-
relativity”, and “self-evaluation-relativity”—argues ogy. Samuel Freeman has proposed that the idea of
that deontological values can be accommodated by agent-neutral reasons presupposes the (teleological)
some forms of consequence-based evaluation notion of a single ultimate good, as against the (de-
(though not by utilitarianism). Sen has gone on to ontological) recognition of an irreducible plurality
develop his concept of “positional objectivity,” in of intrinsic goods.
terms of which he sees “no basic conflict between The problem of determining the limits of moral-
consequential ethics and agent-relativity.” ity’s claims remains. The flourishing of an individual
But how is the force of agent-relative considera- life in its necessary social context (what ARISTOTLE
tions to be understood? Three questions can be [384–322 B.C.E.] called eudaimonia) may be viewed
distinguished. either (1) as requiring virtue-or-excellence (arete),

41
agent-centered morality

as EUDAIMONISM suggests; or (2) as setting a limit Buchanan, Allen. “Justice as Reciprocity versus Subject-
to the impersonal demands the morally responsive Centered Justice.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 19
(1990): 227 – 52. Unusual in applying “subject-
agent must endure. On the latter view, a morality centered” (and, more narrowly, “agent-centered”) to
which precluded all possibility of personal fulfill- theories which make moral status depend on features
ment in the agent’s life would simply demand too of the subject other than power to affect the well-being
much. If moral virtue goes with human flourishing, of others. This engages a set of issues different from
then how can agents be called upon to sacrifice what those discussed here.
is vital to that flourishing? On the other hand, if Darwall, Stephen. “Agent-Centered Restrictions from the
flourishing is not possible apart from the life of vir- Inside Out.” Philosophical Studies 50 (1986): 291–
319.
tue, how can even the most stringent demand of mo-
Freeman, Samuel. “Utilitarianism, Deontology, and the
rality be subverted in the name of self-interest?
Priority of Right.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 23
Scheffler has argued (against the view that mo- (1994): 313–49.
rality is “stringent” and against the opposed view Hare, R. M. Moral Thinking: Its Levels, Method, and
that it is merely coincident with self-interest) that Point. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1981. Utilitar-
morality is in fact “moderate”—an attempt to do ianism defended.
justice both to the idea that all INTERESTS have equal Harris, John. Violence and Responsibility. London: Rout-
intrinsic importance and to the idea that each per- ledge and Kegan Paul, 1980. Consequentialist negative
son’s interests have a personal significance “out of responsibility defended.
proportion to their importance from an impersonal Hurley, Paul. “Agent-Centered Restrictions: Clearing the
Air of Paradox.” Ethics 108 (1997): 120–46.
standpoint.” On his version of agent-relativity, mo-
rality takes our partialities seriously, but also forms Kagan, Shelly. The Limits of Morality. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1989. Consequentialism defended.
part of a complex social and psychological reality in
Kamm, F. M. “Non-Consequentialism, The Person as an
which it becomes possible for moral considerations
End-in-Itself, and the Significance of Status.” Philoso-
to acquire a motivating force independent of our phy and Public Affairs 21 (1992): 354–89.
personal desires. “Not only does morality itself aim Korsgaard, Christine M. “The Reasons We Can Share: An
in part to accommodate the interests of the agent, Attack on the Distinction between Agent-Relative and
but at the same time agents who acquire moral mo- Agent-Neutral Values.” Social Philosophy and Policy
tives try, in effect, to shape their own interests in 10 (January 1993): 24–51. Reprinted in her Creating
such a way as to avoid conflict with morality.” This the Kingdom of Ends (Cambridge University Press,
1996), chapter 10.
subtle and perceptive account of, as Scheffler puts
Lippert-Rasmussen, Kasper. “Moral Status and the Im-
it, human morality deserves better than the disdain-
possibility of Minimizing Violations.” Philosophy and
ful sniff it would doubtless receive from Bentham. Public Affairs 25 (1996): 333–51.
See also: AUTONOMY OF ETHICS; AUTONOMY OF Mack, Eric. “Personal Integrity, Practical Recognition, and
MORAL AGENTS; CHARACTER; CONSEQUENTIALISM;
Rights.” Monist 76 (1993): 101–18. See also other ar-
ticles by Mack cited therein.
DEONTOLOGY; DESIRE; DUTY AND OBLIGATION;
McNaughton, David, and Piers Rawling. “Deontology and
EQUALITY; EUDAIMONIA, -ISM; FEMINIST ETHICS; IM-
Agency.” Monist 76 (1993): 81–100.
PARTIALITY; INTEGRITY; INTUITIONISM; KANTIAN
Nagel, Thomas. The View from Nowhere. Oxford: Oxford
ETHICS; MORAL POINT OF VIEW; MORAL RELATIVISM;
University Press, 1986. Chapter 9 discusses three kinds
MOTIVES; PARTIALITY; PUBLIC AND PRIVATE MORAL- of agent-relativity. Reprinted in Scheffler.
ITY; REASONS FOR ACTION; RESPONSIBILITY; SELF ———. Equality and Partiality. Oxford: Oxford Univer-
AND SOCIAL SELF; SUBJECTIVISM; UTILITARIANISM; sity Press, 1991.
WILLIAMS. Nozick, Robert. Anarchy, State, and Utopia. New York:
Basic Books, 1974. Chapter 3 introduces nonutilitarian
“side constraints.” Extracted in Scheffler.
Bibliography
Parfit, Derek. Reasons and Persons. Oxford: Oxford Uni-
Brink, David O. Moral Realism and the Foundations of versity Press, 1984. Argues that our reasons for acting
Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989. should become more impersonal.
Includes critique of Scheffler. Raz, Joseph. The Morality of Freedom. Oxford: Oxford
Brook, Richard. “Agency and Morality.” Journal of Phi- University Press, 1986.
losophy 88 (1991): 190–212. Critique of Scheffler. Scheffler, Samuel. The Rejection of Consequentialism.

42
agnosticism

Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1982. The “hybrid” by the methods of the sciences. Any attempt to ex-
theory. tend this knowledge beyond the phenomena, and to
———. Human Morality. Oxford: Oxford University make claims about a God or gods is, however, dis-
Press, 1992. A subtle, humane discussion.
missed as presumptuous. With regard to the exis-
———. “Relationships and Responsibilities.” Philosophy
and Public Affairs 26 (1997): 189–209.
tence and properties of a God or gods, the agnostic’s
———, ed. Consequentialism and Its Critics. Oxford: Ox- creed is not just the modest and unassuming “I don’t
ford University Press, 1988. Invaluable anthology. know” but the much more challenging “we can’t
Sen, Amartya. “Rights and Agency.” Philosophy and Pub- know,” i.e., there is some reason of principle why
lic Affairs 11 (1982): 3–39. Especially Sections 5–7. such knowledge is unattainable for us.
Reprinted in Scheffler. Agnosticism became a widely accepted doctrine
———. “Positional Objectivity.” Philosophy and Public among the intellectuals of late Victorian Britain, as
Affairs 22 (1993): 126–45. Especially Section 9. the implications for epistemology of the work of
Slote, Michael. Common-Sense Morality and Consequen- HUME (1711–1776) and KANT (1724–1804) be-
tialism. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1985.
came assimilated. Although their philosophies differ
Stewart, Robert M. “Agent-Relativity, Reason, and Value.”
Monist 76 (1993): 66–80. Critique of Scheffler and
in fundamental respects, both Hume and Kant pro-
Nagel. duced accounts of human knowledge which saw it
Unger, Peter. Living High and Letting Die: Our Illusion of as necessarily confined to the realm of appearances
Innocence. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996. or phenomena. For Kant, there is a noumenal realm
Williams, Bernard. “A Critique of Utilitarianism.” In Util- of things-in-themselves behind the phenomena, but
itarianism: For and Against, by J. J. C. Smart and Ber- we can say nothing positive about this realm; for
nard Williams, 75–150. Cambridge: Cambridge Uni- Hume, it is a real possibility that there are only the
versity Press, 1973. The place to start. Extracted in
appearances. Both men rejected the traditional ar-
Scheffler.
———. Moral Luck. Cambridge: Cambridge University
guments for the existence of God, whether a priori
Press, 1981. Especially chapters 1 and 3, which elab- or empirical, as inconclusive. The traditional argu-
orate and extend the attack on impersonal morality. ment to design, however, survived their critique, and
———. Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy. Cambridge: was widely employed in the first half of the nine-
Harvard University Press, 1985. teenth century as a proof of a wise and benevolent
———. Making Sense of Humanity. Cambridge: Cam- designer God. It was only after the publication of
bridge University Press, 1995. DARWIN’s (1809–1882) Origin of Species (1859)
Wilson, Catherine. “On Some Alleged Limitations to that atheists and agnostics could give a convincing
Moral Endeavor.” Journal of Philosophy 90 (1993):
reply to this argument, citing Darwin’s theory as
275–89.
proof that the functional adaptation of the parts of
Edward Johnson plants and animals need not be taken as evidence of
intelligent design.
The main agnostic writers—Spencer, Tyndall,
agents Huxley, Stephen, and Clifford—never formed a
closed group with an agreed body of doctrine. One
See autonomy of moral agents; idealized agents.
crucial question which divided them was whether
agnosticism was essentially a positive or a negative
doctrine. For Herbert SPENCER (1820–1903), the
agnosticism agnostic has a positive belief in ‘The Unknowable’,
The term ‘agnosticism’ was coined by the English and should even redirect his or her religious emo-
biologist Thomas Henry Huxley (1825–1895) tions toward it. Religion, he argues, spontaneously
around 1869, but the position itself is far more an- evolves into agnosticism as it replaces more primi-
cient: there have doubtless been agnostics ever since tive and anthropomorphic conceptions of God with
people first began to think seriously about the gods. more sophisticated and abstract ones. The Irish
The agnostic is a sort of partial or limited sceptic. physicist John Tyndall (1820–1893) shared this
He or she is quite happy to accept that we have view, arguing that agnosticism is hostile only to dog-
knowledge of the world of phenomena, obtained matic theology, not to RELIGION as such. For Huxley,
first by ordinary sense experience and then extended however, agnosticism is a much more negative doc-

43
agnosticism

trine: in his article “Agnosticism,” he characterizes “It is wrong always, everywhere, and for any one, to
it simply in terms of adoption of a critical, sceptical believe anything upon insufficient evidence.” A per-
attitude toward religious and metaphysical claims, son who believes something without adequate evi-
and dismisses with some scorn the suggestion that dence is, for Clifford, like the carrier of a plague
it could become itself a sort of surrogate religion virus—an argument that has been repeated in our
with its own creed. The great Victorian man of let- own time by Richard Dawkins. This seizing of the
ters Leslie Stephen (1832–1904), and the mathe- moral high ground by the anti-clerical party repre-
matician William Kingdom Clifford (1845–1879), sents a turning point in intellectual history. Until this
shared this negative, more Humean conception of point, the high ground had always seemed to belong,
agnosticism. as if by divine right, to the clerics, who never ceased
The implications of agnosticism for ethics are ba- to portray the freethinkers as dangerous and im-
sically the same as those of ATHEISM. Even if there moral rogues. Now the freethinkers could turn the
is a God or a pantheon of gods, if we can know tables, claiming that they at least were honest and
nothing about him, her, it, or them, it follows that sincere searchers after truth, willing to confess their
we can know nothing about whatever moral prop- ignorance where evidence is lacking, and portraying
erties the God or gods may possess, or what sorts of their clerical opponents as standing for little more
conduct he, she, it, or they may command or pro- than pride and prejudice.
hibit. In practice, therefore, the agnostic must adopt Opponents of agnosticism were thus faced with
a purely secular view of ethics. He or she might con-
a simple choice. They could either insist that the ag-
sistently adopt a utilitarian moral theory, or a Kan-
nostics were wrong about the epistemology—that
tian one. In point of historical fact, however, several
there was evidence, after all, for the existence of a
prominent agnostics adopted the evolutionary-
God with some knowable properties. Or they could
naturalist account of ethics championed by Herbert
take issue with the agnostics about the ethics of be-
Spencer in his Data of Ethics. On this account,
lief and defend faith against Clifford’s attack. It is
MORAL RULES seem intuitive and a priori to the in-
not hard to find champions of each of these ap-
dividual, but have been ‘learned’ by the race, in the
proaches. The Jesuit Charles Coupe (1853–1910),
sense that communities of humans with such moral
for example, argues, against Huxley, that God “has
intuitions have tended, over the course of evolution-
not left Himself without witness” in the world, and
ary history, to flourish at the expense of others. On
this theory, the PHENOMENOLOGY of individual that the agnostics’ profession of ignorance is disin-
moral experience and moral judgment is intuition- genuous and therefore culpable. Another Catholic
istic, but the theory of EVOLUTION explains how we priest, William Barry (1849–1930), argues that Dar-
came to be the sort of beings who have such moral winism only overthrows the crudest versions of the
‘intuitions.’ argument to design, and that more sophisticated ver-
A distinctive feature of the controversy over ag- sions are still defensible. A disciple of Newman
nosticism was the issue of the ethics of belief. Over (1801–1890), John Bernard Dalgairns (1818–
the centuries, the defenders of established religions 1876), argues that even if the natural world shows
have sought to represent faith as a virtue and doubt no evidence of God, human moral and spiritual ex-
as a vice. For agnostics like Huxley, Stephen, and perience furnishes all the evidence we require. De-
Clifford, exactly the opposite is the case. They ap- fenders of the virtue of faith include W. H. Mallock
peal explicitly to such moral VIRTUES as frankness, (1849–1923) and the American pragmatist William
honesty, and humility in their defence against cleri- JAMES (1842–1910), whose famous essay “The Will
cal opponents. If there are some things we humans to Believe” is in large part a reply to Clifford.
simply can’t know, they argue, surely it is better
freely to admit as much, rather than to try to defend See also: ABSURD, THE; ATHEISM; EVOLUTION; HU-
old exploded creeds by increasingly sophistical ar- MANISM; INTUITIONISM; METAPHYSICS AND EPISTE-
guments? This argument is most forcefully ex- MOLOGY; MORAL RULES; NATURALISM; PHENOME-
pressed in Clifford’s famous essay, “The Ethics of NOLOGY; PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION; RELIGION;
Belief,” which portrays honest doubt as a moral duty SKEPTICISM IN ETHICS; SPENCER; THEISM; THEOLOG-
and blind faith as a dangerous and anti-social vice: ICAL ETHICS.

44
agricultural ethics

Bibliography about health yearn for home-grown, chemical-free


food, while representatives of the agribusiness and
Clifford, William Kingdom. Lectures and Essays. Edited
by L. Stephen and F. Pollock. London: Macmillan, chemicals industries boast that their technical ad-
1879. Contains the famous essay “The Ethics of vances have helped reduce hunger and starvation.
Belief.” The debate over agricultural ethics focuses on at
Flint, Robert. Agnosticism. Edinburgh: Blackwoods, least six issues. These concern (1) agricultural
1903. A weighty and substantial account of Victorian threats to public health and safety (e.g., pesticides);
agnosticism. Very thorough, but tends to assimilate ag- (2) government RESPONSIBILITY for controlling ag-
nosticism too closely to scepticism in general.
ricultural resource depletion (e.g., loss of prime crop
Huxley, Thomas Henry. Science and the Christian Tradi-
tion. London: Macmillan, 1897. This volume, number
land to developers); (3) agricultural contributions to
six of Huxley’s collected essays, contains the famous ecological disturbance (e.g., topsoil losses); (4) gov-
article “Agnosticism” (first published in The Nine- ernment responsibility for preserving the family,
teenth Century in 1889) and other relevant essays. rather than the corporate, farm (e.g., on the grounds
Lightman, Bernard. The Origins of Agnosticism. Balti- that it contributes to DEMOCRACY, self-reliance, and
more: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1987. The best environmental stewardship); (5) problems with fac-
modern study, stressing the positive aspect of Victorian
tory farming and animal husbandry (e.g., subjecting
agnosticism.
Pyle, Andrew, ed. Agnosticism: Contemporary Reactions
animals to unnecessary suffering); and (6) monop-
to Spencer and Huxley. Bristol: Thoemmes Press, olistic control of food production by agribusiness in-
1995. Valuable collection of essays by the agnostics dustries (e.g., petrochemical industries’ thwarting
and their critics. the development of safer biological means of pest
Spencer, Herbert. First Principles. London: Williams and control). We shall discuss each of these issues in
Norgate, 1862. The classic statement of ‘positive’ ag- order.
nosticism, with ‘the Unknowable’ coming to take the
place of God.
———. The Data of Ethics. London: Williams and Nor-
gate, 1879. The classic statement of evolutionary Agricultural Threats to Public Health
ethics.
and Safety
Stephen, Leslie. An Agnostic’s Apology and Other Essays.
London: Smith, Elder, 1893. Contains the famous es- Modern agriculture has increased the use of food
say, “An Agnostic’s Apology,” first published in The preservatives, fertilizers, and pesticides. Many phi-
Fortnightly Review in 1876.
losophers have questioned the ethical justifiability of
———. The Science of Ethics. London: Smith, Elder,
employing these chemicals. Claiming that use of ag-
1882. Reprinted Bristol: Thoemmes, 1991. Another
important statement of the evolutionary-naturalist ricultural toxins violates citizens’ rights to bodily
ethics favoured by the agnostics. security, equal protection, and due process, philos-
ophers such as Alan GEWIRTH and Kristin Shrader-
A. J. Pyle Frechette use deontological arguments to show that
farmers are ethically wrong to employ chemicals that
cause cancer and genetic damage.
agricultural ethics Representatives of the agriculture industry re-
Almost all persons have benefited from “the green spond, however, that use of chemical pesticides, fer-
revolution,” from agricultural progress that has cre- tilizers, and preservatives lowers the price of food
ated high-yield hybrids, fertilizers, pesticides, and and hence makes good nutrition more widely avail-
preservatives for our food. In the United States, ag- able. Pesticide promoters claim that, on a utilitarian
riculture has been so successful that fewer than 4 balance, agricultural chemicals create more benefit
percent of us are able to grow enough food both to than harm. Moreover, they point out that use of pes-
feed the other 96 percent and to export significant ticides and fertilizers is necessary because per capita
surpluses. amounts of crop land are decreasing worldwide. The
Responses to “the green revolution,” to the luxury only way to increase crop yields and decrease crop
of abundant, inexpensive food created by technolog- acreage is with chemical assistance. But this raises
ical and economic advances, however, have been the issue of whether government ought to protect
mixed. Nostalgic romantics and persons concerned valuable agricultural lands.

45
agricultural ethics

those rights, is the best way to provide economically


Ought Government to Prevent Agricultural
and ecologically sustainable agriculture. Debates
Resource Depletion?
among proponents of government-regulated, versus
Proponents of regulation to protect agricultural private, agriculture also focus on (a) acceptable
land, like Lester Brown, argue that the United States levels of environmental degradation; (b) the cost-
annually loses 3 million acres of prime crop land to benefit trade-off between ecological disturbance and
other uses. This is a loss, they claim, that will even- agricultural productivity; and (c) whether coercive,
tually interfere with our ability to feed ourselves. versus incentive, regulatory programs are more ac-
They argue that, for the sake of the common good, ceptable from an ethical point of view.
government ought to restrict PROPERTY rights to
crop land so as to protect agricultural acreage and
The Ethical and Political Desirability of the
prevent resource depletion.
Family Farm
Opponents of using zoning, regulation, and tax-
ation to protect agricultural land claim that such One proposed solution to the problem of agri-
practices amount to a “taking” without just compen- cultural degradation is to provide government sup-
sation since they typically cause a reduction in the port for the family farm, on the grounds that owners
market value of land and hence unjustly restrict of small, private farms exercise more stewardship
property rights. Opponents of protecting farmland over land resources than do hired workers on large
also say that agricultural zoning is exclusionary. corporate farms. Proponents of family farms argue
They claim that it violates the equal-protection and that, in addition to conserving the soil, family farms
due-process rights of low-income people who need have higher yields per acre. They also provide a
land for housing. strong foundation for self-reliance and for a Jeffer-
sonian notion of democracy based on economically
independent, and therefore politically free, farmers.
Sustainable Agriculture and Ecologically
Opponents of government incentives for family
Sound Farming
farming maintain that these farms are inefficient, be-
Farmland is not threatened, however, merely by cause they do not have the advantage of economies
developers who want acreage for other purposes, of scale. They also claim that a Jeffersonian agrarian
like housing. As Wendell Berry shows, it is also jeop- society is excessively idealistic. Belief in “antiquated
ardized by ecologically unsound agricultural man- farming methods” is unrealistic, says Keith Camp-
agement. Brown estimates that the world annually bell, because chemically intensive, highly technolog-
loses 23 billion tons of soil from crop lands in ex- ical, and automated agriculture is necessary if food
cess of new soil formation. Many agricultural tech- prices are to remain low enough to enable the poor
niques encourage topsoil loss (e.g., failure to ter- to have access to adequate food. Hence, on balance,
race, maximum-till practices, overgrazing). Some they claim that the benefits of corporate farming out-
moral philosophers, like William Aiken, argue for weigh those of family farming.
a government duty to regulate this commons (soil)
in a way that will not bankrupt members of FUTURE
Factory Farming and Animal Rights
GENERATIONS.
Opponents of government regulation of agricul- One of the main components of corporate farm-
tural land claim that markets, not governments, are ing is an animal husbandry designed to maximize
better regulators of resources. They say that when milk, meat, or egg yield. In the name of economic
erosion and use of pesticides become so destructive efficiency, factory farmers often keep animals in
that farmers are hurt financially, they will change darkness or cage them so closely that they cannot
their ecologically unsound practices. They also argue move. They defend their procedures, as Campbell
that the countries with the most government control and R. G. Frey do, by claiming that their efficiencies
of farming, e.g., the former Soviet Union, have the are able to make meat available to virtually everyone
worst record of agricultural abuse of the land. Hence and at low prices. For them, factory farming pro-
they claim that strengthening property rights to duces the greatest good for the greatest number of
land, not increasing government constraints on people. Other moral philosophers, like Hugh Leh-

46
agricultural ethics

man, argue that there are cases in which, even if See also: ANIMALS, TREATMENT OF; APPLIED ETHICS;
animals have RIGHTS, it is morally acceptable to kill BIOETHICS; BUSINESS ETHICS; COMMON GOOD; CON-
them for food or scientific experimentation. SENT; CONSERVATION ETHICS; COOPERATIVE SUR-
Philosopher critics of factory farming fall into PLUS; COST-BENEFIT ANALYSIS; ECONOMIC ANALYSIS;
two categories. Whether utility-oriented, like Peter ENVIRONMENTAL ETHICS; EQUALITY; FUTURE GEN-
Singer, or rights-oriented, like Tom Regan, they ar- ERATIONS; GENETIC ENGINEERING; GOVERNMENT,
gue that because animals feel pain, they deserve to ETHICS IN; JUSTICE, DISTRIBUTIVE; LAND ETHICS; LE-
have their INTERESTS taken into account. Singer GAL ETHICS; LIBERTARIANISM; LIBERTY, ECONOMIC;
claims that there is an ethical imperative to be a veg- NATURE AND ETHICS; PROPERTY; PUBLIC HEALTH
etarian because of the necessity to recognize the in- POLICY; PUBLIC POLICY; RISK; TECHNOLOGY; TECH-
terests of animals normally eaten as food. Other NOLOGY AND NATURE.
philosophers do not go so far as promoting vegetar-
ianism, but they argue that causing animals any un- Bibliography
necessary suffering is ethically indefensible.
Aiken, William. “Ethical Issues in Agriculture.” In Earth-
bound, edited by Tom Regan, 247–88. New York: Ran-
dom House, 1984. Excellent overview of issues.
Oligopoly and Agribusiness Aiken, William, and Hugh LaFollette, eds. World Hunger
and Moral Obligation. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice
For proponents of factory farming, however, Hall, 1977. Ethical obligations regarding hunger.
causing animal suffering is a small price to pay for Berry, Wendell. The Unsettling of America. San Francisco:
meeting human needs. Accepting the proposition Sierra Club, 1977. Argues for sustainable agriculture.
that humans are superior to other animals, they con- Blatz, Charles, ed. Ethics and Agriculture. Moscow, ID:
clude that factory farming is not unethical in any University of Idaho Press, 1991. Collected essays on
ethical issues in agriculture.
important sense. Indeed, agriculturalists like Camp-
Brown, Lester, ed. State of the World 1985; . . . 1986. New
bell claim that factory farming is ethical in that it York: W. W. Norton, 1985; 1986. See his articles: “Re-
uses economies of scale to provide inexpensive meat ducing Hunger,” pp. 53–73 of the 1985 volume (sur-
to a great many people. In other words, “big” agri- veys agricultural reforms needed to reduce hunger);
culture, accounting for one-fourth of the gross na- and “Conserving Soils,” pp. 23–41 of the 1986 volume
tional product in the United States by means of food (surveys agricultural reforms to reduce topsoil losses).
production, processing, and merchandising, is able Burkhardt, Jeffrey. “Agribusiness Ethics.” Journal of Busi-
ness Ethics 5 (1986): 333–45. Reviews the major busi-
to democratize nutrition by making inexpensive pro- ness ethics issues applicable to agriculture.
tein widely available. Busch, Lawrence, and William Lacy, eds. The Agricultural
Not everyone agrees that “big” agriculture is good Scientific Enterprise. Boulder, CO: Westview, 1986. Is
agriculture, however. Just as it produces the abuses agricultural research ethically biased?
of factory farming, big agriculture allegedly exem- Campbell, Keith. Food for the Future. Lincoln: University
plifies other ethical and social problems typical of of Nebraska Press, 1979. Defends progressive, large-
any industry that has monopolistic control of the scale, high-technology, chemical-intensive agriculture.
economy in a given area. Robert van den Bosch ar- Carson, Rachel. Silent Spring. Cambridge, MA: Riverside,
1962. Classic analysis of the hazards of pesticide use.
gues, for example, that because agribusiness is so
Frey, R. G. Rights, Killing, and Suffering. Oxford: Basil
powerful, it is able to subvert and manipulate even Blackwell, 1983. Ethical defense of meat eating and
attempted pesticide regulation done on behalf of the animal husbandry.
COMMON GOOD. The result, he argues, is that ordi- Gewirth, Alan. “Human Rights and the Prevention of Can-
nary citizens, in practice, lose their equal-protection cer.” American Philosophical Quarterly 17 (1980):
and due-process rights, as well as their rights to con- 117–26.
sent to agricultural risks affecting them. To the de- Hurnik, J., and Hugh Lehman. “Ethics and Farm Animal
Welfare.” Journal of Agricultural Ethics 1, no. 4
gree that agriculture is agribusiness, accomplished
(1988): 305–18. Ethical obligations in animal hus-
through large corporate farms that exercise monop- bandry.
olistic control over certain crops and oligopolistic Kunkel, H. “Agricultural Ethics.” Agriculture and Human
control over government, agricultural ethics deals Values 1 (1984): 20–23. Survey of issues in agricul-
with some of the same issues as BUSINESS ETHICS. tural ethics.

47
agricultural ethics

Lehman, Hugh. “On the Moral Acceptability of Killing cussion and to a wide variety of further adaptations
Animals.” Journal of Agricultural Ethics 1, no. 2 and applications of the notion, not only within
(1988): 155–62. Analysis of situations in which it is
ethically defensible to kill animals.
Marxist circles but also in existential philosophy and
Regan, Tom, and Peter Singer, eds. Animal Rights and
theology, in SOCIOLOGY and social psychology, and
Human Obligations. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice in critiques of modern life and society. Consequently,
Hall, 1976. Classic anthology on ethical arguments re- while one may speak of “the phenomenon of alien-
garding animal treatment and factory farming. ation” in Hegel, and of “the alienation syndrome” in
Shrader-Frechette, Kristin. “Agriculture, Ethics, and Re- Marx, the term today no more designates anything
strictions on Property Rights.” Journal of Agricultural specific than does the term “separation,” with which
Ethics 1, no. 1 (1988): 21–40. Arguments for restrict-
it is now roughly synonymous.
ing property rights in order to promote the family farm,
ensure equal opportunity, and discourage agribusiness
monopolies.
Alienation in Hegel and Marx
———. Environmental Ethics. Second edition. Pacific
Grove, CA: Boxwood, 1991. “Pesticide Toxicity: An Hegel introduced the notions of alienation and
Ethical Perspective” argues that use of broad-spectrum self-alienation in the context of his scheme of the
pesticides is ethically indefensible. self-actualizing development of Geist (spirit). This
Steiner, Frederick, and John E. Theilacker, eds. Protecting process, as he conceived of it, involves a repeated
Farmlands. Westport, CT: AVI, 1984. Discussion of ar-
guments for protecting farmland.
three-stage pattern in which some form of objectiv-
Thompson, Paul. “Ethics in Agriculture Research.” Jour- ity is established, and with it an associated form of
nal of Agricultural Ethics 1, no. 1 (1988): 11–20. Sur- consciousness that is initially at one with it. This
vey and an analysis of key ethical issues in agricultural gives way to a stage in which consciousness comes
research. to experience that objectivity as an alien reality, with
van den Bosch, Robert. The Pesticide Conspiracy. New which it ceases to identify. The third stage involves
York: Doubleday, 1978. Reprinted, Berkeley: Univer- the overcoming of this separation, as consciousness
sity of California Press, 1989.
discovers the objectivity to be an expression (or ob-
Kristin Shrader-Frechette jectification and realization) of its own nature, and
so reidentifies itself with it. Hegel characterized the
second-stage withdrawal or absence of identification
akrasia in terms of alienation. He further took it to have the
significance of self-alienation, by which he meant
See weakness of will. both that, in the absence of such identification,
something with which one’s self is bound up has
become alien to one, and that an essential element
al-Fārābı̄ of one’s full self-realization as Geist is thus lacking.
See Fārābı̄, al-. The most salient instance of such alienation and self-
alienation in Hegel is that associated with the ex-
perience of the “substance” of one’s society as an
alien reality.
alienation Inspired in part by Ludwig FEUERBACH (1804–
The English term “alienation,” like its French and 1872) and his critique of Hegel, Marx appropriated
German counterparts, has long had a number of these Hegelian notions and gave them a different
uses. Prior to HEGEL (1770–1831), however, these application and explication. For Marx, “alienation”
terms had no significant employment in philosophy. retained its basic Hegelian meaning and use in con-
Hegel made important use of the concept of alien- nection with our relation to our self-objectifying and
ation (Entfremdung), in ways that were seized upon self-developing activity. However, he made its focus
and adapted by Karl MARX (1818–1883); but little the concrete practical activity of productive labor,
notice was taken of any of this until Marx’s early and took the inability to identify with one’s labor
writings were published and began to attract atten- and the products of one’s labor (under the condi-
tion in the 1930s. tions prevailing in capitalist society) to be the fun-
This led both to the rediscovery of Hegel’s dis- damental forms of alienation. While Marx also ex-

48
alienation

tended the application of the notion to encompass posed to signify not merely that a separation of some
several associated forms of separation of human be- sort has come to obtain, but moreover that some-
ings from each other, he curiously made no use of it thing is wrong with the separation, which therefore
(as Hegel and many others have) in connection with should be overcome if it can be, and is to be la-
our relation to social and cultural formations. He mented if it cannot. The most interesting of such
did, however, follow Hegel in employing the notion conceptions of alienation designate certain relations
of “self-alienation” to refer to human existence that of separation in which one may stand to aspects of
falls short of full human self-realization, as he one’s society (social, cultural, and political alien-
(rather differently from Hegel) understood it, and ation), the world of nature and things (world alien-
likewise considered such self-alienation to be linked ation), God (religious alienation), other people (in-
to the specific forms of alienation he discusses. terpersonal alienation), one’s labor and products
(WORK alienation), and one’s “self” or true nature
(self-alienation).
Subsequent Uses of “Alienation”
Not all such separations, however, are intrinsi-
The ways in which these notions have subse- cally and indisputably undesirable. Indeed, in some
quently been construed and applied are legion. contexts certain of them may actually have positive
While some of the phenomena specified may be re- rather than negative significance. If it is possible for
lated to each other, all of them cannot possibly be individuals to preserve or achieve relations of iden-
supposed to be connected in any significant way. In- tification, harmony, community, integration or ac-
terpersonal relationships admit of various sorts of cordance with something they confront, produce,
separations to which the term has been applied, as do, or are, and if such relations do not obtain, the
do one’s relations to God, nature, one’s own prod- contrasting separations may be described in terms
ucts, the products of others, social structures, po- of “alienation.” Further argument is needed, how-
litical INSTITUTIONS, cultural formations, prevailing ever, to determine whether and why any of these re-
NORMS and values, events one does not comprehend, lations are objectionable. The fact that such sepa-
processes one does not control, and one’s own labor, rations may be termed forms of alienation by itself
actions, and body. Such “forms” of alienation have neither establishes that something is wrong with
in common only that they may be characterized as them, nor indicates what it is that is wrong with
separations of some sort, in contrast to some prior, them, nor implies anything about what would be
possible, or merely conceivable forms of unity. preferable to them. The burden of doing so falls on
Generally speaking, forms or conceptions of the interpretive-evaluative theory in the context of
alienation pertain to relations in which one may which the notion is thus employed.
stand to something other than oneself, while self- See also: ATHEISM; AUTHENTICITY; CAMUS; COMMU-
alienation has to do with one’s relation to one’s own NITARIANISM; CRITICAL THEORY; CULTURAL STUDIES;
(true) self or nature. In some conceptions of alien- EXISTENTIAL ETHICS;FEUERBACH; HEGEL; HEIDEG-
ation, the basic idea is that of the experience of the GER; INTEGRITY; INTERESTS;
MARX; MARXISM;
radical otherness of something, in contrast to a feel- NEEDS; PERSON, CONCEPT OF; PERSONAL RELATION-
ing of identification or unity with it. In others, the SHIPS; POSTMODERNISM; PRAXIS; SARTRE; SELF-
basic idea is that of a condition of the absence of KNOWLEDGE; SOCIOLOGY; WORK.
unity with these things, regardless of how (if at all)
one regards or experiences them. The notion of self-
Bibliography
alienation, conceived in terms of a disparity between
one’s actual condition and one’s true (or truly hu- Camus, Albert. The Myth of Sisyphus. Translated by Justin
man) nature, is a special case of this sort. O’Brien. New York: Vintage, 1959 [1942]. A classic of
the alienation literature that does not use the word, by
the author of The Stranger.
Normative-Evaluative Import Feuer, Lewis. “What Is Alienation? The Career of a Con-
cept.” New Politics 1, no. 3 (1962): 116–34. A critique
The idea of alienation owes much of its contem- and lament.
porary appeal to the normative-evaluative force it is Feuerbach, Ludwig. Principles of the Philosophy of the
commonly understood to convey. It is often sup- Future. Translated by Manfred H. Vogel. Indianapolis,

49
alienation

IN: Hackett, 1986. Criticism of Hegel, on alienation


and more generally. Definition
Fromm, Erich. Escape from Freedom. New York: Avon, Some social psychologists tend to define altruism
1941. Along with his The Sane Society (London: Rout-
ledge and Kegan Paul, 1955), the book that popular-
in terms of action intentionally aimed at helping oth-
ized the concept of alienation. ers. But since such action could be engaged in for
Hegel, G. W. F. Phenomenology of Spirit. Translated by purely self-interested reasons, philosophers have
A. V. Miller. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977 [1807]. wanted to define altruism as involving in addition
Especially chapter 6B. Where it all began. some other-directed motivation—a regard for the
Heidegger, Martin. Being and Time. Translated by John well-being of others for its own sake. Even so, con-
Macquarrie and Edward Robinson. New York: Harper fusion remains about the definition of altruism. Some
and Row, 1962 [1927]. See especially sections 38, 51,
use it implicitly or explicitly to refer to any such re-
and 68. The book that launched existential philosophy,
featuring alienation in connection with inauthenticity. gard for others; some restrict it to a placing of the
Josephson, Eric, and Mary Josephson, eds. Man Alone: INTERESTS of others ahead of those of oneself. The
Alienation in Modern Society. New York: Dell, 1962. latter seems to correspond more to ordinary usage,
Anthology of alienation literature. while the former has become the definition of choice
Keniston, Kenneth. The Uncommitted: Alienated Youth in for most philosophers and many psychologists.
American Society. New York: Harcourt, Brace and A further definitional issue concerns unconscious
World, 1965. Why Johnny drops out.
motivation. Anna Freud (1895–1982) describes a
Marx, Karl. “Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts of
patient—a governess—who seems to care genuinely
1844.” In The Marx-Engels Reader, edited by Robert
Tucker. 2d edition, 66–125. New York: W. W. Norton, and selflessly for her friends and the children in her
1978. After Hegel, the locus classicus. Also see other charge; but Freud diagnoses her as being animated
early writings of Marx in this volume. on an unconscious level by a vicarious living out of
Petrovic, Gajo. Marx in the Mid-Twentieth Century. Gar- long-suppressed self-centered desires for affection,
den City, NY: Doubleday, 1967. Especially part 2. A romance, and success. Standard philosophic defini-
Marxist-humanist’s interpretation. Alienation as
tions of altruism would seem unproblematically to
dehumanization.
count this as altruism, since there does seem to be
Schacht, Richard. Alienation. Garden City, NY: Double-
day, 1970. A critical analysis of the literature from He- some conscious level on which Freud’s patient cares
gel onward. for others and acts on their behalf. Nevertheless, one
———. The Future of Alienation. Urbana and Chicago: might at least provisionally want to distinguish dif-
University of Illinois Press, 1994. A reconsideration of ferent levels of altruism, saying that someone can be
these central themes. consciously altruistic but unconsciously egoistic.
Seeman, Melvin. “On the Meaning of Alienation.” Amer- One might also take a step further to inquire
ican Sociological Review 24, no. 6 (1959): 783–91. A
whether the governess’s concern manifests a genu-
useful survey of sociological uses.
ine understanding of the other person, or whether,
Tillich, Paul. Systematic Theology, vol. II. Chicago: Uni-
versity of Chicago Press, 1957. Self-alienation in exis- by contrast, she seems to be attributing to her
tentialist theology. friends and the children desires and NEEDS they do
not have, desires and needs which the governess her-
Richard Schacht self has but cannot acknowledge. The latter situation
might make us more hesitant to say flatly that the
woman is altruistic, on any level, at least without
altruism some of the qualifications discussed below. In any
In some form altruism has been a perennial concern case, these issues of unconscious motivation, largely
of moral philosophy, and more recently of PSYCHOL- ignored by philosophers, cannot be avoided in a dis-
OGY, economics, SOCIOLOGY, and biology as well. Is cussion of altruism.
altruism possible, and if it is, is it a good or a bad This motivational question is raised also by the
thing, are questions familiar from the time of PLATO contribution of sociobiology to an understanding of
(c. 430–347 B.C.E.). Yet the assessment of altruism altruism. Sociobiology sees the risk-taking or self-
depends on its definition; and in this area much con- sacrificing behavior of various animal and even in-
fusion still remains. sect species—for example, birds giving warning

50
altruism

cries at the appearance of a predator, and in doing definition of altruism, as mentioned earlier. If altru-
so risking revealing their own location—as contrib- ism is defined as requiring suppression, negation, or
uting to the survivability of that species. Thus socio- belittling of the self—as involved in valuing of the
biologists see what they call “altruism” as having other above the self—it is more open to Nietzsche’s
evolutionary significance for natural selection. Some criticisms than if it merely means concern for others.
adherents of this perspective, most notably E. O. SCHELER (1874–1928), while affirming Nietzsche’s
Wilson and Richard Dawkins, draw the inference view that concern for others can be a product of self-
that the behavior in question is not in fact altruistic disvalue and self-escape, pointed out that a concern
since it is simply the species’ gene pool’s—or even for others can also be rooted in a strong and confi-
the individual agent’s genes’—way of perpetuating dent self, one which can attend to the plight of oth-
itself. As with unconscious motivation, deep prob- ers and react with fellow feeling or compassion pre-
lems arise here concerning the level of analysis on cisely because it is able to take care of its own needs
which altruism is being defined. But critics, such as without great self-absorption and continual bolster-
Mary Midgley, point out that showing the evolution- ing of its sense of self-worth.
ary origins of human altruistic concern in animals Many philosophers have understood human mo-
hardly shows it not actually to be altruism. tivation in such a way that any altruistic action is
Whether altruism really exists, or whether all
always at the expense of the self; the thought is that
seemingly altruistic acts are really motivated by self-
in every situation one must choose between the good
interest, has been a matter of great controversy
of others or of oneself (except when they fortunately
within the history of moral philosophy. Bishop Jo-
coincide). This mistaken view lends support to the
seph BUTLER (1692–1752) demonstrated to the sat-
definition of altruism as always involving self-
isfaction of many that concern for the well-being of
negation, and thereby leaves it open to Nietzsche’s
particular other persons cannot be assimilated to
criticisms. Butler preceded Scheler in seeing that al-
concern for one’s own well-being. But the contro-
versy continues, and the assumption that all human truistic action need entail no loss to the self, and the
motivation is egoistic still animates important development of depth psychology in the twentieth
strands within psychoanalytic and empirical psy- century has supported the view that a healthy atten-
chology, as well as moral philosophy. tion to self and a healthy concern for others, far from
being at odds, often tend to reinforce one another.
This is not to deny that altruism can involve great
Value of Altruism
personal RISK or sacrifice, as seen, for example,
Some commentators, such as Arthur SCHOPEN- among Righteous Gentiles in the Holocaust (non-
HAUER (1788–1860), regard altruism as the corner- Jewish rescuers of Jews in Nazi Europe), studied in
stone of ethics; and some Christian ethical thought, depth by Samuel and Pearl Oliner. Nevertheless,
such as that elaborated by Søren KIERKEGAARD even in many of these cases it is psychic health and
(1813–1855) in Works of Love, lends support to SELF-ESTEEM which enable these individuals to en-
this position. Yet the ethical views of Plato and AR- gage in such risk.
ISTOTLE (384–322 B.C.E.) entirely lack a concept of
Yet questions about the value of altruism still re-
altruism, and others see altruism as only one among main. Certainly one basis on which to assess altru-
many equally important virtues. Friedrich NIE-
ism as good or bad (whether this is strictly a moral
TZSCHE (1844–1900) even condemned altruism,
basis is unclear) has to do with whether the altruism
seeing it as grounded in RESENTMENT and in escape
is healthy for the agent herself. Following on Nie-
from the self and from those higher values (such as
tzsche’s, Scheler’s, and Anna Freud’s insight, one
COURAGE and spiritual strength) which only the self
may say that if the agent’s altruism (toward some
can create.
individual, or even in general) helps maintain an un-
healthy (e.g., dependent, un-self-knowing) structure
Altruism and Self-Negation of CHARACTER or mode of life, then even if it is per-
Some of these differences on the centrality of al- fectly genuine the altruism is unhealthy and in that
truism to ethics are the product of confusions in the respect bad.

51
altruism

which an agent can have altruistic concern, though


Altruism and the Good of the Other
the agent may recognize this need for autonomy
A second basis has to do with the effect of the while having no genuine (altruistic) concern for the
altruism on the good of the other person. If altruism other person at all. Thus we need not accept ordi-
is defined solely in terms of a desire for another’s nary language’s seeming association (present in
good, there is no guarantee that the good of the much philosophical usage as well) of altruism with
other is actually served by the altruism. Perhaps the active intervention in another person’s situation. We
agent has no understanding of the other’s good, and can rather accept Milton Mayeroff’s and Nel Nod-
his action subverts that good rather than furthering dings’s concept of an active enabling—a giving to
it. Iris MURDOCH rightly notes that understanding a the other of space to find her own way to knowing
(specific) other person is often a difficult task and a and meeting her own needs—as a way of picturing
morally significant one. Perhaps one could build in an altruism which takes seriously the other’s auton-
such an understanding as part of the definition of omy as part of her overall good.
altruism. For it could be argued that if the agent is
truly concerned with the other’s good, then she must
Types of Altruism
be concerned to understand that good; if she does
not, this is evidence that she is not really concerned, Even without the implication of self-sacrifice, and
and hence not truly altruistic. with autonomy and the knowledge of others built
Yet in many cases we acknowledge altruistic con- into the definition of altruism itself, the notion of
cern as itself genuine and authentic even when the altruism as concern for others is not a unified phe-
agent shows little understanding of the other. If we nomenon but encompasses distinct phenomena,
adhere to a definition of altruism which makes it which might be differently evaluated. The definition,
distinct from understanding of the other, then we for example, would seem to include LOVE for one’s
can at least say that altruism combined with under- relations (either kin or friends), since presumably
standing is more clearly a good than mere altruism one cares for them for their own sakes. But this is a
per se. A seemingly more systematic problem with very different phenomenon from being concerned
altruism, related to the issue of the good of the other about a stranger. One difference is that one’s own
(and often associated particularly with CHARITY), is specific good is bound up with one’s relations in a
that while one can genuinely care about the other way it is not with strangers; so acting on one’s
and succeed in meeting that person’s need, some- friend’s behalf, out of concern, is inevitably bound
times it can be better not to help but to allow the up with the good of that relationship to oneself (even
person to meet his or her own need. Too much help if not done with the goal of sustaining that good).
can cause or reinforce a sense of dependency, which For this reason some are reluctant to call such action
undermines the other’s capacities for self-help and “altruistic” at all, insofar as they take altruism en-
autonomous need satisfaction. Nevertheless, this tirely to exclude intrinsic connection to a good to
worry can be overstated, as, for example, SIDGWICK the self.
(1838–1900) does in affirming that it is better that Consider also cooperation, construing it here as
each adult have the general expectation that he him- meaning more than merely adhering to rules of mu-
self rather than others will meet his needs. As KANT tual self-protection and self-interest. Let us assume
(1724–1804) said, we are dependent beings and it to include a valuing of the cooperative endeavor
need to rely on one another for all sorts of things; for its own sake and to include TRUST in the other
needing to receive from others is not as a general person or persons involved in the endeavor. One im-
rule something to seek to avoid. plication of this trust is that one restrains the pursuit
Still, meeting an individual’s needs at the expense of one’s own interest out of regard for that of the
of her autonomy could turn out to be on the whole other with whom one is cooperating. But this is far
a bad rather than a good thing for her; and, in some from the active concern for the other’s good which
situations, letting others remain in distress or sink is more generally associated with the concept of al-
into a personal morass can be the best thing to do truism; in fact, trust and cooperation can be seen as
for them. Regard for the autonomy of others can having their own specific kind of value precisely be-
perhaps be included as part of the overall good for cause they do not require active concern for the good

52
altruism

of others. They require only a limited regard, which SHIP; INTERESTS; MOTIVES; NEEDS; PERSONAL RE-
is internal to and bounded by the cooperative en- LATIONSHIPS; PSYCHOLOGY; RATIONALITY VS.
deavor itself, while that endeavor as a whole (though REASONABLENESS; REASONS FOR ACTION; RECIPROC-
not each individual act within it) is seen as a good ITY; RISK; SCHOPENHAUER; SELF AND SOCIAL SELF;
to the individual participant. Yet, as in the analogous SELF-ESTEEM; SELF-KNOWLEDGE; SOCIAL PSYCHOL-
case of FRIENDSHIP mentioned above, this motiva- OGY; SOCIOLOGY; SYMPATHY.
tion is covered by the general definition of altruism
as including action taken out of regard for another’s
Bibliography
good.
Thus while concern for strangers, concern for Blum, Lawrence. Friendship, Altruism, and Morality. Lon-
friends, and cooperative activity all fall within the don: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1980. Discussion of
general rubric of altruism, they are significantly dis- nature of altruism as emotion-based phenomenon, and
its importance for morality.
tinct psychic and moral phenomena.
Butler, Joseph. Five Sermons Preached at the Rolls Chapel.
Indianapolis: Hackett, 1983 [1726]. Classic defense of
possibility of altruism against Hobbes’s version of psy-
Is Altruism Rational? chological egoism.
A further issue also related to the value of altru- Freud, Anna. “A Form of Altruism.” Chapter 10 in her
ism—one which has particularly engaged the atten- The Ego and the Mechanisms of Defense. Rev. ed. New
York: International Universities Press, 1966 [1936].
tion of Anglo-American philosophers in the last sev- Important discussion in psychoanalytic tradition.
eral decades—is whether altruism is rational, that Kierkegaard, Søren. Works of Love. Translated by Howard
is, whether the good of another itself supplies a rea- and Edna Hong. New York: Harper and Row, 1962
son for an agent to further that good. Some affirm [1847]. Important disquisition on nature of Christian
the traditional “ethical egoist” position that ration- love.
ality involves taking only one’s own interests as REA- Mayeroff, Milton. On Caring. New York: Harper and Row,
SONS FOR ACTION (though one may happen to take 1971. Discussion of connection between altruism and
understanding of the other person’s good.
such an interest in another person’s interests).
Midgley, Mary. Beast and Man: The Roots of Human Na-
Others, such as Thomas Nagel, affirm the ration-
ture. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1978. Good
ality of altruism on the grounds that reason requires discussion of implications of sociobiology, and biology
us to recognize that we are only one person among more generally, for understanding of altruism.
others, and that this recognition must be reflected in Monroe, Kristen Renwick. The Heart of Altruism: Percep-
‘agent-neutral’ reasons for action. It is not entirely tion of a Common Humanity. Princeton: Princeton
clear whether this view rationally requires altruism, University Press, 1996. General theory of altruism and
or only declares it (contrary to some versions of eth- critique of self-interest models of behavior based on
study of Holocaust rescuers.
ical EGOISM) rationally intelligible. This ambiguity in
Nagel, Thomas. The Possibility of Altruism. Oxford: Clar-
turn yields an ambiguity in the view’s implications
endon Press, 1970. Argues that altruism is rational.
for the moral status—and more generally the moral
Oliner, Samuel P., and Pearl M. Oliner. The Altruistic Per-
value—of altruism. sonality: Rescuers of Jews in Nazi Europe. New York:
In either case, little attention has been given to The Free Press, 1988. Important empirical-theoretical
the connection between this rational altruism and study of altruism, especially in extreme situations.
altruism as a psychological phenomenon. For ex- Scheler, Max. The Nature of Sympathy. Translated by Pe-
ample, does rational altruism supply its own moti- ter Heath. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1954
vational force, and how motivationally efficacious is [1913]. Important discussion of relation of altruism to
self-worth and self-negation.
that force? Nor has rational altruism been placed
Schopenhauer, Arthur. On the Basis of Morality. Trans-
within the wider context of value within which al-
lated by E. F. J. Payne. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill,
truism as a whole must be evaluated. 1965 [1842]. Argues that altruism in the form of com-
passion is the basis of morality.
See also: AUTONOMY OF MORAL AGENTS; BENEVO-
Thomas, Lawrence. Living Morally: A Psychology of
LENCE; BIOETHICS; BIOLOGICAL THEORY; BUTLER; Moral Character. Philadelphia: Temple University
CARE; CHARITY; COOPERATION, CONFLICT AND CO- Press, 1989. A theory of moral character built around
ORDINATION; EGOISM; EVOLUTION; FAMILY; FRIEND- altruism—its biological substratum, what it sustains

53
altruism

intrapersonally and socially, and how it is bound up and on individuals who can attain fulfillment only in
with individual flourishing. community. They stressed the significance of dem-
Williams, Bernard. “Egoism and Altruism.” In his Prob- ocratic processes, affirmed the possibility of moral
lems of the Self. Cambridge: Cambridge University
progress, and celebrated the multiplicity of values
Press, 1973.
that coexist in a pluralist society.
Lawrence Blum William James’s “The Moral Philosopher and the
Moral Life” (1891) is a classical statement of plu-
ralist DEMOCRACY in the world of moral values. He
insists that nothing can be good without some con-
American moral philosophy scious being demanding or desiring it. All such de-
National designations can function only as short- mands are legitimate, all must be considered, and all
hand for characteristics that are pervasive but nei- impose obligations on everyone who can help. In the
ther universal nor unique. We may speak of German final analysis, of course, some claims may have to
idealism and French positivism so long as we re- remain unmet, but only because they get in the way
member that there are German positivists and of attaining greater satisfactions.
French idealists, and that Germans who lose their James adopted from C. S. PEIRCE (1839–1914)
idealism do not forfeit their national identity. the idea of an open future that invites experimen-
This is the only sensible spirit in which we can tation. He laments “a certain blindness” in human
discuss American moral philosophy. For every major beings that prevents them from appreciating the
position in ethics is well represented in American commitments and enjoyments of others. He believes
thought, and none can be dignified as uniquely ex- that we cannot determine what is truly good “until
pressive of the American psyche. Yet certain themes the last man has had his say.” In the meantime, how-
and approaches appear prevalent in the works of ever, we can improve life by channeling human ag-
major thinkers, and we find surprising similarities in gressive energies into “moral equivalents” to war.
ethics among philosophers whose positions in other The 1910 essay introducing this idea served as an
fields lead us to expect differences. inspiration for founding the Peace Corps (estab-
A general characterization of American moral lished 1961). James’s is a morality of caring whose
philosophy is most easily developed by considering aim is to contribute to the maximization of valuable
the views of such major thinkers of the classical pe- experiences.
riod as William JAMES (1842–1910), John DEWEY Josiah ROYCE (1855–1916), though an idealist,
(1859–1952), and George SANTAYANA (1863– is no less experimental and empirical in ethics than
1952). When Ralph Waldo EMERSON (1803–1882) his Harvard colleague James. His eloquent book,
called on American scholars to develop and cele- The Philosophy of Loyalty, depicts individuals as ca-
brate “an original relation” to the world, he set ex- pable of achieving fulfillment only by wholehearted
perience as the standard of philosophical thought devotion to their chosen causes. The cause must
and gave voice to the significance of immediacy. reach beyond the individual and encompass the
He and such other powerful representatives of the community, but it always remains a matter of revok-
American spirit as Walt Whitman desired to over- able choice open to improvement through consci-
come what they believed were the artificial dichot- entious experimentation.
omies of their European forebears. They refused to Loyalty to LOYALTY, Royce thinks, is the highest
acknowledge an ultimate difference between the in- principle of morality and captures the truth of both
terests of individuals and those of their communi- the GOLDEN RULE and KANT’s (1724–1804) cate-
ties. They rejected a sharp distinction between hu- gorical imperative. It amounts to the tolerant and
mans and the natural world. They embraced a view democratic value of choosing only those causes that
of human nature that depicted mind, will, emotions, enable others to pursue their own. Royce did not
and spirit as continuous with the body. draw a sharp line between the consequentialist bene-
These articles of faith made a profound impres- fits that flow from energetic pursuit of worthy goals
sion on the great philosophers who flourished be- and the soul-making value of persons attaining vir-
tween 1880 and 1950. Their moral views focused tue through resolve and sacrifice.
on the good as it is derived from DESIRE and need, A disagreement between James and Royce sheds

54
American moral philosophy

interesting light on a certain ambivalence in the This union of the “instrumental” and the “con-
American psyche. An unfailing advocate of the Prot- summatory” constitutes moments of human control
estant ethic, Royce believes that we can never do and satisfaction that make existence glow. Dewey’s
enough to meet our obligations. “Woe unto them ultimate ideal of growth must be understood as the
that are at ease in Zion,” he thunders, calling for the concurrent expansion of means and ends by which
greatest exertions in pursuit of the right and the human satisfactions become more widely shared,
good. more diversified, and more secure.
James, by contrast, argues for the legitimacy of Although Dewey’s position appears similar to
“moral holidays,” suggesting that we must allow UTILITARIANISM, he is anxious to distance himself
ourselves the luxury of taking care of our own affairs from that view. He argues that the utilitarian tradi-
or of occasionally enjoying a break from doing good. tion is burdened with a monistic conception of the
Though by no means self-indulgent, James’s attitude good, a simplistic idea of motivation, and too sharp
affirms the virtue of respite from the cares of the a distinction between means and ends. He main-
world. But, revealingly, even James believes that tains, instead, that the good is constructed in the
such moral holidays must support our “strenuous process of converting the satisfying into the
mood.” They ought not to be more than breaks in satisfactory.
the necessary activities of helping others and devel- Satisfaction is a mere fact of nature. It becomes
oping ourselves. normative when we direct human effort to sustain-
Santayana and Dewey present a similarly inter- ing it and find that it continues to satisfy over time
esting contrast. Both view the good as connected to in a broad social context of experience. The future,
the natures of those who seek it, but Santayana the community, and the critical balancing of values
thinks that such natures can be understood by ref- become, in this way, inseparably involved in the
erence to individuals alone. So the good is whatever good life of any individual. DESIRE, intelligent effort,
truly satisfies the cravings of the private soul, leaving control over consequences, and sustained fulfillment
the social maximization of satisfactions as an op- are thus the socially conditioned elements that,
tional community goal. His stress on the insular in- properly related, constitute the good.
dividual brings Santayana close to being an Ameri- Though lacking elaborate technical details,
can existentialist, though his appreciation of a Dewey’s moral thought presents a fully worked out
disinterested spectatorial stance points to a connec- naturalistic ethics. He has little sympathy for
tion with SCHOPENHAUER’s (1788–1860) aesthetic RIGHTS, but his commitment to democratic EQUAL-
transcendence and to Stoic thought. ITY makes him take the demands of justice seriously.
For Dewey, by contrast, individuals cannot be un- His view is a celebration of social intelligence and
derstood apart from their social context. Borrowing cooperation as they lead to the gradual improvement
from Aristotle, he maintains that morality must be of human life. Although critical of the dehumanizing
built on a platform of habits that render life in a aspects of industrial life, Dewey is in full agreement
community rich and satisfying. The only reliable with the energetic optimism of the American spirit.
means of constructing such habits is education de- He thinks our efforts can move us in the direction
signed to enhance intelligence. The function of in- of what Santayana calls “a life of reason” by estab-
telligence is to assess the conditions and conse- lishing salutary habits, harmonizing desires, and in-
quences of our actions, so that we may attain our creasing the satisfactions of as many persons as
ends more effectively or reconstruct our desires to possible.
accord with what is possible. American moral philosophy has too many varie-
Both means and ends are, therefore, open to ra- ties to be reduced to a single type. Yet Dewey’s
tional examination. We assess means by reference to thought comes near to serving as its paradigm. R. B.
their tendency to conduct us to our ends, and ends PERRY’s (1876–1957) general theory of value, C. I.
in relation to other objectives whose attainment they LEWIS’ (1883–1964) work in ethics, and many cur-
advance or impede. Resisting an absolute distinction rent versions of American naturalism reflect
between means and ends, Dewey calls attention to Dewey’s influence or display striking similarities to
those remarkable times in life when every experience his views. Even John RAWLS shares his love of LIB-
is both useful and delightful. ERTY and concern for the disadvantaged, though

55
American moral philosophy

Dewey would have profound misgivings about the ———. Values and Imperatives. Edited by John Lange.
individualistic foundations of Rawls’s system and Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1969.
about the role rights and intuitions play in his McDermott, John. The Culture of Experience. New York:
New York University Press, 1976.
thought.
———. Streams of Experience. Amherst, MA: University
Much that goes by the name of “neo-pragma- of Massachusetts Press, 1986.
tism,” however, appears to have lost contact with the McGee, Glenn. Pragmatic Bioethics. Nashville, TN: Van-
vital impulse to improve the human condition. Rich- derbilt University Press, 1999.
ard Rorty’s solidarity is anemic by comparison with Perry, Ralph B. General Theory of Value. New York: Long-
James’s stress on enriching life and Dewey’s efforts mans Green, 1926.
at public critique and reform. The true heirs of the Royce, Josiah. The Philosophy of Loyalty. Nashville, TN:
American tradition of moral philosophy are think- Vanderbilt University Press, 1997.
ers, such as John McDermott, who continue to ex- ———. The World and the Individual. Gloucester: Peter
Smith, 1976.
plore the crisis points of life in industrial society and
Santayana, George. Reason in Common Sense. New York:
philosophers who bring the insights of PRAGMATISM
Dover, 1980.
to bear on environmental problems and difficult is- ———. Winds of Doctrine. New York: C. Scribner’s Sons,
sues in health care. 1926.
See also: ADLER; BRANDT; DEWEY; DWORKIN; ED- John Lachs
WARDS; EMERSON; FRANKENA; FULLER; GERT; GE-
WIRTH; JAMES; JEFFERSON; KING; LEOPOLD; LEWIS;
MACINTYRE; MEAD; MURPHY; NOZICK; PAINE; amnesty and pardon
PEIRCE; PERRY; RAND; RAWLS; ROYCE; SANTAYANA;
Amnesty and pardon are official acts of clemency
SINGER; STEVENSON; TAYLOR; THOMSON; THO-
that exempt a person from some or all of the punitive
REAU; TUFTS; WALZER. Also see: BIOETHICS; COM-
consequences of a criminal conviction. Granting
MUNITARIANISM; DEMOCRACY; ENVIRONMENTAL
amnesty or pardon ensures that the person to whom
ETHICS; EQUALITY; EXISTENTIAL ETHICS; GOLDEN
it is given will not suffer all the PUNISHMENT the law
RULE; INDIVIDUALISM; INTUITIONISM; LIBERTY; LOY-
inflicts for the crime charged.
ALTY; MORAL PLURALISM; MULTICULTURALISM; NAT-
Although the distinction between amnesty and
URALISM; NEO-STOICISM; PRAGMATISM.
pardon can be difficult to draw in practice, amnesty
has been defined as an act of oblivion, by which an
offender is granted immunity to prosecution. Usu-
Bibliography
ally granted before a trial takes place and often be-
Dewey, John. The Middle Works of John Dewey. See De- fore offenders have been charged with specific
mocracy and Education, vol. 8, and Human Nature crimes, amnesties are usually granted to groups of
and Conduct, vol. 14. Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois
people, often unnamed members of a class defined
University Press, 1976.
by a particular, often political, offense. However,
———. The Later Works of John Dewey. See Experience
and Nature, vol. 1, and The Quest for Certainty, vol.
amnesty can also be granted to individuals, usually
4. Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University Press, as a step toward reconciliation after a war or politi-
1988. cal upheaval.
Emerson, Ralph Waldo. “The American Scholar.” In his Like amnesty, the pardon can take many forms.
Essays, First and Second Series. Franklin Center, PA: Pardons can be full or partial, absolute or condi-
Franklin Library, 1981 [1837]. tional. They can be individual or general—a fact that
Gouinlock, James. Rediscovering the Moral Life. Buffalo, complicates the distinction between amnesty and
NY: Prometheus Books, 1993. pardon. Although there are famous exceptions, in
James, William. “The Moral Philosopher and the Moral typical cases in the United States the pardon is
Life,” “On a Certain Blindness in Human Beings,” and
granted only after an offender has been convicted
“The Moral Equivalent of War.” In The Writings of Wil-
liam James, edited by John J. McDermott. Chicago: and sentenced, in which case it prevents further pun-
University of Chicago Press, 1977 [1891; 1899; 1910]. ishment; most often, the pardon is granted only after
Lewis, C. I. The Ground and Nature of the Right. New the offender has completed the sentence and a sub-
York: Columbia University Press, 1955. sequent waiting period, when a pardon helps the of-

56
amnesty and pardon

fender regain civil rights lost as a consequence of a


Amnesty and Pardon in Western History
criminal conviction.
The history of amnesty and pardon is as old as
the history of punishment. In Genesis, God granted
what amounts to a conditional pardon to Cain, the
The Exercise of Clemency Powers
world’s first murderer, banishing him to the Land of
Amnesty and pardon are common to all cultures Nod. Ancient Athens granted pardons on the vote
and all periods of history. With the exception of of 6,000 citizens, and the Romans had a detailed and
China, all nations claim a pardoning power of some sophisticated system of pardoning. The practice of
sort. Under Article II, Section 2 of the United States decimation, for example, was a form of clemency:
Constitution, the president has the “Power to grant rather than execute an entire army after a mutiny,
Reprieves and Pardons for offenses against the the commander would order his men to count off,
United States, except in cases of impeachment.” For pardoning the first nine and killing each tenth sol-
violations of state law—the bulk of all offenses, in- dier. Probably the most famous Roman pardon was
cluding murder—the power to pardon rests with the granted by Pontius Pilate who, following Passover
governor or an executive pardoning board. In most custom, released a murderer named Barabbas rather
nations, pardon and amnesty powers are not subject than the prisoner named Jesus.
to legal restriction or review. From the end of the Roman Empire to the En-
The exercise of clemency powers has historically lightenment, rival authorities struggled for the
been justified by considerations of public interest, power to pardon, a power correctly recognized as at
justice, and MERCY. The authors of the U.S. Consti- least as great as the power to punish. The right to
tution, for example, recognized that the public in- pardon was claimed by everyone who claimed a right
terest is sometimes better served by forgoing pun- to punish—earls, kings, archbishops, clan chiefs,
ishment than by exacting the full measure of priests, mobs, legislatures, and courts. In the harsh
punishment allowed by law. Alexander Hamilton penal systems of the time, there was good reason for
(1755–1804) wrote, “In seasons of insurrection or the liberal use of the pardon power; but many par-
rebellion, there are often critical moments when a dons were granted instead for military, political, per-
well-timed offer of pardon . . . may restore the tran- sonal, and financial reasons. Selling pardons (or in-
quility of the commonwealth,” a tranquility that dulgences, in the case of the church) became a
President Gerald Ford also cited in defending his dependable source of income for church and state.
pardon (1974) of Richard Nixon (1913–1994). Frequent use and abuse of the pardoning power
In addition to advancing the public interest, clem- met harsh criticism: Since all government was pre-
ency powers can be justified by considerations of sumed to come from God, all crimes were crimes
justice. A pardon may correct an injustice done by against God. God can forgive offenses against Him-
the courts, as when evidence indicates that a con- self, critics argued, but civil governments should not
victed person is innocent or, while not legally inno- usurp the divine prerogative. Eighteenth-century at-
cent, morally blameless or morally justified. Legal tacks on the abuses of the great monarchies brought
systems make mistakes, and the clemency powers a parallel argument: In a DEMOCRACY, a crime
offer a last chance to ensure that only those who against the state is a crime against the people, and
deserve punishment are punished and only so much only the people have a right to forgive offenses
as they deserve. against them. English jurist Sir William Blackstone
Pardon and amnesty also serve to soften the (1723–1780) declared that in democracies, “this
harshness of the law. “The criminal code of every power of pardon can never subsist,” and the par-
country partakes so much of necessary severity that doning power was swept away by the French Rev-
without an easy access to exceptions in favor of un- olution in 1789.
fortunate guilt, justice would wear a countenance In 1795, Immanuel KANT (1724–1804) pub-
too sanguinary and cruel,” Hamilton wrote. FOR- lished, in The Metaphysical Elements of Justice, a
GIVENESS is, after all, a virtue, and the pardoning powerful polemic against pardon. “The law concern-
power is a way to respond to pain with a simple act ing punishment is a categorical imperative, and woe
of kindness. to him who rummages around in the winding paths

57
amnesty and pardon

of a theory of happiness looking for some advantage are gifts that are undeserved, unfathomable, and not
to be gained by releasing the criminal from punish- subject to examination or critique. They are rooted
ment or reducing the amount of it.” People who dis- in the virtues of BENEVOLENCE and a forgiving spirit.
obey the law do the other members of the commu- However, philosophers and jurists alike point out
nity a comparative injustice by exercising freedoms that mercy without good reason is a kind of immor-
they are not willing to grant to others, Kant argued. ality. In any given case, if a court has mandated a
Punishment limits the freedom of the offender and, sentence that is, in fact, just, then exacting less than
by that means, removes the injustice of the act. the deserved sentence works a retributive injustice,
Nothing less than like for like will restore EQUALITY. since the offender does not receive the punishment
If a state is to act justly, it has not only the right, but deserved; and it works an additional comparative
the duty, to punish. injustice, since the reduced punishment will be less
Jeremy BENTHAM (1748–1832), the utilitarian re- than that imposed on other, similar offenders. It
former, also argued against the unrestrained use of would seem that the merciful act of granting relief
pardons, but on very different grounds. Following from a just sentence is virtuous and unjust at the
the Principle of Utility, he argued, punishment same time. As the twentieth century draws to a
should be imposed when it bestows some benefit close, the paradox plays out on an international
that outweighs its harm. In Bentham’s view, the stage, as nations attempting to use amnesty and par-
overriding benefit of punishment is deterrence, and dons as means of national reconciliation find that the
a penal system that hopes to deter crimes cannot competing claims of mercy and justice make clem-
tolerate exceptions. So mercy is seldom beneficial on ency decisions painful and complex.
balance, and punishment should always be imposed,
See also: BENEVOLENCE; CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE; COR-
unless it is “inefficacious . . . , groundless . . . , need-
RECTIONAL ETHICS; DETERRENCE, THREATS AND RE-
less . . . or too expensive”—the limited circum-
TALIATION; EQUALITY;
FAIRNESS; FORGIVENESS;
stances that call for clemency.
GUILT AND SHAME;HART; INNOCENCE; JUSTICE, CIR-
CUMSTANCES OF; JUSTICE, RECTIFICATORY; LEGAL
Contemporary Debates about PHILOSOPHY; MERCY; OBEDIENCE TO LAW; POLICE
Amnesty and Pardon ETHICS; PUNISHMENT; REVOLUTION; SYMPATHY;
UTILITARIANISM.
Debates about pardon and amnesty faded from
philosophical discussions during much of the nine-
teenth and twentieth centuries, and pardons them- Bibliography
selves gradually became less and less common in the
Barnett, J. “The Grounds of Pardon.” Journal of Criminal
United States, to be replaced to some extent first by Law, Criminology, and Political Science 17 (1926):
the indeterminate sentence and then by a rigid get- 490–530. A thorough discussion of the grounds on
tough-on-crime stance. But in the later half of the which pardons may properly be granted.
twentieth century, the unpopular pardon of Richard Bentham, Jeremy. The Principles of Morals and Legisla-
Nixon, controversial amnesties granted to Vietnam tion. Darien, CT: Hafner, 1948 [1780]. See especially
War draft evaders, and the process of truth and rec- pages 171–77. A utilitarian justification for pardon un-
der specified conditions.
onciliation taking place following radical changes of
Card, Claudia. “On Mercy.” Philosophical Review 81
government in South Africa, Latin America, and (1972): 182–207. A careful argument about the rela-
elsewhere have reopened discussion of amnesty and tion between justice and mercy.
pardons and revealed just how morally complicated “Clemency and Pardons Symposium.” University of Rich-
clemency is. mond Law Review 27 (1993). A symposium on clem-
The pardoning power in the United States is a ency which includes articles by Anaya, Bedau, Kobil,
direct descendent of English pardoning practices, Ledewitz and Staples, MacFarlane, Moore, Radelet
and Zsembik, and Vandiver.
which were reputedly patterned after God’s. Ac-
Humbert, W. H. The Pardoning Power of the President.
cordingly, pardons have long been thought of as acts
Washington, DC: The American Council on Public Af-
of mercy akin to divine grace, a view affirmed by the fairs, 1941. A fascinating compilation of information
Supreme Court in United States v. Wilson (1833). about the pardons presidents have granted and the rea-
This view makes pardons supererogatory; pardons sons they have given.

58
analogical argument

Kalt, Brian C. “Pardon Me?: The Constitutional Case between the observed structure of things like spiral
against Presidential Self-Pardons.” The Yale Law Jour- staircases and the unobserved structure of DNA, the
nal 106 (1996): 779–809. An argument that presi-
dents cannot pardon themselves.
fundamental genetic material; and how inferences
Kant, Immanuel. The Metaphysical Elements of Justice. were made based on such analogies. This article will
New York: Bobbs-Merrill, 1965 [1797]. See especially focus on analogical thinking in law and morality, but
page 100. Kant’s famous argument against the abuse models developed in one area of employment should
of the pardoning power. fit others as well.
Kobil, Daniel T. “The Quality of Mercy Strained: Wresting A characteristic feature of our legal system is its
the Pardoning Power from the King.” Texas Law Re- dependence on PRECEDENT. The requirement of pre-
view 64 (1991): 569–641. A consideration of the
proper rules of clemency in the American justice
cedent calls for deciding similar cases similarly.
system. Much legal reasoning, especially in appellate courts,
Moore, Kathleen Dean. Pardons: Justice, Mercy, and the is devoted to showing that the case in question is (or
Public Interest. New York: Oxford University Press, is not) analogous to some earlier case which was
1989. A history and analysis of the moral justification decided in a favorable way. An excellent case of
for pardoning. analogical reasoning in both law and morality is
Murphy, Jeffrie. “Mercy and Legal Justice.” Social Philos- Kenneth F. Schaffner’s “Philosophical, Ethical, and
ophy and Policy 4 (1986): 1–14. An attempt to address
the paradox of mercy, i.e., to be merciful is, perhaps,
Legal Aspects of Resuscitation Medicine. II: Rec-
to be unjust. ognizing the Tragic Choice: Food, Water, and the
Roberts, H. R. T. “Mercy.” Philosophy 66 (1971): 352– Right to Assisted Suicide.”
53. A paper that proposes that merciful acts are either In “Tragic Choice,” a paper on physician-assisted
unjust or they are a kind of justice. SUICIDE, Schaffner reviews the moral foundations of
Sebba, L. “The Pardoning Power: A World Survey.” Jour- decisions to suspend life-sustaining medically sup-
nal of Criminal Law 78 (1977): 83–121. A survey of
plied nutrition and hydration for seriously ill and
pardoning practices around the world.
permanently comatose patients. He also examines
Smart, Alwynne. “Mercy.” Philosophy 43 (1968): 345–
59. The first essay in the contemporary debate about three crucial legal cases in this area: Barber, Bouvie,
when pardon can be justified. and Brophy. As a philosopher of science, Schaffner
U.S. Presidential Clemency Board. Report to the Presi- is interested in causation, and he finds that the cause
dent. Washington, DC: GPO, 1975. A history of the of such patients’ deaths, according to the consensus
Anglo-American heritage of amnesty and pardon. at the time (1988), is the underlying illness. He criti-
cizes that view, and argues that the “responsible
Legal Cases cause” in such cases is typically the physician’s de-
Biddle v. Perovich, 274 U.S. 480 (1926). Oliver Wendell cision to suspend medical nutrition and hydration,
Holmes’s opinion, defending the view that a pardon is a decision made with the deliberate authorization of
not an act of grace, but a tool for the public good. the patients, families, and sometimes the courts. The
United States v. Wilson, 32 U.S. (7 Pet.) 150 (1833). most challenging analogical argument in his paper
Chief Justice John Marshall’s opinion that a pardon is
is that, with proper safeguards, this is both a morally
an act of grace.
justifiable policy and one that ought to be inter-
Kathleen Dean Moore preted as “a general surrogate” for rational, medi-
cally assisted suicide. This essay is already a central
part of the literature of BIOETHICS on the issue, and
analogical argument it should become a standard case for reflection on
Analogical thinking is perhaps the most basic and analogical thinking. It will be so used here, as far as
common rational process. It is so frequently em- constraints allow.
ployed in everyday thought that we scarcely notice Another good case for analysis of analogical rea-
it, until something goes wrong. We routinely use and soning is found in “Genetic Encores: The Ethics of
encounter it in law and morality as well as in science. Human Cloning” by Robert Wachbroit. Molecular
Perhaps the best-known case of analogical thinking biologists took over from botanists the term
in science is the discovery of the structure of DNA, “clone”—which meant, as a noun, the multiple iden-
as told by James D. Watson in The Double Helix tical descendants of a single cell—to describe a cul-
(1968). It is the story of how analogies were drawn ture of bacteria grown up to multiply transplanted

59
analogical argument

genes. They speak of making copies of a gene in or- enhancement through genetic surgery). If there were
der to have enough to study. The term is also used a moral consensus in favor of the use of reproductive
as a verb to refer to the process of copying genes, technologies but against the use of genetic engineer-
cells, or now biological individuals. Dr. Ian Wilmut, ing, the result of seeing cloning as analogous with
a Scottish scientist, reported the successful cloning one rather than the other is obvious. However,
in 1997 of an adult sheep from its somatic (rather which analogy we should draw, and how we can jus-
than germ) cells. Since then clones of adult cows tify inferences from it, are not so obvious. That is
(several calves) have been born, produced by a tech- the focus of the rest of this article.
nique similar to that used to produce Dolly, the We draw analogies and make inferences based on
sheep. Many articles in the scientific as well as pop- them in law, morality, science, and everyday life.
ular media are claiming that the cloning of humans Most of us do these things very well. That is not to
is now not only technologically possible but practi- say, however, that we understand how we do it or
cally inevitable. The question of its ethics is open for know explicitly the criteria we use to judge whether
discussion, and Wachbroit does a good job of ori- it has been done well or not. According to a stock
enting the discussion. example of this sort of thing, it is fairly easy to ride
First of all, there is room for serious misconcep- a bicycle, but rather difficult to describe how it is
tions in using the term “human cloning.” The pro- done. So it is with analogical inference. There is both
cess (cloning) is a kind of “copying”; but the product a problem of description and a problem of justifi-
(the clone) is from the somatic cells of an adult and cation concerning this common practice. Setting
is not initially an adult human being: it is an embryo, aside for this article questions concerning the draw-
fetus, infant, and so on. If it grows into a human ing of analogies, how should we describe our prac-
adult, its growth takes the same length of time as tice of making analogical inferences? What are the
normal human development (unlike what happened conditions under which they are reliable?
in the 1996 film Multiplicity, in which several iden- First, let us try to solve the problem of describing
tical grown men were produced almost at the same analogical inferences. Their content is a clue: they
time). are all based on analogies. One entity, A, is known
Wachbroit does a good job of clarifying the con- to have attributes a, b, c, and d. Another entity, B,
cepts as well as the facts of cloning. If adult humans is known to have attributes a, b, and c, but it is not
are cloned, the genetic material of the donor and known whether it also has attribute d. On the basis
resulting individual will be identical. They will have of the known similarity or analogy, it is inferred that
the same genome. Will the new individual be a “car- B also probably has attribute d. Entities A and B, in
bon copy” (perhaps we need to recognize another this abstract and idealized model of analogical in-
technological change and begin to call it a “photo ference, might be forgoing medically supplied nutri-
copy”) of the earlier individual? Only if we accept tion and hydration on the one hand, and medically
genetic determinism, and there is an overwhelming assisted rational suicide, on the other, as in the
scientific consensus that such a theory is false. The Schaffner article cited above; and attribute d then
clone will be an exact copy of the cloned only to the would be recognizing a moral and legal right to both.
extent that identical twins are. They have the same Likewise, the model fits the Wachbroit case of ar-
DNA but become distinct individuals. Here we en- guments about cloning humans and the birth of
counter a key analogy in this discussion. Is the clone identical twins. The moral LEGITIMACY of the former
an “offspring” or a “sibling” of the adult from whom based on acceptance of the latter is attributed.
it was cloned? Does it have one biological parent Arguing by analogy may be based on a compari-
(the adult from which it was cloned), or two (the son of attributes of more than two entities, so a vari-
same two as the donor of its DNA)? Much of the ation on the above model would be:
moral debate turns on inferences made from the
analogies given in answer to these questions. A Entities A, B, C, and D all have attributes a,
closely related set of analogies tries to identify clon- b, and c.
ing with either REPRODUCTIVE TECHNOLOGIES (such Entities A, B, and C also have attribute d.
as in vitro fertilization or artificial insemination) or Therefore, entity D probably has attribute d
GENETIC ENGINEERING technologies (such as genetic as well.

60
analogical argument

In recent arguments about cloning humans, the In Book II, Chapter 24, of Prior Analytics, Aris-
technology for cloning is sometimes said to be anal- totle discusses argument by “example” in a way
ogous to either reproduction technologies (artificial which connects more directly with our arguments by
insemination, semen donation, ova donation, in analogy than with what is today often called “induc-
vitro fertilization, etc.) or genetic engineering tech- tive generalization,” or argument based on a sample.
nologies (genetic surgery, control of gene expression His case has to do with “making war against neigh-
by the use of anti-sense nucleic acids, and other ge- bors.” If we wish to argue that war by Athenians
netic therapies). The various technologies are against Thebans is an evil, we use the analogy with
known to be alike in several aspects, and claimed to war by Thebans against Phoenicians. It was a war
be alike in crucial moral respects, such as being mor- between neighbors, and an evil. War between Athe-
ally permissible. nians and Thebans is also a war between neighbors,
A slight modification of this model results in a and probably evil as well. Aristotle’s remark,
statistical one. “Clearly then an example stands neither as part to
whole, nor as whole to part, but rather as part to
N percent of type I entities having attributes part, when both are subordinate to the same term,
a, b, and c also have attribute d. and one of them is familiar,” is in need of extensive
A is a Type I entity having attributes a, b, interpretation. Aristotle seems to characterize ar-
and c. gument by example or analogy as a mixture of in-
Therefore, the probability is N percent that A duction (war A was between neighbors, and was an
has attribute d as well. evil; therefore all wars between neighbors are prob-
ably evils) and deduction (all wars between neigh-
Analogical arguments of each of these three bors are probably evils, and this war is between
forms are common. The content is the same gener- neighbors; therefore it is probably an evil).
ally, in each form: an analogy is the basis of the in- Peirce’s model of analogical argument is also a
ference. The difference is between an inference mixture of deduction and induction. His general for-
based on similarities known to hold between two mula for analogy is
entities or between more than two. Does basing the
inference on more than two instances increase its t is P⬘, P⬙, and P⵮
reliability? It might seem to, in view of common S⬘, S⬙, and S⵮ are q;
sense and logical theory concerning inductive or Therefore t is q. (1932, 2.512)
nondeductive inferences. Analogical arguments are
not purely deductive. The premises are not said to We might interpret this form, according to Schaff-
support the conclusion in such a way that it is im- ner’s argument, to the moral permissibility of med-
possible for the premises to be true and the conclu- ically assisted suicide as
sion to be false. When this deductive feature of an
argument form is absent, let us call that sort of ar- t ⳱ medically assisted suicide
gument nondeductive. Surely, the premises of an an- S⬘ ⳱ Barber
alogical argument could all be true and yet the con- S⬙ ⳱ Bouvie
clusion could be false. S⵮ ⳱ Brophy
An interesting question concerning the form of P⬘ ⳱ deaths due to removal of life support in
analogical arguments, raised by ARISTOTLE (384– S⬘
322 B.C.E.) and C. S. PEIRCE (1839–1914), as well P⬙ ⳱ deaths due to removal of life support in
as by such recent logicians as David Kelley and Pat- S⬙
rick Hurley, asks whether they are purely nonde- P⵮ ⳱ deaths due to removal of life support
ductive. Kelley joins Aristotle and Peirce in consid- in S⵮
ering them to be a mixed form, while Hurley sees q ⳱ legally and morally acceptable or
them as purely nondeductive. In this brief article we permissible.
cannot consider the details on which their decisions
are based to a great extent, but we can grasp the Peirce says that such an argument is “double,” as it
issue. contains both of these arguments:

61
analogical argument

(1) between S and P? Of course, it involves analogy, but


S⬘, S⬙, S⵮ are taken as being P⬘, P⬙, P⵮, more needs to be said in order to see why such rea-
S⬘, S⬙, S⵮ are q; soning is reliable and under what conditions. The
Therefore (inductively) P⬘, P⬙, P⵮ is q. premises in an analogical argument assert that some
t is P⬘, P⬙, P⵮; similarity exists between the data objects and the
Therefore (deductively) t is q. inference object, but why should similarity in one
respect give us reason to infer similarity in another?
(2) After all, everything is similar to everything in some
S⬘, S⬙, S⵮ are, for instance, P⬘, P⬙, P⵮, respect. Kelley’s insight, in the tradition of Aristotle
t is P⬘, P⬙, P⵮; and Peirce, is that the connection between the ob-
Therefore (by hypothesis) t has the common served similarity and the inferred similarity should
characteristics of S⬘, S⬙, S⵮, be made explicit. He does this by modeling it as rest-
S⬘, S⬙, S⵮ are q; ing on an implicit generalization. Perhaps this re-
Therefore (deductively) t is q. construction of one argument for human cloning ex-
presses the point:
He further comments that “Owning to its double
character, analogy is very strong with only a mod- IVF (in vitro fertilization) is a reproductive
erate number of instances.” technology.
This mixed model is opposed by most recent lo- IVF is morally acceptable.
gicians, represented by Hurley. He considers analog- Therefore all reproductive technologies are
ical reasoning to depend on a comparison of in- morally acceptable.
stances, as in my first version of the model of Cloning humans is a reproductive technology.
analogical arguments given above, and further con- Therefore cloning humans is morally
siders them as closely related to generalizations. He acceptable.
reverses the way Aristotle and Peirce represent these
two forms of argument. In generalization, Hurley The first step, Kelley says, is inductive: a gener-
thinks the arguer begins with one or more instances alization. The second is deductive, a categorical syl-
and then draws a conclusion about all of the mem- logism. Any argument by analogy can, he claims, be
bers of a class. He may then apply the generalization described in this way, once we have identified the
to one or more members of this class that were not common property (S) which makes A and B similar.
noted earlier. Thus there is an initial inductive stage, Thus his model is:
and a second deductive one. In contrast, he thinks
that in a argument from analogy, the arguer moves A is S Ⳮ A is/is not P
directly from one or more individual instances to a f
conclusion about another individual instance with- All/no S is P (inductive generalization)
out appealing to an intermediate generalization. B is S
Thus, analogical argument is purely inductive, or B is/is not P (categorical syllogism)
nondeductive.
Among contemporary logicians, Kelley seems to To describe the practice this way makes the criti-
be the lone continuer of the Aristotle-Peirce tradi- cal analysis of such an argument mainly a matter of
tion. His provisional description of analogical infer- finding the common property S which functions as
ence is similar to Hurley’s: a middle term in the deductive step. To evaluate the
argument, the main task is to evaluate the inductive
A and B have property S. step. The deductive step will always be valid.
A has property P. As it turns out, evaluation on Kelley’s model is
Therefore, B has property P. not very different from evaluation on Hurley’s. The
step Kelley calls inductive in his model seems to be
Interpret this according to the above arguments con- as suspect as the inference in Hurley’s model.
cerning medically assisted suicide or cloning hu- Let us turn to the problem of justifying analogical
mans. The question arises: What is the relationship inferences. Under what conditions are we justified

62
analogical argument

in relying on analogical arguments? There are two “data instances,” or “primary analogates” (Hurley).
basic conditions, which need to be further specified The greater the number of them, the higher the de-
to be useful in evaluating inferences. The degree of gree of analogy, roughly. There seem to be enough
analogy on which the inference is based must be suf- different technologies of this sort to make the degree
ficient, and the relevance of the analogy mentioned of analogy fairly high. They are also rather diverse
in the premises to the conclusion must also be suf- within the type. Some, like IVF, involve genetic ma-
ficient. Since the reliability of nondeductive argu- terial from both nurturing parents, while others, like
ments is a matter of degree, the criterion of suffi- sperm or ova donation, involve material from only
ciency cannot be quantified precisely. The measure one. Thus, number and diversity of data instances
will vary, depending on such pragmatic considera- are added conditions specifying number of similar-
tions as the seriousness of the consequences of re- ities, which specifies degree of analogy.
lying on the conclusion. The second main condition for reliable analogical
First, the degree of analogy must be high. Can we inferences is the relevance of the analogies men-
be more specific about the degree of analogy be- tioned in the premises to the one in the conclusion.
tween cloning humans and reproductive technolo- The similarities mentioned in the premises of some
gies such as in vitro fertilization? Yes. The number arguments for cloning humans include the purpose
of similarities is a specification of degree of analo- of providing a couple with a biological child which
gies. Both technologies can be seen as ways of pro- they would otherwise be unable to have. How is that
viding a couple with a biological child which they relevant to the conclusion that it is morally accept-
might otherwise be unable to have. That seems to able? The ends are the same, to be sure, but are the
be an important similarity, but alone it does not seem means? One could argue that they are properly de-
to be sufficient to support the inference to the moral scribed as being very different. IVF is more closely
acceptability of cloning humans. Are there other analogous to the more common fertilization of an
similarities? The child produced in each of these ovum by sperm as a result of a couple’s sexual in-
ways will become a unique individual, if genetic de- tercourse than cloning is, since cloning does not in-
terminism is rejected (as scientific consensus today volve sperm or ova at all, but uses somatic cells.
says it should be). The liabilities to harm seem to be Many people think that common ends do not nec-
about the same for children produced in these ways. essarily justify diverse means. Thus, the condition of
A case can be made for a high degree of analogy in relevance in this sort of argument is open for dis-
the sense of a large number of similarities between cussion. The same is true of the relevance of simi-
the two technologies. larities between cases of withdrawing medical nu-
A second specification involves the nature and trition and hydration, on the one hand, and cases of
number of dis-analogies. In vitro fertilization, when medically assisted suicide on the other, to a conclu-
sperm and ova come from the couple who will raise sion about the moral and legal acceptability of the
the child, is clearly a technology which produces an latter based on that of the former.
“offspring” with two parents. But a clone is the prod- This condition of relevance has been discussed so
uct of one of the couple, probably the female. The far in terms of the purely nondeductive model of
child is not clearly her “offspring,” but may better analogical arguments (Hurley). In terms of the
be considered her “sibling.” Cloning, in this per- mixed model (Kelley), it can be restated in terms of
spective, is a sort of “delayed twinning.” This seems the relevance of the connection between S and P. I
to weaken the analogy. However, the child produced leave this to the reader.
by cloning does have, arguably, two parents: the In this article we have considered the problems
same two as the woman from whom she was cloned. of describing and justifying our common practice of
The importance of this has to do with lineage iden- making inferences based on analogies. The inconclu-
tified responsibilities, as Wachbroit points out. The siveness of these considerations should show that—
analogy is strengthened again when we are told that contrary to claims that in logic things are “cut and
some assisted reproductive technologies raise simi- dried” (as is tobacco raising!)—there is much left to
lar questions about lineage and identity. be thought through about analogical argument.
The number of similarities can be further speci- See also: BIOETHICS; CASUISTRY; GENETIC ENGINEER-
fied. Call assisted reproductive technologies the ING; LEGAL PHILOSOPHY; LEGITIMACY; LITERATURE

63
analogical argument

AND ETHICS; LOGIC AND ETHICS; MEDICAL ETHICS; Wachbroit, Robert. “Genetic Encores: The Ethics of Hu-
MORAL REASONING; NARRATIVE ETHICS; PERSON,
man Cloning.” Report from the Institute for Philosophy
and Public Policy 17, no. 21 (Fall 1997): 1–7. An ar-
CONCEPT OF; PRECEDENT; RATIONAL CHOICE; REPRO-
ticle on cloning humans which makes clear many of the
DUCTIVE TECHNOLOGIES; UNIVERSALIZABILITY. analogies, and inferences based on them, involved in
this issue.

Bibliography Ted Klein


Aristotle. Prior Analytics. In The Complete Works of Ar-
istotle, edited by Jonathan Barnes, vol. l. Princeton:
Princeton University Press, 1984. A classic work in analytic philosophy and ethics
logic, which treats argument by “example” (analogy)
It has been claimed that SOCRATES (c. 470–399
as a mixture of deduction and induction.
B.C.E.) practiced analytic philosophy, and certainly
Churchill, Robert Paul. Logic: An Introduction. 2d ed.
New York: St. Martin’s, 1990. A widely used contem- he was interested in ethics; but for the purposes of
porary textbook, discussed in the Klein and Wertz ar- this article analytic philosophy in relationship to
ticle. Includes a good discussion of legal and moral ethics begins with G. E. MOORE’s (1873–1958)
reasoning. Principia Ethica (1903) and ends fifty-five years
Conway, David A., and Ronald Munson. The Elements of later with Kurt BAIER’s The Moral Point of View
Reasoning. 2d ed. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth, 1997. A (1958). It was only during this period that there was
recent elementary textbook, which offers two main
a distinctive approach to ethics that deserves to be
conditions for the reliability of analogical arguments:
degree and relevance of analogy. marked off and given special attention.
Hurley, Patrick J. A Concise Introduction to Logic. 6th ed. Although there is a direct line from JOHN STUART
Belmont, CA: Wadsworth, 1997. A widely used con- MILL (1806–1873) through Henry SIDGWICK
temporary textbook, which treats analogical argument (1838–1900) to G. E. Moore, Moore spent much
as purely nondeductive, but generalization as a mixture more time than did his predecessors explicitly ex-
of deduction and induction.
amining the meaning of the terms we use when mak-
Kelley, David. The Art of Reasoning. 2d, expanded ed.
ing moral judgments. Even more important, Moore
New York: W. W. Norton, 1994. A contemporary text-
book which differs from the majority in interesting was the catalyst for those who, unlike Moore him-
ways, including treating analogical argument as a mix- self, were primarily interested in the meaning of
ture of induction and deduction. MORAL TERMS rather than in substantive moral
Klein, Ted, and S. K. Wertz. “Legal Reasoning and Ana- questions.
logical Argument: Two Models.” Contemporary Philos- Although analytic philosophy has continued since
ophy 13, no. 5 (Sept./Oct. 1990): 3–6. An article dis- the publication of Baier’s book, there is no longer
cussing the conflict of interpretation of analogical
any clear movement in ethics which can labeled as
argument between Churchill and Kelley.
analytic. Analytic philosophers are now more likely
Peirce, Charles Sanders, Elements of Logic. In The Col-
lected Works of Charles Sanders Peirce, edited by to put forward substantive ethical views (e.g.,
Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss, vol. 2. Cambridge: Hobbesian, Kantian, or utilitarian) than they are to
Harvard University Press, 1960. The logical writings of view their analyses of ethical terms as having no nor-
the great American pragmatist, in which he gives a mative implications. The distinction between con-
model for analogical argument with both inductive and cern with analyzing the terms or concepts involved
deductive stages.
in moral discourse and concern with substantive
Salmon, Merrilee H. Introduction to Logic and Critical
Thinking. 3d ed. Fort Worth, TX: Harcourt Brace,
moral problems has largely disappeared. It is now
1995. A widely used textbook which offers a model of generally held that analysis of moral concepts will
induction and set of conditions of reliability similar to yield substantive moral conclusions, even by many
those in this article. of those who earlier thought that analyses of ethical
Schaffner, Kenneth F. “Philosophical, Ethical and Legal concepts had no normative implications whatsoever.
Aspects of Resuscitation Medicine. II: Recognizing the In the very first paragraph of Principia Ethica,
Tragic Choice: Food, Water and the Right to Assisted
Moore says, “In the vast majority of cases, where we
Suicide.” Critical Care Medicine 16, no. 10 (Oct.
1988): 1063–68. An article which uses analogical ar- make statements involving any of the terms ‘virtue,’
gument in law and morality on the issue of medically ‘vice,’ ‘duty,’ ‘right,’ ‘ought,’ ‘good,’ ‘bad,’ we are
assisted suicide. making ethical judgments; and if we wish to discuss

64
analytic philosophy and ethics

their truth, we shall be discussing a point of Ethics.” esting parallel.) Most agreed with Moore that
Although any reasonably close examination of news- “good” did not refer to any complex property as pro-
papers and magazines, or even reflection on what posed by the subjectivists, but all denied that it re-
we ourselves say, shows Moore to be completely ferred to some simple nonnatural property as pro-
mistaken about the majority of cases in which we posed by Moore. One result was that many denied
use these terms, the philosophers who criticized that “good” referred to anything, claiming that
Moore’s account of the meaning of these terms never “good” was not a referring word. This led to the rec-
challenged his claim that statements involving their ognition that language is not always used to describe
use are moral judgments. Moore and his critics seem the world, but it has many other uses (a fact that
to have forgotten that they themselves recom- HOBBES [1588–1679], sometimes regarded as a
mended, condemned, and praised music, novels, founder of analytic philosophy, had explicitly
wines, meals, athletes, or moves in games, and did pointed out three centuries earlier).
not use the terms “right,” “ought,” “good,” and The first account offered by those who rejected
“bad” only when making ethical judgments. the view that “good” refers came to be known as
Whatever the explanation, analytic philosophers “emotivism” or the emotive theory of ethics. There
in the first half of the twentieth century took ethics is some dispute as to who put this theory forward
to be the study of moral judgments, and they re- first: Some claim that it was Ogden and Richards in
garded as paradigm cases of moral judgments those The Meaning of Meaning (1923), but clearly the
which used the terms “good,” “bad,” “right,” most influential early statement of this view was pre-
“wrong,” and “ought.” Moore claimed that the sented by A. J. AYER (1910–1989) in his classic,
“question, how ‘good’ is to be defined is the most Language, Truth and Logic (1935). In the sixth
fundamental question in all Ethics.” And much of chapter of that book Ayer claimed, “in every case in
analytic philosophy for the next fifty-five years con- which one would commonly be said to be making
sisted in refutations of Moore’s account of the mean- an ethical judgment, the function of the relevant eth-
ing of “good” and attempts to provide alternatives. ical word is purely ‘emotive.’ It is used to express
Moore was regarded by many as having already feeling about certain objects, but not to make any
shown the inadequacy of the several naturalistic def- assertion about them.” Ayer goes on to claim that
initions of “good,” including a utilitarian definition, “ethical terms do not serve only to express feeling.
i.e., “good” means “pleasure” and various subjectiv- They are calculated also to arouse feeling, and so to
ist definitions, i.e., “good” means “I approve of this,” stimulate action.”
or “My society approves of this.” He did this by Ayer’s points were developed in much greater de-
means of what is called the open-question argument. tail by Charles STEVENSON (1908–1979) in Ethics
Moore claimed that if we ask, “Is pleasure good?” and Language (1944). Stevenson and others recog-
or “Is what I (my society) approve(s) of good?”, we nized that ethical judgments are primarily made in
will immediately see that these are genuine or open order to influence others, so that what came to be
questions, not ones that can be answered simply by known as “prescriptivism” or the imperative theory
looking at the meaning of the words involved. replaced the emotive theory. However, these theories
Moore concluded that “good” is indefinable and were often regarded as complementary rather than
claimed that “good” refers to a simple property just conflicting, it being recognized that the same judg-
as “yellow” does, although in all other respects good- ment can be used both to express one’s feelings and
ness is quite a different kind of property than to prescribe actions to others. PRESCRIPTIVISM was
yellowness. developed in great detail by R. M. HARE in a number
On the basis of his examination of the meaning of books, including The Language of Morals (1952)
of the word “good,” Moore put forward what he and Freedom and Reason (1963). Hare pointed out
himself called a “nonnatural” property of goodness. that there can be logical relationships between im-
Although Moore was not the last nonnaturalist, an- peratives. Much of his moral philosophy involved an
alytic philosophers universally rejected nonnatural- examination of MORAL REASONING. Thus, although
ism. (ARISTOTLE’s [384–322 B.C.E.] rejection of prescriptivism and EMOTIVISM both denied that eth-
PLATO’s [c. 430–347 B.C.E.] account of goodness as ical terms refer to any properties and that ethical
involving the Form of the Good provides an inter- judgments describe any facts, there were important

65
analytic philosophy and ethics

differences between the two views. According to marked the end of a distinctive analytic approach to
prescriptivism, the primary subject matter of ethical ethics. By making clear that the terms “right,”
judgments had to be behavior, whereas according to “ought,” “good,” and “bad” were primarily related
emotivism, there was no limit on the content of to rationality, not morality, e.g., that we offer reasons
moral judgments. for choosing and doing many things in addition to
Although Hare shared the common assumption those related to morality, Baier convinced many that
that moral judgments were to be identified by their concentration solely on the use of these terms could
containing words like “good,” “bad,” and “ought,” not reveal much of significance about ethics. Anal-
he recognized that not all judgments using these yses of those concepts and others peculiar to ethics
words were moral judgments. Hare claimed that came to be routinely combined with substantive dis-
moral judgments were prescriptive judgments that cussion of moral issues.
were both universalizable and overriding. But, like Of course, the present discussion vastly oversim-
most analytic philosophers who did what was called plifies what actually went on in the first half of this
“metaethics,” Hare denied that there was any limit century. However, there is no question that the pri-
to the content of moral judgments; any prescriptive mary effect of analytic philosophy on ethics was to
judgment that any person was prepared to univer- divert attention away from substantive moral prob-
salize and accept as overriding was a moral judg- lems. The analytic philosophers were primarily in-
ment. Hare also denied that there was any way to terested in the uses of language or in the analyses of
show that the moral judgments of such a person concepts. Insofar as they thought they could have
were mistaken. (In his most recent books, e.g., any practical effect, it was simply the effect of help-
Moral Thinking [1981], Hare seems to have ing people become clear about what they were say-
changed some of his views.) ing and the implications of what they said. It some-
During the 1950s the analyses of moral judg- times seems as though the analytic philosophers
ments became more sophisticated; philosophers thought that all they were doing was what is now
pointed out that judgments containing the ethical called values clarification.
terms were used in many different ways—some- In ethics, as in all other fields of philosophy, an-
times to express and arouse emotions; sometimes to alytic philosophers thought of themselves as sharp-
advise, commend, or prescribe ways of acting; and, ening the tools of thought. Their sole task was to
surprisingly, sometimes even to describe. Much make our concepts as clear and precise as possible;
more attention was paid both to the different con- they wanted to have nothing to do with using these
texts in which judgments were made and to the dif- concepts to arrive at substantive conclusions. How-
ferent functions that they perform. However, it also ever, as the tools of thought became sharper, the
came to be realized that this linguistic analysis of temptation to use them became almost irresistible.
moral judgments left out much of what had been Analytic philosophers, benefiting from work in other
discussed by moral philosophers prior to the twen- areas of philosophy, especially philosophy of lan-
tieth century. guage, clarified many ethical concepts and did sig-
Stephen Toulmin, for example, in The Place of nificantly raise the level of moral philosophy. But af-
Reason in Ethics (1950), explicitly tried to get away ter two world wars and fifty-five years of analysis of
from examination of the so-called ethical terms and concepts, most moral philosophers went back to
to replace it with an examination of moral reasoning, their traditional task, trying to use their new under-
but he did not emphasize the difference between standing of the concepts related to morality to per-
moral judgments and other kinds of value judg- suade their readers to act morally.
ments. Kurt Baier, in The Moral Point of View
(1958), made the distinction between moral judg- See also: AYER; BAIER; EMOTIVISM; GOOD, THEORIES
ments and other value judgments a central part of OF THE; HARE; HISTORY OF WESTERN ETHICS,
his account of morality. He tried to show that moral TWENTIETH-CENTURY ANGLO-AMERICAN; HOBBES;
judgments were supported by reasons that involved IMPARTIALITY; LOGIC AND ETHICS; METAETHICS;
taking an impartial point of view. Baier’s attempt to JOHN STUART MILL; MOORE; MORAL REASONING;
use his analyses of rationality, IMPARTIALITY, and MORAL TERMS; NATURALISM; NORMS; PRACTICAL
morality to arrive at substantive moral conclusions REASON[ING]; PRESCRIPTIVISM; RATIONALITY VS.

66
anger

REASONABLENESS; RUSSELL; STEVENSON; SUBJECTIV- tially constitutive of complex emotions like shame,
ISM; THEORY AND PRACTICE; UNIVERSALIZABILITY; regret, and ENVY, and that such emotions are rec-
UTILITARIANISM; WITTGENSTEINIAN ETHICS. ognizable on the basis of the different cognitions in-
volved in their production. So, angry emotions such
as indignation, scorn, and contempt are distinguish-
Bibliography
able in virtue of the cognitions that partially consti-
Ayer, A. J. Language, Truth and Logic. London: Dover, tute them. Though not without its problems, this
1936. See Chapter 6. cognitivist framework offers a useful and straight-
Baier, Kurt. The Moral Point of View. Ithaca, NY: Cornell forward way of delineating the angry emotions and
University Press, 1958. Abridged under same title, their relation to morality. In the remainder of this
New York: Random House, 1965.
article I shall use “beliefs” as the cognitions which
Hare, R. M. The Language of Morals. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1952.
combine with feelings to produce such emotions.
Moore, G. E. Principia Ethica. Cambridge: Cambridge
Anger admits of three forms, the first of which
University Press, 1903. corresponds to what Joseph BUTLER (1692–1752)
Schlick, Moritz. The Problem of Ethics. New York, Pren- has called “hasty and sudden” anger, a kind of anger
tice Hall, 1938. connected to the impulse for self-preservation. This
Stevenson, Charles L. Ethics and Language. New Haven: is the sort of anger persons and animals may expe-
Yale University Press, 1944. rience when feeling tormented or trapped. The sec-
Toulmin, Stephen Edelston. The Place of Reason in ond sense, “settled and deliberate” anger, is anger
Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1950. constituted in part by an agent’s beliefs about how
Bernard Gert she is perceived and treated by others. P. F. Straw-
son’s notion of a “reactive attitude” helps amplify
this sense of anger. For Strawson, reactive attitudes
involve personal feelings which “depend upon, or
anger involve” our beliefs about the attitudes, intentions,
Philosophy has always been concerned with human and actions of others toward us. Thus, for example,
nature. Since emotions play a large role in human resentment is a reactive attitude typically felt toward
experience, philosophers have devoted a consider- another you believe intended to wrong you. Indeed,
able amount of attention to answering three key resentment is ordinarily defined as taking offense,
questions about them: What is an emotion? How do umbrage, or exception to the perceptions or deeds
we distinguish between different emotions? And of others, and such notions as “taking umbrage” or
what is the relationship between emotions and a “offense” presuppose moral judgments (i.e., moral
morally good life? These queries may also be used beliefs). By contrast, resentment is not typically felt
to structure an investigation into specific emotions toward those who harm you accidentally or inadver-
such as anger, which is the purview of this article. tently, for such harms do not reveal another’s wrong-
Although there is disagreement about how to ful feelings, intentions, or actions toward you. Con-
conceive of emotions (are emotions feelings, sensa- sequently, resentment is a paradigm of moral anger
tions, cognitions, physiological conditions, behav- because of the nature of the beliefs involved in it.
ioral patterns, tendencies, or some combination of Instinctive anger and anger as a reactive attitude are
these?), I shall assume for the sake of this article typically episodic, whereas some forms of anger are
both that emotions inhere in agents (contrary to the relatively fixed dispositions. This third form of an-
view in some cultures that emotions occur not in but ger, of which such postures as irritability, sullenness,
between agents), and that many emotions linked to or churlishness are examples, link anger more to
morality (e.g., guilt, PRIDE, and RESENTMENT) are character traits than to instincts or cognitions. Of
combinations of feelings and cognitions. This latter these general types of anger, episodic anger involv-
view I shall label “cognitivism,” which in one form ing cognitions and dispositional anger are clearly re-
or another is the prevailing paradigm among con- lated to morality, though in different ways. The two
temporary theorists of emotions. Cognitivism is main ways in which angry emotions connect with
(generally) the view that beliefs, evaluations, prop- moral concerns are that, on the one hand, some an-
ositional attitudes, or other such cognitions are par- gry emotions are “moral” by their very nature, in-

67
anger

sofar as they are partially constituted by moral be- tivating group action such as riots, revolutions, and
liefs. On the other hand, we can inquire about the political boycotts. MARX’s (1818–1883) effort to in-
moral status of the presence and expression of epi- spire the violent overthrow of capitalism by appeal-
sodic and dispositional anger in a person’s life. I ing to the anger of the working class is an example,
shall discuss these in turn. as is the late-twentieth-century feminist claim to
Using resentment as a model, we can clarify the have “appropriated” anger (heretofore an essentially
way in which some angry emotions are moral by male emotion) as the emotion of choice for fueling
their very nature. As noted, resentment ordinarily the struggle against sexism. Many other ongoing po-
involves the belief that you have been wronged, and litical and moral struggles (e.g., anti-abortion ef-
this is a moral belief. This belief, in turn, implies forts, the fight for animal rights, etc.) are also
both that the object of resentment must be perceived grounded, at least in part, in moral outrage. And
as a moral agent, for only moral agents can commit collective anger takes formal institutional expres-
wrongs, and that the subject of resentment (i.e., sions as well, as when a society imposes sanctions
those on whose behalf such anger is stimulated) be for the violation of its legal rules.
a moral subject. Since resentment is a paradigmatic In addition to questions regarding the nature of
instance of moral anger, we may conjecture that the different forms of anger, and the manner in which
belief that oneself or some other moral subject has we distinguish between varieties of moral anger,
been wronged will be characteristic of all forms of such as resentment, indignation, and scorn, is the
moral anger, and so moral anger of any sort is a re- general concern about the place of anger in a morally
active attitude felt toward another you believe has good life. What relation does anger bear to such cen-
wronged a moral subject. To refer to anger as tral ethical concerns as SELF-RESPECT, RESPONSIBIL-
“moral” in this sense is to describe the moral content ITY, LOVE, and FORGIVENESS, and virtue and vice in
of such feelings, not to judge them as praiseworthy general? Though a brief essay cannot adequately
or blameworthy, virtuous or vicious. summarize all the views related to these concerns, I
Since moral anger can be aroused only on behalf will close with a selective overview of some of the
of a moral subject, and a moral subject is anything more important general positions on the moral
that has moral standing (i.e., anything that is vested status of the presence and expression of various
with moral RIGHTS, INTERESTS, or claims to respect), forms of anger.
then persons, individually and collectively, animals, The ancient Greek view of demonstrations of an-
and perhaps other parts of the natural environment, ger was that, in general, such expressions were man-
are appropriate subjects of moral anger. We might ifestations of intemperance, which is a vice. PLATO’s
then say that when moral anger is generated pri- (428–348 B.C.E.) tripartite division of the soul into
marily on behalf of oneself, it is personal moral an- reason, PASSION, and thumos, with passion (and
ger; when aroused primarily for the sake of other thus anger) requiring the control of reason in order
moral subjects, it is vicarious moral anger. The dis- for a person to be just, is echoed in more recent
tinction between personal and vicarious moral anger views such as that of Freud (1856–1939), who
further enables us to classify the various forms of viewed the strong emotions as explosive, volatile,
moral anger such as resentment, indignation, scorn, and dangerous. Common sense supports this view,
and contempt based on the beliefs typical of those regarding those who are consumed by REVENGE or
emotions. For instance, if I react with anger over an who wallow in an ecstasy of rage as being in the grip
injustice done to a stranger, then since the consti- of a morally dubious emotional state. This is consis-
tutive belief of my anger is that a moral subject other tent with ARISTOTLE’s (384–322 B.C.E.) contention
than myself has been wronged, my anger is more that the person who is angry “at the right things and
plausibly regarded as indignation or some other towards the right people, and also in the right way,
form of moral anger other than resentment, which at the right time and for the right length of time” is
is personal moral anger. morally praiseworthy. Aristotle’s view implies that
Beyond personal and vicarious moral anger we anger is rationally assessable, and thus that it makes
need to acknowledge the reality of collective anger, sense to evaluate anger as reasonable or unreason-
for it is important to note that anger may reside able, justified or unjustified.
within and across persons simultaneously, often mo- That anger and its expression can and should be

68
anger

controlled by reason is a view supported by KANT and others that are essentially unrelated to the
(1724–1804), who contends that vengeance is vi- causes of one’s rage. It is well known, for instance,
cious because it is “excessive anger,” that is, anger that enraged people fly off the handle and strike out
disproportionate to the adequate defense of one’s at others in ways disproportionate to the severity of
DIGNITY. Kant’s view of vengeance occurs in a con- the wrong done them; and enraged persons are more
text in which he argues that the person who fails to likely to inflate the importance of minor inconven-
become angry at injustices done to him is one who iences or problems (e.g., being cut off in traffic) as
lacks dignity or “manhood,” a view reminiscent of a pretext for venting their rage.
HUME’s (1711–1776) claim that since anger and ha- These last remarks echo a third dissenting view,
tred are passions “inherent in our very frame and that of the Stoic SENECA (c. 4 B.C.E.– C.E. 65), which
constitution,” the lack of them is sometimes evi- maintains that all forms of anger are inconsistent
dence of “weakness and imbecility.” Resentment, with the good life because they dispose us to CRU-
our paradigm of moral anger, also asserts the value ELTY and vengeance, which passions encourage us
of self-respect, since its focus is, directly or indi- to see other people as less than fully human. On this
rectly, the self. Thus, expressions of anger controlled view, the person of virtue is one who strives to ex-
by or at least prominently involving reason have tirpate, mot merely control, anger.
come to be seen as manifesting virtue, while the lack Other questions pertaining to the morality of an-
of anger, or the absence of the governing influence ger include whether there are any intrinsically good
of rationality in expressing it, have come to be or evil forms of anger, whether and in what sense
viewed as morally unacceptable. people can be held responsible for their anger or
But three contrary views should be mentioned. perhaps even, as SARTRE (1905–1980) suggests,
First, NIETZSCHE’s (1844–1900) conception of “res- choose to be angry, and whether some forms of an-
sentiment” as sublimated anger/envy directed at the ger are logically or causally necessary for the exis-
noble man suggests the interesting idea that at least tence of certain sorts of goods like forgiveness and
some forms of dispositional anger such as irascibility MERCY.
or bitterness may be manifestations of weakness, not
See also: CRUELTY; EMOTION; EMOTIVISM; ENVY;
strength. More interesting still is the idea that even
GUILT AND SHAME; HARM AND OFFENSE; HATE; IN-
episodic resentment or indignation may be ignoble,
TENTION; PASSION; PRIDE; RESENTMENT; REVENGE;
insofar as such emotions implicitly concede power
REVOLUTION; SELF-CONTROL; SELF-DEFENSE; VIO-
to others by revealing one’s vulnerability to injury.
LENCE AND NON-VIOLENCE.
But the truly noble are thought to have, in some
sense, no such vulnerabilities.
Second, some late-twentieth-century popular Bibliography
views suggest that the uninhibited expression of Aristotle. Nicomachean Ethics. Translated by Terence Ir-
even rage is a good thing, insofar as such venting is win. Hackett, 1985. A rich source of insight into dif-
cathartic. But on consequentialist grounds alone it ferent types of anger and their relation to personal
seems clear that controlling intense anger rather character, moral virtue, and vice.
than its unfettered venting is closer to what a good Butler, Joseph. Fifteen Sermons Preached at Rolls Chapel.
life requires, for though anger may sometimes be (1726) Sermon VII, “Upon Resentment.” Offers an im-
portant distinction between a kind of instinctive non-
enabling (e.g., in motivating changes to unjust or
moral anger linked to the impulse of self-preservation,
otherwise unhappy circumstances), its indiscrimi- and “settled and deliberate” anger which is connected
nate expression is more likely to be disabling, both to our beliefs about others, much as are the “reactive
for those expressing it and for those around them. attitudes” discussed by P. F. Strawson.
The difference between anger and rage has often Deigh, John. “Cognitivism in the Theory of Emotions.”
been remarked on by psychologists and (less so) by Ethics 104 (July 1994): 824–54. A detailed overview
of the origins of contemporary cognitivist theories of
philosophers, with the latter emotion associated
emotion, differences between them, and shortcomings
more closely with destructive violence than with mo- of various versions.
tivating constructive solutions to personal or politi- Goleman, Daniel. “On Rage.” In his Emotional Intelli-
cal problems. This is partly because rage tends to gence. New York: Bantam Books, 1995. Reprinted in
fester and influence a person’s perception of events Vice and Virtue in Everyday Life: Introductory Read-

69
anger

ings in Ethics, 4th ed., edited by Christina Hoff Som- knowing the common themes (chance variation and
mers, 445–55. Fort Worth, TX: Harcourt Brace, 1997. adaptation to an ever-changing environment, for ex-
Hughes, Paul M. “Moral Anger, Forgiving, and Condon- ample) that characterize the EVOLUTION of all spe-
ing.” Journal of Social Philosophy 26, no. 1 (Spring
1995): 103–18. Types of moral anger and moral un-
cies of animals, our own included. Yet some of these
happiness are distinguished and related to forgiveness, thinkers display at least a partial understanding of
toleration, and condonation. our animality. ARISTOTLE (384–322 B.C.E.) is one.
Jacoby, Susan. Wild Justice: The Evolution of Revenge. Along with plants, in his view, humans and other
New York: Harper and Row, 1983. animals seek nourishment and reproduce. But unlike
Murphy, Jeffrie. “Forgiveness, Mercy, and the Retributive plants, humans and other animals share additional
Emotions.” Criminal Justice Ethics 7 (1988): 3–14. capacities: sensation, DESIRE, memory, and imagi-
Murphy, Jeffrie, and Jean Hampton. Forgiveness and
nation, for example. On Aristotle’s account, only
Mercy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988.
Discusses such topics as the nature and value of re- when we consider the ability to reason do we find a
sentment and moral hatred and their relation to moral capacity that distinguishes humans from the rest of
responses to wrongdoing such as forgiveness, mercy, the animal kingdom. For it is “man” (and “man”
and condonation. alone) among all the animals who is said to be
Nussbaum, Martha. The Therapy of Desire: Theory and rational.
Practice in Hellenistic Ethics. Princeton: Princeton It is difficult to exaggerate the importance Aris-
University Press, 1994.
totle and legions of other Western moralists attach
Seneca. Moral Essays. Translated by John W. Basore.
Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1958.
to rationality. As different as Aristotle’s ethic is from
Strawson, Peter F. Freedom and Resentment, and Other Immanuel KANT’s (1724–1804), or THOMAS AQUI-
Essays. London: Methuen, 1974. See especially pp. NAS’s (1225?–1274) from John RAWLS’s, they are
10–11. Articulates a theory of reactive attitudes, their in one respect the same: the possession of this par-
nature, and their relation to the attitudes, intentions, ticular capacity—reason—affords its possessor a
and actions of others toward us. morally exalted status. Why this is so, and what it
Woodward, Kathleen. “Anger . . . and Anger: From Freud implies, can be explained by distinguishing between
to Feminism.” In Freud and the Passions, edited by
John O’Neill, 73–95. University Park: Pennsylvania
direct and indirect duties.
State University Press, 1996.

Paul M. Hughes Direct and Indirect Duties


Duties of the former (the direct) kind are duties
owed to identifiable individuals, and those to whom
animals, treatment of they are owed are prima facie entitled to demand
How we talk about one another is symptomatic of compliance. If, as is commonly thought, direct du-
the morally precarious position other animals have ties have correlative RIGHTS, then this entitlement
occupied in the history of Western thought. To be can be expressed in terms of individual rights. That
called a pig, sloth, snake in the grass, bitch, or vul- Antony has a duty to speak the truth to Cleopatra,
ture, for example, is hardly a compliment. But the for example, goes hand-in-glove with Cleopatra’s
symptoms of moral precariousness go deeper. In our having a right to demand truthfulness from Antony.
speech habits “we” are humans while “they”—well, Indirect duties differ. These duties involve certain
“they” are animals. That we humans are animals, it individuals or things, but they are not duties owed
seems, is something we would like to forget. to them. The duty to respect another’s PROPERTY is
Certainly this is true of most of our major ethical a duty of this kind. For we have no duty to the prop-
theorists. Intent, as they are, in finding an unbridge- erty in question; rather, the duty involves the prop-
able gulf between the moral principles that prescribe erty, but the duty is owed to the owner, not to the
how we must treat human beings and how we may thing owned.
treat (mere) animals, these thinkers tend either to This distinction—between direct and indirect du-
ignore or to underestimate the importance of the ties—can be used to define the moral community.
biological and other ties that bind all animals On this account the moral community consists of all
together. and only those individuals (a) who have direct duties
Pre-Darwinian moralists may be forgiven for not or (b) to whom direct duties are owed. Anything or

70
animals, treatment of

anyone standing outside the moral community at the capacity of common sense to withstand the ex-
most can be involved in duties owed to individuals cesses of philosophical theory.
belonging to this community (and thus figure in
some indirect duty), but nothing and no one outside
The Sentientist Tradition
the community either can be owed a direct duty or
can possess a correlative right. In view of the morally relevant differences that
separate cabbages and garter belts from sparrows
and mice, critics of the rationalist tradition seek an
The Rationalist Tradition
alternative to the capacity to reason as the criterion
The question “Who belongs to the moral com- for admission to the moral community. Jeremy BEN-
munity?” is therefore fraught with both theoretical THAM (1748–1832), JOHN STUART MILL (1806–
and practical significance, and it is hardly unimpor- 1873) and, among contemporary utilitarians, Peter
tant that Aristotle and the many other thinkers who Singer argue forcefully for the inclusion of other ani-
are part of what we might term the “rationalist tra- mals in the moral community. It is, they think, sen-
dition” answer this question by insisting that the ca- tiency (that is, the capacity to experience PLEASURE
pacity to reason is decisive. Given this answer, and and pain) that determines who does, and who does
given the further thesis that it is humans and humans not, belong. As Bentham writes, in an oft-quoted
alone (among terrestrial creatures) who have this ca- passage, “The question is not, can they [that is, non-
pacity, the theoretical exclusion of other animals human animals] reason? Nor, can they talk? But can
from the moral community is guaranteed. they suffer?”
We have, then, according to the rationalist tra- If sentiency serves as the test for admission, then
dition, no direct duties to other animals. There is the moral landscape is radically transformed. At
nothing we owe them, no wrong we can do to them. least some of our duties regarding nonhuman ani-
At the very most we can be prohibited from treating mals emerge as direct duties—duties we owe to
other animals in certain ways because of what we these animals themselves, not to some human being
owe to rational beings, ourselves or others. A venge- who happens to be an interested third party. In par-
ful person, who sets fire to a neighbor’s dog in order ticular, the general duty of nonmaleficence applies
to get even, does nothing wrong to the dog; it is the directly to our dealings with sentient beings if, as is
harm done to the neighbor’s property, or the neigh- generally assumed, pain is intrinsically evil. Prima
bor’s psyche, or the agent’s moral CHARACTER that facie, that is, we have a direct duty not to cause any
explicates what is wrong. As strange as it may seem, sentient being pain, regardless of the species to
the wrong done in a case like this, given the ration- which the individual belongs.
alist tradition, differs in no essential respect from the To resist this extension of direct duties to animals
wrong done if the person bent on revenge sets fire other than human beings, on the ground that non-
to the neighbor’s car or shrubbery. human animals do not belong to the species Homo
Not a few moralists find this more than strange; sapiens, thus emerges as a moral prejudice cut from
they find it plainly false. For there are important dif- the same defective moral cloth as racism and sexism.
ferences between burning a dog and burning a car Like these latter prejudices this newly recognized
or a bush. A car feels nothing, while a dog is capable one—speciesism, as it is commonly called—at-
of experiencing not only pain but also fear, and tempts to justify moral differences simply on the ba-
whereas the destruction of a plant ends the plant’s sis of biological differences. However, just as the
life, there is no reason to believe either that the plant color of one’s skin and the gender of one’s sex
is aware of anything or that its death is something should not determine one’s membership in the
that matters to the plant. True, some philosophers— moral community, so the classification of one’s spe-
René DESCARTES (1596–1650) in particular— cies should be similarly impotent. At the most fun-
maintain that nonhuman animals are totally devoid damental moral level, all sentient animals are equal.
of mind. On this (astonishing) view, gorillas and cats The egalitarianism central to what might be called
are just as psychologically impoverished as BMWs “the sentientist tradition,” when coupled (as it cus-
and holly bushes. Few people are even momentarily tomarily is) with utilitarian theory, gives rise to re-
tempted to side with Descartes, a reassuring sign of sults many find counterintuitive. For example, the

71
animals, treatment of

murder of innocent human beings seems to be per- in themselves (or have inherent value), inherentists
mitted by the theory, if the aggregate balance of good maintain that other animals have this same moral
mental states over bad mental states is thereby status. Moreover, inherentism’s advocates see them-
achieved—as well it may be in particular cases. Such selves as offering a philosophical foundation of hu-
an outcome cannot bode well for the protection non- man and animal rights, arguing that those individ-
human animals are afforded by utilitarians operating uals who have inherent value, whether humans or
within the sentientist tradition. Given this approach not, also possess the basic moral right to be treated
there is nothing wrong with a matador’s painfully with respect (or, alternatively, to be treated as ends
draining the life from a bull, for example, provided in themselves).
only that enough people find the spectacle suffi- Thus, to the extent that the equal value of the
ciently pleasant. To protest that it is immoral to take individual plays a dominant role in the rationalist
pleasure in such a barbarous custom is an objection tradition, inherentism makes use of an important
that is unavailable to utilitarians since whether this idea from this tradition. And to the extent that non-
is immoral is itself an open question, given utilitar- speciesism plays a dominant role in the sentientist
ian theory. In short, when it comes to how humans tradition, inherentism makes use of an important
treat other animals, utilitarian theory seems better idea from this tradition, too. In view of the key
suited to defending rather than reforming the sta- points of resemblance between inherentism, on the
tus quo. one hand, and the rationalist and sentientist tradi-
Utilitarians offer a variety of replies to these and tions, on the other, it is reasonable to say that inher-
other objections, and it must be said that, whatever entism is the attempt to synthesize what, according
the shortcomings of the theory, its champions are to its advocates, are the best features of these two
exceptional for their resourcefulness and tenacity. widely divergent philosophical traditions.
Nevertheless, many thinkers find the position inade- How successful inherentism is in this regard is
quate, some because of the meager protection it af- very much open to debate. At least some of the dis-
fords nonhuman animals. While acknowledging the agreement is occasioned, not by the logic of the po-
improvement sentiency represents over rationality sition, but by what many view as its “radical” impli-
as a criterion of membership in the moral commu- cations. And it is true that, when compared with the
nity, and while agreeing that, as the sentientist tra- status quo, inherentism’s practical implications do
dition implies, humans have some direct duties to seem “radical.” For example, inherentism categori-
nonhuman animals, these latter critics of UTILITAR- cally prohibits not only such blood sports as bull-
IANISM seek a moral theory that retains the strengths fighting and recreational hunting, it takes a similar
of the sentientist tradition while shedding its stance against using nonhuman animals in science
weaknesses. or raising them for purposes of human commerce or
gustatory delight. In all these instances (and more),
inherentism sees some individuals being treated as
Inherentism
mere means by other individuals, something the the-
Inherentism is one form such a theory can take. ory’s most basic principle condemns uncondition-
Like the sentientist tradition, inherentism is egali- ally. At the level of practice, therefore, inherentism
tarian in spirit. But unlike this former tradition, in- is an abolitionist philosophy.
herentism identifies individuals, not mental states as Not a few people are anxious to refute this “ex-
the locus of ultimate value. The kind of value indi- treme” view, often for the worst of reasons. Surpris-
viduals possess is modeled after Kant’s idea of “end ingly—perhaps—even otherwise astute philoso-
in itself.” Individuals who have inherent value have phers commit fallacies worthy of the most unbridled
a morally significant value in themselves, apart from sophomore, arguing, for example, that the very idea
their possible usefulness to others and indepen- of “animal rights” is absurd because dogs and cats
dently of the episodic or overall value of their mental cannot vote (and so cannot have a right to vote),
states. cannot learn calculus and geography (and so cannot
But inherentism differs from the position of Kant have a right to an education), and so on. However,
and his followers in a fundamental respect. Whereas it is implausible to assume that an individual must
Kantians deny that nonhuman animals exist as ends have every right in order to have any right. This is

72
animals, treatment of

not a standard we insist on in the case of human certain: The question of the moral status of nonhu-
beings. We do not, for example, maintain that a re- man animals has attained a respectability and stay-
tarded child who cannot learn calculus or geometry ing power few people would have thought possible
has no right to medical care or, more basically, can- even as recently as twenty years ago. When Mill
not have a right to be treated respectfully. This much writes that “all great movements go through three
granted, it cannot be logical to deny all rights to non- stages: ridicule, discussion, adoption,” those who
human animals because, like this child, they cannot are active in the animal rights movement under-
have every right. standably hope he speaks prophetically of their
Similarly deficient, and for similar reasons, is the cause. How far this movement will advance, no one
attempt to deny all rights to these animals on the can know. What is known, is that philosophers have
grounds that they cannot understand what a right is forced the issue of animal rights beyond the stage of
or, alternatively, that they themselves cannot claim, ridicule to that of serious discussion. In this respect,
waive, exercise, etc. their rights. Many humans are and for this reason, all moral philosophers can take
similarly disadvantaged yet do not for this reason comfort in knowing that moral philosophy some-
necessarily lack every right. And as for certain theo- times does make a difference.
logical bases for attributing rights to all humans
See also: ABORTION; ARISTOTLE; BENTHAM; BIOETH-
while denying them to every other animal (for ex-
ICS; BIOLOGICAL THEORY; DUTY AND OBLIGATION;
ample, the view that all and only human beings have
ENVIRONMENTAL ETHICS; EUTHANASIA; EVOLUTION;
souls), these turn out to be more controversial in
EXPLOITATION; FEMINIST ETHICS; GOOD, THEORIES
their major assumptions than the ideas they are en-
OF THE; HARM AND OFFENSE; HUMANISM; INFANTI-
listed to combat.
CIDE; KANT; JOHN STUART MILL; MORAL COMMU-
However, even if inherentism is able to defend
NITY, BOUNDARIES OF; NATURE AND ETHICS; PAIN
itself against these sorts of criticism, its own major
AND SUFFERING; PLEASURE; RIGHT HOLDERS; RIGHTS;
teachings are far from settled. Among the questions
SOCIAL CONTRACT; SPORT; UTILITARIANISM; VALUE,
it must address, one concerns the criteria for pos-
THEORY OF.
sessing inherent value. Because inherentists are in-
clined to answer this question by making reference
to possessing a fairly rich psychology, a psychology Bibliography
that includes not only beliefs and desires but also Callicott, J. Baird. In Defense of the Land Ethic: Essays in
the ability to act intentionally, proponents of this Environmental Philosophy. Albany: SUNY Press, 1988.
view are faced with daunting challenges in the phi- Clark, Stephen. The Moral Status of Animals. Oxford:
losophy of mind. Moreover, difficult line-drawing Clarendon Press, 1977.
problems arise concerning which animals actually ———. The Nature of the Beast. Oxford: Oxford Univer-
are as psychologically rich as inherentists require, sity Press, 1983.
even assuming that some are. And there are, finally, Fox, Michael Allen. The Case for Animal Experimenta-
tion. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1986.
vexing questions posed by some environmental phi-
Frey, R. G. Interests and Rights: The Case against Ani-
losophers about inherentism’s difficulties in ac- mals. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980.
counting for the value of nonanimate nature gener- ———. Rights, Killing and Suffering: Moral Vegetarian-
ally and of species in particular, and still other ism and Applied Ethics. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1983.
challenges emanating from feminist thinkers who Godlovich, Stanley, Roslind Godlovich, and John Harris,
discern a patriarchal bias in the rights/duties tradi- eds. Animals, Men and Morals. London: Gollancz,
tion at the heart not only of inherentism but of West- 1972.
ern moral theory generally. Clearly, even if animals Linzey, Andrew. Animal Rights: A Christian Assessment.
are not part of their daily bread, the inherentist’s London: SCM Press, 1976.
plate is loaded with difficult questions. ———. Christianity and the Rights of Animals. London:
SPCK; New York: Crossroad, 1988.
Magel, Charles. A Bibliography on Animal Rights and Re-
Beyond Ridicule lated Matters. Washington, D.C.: University Press of
America, 1981.
Whether or not inherentists have the wherewithal ———. Keyguide to Information Sources on Animal
to defend their abolitionist philosophy, one thing is Rights. Jefferson, NC: McFarland, 1989.

73
animals, treatment of

Midgley, Mary. Animals and Why They Matter: A Journey attention deeply questionable assumptions charac-
Around the Species Barrier. Harmondsworth: Penguin, terizing moral philosophy as it has been taught and
1984.
thought about; she also criticized prominent fea-
———. Beast and Man: The Roots of Human Nature. Ith-
tures of nonacademic thought about ethics, Catholic
aca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1978.
as well as non-Catholic. This distance from the
Miller, Harlan, and William Williams, eds. Ethics and Ani-
mals. Clifton, NJ: Humana Press, 1983. modes of thought of the age distinguishes also her
Paterson, David, and Richard Ryder, eds. Animals’ Rights: writings on metaphysics; here too she brings to at-
A Symposium. Fontwell, Sussex: Centaur, 1979. tention and criticizes the “cast of mind . . . charac-
Regan, Tom. All Who Dwell Therein: Essays on Animal teristic of our whole culture.” Cultural criticism and
Rights and Environmental Ethics. Berkeley: University philosophical criticism are joined in her work, which
of California Press, 1982. is thus set apart from most analytic philosophy. (The
———. The Case for Animal Rights. Berkeley: University philosopher most clearly influenced by her way of
of California Press, 1983. bringing together cultural and philosophical criti-
———. Defending Animal Rights. Champaign: University cism is Alasdair MACINTYRE.)
of Illinois Press, 2001. Her most influential contribution to ethics has
Regan, Tom, and Peter Singer, eds. Animal Rights and been “Modern Moral Philosophy” (in Anscombe
Human Obligations. 2nd ed. Englewood Cliffs, NJ:
1981; originally published in 1958), a principal aim
Prentice Hall, 1989 [1976].
of which was to let people see modern moral phi-
Regan, Tom, and Carl Cohen. The Animal Rights Debate.
Towata, NJ: Rowman and Littlefield, 2001. losophy as not the only, the obvious, the self-evident
way in which the subject might be done. She wanted
Rollin, Bernard. Animal Rights and Human Morality. Buf-
falo, NY: Prometheus Books, 1981. to reveal the state of moral philosophy to be thor-
Salt, Henry. Animal Rights. Fontwell, Sussex: Centaur, oughly unsatisfactory, dependent on incoherent con-
1980 [1892]. cepts and unrecognized assumptions; and she ar-
Singer, Peter. Animal Liberation. 1983 [1975]. Various gued that, in the form in which it was then practiced,
publishers. it should be given up. In the course of her argument
———. Practical Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge Univer- she stated and defended three theses, each of which
sity Press, 1979. has been important in the subsequent development
———, ed. In Defence of Animals. Oxford: Basil Black- of philosophical ethics.
well, 1985. The first of her theses was that moral philosophy
Tom Regan could not profitably be done without an adequate
philosophy of PSYCHOLOGY, and that it should be
put aside in the meantime. Thus, for example,
HUME’s (1711–1776) famous argument about the
relation between “is” and “ought” concerns the kind
Anscombe, G[ertrude]
of influence on action which various sorts of consid-
E[lizabeth] M[argaret] eration are capable of having, but the discussion of
(1919–2001) that issue in Hume’s own writings and in post-
Anscombe made significant contributions not only Humean philosophy reflects great unclarity about
to ethics but also to philosophy of mind, metaphys- how NEEDS and wants are related to other sorts of
ics, philosophy of logic and language, and the history facts and to reasoning about what to do. An-
of philosophy. She studied at Cambridge with Lud- scombe’s argument for the importance to moral phi-
wig Wittgenstein after taking a degree at Oxford. losophy of philosophical psychology stimulated a re-
ARISTOTLE (384–322 B.C.E.) and WITTGENSTEIN vival of interest in such topics as ACTION, INTENTION,
(1889–1951) are the most important philosophical PRACTICAL REASON, MOTIVES, and DESIRE. But her
influences on her thought, which has also been thesis concerning the importance to moral philoso-
shaped by the Roman Catholicism which she ac- phy of such discussion is still controversial. While
cepted while in her teens. the acceptance of her idea is reflected in the orga-
Anscombe’s work on ethics has from the start nization of this encyclopedia (see, for example, the
been distinguished by its critical distance from the entries on action; character; deliberation and choice;
dominant modes of thought of the age. She called to emotion; motives; pleasure; practical reason[ing];

74
Anscombe, G. E. M.

voluntary acts; weakness of will), its rejection is of a virtue in Aristotle’s thought, helped to turn the
plain in the organization of the Blackwell Compan- attention of philosophers to the VIRTUES and to the
ion to Ethics, which contains no article on any topic possibility of forms of moral thought in which the
in philosophical psychology, even those of obvious concept of a virtue is central.
relevance to moral philosophy. Anscombe’s own The third thesis was that English moral philoso-
contributions to philosophical psychology include phers from Sidgwick on differ only in superficial
her monograph, Intention (1957). In it she discusses ways. However different the details of their theories,
questions about intention, action, and practical such moral thinkers as SIDGWICK (1838–1900),
thought (practical reasoning and practical knowl- MOORE (1873–1958), ROSS (1877–1971), Nowell-
edge). She rejected the prevalent philosophical idea Smith, and HARE all hold that that action is right
of intention as a kind of mental state or event, and which produces the best possible consequences, in-
developed instead an account of intentional action cluding among consequences the intrinsic values
in terms of the applicability to such action of a kind which theorists like Ross believe we should pro-
of question asking for the agent’s reason. She was mote. Anscombe introduced the term CONSEQUEN-
thus able to show the importance of conceptions of TIALISM for the shared view; what consequentialists
good in practical thought. Her later writings take deny is that there is anything prohibited simply in
further the question how practical thinking and virtue of its being describable as such-and-such kind
goodness are related, and thus bear closely on the of action, like murder, say, or adultery. It is this de-
question how actions may be evaluated as good or nial that is central to the similarity averred in her
bad. (See especially her “Von Wright and Practical thesis. (That is, someone who held that the motive
Inference,” 1989.) of duty had supreme value might argue that murder
Anscombe’s second thesis was that the concepts would not be prohibited if done from duty; this view,
of moral duty, moral obligation, and the moral though not explicitly consequentialist, would fall
“ought” should, if possible, be abandoned; they were into the group of views which Anscombe was ar-
survivals of a divine law conception of ethics that guing were only superficially different from each
had been given up and were unintelligible outside other.) The third thesis has been very influential in
that framework of thought. Anscombe has been ac- one regard, but much less so in another. That is, the
cused of failing to recognize the distinction between term “consequentialism” has entered the general
moral obligation and requirements established philosophical vocabulary; the debate between con-
through some sort of convention, the idea being that sequentialists and anti-consequentialists is now part
only in the latter sort of case might an authoritative of philosophical curricula, a topic for anthologies
source of the obligation be necessary (see Baier). But and symposia. But the third thesis itself—the thesis
she does herself distinguish between obligations de- of superficial differences—has not had much seri-
pendent and those not dependent on convention. ous attention. The question she wanted her audi-
The idea that the distinction undercuts her argument ence to think about concerned the cast of mind of
may rest on some confusion about what she was ar- a culture—the philosophical culture and the larger
guing; she has not held that whether an act is good culture. But, with few exceptions, analytic philos-
or bad, just or unjust, is a matter of the promulga- ophers have not followed Anscombe in reflecting
tion of a divine law. She has held that the idea of a on such issues. It seems, indeed, that the sting of
supposed moral sense of “ought” can lead to cor- Anscombe’s third criticism has been drawn by the
ruptions of thought, as when we wonder whether, in transformation of her issue into a debate which
some difficult circumstances, we “morally ought” to could be integrated into the academic culture
do some admittedly unjust act. which she was criticizing. What suggests this most
Anscombe’s discussion of her second thesis has clearly is the regular use, in the debate, of a type of
been more influential than the thesis itself, which argument in which we are asked, for example,
has not been widely accepted. In arguing for the the- whether it would not be our duty to boil one baby
sis, she made a contrast between forms of ethics de- if by doing so a thousand deaths could be averted
pendent on the suspect concepts and Aristotle’s (see 1981, III, 65); but the use of such examples is
ethics, in which those concepts have no role. Her itself an expression of the cast of mind with which
account of the contrast, and of the role of the notion the third thesis was concerned.

75
Anscombe, G. E. M.

Throughout her life, Anscombe was greatly inter- Bibliography


ested in particular moral questions, like those con-
cerning EUTHANASIA, war, and contraception. Her Works by Anscombe
approach to these issues and her concerns are well Intention. Oxford: Blackwell, 1957.
illustrated by the three essays on war in Anscombe “Prolegomenon to a Pursuit of the Definition of Murder:
1981 (“The Justice of the Present War Examined,” The Illegal and the Unlawful.” Dialectics and Human-
“Mr Truman’s Degree,” “War and Murder,” origi- ism no. 4 (1979): 73–77.
nally dating, respectively, from 1939, 1957, and Collected Philosophical Papers. Oxford: Blackwell, 1981;
Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1981. Vol.
1961). All three essays reflect her understanding of
III, Ethics, Religion and Politics, contains most of An-
the importance for ethics of clarity about the con- scombe’s pre-1979 writings on ethics.
cepts of action and intention; in all three An- “Action, Intention and ‘Double Effect.’” Medalist’s Ad-
scombe’s reasoning depends on the principle of dress. In Proceedings of the ACPA, 1982, 12–25. Im-
DOUBLE EFFECT, which is explicitly discussed in two portant discussion of action; clarification of issues con-
of the essays; all three are concerned with ways in cerning intended and unintended killing.
which moral thought may be corrupted. The second “Von Wright and Practical Inference.” In The Philosophy
of Georg Henrik von Wright, edited by Paul Arthur
and third essays treat the conception of murder as Schilpp and Lewis Edwin Hahn, 377–404. La Salle,
central. Both these essays attack PACIFISM as a doc- IL: Open Court, 1989. Reprinted under the title “Prac-
trine which is both false and harmful, harmful in tical Inference,” in Virtues and Reasons, edited by Ros-
that it contributes to a loss of understanding in con- alind Hursthouse et al., 1–34. Oxford: Clarendon
Press, 1995.
temporary thought of what murder is; both these
“Murder and the Morality of Euthanasia: Some Philo-
essays discuss also the AUTHORITY of the state. An-
sophical Considerations.” In Euthanasia, Clinical
scombe’s essays on war thus lead into some wider Practice and the Law, edited by Luke Gormally, 37–
topics, to each of which she devoted further atten- 51. London: Linacre Centre for Health Care Ethics,
tion: murder, the authority of the state, and the prin- 1994.
ciple of double effect. Much of this work is not in- “Who is Wronged?” Oxford Review 1967: 16–17. Con-
cluded in Anscombe 1981 and is not widely known; troversial discussion of whether a person acts badly in
choosing to save a smaller rather than a larger number
the most significant essays are “Prolegomenon to a
of people.
Pursuit of the Definition of Murder: The Illegal and
the Unlawful” (1979), “Action, Intention and ‘Dou-
Works about Anscombe
ble Effect’”(1982), and “Murder and the Morality of
Euthanasia: Some Philosophical Considerations” Baier, Kurt. “Radical Virtue Ethics.” In Midwest Studies
(1994). These essays develop her earlier views (for in Philosophy, vol. XIII, 126–35. Notre Dame, IN:
University of Notre Dame Press, 1988. Criticism of the
example, on double effect); they constitute together
second thesis of “Modern Moral Philosophy.”
a powerful argument for the importance in moral
Conant, James. “Nietzsche, Kierkegaard and Anscombe
thought of the concept of murder, and an incisive on Moral Unintelligibility.” In Religion and Morality,
criticism of contemporary thought about LIFE AND edited by D. Z. Phillips, 250–98. New York: St. Mar-
DEATH. tin’s Press, 1996. Discussion of the second thesis of
“Modern Moral Philosophy.”
See also: ACTION; ARISTOTLE; CHARACTER; COMPAR- Diamond, Cora. “The Dog that Gave Himself the Moral
Law.” In Midwest Studies in Philosophy, vol. XIII,
ATIVE ETHICS; CONSEQUENTIALISM; CONVENTIONS;
161–79. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame
DELIBERATION AND CHOICE; DESIRE; DOUBLE EFFECT; Press, 1988. On the second thesis of “Modern Moral
DUTY AND OBLIGATION; EMOTION; EUTHANASIA; Philosophy.”
HARE; HOMICIDE; HUME; INTENTION; LIFE AND Diamond, Cora, and Jenny Teichman, eds. Intention and
DEATH; MACINTYRE; METAPHYSICS AND EPISTEMOL- Intentionality: Essays in Honour of G. E. M. An-
OGY; MOORE; MORAL PSYCHOLOGY; MOTIVES;
scombe. Brighton: Harvester Press, 1979; Ithaca, NY:
Cornell University Press, 1979. Contains essays on An-
OUGHT IMPLIES CAN; PACIFISM; PLEASURE; PRACTICAL
scombe’s discussions of intention in war and in sex,
REASON[ING]; PRACTICAL WISDOM; ROSS; SIDGWICK; and of topics from her Intention.
VIRTUE ETHICS; VIRTUES; VOLUNTARY ACTS; WAR AND Haber, Joram Graf, ed. Absolutism and its Consequen-
PEACE; WEAKNESS OF WILL; WITTGENSTEIN. tialist Critics. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield,

76
Anselm, Saint

1994. On questions connected with the third thesis of conduce to external conditions that did not promote
“Modern Moral Philosophy.” happiness—indeed, even if doing so were to result
Richter, Duncan. Ethics after Anscombe: Post “Modern in the destruction of the present world. Similarly,
Moral Philosophy.” Dordrecht and Boston: Kluwer
Academic Publishers, 1999.
both in De libertate arbitrii 5–6 and in De concordia
Winch, Peter. “Professor Anscombe’s Moral Philosophy.”
I, 6, in which he alludes hypothetically to someone’s
In Commonality and Particularity in Ethics, edited by choice between telling a lie or being killed, he inti-
Lilli Alanen, et al., 177–96. New York: St. Martin’s mates that the lie ought not to be told. Cur Deus
Press, 1997. Critical discussion of “Modern Moral Phi- homo II, 18–19, cites the instance of Christ, who,
losophy” in relation to two of Anscombe’s later papers. according to Anselm’s point of view, allowed him-
Cora Diamond self to be put to death rather than mendaciously
deny that he was the Son of God. Such commitment
to truth Anselm views as both exemplary and
meritorious.
Anselm, Saint (1033–1109) Anselm conceives of morally upright actions as
Abbot of the monastery at Bec-Hellouin in Nor- actions approved by God. But he presumes that we
mandy; Archbishop of Canterbury. In his first phil- can determine which actions are moral and which
osophical work, the Monologion, Anselm indicates are immoral other than by direct insight, as it were,
that the ability to make value judgments is the very into the mind of God. Although God’s will is always
essence of rationality: “for a rational nature to be ultimately determinative of moral rightness and
rational is nothing other than for it to be able to wrongness, God’s will is never arbitrary; rather,
discriminate what is just from what is not just, what whatever God wills he wills for a reason; and in
is true from what is not true, what is good from what discerning something of these reasons we are able
is not good, what is more good from what is less to appeal to them as the basis for our moral obli-
good” (chap. 68). Anselm’s emphasis on rationality gations (Cf. Cur Deus homo I, 8).
is so strong that one would expect him to present a Clearly, Anselm’s conception of morality is fun-
theory of natural-law ethics. Yet he never explicitly damentally related to his theological position. In ac-
moves in that direction—except for stating, in Cur cordance with his theology he points out that as a
Deus homo I, 20, that “[human] nature teaches you result of the Fall human beings have lost the original
to deal with your fellow-servant . . . as you would inclination for justice. Accordingly, the relationship
want to be dealt with by him and teaches that anyone between intellect and will has become distorted, so
who is unwilling to give of what he has ought not to that within the moral domain there is now a ten-
receive what he does not have.” dency for fallen human beings to will that which ex-
A major task of Anselm’s ethical theory, generally, ceeds the moderating requirements of iustitia. Even
is to ascertain the relationship that obtains between when fallen human beings will that which is objec-
reason and will. Anselm has no doubt about the fact tively right, they do not (apart from the special as-
that all rational beings are motivated in terms of an sistance of grace) successfully do so for the right
inalienable inclination toward HAPPINESS. In Adam reason. This theological consideration leads Anselm
this inclination was accompanied by an inclination to refer to moral EVIL as itself a privation, for it is
toward iustitia—i.e., justice, in the sense of right- the absence of justice where justice should be pres-
eousness—so that originally Adam took delight ent—viz., in the will. Anselm distinguishes evil-that-
both in doing the right thing and in doing it for the is-injustice from evil-that-is-detriment (e.g., pain),
right reason, viz., because it is right. With an eye to and he claims that only the former evil is privation.
Adam’s original state Anselm defines a just will as His use of the term “privation” gives emphasis both
one that adheres to moral rectitude for its own sake; to his belief that moral evil results from the lack of
and he makes clear, in De veritate 12, that he means uprightness in the will and to his belief that only
adhering to moral rectitude for its own sake only and such a deficiency is evil per se.
not in order to procure, or to increase, happiness. In The moral basis articulated by Anselm vis-à-vis
Cur Deus homo I, 21, Anselm implies that each hu- his theory of the Atonement has often been studied.
man being has an obligation to act virtuously and in Central to it are the notions of satisfaction, compen-
accordance with God’s will even if doing so were to sation, and HONOR —as well as the presuppositions

77
Anselm, Saint

that only a service performed by a descendant of ably be either dismissed as a mere remnant of feudal
Adam could make satisfaction for the wrongdoings thinking or relegated exclusively to the sphere of
of Adam and his race, and that apart from such a theology.
meritorious service God’s honor could be preserved
See also: CHRISTIAN ETHICS; EVIL; FORGIVENESS;
only by punishing, and not by forgiving, members of
FREE WILL; FREEDOM AND DETERMINISM; GOLDEN
the human race. In De conceptu virginali Anselm
RULE; GOOD, THEORIES OF THE; MERCY; METAPHYS-
insists that no descendants of Adam will be held ac-
ICS AND EPISTEMOLOGY; MOTIVES; NATURAL LAW;
countable for Adam’s sin but only for their own sins,
PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION; PUNISHMENT; RATIONAL
even though because of Adam’s personal sin his nat-
CHOICE; RATIONALITY VS. REASONABLENESS; RELI-
ural descendants inherit a sinful nature that predis-
GION; RIGHT, CONCEPTS OF; THEOLOGICAL ETHICS;
poses them to sin personally. Anselm’s moral and
VIRTUES.
theological perspectives require the metaphysical
view that just as Adam’s personal action contami-
nated his nature, so his descendants’ respective na- Bibliography
ture contaminates their respective persons, even be-
fore they sin personally. Works by Anselm
Though Anselm teaches that fallen human beings The Complete Philosophical and Theological Treatises of
who reach the age of accountability inevitably Anselm of Canterbury. Translated by Jasper Hopkins
choose at some time to do evil, he nowhere supposes and Herbert Richardson. Minneapolis, Banning Press,
that their choice is other than free. Yet his intriguing 2000.
view of freedom is problematical since it depends on Memorials of St. Anselm. Edited by R. W. Southern and
F. S. Schmitt. London: Oxford University Press, 1969.
an objectionable construal of the claim that people
Contains De similitudinibus.
have FREE WILL insofar as they cannot be compelled
Opera omnia anselmi. Edited by F. S. Schmitt. 2 vols.
to will anything against their will—i.e., insofar as Stuttgart: F. Frommann, 1968.
their will cannot be forced: “A man can be bound
against his will, because he can be bound when he
is unwilling to be bound. . . . But a man cannot will Works about Anselm
against his will, because he cannot will if he is un- Crouse, Robert. “The Augustinian Background of St. An-
willing to will. For everyone-who-wills wills that he selm’s Concept of Justitia.” Canadian Journal of The-
will” (De libertate arbitrii 5). Insofar as Anselm con- ology 4 (1958): 111–19.
ceives of willing something against one’s will as will- Eadmer. The Life of St. Anselm, Archbishop of Canterbury.
Edited and translated by R. W. Southern. New York:
ing it unwillingly, and conceives of this latter as self-
Thomas Nelson, 1962.
contradictory, he makes compulsion of the will
Fairweather, Eugene. “Truth, Justice and Moral Respon-
logically impossible and freedom of the will logically sibility in the Thought of St. Anselm.” In Actes du pre-
necessary. In the end, then, his theory of freedom mier congrès international de philosophie médiévale:
seems question-begging and therefore unconducive L’homme et son destin, 385–91. Louvain: Nauwe-
to legitimating the moral practices of blaming and laerts, 1960.
praising. Gombocz, Wolfgang L. “Anselm von Aosta als Schrecken
In the Proslogion Anselm attempts to show that der ‘europäischen’ Anthropologie? Anmeldung der
philosophischen Pflicht, ‘Cur Deus Homo’ zu durch-
there is no conflict between the notions of justice kreuzen.” In Entwicklungslinien mittelalterlicher Phi-
and of MERCY as they apply to God. His attempted losophie, edited by Gerhard Leibold and Winfried Löff-
harmonization consists of the ingenious strategy of ler. Vorträge des V. Kongresses der Österreichischen
deriving mercy from justice, by way of considera- Gesellschaft für Philosophie. Teil 2, 73–86. Vienna:
tions of goodness. Glimpses of Anselm’s practical Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky, 1999.
thinking about the VIRTUES may be gathered from Heyer, George S., Jr. “St. Anselm on the Harmony between
God’s Mercy and God’s Justice.” In The Heritage of
De similitudinibus and from the Vita Anselmi of
Christian Thought: Essays in Honor of Robert Lowry
Eadmer (1060–1124). Calhoun, edited by Robert E. Cushman and Egil Gris-
All in all, Anselm’s conception of morality— lis. New York: Harper and Row, 1965.
though never systematically expounded by him— Hopkins, Jasper. “Anselm of Canterbury.” In Routledge
commands our respect. Assuredly, it cannot reason- Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Edward Craig, general ed-

78
anthropology

itor. Vol. 1, 283–97. London and New York: Rout- be, as many people hold, a general obligation to re-
ledge, 1998. spect rights to PRIVACY in the human sciences, even
Hufnagel, Alfons. “Anselm und das Naturrecht.” In Ana- when the resulting harm over and above mere ex-
lecta Anselmiana, edited by Helmut Kohlenberger, vol.
posure is not great or amounts simply to embar-
5, 189–94. Frankfurt am Main: Minerva, 1976.
rassment.
Kane, G. Stanley. “Elements of Ethical Theory in the
Thought of St. Anselm.” In Studies in Medieval Cul- Anthropology thus often raises a sharp conflict
ture, vol. 12, 61–71. The Medieval Institute. Kalama- between the scholarly concern for truth and verifi-
zoo: Western Michigan University, 1978. ability and the moral concern for the potential uses
McIntyre, John. St. Anselm and His Critics: A Reinterpre- of the information one makes available. Professional
tation of the Cur Deus homo. Edinburgh: Oliver and norms rightly require anthropologists to maintain
Boyd, 1954. adequate field notes and to deposit copies of them
Pouchet, Robert. La rectitudo chez saint Anselme: un in archives—including in the country where the re-
itinéraire augustinien de l’âme à Dieu. Paris: Etudes
augustiniennes, 1964.
search is carried out—so that later researchers can
Sheets, John R. “Justice in the Moral Thought of St. An-
examine them for such scholarly, and broadly epi-
selm.” The Modern Schoolman 25 (January 1948): stemic, purposes as confirming the anthropologist’s
132–39. linguistic competence, honesty, and reliability; ex-
Torrance, Thomas F. “Ethical Implications of Anselm’s De ploring alternative interpretations; and developing
veritate.” Theologische Zeitschrift 24 (September– analyses of material not published by the original
October 1968): 309–19. researcher. But if, for example, information provided
Vuillemin, Jules. “Justice anselmienne et bonne volonté by an informant is embarrassing to the government
kantienne: essai de comparison,” pp. 361–75 in D. E.
(or some powerful elite) of that informant’s country,
Luscombe and G. R. Evans, editors, Anselm: Aosta,
Bec and Canterbury. Sheffield, England, Sheffield Ac- and that government or elite regularly uses force
ademic Press, 1996. against individuals who “slander the state,” then it
is clear that such purposes may have to be overrid-
Jasper Hopkins den by the researcher’s obligations to the safety and
well-being of the informant.
Some of these issues are questions of maintaining
professional confidences: if information is provided
anthropology
to a researcher on the understanding that its source
The ethical question most frequently raised by an- will not be revealed (or that it will not be revealed
thropology is that of relativism, the term “cultural during the informant’s lifetime), there is a very
relativism” having been widely propagated in Amer- strong presumption that the researcher ought to
ican cultural anthropology by Melville Herskovits. maintain those confidences. Further, since anthro-
But many other ethical issues are raised both in and pologists are usually outsiders, they ought generally
by the practice of anthropology. to seek guidance from their informants as to what
dangers the publication of information might cause.
But just as, in many cases, anthropologists may be
Information and Informants
unaware of the risks associated with revealing their
Anthropologists often explore topics related to sources, so their informant may be unaware of the
RELIGION, sexuality, and social POWER —topics that risks. The obligation to one’s informants cannot be
are extremely sensitive in the societies they write discharged by getting their permission to release in-
about. To reveal the sources of information about formation in circumstances where they have no clear
these topics—or the information itself—would of- sense of the risks.
ten have a catastrophic impact on individuals or on
the community. Such information could be used by
Respect and Autonomy
people both within those societies and from outside
to threaten, manipulate, or embarrass; and revealing Such cases raise delicate questions about the
a source may put her at risk of anything from ostra- wider issue of respect for the autonomy of peoples
cism to assault. Not only may the publication of in- in other cultures and respect for their cognitive and
formation have bad consequences, there may also moral views. Anthropologists very generally do not

79
anthropology

share the central beliefs—in gods, in witchcraft, or ing ethical issues in anthropology are those that arise
in oracles, say—of the societies in which they work. from the considerable asymmetries of power and
At the same time they make it their business to un- wealth between the individuals and institutions of
derstand these views. This makes it possible for the European and American academy and those of
them to manipulate the people whose culture they the Third World. Anthropologists may, for example,
are studying; for example, to get them to provide find themselves able to take advantage of their rela-
information under false pretenses of one kind or tive wealth to pay informants for information the
another. Manipulation of this kind involves using informants would not willingly give without pay-
people as means rather than ends in the way that ment. In circumstances of extreme poverty such pay-
Immanuel KANT (1724–1804) would rule out by re- ments are plainly exploitative.
spect for their autonomy. It has also been argued recently that anthropol-
But the differences between what the anthropol- ogists have displayed too little sensitivity to issues of
ogist knows and what people in the culture know acknowledgment. Failing to acknowledge the con-
also raise questions of PATERNALISM. What duties, tribution of theorists who are members of the cul-
for example, does an anthropologist, who is working ture under study, when such help would certainly be
in a culture not her own, have toward people she acknowledged if it came from a Western student or
knows are in danger from the practices they engage colleague, also constitutes a form of EXPLOITATION.
in? If an anthropologist fails to persuade such peo-
See also: AUTONOMY OF MORAL AGENTS; CULTURAL
ple of these dangers, because they have radically dif-
STUDIES; EXPLOITATION; MORAL RELATIVISM; PATER-
ferent theories of how the world works, does respect
NALISM; PROFESSIONAL ETHICS; SECRECY AND
for autonomy require the anthropologist to allow the
CONFIDENTIALITY.
people to proceed unhindered? Or does the fact that
these people are not properly informed allow over-
riding their autonomy in ways that seem appropriate Bibliography
in other cases: for example, with children? That chil- Van Olden, J. F. “Anthropology and Ethics: Annotated
dren are the obvious model here indicates that mak- Bibliography.” Sociologische Gids 19, no. 5–6 (Sept.–
ing these decisions raises substantial risks of eth- Dec. 1972): 404–19.
nocentrism. But what if the people in question are
Kwame A. Appiah
children, and the beliefs that threaten them are those
of their parents?
Anthropologists influenced by Herskovits—un-
like Herskovits himself—have sometimes held that anti-realism
it is always wrong to intervene in such cases, appar- See metaphysics and epistemology; moral realism;
ently on the basis of the argument that the truth of moral relativism.
MORAL RELATIVISM requires it. While this seems a
poor argument, it is certainly true that interventions
by outsiders who are insufficiently informed are of-
ten counterproductive—there is an argument here
applied ethics
from epistemic modesty; and that considerations of Conceived broadly, applied ethics is the application
respect for autonomy strongly argue against over- of ethical considerations—reasons, principles, val-
ruling the decisions of any agent in circumstances ues, ideals—to any policy or practice—personal or
where they flow in the normal way from her beliefs social—for the purpose of evaluating (and thus en-
and values. dorsing or rejecting) that policy or practice on eth-
ical grounds. Thus, applied ethics is the branch of
PRACTICAL REASONING in which ethical (as opposed
Exploitation
to prudential or selfish) considerations are employed
Finally, there are ethical issues raised by the fact to guide individual and collective conduct.
that anthropologists have by and large come from Applied ethics is to be contrasted with other phil-
rich nations and institutions and worked in poor osophical undertakings in ethics, notably META-
nations among poor people. Some of the most press- ETHICS (the analysis of ethical concepts and ethical

80
applied ethics

reasoning), normative ethics (the study of the (medicine, business, JOURNALISM, etc.). Applied
NORMS used in making ethical judgments), and eth- ethics is more inclusive, however, since not all prac-
ical theory (the comprehensive investigation of eth- tical problems requiring ethical reflection fall con-
ical problems, concepts, principles, reasoning, and veniently within the domain of any recognized pro-
judgments, their interconnections and justification). fession or vocation.
Applied ethics is a part, perhaps the major part,
of applied philosophy generally; and the terms ‘ap-
History
plied ethics’ and ‘applied philosophy’ are often used
Applied ethics has attracted at least the passing as synonyms. Taken strictly, however, the two fields
attention of the greatest thinkers, from SOCRATES’ are distinct. Insofar as applied philosophy addresses
(c. 470–399 B.C.E.) defense of his refusal to escape problems in art, education, law, politics, etc., and
from undeserved PUNISHMENT to Bertrand RUS- insofar as these problems are not solely ethical, ap-
SELL’s (1872–1970) defense of CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE plied philosophy is much the broader field.
to protest deploying atomic weapons. Other exam-
ples include LOCKE (1632–1704) on religious TOL-
The Role of Theory
ERATION, HUME (1632–1704) on SUICIDE, KANT
(1724–1804) on lying to prevent HARM to the in- The proper role of ethical theory in applied ethics
nocent, BENTHAM (1748–1832) on the French Dec- is controversial. Indeed, what that role should be
laration of the Rights of Man, JOHN STUART MILL constitutes the principal problem in the theory of
(1806–1873) on EQUALITY between the sexes, applied ethics.
NIETZSCHE (1844–1900) on punishment, DEWEY At the one extreme are those philosophers who
(1859–1952) on DEMOCRACY in America, and argue, in effect as PLATO (c. 430–347 B.C.E.) does,
SARTRE (1905–1980) on GENOCIDE in Vietnam. that unless applied ethics is clearly and adequately
As a study of these examples will confirm, no one rooted in ethical theory, it is no better than a re-
style of investigation and argument is practiced by sourceful defense of prejudice. The very term ‘ap-
philosophers in the field of applied ethics. Hetero- plied ethics’ suggests a top-down application of eth-
geneity is one of the hallmarks of applied ethics— ical theory or of an ethical norm to a practical
its problems, methods, and results. Applied ethics problem. On this view, a major problem is which
also offers opportunities for philosophers to apply ethical theory or norm to apply, since there is more
theory to concrete cases; Bentham’s attack on the than one and the practical dictates of the various
“anarchical fallacies” of the French Declaration of theories and norms are not identical in all cases.
1789, for example, is a vivid case study of his posi- Thus, a utilitarian and a Kantian might agree that it
tivistic UTILITARIANISM. is wrong to lie, even in a good cause, but their rea-
soning would be quite different. In other cases, e.g.,
whether murderers ought to be punished with death,
Related Fields
both the reasoning and the conclusions reached by
Applied ethics includes traditional CASUISTRY — a Kantian and a utilitarian are likely to be different.
the application of ethical reflection to cases of prac- At the other extreme are those who argue, as AR-
tical concern. Like casuistry, applied ethics is typi- ISTOTLE (384–322 B.C.E.) in effect does, that—since
cally situational rather than abstract, in the sense no known ethical system is complete and ade-
that the reflective task is focused on an actual prob- quate—no independent theoretical fulcrum exists
lem rather than on any broader issue. However, in- on which to turn practical arguments one way or the
sofar as casuistry has a distinctive method (“the other. Instead, an ethical theory must itself be tested
method of cases”), is confined to cases where MORAL for its adequacy by its practical implications and not
RULES apparently conflict, and is designed to assist the other way around. The main danger here is that
some actual agent in deciding what to do, applied uncriticized moral intuitions (e.g., the principles un-
ethics is much broader and less well defined. reflectively accepted that underlie the prevailing so-
Applied ethics also includes PROFESSIONAL cial practices of this or that subculture) may come
ETHICS, the reflection on the ethical aspects of issues to dominate more systematic and principled
and problems that arise within particular vocations thinking.

81
applied ethics

In recent years, under the influence of John nature of the case to determine which woman was
RAWLS, a third alternative has emerged. On this view, the biological parent, he proposed dividing the in-
we should seek a reciprocal interaction between ab- fant and giving half to each claimant. Immediately
stract theory (which provides the method for choos- one of the women waived her claim in favor of the
ing principles; in Rawls’s case they will be principles other. Then Solomon in his wisdom awarded the
chosen in the original position behind a veil of igno- baby to the first woman; she had provided the best
rance) and considered judgments about actual cases evidence of a readiness to sacrifice for the welfare
(which serve as provisional fixed points for our sub- of the infant, as a true mother (whether the biologi-
stantive judgments, e.g., that the murder of innocent cal parent or not) would do. Solomon’s genius lay
children is a grave wrong), with the aim of obtaining in adopting a stratagem for discovering which claim-
a wide REFLECTIVE EQUILIBRIUM between the two. ant was worthy of maternal responsibility. Modern
Philosophers have used wide reflective equilibrium GAME THEORY nicely vindicates Solomon’s shrewd
mainly to justify choice of ethical or political princi- behavior. But rarely do we have such a clear-cut
ples, but it can also be used to reach solutions to method to achieve the ethically preferred outcome;
practical problems in a manner superior to either the the paradigm case of fair division between two per-
Platonic or Aristotelian methods described above. sons, in which one of them cuts and the other
chooses, has few applications or parallels in real life.
Triage during wartime (or other) disaster consti-
Methods
tutes a familiar strategy for allocating scarce re-
The simplest method of reasoning in applied sources. The task is to classify casualties for appro-
ethics is to give advice or render a judgment based priate treatment, aiming both to conserve medical
on the application of an accepted norm to the prob- resources and preserve the effectiveness of the army
lem case: If lying is wrong, and someone is about to in the field. Sorting casualties into three (not two and
tell a lie, then what that person is about to do is not four or more) categories will suffice: those whose
wrong. This turns applied ethics into an exercise in wounds will cause them to die; those who can be
deductive reasoning from two premises: one that ex- saved but only by major hospitalization; and those
presses the sole relevant ethical consideration (rule, less seriously wounded. The first group should re-
principle, ideal, etc.), and the other that character- ceive only pain medication. The second should be
izes the case at hand in such a manner as to enable sent to the rear for further attention. For the remain-
the ethical considerations to be applied to it. der, they should be treated immediately and returned
A more complex example with these same basic to their units as quickly as possible. A utilitarian
features appears in the standard argument for phy- would see such triage as a strategy to maximize fight-
sician assistance in dying: On the assumption that ing potential and minimize suffering and so the best
patient autonomy ought to be protected and re- thing to do. A Kantian would view triage as giving
spected, and that the patient in question is dying and equal consideration to each of the wounded soldiers,
wants medical help to ease the passage to death, followed by treatment fairly apportioned in the cir-
medical personnel ought to provide such assistance. cumstances. Soldiers behind a veil of ignorance ought
In each of the cases above, simplicity is achieved by to accept the treatment allotted for each category, no
assuming that exactly one norm applies and that it matter into which category they individually might
applies without exceptions. fall were they to be wounded.
However, most actual cases—whether of interest Argument over ABORTION is more complex. First,
to the ordinary person or to the philosopher, so far it is clear that no one moral rule applies with decisive
as neither is in the rigid grip of a normative theory— consequences. For example, causing the DEATH of a
are much more complex. The diversity of problems nonviable human embryo does not obviously violate
and approaches to them can be illustrated by con- the moral rule against murder. On the other hand,
sidering three very different kinds of examples that the principle that one may do as one pleases with
involve ethical decision making. one’s own PROPERTY (including the contents of one’s
According to the Bible (I Kings 3:17–28), Solo- body) hardly applies with dispositive force, either.
mon had to decide which of two women claimants Yet each of these considerations points to relevant
was the “real” mother of the infant. Unable in the concerns, albeit with opposite effect: respect for hu-

82
applied ethics

man life and respect for women’s autonomy. Second, through their publications, conferences, and work-
deciding what are the relevant facts to which a prin- shops. Pioneering the field is The Hastings Center
ciple can be attached is controversial: Is it the fact (New York), founded in 1969 with a focus on BIO-
that the embryo or fetus is alive, or that it is human ETHICS. Most such centers are affiliated with univer-
progeny, or that it is a potential person (assuming sity departments of philosophy, such as the Center
normal development) that matters? Or is what mat- for Philosophy and Public Affairs (University of
ters whatever concerns the impact of the pregnancy Maryland, 1976), the Center for the Study of Values
and subsequent responsibilities that would fall to the (University of Delaware, 1977), the Center for Val-
woman in question? Several principles and various ues and Social Policy (University of Colorado,
facts all seem relevant, and perhaps none is decisive. 1979), and the Social Philosophy and Policy Center
(Bowling Green State University, Ohio, 1981).
Interdisciplinary Tendencies
Journals and Encyclopedias
In actual controversial cases (e.g., Ought CAPITAL
PUNISHMENT be abolished? Was the Gulf War a just Although articles in applied ethics have from time
war? Ought affirmative action be abolished? Does to time appeared in almost every professional jour-
FAIRNESS require a flat tax?), it is often extremely nal in philosophy (notably, in Ethics, founded in
difficult to obtain an accurate and complete account 1890), the desire to provide a regular forum for
of all the relevant facts. those interested primarily in this field has led to the
In addition, the necessary factual information can founding of several quarterlies devoted to problems
often be obtained only by practitioners in the field in applied ethics: Social Theory and Practice
and by using the methods of the social sciences (sta- (1970–), Philosophy and Public Affairs (1971–),
tistics, survey research, etc.). As a result, philoso- Social Philosophy and Policy (1983–), Journal of
phers engaged in applied ethics must rely on experts Applied Philosophy (1984–), and Public Affairs
in the pertinent fields to provide them with the rele- Quarterly (1987–). A comprehensive account of is-
vant data, or they must develop the skills to gather sues, problems, and methods can be found in the
their own data. Applied ethics independent of em- Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics, three volumes,
pirical information is like Hamlet without the Prince 1977. Biomedical issues have their own comprehen-
of Denmark. sive treatment in Encyclopedia of Bioethics, 2d,
1995.

Ethicists as Experts See also (in addition to the many articles on specific
moral issues): ACADEMIC ETHICS; AGRICULTURAL
Philosophers who study and teach applied ethics ETHICS; ANIMALS, TREATMENT OF; BIOETHICS; BUSI-
(often now called “ethicists,” especially in the field NESS ETHICS; CASUISTRY; CHILDREN AND ETHICAL
of biomedical ethics) have begun to play a profes- THEORY; CONSERVATION ETHICS; CORRECTIONAL
sional role as consultants and investigators, provid- ETHICS; ENGINEERING ETHICS; ENVIRONMENTAL
ing expert advice, evidence, and testimony in many ETHICS; GOVERNMENT, ETHICS IN; INTERNATIONAL
different institutional settings. Since the 1970s, phi- JUSTICE; JOURNALISM; LAND ETHICS; LEGAL ETHICS;
losophers have served as members of various com- LIBRARY AND INFORMATION PROFESSIONS; MASS ME-
missions (primarily on issues of MEDICAL ETHICS), DIA; MEDICAL ETHICS; NUCLEAR ETHICS; NURSING
testified before legislative committees and PUBLIC ETHICS; POLICE ETHICS; PRINCIPLISM; PROFESSIONAL
POLICY panels, and have performed other duties in
ETHICS; PUBLIC POLICY; REFLECTIVE EQUILIBRIUM;
which their ability to identify and evaluate the ethi- SEXUALITY AND SEXUAL ETHICS; SITUATION ETHICS;
cal impact of various policies and practices has been SLIPPERY SLOPE ARGUMENTS; SPORT; THEORY AND
utilized. PRACTICE; WELFARE RIGHTS AND SOCIAL POLICY.

Research Centers Bibliography


In recent years, the study and practice of applied Bedau, Hugo Adam. Making Mortal Choices: Three Ex-
ethics has been concentrated at research centers ercises in Moral Casuistry. New York: Oxford Univer-

83
applied ethics

sity Press, 1997. Close scrutiny of three cases (two of deeds, both good and evil, would win immortal
them hypothetical) involving life-and-death choices. fame.
Brams, Stephen. Biblical Games: A Strategic Analysis of Though she never explicitly renounced her earlier
Stories in the Old Testament. Cambridge: MIT Press,
1980. Application of game theory to various biblical
nonmoral conception of political action, Arendt’s
stories, including Solomon’s judgment in awarding the later works, beginning with the controversial Eich-
infant. mann in Jerusalem (1963), amount in fact to a sus-
Daniels, Norman. Justice and Justification: Reflective tained effort to remoralize the theory of political ac-
Equilibrium in Theory and Practice. New York: Cam- tion. They thus mark a break with her own earlier
bridge University Press, 1996. A detailed discussion of work; they also form one of the twentieth century’s
the method of wide reflective equilibrium and appli-
most distinguished bodies of writing on MORAL PSY-
cation to several problems in health care. Bibliography.
CHOLOGY. In Eichmann Arendt developed her most
DeMarco, Joseph P., and Richard M. Fox, eds. New Di-
rections in Ethics: The Challenge of Applied Ethics. famous concept, the “banality of evil.” She discov-
London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1986. Nineteen ered in Adolf Eichmann (1906–1962) a “banal”
essays by contemporary authors on the nature of ap- mass murderer moved by no monstrous intentions,
plied ethics and related issues. ideological convictions, or insanity. Eichmann’s
Rosenthal, David M., and Fadlou Shehadi, eds. Applied moral infirmity lay in an inability to think from the
Ethics and Ethical Theory. Salt Lake City: University point of view of others, and therefore to think at all.
of Utah Press, 1988. Essays by contemporary writers
exploring the tasks of applied ethics, its usefulness, fea-
From this infirmity arose, on the one hand, Eich-
sibility, and relation to theory. mann’s striking lack of psychological and even per-
Singer, Peter, ed. Applied Ethics. Oxford: Oxford Univer- sonal identity over time, and, on the other hand, his
sity Press, 1986. Reprints fourteen essays on as many lack of moral judgment.
topics, including two classics (Hume on suicide, J. S. Arendt developed both sides of this argument in
Mill on the death penalty). Bibliography. the important essay “Thinking and Moral Consid-
Hugo Adam Bedau erations” (1971). She identifies the capacity for
thought with the ability to divide one’s point of view
and conduct an internal dialogue. It is this capacity,
she claims, that makes possible both consciousness
Aquinas and CONSCIENCE —personal identity and moral judg-
See Thomas Aquinas, Saint. ment. But she admits puzzlement about how think-
ing works to insulate us from bad judgment. This
question motivates her final work in moral psychol-
ogy, the incomplete Life of the Mind (1978) and the
Arendt, Hannah (1906–1975) posthumously assembled Lectures on Kant’s Politi-
Born in Königsberg, East Prussia (now Kaliningrad, cal Philosophy (1982).
Russia); emigrated to France, 1933, and to the Arendt laid special emphasis on the faculty of
United States, 1941. judgment—the capacity to assess actions without
Before 1960, Arendt was best known for two appealing to rules. It seemed clear to her that sound
books. In The Origins of Totalitarianism (1951) she judgment, and not faithfulness to MORAL RULES or
analyzed “the burden of our time”: the thorough- to a procedure of moral assessment, is the key to
going eradication of political freedom by totalitarian decency. (Throughout her writing she insists that
regimes, accomplished through ideology and terror. concrete stories, not theories, are the source of
The Human Condition (1958) elaborated her re- meaning for us.) She hoped to elaborate on Imman-
sponse to that “burden,” a revival of the Greek idea uel KANT’s (1724–1804) thought that judgment
that political action is the freest, most characteris- arises from an “enlarged mentality” whereby one se-
tically human, and most meaningful form of activity. rially adopts representative standpoints (Critique of
Though morally motivated, Arendt’s classical con- Judgment, Sect. 40). But she died with only the title
ception of politics was a nonmoralized one. She was and epigraphs of her book on judgment written.
concerned to vindicate the value of political action Arendt has had little influence on Anglo-American
as such, not just good political action; she quotes ethical theory. This is to be regretted. Arguing as she
with approval Pericles’s boast that Athens’s great does that personal identity requires the capacity to

84
Aristotelian ethics

adopt external standpoints, Arendt is close to phi- Hinchman, Lewis P. and Sandra K. Hinchman, eds.
losophers such as Thomas Nagel and Derek Parfit Hanna Arendt: Critical Essays. Albany, NY: SUNY
Press, 1994.
who have examined related theories. And her em-
Kateb, George. Hannah Arendt: Politics, Conscience,
phasis on the priority of moral judgment over sys- Evil. Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Allanheld, 1983. Con-
tematic morality places her work in natural sympa- tains a bibliography of works about Arendt.
thy with the many contemporary philosophers who Villa, Dana Richard. The Cambridge Companion to Han-
share her interests in CHARACTER, judgment, and nah Arendt. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
the importance of concrete narratives for moral 2000.
philosophy. Young-Bruehl, Elisabeth. Hannah Arendt: For Love of the
World. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1982. Con-
See also: CHARACTER; CONSCIENCE; EXTERNALISM tains a complete bibliography of Arendt’s works.
AND INTERNALISM; KANT; LIBERTY; MORAL PSY-
CHOLOGY; MORAL REASONING; NARRATIVE ETHICS;
David Luban
PRACTICAL REASON[ING]; SELF-KNOWLEDGE; SOCIAL
AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY; SYMPATHY.
arete
Bibliography See excellence; virtues.

Works by Arendt
Arendt published 140 articles and 9 books (in English) Aristotelian ethics
during her lifetime; 4 more books appeared posthumously Much of current moral theorizing is spent in an ef-
as have several volumes of her correspondence. Listed
fort to tailor the moral theories of historically
here are only those most important for her moral
philosophy. prominent thinkers or schools of thought to the
Between Past and Future: Eight Exercises in Political complexities of the contemporary human condi-
Thought. Rev. ed. New York: Viking, 1968 [1961]. tion. Fueling this is a conviction that very real
Crises of the Republic. New York: Harcourt Brace Jova- moral gains are to be achieved by bringing the his-
novich, 1972. tory of ethics to bear on modern life. As a result,
Eichmann in Jerusalem: A Report on the Banality of Evil. we have neo-Aristotelianism, NEO-STOICISM, neo-
Rev. ed. New York: Viking, 1965 [1963]. Kantianism, and neo-Hegelianism. We have not yet
The Human Condition. Chicago: University of Chicago seen a revival of EPICUREANISM, perhaps because we
Press, 1958.
are not yet that far removed from the popular culture
Lectures on Kant’s Political Philosophy. Edited and with
an interpretive essay by Ronald Beiner. Chicago: Uni-
of the 1960s when being “laid back” was a crude
versity of Chicago Press, 1982. substitute for ataraxia. Nor does it seem that there
The Life of the Mind. Edited by Mary McCarthy. New is that much movement on the UTILITARIANISM
York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1978. front, a view thatby its very name discourages nos-
Men in Dark Times. New York: Harcourt, Brace and talgia and by its method any robust need for history.
World, 1968. What is it, then, that has led many to look back to
“Thinking and Moral Considerations: A Lecture.” Social thinkers of the past to find the key to the future re-
Research 38 (1971): 417–46. garding ethics, and what must any view with his-
torical roots in Aristotle (or the Stoics, or Kant, or
Works about Arendt Hegel) provide if it is to be adequate to the lives of
Of the dozens of works on Arendt, many recent, the fol- contemporary persons? Finally, is there anything
lowing are particularly crucial for understanding her con- that might favor Aristotelian prospects over opti-
tributions to ethics. mistic competitors or pessimistic postmodernists?
Beiner, Ronald. “Hannah Arendt on Judging.” In Lectures One way to focus debate is in terms of PRACTICAL
on Kant’s Political Philosophy, 89–156. Chicago: Uni-
REASON: What is it for contemporary persons to be
versity of Chicago Press, 1982.
practically rational in regard to the complex prob-
Bernstein, Richard J. “Judging—The Actor and the Spec-
tator.” In his Philosophical Profiles: Essays in a Prag- lems of modernity? First, posing this question ex-
matic Mode, 221–37. Philadelphia: University of Penn- plains why there is an inquiry in the first place. Mod-
sylvania Press, 1986. ern persons seem to be groping for a way to think

85
Aristotelian ethics

rationally about the complexities of their lives, and for neo-Aristotelians is constructing a view from Ar-
a major part of the problem seems to be a conflict istotle that is adequate to the contemporary person’s
of frameworks. Some of our moral history regarding cosmopolitan values. The task for neo-Kantians is
practical reason has a lineage to ARISTOTLE (384– constructing a view from Kant that is adequate to
322 B.C.E.) and the pre-Hellenistic Greeks; other as- the contemporary person’s personal values.
pects go back through KANT (1724–1804) and Viewed from this perspective, some neo-Aristo-
Christianity to the Stoics. Still others seem to find telian attempts seem doomed to failure, simply be-
their home in medieval Christianity. Hence all the cause they do not make sufficient place for those
competitors are conservative in regard to postmod- beyond personal borders. At least, this seems to be
ernist options: they all think that the key to modern a widely held opinion of the fate of Alasdair MAC-
reason lies in realizing how to adjust the insights of INTYRE’s project. Aristotelian communitarianism
the past to the complexities of the present. Second, seems too cloistered to house our cosmopolitan
focusing the debate in this way explains why, to date, needs and aspirations. Other forms of COMMUNITAR-
the major competitors are Aristotelian and Kantian IANISM, such as Charles TAYLOR’s, seem to suffer
(though the Stoics are beginning to mount an of- similar difficulties, though they are more traceable
fense). Why? Because both Aristotle and Kant had to HEGEL (1770–1831) than to Aristotle. But even
developed views on practical reason. if these views fail for their inability to address our
The most pressing complexities to be addressed cosmopolitan concerns, they nonetheless pose a
by any updated version of either Aristotle or Kant challenge to more cosmopolitan-oriented theories,
include at least two crucial matters: the relationship such as are found in Kant and the Stoics and their
between partial and impartial concerns—between progeny. Our social values place too high a premium
near and distantly related persons—and the need to on the values of family, friendship, and community
acknowledge adequately the tragic dimensions of to be subsumed in some way under a concern for
life. Contemporary persons are, by and large, cos- universal justice or BENEVOLENCE.
mopolitan by necessity rather than choice. It is sim- Moreover, MacIntyre seems to have won an im-
ply quite difficult to remain parochial in one’s moral portant part of the debate, namely, that practical rea-
concerns given that the complexities of our daily son is narratival, which requires that in order for an
lives present us with the necessity of recognizing the agent’s actions to be comprehensible as options they
value of others who are much different from us and must be placed within a context that is thickly de-
who are not related to us through various personal scribed in a way that makes essential reference to a
bonds, such as familial affection, FRIENDSHIP, and meaningful life from the agent’s own point of view.
community or cultural LOYALTY. On the other hand, The evidence that MacIntyre (and Bernard WIL-
however cosmopolitan we are in our concerns, the LIAMS and others) have won this part of the debate
ties of love of FAMILY, of friends, of community must is that contemporary Kantians are now concerned to
be robust for most of us to have any reasons to live show that Kant can and must be understood to allow
at all. Without these ties, ALIENATION seems the for this requirement. In this sense, contemporary
more likely result than either rationality or libera- Kantians are less concerned to maintain as radical a
tion. Much the same can be said for the value of distinction between kinds of moral schemes as either
aesthetic activity, meaningful activity that we find Kant himself or the early RAWLS were. By abandon-
interesting, fascinating, captivating, and the like, in- ing the notion that the right is prior to the good and
dependent of its service to humanity or to our loved by accepting the narratival nature of practical rea-
ones. Life has to be interesting to some degree to be son, contemporary Kantians think they can provide
worth living, and any theory of practical reason that both a satisfactory cosmopolitanism and a concep-
is indifferent to these nonsocial concerns is simply tual scheme rich in personal values.
overly moralized. So construed, the Aristotelian victory is less than
In regard to the issue of the relationship between ultimate because it requires only a reshaping of Kan-
the personal and the impersonal, Kant would seem tian boundaries so that what is right in Aristotle can
to offer more of a solution to the problems of the be annexed into Kantian territory; it does not require
cosmopolitan self and Aristotle more regarding the Kantians to abandon the field. Indeed, the ultimate
problems of the personal self. In this regard, the task victory belongs to Kant, or so the story goes.

86
Aristotelian ethics

The Kantian reconstruction of Aristotle (so argue that, within this framework, we can assimilate what-
the revisionists) must and can be expressed narra- ever is salvageable from Aristotle to Kant. Hence,
tively in terms of the flourishing of a rational agent, we can have both the personal and the cosmopoli-
and the structure of Kantian narrative, which is tan, thickness of character and a morally expansive
thick with the personal and broad with the cosmo- will, within a Kantian framework.
politan, is roughly as follows. Rational human be- The prospects for a contemporary Aristotelian
ings come to the task of practical reason with a va- view that resists assimilation by this neo-Kantian
riety of ends, some of which are subordinate to program must demonstrate the ways in which it dif-
others but nonetheless are valued as ends rather fers from the Kantian view and its structure of du-
than as mere means. But there is one end that is of ties; it must establish a plausible cosmopolitanism
a different value and more central to the flourishing without sacrificing the real value of the personal;
of a rational agent than any other value. This is the and it must establish itself as a better alternative
value of our rational nature or rational agency, than postmodernist alternatives.
which is our ability to set ends for ourselves in a way Perhaps the most visible attempt at an Aristote-
that is consistent with the equal value of any other lian solution to the cosmopolitan problem is made
rational being to set ends for him- or herself. All by Martha Nussbaum. The project begins with an
other ends, on this view, are subordinate to this end attempt to isolate a set of what she calls nonrelative
in the sense that the value of our rational nature virtues that have their foundation in the fact that we
regulates all our other ends: in cases of conflict we are human beings rather than gods or beasts. Both
never compromise on the value of our rational eudaimonia (living well) and virtue are understood
agency. The capacity for a good will is what gives us in terms of basic capacities, which are functional ca-
our DIGNITY, and this dignity is absolutely inviolable pacities of an organism that are central to its living.
in regard to other values. Thus, whatever personal A basic capacity for a god is one thing; for a beast,
values we have need not be derived from the value another; and for a human being, something else en-
of human dignity—they can have their own inde- tirely. Accordingly, accounts of eudaimonia and the
pendent irreducible value—but the place they have virtues internal to a way of life for a particular kind
in our lives when we flourish as rational agents must of organism depend on whether the organism is a
be regulated by the concern for respect for human god, a beast, or a human. The hope of this approach
dignity as an absolute and inviolable value. is that there is some set of basic capacities that hu-
So morality is roughly divided into perfect and man beings have in virtue of being human rather
imperfect duties. Perfect duties take priority over than being divine or beastly that will serve as the
imperfect duties and are more strict in the actions basis for a set of nonrelative virtues.
they require than imperfect duties. Keeping prom- Specification of the content of any virtue included
ises and CONTRACTS, telling the truth, avoiding SUI- in a set of virtues proceeds from the thinnest account
CIDE, gaining and honoring CONSENT, not interfering of human capacities to thicker accounts. The thin-
with autonomous choices, and considerations of jus- nest account is one that applies most broadly to hu-
tice are salient duties of this sort. Here the notion is mans as humans rather than as beasts or as gods.
that some aspects of the value of rational agency are But even when the thinnest set is isolated, the con-
so fundamental that they leave little room for indi- tent of these virtues is specified at different levels of
vidual latitude about what is to be done and they are concreteness. Typically Aristotelian virtues like
lexically prior to other considerations of agency. COURAGE, moderation, justice, for example, are
Considerations of humanity in the cosmopolitan likely to be in the thinnest set because unlike gods
sense reign supreme. Imperfect duties, on the other humans must have the capacity to control fear in the
hand, commit us to certain obligatory ends: perfect- face of danger and to moderate their appetites, and
ing our CHARACTER, developing our talents, and con- unlike either beasts or gods they must cooperate
tributing to the HAPPINESS of others. And it is under with others in the expression of their sociality. The
these obligatory ends that we have obligations that content of virtues, however, is specified more locally
apply more to the personal, less cosmopolitan as- in cultural and historical context.
pects of human dignity. What the mean is regarding any virtue, say, cour-
There is an extensive literature that tries to show age, moderation, or magnanimity, is specified not

87
Aristotelian ethics

just in terms of being human rather being beastly or of relative rationality and differ from Nussbaum in
divine, but also in terms of humanly contingent fac- being more agnostic or skeptical about nonrelative
tors like being a parent rather than childless, being rationality or virtue. Henry Richardson develops a
female rather than male, or being Chinese rather conception of practical reason that is Aristotelian in
than American. These thicker specifications of the spirit that accommodates the capacity within prac-
content of particular virtues are all various functions tical reason to deliberate about final and even ulti-
of our being human understood in terms of more mate ends. Richardson argues that in order for de-
generalized descriptions of our basic capacities but liberation about final ends to be possible, the
concretely tailored in their expression to specific his- regulative relationships among practical ends must
torical and cultural contexts. be bidirectional. Moreover, he argues that there can
The basis for an Aristotelian cosmopolitanism is be conflicts among our ends that are incommensu-
the understanding that the thicker, more local spec- rable. This requires a construction of an Aristoteli-
ifications of the content of a set of virtues are all anism according to which eudaimonia is not a com-
functions of a common humanity. Thus we see same- mensurans for the ordering of ends in cases of
ness in diversity and difference. The idea then is to conflict. Rather, the ends of practical reason are mu-
spell out a conception of minimal human worth tually supporting, none of which are immune to re-
based on the notion of basic human capacities. A vision in the deliberative attempt to further specify
successful account should yield a result that distin- our ends.
guishes the Kantian agent from the Aristotelian If Richardson is correct that relative rationality
agent. This will mean that the Aristotelian concep- begins with a set of ends and proceeds with refining
tion of the worth of persons as a function of dis- a conception of those ends through the employment
tinctively human capacities will not reduce to the of practical reason in concrete particular situations
Kantian notion of the value of autonomy. The rec- that require ACTION, then human dignity cannot be
ognition of the worth of persons as having certain the kind of end Kantians claim that it is. For it is a
basic capacities will regulate the place of more local crucial feature of the Kantian view that the value of
specifications of what we think is good character rational agency is an end that is not subject to revi-
and good living in a way that is analogous to the way sion through deliberation. It is not an end that is
in which respect for autonomy regulates our more bidirectionally related to other ends. Richardson’s
personal commitments on the Kantian view. By thin- conception of mutually supportable ends that are bi-
ning the basis for the worth of persons, Nussbaum directionally related leaves open the possibility that
hopes to avoid some of the problems charged by we can revise our ends in such a way that we care a
postmodernists that any cosmopolitan view is in the great deal about those who do not stand within our
end a form of parochialism. Should such a project personal borders and the central focus of our lives
succeed there could be little room for postmodernist is more personal and local in orientation. The Aris-
charges of cultural imperialism in the guise of uni- totelian task, then, is to start where we are (with
versal morality as there is when Kantians insist on relative rationality) and see if the project of a ra-
ideals of autonomy against cultural ideals that place tional specification of our ends yields an equilibrium
less value than the Kantian scheme can allow. of mutually supporting ends that reflects both a ro-
Nussbaum is also concerned to address the issue bust cosmopolitanism and a thickly personal life. So
of TRAGEDY, and it is not yet clear how the tragic unlike Nussbaum’s strategy, Richardson builds from
aspect of life is depicted on the Aristotelian scheme the bottom up, from the thick ends that we do have
she is ultimately going to endorse, but it is nonethe- to the possibility of a more expansive concern for
less a central concern of her project. One very im- humanity. Whereas, Nussbaum’s strategy is top
portant aspect of the problem of tragedy for her will down: she first articulates a set of nonrelative vir-
be the nature of practical reason when cosmopolitan tues and then attempts to show how a person hav-
values come into irresolvable conflict with the per- ing that set is culturally sensitive to more local con-
sonal, as they surely can, even on her view. Whether cerns. Both recognize tragic, rationally irresolvable
and to what extent this kind of project will succeed conflicts.
is a story now in the telling. Another attempt to develop an Aristotelian con-
Other appeals to Aristotle make use of the notion ception of relative rationality (Harris 1999) begins

88
Aristotelian ethics

with a specific conception of good character and son committed to EXCELLENCE at what you do. The
provides an account of practical reason within it, task, then, is to provide an account of practical rea-
with the concept of INTEGRITY playing a central role. son fitted to this thick conception of integrity that is
Presented in the second person to emphasize the a competitor to recent Kantian accounts. For on the
agent-centeredness of practical reason, the account Kantian view, a good person would be described as
conceives of practical reason as an integrative psy- person who fits the description of the thick concep-
chological function that allows you (the agent) to tion of integrity.
integrate in a coherent way the various practical con- Juxtaposed, then, are both recent Kantian ac-
cerns and commitments you have. counts and the proposed Aristotelian alternative:
In any particular concrete situation, the task of both attempt to account for how such a person could
practical reason is to find a way to integrate the vari- rationally integrate all the concerns that a person of
ous concerns and commitments you have so that you integrity in the thick sense would have in various
can see a coherent way into the future either with kinds of problematic situations. Similarly juxta-
your commitments intact or with a revised set of posed are Kantian accounts and a proposed Aristo-
commitments. Otherwise, integrity cannot be main- telian account of practical deliberation. It is argued
tained. Hence, this integration test is the ultimate that a conception of practical reason in which all its
test for an acceptable account of practical reason. NORMS are symmetrical (bidirectional in Richard-
Normative beliefs, then, are rational insofar as they son’s sense) in their regulative functions requires
resolve for the person of integrity what PEIRCE that human dignity cannot be treated as the kind of
(1839–1914) and DEWEY (1859–1952) called value Kantians claim that it is for a person of this
“problematic situations,” situations that involve sort and the conception be able to pass the integra-
complex integration problems. tion test. Moreover, the proposed account, wherein
As with any conception of relative rationality, the the norm of human dignity is treated as symmetri-
kinds of integration problems you face depend on cally related in its regulative functions within prac-
the kinds of concerns and commitments you start tical reason to other more local normative concerns
out with, and your starting point says something (family, friends, work, and culture), can pass the in-
about the kind of person you are. It is in this sense tegration test, while providing a more plausible ac-
that practical reason is character-relative. The ac- count of the latitude of practical reason than the ac-
count diverges in its structure from the accounts of count of perfect and imperfect duties found in the
both Nussbaum and Richardson, because unlike Kantian literature. The Aristotelian criteria of final-
Nussbaum’s, it does not start with a commitment to ity and self-sufficiency are given direct roles in prac-
a nonrelative account of practical reason and virtue, tical deliberation and are employed to bring coher-
and unlike Richardson’s, it does not simply begin ence to what Barbara Herman has called an agent’s
with concrete situations and reason up to a set of deliberative field—better, it is argued, than the best,
mutually supporting ends. Rather, it asks, what kind most recent interpretations of the Kantian Categor-
of character would a person have who had both cos- ical Imperative. A theory of personality disintegra-
mopolitan concerns and a robust personal life with tion is presented that serves as an empirical con-
more local concerns? What thicker description straint on whether the integration test has been met.
could we give of you if we were to describe you as Both Kantian and Aristotelian alternatives are tested
such a person? across a broad range of practical contexts as they are
The thicker description given in the account, faced by a person who fits the thick description. Fi-
called the thick conception of integrity, is as follows: nally, by addressing issues of incommensurability in
you would be a respectful and sympathetic person concrete deliberative contexts, the account illus-
regarding those with whom you are not personally trates both some of the ineliminably tragic aspects
or specially attached; you would be a loving person of life that face human deliberation and some of the
in a variety of ways—(possibly and probably) a lov- limits of the unity of practical reason, a topic central
ing parent, a loving friend, and a loving neighbor; to an adequate response to POSTMODERNISM.
you would be a person who takes aesthetic delight Concessions of some sort to postmodernist views
(in a broad sense) in an extensive range of activities seem in order from any plausible historically ori-
valued for their own sake; and you would be a per- ented theory, whether it is Aristotelian, Kantian,

89
Aristotelian ethics

Stoic, or whatever. Both Aristotle and Kant, for ex- Broadie, Sarah. Ethics with Aristotle. London: Oxford
ample, held rather strong views regarding the unity University Press, 1993 (1991).
of the virtues and the unity of practical reason. What Engstrom, Stephen P., and Jennifer Whiting, eds. Aristotle,
Kant, and the Stoics. Cambridge: Cambridge Univer-
we now know about the brain alone makes it un-
sity Press, 1996.
likely that these views can be sustained through
Harris, George W. Dignity and Vulnerability: Strength and
further inquiry. But admitting this is a far from Quality of Character. Berkeley: University of California
conceding some of the more extreme views of self- Press, 1997.
fragmentation portrayed by some postmodernists. ———. Agent-Centered Morality: An Aristotelian Alter-
Moreover, our increasing understanding of incom- native to Kantian Internalism. Berkeley: University of
mensurable values through the work of thinkers like California Press, 1999.
Isaiah Berlin (1909–1997) requires a rethinking of Herman, Barbara. The Practice of Moral Judgment. Cam-
the nature of tragedy, something perhaps neither Ar- bridge: Harvard University Press, 1993.
istotle nor Kant understood well enough to ade- Hurka, Thomas. Perfectionism. Oxford: Oxford Univer-
sity Press, 1993.
quately address postmodernist worries. The issue,
Kenny, Anthony John Patrick. The Aristotelian Ethics: A
however, is whether it is best to adjust these his-
Study of the Relationship between the Eudemian and
torical conceptions of ethics to what we now know Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle. London: Oxford Uni-
and to what we now face in life, or do we in facing versity Press, 1978.
the future come to that task with a fragmented array Korsgaard, Christine M. Creating the Kingdom of Ends.
of irreconcilable cultural relics? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996.
There are many other Aristotelian projects related ———. The Sources of Normativity. Cambridge: Cam-
to issues in contemporary ethics of a less systematic bridge University Press, 1996.
scope than the ones explicitly discussed here, some MacIntyre, Alasdair. After Virtue. London: Duckworth,
of which are dealt with in the works listed in the 1981.
bibliography. Also, Thomas Hurka’s version of Ar- McDowell, John. Mind, Value, and Reality. Cambridge:
Harvard University Press, 1998.
istotelian PERFECTIONISM is not discussed here be-
Nussbaum, Martha. The Fragility of Goodness. Cam-
cause there is an independent entry on that subject
bridge: Cambridge University Press. 1986.
by Hurka himself.
———. “Aristotle on Human Nature and the Foundations
See also: ARISTOTLE; AUTONOMY OF MORAL AGENTS; of Ethics.” In World, Mind, and Ethics: Essays on the
Ethical Philosophy of Bernard Williams, edited by J.
COMMUNITARIANISM; COSMOPOLITAN ETHICS; CUL-
Altham and R. Harrison, 86–131. Cambridge: Cam-
TURAL STUDIES; DIGNITY; DUTY AND OBLIGATION;
bridge University Press, 1995.
EUDAIMONIA (ISM); IMPARTIALITY; INTEGRITY; KANT;
———. The Therapy of Desire: Theory and Practice in
KANTIAN ETHICS; LIFE, MEANING OF; MORAL COM- Hellenistic Ethics. Princeton: Princeton University
MUNITY, BOUNDARIES OF; MORAL RELATIVISM; MUL- Press, 1994.
TICULTURALISM; NARRATIVE ETHICS; NEO-KANTIAN Nussbaum, Martha, and Amartya Sen, eds. The Quality of
ETHICS; NEO-STOICISM; PARTIALITY; POSTMODERN- Life. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1993.
ISM; PRACTICAL REASON[ING]; RATIONAL CHOICE; O’Neill, Onora. Towards Justice and Virtue. Cambridge:
RATIONALITY VS. REASONABLENESS; SELF-KNOWL- Cambridge University Press, 1996.
EDGE; SELF-RESPECT; STOICISM; TAYLOR; WILLIAMS. Richardson, Henry S. Practical Reasoning about Final
Ends. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997
(1994).
Bibliography Sherman, Nancy. The Fabric of Character: Aristotle’s The-
ory of Virtue. New York: Oxford University Press,
Annas, Julia. The Morality of Happiness. New York: Ox- 1989.
ford University Press, 1993. ———. Making a Necessity of Virtue: Aristotle and Kant
Baron, Marcia. Kantian Ethics Almost without Apology. on Virtue. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1995. 1997.
Becker, Lawrence C. A New Stoicism. Princeton: Prince- Taylor, Charles. Sources of the Self: The Making of the
ton University Press, 1998. Modern Identity. Cambridge: Harvard University
Berlin, Isaiah. The Crooked Timber of Humanity: Chapters Press, 1989.
in the History of Ideas. Princeton: Princeton University Wiggins, David. Needs, Values, Truth. Oxford: Basil
Press, 1997 (1991). Blackwell, 1987.

90
Aristotle

Williams, Bernard. Moral Luck. Cambridge: Cambridge EN and the Politics as parts of a single inquiry (EN
University Press, 1981. 1181b12–23).
———. Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy. Cambridge:
An account of the human good, in Aristotle’s
Harvard University Press, 1985.
view, ought to show (a) what the VIRTUES of CHAR-
George W. Harris ACTER are, and why they are virtues; (b) why Plato
in the Republic is right to claim that we are always
better off if we have justice and the other virtues;
Aristotle (384–322 B.C.E.) and (c) how we should acquire the virtues. On these
Born in Stagira (Macedon), lived in Athens 367– questions Aristotle’s views are closer to Plato’s than
347, then in Lesbos, and in Macedon, before re- to SOCRATES’ (c. 470–399 B.C.E.) (MM 1182a15–
turning to Athens. Student of PLATO (c. 430–347 30, EE 1216b3–25, EN 1104b11–13, 1145b23–
B.C.E.); founder of the Lyceum school in Athens. 31). (He criticizes Plato, however, for introducing
the Form of the Good into ethical argument; he re-
jects the Theory of Forms in general, and thinks it is
Aristotle’s Ethical Works
in any case inappropriate to ethics [EN i 6].)
Aristotle’s ethical theory is mostly contained in
three treatises: the Magna Moralia (MM), the Eu-
The Human Good
demian Ethics (EE), and the Nicomachean Ethics
(EN). Some questions about the relation between Aristotle argues that a human being has an ulti-
these works are still unsettled: (1) The MM is widely mate good, an end that we want for its own sake,
agreed not to have been written by Aristotle. Some and for the sake of which we want other things
believe, however, that it is authentic in substance— (1094a18–19). This ultimate end is HAPPINESS, EU-
that it contains a student’s notes on an early course DAIMONIA (1095a14–20), for the sake of which all
of lectures by Aristotle. Others believe (less plausi- of us do all the other things (1102a2–3). If it is to
bly) that it is a post-Aristotelian compilation based be an ultimate end, happiness must be complete (or
on the EE and EN. (2) The EE is widely agreed to ‘final’, teleion) and self-sufficient (1097a15–b21).
be authentic. It is generally, but not universally, For if it is reasonable for us to choose everything for
taken to be earlier than the EN. (3) Three books (EN the sake of happiness, and happiness for the sake of
v–vii and EE iv–vi) are assigned by the manuscripts nothing else, then we must have reason to believe
to both the EE and the EN. They are fairly generally that no genuine intrinsic good lies outside happi-
believed to have been originally written for the EE; ness; for if there were any such good, then it would
but many critics believe they were partly rewritten not be clear why happiness (rather than happiness
to fit the EN. plus this further good) should be our ultimate end.
Though the differences between the ethical works Aristotle takes happiness to be comprehensive,
are not trivial, the area of agreement is very large. insofar as he claims that a self-sufficient good must,
This article ignores the differences, and is based all by itself, make life lacking in nothing. He de-
largely on the EN (all references refer to it unless scribes a test that implies the comprehensiveness of
indicated otherwise). happiness: if we think some good G is to be identi-
In his ethical arguments Aristotle normally fol- fied with happiness, but then find that we can add
lows the method of dialectic (Topics i 2, EE i 3, 6, some further good H to G, so that the total of G Ⳮ
EN 1145b2–7). He examines the puzzles (aporiai) H is a greater good than G alone, then G cannot be
raised by common beliefs (endoxa), and tries to find identified with happiness.
a general principle that will resolve the puzzles, and These general criteria for happiness do not by
justify most, or the most important, of the common themselves imply that some definite kind of life
beliefs. His method is closely related to the Socratic achieves happiness. But Aristotle thinks we can
dialogue, without the overt form of a dialogue. reach a more definite account of happiness by atten-
Aristotle conceives ‘ethics’ (MM 1181a24– tion to the human function (ergon), the character-
1182a1) as a part of political science; it is the part istic activity that is essential to a human being, in
concerned with finding the good for an individual the same way as a purely nutritive life is essential
and a community (EN 1094b5–10). He treats the to a plant, and a life guided by sense-perception

91
Aristotle

and DESIRE is essential to an animal (1097b32– Socratic view fails to describe a suitably
1098a18). Since a human being is essentially a ra- complete and self-sufficient life; for exter-
tional agent, the essential activity of a human being nal misfortunes impede rational activity
is a life guided by PRACTICAL REASON. Now the good (1100b29–30), and take away happiness
life for a human being must be good for a being with (1100a5–9).
the essential activity of a human being; hence it must 3. Though virtue is insufficient for happiness,
be a good life guided by practical reason, and hence it is nonetheless its dominant component.
it must be a life in accordance with virtue (EXCEL- No matter what we have to lose as a result
LENCE; aretê). Aristotle therefore defines the human of being virtuous, we still have better rea-
good as an actualization of the soul in accordance son to choose virtue than we have to choose
with complete virtue in a complete life (1098a16– any combination of other goods that are in-
20). A life that is not guided by reason might be compatible with it (1100b30–1101a8). Ar-
good for some other sort of creature, but not for a istotle agrees with Plato’s Republic on the
human being. relation of justice to happiness.
In speaking of a life in accordance with reason, 4. From the general conception of happiness
Aristotle does not exclude all animal or vegetative Aristotle infers the general features of a vir-
activities from the life that achieves happiness. He tue of character (êthikê aretê; sometimes,
assumes only that rational activity is the distinctive and not unreasonably, rendered “moral vir-
and essential feature of the human soul, and that this tue”) (i 13). Since (following Plato) he rec-
organizes the human being’s other activities. He ognizes both rational and nonrational de-
does not thereby advocate any exclusive attachment sires, he argues that the excellent and
to thinking as opposed to ACTION. (See also below.) virtuous condition of the soul will be the
He claims that a life that does not essentially include one in which the nonrational elements co-
the rational control of action cannot be good for a operate with reason. Human beings fulfill
human being. their function well and in accordance with
complete virtue, insofar as their nonra-
tional desires are guided by their rational
Different Conceptions of Happiness
desires.
Though Aristotle recognizes that this is only an
outline of happiness (1098a20–2), he thinks it is
Virtue of Character
definite enough to guide our further deliberation in
the right direction. A virtue of character is defined as “a state involv-
ing decision, lying in a mean, a mean that is relative
1. It rules out the life devoted purely to PLEA- to us, a mean defined by reason, and by the reason
SURE (1095b19–20). This life is incomplete by which the wise person would define it”
because it allows no essential role to ra- (1106b36–1107a2). The different elements in this
tional activity; and mere pleasure without definition deserve discussion.
rational activity is not the good for a ra-
tional agent (1174a1–4). Since a life of 1. A virtue is a state (hexis), not simply a ca-
pleasure can be improved on in this way, pacity or a feeling, though it involves both
pleasure cannot be the good (1172b28– capacities and feelings (ii 5). I may have a
32). Hence Aristotle rejects HEDONISM capacity without using it properly on the
(later accepted by the CYRENAICS, and, in a right occasions; for example, I may have
form perhaps modified in an attempt to medical skill, even if I do not bother to use
meet Aristotle’s objections, by EPICURUS it at all, or I use it to poison my patients.
[341–270 B.C.E.]). But I am not a generous person simply be-
2. The Socratic view (later accepted by the cause I know how to give money on the
CYNICS, and in some form by the Stoics), right occasions; GENEROSITY requires an ac-
that virtue is sufficient for happiness, con- tual desire and disposition to give the
flicts with common beliefs (1096a2). This money (Metaphysics 1025a1–13).

92
Aristotle

2. In insisting on a state, rather than a pattern feelings of PRIDE or shame or RESENTMENT


of behavior, Aristotle shows that he is con- (1126a3–8), or their desire for other peo-
cerned with virtues as something more than ple’s good opinion. Brave people are appro-
means to virtuous action. Actions may be priately afraid of serious danger (1115b10–
virtuous even though they are not done for 20), and if the cause is not worth the danger
the virtuous person’s reasons (1105a26– they withdraw; but when the cause justifies
b9, 1144a11–20). But agents are not vir- their standing firm, their fear is not so strong
tuous unless they do the virtuous action be- that they have to struggle against it.
cause they have decided to do it for its own 5. In claiming that the virtuous person makes
sake. Aristotle assumes that in praising and a decision (prohairesis, discussed in iii
valuing virtuous people we do not value 2–3) to do the virtuous action for its own
simply their reliable tendency to produce sake, Aristotle implies that a certain pattern
virtuous actions, but also value the state of of desire and deliberation (which are the
character that they display in their actions. origins of a prohairesis, 1113a2–12,
On this point he agrees with KANT (1724– 1139a21–b5) is characteristic of the virtu-
1804) (in the contrast between doing what ous person. In claiming that the mean is de-
duty requires and acting from duty; Grund- termined by the wise (phronimos) person,
legung, Akad. pp. 397–98). he refers to the intellectual virtue that is re-
3. In arguing that a virtue of character must sponsible for good deliberation (1140a24–
be a “mean” or an “intermediate” state, Ar- 31). These aspects of his definition of virtue
istotle is not necessarily recommending of character imply that it is inseparable
“moderation” in actions or in feelings. He from virtue of intellect.
does not mean, for example, that if we
achieve the mean in relation to ANGER we
Wisdom and Virtue
will never be more than moderately angry;
on the contrary, the virtuous person will be But while Aristotle clearly sees a crucial role for
extremely angry on the occasions when ex- WISDOM and practical reason in virtue of character,
treme anger is called for. Still, Aristotle’s it is less clear what the precise role is. For if correct
doctrine is more than the trivial advice that decision and wisdom are expressed in action on
we should do what is appropriate to the oc- good deliberation, then the special role of practical
casion. Possible treatments of nonrational reason in virtue seems to be its role in deliberation.
impulses would be these: (a) indulgence, But deliberation in Aristotle seems to have a rather
leaving them completely unchecked; (b) narrow scope, insofar as it is concerned with what
suppression, as far as possible (1104b24– “promotes” an end (to pros to telos). If “x promotes
26); (c) control or continence (cf. 1102b13– y” is interpreted as “x is an instrumental means to
20), as far as possible; (d) harmony and y” (i.e., x causally contributes to y, without being
agreement with the rational part. In treat- part of y—as shopping for food contributes to eating
ing a virtue as a mean, Aristotle signals his our dinner), then Aristotle claims that deliberation
adherence to the last solution, as opposed and wisdom are concerned only with instrumental
to any of the first three. He thinks it should means to ends. They will tell us how to find the
be intermediate between the extremes of means to happiness, but they will not tell us anything
excess (leaving anger, say, totally un- about what happiness is. In that case Aristotle seems
checked) and the extreme of deficiency to anticipate HUME’s (1711–1776) view that prac-
(complete suppression of anger). tical reason is subordinate to nonrational desires
4. The task of MORAL EDUCATION, therefore, (Hume, Treatise ii 3.3).
is not merely to subject the nonrational part Aristotle need not, however, restrict the scope of
of the soul to practical reason. Virtuous practical reason in this way, if “x promotes y” is not
people allow reasonable satisfaction to confined to instrumental means. He also uses the
their appetites; they do not suppress all phrase for cases where x is a part or component of
their fears; they do not disregard all their y, or doing x partly constitutes doing y (as, for ex-

93
Aristotle

ample, serving partly constitutes playing tennis, or proper objects of praise and blame are the things
eating the soup is part of eating the meal). If he al- that we ourselves, rather than necessity or fortune,
lows deliberation about components of ends, Aris- are responsible (aitios) for (EE 1223a9–15), and he
totle is entitled to claim that wisdom is especially tries to show that we are responsible for our virtuous
concerned with deliberation about what promotes and vicious actions and characters. Aristotle does
happiness. For wisdom finds the actions that pro- not explicitly confront the questions raised by Epi-
mote happiness insofar as they are parts of the happy cureans and Stoics about the relation between causal
life. Such actions are (a) to be chosen for their own determinism and responsibility; and his claims
sake, as being their own end, rather than (b) to be might seem to give support to more than one of the
chosen simply as instrumental means to some fur- views developed by his successors. But he clearly
ther end. Aristotle identifies (a) as praxis (“action” sees the relevance of issues about responsibility to
or “activity”) and (b) as poiêsis (“production”) questions about virtue and character.
(1140b4–7). He draws a closely connected distinc- He claims that we are open to praise and blame
tion between energeia (“activity”) and kinêsis (“pro- for our voluntary (hekousia) actions, and that vol-
cess”) (1174a14–b14). untary actions are those that are caused neither by
The wide scope of deliberation makes it clearer force nor ignorance, but have their “origin in us,”
why decision is an essential element in virtue and insofar as we know the particular circumstances of
why Aristotle claims—surprisingly at first sight— the action (1111a22–24). These actions are the ap-
that we can decide on an action for its own sake, propriate objects of praise and blame.
even though decision is always about what promotes These criteria for voluntary action imply, accord-
an end. For the virtuous person’s decision is the re- ing to Aristotle, that nonrational animals also act
sult of deliberation about the composition of hap- voluntarily (1111a24–26). These nonrational agents,
piness; and this deliberation results in specific claims however, are not open to praise or blame. Hence the
about which actions are non-instrumentally good criteria for voluntariness do not seem sufficient for
components of happiness. These are the actions that praise and blame.
the virtuous person decides on, both for their own Aristotle need not face this objection, however, if
sakes and for the sake of happiness. the implications of his demand for the origin “in us”
In claiming that wisdom involves deliberation, (1110a17–18, 1111a22–24, 1113b20–21) are made
Aristotle also emphasizes the importance of its clearer. If the origin is in us, then it must involve us
grasping the relevant features of a particular situa- as essentially rational agents (that is why a mere
tion, since this is necessary if deliberation is to re- bodily process, such as aging, over which we have
sult in a correct decision about what to do here no rational control, does not have its origin “in us”).
and now. The right moral choice requires experience Hence voluntary action is significant insofar as its
of particular situations, since general rules cannot origin is in our control as rational agents, and since
be applied mechanically to particular situations it is in our control, we are justly praised and blamed
(1103b34–1104a11); and Aristotle describes the for it. (Though the voluntary action of a nonrational
relevant aspect of wisdom as a sort of perception or animal has its origin in the animal, it is not in the
intuitive understanding of the right aspects of par- control of the animal’s [nonexistent] rational agency,
ticular situations (1143a32–b5). and so the animal is not praised and blamed for it.)
Even if we act without deliberation and premedita-
tion on a sudden impulse of EMOTION or appetite,
Voluntary Action and Responsibility
the origin is still in our character and decision; for
In his general account of virtue of character Ar- the presence or strength of our desire is the result
istotle includes an account of voluntary action and of the character and decisions we have formed.
conditions for moral RESPONSIBILITY. This is rele- It follows that we are held responsible for our
vant to his main concerns, because he wants to show actions insofar as they reflect our character, deci-
how his account of the nature of virtue supports the sions, and hence (given the previous account of
common belief that we are justly praised and blamed practical reason) our deliberation about the good.
both for virtuous and vicious actions and for being For similar reasons, Aristotle believes that our char-
virtuous and vicious people. He agrees that the acter and outlook are also open to justified and ef-

94
Aristotle

fective criticism (1114a4–9); for it is in our rational be the one devoted exclusively to the pursuit of
control (when, presumably, we pass beyond the pure pleasure.
habituation of early childhood) to affect the way our
character develops. Rational deliberation and deci-
The Reciprocity of the Virtues
sion are the source of responsibility for character no
less than for action. Aristotle’s views on the role of reason, feeling,
and pleasure in virtue define the area of agreement
and disagreement with Socrates. With Plato, he re-
Pleasure
jects Socrates’ belief in the unity of the virtues (i.e.,
Aristotle’s demand for the virtuous person to de- that all the virtues are really one and the same vir-
cide on the virtuous action for its own sake is con- tue), since he denies that knowledge of the good is
nected with two further claims: First, the virtuous sufficient for virtue. Different virtues require the
person must take pleasure in virtuous action as such training of different feelings, and Socrates was
(1099a7–21, 1104b3–11). Second, in doing so, the wrong to leave out these noncognitive aspects of
virtuous person has the most pleasant life. In these virtue.
claims Aristotle relies on his views about the nature On the other hand, Aristotle accepts the reci-
of pleasure and its role in happiness. procity of the virtues (again agreeing with Plato),
To begin with, Aristotle identifies the life of plea- because he believes that each virtue requires wis-
sure with the life devoted (as the comment on Sar- dom, and that wisdom requires all the virtues
danapallus suggests, 1095b21–2) to the life of (1144b32–1145a2). We may mistakenly reject the
rather gross sensual pleasures. This is not Aristotle’s reciprocity of the virtues if we confuse “natural vir-
last word on pleasure in the Nicomachean Ethics. tue” with “full virtue.” People with merely natural
Book vii (EE vi) and Book x contain quite elaborate virtue have natural tendencies to do the brave or
(and on some points apparently different) discus- generous actions; but without wisdom they will not
sions of the nature of pleasure and the different reliably find the best actions (1144b9), and so will
value of different types of pleasure; and Aristotle not have a full virtue.
believes that true judgments about pleasure imply Aristotle assumes that each virtue will be subject
that the virtuous person’s life is also the most pleas- to the direction of wisdom, because the point of each
ant life. virtue is to achieve what is best, and each will accept
He rejects the view that pleasure is some uniform the judgment of wisdom about that. In some cases,
sensation to which different kinds of pleasant action for example, a decision about the generous action to
are connected only instrumentally (in the way that do for my friend requires some grasp of the require-
the reading of different kinds of books might in- ments of justice (since generosity does not require
duce the same feeling of boredom). Instead he ar- me to steal from a beggar to give a present to my
gues that the specific pleasure taken in x rather than rich friend). To find the appropriate action in the
y is internally related to doing x rather than y, and sphere of one virtue we need the cooperation of the
essentially depends on pursuing x for x’s own sake. other virtues. That is why the mean in which a virtue
(The pleasure of lying on the beach in the sun and lies must be determined by the sort of reason by
the pleasure of solving a crossword puzzle are not which the wise person would determine it (1107a1–
two instances of the same sensation that just happen 2). Aristotle rejects any suggestion that two different
to have different causes.) In Aristotle’s terms, plea- virtues could prescribe incompatible actions in the
sure is a “supervenient end” (1174b31–33) result- same situation (MM 1199b36–1200a11); for each
ing from an activity that one pursues as an activity fully developed virtue must focus on what is best
(PRAXIS or energeia) rather than a mere process or overall.
production (kinêsis or poiêsis); and he insists (fol-
lowing Plato in the Philebus) that the value of the
Incontinence
pleasure depends on the value of the activity on
which the pleasure supervenes (1176a3–29). Hence Aristotle also disagrees with Socrates over the
he infers both that the virtuous person has the most possibility of incontinence; since he assumes an ir-
pleasant life and that the most pleasant life cannot reducible difference between rational and nonra-

95
Aristotle

tional desires, he rejects Socrates’ view that only ig- son decides on the virtuous action because it is “fine”
norance of what is better and worse underlies (kalon) and for its fineness (1115b13). He assumes
apparent incontinence; he asserts that the Socratic that the fine systematically promotes the good of
view evidently conflicts with the appearances others, and he regards fine action as a necessary con-
(1145b27–28). dition for finding the mean that is characteristic of
In Aristotle’s view, incontinents make the right a virtue (1122b6–7). It is reasonable, therefore, that
decision (1152a17), and act against it (1148a13– he thinks justice is nothing beyond the other virtues
17, 1151a5–7). Their failure to stick to their deci- of character, since they already involve the appro-
sion is the result of strong appetites; in Aristotle’s priate concern for others.
example, we recognize that we ought to avoid eating To justify concern for the good of others, Aristotle
this sweet thing, but our recognition that it is sweet appeals to human nature. A human being, he claims,
actually triggers our appetite for sweet things, which is a political animal insofar as human capacities and
causes us to eat it after all. aims are completely fulfilled only in a community;
Still, Aristotle agrees with Socrates, against com- the individual’s happiness must involve the good of
mon sense, in believing that an appeal to ignorance fellow members of a community (1097b8–11,
is an important part of the explanation of inconti- 1169b16–19).
nence. Though he admits that incontinents have the Aristotle defends this claim in his discussion of
right decision and act against it because of appetite, FRIENDSHIP. His term philia, usually rendered by
he believes it is impossible for them to act against a “friendship,” actually covers many more cooperative
correct decision that they fully accept at the very relations (as, for example, between business part-
moment of incontinent action (1147b15–17). ners, allies, members of families) than we find it nat-
Aristotle therefore claims that incontinent peo- ural to regard as friendships; and Aristotle’s classi-
ple’s appetite causes them to lose part of the reason- fication recognizes the many varieties of philia. All
ing that formed their correct decision. They retain three of the main types of friendship (for pleasure,
the right general principles, but they fail to see how for advantage, and for the good) are concerned with
these apply to their present situation, and even the good of the other person; but only the best sort
though they say they know they are wrong to do of friendship—friendship for the good between vir-
what they are doing, they are just saying the words tuous people—involves A’s concern for B’s good for
without really meaning them (1147b9–12). To this B’s own sake and for B’s essential character
extent Aristotle thinks Socrates is right to appeal to (1156b7–12).
ignorance—though he disagrees with Socrates In the best sort of friendship the friend is “another
about the kind of ignorance that is relevant. self,” so that if A and B are friends, A takes the sorts
of attitudes to B that A also takes to A (1170b5–7).
Aristotle uses this feature of friendship to explain
The Scope of the Virtues
why friendship is part of a complete and self-suffi-
The virtues of character recognized by Aristotle cient life (1170b14–19). Friendship involves living
include some that seem largely self-regarding (e.g., together (that is, sharing the activities one counts as
TEMPERANCE, magnanimity), some that seem to in- especially important in one’s life), and especially the
volve good manners (e.g., truthfulness [about one’s sharing of reasoning and thinking (1170b10–14).
own merits] and wit), and some that concern the Friends cooperate in deliberation, decision, and ac-
good of others to some degree (bravery, mildness, tion; and the thoughts and actions of each provide
generosity). Only one virtue—justice (in its general reasons for the future thoughts and actions of the
form)—is clearly focused on the good of others in other. If A regards B as another self, then A will be
its own right (1129b25–1130a5). This rather broad concerned about B’s aims and plans, and pleased by
conception of a virtue sometimes encourages the B’s successes no less than by A’s own. The cooper-
view that these Aristotelian virtues are really not ative aspects of friendship with B more fully realize
moral virtues at all—on the assumption that genu- A’s own capacities as a rational agent, and so pro-
inely moral virtues are essentially concerned with mote A’s happiness more fully.
the good of others. For this reason Aristotle thinks that the full de-
Aristotle insists, however, that the virtuous per- velopment of a human being requires concern for

96
Aristotle

the good of others. He defends his claim initially for bodies, contemplation would be the whole of our
friendship between individuals, but also for the type good (as it is for an immortal soul, as Plato conceives
of friendship that forms a political community (a po- it in the Phaedo). Still, we are not in fact merely
lis), the “complete community” (Politics 1252a1–7, intellects (1178b3–7); and Aristotle recognizes that
b27–30) that achieves the complete life that is iden- the good must be the good of the whole human be-
tified with happiness. ing. In his considered view, contemplation is the
highest and best part of our good, but not the whole
of it. (2) Though contemplation is the single most
Two Conceptions of Happiness?
self-sufficient activity, insofar as it is the single ac-
Though one direction of argument leads Aristotle tivity that comes closest to being self-sufficient, this
to emphasize the other-regarding, social aspects of degree of self-sufficiency does not justify the iden-
happiness, his argument also seems to lead in a rad- tification of contemplation with happiness. For Ar-
ically different direction. In EN x he has also some- istotle has argued that happiness must be complete,
times been taken to identify happiness exclusively and for this reason he argues that neither virtue
with pure intellectual activity (or “study,” theôria)— alone nor pleasure alone can be happiness. He should
the contemplation of scientific and philosophical not, then, agree that contemplation is happiness just
truths, apart from any attempt to apply them to prac- because it is invulnerable and self-contained. For con-
tice. Plato is sometimes attracted by this view of a templation is not the complete good; we can think of
person’s good, and suggests that the philosopher other goods (e.g., virtue and HONOR) that could be
will be wholly absorbed in the contemplation of added to it to make a better good than contemplation
Forms. EN x provides strong evidence to suggest alone.
that Aristotle seems to share Plato’s contemplative Aristotle does not explain how we should decide
ideal, without the Platonic Forms. on particular occasions whether to pursue contem-
Aristotle argues that the contemplative life meets plation or to prefer one of the other components of
the general criteria for happiness (1177a18-b26), happiness; and decisions of this sort raise some dif-
and he especially focuses on two criteria. (1) The ficulties for his general position. But the difficulties
connection between the human function and human do not seem insuperable; and Aristotle’s claims
happiness supports contemplation. For contempla- about contemplation do not require any drastic
tion is the highest fulfillment of our nature as ra- modification of his general conception of happiness
tional beings; it is the sort of rational activity that as a compound of rational activities that assigns a
we share with the gods, who are rational beings with central and dominant place to the moral virtues.
no need to apply reason to practice. (2) Contempla- See also: ARISTOTELIAN ETHICS; CHARACTER; CYN-
tion is the activity that best fulfills the demand for a ICS; CYRENAICS; DELIBERATION AND CHOICE; DESIRE;
self-sufficient life. For it does not require many re- EPICUREANISM; EUDAIMONIA, -ISM; EXCELLENCE; FI-
sources outside it, whereas virtuous activity is vul- NAL GOOD; FRIENDSHIP; GOOD, THEORIES OF THE;
nerable to external misfortunes that may prevent it HAPPINESS; HEDONISM; MORAL EDUCATION; PHRO-
from resulting in happiness. NESIS; PLATO; PRACTICAL REASON[ING]; PRACTICAL
These advantages of contemplation lead Aristotle WISDOM; PRAXIS; RESPONSIBILITY; SOCRATES; STOI-
to suggest that it is the happiest life available to us, CISM; VIRTUE ETHICS; VIRTUES; VOLUNTARY ACTS;
to the extent that we have the rational intellects we WEAKNESS OF WILL; WISDOM.
share with gods, and that the life of virtuous activity
is a second-best form of happiness (1177b26–
Bibliography
1178a10).
Though the evidence suggesting that Aristotle
Works by Aristotle
holds this purely contemplative conception of hap-
Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford Trans-
piness is strong, it is not conclusive. He does not
lation. Edited by J. Barnes. 2 vols. Princeton: Princeton
clearly claim that contemplation fully satisfies these University Press, 1984.
criteria for happiness, and therefore he does not in- L’Ethique a nicomaque. Translated and edited by R. A.
fer that by itself it is sufficient for happiness. (1) If Gauthier and J. Y. Jolif. 2d ed. 4 vols. Louvain: Nau-
we were pure intellects with no other desires and no welaerts, 1970.

97
Aristotle

Nicomachean Ethics. Translated by Terence Irwin. 2nd totle.” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 68
ed. Indianapolis, IN.: Hackett, 1999. (1986): 70–95.
Aristotle: Eudemian Ethics I, II, VIII. Translated and ed-
T. H. Irwin
ited by M. J. Woods. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1982.

Works about Aristotle atheism


Ackrill, J. L. “Aristotle’s Distinction between Energeia Atheism (the belief that neither God nor any other
and Kinesis.” In New Essays on Plato and Aristotle,
supernatural phenomena exist) was once thought to
edited by R. Bambrough, 121–41. London: Routledge
and Kegan Paul, 1965. be a form of madness. As late as the seventeenth
Barnes, J. “Aristotle and the Methods of Ethics.” Revue century even such a progressive thinker as John
Internationale de Philosophie 34 (1981): 490–511. LOCKE (1632–1704) thought atheism to be beyond
Barnes, J., M. Schofield, and R. Sorabji, eds. Articles on the pale of intellectual and moral respectability. But
Aristotle. 2 vols. London: Duckworth, 1977. See es- by the end of the twentieth century, particularly
pecially “Thought and Action in Aristotle,” by G. E. M. among the intelligentsia, atheism had become com-
Anscombe (chapter 6); and “Aristotle on the Volun- monplace. There is no distinctive ethical theory that
tary,” by D. Furley (chapter 5).
goes with atheism, though atheists will typically
Broadie, S. W. Ethics with Aristotle. Oxford: Oxford Uni- have the spectrum of values characteristic of the En-
versity Press, 1991.
lightenment. Atheists are frequently utilitarians; but
Charles, D. Aristotle’s Philosophy of Action. London:
some are deontologists or perfectionists. In META-
Duckworth, 1984.
ETHICS atheism fits well with either ethical NATU-
Cooper, John M. Reason and Human Good in Aristotle.
RALISM or noncognitivism. While religious thinkers
Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1975.
tend to be cognitivists and intuitionists, the link,
———. Reason and Emotion. Princeton: Princeton Uni-
versity Press, 1998. however, is not tight. Henry SIDGWICK (1838–
Dahl, N. O. Practical Knowledge, Aristotle, and Weakness 1900), G. E. MOORE (1873–1958), and C. D.
of Will. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, Broad (1887–1971) were distinguished intuition-
1984. ists, one might say the most distinguished intuition-
Engberg-Pederson, T. Aristotle’s Theory of Moral Insight. ists. Yet they were either atheists or agnostics.
Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983. The key problem for atheists vis-à-vis morality is
Gosling, J. C. B., and C. C. W. Taylor. The Greeks on Plea- not to work out a distinctive ethical theory providing
sure. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1982. See chapters the unique fit for atheism but to meet the challenge
11–17. thrown out by religious believers and even by some
Hardie, W. F. R. Aristotle’s Ethical Theory. 2nd ed. Ox- existentialist atheists—CAMUS (1913–1960) and
ford: Clarendon Press, 1980.
SARTRE (1905–1980)—that if God is dead nothing
Irwin, Terence. Aristotle’s First Principles. Oxford: Clar- matters, or at least nothing really ultimately matters.
endon Press, 1988. See especially chapters 15–21.
Or, more moderately, atheists need to meet the claim
———. “Aristotle’s Methods of Ethics.” In Studies in Ar-
of some religious moralists that a secular ethic must
istotle, edited by D. O’Meara, 193–223. Washington,
D.C.: Catholic University Press, 1981. be inadequate when compared with at least a prop-
Kraut, Richard. Aristotle on the Human Good. Princeton:
erly nuanced religious morality.
Princeton University Press, 1989. In our societies moral perplexity runs deep and
Rorty, Amelie, ed. Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics. Berkeley: cynicism or at least ambivalence about moral belief
University of California Press, 1980. See especially is extensive. A recognition of this situation is com-
“Aristotle on Eudaimonia,” by J. L. Ackrill (pp. 15– mon ground between reflective and informed athe-
34); “Aristotle’s Doctrine of the Mean,” by J. O. Urm- ists and believers. Atheists will argue that there is
son (157–70); “Aristotle on Learning to be Good,” by no reason to lose our nerve and claim that we must
M. F. Burnyeat (69–92); “Deliberation and Practical
Reason,” by D. Wiggins (221–40); “Reason and Re-
have religious commitments in order to make sense
sponsibility in Aristotle,” by Terence Irwin (117–56); of morality. Torturing human beings is wrong, CRU-
and “Aristotle on Friendship,” by John M. Cooper ELTY to human beings and animals is wrong, treating
(301–40). one’s PROMISES lightly or being careless about the
Whiting, J. “Human Nature and Intellectualism in Aris- truth is wrong, exploiting or degrading human be-

98
atheism

ings is vile. If we know anything to be wrong, we manded by an omnipotent and perfectly intelligent
know these things to be wrong and to be just as being. Unless we wish to reduce morality to PRU-
wrong in a godless world as in a world with God. DENCE, to take the will of such a being as our moral
God’s not existing has no effect on their moral status law is to reduce morality to POWER worship. Might,
or on our moral standing. even omnipotence, doesn’t make right; a perfectly
There is a philosophical problem about how we intelligent being could be evil through and through.
know these things to be wrong, but that is as much However, to this criticism of the Divine Com-
a problem for the believer as for the atheist. For if mand Theory it is not implausible to respond that it
any person, believer and nonbeliever alike, has an is God’s commanding that makes all the difference,
understanding of the concept of morality, has an un- for God, after all, is the supreme, perfect good. In
derstanding of what it is to take the MORAL POINT turn, it can be asked how we know that. If we say
OF VIEW, than that person will eo ipso have an un- we know it through studying the scriptures and
derstanding that it is wrong to harm others, that through the example of Jesus where his goodness is
promises are to be kept and truth is to be told. This manifest, then we know it only by virtue of our own
does not mean that such a person will be committed quite autonomous moral appreciation of his good-
to the belief that a lie can never be told, that a prom- ness. In Bible stories we read about behavior which
ise can never be broken, or that a human being in we take to be morally exemplary. However, it is
no circumstance whatsoever can rightly be harmed. through our own appreciation of what goodness is,
But if there is no understanding that such acts al- our own at least rudimentary conception of good-
ways require special justification and that the pre- ness, that we can appreciate morally exemplary be-
sumption of morality is always against them, then havior. Understanding something of what morality
there is no understanding of the concept of morality. is, we feel the moral force of the story of Jesus dying
But this understanding is not logically bound up on the cross to save humankind. Moral understand-
with a belief in God or adherence to a religious point ing is not grounded in a belief in God; just the re-
of view. verse is so. An understanding of the religious signif-
icance of Jesus and the scriptures presupposes a
logically independent moral understanding.
Divine Command Theory
If alternatively we claim that we do not come to
Defenders of Divine Command Theory, one of the understand that God is the supreme and perfect
major types of religious ethical theories, maintain good in that way, but instead understand it as a nec-
that such an understanding does imply at least some essary truth like ‘puppies are young dogs’ (some-
minimal knowledge of God because we know things thing which is true by definition), then we still
to be wrong only when we know they are against should ask, how do we understand that putatively
God’s will. Something is good only because God necessary proposition? But again we should recog-
wills it, and wrong only because He prohibits it. That nize that it is only by having an understanding of
is the central claim of the Divine Command Theory. what goodness is that we come to have some glim-
Setting aside skeptical questions about how we mering of the more complex and extremely perplex-
can know what God does and does not will, the old ing notions of supreme or perfect goodness. Only if
conundrum arises—something as old as PLATO (c. we understand what a good meal is can we possibly
430–347 B.C.E.): Is something good simply because have any inkling of what a wonderfully good meal
God wills it, or does God will it because it is good? is. Only if we understand what a sacrifice is can we
Leaving God aside for the moment, what is evident understand what a supreme sacrifice is.
is that something is not good simply because it is The crucial thing to see is that there are things
willed or commanded. A military officer can com- which we can come to appreciate on reflection to be
mand his troops to take no prisoners, or a father can wrong, God or no God. Whatever foundational ac-
command his son to lie to his mother. Neither of count of morality we give, or indeed whether we can
these things becomes good or in any way morally give one or need to give one at all, we can be far
acceptable simply in virtue of being commanded. In- more confident we are right in claiming that tortur-
deed, something is not even morally speaking a good ing, lying, or breaking faith with people is wrong
thing to do simply because it is willed or com- than we can be in claiming any rational belief in God

99
atheism

or knowledge of his order or of what he requires of while a Jewish, Christian, or Islamic morality can.
us. There are primitive moral certainties that are God, on such conceptions, is taken to be a creator
vastly more certain than any religious belief, and who is the supreme source of CARE, protection, and
these certainties are not at all undermined by ‘the moral guidance. At least in certain vital respects we
death of God.’ will be, if our faith is strong, free of anxiety and fear.
With a firm belief in God, we have the reassurance
that, if we orient our will to God, we will be saved,
God, Morality, and the Causal Order
EVIL will not ultimately triumph, and our moral
Someone might respond to the above critique of struggles will not be in vain because the evil in the
Divine Command Theory by maintaining that since world will not prevail and overwhelm us. In belief
God, assuming there is a God, is the cause of every- in God we can find peace and reassurance that all
thing, there could be (if the Judeo-Christian cos- is not hopeless. Jews, Christians, and Moslems can,
mological story is true) no goodness or anything else if their faith is strong, have a confident, future-
if there were no God. Given the truth of that tale, oriented view of the world. Such a view would af-
without God there would be nothing, and thus there firm that there is a purpose to life, that we are crea-
would be no valuable somethings. But this confuses tures of God made for a purpose in which ultimately
causes with reasons: confuses questions about there will be human liberation in a life of bliss. There
bringing something into existence causally and sus- is, the claim goes, a hope and moral promise arising
taining and justifying its existence. If God exists and from faith that no secular morality can match.
if he is what the scriptures say he is, everything caus- At this stage in the argument the viability of the
ally depends on him. However, even if there were no truth-claims of religion become important in a way
God who made the world, it still would be vile to that is not the case in arguing about the Divine Com-
torture little children. Even if God had not created mand Theory. If, as atheists claim, we cannot know
people and thus there were no people to be kind, it or even reasonably believe what religious people
would still be timelessly true that kindness is a good claim we know or can reasonably take on faith, we
thing. The goodness of kindness does not become should not crucify our intellects, and try to rely on
good or cease to be good by God’s fiat or anyone a religious morality. Moreover, the religious moralist
else’s, or even because of the fact that there happen portrays things in a godless world as being much
to be kind people. In terms of its fundamental ratio- grimmer than they actually are. There is no good
nale, morality is utterly independent of belief in reason to think life without God is senseless or with-
God. Atheists can respond to the religious claim that out point. There are purposes in life even if there is
if God is dead nothing matters by asserting that to no purpose to life. And to be made for a purpose as
make sense of our lives as moral beings there is no the religious story maintains is not so morally un-
need to make what may be an intellectually stulti- problematic, for at the very least it seems to rob us
fying blind leap of religious faith. Such a moral un- of our autonomy. An atheist need not be limited to
derstanding, as well as a capacity for moral response small, rather personal purposes in life. There are also
and action, is available to us even if we are utterly larger, rather impersonal things that can perhaps be
without religious faith. There is no reason the atheist realized through political and social struggle, things
should be morally at sea. that we can make our own purposes by our own
deliberate acts. At a minimum, we can fight the
plague; maximally, we can struggle to transform the
Religious versus Secular Morality
world. Such efforts afford plenty of meaning in life
There are religious moralists who would ac- and prevent the threat of meaninglessness.
knowledge this and yet still maintain that there are Morality, it should be added, still has a funda-
religious moralities which are (morally speaking) mental function in a godless world, just as much as
more adequate than anything available to atheists. in any other kind of world: namely, its function to
We are religious beings in need of rituals and saving adjudicate in a fair way the conflicts of INTERESTS
myths. Without belief in God and immortality, our between persons. Atheists as well as religious people
lives remain fragmented and meaningless. A secular might very well come reflectively to desire that
morality can afford us no sense of providential care, something like a kingdom of ends will obtain. An

100
atheism

atheist, just as well as the religious person, can re- There are trade-offs here, and the trade-offs athe-
spect persons simply because they are persons. Athe- ists will make are not, to put it circumspectly, obvi-
ists, as others, will recognize SELF-RESPECT to be a ously mistaken or indicative of a shallow worldview
fundamental good. This will lead them to a respect with a shallow morality and conception of life. The
for others, for as moral agents we will recognize, if atheist’s view is that there is no need to make an
we think at all carefully, that if self-respect is a good arbitrary Kierkegaardian leap of faith and believe to
for ourselves as individuals it will be a good for ev- make sense of one’s life, including one’s moral life,
eryone else as well. UNIVERSALIZABILITY and FAIR- in what one admittedly takes to be absurd. What
NESS require us to go beyond ourselves and at least should be had by way of moral belief and commit-
acknowledge the appropriateness of a world in ment is not independent of the probabilities here.
which respect for persons plays center stage. Similar Atheists believe, and not unreasonably, that the
things should be said for the relief of human suffer- probabilities go very much against religious belief.
ing. If we can know anything to be bad we can know To have a robust moral conception of life one need
that suffering is bad. (It may sometimes be instru- not go against those at least putative probabilities.
mentally good but it is never intrinsically good.)
See also: ABSURD, THE; AGNOSTICISM; ALIENATION;
Where there is some reasonable expectation that we
AUTONOMY OF ETHICS; AUTONOMY OF MORAL
can, at least without extensive sacrifice, do some-
AGENTS; CHRISTIAN ETHICS; DEONTOLOGY; EVIL;
thing about suffering, we have, God or no God, an
FAIRNESS; GOOD, THEORIES OF THE; HUMANISM; IN-
obligation to relieve it.
TEGRITY; ISLAMIC ETHICS; JEWISH ETHICS; METAETH-
Again, a religious moralist can acknowledge the
ICS; MORAL POINT OF VIEW; NATURALISM; NIHILISM;
truth of at least a number of the points raised above
PERFECTIONISM; PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION; RELI-
and still respond that there are morally relevant
GION; THEISM; UNIVERSALIZABILITY; VOLUNTARISM.
NEEDS that religious morality responds to that sec-
ular morality does not. But it is also true that there
are needs that a secular morality responds to that Bibliography
religious morality does not. There is a question of Frankena, William, and J. Granrose, eds. Introductory
choices and of trade-offs. With a religious morality Readings in Ethics, 94–111. Englewood Cliffs, NJ:
there is a hope for immortality and a belief in a world Prentice Hall, 1974. Clear exchange between secular
of providential care in which we can have at least and religious-based moralities.
Hauerwas, Stanley, and Alasdair MacIntyre, eds. Revi-
the putative guarantee that our moral efforts will not
sions: Changing Perspectives in Moral Philosophy. No-
be defeated. If religious beliefs, including belief in tre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1983.
immortality, are held to be reasonably plausible, that Challenges the more standard treatments of ethics and
might be enough to tip the scale in favor of a reli- religion.
gious morality; but if, as atheists believe, belief in Idziak, Janine, ed. Divine Command Morality: Historical
the existence of God and immortality is highly im- and Contemporary Readings. New York: Edwin Mel-
plausible, then a religious ethic becomes less attrac- len, 1979. Good collection of historical writings on the
Divine Command Theory.
tive, for it appears that to adhere to it there must be
Mitchell, Basil. Morality: Religious and Secular. Oxford:
a crucifixion of the intellect which, pace Kierke- Oxford University Press, 1980.
gaard, is not such a plainly desirable thing. In such Nielsen, Kai. Ethics without God. Rev. ed. Buffalo, NY:
a circumstance, moral INTEGRITY is a threat to or at Prometheus Books, 1989. A defense of secular ethics.
least a problem for a religious morality. Atheists will ———. Naturalism and Religion. Amherst, NY: Prome-
argue that there is something to be said for the per- theus Books, 2000.
son who can hold steadily on course in the moral ———. Naturalism without Foundations. Amherst, NY:
world without telling herself fairy tales or feeling the Prometheus Books, 1996.
need to believe things which are wildly implausible, Outka, Gene, and John Reeder, eds. Religion and Moral-
ity. Garden City, NY: Anchor Books, 1973. Wide-
perhaps even incoherent. Moral integrity, fraternity,
ranging collection.
and love of humankind are worth subscribing to
Pojman, Louis, ed. Philosophy of Religion: An Anthology.
without a thought to whether such virtues will be Belmont, CA: Wadsworth, 1987. See pp. 493–537 for
rewarded in heaven or will predominate in our clear exchange between secular and religiously based
world. moralities.

101
atheism

Quinn, Philip. Divine Commands and Moral Require- that is otherwise devoted to biblical exegesis or pas-
ments. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1978. Careful discus- toral advice.
sion of Divine Command Theory.

Kai E. Nielsen
Heresy
Among the Christian church fathers, Augustine
is, perhaps, the leading definer of heresy, and hence,
attention of Christian orthodoxy. In particular, he wrote ex-
See moral attention; moral perception. tensively to define and reject Pelagianism, Mani-
cheanism, and Donatism. In the case of each of these
heresies, both Augustine’s own view and the view
he rejects have implications for ethics.
Augustine, Saint (354–430) Pelagianism denies that “in Adam’s sin we sinned
Aurelius Augustinus, bishop of Hippo and Christian all,” and puts forward instead the notion that human
church father, was born in Thagaste, Northern Af- beings have it within their natural power to be with-
rica (modern Souk Ahras, Algeria). He was trained out sin. Pelagianism affirms the dictum, known to
in rhetoric in Thagaste and Carthage and, except for modern philosophers through KANT (1724–1804),
five years in Rome and Milan, from 383–388, he OUGHT IMPLIES CAN. Through his formulation and
lived his life in North Africa and died in Hippo defense of the doctrines of original sin and human
(modern Annaba, Algeria) in 430. depravity, Augustine denies human perfectibility
Augustine had nothing that one could properly and maintains that inability to perform an action
describe as formal training in philosophy, nor did he unaided by the unearned grace of God does not free
ever enjoy the company of another philosopher as an agent from the obligation to perform that action.
good, or even nearly as good, as he was. He was Early in his adult life Augustine was himself a
trained in rhetoric and he became a teacher of rheto- Manichee; thus, he supposed there to be a principle
ric. His studies led him to become a great admirer of EVIL, or darkness, roughly coequal with the prin-
of CICERO (106–43 B.C.E.). Augustine’s study of ciple of goodness, or light. In rejecting Manichean-
Cicero’s works influenced more than his writing ism he took on the burden of showing how the ex-
style; through a careful and extensive reading of him, istence of an all-good and all-powerful god is
Augustine got much of his education in philosophy, compatible with the existence of evil (the classic
as well as much of his early enthusiasm for the sub- “problem of evil”). (For a statement of the problem
ject. Of the various philosophical schools known to in Augustine, see Confessions 7.5.)
him, neo-Platonism influenced him the most. But he Among Augustine’s many responses to the prob-
took the skepticism of the New Academy seriously lem of evil is the neo-Platonic suggestion that evil is
enough to try to answer it in brief discussions scat- a privation, so that “whatever is, is good” (Confes-
tered throughout his writings. His most celebrated sions 7.12). The idea seems to be that if, strictly
response to the skeptic’s challenge, “What if you are speaking, evil does not exist, there can be no prob-
dreaming?”, includes the assertion, “If I am mis- lem about how the existence of evil is compatible
taken, I am” (si fallor, sum, in City of God 11.26), with there being an all-good and all-powerful god.
which foreshadows DESCARTES’s (1596–1650) even Another influential Augustinian response to the
more famous saying, cogito, ergo sum (“I think, problem of evil is the suggestion that evil, or sin, is
therefore I am”). like a dark color in a beautiful painting—in itself,
Only the earliest of Augustine’s voluminous ugly, but in context something that contributes to the
writings are explicitly philosophical. But in virtu- beauty and goodness of the whole (City of God
ally everything Augustine wrote, including the let- 11.23). He also suggested, though left undeveloped,
ters, the sermons, and the biblical commentaries, the idea that FREE WILL is a good of sufficient value
he displays characteristically philosophical preoc- that an all-good and all-powerful being would want
cupations along with his theological and pastoral to create it, even at the risk of the evil that has re-
concerns. One often finds a philosophically inter- sulted from it (De libero arbitrio 1.18.186).
esting paragraph tucked away in a sermon or letter Donatism is the view that the Christian sacra-

102
Augustine, Saint

ments are not valid unless the priest who adminis-


Free Will
ters them is in a state of grace. In rejecting Dona-
tism, Augustine sought to free communicants from In the early dialogue, De libero arbitrio, there is
having to make moral judgments about their priests extensive discussion of how there can be such a
in the hope of finding in them good works that might thing as free will. As Augustine maintains in the City
be a sign of grace. “The conscience of a man is often of God (5.9), unless there is free will, praise and
unknown to me,” he writes (In Answer to the Letters exhortation is vain, and there is no justice in reward
of Petillian 1.7–8), “but I am certain of the mercy or PUNISHMENT. In both City of God and On Free
of Christ.” More broadly, the rejection of Donatism Choice of the Will, Augustine sought to disarm the
makes the importance of the Church as an institu- threat to human free will that God’s foreknowledge
tion largely independent of whether her clergy, as seems to pose by suggesting that God can foreknow
individuals, are morally or religiously upright. that we will do something by the power of our own
will, that is, of our own free will. His idea is that
such foreknowledge, instead of being incompatible
with free will, actually guarantees it (De libero ar-
Intentionalism
bitrio 3.3.33–5; City of God 5.9–10).
Augustine was an extreme intentionalist in ethics.
In his Commentary on the Lord’s Sermon on the
Lying
Mount (1.12.34) he identifies the necessary and suf-
ficient conditions for committing a sin as (a) receiv- Among Augustine’s contemporaries the question
ing an evil suggestion; (b) taking PLEASURE in the as to whether lying might ever be morally or reli-
evil act or thought suggested; and (c) consenting to giously permissible, perhaps even obligatory, was
accept the thought or undertake the action. If this is hotly debated. Augustine addressed this issue in
right, then whether one commits a sin is not in any many of his works, and devoted two treatises wholly
way dependent on whether one actually performs a to the topic of lying. In both of them he condemns
bodily ACTION as a result of the evil suggestion, plea- lying, even when the lie might have been thought to
sure, and CONSENT. And where an action does result, bring about some greater good. He bases his con-
it will be the INTENTION (understood as suggestion, demnation on the commandment, “You shall not
pleasure, and consent), rather than the conse- bear false witness,” and in both treatises he views
quences of the action, that give it its immoral lying as a kind of self-defilement.
character. The first of the two treatises devoted solely to this
topic, De mendacio, begins with a philosophically
provocative discussion of the nature of lying. Au-
gustine is inclined to suppose that a person, A, lies
Weakness of the Will
in saying that p, if, and only if, the following con-
Augustine’s Confessions is the first important au- ditions are fulfilled:
tobiography in Western culture. It includes extensive
passages of reflection on, and assessment of, his own 1. it is in fact false that p;
motivation. In Augustine there is no sign of a Pla- 2. A believes it is false that p; and
tonic or Aristotelian worry (see, for example, Aris- 3. A says that p with the intention of deceiving
totle’s Nicomachean Ethics, Book vii) about how someone.
akrasia, or WEAKNESS OF WILL, is possible; that is,
how it can ever be that one is doing what one knows But against the necessity of these conditions he
one ought not to be doing. In recounting the child- considers:
hood prank of stealing pears with a gang of his
friends, he confesses that he didn’t do it for the (a) the case of someone who believes false
pears; he had, he says, better pears at home. It was what is in fact true, so that the first con-
simply doing something he knew to be wrong, he dition is not fulfilled, though there is still
says, that motivated the action. “The evil in me was an intention to deceive;
foul, but I loved it” (Confessions 2.4). (b) the case of someone who, hoping and ex-

103
Augustine, Saint

pecting to be disbelieved, says what is false A second possibility for exculpation might be to
to get someone to believe the truth; and say that, after all, what happens only in a dream does
(c) the case of someone who, expecting to be not really happen. But Augustine’s strong intention-
disbelieved, tells the truth in order to de- alism makes this excuse unavailable to him. On Au-
ceive another (like the fabled traveling gustine’s view, in dreaming an immoral dream (say,
salesman in old Russia, whose competitor a dream in which one commits adultery), one has
charges, “You’re just telling me you’re go- really done something—indeed really done the cru-
ing to Minsk so that I’ll think you’re going cial thing—since one has formulated the intention
to Pinsk; but you really are going to Minsk, to do something immoral. Augustine’s discussion of
you liar!”). Jesus’ warning, “Whoever looks at a woman to lust
after her, has already committed adultery with her
Augustine seems uncertain about what to do with in his heart” (Commentary on the Lord’s Sermon on
these putative counter-examples. He contents him- the Mount 1.12.33–34) makes clear that, in his view,
self with insisting that the three conditions are physical copulation is not required for the sin of
jointly sufficient and leaves undecided whether they adultery to have taken place.
are severally necessary (De mendacio 4.5). Finally, Augustine’s concession to radical skepti-
This discussion of lying illustrates two important cism removes for him the excuse that, after all, I am
features of Augustine’s thought. First, he empha- not my dream self. Thus in his Contra academicos,
sizes the “inner man” (homo interior), an emphasis when he offers “I know that I taste a sweet taste” as
that leads to the intentionalism in ethics mentioned a claim immune to skepticism and considers the
above. Second, he holds fast to the truth of certain skeptic’s taunt, “What if you are only dreaming?”,
tenets, especially biblical claims and religious doc- he responds: “Still that would give me pleasure even
trines with a strong basis in scripture, even when in my sleep” (3.11.26). Consistent with that reply to
key notions in those tenets are highly problematic the skeptic’s challenge, Augustine cannot deny that
and seemingly recalcitrant to satisfactory philosoph- he is his dream self. Unlike Plato and Descartes, Au-
ical analysis. This second feature of his thought pre- gustine continued to show concern for this problem
figures the tendency of certain twentieth-century an- throughout much of his life.
alytic philosophers to suppose that the deliverances
of natural science, or of common sense, are true,
Vice
whether or not a philosopher can give them a sat-
isfactory analysis. Augustine distinguishes between things desirable
in themselves and things desirable for the sake of
something else by saying that things of the first sort
Moral Dream Problem
are to be enjoyed (frui), whereas those of the second
Like PLATO (c. 430–347 B.C.E.) before him (Re- are to be used (uti). Using this uti-frui distinction he
public 571C) and Descartes after him (Letter to then characterizes vice as wanting to use what is
Elizabeth, 1 September 1642), Augustine is con- meant to be enjoyed and to enjoy what is meant
cerned about whether one does something morally merely to be used (De diversis quaestionibus
wrong by doing something immoral in a dream LXXXIII 30).
(Confessions 10.30). His anti-Pelagianism removes
for him the excuse that, since ought implies can and
Virtue
he can’t prevent himself from acting immorally in
his dreams, he is not morally or religiously respon- Augustine follows Ambrose (d. 397) in adding
sible for what he does in them. According to Au- the four cardinal VIRTUES of Greek antiquity to the
gustine, ought does not imply can; or better, ought distinctively Christian virtues of faith, HOPE, and
does not imply that one can do anything without the LOVE. Not only does he follow St. PAUL (5?–67?) in
gratuitous assistance of God. And, of course, Au- assigning primacy to love (caritas, or agape, not cu-
gustine is not really free to justify his immoral piditas, or eros), but he even suggests an interpre-
dreams with the complaint that God has not granted tation of the original four virtues that makes them
him enough gratuitous assistance. expressions of love, too—in fact, expressions of the

104
authenticity

love of God. Thus he says that TEMPERANCE is “love Gilson, Etienne. The Christian Philosophy of St. Augus-
keeping itself whole and incorrupt for God”; forti- tine. New York: Random House, 1960 [1943].
tude is “love bearing everything readily for the sake Kirwan, Christopher. Augustine. Arguments of the Philos-
ophers. London: Routledge, 1989.
of God”; justice is “love in serving God alone and
Matthews, Gareth B. Thought’s Ego in Augustine and
therefore ruling everything else well”; and PRUDENCE Descartes. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1992.
is “love making the right distinction between what ———, ed. The Augustinian Tradition. Berkeley: Univer-
helps one toward God and what hinders one” (De sity of California Press, 1999.
moribus ecclesiae catholicae 15.25). In this way he Rist, John M. Augustine: Ancient Thought Baptized. Cam-
can insist that virtue is nothing other than the per- bridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994.
fect love of God. And in this way he provides a Wetzel, James. Augustine and the Limits of Virtue. Cam-
Christian analogue to the old Platonic idea (cf. Pro- bridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992.
tagoras 329CD) that the many virtues are really only Wills, Garry. Saint Augustine. New York: Viking Press,
one. 1999.

See also: CHARITY;CHRISTIAN ETHICS; CICERO; Gareth B. Matthews


COURAGE; DECEIT; EVIL; FREE WILL; FREEDOM AND
DETERMINISM; GOOD, THEORIES OF THE; INTENTION;
KANT; KANTIAN ETHICS; LOVE; OUGHT IMPLIES CAN; authenticity
PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION; PRUDENCE; RESPONSIBIL-
The term, introduced into existentialist philosophy
ITY; SKEPTICISM IN ANCIENT ETHICS; TEMPERANCE;
by Martin HEIDEGGER (1889–1976), was popular-
THEOLOGICAL ETHICS; VIRTUE ETHICS; VIRTUES;
ized by Jean-Paul SARTRE (1905–1980). Although it
WEAKNESS OF WILL.
has come to denote the chief, if not the only, exis-
tentialist “virtue,” Heidegger insisted he was not us-
Bibliography ing it in a moral sense. But implying, as it does, such
key existentialist values as autonomy, commitment,
Works by Augustine individual RESPONSIBILITY, and finite freedom, it is
Complete Works. In vols. 32–47 of Patrologia Latina, ed- clearly an evaluative term for all thinkers in the so-
ited by J. P. Migne. Paris, 1844–64. The Maurist edi- called existentialist tradition.
tion; in Latin. The Heideggerian term “eigentlich,” translated
Works. In A Select Library of the Nicene and Post-Nicene “authentic” or “proper,” denotes that mode of com-
Fathers, edited by Philip Schaff. New York: Scribner’s,
porting oneself that individualizes and distinguishes
1892. The largest collection of Augustine’s works in
English translation. one human way of being (Dasein) from all others.
English translations of many of Augustine’s works are to Since it is one’s finitude, temporality, and ultimately
be found scattered throughout these two ongoing se- one’s DEATH that so distinguishes Dasein, authentic
ries: Ancient Christian Writers (Westminster, MD: existence consists in resolutely accepting and living
Newman Press); and Fathers of the Church (Washing- one’s being-unto-death as one’s proper possibility.
ton, D.C.: Catholic University Press). “Authenticity” in the Heideggerian sense, therefore,
The first English-language translation of Augustine’s com- refers to the ultimate focus of one’s concerns in the
plete works is currently being published in forty-six vol-
umes, edited by John E. Rotelle. Brooklyn, NY: New City
finite context established by one’s being-unto-death.
Press, in conjunction with the Augustinian Heritage Inauthenticity, conversely, consists in the flight
Institute. from this finitude, the loss of this focus, the dissi-
pation of one’s resoluteness in the “average every-
Works about Augustine day” of mass culture and superficial concerns. From
a moral point of view, inauthenticity would show
Brown, Peter. Augustine of Hippo. Berkeley: University of
itself in the grasping after pat formulae or ready
California Press, 1967.
guarantees to relieve the anguish of pursuing one’s
Clark, Mary T. Augustine. Washington, D.C.: Georgetown
University Press, 1994. unique path of finite existence. The Nietzschean
Elshtain, Kean Bethke. Augustine and the Limits of Poli- challenge of moral creativity is refused by the inau-
tics. Notre Dame, IN: Notre Dame University Press, thentic individual, who prefers the security of think-
1995. ing and acting as “they” would have one do. Tol-

105
authenticity

stoy’s (1828–1910) Ivan Ilych (in The Death of Ivan brute contingency (facticity) of existence by making
Ilych, 1886) exemplifies this inauthentic state by it one’s own and constituting one’s individuality in
seeking to live his life “comme il faut.” The relation the process.
between failure to choose and loss of self that Others in this tradition, such as Jose Ortega y
“proper” sets in relief is captured most graphically Gasset (1883–1955), Karl Jaspers (1883–1969),
in Either/Or (1843) by KIERKEGAARD (1813–1855) and Gabriel Marcel (1889–1973), have a similar
who compares the one who fails to choose to the sense of the anguish that accompanies our radical
captain of a ship who, in hesitating to shift direction, freedom and the resultant inclination to flee this
is all the while moving forward: “because others freedom/responsibility for inauthentic (uncreative)
have chosen for him, because he has lost himself” existence. Ortega underscores the creative choice of
(2:164, translation modified). the authentic individual; such a one is an artist. For
Sartre’s moral usage is more straightforward than Jaspers, authenticity is a function of my unique, his-
Heidegger’s. He introduces the term in Being and torical self (Existenz) in the face of Transcendence.
Nothingness (1943), where he promises an ethic of For Marcel, it entails being “faithful” to the recol-
authenticity as the sequel to his ontological master- lected presence of absolute being in oneself and in
work. In the posthumously published notes for that the other; but such FIDELITY is likewise “creative.”
ethic, he characterizes “authentic existence” as the From the many writers, both philosophical and
tensive feature of the human project’s being both literary, who have advocated authenticity as a moral
radically gratuitous and reflexively willed (see Note- value, several common features emerge. Authentic-
books for an Ethics). If it is our finitude that Hei- ity denotes practical consistency, a kind of truth-to-
deggerian authenticity resolutely chooses to live, it oneself, however that “self” may be conceived. This
is our contingency that is the focus of Sartrean in turn implies an ontological understanding of hu-
choice. Whatever human reality (Sartre’s translation man nature and/or the human condition, focused
of “Dasein”) may be, it is in the manner of not-being on finitude, creative freedom, and responsibility.
it, that is, in the manner of being at an inner distance Whether one “makes of [one’s] life a work of art”
from its predicates, its intentions, its very self. This (Nietzsche) or “dwells poetically” in the world (Hei-
nonself-coincidence is the ground of our freedom. degger), the model of the authentic individual is the
Authenticity is to choose to live this freedom; in- creative artist. Even Kierkegaard, for whom the poet
authenticity, or BAD FAITH, is to flee it by trying to was paradigmatically inauthentic, advocates in the
coincide with ourselves (with our self-image, for ex- choice of faith the typically artistic superiority of the
ample, or with that image which others have of us). individual over the universal. The sometimes pro-
Simone DE BEAUVOIR (1908–1986), though she found differences between these thinkers—whether
does not use the term, appropriates the idea when this creativity, for example, is a “doing,” a “respond-
she insists: “it is a matter of reconquering freedom ing,” or a “letting be”—are functions of their re-
on the contingent facticity of existence, that is, of spective ontologies.
taking the given, which, at the start, is there without Authenticity thus belongs to that ethical tradition
any reason, as something willed by man” (The Ethics which insists one “become what one is.” But what
of Ambiguity, 1947). Likewise, Albert CAMUS distinguishes it from more conservative forms of this
(1913–1960) holds up for emulation the “decision” position is its view of “what one is” as unique, open-
of Sisyphus as he returns to the foot of the hill to ended, transcending one’s circumstances and crea-
begin rolling the rock to the top yet again: “One tive of values. It thus resembles some forms of
must imagine Sisyphus happy” (The Myth of Sisy- PRAGMATISM. But it likewise risks dismissal as con-
phus and Other Essays, 1942). The similarity be- stituting an ethical style, not a content; of warranting
tween these attitudes and that of NIETZSCHE’s any sort of commonly acknowledged immoral activ-
(1844–1900) Zarathustra is more than coinciden- ity (racism or rape, for example) so long as one acts
tal. The latter’s inversion of Christian salvation in full awareness of the freedom of the decision and
reads: “To redeem those who lived in the past and owns the consequences of the act. So the challenge
to recreate all ‘it was’ into a ‘thus I willed it’—that to any existentialist ethics is to flesh out the imper-
alone should I call redemption” (Thus Spoke Zara- ative of authenticity so that one may exclude certain
thustra, 1885). In such instances one is affirming the acts that could scarcely be conceived as authentic.

106
authority

Finally, the term seems to find its proper place either Taylor, Charles. The Ethics of Authenticity. Cambridge:
in a SITUATION ETHICS or as the complement to any Harvard University Press, 1992. Excellent study, by a
nonexistentialist, of the ethical value of authenticity.
number of ethical theories that demand a corrective
Zimmerman, Michael E. Eclipse of the Self. 2d, rev. ed.
to their excessively impersonal rules and principles. Athens: Ohio University Press, 1986. The development
See also: AUTONOMY OF MORAL AGENTS; BAD FAITH; of Heidegger’s concept of authenticity.
BUBER; CAMUS; DE BEAUVOIR; EXISTENTIAL ETH- Thomas R. Flynn
ICS; FIDELITY; HEIDEGGER; INDIVIDUALISM; LIBER-
TARIANISM; KIERKEGAARD; NIETZSCHE; RAND;
RESPONSIBILITY; SARTRE; SELF-DECEPTION; SELF- authority
KNOWLEDGE; SITUATION ETHICS.
Accounts of the concept of authority often begin
with an etymological point. The word comes from
Bibliography the same root as “author.” This suggests that a
Adorno, Theodore. The Jargon of Authenticity. Evanston, holder of authority is a source of something, in par-
IL: Northwestern University Press, 1973. Neo-Marxist ticular, the decisions or judgments of the people over
critique of Heidegger. whom authority is exercised. But in the modern
Camus, Albert. The Myth of Sisyphus and Other Essays. world, where hierarchy is not taken for granted, the
New York: Vintage Books, 1955 [1942]. Authenticity concept of authority is probably best understood by
as revolt. focusing not on those who hold authority but on
Heidegger, Martin. Being and Time. New York: Harper those potentially subject to it. Regarded in this way,
and Row, 1962 [1927]. Classic statement of authentic-
ity in the context of fundamental ontology.
the essence of authority is deference. Those subject
Jaspers, Karl. Reason and Existenz. Translated by William
to authority defer to the communications of the
Earle. New York: Noonday Press, 1955 [1935]. Au- holders of authority. Two main questions arise about
thentic existence elucidated. this deference: How is it to be understood? And how
Kierkegaard, Søren. Either/Or. Princeton, NJ: Princeton is it to be justified?
University Press, 1987 [1843]. Choice and self- Discussion of both these points is facilitated by
constitution. making two distinctions. The first distinction is be-
———. Two Ages. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University tween de facto authority and justified or legitimate
Press, 1978 [1846?]. Inauthentic forms of existence.
authority. De facto authority obtains when people
———. Sickness unto Death. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
are in fact prepared to defer to the communications
University Press, 1980 [1849]. Choice of self in a re-
ligious context. emanating from some source. Authority is legitimate
Marcel, Gabriel. The Mystery of Being. Chicago, IL: Reg- when this deference is justified, in the sense that
nery, 1950–51. Definitive exposition of his thought in there is good reason, from the standpoint of those
the Gifford lectures. displaying deference, to do so.
Martin, Mike W. Self-Deception and Morality. Lawrence: The second distinction is between subordinating
University Press of Kansas, 1986. Discussion of the authority and expert authority. De facto subordinat-
“authenticity tradition”; bibliography.
ing authority involves uncoerced deference to direc-
Nietzsche, Friedrich. Thus Spoke Zarathustra. 1883–85.
tives. These enjoin an agent to perform a certain ac-
The “overman” versus the last man.
tion in a certain situation. Presumably, the agent is
Ortega y Gasset, Jose. Meditations on Quixote. New York:
Norton, 1961 [1914]. The authentic individual as capable of making up her own mind about what
artist. course of action is appropriate in that situation, of
Sartre, Jean-Paul. Anti-Semite and Jew. New York: deciding for herself what all the relevant consider-
Schocken, 1948. His classic analysis of authenticity/ ations require. But if she accepts the authority of
inauthenticity. some source of directives, she regards these direc-
———. Notebooks for an Ethics. Translated by David Pel- tives as taking precedence over her own judgment
lauer. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1992. Ex-
concerning what to do. Joseph Raz has employed the
tensive treatment of authenticity, including a discus-
sion of authentic love. (Written 1946–47; published concept of preemption to characterize the relation
posthumously as Cahiers pour une morale.) between the communications of an authority and the
———. Saint Genet, Actor and Martyr. New York: George judgments of those subject to it. To accept the au-
Braziller, 1963 [1952]. Authenticity exemplified. thority of some source of directives is to allow its

107
authority

directives to displace the reasons that would other- as more competent reasoners. When subordinating
wise determine judgment. This has the effect of mak- authority is justified in this way, it shades into expert
ing the directives decisive REASONS FOR ACTION. authority.
To justify subordinating authority to an individual When a subordinating authority directs people to
is to provide her with a rationale for the preemption, behave cooperatively, the justification of the pre-
by the putative authority’s directives, of her judg- emption that it involves can also be understood an-
ments concerning what to do (in situations of the other way. We can regard the reasoning that is pre-
kind at issue). This raises the most philosophically empted as reasoning concerning how an agent can,
intriguing problem about authority. How can there as an individual, maximize the satisfaction of the
be good reason for an agent to set aside an all-things- considerations that he regards as reasons for action.
considered judgment regarding what there is good As is well known, maximizing reasoning of this sort
reason to do? Obviously we need to make a distinc- can dictate free riding, and when generally followed
tion. The preempted judgment is based on all the in a group, leads to the breakdown of cooperation.
relevant substantive considerations, but there must If a source of directives that has de facto authority
be further considerations of a different sort that jus- in a group directs cooperative behavior instead, each
tify its preemption. What might they be? subordinate will find that his compliance is matched
Historically, perhaps the most important way of by that of others, with the result that the consider-
justifying subordinating authority has employed a ations he takes as reasons for action are better sat-
promise to obey—or CONSENT having promissory isfied than they would be in the situation of general
force. It is doubtful, however, whether this approach noncooperation. This is a second way of regarding
is generally applicable. If it is to justify subordinating those who accept subordinating authority as doing
authority, a promissory obligation must have pre- better in terms of the very considerations, including
emptive force relative to the reasons that would oth- moral considerations, that ground the preempted
erwise determine what to do. This is, perhaps, pos- judgments.
sible when the other reasons are nonmoral, for Expert authority involves the displacement of an
example, reasons of self-interest. But a promissory all-things-considered judgment not by a directive,
obligation cannot plausibly be regarded as preempt- but by the assertion of a putative expert. Deference
ing other moral considerations. It is just a further to expert authorities is a sensible social response to
substantive moral reason for action, which must the proliferation of specialized knowledge. No one
compete with the moral considerations that would can master it all, and thus general social perfor-
otherwise guide an agent, and may be defeated by mance will be defective if people try to answer on
them. So this method cannot reliably justify author- their own all the questions germane to modern life.
ity when agents have moral reasons for disobeying. A better—though obviously not foolproof—policy
To understand how subordinating authority involves a division of labor in which some become
could be vindicated when agents have moral reasons experts on matters of a particular sort, and everyone
for disobeying, we must consider how the displace- else defers to the assertions of these people in the
ment of a judgment encompassing even moral con- areas of their expertise. Here, too, we can distin-
siderations might be justified. One possibility is that guish between de facto and legitimate authority. An
the agent’s own reasoning is defective, or at any rate, individual’s assertions may in fact be decisive in de-
not as accomplished as the reasoning of the desig- termining the beliefs of the members of some group,
nated authority. He is likely to do better by comply- whether this is justified or not. What, then, justifies
ing with the directives of an authority, where doing expert authority?
better is understood as better satisfying the very Again, the justifying reason cannot be a substan-
same reasons the force of which he would try to cap- tive consideration that has somehow been left out of
ture in an all-things-considered judgment. Of an all-things-considered judgment. The justification
course, this presupposes that the holder of authority must be that the expert is better at assessing the
undertakes to base her directives on these reasons. force of all the applicable substantive considera-
This way of justifying subordinating authority re- tions. Typically, this is established inductively, by a
quires that the subordinates have available to them history of successful judgment. It becomes appro-
a sound basis for regarding those issuing directives priate for the members of a group to defer to some-

108
autonomy of ethics

one’s sincere assertions when they have repeatedly ISES; REASONS FOR ACTION; RELIGION; SOCIAL AND
compared her judgments with their own and found POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY; THEOLOGICAL ETHICS;
hers better. One prominent case is that in which an TRUST.
individual is more successful in predicting what will
happen next in situations of a certain type. In such
Bibliography
cases, the authority may employ a form of reasoning
that is completely inaccessible to those who defer to Arendt, Hannah. “What Was Authority?” In Authority,
her. To have a good reason for deferring, they need edited by Carl Friedrich for the American Society for
only be able to observe whether her predictions are Political and Legal Philosophy, 81–112. Nomos 1.
Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1958.
more accurate than their own. In other cases, how-
Coleman, James. The Foundations of Social Theory. Cam-
ever, expert authority is based on a difference in the bridge: Harvard University Press, 1990.
degree of some shared competence. A given individ- Dan-Cohen, Meir. “In Defense of Defiance.” Philosophy
ual can reason more efficiently or creatively, about and Public Affairs 23 (1994): 24–51.
matters of a particular sort, than other people. The De George, Richard. The Nature and Limits of Authority.
deference characteristic of authority becomes justi- Lawrence: University of Kansas Press, 1985.
fied when, after a number of trials in which those Friedman, Richard. “On the Concept of Authority in Po-
whose thinking is more cumbersome eventually as- litical Philosophy.” In Authority, edited by Joseph Raz,
certain that the designated individual is correct, in- 56–91. New York: New York University Press, 1990.
ductive reasoning supports simply accepting her fu- Green, Leslie. The Authority of the State. Oxford: Clar-
endon Press, 1988.
ture assertions. Expert authority in moral matters
McMahon, Christopher. Authority and Democracy: A
would be of this sort. But given the ubiquity of moral
General Theory of Government and Management.
disagreement, it is doubtful that anyone could dem- Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1994.
onstrate superior moral competence to most of the Peters, R. S. “Authority.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian
members of a large community. Society Suppl. vol. 32 (1958): 207–24.
The phenomenon of authorization should also be Raz, Joseph. The Morality of Freedom. Oxford: Clarendon
mentioned. We sometimes say that an individual acts Press, 1986.
by the authority of another, in the sense of being ———, ed. Authority. New York: New York University
authorized by him to perform the actions in ques- Press, 1990.
tion. For example, the agent of a principal acts by Soper, Phillip. “Legal Theory and the Claim to Authority.”
the authority of the principal. This use of the concept Philosophy and Public Affairs 18 (1989): 209–37.
of authority is also connected with the idea of au- Christopher McMahon
thorship highlighted by etymological considerations.
However, deference need not be at issue. To act by
the authority of another is to act by his RIGHTS.
Sometimes rights can be transferred from one per-
autonomy of ethics
son to another. But there is also room for the idea More has been written explicitly on the autonomy of
that an individual can consent, in the normative some other areas of culture, especially art and RE-
sense that involves incurring obligations, to the ex- LIGION, than on the autonomy of ethics as such; but
ercise of his rights by another, while still retaining autonomy issues in regard to ethics have been writ-
these rights himself. In such cases, we speak of the ten about and discussed extensively.
second person as acting by the authority of the first. Different things have been meant by the “auton-
omy” of an area of the culture or of a discipline.
See also: CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE; COERCION; CONSENT; Goran Hermeren distinguishes twelve different the-
CONTRACTS; COOPERATION, CONFLICT AND COORDI- ses meant by “autonomy” of art. Any one of at least
NATION; DUTY AND OBLIGATION; ELITE, CONCEPT OF; seven theses may be meant by “autonomy” of ethics:
EXCELLENCE; FREEDOM OF THE PRESS; GOVERNMENT, (1) Ethics is not subject to being explained biologi-
ETHICS IN; INEQUALITY; JOURNALISM; LEGAL ETHICS; cally, psychologically, or sociologically; (2) ethics is
LIBRARY AND INFORMATION PROFESSIONS; LOYALTY; not dependent on, or derived from, religion; (3) eth-
MASS MEDIA; MEDICAL ETHICS; OBEDIENCE TO LAW; ical concepts are not reducible to, or definable in
PATERNALISM; POWER; PROFESSIONAL ETHICS; PROM- terms of, nonethical concepts; (4) the justification of

109
autonomy of ethics

ethical judgments does not depend exclusively on some uniquely ethical property or structure (à la
nonethical beliefs; (5) ethics is a language game G. E. MOORE [1873–1958] and other moral real-
grounded in a form of life rather than in objective ists) or are devoid of cognitive meaning (à la logical
values or normative structures in the external world; positivists, existentialists, or prescriptivists). Thesis
(6) ethical judgments are not determinant judg- 4 holds (à la HUME [1711–1776], KANT [1724–
ments (they are not determined by, or accountable 1804], and others) that no ethical conclusion fol-
to, any objective truth or principle); and (7) philo- lows logically from purely factual premises; and, fur-
sophical ethics is independent of other philosophical thermore, that no set of factual beliefs alone can
disciplines, such as epistemology, metaphysics, and justify an ethical judgment. Some claim that an eth-
philosophy of mind. ical premise or commitment is always presupposed
Thomas Nagel argues for thesis 1. His attack is in justifying an ethical judgment with factual state-
on a biological theory of ethics, but his argument ments. Others have invoked an emotive response to
would apply equally to psychological and sociologi- the comprehended facts to account for the move-
cal theories as well. Nagel maintains that if ethics is ment from factual premises to an ethical conclusion;
“a theoretical inquiry that can be approached by ra- some have spoken of ethical rules of inference, some
tional methods, and that has internal standards of of social conventions, and some of a special (but
justification and criticism,” then biology can no optional) point of view that justify ethical conclu-
more explain ethics than it can explain mathematics sions from factual premises; E. M. Adams has ar-
or physics; and he argues that ethics is, in fact, such gued for the perception of objective normative re-
an enterprise. If ethics is a rational discipline, and quirements. There is wide agreement with Hume,
the evidence seems to support Nagel on this, then Kant, and Moore (although the opposition has been
moral experiences, ethical judgments and argu- strong) that ethical terms are semantically different
ments, and human actions in general do not have from nonvalue terms and that the justification of
the appropriate categorial structure to be subject to ethical judgments is different from that of factual
scientific description and explanation, whether in bi- beliefs.
ology, psychology, or sociology. Ronald DWORKIN is a prominent advocate of the-
With regard to thesis 2, many claim that ethics is sis 5. He holds that the objectivity and truth of an
dependent on, and derivable from, religion; and ethical judgment are an internal matter for the par-
that, in a secular culture, ethics, deprived of its foun- ticular ethical language game and form of life of
dation in religion, tends toward dissolution. Others which it is a part. A judgment is objective and has a
(e.g., Falk) contend that ethics, as a rational disci- truth-value not by virtue of its relationship to an ex-
pline, is grounded in selfhood, rational agency, or ternal, independent reality, but by virtue of the fact
reflectively living a human life, or in cooperative en- that it is embedded in a theory or practice with suf-
deavors and social organization; that, while religion ficient complexity for it to generate logical tensions
may reinforce ethics, ethics is more basic than, and within the system. This position is countered by all
can stand apart from, religion; and that religions of- the arguments for MORAL REALISM, whether natu-
ten lag behind the developing moral consciousness ralistic or nonnaturalistic.
of humankind. It seems obvious that rational dia- Thesis 6 invokes a sense of “autonomy” intro-
logue across cultures is more fruitful on ethical mat- duced in Kant’s Critique of Judgment (1790). Kant
ters than on religious issues. THOMAS AQUINAS held that aesthetic judgments of taste and teleolog-
(1225?–1274) and other Christian philosophers of ical judgments about nature are autonomous in that
the Middle Ages agreed with the Greeks and Ro- they are not determined by any objective truth or
mans that there is an independent rational basis for principle but rather by reflection on the appropri-
ethics; and since the seventeenth century it has been ateness of some object to one’s own sensibility or
widely accepted by philosophers that ethics is epis- intellectual powers. Friedrich SCHILLER (1759–
temologically independent of religion. 1805), Ralph Waldo EMERSON (1803–1882), and
Theses 3–6 have been at the center of the contro- others (see Richard Smyth) have claimed that ethical
versies in moral philosophy in the modern age (see judgments are autonomous in this sense. This, too,
E. M. Adams). Thesis 3 holds that ethics is seman- is countered by all the arguments for moral objec-
tically autonomous; that ethical terms either locate tivism and realism.

110
autonomy of moral agents

Thesis 7, the independence of moral philosophy Subject.” In Morality as a Biological Phenomenon, ed-
from other philosophical disciplines, is more as- ited by Gunther Stent, 198–205. Berkeley: University
of California Press, 1980.
sumed in practice than argued for by moral philos-
Rawls, John. “The Independence of Moral Theory.” Pro-
ophers. Dworkin, however, argues explicitly that no
ceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical
skeptical argument about morality and no argument Association 48 (1974): 5–22.
for the objectivity of morality can be other than a Smyth, Richard. “Voyages to Syracuse: Adams, Schiller,
moral argument. John RAWLS claims that moral the- Emerson.” In Mind, Value, and Culture, edited by Da-
ory, the analysis of substantive moral concepts and vid Weissbord. Altascadero: Ridgeview, 1989.
their relationship to our moral sensibility and natu-
E. M. Adams
ral attitudes (which he acknowledges is not the
whole of moral philosophy), is independent of epis-
temological and metaphysical considerations. How-
ever, a case can be made (see Adams) for the claim
that most theories of ethics are in response to phil-
autonomy of moral agents
osophical skepticism about ethics that is generated The idea of autonomy (from autos, self, and nomos,
by epistemological and metaphysical positions rule or law) applied initially to states that were self-
reached independently of moral philosophy, and that governing, as opposed to colonies and conquered
these epistemological and metaphysical positions peoples that were ruled by others. In modern times
may distort moral theory. the idea has been extended in various ways to char-
acterize individuals. The general description of auton-
See also: INTUITIONISM; METAETHICS; METAPHYSICS
omous agents as self-governing or self-determining,
AND EPISTEMOLOGY; MORAL REALISM; MORAL REA-
in some sense, is common to all accounts, but phi-
SONING; MORAL SENSE THEORISTS; NATURAL LAW;
losophers differ widely in their interpretations of this
NATURALISM; PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION; PRESCRIP-
general idea and in the value they place on it. Like
TIVISM; RELIGION.
many philosophical terms of art, “autonomy” gets its
specific meaning in the context of various theories,
Bibliography and these have developed in response to somewhat
different philosophical issues. (See Christman, 1988;
Adams, E. M. Ethical Naturalism and the Modern World-
View. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, Dworkin; Feinberg, 1986; and T. Hill.)
1960. Many writers, in discussing the foundations of
———. Philosophy and the Modern Mind. Chapel Hill: ethics, treat autonomy as a basic condition of moral
University of North Carolina Press, 1975. Reprint. agency. Prominent among these is Immanuel KANT
Washington, D.C.: University Press of America, 1985. (1724–1804), whose conception of autonomy may
See chapters 4 and 5. be seen as an ancestor of many contemporary con-
Alston, William P. “The Christian Language-Game.” In ceptions which differ significantly from his. In The
The Autonomy of Religious Belief, 128–62. Notre
Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1981.
Social Contract (1762) ROUSSEAU (1712–1778)
Collingridge, David. “The Autonomy of Evaluation.” Jour-
had set himself the task of finding a form of political
nal of Value Inquiry 14 (1980): 119–28. union that would preserve to each citizen “moral lib-
Dworkin, Ronald. A Matter of Principle. Cambridge: erty,” which he understood as being subject only to
Harvard University Press, 1985. See especially pp. laws that one gives to oneself. Adopting this idea for
167–77. ethics, Kant maintained that, contrary to all previous
Falk, W. D. “Morals without Faith.” In Ought, Reasons, moral theories, the crucial condition for being a
and Morality: The Collected Papers of W. D. Falk, moral agent is having “autonomy of the will.” Nega-
163–79. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1986.
tively, this means that principles cannot acquire
Hermeren, Goran. “Autonomy of Art.” In Essays on Aes-
moral force simply by being demanded by something
thetics, edited by John Fisher, 35–49. Philadelphia:
Temple University Press, 1983. external to the rational agent, such as God, secular
AUTHORITY, tradition, or natural instinct. Positively,
Myers, David B. “Marxism and the Autonomy of Critical
Thought.” International Philosophical Quarterly 19 it means that one imposes moral constraints on one-
(1979): 213–26. self through one’s own reason.
Nagel, Thomas. “Ethics as an Autonomous Theoretical Kant argues that autonomy of the will is a positive

111
autonomy of moral agents

freedom inseparable from freedom conceived nega- principles that would be adopted in his original
tively, and together these apparently imply: (a) being position.
able to act on principles without one’s act being Some moral theorists who treat autonomy as a
causally determined; (b) being able to act for reasons fundamental feature of moral agency conceive of au-
other than to satisfy inclinations; (c) having and be- tonomy quite differently from Kant and Rawls. On
ing able to act on principles that are rational, do not some accounts, for example, moral agents have the
merely prescribe means to given ends, and are in autonomy, or freedom, to adopt moral principles, or
some sense rationally self-imposed rather than bind- to make moral decisions, for themselves without be-
ing by virtue of one’s desires or the commands of ing constrained by Kantian rationality, a Rawlsian
others. Kant attributed this property to the will of “original position,” objective moral truths, or any
all rational agents, as a necessary and (with sensi- substantive standards. Some versions of this view
bility) a sufficient condition of moral agency; but he are held by R. M. HARE, Aiken, SARTRE (1905–
held that only acts actually motivated by respect for 1980), and others. Like Kant, these philosophers re-
such rational principles manifest one’s autonomy ject the idea that morally binding principles are to
and thereby have moral worth. Kant argued for the be “discovered” in nature, tradition, or theology; but
autonomy of all rational moral agents not on empir- they also deny that such principles are commands of
ical grounds but as a necessary presupposition of reason or constructs of RATIONAL CHOICE. Moral
moral obligation and PRACTICAL REASON in general. agents are “free” to adopt their own principles, lim-
He argued, further, that any rational agent with au- ited only by requirements such as sincerity, consis-
tonomy is necessarily committed to the Categorical tency, thinking for oneself, and willingness to apply
Imperative, the supreme moral principle, and from the same principles to others. Such procedural re-
this he attempted to justify some of the more specific quirements do not guarantee that all rational moral
moral principles that contemporary writers often agents will adopt the same moral principles, though
classify as RIGHTS and duties of autonomous how often and how deeply they will disagree is an
persons. empirical question. The autonomy, or moral free-
Following Kant with modifications, John RAWLS, dom, in question here is obviously not (as for Kant)
in A Theory of Justice (1971), holds that the prin- freedom from the influence of inclination and per-
ciples of justice are whatever principles would be sonal desire. Assuming one is sincere, consistent,
adopted by rational and free agents in an idealized etc., one is “self-governing” in moral conduct when
choice situation. Rawls stipulates that persons in one lives by principles one actually accepts for one-
this “original position” be mutually disinterested, self as the particular individual one is, not by virtue
motivated to acquire certain “social primary goods,” of conforming to universal principles that one would
but excluded by a “veil of ignorance” from consult- adopt if choosing with Kantian autonomy or from
ing their individual goals, loyalties, and conceptions Rawls’s original position. The theories in question
of the good life. Thus the perspective from which attribute to all moral agents the freedom to adopt
Rawls derives the principles of justice is partially one’s own moral principles (within the limits men-
analogous to the point of view of Kant’s rational tioned); and this is generally seen as an implication
agents with autonomy of will. Though Rawls seeks of the theories’ conception of morality, not as a
to avoid the extreme metaphysical commitments as- metaphysical claim or an empirical observation.
sociated with Kant’s ethics, in both theories rational However, whether a particular individual exercises
agents adopt or acknowledge moral constraints in that freedom, and so lives autonomously, may de-
detachment from the particular ends they desire; pend on the empirical facts about whether the per-
and acting autonomously is construed as acting from son makes and lives by his or her moral commit-
principles that one would consent to as a free and ments with the requisite sincerity, independence,
equal rational being. A significant difference, how- consistency, etc.
ever, is that Kant holds that all rational agents, by Many contemporary writers construe autonomy
virtue of their autonomy of will, necessarily ac- not as a basic condition of all moral agents but as a
knowledge the moral law as rationally binding even feature of persons who are especially self-controlled,
when they fail to conform. Rawls, by contrast, does independent, or authentic. The typical context for
not claim that every rational agent is committed to this conception is discussion of VIRTUES and ideals

112
autonomy of moral agents

rather than the source of moral obligation. Some ar- tion, etc., to interfere with an agent’s efforts to make
gue, for example, that an ideal for education is to and carry out these decisions. Authors differ about
develop autonomous individuals rather than blind the range and definition of the right of autonomy,
conformists. Others condemn sexist and manipula- but none would deny that what one may decide for
tive practices on the ground that they undermine a oneself is limited by others’ autonomy and perhaps
person’s ability to make autonomous decisions. Au- further moral considerations (e.g., PROMISES, non-
tonomy as self-control, in contrast to “wanton” and injury, and justice). Appeals to the individual’s right
addictive behavior, is sometimes presented as an at- of autonomy are common in criticisms of UTILITAR-
tainable sort of “free will” compatible with causal IANISM and, more specifically, of PATERNALISM in
determinism. MEDICAL ETHICS. Some feminist writers have argued
These writers generally agree that not everyone that sexist and gender stereotypes violate women’s
satisfies the ideal of autonomy and that one can be right to autonomy or undermine their capacity to
autonomous to various degrees. How to define the exercise it.
ideal, however, remains a matter of controversy. Sev- Important questions arise about how these vari-
eral have attempted to characterize it as control over ous conceptions of autonomy are related. For ex-
one’s first-order desires and preferences by higher ample, is Kantian or Rawlsian autonomy the ground
order desires or evaluations resulting from deliber- for the autonomous individual’s right to make self-
ation (Frankfurt; Watson). This strategy prompts regarding decisions without interference? If so, what
questions about how to distinguish autonomously is the argument that makes the connection? Is it a
formed higher-order desires from manipulated ones necessary condition of having the right of autonomy
and whether an infinite regress can be avoided. An- that one fully satisfy the ideal of rational self-control,
other controversial issue is whether autonomous AUTHENTICITY, and independence, or does the right
persons can choose to be ruled by others. Kuflick, extend to all who are autonomous to some minimal
for example, argues that autonomy is inalienable, threshold degree? If ideal autonomy is necessary,
but Dworkin argues that autonomy requires merely only a relatively few elite will have the right; but if
procedural and not substantive independence from a lower threshold suffices, then this minimum needs
others. In order to make autonomy compatible with to be specified and justified. Finally, if moral agents
“loyalty, objectivity, commitment, and love,” Dwor- are free to adopt their own moral principles subject
kin offers a “content-free” definition of autonomy as only to the procedural restrictions of Hare, Aiken,
“a second-order capacity of persons to reflect criti- and others, is there any common ground for holding
cally upon their first-order preferences, desires, that we have a right of autonomy or that it is an ideal
wishes, and so forth and the capacity to accept or to be an autonomous person?
attempt to change these in the light of higher-order A variety of objections have been raised against
preferences and values.” theories which stress the importance of autonomy.
A rather different conception of individual auton- For example, communitarians in political theory
omy is suggested by the analogy with autonomous criticize the Kantian and Rawlsian conceptions of
states that have the right to govern their own internal autonomy as excessively metaphysical and individ-
affairs. Similarly, many believe, individuals have a ualistic. These conceptions, they contend, identify
moral right to make their own decisions with regard one’s “true self” as an abstract rational being iso-
to a wide range of matters concerning their lives. lated from the community values that make one who
That is, individuals, at least those sufficiently ra- one is. Theories of the sort advocated by Hare, Ai-
tional and responsible to qualify for the right, are ken, and Sartre have drawn many objections, most
seen as “sovereign authorities” over questions such prominently perhaps the complaint that the sup-
as how to dress, what to read, when to refuse sexual posed freedom to choose our own moral principles
advances, whether to worship, sell their PROPERTY, (with minimal restrictions) is incompatible with the
pursue this or that lawful career, and so forth. The objectivity of morals. Ideals of autonomy as self-
right to make such decisions for oneself may be con- control, independence, etc., are suspected of cul-
strued as a right against individuals or against the tural (and male) bias. More choice, some argue, is
state, but the point in either case is that others would not always better than less, and LOYALTY, commit-
be wrong to use COERCION, manipulation, decep- ment, and compassion may be more important than

113
autonomy of moral agents

living autonomously. The supposed right of auton- ———, ed. The Inner Citadel: Essays on Individual Au-
omy invites the objections that, if broadly extended, tonomy. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989.
it protects decisions that are foolish and contrary to Downie, R. S., and E. Telfer. “Autonomy.” Philosophy 46
(1971): 296–301.
the general welfare and, if narrowly restricted to ide-
ally autonomous persons, it gives little guidance for Dworkin, Gerald. The Theory and Practice of Autonomy.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988. For
the real problems that arise, for example, in medical
quoted passage, see p. 20.
ethics.
Feinberg, Joel. Rights, Justice, and the Bounds of Liberty.
Further objections come from feminists who be- Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1980. See
lieve that traditional ethical theories have overem- “The Idea of a Free Man,” pp. 3–29. Reprinted from
phasized autonomy to the neglect of compassion and Educational Judgments, ed. by James F. Doyle (Lon-
PERSONAL RELATIONSHIPS. Carol Gilligan’s influen- don: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1973).
tial study of moral development in young women ———. The Moral Limits of the Criminal Law. 3 vols.
suggested that women and men typically see moral Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1984–88. See vol. 3,
problems from different perspectives, the character- Harm to Self, chapter 18.
istic values of men being autonomy, independence, Frankfurt, Harry G. “Freedom of the Will and the Con-
cept of a Person.” Journal of Philosophy 68 (1971):
and emotional detachment, while women are more
829–39.
concerned with caring, personal relationships. This
———. “Identification and Wholeheartedness.” In Re-
work has inspired hopes for new feminist theories
sponsibility, Character and the Emotions, edited by F.
that articulate women’s moral perspectives as alter- Schoeman, 27–45. Cambridge: Cambridge University
natives to autonomy-based theories sometimes seen Press, 1987.
as reflecting the values of male-dominated societies. Gilligan, Carol. In a Different Voice. Cambridge: Harvard
Unfortunately, most contemporary discussions of University Press, 1982.
autonomy to date have been brief or incidental to Hare, R. M. Freedom and Reason. Oxford: Clarendon
other projects. A challenge for future work would Press, 1963.
be to attempt to develop a unified account of auton- Haworth, Lawrence. Autonomy: An Essay in Philosophi-
omy that is sensitive both to the critics’ objections cal Psychology and Ethics. New Haven: Yale University
and to the best of the diverse ideas that have passed Press, 1986.
as autonomy. Hill, Sharon Bishop. “Self-Determination and Autonomy.”
In Today’s Moral Problems 3d ed., edited by Richard
See also: AGENCY AND DISABILITY; AGENT-CENTERED Wasserstrom, 118–33. New York: Macmillan, 1985.
MORALITY; AUTHENTICITY; AUTHORITY; CARE; CAT- Hill, Thomas E., Jr. Autonomy and Self-Respect. Cam-
EGORICAL AND HYPOTHETICAL IMPERATIVES; COER- bridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991.
CION; COMMUNITARIANISM; CONSENT; DECEIT; DE- Kant, Immanuel. Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Mor-
LIBERATION AND CHOICE; DUTY AND OBLIGATION; als. Translated by H. J. Paton. New York: Harper and
FEMINIST ETHICS; FREEDOM AND DETERMINISM; Row, 1964 [1785].
HARE; IDEALIZED AGENTS; KANT; LIBERTY; LOVE; Kittay, Eva, and Diana Meyers, eds. Women and Moral
LOYALTY; OPPRESSION; PATERNALISM; PRACTICAL Theory. Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Littlefield, 1987.
REASON[ING]; RATIONAL CHOICE; RAWLS; ROUS- Kuflick, Arthur. “The Inalienability of Autonomy.” Philos-
SEAU; SELF-CONTROL; SELF-RESPECT; SEX AND SEX- ophy and Public Affairs 13 (1984): 271–98.
UAL ETHICS; SOCIAL CONTRACT. Meyers, Diana. Self, Society, and Personal Choice. New
York: Columbia University Press, 1989.
Rawls, John. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge: Harvard
Bibliography University Press, 1971.
———. “Kantian Constructivism in Moral Theory.” Jour-
Aiken, Henry. Reason and Conduct. New York: Knopf,
nal of Philosophy 77 (1980): 515–35.
1962. See “The Concept of Moral Objectivity.”
Richards, David A. J. “Rights and Autonomy.” Ethics 92
Berlin, Isaiah. Four Essays on Liberty. Oxford: Oxford
(1981): 3–20.
University Press, 1969. See “Two Concepts of Liberty,”
pp. 118–72. Scanlon, T. M. “A Theory of Freedom of Expression.” Phi-
Christman, John. “Constructing the Inner Citadel: Recent losophy and Public Affairs 1 (1972): 204–26.
Work on the Concept of Autonomy.” Ethics 99, no. 1 Watson, Gary. “Free Agency.” Journal of Philosophy 72
(1988): 109–24. (1975): 205–20.

114
Avicenna [Ibn Sı̄nā]

Young, Robert. Personal Autonomy: Beyond Negative and think that Avicenna’s Healing was devoted solely to
Positive Liberty. New York: St. Martin’s, 1986. theoretical philosophy or science, that it had nothing
Thomas E. Hill Jr. to say about practical philosophy or science. Indeed,
it is not until the very end of his discussion of meta-
physics that he speaks of the practical sciences or
Averroës arts of ethics and politics. As he puts it, this “sum-
mary of the science of ethics and of politics” is
See Ibn Rushd.
placed there “until I compose a separate, compre-
hensive book about them.”
Avicenna’s fuller teaching reveals, however, that
Avicenna [Ibn Sı̄nā] (980–1037) ethical and political science belong after divine sci-
Abū ÛAlı̄ al-Husayn ibn ÛAbd Allāh ibn Sı̄nā, or ence intrinsically and not provisionally. Indeed, they
Avicenna. Of all the medieval Islamic philosophers, are the human manifestation of divine science—its
we are best acquainted with the life of Avicenna practical proof. They testify to divine providence for
thanks to the efforts of his devoted pupil and long- humankind and thus to the truth of revelation more
time companion, al-Jūzjānı̄, who preserved some- clearly than any of the other sciences investigated in
thing resembling an autobiography along with his the Healing. Yet because the correctness of what
own biographical appendix. We learn from it that they teach can also be verified by Aristotelian or pa-
Avicenna was an assiduous and devoted learner gan reasoning processes, Avicenna must elucidate
from the days of his youth to his death. the relationship he discerns between pagan philos-
Having proved himself in the study of the Quran ophy and the revelation accorded the Prophet
and related works of literature by the age of ten, he Muh. ammad.
turned to Indian mathematics and Islamic jurispru- Avicenna’s description of PLATO’s (c. 430–347
dence, then to the study of philosophy. Afterward, B.C.E.) Laws as a treatise on prophecy provides a
he set about reading Porphyry’s (c. 234–305) Isa- clue to how interrelated he deems philosophy and
goge, logic in general, Euclid (fl. c. 300 B.C.E.), Ptol- revelation. Indeed, with one exception, he consis-
emy’s (second cent. C.E.) Almagest, and eventually tently presents the revelation of ISLAM in terms that
undertook the natural sciences and metaphysics. For admit rational defense. The exception concerns the
the latter two pursuits, he claims to have read both question of ultimate HAPPINESS. Even here, however,
the original texts—presumably ARISTOTLE (384– he preserves philosophy’s role, never insisting on the
322 B.C.E.)—and the commentaries. Such theoreti- character of that happiness.
cal inquiries soon gave way to more practical ones Similarly, the attention he gives to the political
as he focused his attention on medicine. Having aspects of prophecy and divine law leads to reflec-
thoroughly mastered the forms of the syllogisms and tion on the most fundamental political questions: the
their various premises by sixteen, he moved on to nature of law, the purpose of political community,
metaphysics. These studies occupied Avicenna until the need for sound moral life among the citizens, the
the age of eighteen, at which time he found an oc- importance of providing for divorce as well as for
casion to present himself as a physician to the ailing marriage, the conditions for just war, the consider-
ruler of Bukhara and gained access to this ruler’s ations that lay behind penal laws, and the end of
well-stocked library. human life. Although he does not address the origin
In the first chapter of the introductory volume to of private PROPERTY any more than he explains how
the logical part of his famous Healing, the logical future successors to the prophet-lawgiver might be
part being at the same time the beginning part, raised so that they will have the moral habits and
Avicenna explains the general order of the whole character traits suitable to such a position, he pro-
work. After the part on logic is another part devoted vides the basic principles for readers to pursue these
to natural science. It is followed by a third part that issues on their own. In this respect, Avicenna’s po-
sets forth mathematics, and the whole compendium litical teaching is propaedeutic rather than provi-
concludes with Avicenna’s explanation of the divi- sional: it provides an introduction to the fundamen-
sions and aspects of the science pertaining to meta- tals of political science and alerts readers to the need
physics. From this account of its scope, one might to think carefully about the strong affinity between

115
Avicenna [Ibn Sı̄nā]

the vision of political life set forth by the pagan formulations of linguistic rules or their conse-
Greek philosophers and that exceptional individual quences; as such, they provided no information, just
who surpasses philosophic virtue by acquiring pro- a reminder how to use language consistently. All
phetic qualities. other meaningful statements were predictions about
what would be observed under certain empirically
See also: ARISTOTLE; CIVIC GOOD AND VIRTUE;
identifiable circumstances and it was only such
DEATH; ISLAM; ISLAMIC ETHICS; ISLAMIC MEDICAL
statements which, if true, provided genuine factual
ETHICS; LEGAL PHILOSOPHY; MEDICAL ETHICS, HIS-
information, or, if they were false, misinformation.
TORICAL; PLATO; WAR AND PEACE.
The point of this doctrine was to distinguish sense
from nonsense. All traditional metaphysical state-
Bibliography ments, such as statements about the Absolute, were
thereby supposed to be exhibited as meaningless,
Works by Avicenna and so were theological statements as advanced by
The Life of Ibn Sina. Edited and translated by William E. most modern believers. (Belief in visible gods, such
Gohlman. Albany: SUNY Press, 1974. as those the Greeks believed were living on Mount
Healing: Metaphysics X. Translated by Michael E. Mar- Olympus, was simply false.) The meaninglessness of
mura. In Medieval Political Philosophy: A Sourcebook, all such statements, on their criterion, was no prob-
edited by Ralph Lerner and Muhsin Mahdi, 98–111. lem for the logical positivist since it was expressly
New York: The Free Press of Glencoe, 1963. designed to show this. But ethical statements were
rather more problematic for, while a society which
Works about Avicenna had no use for metaphysics, theology, or religion was
Butterworth, Charles E. “Medieval Islamic Philosophy and much to their liking, they were not quite happy to
the Virtue of Ethics.” Arabica 34 (1987): 221–50. urge a society emptied of all moral thought and con-
Marmura, Michael E. “Avicenna on Primary Concepts in cern (though some critics took this to be the upshot
the Metaphysics of his al-Shifā.” In Logos Islamikos: of their doctrine).
Studia Islamica in Honorem Georgii Michaelis Wick- Moritz Schlick (1882–1936), the founder of the
ens, edited by Roger M. Savory and Dionisius A. Agius, Vienna Circle, had interpreted ethical statements as
219–40. Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval
informative about the effects on human HAPPINESS
Studies, 1984.
of various forms of behaviour. To call an action
Charles E. Butterworth “right” was to say that it promoted human happiness
while to call it “wrong” was to say that it did the
opposite.
Ayer, however, could not accept this, for he be-
Ayer, A[lfred] J[ules] lieved that G. E. MOORE (1873–1958) had shown,
(1910–1989) with his doctrine of the NATURALISTIC FALLACY, that
A. J. Ayer wrote little in philosophical ethics, but it it could never be an analytic truth that actions with
was not without importance. His position differs certain empirically identifiable consequences (such
only marginally from the more elaborately worked as an increase or decrease of human happiness) were
out EMOTIVISM of Charles L. STEVENSON (1908– right, or were wrong, since in applying these ethical
1979). predicates to such actions one was evidently engag-
In his notorious first book, Language, Truth and ing in something other than mere tautology. Ayer’s
Logic (1936), Ayer’s main concern was to provide alternative view was that ethical statements were
an account of ethical statements which was com- factually meaningless but served to express our fa-
patible with the logical positivist doctrine of which vourable or unfavourable feelings toward some-
it was the main British exposition. According to the thing. They were no more true or false than such
positivist’s verification principle as there formulated exclamations as “Hooray for English beer” or
there were only two types of meaningful factual “Down with English cooking”; in fact some typical
statement: analytic statements and empirically test- ethical “statements” were virtually equivalent to
able hypotheses. All necessary truths, such as those such exclamations as “Hooray for capital punish-
of logic and of mathematics, were analytic, that is, ment” or “Down with adulterers.” This emotivist

116
Ayer, A. J.

analysis of ethical statements was sharply distin- dones it or not. For to say that torture is wrong in
guished from the subjectivist analysis according to all circumstances is to express and attempt to arouse
which they asserted something about the speaker’s in others an unfavourable attitude to it wherever and
feelings, since that would make them mere state- whenever practised. The emotivist is not saying that
ments of psychological fact and render ethical dis- there is nothing right or wrong but thinking makes
agreement impossible (since what I say about my it so. For to say that is to express the rather peculiar
feelings cannot contradict the truth of what you say attitude of favouring all actions which the agent re-
about yours). gards as morally satisfactory—for example, the per-
From the point of view of his later cooler reflec- secution of the Jews by the Nazis, something unlikely
tions Ayer thought it a mistake to have treated the to be endorsed by the emotivist philosopher. An as-
alleged meaninglessness of theological and of ethical similation of emotivism to ethical relativism is a still
statements as on a par. For while he wished to dis- worse mistake than its confusion with SUBJECTIVISM
miss theology and religion as nonsense to be avoided as characterised above.
he did not really wish so to dismiss moral thinking Emotivism was a metaethical analysis of ethical
or morality. The essential doctrine was formulated language, not the expression of a moral position.
more satisfactorily in his article “On the Analysis of And Ayer held that the expression of moral opinions
Moral Judgements” (1949). Here it is attitudes had no role in philosophy proper, as philosophical
rather than feelings which are expressed by moral argument had no bearing on their acceptability. Ayer
judgements, and it is suggested that “moral attitudes did, however, give some expression to his own eth-
consist in certain patterns of behaviour, and that the ical outlook which might be described as qualified
expression of a moral judgement is an element in the desire-fulfilment UTILITARIANISM. Though favoura-
pattern.” Likewise the role of moral argument is up- bly disposed to Jeremy BENTHAM’s (1748–1832)
graded, though our “reasons” for our moral views greatest happiness principle he drew back from its
are simply the considerations which prompt them in complete endorsement for such reasons as that it
ourselves and to which we refer in the effort to per- might justify the persecution of minorities to fulfil
suade others to share them. Thus when I say that an the desires of the majority.
action is wrong I am committing myself and urging
See also: ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY AND ETHICS; EMO-
others to avoid such actions, but there is no factual
TIVISM; LOGIC AND ETHICS; MOORE; MORAL RELA-
truth about the matter. “True” and “false” may, in-
TIVISM; NATURALISTIC FALLACY; RELIGION; STEVEN-
deed, be used to show agreement or disagreement
SON; SUBJECTIVISM; THEOLOGICAL ETHICS.
with a moral position, but their use is logically
misleading.
This is completely different, argues Ayer, from the Bibliography
MORAL RELATIVISM which asserts that what is right
or wrong varies from society to society or that any- Ayer, A. J. Language, Truth and Logic. Rev. ed. London:
Victor Gollancz, 1946 [1936]. Chapter 6.
thing goes which the agent himself thinks right.
There is nothing logically or philosophically suspect ———. Philosophical Essays. London: Macmillan, 1954.
Essays 10 and 11.
in someone holding that TORTURE is absolutely
wrong, independently of whether any society con- Timothy L. S. Sprigge

117
B

bad faith is itself in bad faith since it both knows and does not
know what to allow into consciousness), Sartre re-
One of the lasting contributions of Jean-Paul SARTRE
lies instead on two dimensions of a totally translu-
(1905–1980) to the philosophical vocabulary is the
cent consciousness: thetic or reflective conscious-
expression “bad faith” (la mauvaise foi). In common
ness, and nonthetic or prereflective consciousness.
parlance it has become synonymous with SELF-
The latter is the direct consciousness that we have
DECEPTION, insincerity, or both. There is some truth
before we advert to the fact that we are conscious.
to each claim yet none exhausts its proper usage in In fact, throughout many of his subsequent writings
the Sartrean sense. As one might expect from its au- and at greatest length in his existentialist psychoan-
thor, the term carries meanings that are at once on- alyses of Jean Genet (1910–1986) and Gustave
tological, epistemological, psychological, and moral. Flaubert (1821–1880), we find Sartre ascribing to
Introduced in his masterwork, Being and Noth- a nonthetically conscious subject intentions and re-
ingness (1943; subtitled “An Essay in Phenomeno- sponsibilities that Freudians would have attributed
logical Ontology”), the term presupposes that one to the unconscious. If lying to another requires no
and the same human individual is radically divided special ontology, lying to oneself clearly does, espe-
between domains of spontaneity and inertia (being- cially when this self-deception occurs within the
for-itself and being-in-itself). The resultant “inner unity of a single, translucent consciousness. What
distance” that characterizes human reality is the on- keeps bad faith from being a “cynical lie” is that it
tological condition for the phenomenon of bad faith. occurs at the level of prereflective consciousness. On
Because it is conscious, human reality is never fully the other hand, for that reason, it may resemble what
identical with itself; it is always “other” than itself is often described as crass or supine ignorance—one
in its temporal dimensions and in the relation of in- suspects there may be better evidence to the contrary
ternal negation that Sartre calls “nihilation” which but doesn’t bother to investigate.
distances the human individual from other individ- Epistemologically, the “faith” of “bad faith” pre-
uals and from its very own self. This is the ontolog- sumes a readiness to rest content with “nonpersua-
ical source of Sartrean freedom: Human reality is sive evidence.” Sartre has a very Husserlian notion
free because it is not a self (which would constitute of evidence as “the intuitive possession of the ob-
thing-like inertia) but a presence-to-self. This duality ject,” minus Husserl’s epistemic nuances. The origi-
is the reason an individual can exist in a state of self- nal project of bad faith is a decision in bad faith on
deception. Without appeal to an unconscious, which the nature of faith, namely, to be persuaded by in-
he explicitly denies (the Freudian censor, he believes, adequate evidence. This is not a reflective, voluntary

118
bad faith

decision but a spontaneous determination of our reflected on because of the “otherness” that infects
way of existing, a determination of which we are every act of reflection: “To believe is to know [re-
prereflectively aware. “One puts oneself in bad faith flectively] that one believes, and to know that one
as one goes to sleep and one is in bad faith as one believes is no longer to believe” (Being and Noth-
dreams” (Being and Nothingness). An entire world- ingness). Such is the circle of spontaneity and inertia
view of bad faith can ensue from this attitude. In that pervades human reality at every turn.
fact, Sartre’s lengthy description of society in Sec- Morally, bad faith is often seen along with inau-
ond Empire France could be read as an example of thenticity, with which it is sometimes identified, as
such a Weltanschauung. the primary existential vice. And yet Sartre, in his
Epistemology and ontology overlap when bad lecture “Existentialism Is a Humanism” (delivered
faith is seen as a fundamental denial of our ontolog- 1945), remarks that anyone who seeks to excuse
ical condition, namely, the denial that the human be- himself by appeal to some deterministic doctrine is
ing is both facticity (in-itself as the given of our sit- a self-deceiver. He then asks himself: “But why
uation) and transcendence of this facticity (for-itself should he not chose to deceive himself?”, and re-
as project). “Bad faith seeks to affirm their identity plies: “It is not for me to judge him morally, but I
while preserving their differences.” The most com- define his bad faith as an error.” This seems to con-
mon form of bad faith seeks to identify with our past firm Sartre’s remark that while HEIDEGGER’s
or with the image others have formed of us. In other (1889–1976) term AUTHENTICITY (Eigentlichkeit),
words, it collapses our transcendence into our fac- despite the author’s objections, carries a clearly
ticity. Such is the condition of the “perfect waiter” moral denotation, “bad faith” does not. The latter is
who wishes to be a waiter in full self-identity, a futile simply an error of judgment. But this stands in such
gesture because consciousness disturbs any would-be contrast with Sartre’s evaluative use of the expres-
identity by the otherness it necessarily introduces. sion throughout his work, not to mention its em-
But our ambivalent condition also enables us to live ployment in ordinary language, that one has the
in denial of our facticity and to project ourselves right to be skeptical about Sartre’s interpretation of
entirely into our possibilities. This is the bad faith of this term in his own work. Since prereflective con-
James Thurber’s (1894–1961) character Walter sciousness is aware of our nonself-coincidence and
Mitty, who exists in a phantasy world with no ac- hence of the self-deception of bad faith, “we are
knowledged link to his factical existence. Every act without excuse.” In a well-known footnote at the
of bad faith is first of all a lie about our human con- conclusion of the chapter in Being and Nothingness
dition of nonself-coincidence and the freedom and on bad faith, Sartre explains:
RESPONSIBILITY that this entails. It is an attempt to
overcome rather than to live positively with this If it is indifferent whether one is in good or
“metastable” condition of presence-to-self that Sar- bad faith, because bad faith re-apprehends
tre describes famously as “being what one is not and good faith and slides to the very origin of the
not-being what one is.” This is why Sartre can claim project of good faith, that does not mean that
that sincerity, the supposed antithesis of bad faith we can not radically escape bad faith. But
understood as “insincerity,” is itself in bad faith to this supposes a self-recovery of being which
the extent that the agent claims to be sincere (or was previously corrupted. This self-recovery
identical with any other state or quality) “the way a we shall call authenticity, the description of
stone is a stone.” One can be sincere only in the which has no place here.
manner of not-being it, that is, as being at least pre-
reflectively aware that this situation is both precar-
ious and sustained by an ongoing project. See also: AUTHENTICITY; DE BEAUVOIR; DECEIT; EX-
Psychologically, bad faith entails the flight from ISTENTIAL ETHICS; FREE WILL AND DETERMINISM; HU-
the freedom and responsibility of our ambivalent MANISM; HUSSERL; INTENTION; METAPHYSICS AND
condition. For Sartre, consciousness, because of its EPISTEMOLOGY; PHENOMENOLOGY; PROMISES; PSY-
destabilizing character, conceals in its being a per- CHOANALYSIS; PSYCHOLOGY; RESPONSIBILITY; SAR-
manent risk of bad faith. In fact, all faith is “trou- TRE; SELF-CONTROL; SELF-DECEPTION; SELF-KNOWL-
bled” in Sartre’s view from the moment that it is EDGE; SITUATION ETHICS; WEAKNESS OF WILL.

119
bad faith

Bibliography he was appointed senior lecturer at Melbourne. In


1957, he moved to Canberra University College
Catalano, Joseph. Good Faith and Other Essays: Perspec-
tives on a Sartrean Ethics. Lanham, MD: Rowman and (now Australian National University) to become
Littlefield, 1996. foundation professor. Then in 1962, he moved to the
Fingarette, Herbert. Self-Deception. London: Routledge, United States, where he became chair of the De-
1969. partment of Philosophy at the University of Pitts-
Gordon, Lewis R. Bad Faith and Antiblack Racism. At- burgh, which in recent decades has been one of the
lantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press, 1995. foremost departments in the analytical tradition.
Klemke, E. D., ed. The Meaning of Life. New York: Ox- In 1958, Baier published his major work, The
ford University Press, 1981.
Moral Point of View. This work established him as
Manser, Anthony. “A New Look at Bad Faith.” In Sartre:
one of the three or four leading voices in the school
An Investigation of Some Major Themes, edited by
Simon Glynn. Brookfield, VT: Gower, 1987. of thought known as the good-reasons approach to
Martin, Mike W. Self-Deception and Morality. Lawrence: ethics. Considered a master of ordinary language us-
University Press of Kansas, 1986. age, Baier is credited with explicating the concept of
———, ed. Self-Deception and Self-Understanding. Law- a reason with great insight and rigor. For an account
rence: University Press of Kansas, 1985. of the difference between reason as an excuse, a jus-
Mele, Alfred R. Irrationality: An Essay on Akrasia, Self- tification, or an explanation, there is perhaps none
Deception, and Self-Control. Oxford: Oxford Univer- better than Baier’s.
sity Press, 1985.
Writing in the Hobbesian tradition, but without
Santoni, Ron. Bad Faith, Good Faith, and Authenticity in
Sartre’s Early Philosophy. Philadelphia: Temple Uni-
invoking the role of Thomas HOBBES’s (1588–1679)
versity Press, 1995. famous Sovereign, Baier’s main objectives in the
Sartre, Jean-Paul. Anti-Semite and Jew. Translated by book are (a) to show the supremacy of moral reasons
George J. Becker. New York: Schocken, 1995 [1945]. over all other reasons and (b) to show that reasons
———. Being and Nothingness. Translated by Hazel E. to act morally can be derived from self-interested
Barnes. New York: Philosophical Library, 1948. Tr. of reasons alone. Much of the excitement of the project
L’Être et le néant [1943]. is owing to the fact that its success would entail that
———. Notebooks for an Ethics. Translated by David Pel- ethical EGOISM (roughly: an act is right if and only
lauer. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1992. Tr.
of Cahiers pour une morale (published posthumously;
if it maximizes a person’s own HAPPINESS) is irra-
written 1946–47). tional. The project attempts a kind of moral magic.
The validity of self-interested reasons is not denied
Thomas R. Flynn at all. What is denied, rather, is that the soundness
of ethical egoism follows from such reasons. A non-
egoistic morality is claimed to follow instead. Inter-
Baier, Kurt E. M. (1917– ) estingly, Baier does not take his position to be that
Born and raised in Austria, Kurt Baier studied law there is one true morality, but rather that there are
at the University of Vienna from 1935 to 1938. He true moralities. This position makes him au courant
first pursued a career as a foreign correspondent. He with theses advanced in the field of scholarship now
was based in England during the Nazi revolution known as literary criticism.
and was interned there in 1940. He was able to es- The influence of The Moral Point of View spans
cape to Australia, where he began his formal train- more than three decades, with writers in ethics as
ing in philosophy, taking the B.A. and M.A. degrees different in their philosophical inclinations as David
(1944, 1947) at the University of Melbourne; there Gauthier, Alan GEWIRTH, Derek Parfit, and John
he was appointed lecturer in philosophy. In 1949, RAWLS acknowledging its influence. Few would
however, Baier decided to return to England in order claim that Baier succeeded in his project. To varying
to receive more formal philosophical training at Ox- degrees, this project has been attempted by others—
ford University, where he studied with John Austin some who have buttressed their arguments with the
(1911–1960), H. L. A. HART (1907–1992), Gilbert theoretical machinery and rigor of RATIONAL CHOICE
Ryle (1900–1976), and Stephen Toulmin. He re- theory; yet it is not clear that others have been any
ceived his D. Phil. from Oxford in 1952 and re- more successful. It seems that either the project will
turned to Australia in 1955, where shortly thereafter succeed as Baier formulated it or it will not succeed

120
Balguy, John

at all. And this is perhaps a great testimony to the Richards, David A. J. A Theory of Reasons for Action.
clarity of Baier’s thought and the depth of his New York: Oxford University Press, 1971.
insight. Thomas, Laurence, ed. Kurt Baier Festschrift. In Synthese
72 (1987). Essays by Stephen L. Darwall, David Gau-
Baier remains convinced that his project can suc-
thier, James P. Sterba, David A. J. Richards.
ceed. As he continues to defend it with characteristic
clarity, he continues to contribute to our understand- Laurence Thomas
ing of the notion of a good reason, having recently
observed that a theory can satisfy the formal con-
ditions of rationality and yet be unreasonable. This
he thinks is true of ethical egoism.
Balguy, John (1686–1748)
Kurt Baier retired as Distinguished Service Pro- English moral philosopher and theologian. Balguy
fessor of Philosophy Emeritus at the University of defended a rationalist view of ethics, influenced by
Pittsburgh. He is the author of over seventy articles, Samuel CLARKE (1675–1729), against the moral
including influential ones in the philosophy of mind sense theories of SHAFTESBURY (1671–1713) and
and political theory and on the topic of AUTHORITY HUTCHESON (1694–1746). Balguy’s most important
especially. ethical work is his highly polemical Foundations of
Moral Goodness, published in two parts. In Part I
See also: ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY AND ETHICS;
(1728), he criticizes Hutcheson’s moral sense theory
AUTHORITY; CRITICAL THEORY; EGOISM; EXCUSES; GE-
and responds to criticisms Hutcheson brought
WIRTH; HISTORY OF WESTERN ETHICS 12: TWENTIETH-
against earlier rationalist theories in his An Inquiry
CENTURY ANGLO-AMERICAN; HOBBES; IMPARTIAL-
concerning Moral Good and Evil (1726) and Illus-
ITY; MORAL POINT OF VIEW; MORAL REASONING;
trations on the Moral Sense (1728). Hutcheson, in
MORAL RULES; RATIONAL CHOICE; RATIONALITY VS.
turn, responds to Balguy in later editions of the Il-
REASONABLENESS; RAWLS; REASONS FOR ACTION;
lustrations. In Part II (1729), Balguy responds to
VIRTUE ETHICS.
forty queries put by a follower of Hutcheson. Be-
cause of the polemical nature of his writings, Bal-
Bibliography guy’s exposition of his rationalism is not systematic;
it emerges in a piecemeal way in his criticisms of and
Works by Baier responses to the sentimentalists.
The Rational and the Moral Order: The Social Roots of Balguy is important because he signals a shift in
Reason and Morality. Chicago: Open Court, 1995. the direction of the British moralist debate. The de-
The Moral Point of View: A Rational Basis of Ethics. Ith- bate is now between the sentimentalists and the ra-
aca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1958. Abridged un- tionalists. There is agreement between Balguy and
der the same title, New York: Random House, 1966. Hutcheson, against HOBBES (1588–1679), on key
“Rationality, Reason, and the Good.” In Morality, Reason issues: Benevolent affections are an original part of
and Truth: New Essays on the Foundations of Ethics, human nature; the motivation and approval of virtue
edited by David Copp and David Zimmerman, 194–
211. Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Allanheld, 1985.
is disinterested; morality is not artificial, the result
“The Social Source of Reason.” Proceedings and Ad-
of a compact, nor is it to be identified with the posi-
dresses of the American Philosophical Association 51 tive laws of a sovereign. They also agree, against le-
(1978): 707–22. galistic theological theories, that the standard of
right and wrong conduct is not to be grounded in
God’s will. Theories that ground morality in God’s
Works about Baier
will, positive law, or a compact were taken by critics
Darwall, Stephen. Impartial Reason. Ithaca, NY: Cornell as implying that morality is something created
University Press, 1983.
wholly by positive means. If morality is created, it is
Hospers, John. Human Conduct: Problems of Ethics. 2d
arbitrary and so not real. Morality must be grounded
ed. New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1972. In
this undergraduate textbook, some of Baier’s central in nature, if it is to be real and worth pursuing.
themes receive a thorough discussion. Both Hutcheson and Balguy agree that virtue con-
Narveson, Jan. Morality and Utility. Baltimore: Johns sists in following nature; but Hutcheson, Balguy
Hopkins University Press, 1967. says, thinks we should follow our instinct rather

121
Balguy, John

than reason. On Hutcheson’s view, as Balguy reads reasons and that actions motivated by benevolent
him, we should follow instinct in two ways: Right affections are not morally worthy. Many of Balguy’s
actions are those motivated by benevolent affections criticisms and points were taken up and developed
(virtue is identified with BENEVOLENCE), and what more systematically by later rationalists (PRICE
makes them right is a moral sense, implanted in us [1723–1791] and REID [1710–1796]). Unlike later
by God, that approves of them. Balguy thinks that rationalists such as Price, Balguy never directly criti-
while Hutcheson is correct in attempting to ground cizes Hutcheson’s Lockean epistemological frame-
morality in nature, he mistakenly identifies our na- work, nor does he provide a rival moral epistemol-
ture with instinct and so the attempt does not suc- ogy.
ceed. Balguy’s central criticism is that morality is as
positive on Hutcheson’s view as on the others. The See also: BENEVOLENCE; CLARKE; FITTINGNESS;
fact that God gives us benevolent affections and a HOBBES; HUME; HUTCHESON; MORAL SENSE THEO-
moral sense that approves of them is just a way for RISTS; PRICE; RATIONAL CHOICE; RATIONALITY VS.

God to create morality by positive means. In the case REASONABLENESS; REASONS FOR ACTION; REID;

of benevolence, Balguy argues that either benevo- SHAFTESBURY.


lence is virtuous in itself or it is not real. If moral
goodness consists in benevolent instincts implanted
in us by God, why did God choose benevolence and Bibliography
not some other affection, for example, malice?
Hutcheson’s reply that God’s perfect goodness con- Works by Balguy
sists in his benevolence, and so he prefers benevo-
A Collection of Tracts Moral and Theological. London,
lence, just pushes the problem back one step. Why 1734. J. Pemberton collected and published most of
is God’s benevolence virtuous? Balguy argues that Balguy’s works, arranging them in the order in which
either a reason can be given, which is then the real they were first published. This collection (with dates
ground of virtue, or God’s goodness is groundless. for the first editions) contains the following: Letter to
If groundless, virtue is arbitrary because God could a Deist Concerning the Beauty and Excellency of Moral
Virtue, and the Support and Improvement which it Re-
have constituted our affectionate natures differently, ceives from Christian Religion (1726), a criticism of
for example, with malicious affections. Virtue is not Shaftesbury; The Foundation of Moral Goodness, Parts
necessarily good. The same argument applies to the I (1728) and II (1729); Divine Rectitude: or, A Brief
moral sense. God could have constituted our moral Inquiry Concerning the Moral Perfections of the Deity,
sense differently, making us approve of ingratitude, Particularly in Respect of Creation (1730); A Second
Letter to a Deist, Concerning a Late Book, Entitled
malice, and so on, and then those acts would be
“Christianity as old as the Creation,” more particularly
right. Either actions are intrinsically and so neces- that Chapter which relates to Dr. Clarke (1731); The
sarily right, or rightness is arbitrary. Balguy con- Law of Truth, or The Obligations of Reason Essential
cludes that virtue and rightness no more depend on to all Religion (1733).
affections or a moral sense than they do on positive
law. There must be something in actions absolutely
good or right antecedent to both affections and law. Works about Balguy
Balguy, following Clarke, claims that moral good- Monro, D. H. A Guide to the British Moralists. London:
ness is a necessary relation between an action and Wm. Collins Sons, 1972.
its situation discoverable by means of reason (e.g., a Price, Richard. A Review of the Principal Questions in
relation of agreement or fitness holds between GRAT- Morals. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1948
ITUDE and kindness; disagreement or unfitness be- [1787]. Reprint, with critical introduction by D. D.
tween ingratitude and kindness). Balguy also makes Raphael, of the 3d edition (1787).
a distinction between external, natural obligation, Selby-Bigge, L. A. British Moralists. Oxford: Clarendon
and internal, moral obligation. He insists that gen- Press, 1897. See the introduction, volume 1.
uinely virtuous actions not only conform to what is Silvester, Tipping. Moral and Christian Benevolence: A
Sermon Containing Reflections upon Mr. Balguy’s Es-
morally right but also are motivated by the rational
say on Moral Goodness. London, 1734.
perception of their rightness. He thus claims, against
Hutcheson, that justifying reasons may be exciting Charlotte Brown

122
bargaining

bargaining tent that it does, enjoy a higher level of preference-


satisfaction and welfare than communities that do
Bargaining is a social practice involving at least two
not. But this presumption in favor of bargaining and
parties, each of whom seeks agreement on some ad-
market systems of distribution is challenged by sev-
vantageous form of cooperation. As a central feature
eral types of consideration. Depending on the issue,
of markets, bargaining has been studied by econo-
the community may act to void the legal effects of
mists, some of whom have developed theoretical
bargained-for agreements, to place special obliga-
models of it. As a preamble to contract, bargaining
tions on would-be bargainers, to prosecute or hold
is typified in the familiar rituals of marketplace dick-
civilly liable one or both of the participants, or to
ering and real estate transactions: inspection of
substitute or add other social mechanisms for con-
goods, offer, rejection, concession, counteroffer, and
ferring entitlement (e.g., rationing).
so on until walkout or acceptance. Though buyers Children and the demented, for example, who
characteristically prefer agreement at a lower price lack stable preferences reasonably congruent with
and sellers at a higher one, barring deadlock, the their welfare, who do not exhibit an adequate grasp
parties will settle at a price acceptable to both. of the world and the consequences of their behavior,
Bargaining, presupposing a diversity of legitimate are appropriately excluded from many forms of bar-
INTERESTS among the actors, may be distinguished
gaining. One can expect bargains to make partici-
from two closely related notions. On one side of the pating parties better off only if they have the capacity
concept, the give-and-take of negotiation shades into to act in their own interests. Consent is vitiated
reasoned discussion. There is no need for concession where that capacity is lost or undeveloped.
where the parties take themselves to have common Consent may also be questioned when a party is
interests: it is rather a question of how to secure or ignorant of or mistaken about material facts. While
maximize some collective good. On the other side, requirements of disclosure are often low in what
bargaining can subtly intensify into conflict. Where lawyers call “arms’-length” relationships, they are
the parties take themselves to have mutually incom- often higher where lay people must entrust impor-
patible, nonnegotiable interests, the ensuing threats tant matters to hired specialists. In medicine and
and acts of force are characteristically intended to law, for example, professionals typically have a fi-
bring about submission rather than cooperation. duciary obligation, beyond the mere prohibition of
As a social practice, bargaining derives appeal fraud, to disclose risks associated with their services.
from its voluntary character, from its implicit ac- Like small children in a strange world, the patient
knowledgment of the diversity of human interests, and the defendant may need instruction—reasoned
and from its contribution to economic efficiency in discussion on the client’s interests as a collective
the social distribution of goods. It is voluntary in good—if they are to choose wisely. Similarly, legally
that either party can break off negotiations, settle- mandated warning labels on cigarette advertising,
ment requires mutual CONSENT, and agreement will package inserts enclosed with prescription drugs,
be vitiated by COERCION and fraud. The goods waiting periods on door-to-door sales contracts,
sought through free exchange are as varied as hu- and prohibitions on tampering with automobile
man DESIRE itself. And, as economists like to stress, odometers all have the softly paternalistic effect of
each party can be expected to emerge from agree- improving the lay consumer’s capacity for RATIONAL
ment better off. For where an offer is advantageous CHOICE.
enough to make (the only kind a rational person will Hard PATERNALISM would impose controversial
make) and attractive enough to accept (the only kind and often odious restrictions on bargained-for ex-
a rational person will accept), both parties will im- changes even where participants are competent, ad-
prove on the endowments of their initial bargaining equately informed, and have had ample opportunity
positions by settling. to deliberate. Nonphysicians, for example, may not
Assuming that the legitimate claims of nonparti- perform surgery even when patients choose the ser-
cipants are respected, it would appear that the com- vices voluntarily and in full understanding of the
munity that facilitates bargaining, respecting vol- risks and benefits of available alternatives. Compa-
untary exchanges of ENTITLEMENTS and relying on rable bargains involving the sale of bodily organs,
the market for distributing goods, can, to the ex- drugs, or sexual services, selling oneself into SLAV-

123
bargaining

ERY, and assistance in SUICIDE have been opposed Like Swimmer, Patient must also choose between
on the heatedly contested grounds that the transac- death and an equivalent indebtedness. And yet few
tions are objectively bad for one or both parties. would routinely permit patients, on that basis, to
Closely related are restrictions imposed in the in- void their bills for vital medical services.
terests of securing certain collective goods. Though There are several standard ways to ease the ten-
some workers might benefit by negotiating with em- sion here. Some—libertarians, for example—would
ployers as individuals, union contracts intended to honor both agreements. Bystander and Doctor are
benefit all employees characteristically impose pro- not threatening to impose harm, the offers do not
hibitions on separate arrangements that undercut make Swimmer and Patient any worse off than they
the terms of collectively bargained agreements. Sim- were in their preproposal situations, nor are the two
ilarly, inalienable RIGHTS —e.g., the right to declare of them somehow entitled to the services they need.
bankruptcy, to file for divorce, and the right to trial Others would press us to acknowledge the special
by jury—are precisely those that may not be given entitlements of the vulnerable. It shocks the CON-
up as part of an enforceable contractual agreement. SCIENCE not to recognize a duty to intervene in the
Though these restrictions on bargaining are some- easy-rescue cases; it is scandalous not to have a right
times defended on paternalistic grounds (see the to desperately needed medical services. If bystanders
preceding paragraph), justification can rest on the had clear legal obligations to shoulder minimal in-
overall desirability of certain social practices. DE- conveniences in order to effect rescues, and if doc-
MOCRACY, for example, cannot survive when citi- tors worked within a national health service, neither
zens bargain away the right to vote for candidates would be permitted to extort tribute from the pre-
of their choice. cariously placed.
Much like voters in a democracy, judges, prose- Still others would focus, neither on the fact of
cuting attorneys, university admissions committees, agreement nor on the vulnerability of the bargainer,
purchasing agents, tax assessors, building inspec- but on the terms of the bargains themselves. While
tors, and so on, all occupy roles in preeminently cor- $10,000 is plainly an excessive price for modest as-
ruptible INSTITUTIONS. Those who occupy such po- sistance out of the water, it may not be unreasonable
sitions characteristically have obligations to exercise to have to pay $10,000 for $10,000 worth of critical
their discretionary POWER in the proper interests of medical care. This third approach requires that we
the institution. BRIBERY and extortion are prohibited distinguish the subjective value of a good (what one
even where all the actors welcome such exchanges. might agree to pay for it under the press of circum-
A good deal of attention has been given to a com- stance) from its objective value, a variation on the
plex of problems involving what have been called medieval theme of the just price. Bystander and
“coercive offers.” Consider the following heavily de- Doctor should receive a fair amount for their efforts,
bated cases: a price approximating objective value. But no one is
entitled to unjust enrichment acquired through EX-
PLOITATION of the vulnerable.
Case 1. Swimmer is drowning near Bystander
who is uniquely and easily able to effect a Under capitalism, the social practice of bargain-
rescue. Bystander offers to save Swimmer ing is close to the heart of economic life. In at least
in exchange for $10,000. some respects, our assessment of the quality of fun-
damental institutions can turn on how we under-
stand the proper place of bargaining transactions
Many would find such agreements void in virtue of and the constraints and limitations that should be
Swimmer’s hard-pressed circumstance: having to imposed on them.
choose between death and a substantial financial
burden. But consider: See also: BAD FAITH; BLACKMAIL; BUSINESS ETHICS;
CHEATING; COERCION; COMPROMISE; CONSENT; CON-
Case 2. Patient is close to death as a TRACTS; COOPERATION, CONFLICT, AND COORDINA-
consequence of a medical condition that TION; CORRUPTION; DECEIT; DETERRENCE, THREATS,
only Doctor can cure. Doctor offers to AND RETALIATION; DISCOUNTING THE FUTURE; ECO-
treat Patient in exchange for $10,000. NOMIC ANALYSIS; ECONOMIC SYSTEMS; ENTITLE-

124
Barry, Brian (M.)

MENTS; EXPLOITATION; FAIRNESS; FIDUCIARY RELA- Illinois Press, 1975. Instructively presented anthology
TIONSHIPS; HONOR; INTEGRITY; INTERESTS; JUSTICE,
of classical papers in the theory of bargaining.
CIRCUMSTANCES OF; JUSTICE, DISTRIBUTIVE; LEGAL Kenneth Kipnis
ETHICS; LIBERALISM; LIBERTARIANISM; MEDICAL
ETHICS; MORAL COMMUNITY, BOUNDARIES OF;
NEEDS; PATERNALISM; PROFESSIONAL ETHICS; RA-
TIONAL CHOICE; RIGHT HOLDERS; RIGHTS; RISK; VOL-
Barry, Brian (M.)
UNTARY ACTS. Peripatetic and prolific, Brian Barry is an Anglo-
American political theorist who has been influential
for his work on theories of justice and DEMOCRACY.
Bibliography Barry has taught at Essex, Oxford, University of Brit-
ish Columbia, University of Chicago, California In-
Frankfurt, Harry G. “Coercion and Moral Responsibility.” stitute of Technology, the London School of Eco-
In Essays on Freedom of Action, edited by Ted Hon-
nomics, and, beginning in 1998, at Columbia
derich, 65–86. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul,
1973. Coercive offers. University in New York.
Barry’s first major work, Political Argument
Gauthier, David. Morals by Agreement. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1986. Bargaining theory as a basis for (1965), called for a research program in the analyt-
ethics. ical study of politics. This research would result
Golash, Deirdre. “Exploitation and Coercion.” Journal of from the “marriage” of “analytical philosophy” with
Value Inquiry 15 (1981): 319–28. Develops a concep- its analysis of concepts and values, and “analytical
tion of objective value. politics” with its empirical models. The aspiration
Goodin, Robert E. Protecting the Vulnerable: A Reanaly- was for “a certain degree of analytical rigor” in
sis of Our Social Responsibilities. Chicago: University studying the forms of INSTITUTIONS that might
of Chicago Press, 1985. Argues for obligations to the
achieve the values identified. In the four decades
vulnerable.
since that work was started, Barry’s writings have
Kipnis, Kenneth. “Criminal Justice and the Negotiated
Plea.” Ethics 86 (1976): 93–106. Assessment of plea
set an example for that kind of analytical political
bargaining. theory.
Lyons, David. “The Last Word on Coercive Offers . . . ?” If there is a theme running through all of Barry’s
Philosophy Research Archives, 393–414. Bowling diverse writings, it is the prospects and limitations
Green, OH: Philosophy Documentation Center, 1983. of “rationality” both for normative evaluation and
A review of the area. for empirical explanation. In Political Argument, he
Nozick, Robert. “Coercion.” In Philosophy, Politics and defended the possibility of making consistent nor-
Society: 4th Series, edited by Peter Laslett, W. G. Run- mative judgments, despite what he argued to be the
ciman, and Quentin Skinner, 101–34. New York:
inevitable pluralism and ultimate incommensurabil-
Barnes and Noble, 1972 [1969]. Influential early anal-
ysis of coercion. ity of political principles. He provided a vocabulary
Postow, B.C. “Coercion and the Moral Bindingness of
that has been widely used for classifying kinds of
Contracts.” Social Theory and Practice 4 (1976): 75– political principles—distinctions between principles
91. Economic necessity, capitalism, exploitation. that are “want-regarding” or “ideal regarding,” those
Scanlon, Thomas M. “Liberty, Contract, and Contribu- that are “public regarding” or “private regarding,”
tion.” In Markets and Morals, edited by Gerald Dwor- and those that are “aggregative” or “distributive.”
kin, Gordon Bermant, and Peter G. Brown, 43–67. Barry argued that these distinctions identify kinds of
New York: Halsted, 1977. Discusses limiting the mar- principles that are ultimately incommensurable.
ket to prevent political domination through control of
essential goods.
Nevertheless, we can establish a basis for rational
consistency in our evaluations by employing an “in-
VanDeVeer, Donald. Paternalism. Princeton, NJ: Prince-
ton University Press, 1987. difference curve” analysis akin to that employed in
Wertheimer, Alan. Coercion. Princeton, NJ: Princeton Uni-
economics. Just as economists will chart the com-
versity Press, 1987. Comprehensive discussion of binations of grapes and potatoes that people are in-
blackmail, duress, necessity, coercive proposals, ex- different between, Barry illustrated trade-offs be-
ploitation, etc. tween efficiency and equity which a rational person,
Young, Oran R., ed. Bargaining. Urbana: University of under certain assumptions, would be indifferent be-

125
Barry, Brian (M.)

tween. This analysis nicely illustrated the complex of certainty that warrants its imposition on those
structures that MORAL PLURALISM and complexity who reject it.” Barry is attempting to employ a more
could take, while conforming to some fairly sim- modest version of John RAWLS’s famous “original
ple and straightforward notions borrowed from position,” one which does not employ the famous
economics. device of a RATIONAL CHOICE behind a “veil of ig-
In Sociologists, Economists and Democracy norance.” Among other reasons for doing away with
(1970), Barry took note of the flowering of the an- the Rawlsian original position, Barry questions
alytical study of politics. Political theory “had for whether “the concept of rationality is strong enough
many years been regarded as something that had oc- to generate a unique solution.” Instead, Barry de-
curred in the past, but could hardly be expected to velops a more modest version, which he calls the
happen nowadays—rather like the Church of Eng- “circumstances of impartiality” and which builds on
land’s view of miracles.” But now the “academic work originally suggested by T. M. Scanlon (and de-
study of politics” has “shown signs of becoming a veloped independently by Scanlon in What We Owe
theoretical subject.” Barry set out one fruitful area to Each Other, 1999). The circumstances of justice
for this development—the connections between in- differ from the original position in two essential
dividual choice and collective decision. The ration- ways. First, “the parties are aware of their identities
ality of voting and political behaviour, of individual and hence of their own interests” and second, they
contributions to collective goods, and of collective are no longer merely self-interested, but motivated
decisions resulting from individual voting decisions by the “desire for reasonable agreement.”
were all explored, both in Sociologists, Economists However, as Barry admits, the Rawlsian version
and Democracy and in Rational Man and Irrational of a choice situation for principles of justice, by ab-
Society? (1982). In the latter volume, Barry (and his stracting from all elements that might lead to differ-
co-editor, Russell Hardin) decried the notion that ent outcomes, at least was designed to lead to a def-
“rationality has displaced both truth and morality as inite conclusion. The looser version which Barry
the ultimate criterion for judging both belief and proposes may lead to different results depending on
conduct.” They argued that we needed to lower ex- what preferences people have, what information
pectations for the research program that held that they have, and what motivations they have. How-
“truth is what it is rational (in ideal conditions) to ever, Barry conceives of a partly a priori and partly
believe, and that principles of justice are what it is “empirical” strategy for dealing with this problem.
rational (in ideal conditions) to adopt.” They con- A priori reasoning can narrow the range of accept-
cluded “the concept of rationality cannot be ex- able solutions. After that, there is room for an em-
tended indefinitely to solve all problems of conduct pirical investigation. “Suppose we observe that a
and evaluation.” rule of a certain kind is found only in societies that
Yet by the time of the three-volume Treatise on approximate the circumstances of justice. The more
Social Justice (vol. 1, 1989; vol. II, 1995; volume III often it is found in those societies, the more confi-
in preparation) Barry offered his theory of “justice dent we can be that it would emerge from a Scan-
as impartiality” as an assertion of the “possibility of lonian original position.” While Barry illustrates this
putting forward a universally valid case in favour of strategy with issues of economic INEQUALITY, he is
liberal egalitarian principles.” His theory was an ex- really launching a research agenda that is partly a
tension of “the ‘Enlightenment project’ of address- priori and partly empirical in its possible application
ing the reason of every human being of sound mind.” to a host of issues. In doing so, he is exemplifying
He rejected the notion that such aspirations were an the aspiration to combine philosophical analysis and
error. Otherwise how could violations of HUMAN the empirical study of politics with which he started
RIGHTS be condemned in countries that had no tra- his career.
ditions of respecting them?
Despite these enlightenment aspirations, a key See also: ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY AND ETHICS; COL-
factor in Barry’s theory of justice is the “need for LECTIVE RESPONSIBILITY; COMMENSURABILITY; COM-
scepticism,” by which he means scepticism about MON GOOD; COST-BENEFIT ANALYSIS; DEMOCRACY;
theories of the good. Barry holds “that no concep- ECONOMIC ANALYSIS; EQUALITY; FUTURE GENERA-
tion of the good can justifiably be held with a degree TIONS; GOOD, THEORIES OF THE; IMPARTIALITY; IN-

126
Beccaria, Cesare

DIVIDUALISM; INTERESTS; JUSTICE, CIRCUMSTANCES in Italy; after its translation into French, it was read
OF; LIBERALISM; LIBERTY, ECONOMIC; MORAL PLU- all over Europe. The first of many English-language
RALISM; NEEDS; POLITICAL SYSTEMS; PUBLIC AND PRI- editions appeared in London in 1767. No other trea-
VATE MORALITY; PUBLIC POLICY ANALYSIS; RA- tise on the subject so well captured the spirit of the
TIONAL CHOICE; RATIONALITY VS. REASONABLENESS; continental Enlightenment.
RAWLS; SOCIAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY; SOCIAL Beccaria argued for reform of the criminal law
CONTRACT; TRUST. from two basic principles. One is that the AUTHOR-
ITY of government is derived from “expressed or

Bibliography tacit compacts” among the governed. Thus Bec-


caria’s conception of political obligation is in the
Works by Barry contractarian tradition of HOBBES (1588–1679),
LOCKE (1632–1704), and ROUSSEAU (1712–1778).
Political Argument. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul,
1965.
Second, under the influence of Claude Helvetius
Sociologists, Economists and Democracy. London: Collier-
(1715–1771), he adopted “the greatest happiness of
Macmillan, 1970. the greatest number” as the sole criterion for eval-
The Liberal Theory of Justice. Oxford: Oxford University uating laws and social practices.
Press, 1973. BENTHAM (1748–1832) acknowledged that it
A Treatise on Social Justice. Vol. 1, Theories of Justice. was from Beccaria that he learned this slogan, later
Berkeley: University of California Press, 1989. Vol. 2, popularized by J. S. MILL (1806–1873) and other
Justice as Impartiality. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995. utilitarians. However, Beccaria also appealed to “the
Essays in Political Theory. Vol. I. Democracy, Power and rights of man,” and it is characteristic of the rather
Justice. Vol. II. Liberty and Justice. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1989; 1991.
superficial quality of his philosophy that he evi-
Barry, Brian, and Russell Hardin, eds. Rational Man and
dences no concern over whether the results of his
Irrational Society? An Introduction and Sourcebook. avowed UTILITARIANISM and his rights-based think-
Beverly Hills, CA: Sage, 1982. ing diverge or clash.
Beccaria’s treatise was best known in its day for
Work about Barry its attack on the prevailing practices of the death
penalty and TORTURE. Against torture, his central
Kelly, P. J., ed. Impartiality, Neutrality and Justice: Re-
objection was that it can be guaranteed only to elicit
reading Brian Barry’s ‘Justice as Impartiality.’ Edin-
burgh: Edinburgh University Press, 1998. false testimony from the weak. It is absurd to make
“pain . . . the crucible of truth.” As to PUNISHMENT
James S. Fishkin generally, its sole purpose is “to instill fear in other
men.” Retribution should play no role in justifying
punishment or in apportioning punishments to
Beauvoir, Simone de crimes. Important though deterrence is, it is a func-
See de Beauvoir, Simone. tion not only of the severity of a punishment but
also of the celerity and certainty with which it is
administered.
Against the death penalty, Beccaria argued as fol-
Beccaria, Cesare [Bonesana], lows: (1) Society has no right to punish anyone by
Marchesi di (1738–1794) DEATH, because rational egoistic contractors cannot
Marchese Cesare Beccaria Bonesana was born in and would not transfer to the state their natural right
Milan and studied law at the University of Pavia. to life. (2) The death penalty is “neither useful nor
With the leisure his family’s wealth provided, he de- necessary” for the protection of society. The only
voted himself to literary and intellectual pursuits. possible exception is the offender whose imprison-
Challenged by the suggestion of a friend to write a ment would not eliminate his capacity to foment
brief critical study of criminal justice, he produced “dangerous revolution.” (3) The prospect of long-
in 1764 his chief work, Dei delitti e delle pene (On term imprisonment (“penal slavery”) is a better de-
Crimes and Punishments). Within months the slim terrent than the threat of death; a life in prison may
volume was the subject of impassioned discussion be—and should be perceived to be—far more

127
Beccaria, Cesare

“cruel” than a death on the scaffold. Executions beneficence


present an “example of barbarity,” thereby under-
The principle of beneficence in its simplest form is
mining respect for lawful authority.
that we ought to do good or, if expressed as an ob-
Save for a brief visit to Paris in 1766 at the height
ligation, that there is an obligation to help others. A
of his fame, Beccaria spent his entire life in his native
more substantial version is that human beings ought
Lombardy. He devoted his adult years to a career in
to be taught to be strongly benevolent and benefi-
local public administration; none of his subsequent
cent; where ‘benevolence’ signifies “a wish or dis-
writings added appreciably to his fame or influence.
position to help others”; where ‘beneficence’ signi-
He died in relative obscurity.
fies “actually producing good”; where by helping
See also: CAPITAL PUNISHMENT; CONTRACTARIANISM; others is meant more than helping one’s children,
CORRECTIONAL ETHICS; DETERRENCE, THREATS, AND FAMILY, friends, or country; and, where the degree

RETALIATION; LIFE, RIGHT TO; SOCIAL CONTRACT; to which we ought to help as well as the question
TORTURE; UTILITARIANISM. whether the relevant normative statement is best ex-
pressed as a virtue, definite or indefinite duty, rule,
or cooperative project is left to the particular theory
to specify.
Bibliography One of the most sustained arguments against the
principle is as follows: There is no good reason why
Editions of Beccaria’s Dei delitti:
we, as, moral agents, ought to be beneficent outside
Dei delitti e delle pene. Leghorn, 1764. The original Ital- our own bailiwick, i.e., outside our children, spouse,
ian edition was published anonymously. Best recent in lesser degree friends, and in time of danger our
text is the one edited by Franco Venturi (Turin: Ei- country. A rational person must first address herself
naudi, 1965).
to her own survival. Unless she duly cares for her-
On Crimes and Punishment. Translated by Henry Pao- self, her CARE for others is quickly ended by DEATH.
lucci. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1963. The most
widely used modern English translation. Moreover, when there are more resources than nec-
essary for subsistence, she should use them to attain
On Crimes and Punishments. Translated by David Young.
Indianapolis: Hackett, 1986. A new translation and re- the best possible life. If there is an even greater sur-
ordering of the text, based on the sixth and final (1766) plus, she should put it away as a form of protection,
edition as approved by Beccaria himself. Bibliography. as insurance against loss. Expressed differently: In
On Crimes and Punishments and Other Writings. Trans- the case of bare subsistence or grinding poverty
lated by Richard Davies with Virginia Cox and Richard there is little to distribute; in situations of abun-
Bellamy, and edited by Richard Bellamy. Cambridge: dance, beneficence—or at least that special form of
Cambridge University Press, 1995. Introduction, bib-
beneficence called kindliness (intended helpfulness
liography and biographical glossary. The best and most
recent edition. toward someone in need, not in return for anything,
nor for the advantage of the helper herself)—is not
conducive to her own welfare. It is not conducive
Works about Beccaria because rational living requires that we live well be-
fore giving to others which, in turn, demands ade-
Hart, H. L. A. “Bentham and Beccaria.” In his Essays on
quate savings or its like.
Bentham: Jurisprudence and Political Theory, 40–52.
Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1982. A few preliminary points need to be made before
considering how some influential moral theories
Maestro, Marcello. Cesare Beccaria and the Origins of Pe-
nal Reform. Philadelphia: Temple University Press, may be able to parry or meet this objection. First, it
1973. The standard biography in English. Includes is necessary to distinguish between ALTRUISM and
bibliography. extreme altruism. Extreme altruism requires that we
Sellin, Thorsten. “Beccaria’s Substitute for the Death Pen- sacrifice our own good for the good of others. Typ-
alty.” In Criminology in Perspective: Essays in Honor ically, it does not place limits on what morality or a
of Israel Drapkin, edited by Simha F. Landau, and Les- principle of beneficence can legitimately demand.
lie Sebba, 3–9. Lexington, MA: D.C. Heath, 1977.
Altruism, or to be more accurate, an altruistic the-
Hugo Adam Bedau ory, requires only that we contribute to the welfare

128
beneficence

of other persons, where ‘other person’ denotes low and the vineyards are not to be pruned, to be
more than one’s children, family, friends, or coun- freely shared by all members of the community in
trymen. It follows that all forms of the more sub- order that the poor of your people may eat (Exodus
stantial version of the principle of beneficence are 23:11, Leviticus 25:27); and canceling all debts at
part of altruistic theory; but not that all theories of the end of the seventh year (Deuteronomy 15:2).
altruism must have an explicit formulation of the More general formulations of this duty include the
principle of beneficence. It also follows that altru- injunction to open one’s hand to one’s poor and
ism, per se, does not require sacrifice. Sometimes needy brother (Deuteronomy 15:11) and to relieve
sacrifice is involved; but often it is not. Thomas Na- the oppressed (Isaiah 1:17).
gel correctly observes that sometimes altruistic ac- Traditional Judaism, conceived of as knowledge
tion involves neither self-sacrifice nor nobility—as of divine law, commands and commends benefi-
when we tell someone he has a flat tire, or a wasp cence to the poor. It insists that there is a general
on his hamburger. Second, it is necessary to avoid duty of BENEVOLENCE, beneficence, and specific du-
the quagmire concerning the role of justice. Justice ties of kindliness. Beneficence is considered the sa-
is often viewed as being synonymous with social jus- cred duty of the individual who must return part of
tice or with morality as a whole. It also may be in- what he has received from God. It is the sacred duty
terpreted more narrowly as giving each person his of the community as well to protect its members
due according to a rather stringent interpretation of against the basic vicissitudes of life; and to the extent
merit and dis-merit. Given the latter, proponents of that the community is rational, it recognizes that un-
beneficence neither believe justice has the sufficient less help and care are effectively institutionalized,
normative power a moral theory requires nor do they the hopes of the poor and the needy will be in vain.
believe that when a benefit is conferred as not being In other words, beneficence is rational because it is
due, it is gratuitous. Third, not all advocates of be- part of the ideal way we are required to live in the
neficence formulate their position in terms of the world. It is rational because we are required neither
principle of beneficence. It is true that modern to sacrifice to the point of, or even close to the point
thinkers tend to do so. But others often begin from of, death, nor are we required to enrich our fellow
a larger or different frame of reference, viz., the per- man. We are only required to maintain life, to live
spective of God’s law, the law of LOVE, compassion more simply in order that others may live.
viewed in its broadest sense, or, as in the empiricist
tradition, from role played by sentiment and
A Christian View
EMOTION.
Christianity, or at least a Thomist (THOMAS AQUI-
NAS [1225?–1274]) interpretation of it, differs. It
Traditional Judaism
stresses the redemptive role of Jesus, the definitive
Perhaps the most influential formulation of the AUTHORITY of the Church, and the importance of
principle of beneficence, one often referred to as the practical beneficence in all its forms, by exalting love
GOLDEN RULE, occurs in Leviticus 19:17–18. We are as the root of all virtue. It also is largely responsible
told: “Thou shalt not hate thy brother in thine heart. for explicating certain distinctions. Jesus declared
. . . thou shalt love thy neighbor as thyself.” In the the love of one’s neighbor to be the second great
same chapter we find the additional injunction that commandment besides the love of God which is the
thou shalt love the stranger as thyself (verse 34). first (Matthew 22:39; Mark 12:31; Luke 10:27).
These passages contain two elements: First, they Combining this with the light of reason, we come to
mandate altruism; second, they instruct us to attach understand that the first principle of morality is the
a prima facie, if not actual, weight to the well-being love of God. Because CHARITY is the efficient cause
of another individual that is exactly equal to our which unites man with God, it is a good which is of
own. In addition, there are other definite duties. prime importance. Beneficence, doing good to some-
These include leaving the gleanings of the grain one, is an act of charity. It, therefore, follows that
fields and orchards and vineyards for the poor and every act of beneficence brings us closer to God. Ev-
for the stranger (Leviticus 19:9–10); allowing the erything which is a duty is good; but the converse is
products of the seventh year, when the fields lie fal- not true—good is not always a duty. An obligation

129
beneficence

is imposed by reason and binds the FREE WILL to according to one’s means, for the sake of their HAP-
perform that act which is necessary for the attain- PINESS and without hoping for anything in return).
ment of the last and absolute end. Supererogatory He also explains why the altruistic maxim of benef-
acts, on the other hand, are desirable (as, for ex- icence toward those in need is a universal duty. The
ample, acts of exceptional goodness or heroism), but reason is that all men are to be regarded as fellow
not mandatory. It is in this vein that the story of Jesus men, i.e., as needy rational beings, united in one
speaking to the rich young man and telling him to dwelling place for mutual aid. However, he does not
sell all that he has and distribute it to the poor (Mat- conclude from this that we have a strict (inflexible)
thew 19:16–30; Mark 10:17–31; Luke 18:18–30) duty to help others. His reasons appear to be: first,
is understood by the fathers of the Church as coun- that it is not within our powers to further the ends
sel, not precept. of all men equally, and that this “law” holds only for
To be worthy of full respect, beneficence cannot maxims, not for definite actions; and second, that
be autonomous. It must work from a system of NAT- we ought to regard the duty of beneficence only as
URAL LAW and rules, including rules other than the a laxer (meritorious) duty because raising it to a
injunction to be beneficent. Yet the authority of nat- stricter duty would deprive some men of their free-
ural law does, indeed, mandate a general duty of dom, their autonomy as ends in themselves, and this
charity and sometimes a definite duty of beneficence. simply will not do. In other words, because we re-
We are not required to do good to every single per- spect and wish to preserve the SELF-ESTEEM of other
son since that is impossible; but each one of us is human beings, and because undiscriminating benef-
bound to do good in some particular case; for charity icence may humiliate or encourage them to be less
binds us, not actually to do good to someone, but to self-helpful than they would otherwise be, we cannot
be prepared to do good to anyone if we have time legislate that men must always be helpful to other
and the resources to spare. Whether a particular act men.
is a duty is determined by comparing the relative
needs of self and others, and requires the judgment
of a prudent person. Some thinkers provide a more
Mill and Sidgwick
canonical formulation and conclude that one is mor-
ally required to help when a neighbor is in imminent JOHN STUART MILL (1806–1873) distinguishes
peril of deadly EVIL to soul or body and is unable to between the virtue and obligation of beneficence,
help himself, when the act of help is neither a venial and in the latter sphere, between the obligations of
sin nor an exposure to the proximate occasion of sin, the individual and of the state. Professor Warnock
and when by helping one would not be so similarly suggests that Mill’s thesis, that “actions are right in
imperiled. proportion as they tend to promote happiness,
wrong as they tend to produce the reverse of hap-
piness,” where happiness “is not the agent’s own
Kant
greatest happiness, but the greatest amount of hap-
Immanuel KANT (1724–1804) also maintains piness altogether” (Utilitarianism), reduces to “the
that we have the duty to relieve the fortuitous dis- contention that beneficence is really the sole and suf-
tress of others when we can do so without great in- ficient moral virtue.”
convenience to ourselves. The difficult question is The question of obligation is, of course, more
whether he held more than this. He admits that the complex. Mill maintains that there are “many posi-
grounds for the duty of beneficence lie, in part, in tive acts for the benefit of others” which a person
the fact that human beings are in need of mutual may “rightly be compelled to perform.” Among
help, and that only by means of mutual help can the these he includes certain acts of individual benefi-
systematic harmony of their purposes be attained. cence, such as saving a fellow creature’s life or in-
Kant often talks as though duty requires a person to terposing to protect the defenseless against ill us-
share with others less fortunate than himself, right age—things which whenever it is obviously a man’s
up to the point when all good fortune is equally di- duty to do he may rightly be made responsible to
vided. He maintains that it is a duty of every man to society for not doing. He also adds that a person may
be beneficent (i.e., to be helpful to people in need cause evil to others not only by his actions but his

130
beneficence

inaction and in either case he is justly accountable tivation of these feelings and the disposition to act
to them for the injury. lovingly, but there is a duty to cultivate them so far
Mill does not say only that it is our duty to render as it is possible to do. His discussion implies a dis-
aid because by not doing so, we harm another. Nor tinction between having the strict duty to feel an
does he formulate a principle of beneficence that re- emotion (which he admits is problematic) and the
quires each person to perform the action, of those duty to inculcate these sentiments in such a way so
available, that will make the best outcome. What he that they will excite, when appropriate, love in both
does say is that it is our duty to render aid in certain the helper and the individual helped, to the mutual
circumstances, when if by not doing so we will harm benefit of both. He reminds us that UTILITARIANISM
others, and when we have evaluated that harm ac- does not prescribe that we love everyone equally, but
cording to the principle of utility. Nor is Mill con- that we should aim at happiness “generally as our
flating the notion of having a moral obligation with ultimate end, and so consider the happiness of any
having a legal one. There are many acts which, being one individual as equally important with the equal
directly injurious only to the agent himself or inju- happiness of any other, as an element of this total;
rious to society only in the short run, ought not be and should distribute our kindness so as to make this
legally interdicted. Rather, the ability to help oneself total as great as possible, in whatever way this result
which may thereby accrue, more often than not, has may be obtained.” Then, because of considerations
overriding utility. He concludes that “a State which of PRACTICAL REASON, he retreats from this formu-
dwarfs its men, in order that they may be more doc- lation and seems unclear as to how it is to be best
ile instruments in its hands even for beneficial pur- formulated. One attempt reads that the utilitarian
poses—will find that with small men no great thing doctrine “is that each man ought to consider the
can really be accomplished” (On Liberty). Thus, we happiness of any other as theoretically of equal im-
are left with a principle of beneficence which in part portance with his own, and only of less importance
reads: society has an actual duty to aid others when practically, in so far as he is better able to realize the
by not rendering aid that omission is a causal factor latter.”
in the harm fortuitously suffered by another, and One may respond that this and similar formula-
when that harm would not be outbalanced by the tions represent an overaccommodation to practical
general utility, the felicific beneficence, of having a reason or mistake PRUDENCE for morality. Prudence
society of autonomous, self-respecting, and often may say that we are entitled to give greater weight
creative human beings. to our own INTERESTS and purposes simply because
In The Methods of Ethics, Henry SIDGWICK they are our own, but morality does not always. Al-
(1838–1900) admits that, although this duty is though Peter Singer’s formulation may be vulnerable
more or less unhesitatingly laid down by common to what Liam Murphy calls “the over-demandedness
sense, it is difficult or impossible to extract from it, objection,” Singer maintains (in his essay “Rich and
so far as it is commonly accepted, any clear and pre- Poor”) that there is a relatively unqualified obliga-
cise principles for the determining the extent of the tion to assist others. “Helping is not, as convention-
duty. What may be of more value is his implemen- ally thought, a charitable act which it is praiseworthy
tation of the distinction between principle and to do, but not wrong to omit; it is something that
method, and his fastidious exploration of the prob- everyone ought to do.” One formulation of the ob-
lem of how to reconcile rational self-interest and ligation to assist others is this: “if it is in our power
duty. Sidgwick is convinced that commonsense mo- to prevent something very bad [as, for example, fam-
rality embodies different ultimate principles and that ine] from happening, without thereby sacrificing
one of them is benevolence. Since benevolence (not anything of comparable moral significance, we
in Aristotle, but in modern times) is frequently held ought to do it.” He is aware of the charge that this
to be a supreme and architectonic virtue, he believes may be too strong a formulation. Nonetheless he
this sufficient to give it the first place after the virtue contends that, given the extreme evil of people starv-
of WISDOM. In his polemic against Kant, Sidgwick ing to death, the more conventionally accepted stan-
insists on the importance of the affection of (the dards are too weak and, therefore, are not as plau-
emotional element contained in) love and kindness. sible as his own. He concludes the chapter with a
Not only does benevolence demand at least the cul- tithing suggestion, namely, that there may be some-

131
beneficence

thing to be said for contributing a round percentage the principle of beneficence is a prima facie obliga-
of one’s income, like 10 percent. This suggestion tion. It is always binding unless it conflicts with ob-
serves to remind us that compassion, when limited ligations expressed in another moral principle, in
to working directly with the needy, is often self- which case a balancing of the demands of the two
defeating and is definitely so in the case of famine principles is necessary.
and similarly complex social problems. In this aspect Most important, Rawls’s discussion of this duty
Singer’s utilitarianism invites comparison with one occurs in the context of his discussion of the nature
of the most important practical insights of Judaism and duty of mutual SELF-RESPECT. Parties in the
and Christianity: as meritorious as acts of an indi- original position (where free and equal persons must
vidual (directly) helping are, unless help and care choose to govern in terms of their cooperation)
are effectively institutionalized, the hopes of the know that in a society they need first and foremost
poor and needy will be in vain. to be assured by the esteem of their associates and,
therefore, understand that everyone benefits from
living in a society where the duty of mutual respect
John Rawls
is honored. Similarly, in Political Liberalism, he
RAWLS’s arguments are similar to Kant’s. The writes that the fundamental “importance of self-
duty of mutual aid is a reasonable requirement be- respect is that it provides a secure sense of our own
cause it is not rational for a person to assume that value, a firm conviction that our determinate con-
she will not need help during her lifetime and that ception of the good is worth carrying out. Without
she will not be better off in a society where everyone self-respect nothing may seem worth doing, and if
is prepared to render aid, when needed and when some things have value for us, we lack the will to
they can easily do so. But he also draws a distinction pursue them.” Thus, self-respect as well as other
between actual beneficence and the sense of security, forms of protection seem to be confirmed, if not
confidence, and TRUST which depends on knowing most effectively encouraged and supported, by the
that one can count on others to come to one’s aid. duty of mutual aid.
As such, a decisive rational advantage is gained. For Finally, it should be noted that not all altruistic
“the primary value of the principle is not measured theories can be reduced to, or should be interpreted
by the help we actually receive but rather by the solely in terms of, moral principles. A principle of
sense of confidence and trust in other men’s good beneficence, even if it is combined with other prin-
intentions and the knowledge that they are there if ciples, seems to make little sense, as far as many
we need them” (A Theory of Justice). altruistic thinkers are concerned. Bertrand RUSSELL
Rawls acknowledges that his definition and ar- (1872–1970) argues that, since there is no conceiv-
rangement of this duty is untidy and that he has able way of making people do things they do not
failed to deal with their more detailed specification wish to do, being a moral person is less a matter of
and with questions of priority. Part of the explana- knowing correct principles, and more a matter of
tion is that “there are no obvious rules for settling having right dispositions. Since the only way to mo-
these questions.” Other thinkers make a stronger tivate people is by ethical education, by strengthen-
claim and say that there are not (and, in principle, ing certain desires and weakening others, what
cannot be) any rules for making generic forms of the should be inculcated is a feeling of benevolence, not
principle more substantial or for explicating how to a principle of beneficence. Lawrence Blum suggests
adjudicate conflicts of principles or conflicts in par- that the duty of beneficence, if it exists, must be re-
ticular cases. In their dispute with Clouser and garded as encompassing only a small area of the po-
GERT, Beauchamp and Childress suggest that their tential aid we may bring to others. Instead of being
“open” formulation may be the best one can do, that content to solve problems by seeking principles that
we may be able to say only that the principle of be- have universal applicability, a growing ethics of care
neficence expresses an obligation to help others fur- movement (inspired in part by the writings of Carol
ther their most important and legitimate interests by Gilligan) stresses the need to develop altruistic dis-
preventing and removing harm, and an obligation to positions and a sense of a broader self as well as the
weigh and balance possible goods against possible need to approach problems situationally, using the
harms of an action. What this, in part, means is that voice of RESPONSIBILITY and relationships.

132
beneficence

The sentiment here being expressed is that a mo- Frankena, William. “Beneficence/Benevolence.” In Benef-
rality that effectively curbs the egoistic or antisocial icence, Philanthropy, and the Public Good, edited by
Ellen Frankel Paul, et al., 1–20. Basil Blackwell for
tendencies of human beings cannot be achieved by Bowling Green State University, 1987.
means of moral principles alone or by placing the Gilligan, Carol. “Remapping the Moral Domain: New Im-
primary emphasis on such principles. Stated posi- ages of Self in Relationship.” In Reconstructing Indi-
tively: The first step is to open the windows of wis- vidualism, edited by T. C. Heller, et al., 237–52. Palo
dom and morality as wide as is reasonably possible Alto, CA: Stanford University Press, 1986.
by assisting human beings to feel more benevolent Hardin, Garrett. The Limits of Altruism: An Ecologist’s
and to extend the scope of their beneficence beyond View of Survival. Bloomington: Indiana University
Press, 1977.
their own compatriots. If benevolent/beneficent
Kant, Immanuel. The Metaphysical Principle of Virtue. In-
people, when they have the power and are reason-
dianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1964 [1797]. Sections 30
ably informed, produce more good than people mo- and 31.
tivated by other attitudes, then it may follow that we Kekes, John. “Beneficence: A Minor Virtue.” In Benefi-
should employ the best means to achieve this end, cence, Philanthropy, and the Public Good, edited by
including ideals and ideology, ethics and law, atti- Ellen Frankel, et al., 21–36. Basil Blackwell for Bowl-
tudes and emotions. ing Green State University, 1987.
Mill, John Stuart. Utilitarianism. With critical essays, ed-
See also: ALTRUISM; BENEVOLENCE; CARE; CAUSA- ited by Samuel Gorovitz. Indianapolis and New York:
TION AND RESPONSIBILITY; CHARITY; CHRISTIAN Bobbs-Merrill, 1971 [1861]. Cited pp. 18, 21.
ETHICS; COLLECTIVE RESPONSIBILITY; DUTY AND OB- ———. On Liberty. Edited by Currin V. Shields. India-
LIGATION; EMOTION; FINAL GOOD; GOLDEN RULE; IN- napolis and New York: Bobbs Merrill, 1956 [1859].
STITUTIONS; INTERNATIONAL JUSTICE: DISTRIBUTION; Cited pp. 14–15.
JEWISH ETHICS; JUSTICE, DISTRIBUTIVE; KANT; LOVE; Milo, Ronald D., ed. Egoism and Altruism. Belmont, CA:
Wadsworth, 1973.
JOHN STUART MILL; MORAL COMMUNITY, BOUND-
Monroe, Kristen Renwick. The Heart of Altruism. Prince-
ARIES OF; PERSONAL RELATIONSHIPS; PRUDENCE;
ton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1996. Explores the
RAWLS; SELF-ESTEEM; SIDGWICK; SUPEREROGATION; causes of altruism, the difference between altruists and
SYMPATHY; THEORY AND PRACTICE; THOMAS AQUI- other people, and provides the groundwork for a social
NAS; UTILITARIANISM; VIRTUE ETHICS; VIRTUES. theory receptive to altruism.
Mulligan, Tim. “Two Conceptions of Benevolence.” Phi-
losophy and Public Affairs 26, no. 1 (1997): 62–79.
Bibliography Murphy, Liam B. “The Demands of Beneficence.” Philos-
Arthur, John. “Rights and the Duty to Bring Aid.” In World ophy and Public Affairs 22. No. 4 (1993): 267–92.
Hunger and Moral Obligation, edited by William Aiken ———. “A Relatively Plausible Principle of Beneficence:
and Hugh La Follette, 37–48. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Reply to Mulligan.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 26,
Prentice Hall, 1977. no. 1 (1997): 80–86.
Beauchamp, Tom L. “The ‘Four-Principles’ Approach.” In Nagel, Thomas. The Possibility of Altruism. Oxford: Clar-
Principles of Health Care, edited by Gillon Raanan, 3– endon Press, 1970.
12. New York: John Wiley, 1994. Nelson, William. “Mutual Benevolence and Happiness: A
Beauchamp, Tom L. and James F. Childress. Principles of Reply to Estland.” Journal of Philosophy 91, no. 1
Bioethics. 3d ed. New York: Oxford University Press, (1994): 50–51.
1989. 195–255. Rawls, John. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge: Harvard
Blum, Lawrence A. Friendship, Altruism and Morality. University Press, (1971) 1972. Sections 30 and 51.
London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1980. Cited p. 339.
Brandt, Richard B. “Morally Required Charitable Giv- ———. Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia Uni-
ing?” In his Facts, Values and Morality, Chapter 8 versity Press, 1993. Cited p. 318.
(222–36). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Sidgwick, Henry. The Methods of Ethics. 2d ed. London:
1996. Macmillan, 1967 [1874]. 238–63. Cited pp. 262, 241,
Clouser, Danner K., and Bernard Gert. “Morality vs. Prin- 252.
ciplism.” In Principles of Health Care, edited by Gillon Singer, Peter. “Rich and Poor.” In Practical Ethics, 158–
Raanon, 251–66. New York: John Wiley, 1994. 81. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981
Eastland, David. “Mutual Benevolence and the Theory of [1979]. Cited pp. 169, 168.
Happiness.” Journal of Philosophy 87, no. 4 (1990): ———. “Famine, Affluence, and Morality.” In World Hun-
187–204. ger and Moral Obligation, edited by William Aiken and

133
beneficence

Hugh La Follette, 22–36. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Pren- conformity to one main requirement of ethics: to act
tice Hall, 1977. for the good of others. However, some VIRTUES, like
Thomas Aquinas. Summa theologica. London: Gates and justice, TEMPERANCE, COURAGE, and WISDOM, are
Washbourne, 1976. See vol. 9: Questions 23 and 24
(on charity); 30–31 (on mercy and beneficence).
important to good lives, others, such as cheerfulness
Warnock, G. J. The Object of Morality. London: Methuen,
and tact, are not. Although the distinction between
1971. Cited pp. 29–30. important and unimportant virtues cannot be
sharply drawn, as a rule of thumb, virtues are more
Marvin Kohl important if they are needed by good lives whatever
forms they may take, and less important if good lives
can be lived without them. One main question, then,
benefit-cost analysis is whether or not benevolence is among the most
See cost-benefit analysis. important virtues.
Benevolence is composed of emotive, cognitive,
and motivational elements. Among them, the emo-
tive one is dominant, for the fundamental source of
benevolence benevolence is the feeling that leads agents to care
In the ethical theories of Christianity, the moral about the good of others. This feeling ranges from
sense school, SCHOPENHAUER (1788–1860), and rejoicing if others flourish, through many varied and
UTILITARIANISM, benevolence has central impor- intermediate stages, to being distressed by the suf-
tance. By contrast, KANT (1724–1804) explicitly fering of others. It is just a fact about human beings
warns against relying on it as a source of ethical mo- that, in the absence of overriding considerations,
tivation, because, like other feelings, it is fickle. The they are inclined to care about the welfare of others.
classical eudaimonistic theories of PLATO (c. 430– They care whether lightning strikes a tree or a per-
347 B.C.E.), ARISTOTLE (384–322 B.C.E.), and the son, or whether a boulder has someone pinned un-
Epicureans and Stoics occupy an intermediate po- der it. Benevolent feelings need to be controlled and
sition between these two extremes. This dispute directed of course, and that is the task of the cog-
about the importance of benevolence is a symptom nitive component of benevolence. It directs the feel-
of a deeper one about the respective roles feelings ing toward appropriate objects, it aims to resolve
and reason have or should have in ethics. Kant de- conflicts between benevolence and justice, duty,
nies the importance of benevolence, partly because RIGHTS, and so forth; and it controls the actions be-
he believes that ethics requires that reason should nevolence prompts. This last introduces the moti-
dominate over feelings. Those who give benevolence vational component of benevolence, for it is a dis-
the pride of place in ethics do so on the ground that position to act so as to increase the welfare or
the ultimate source of ethics is feelings and the role decrease the suffering of others.
of reason is merely to prevent feelings from going Interpreted in this way, benevolence is said to be
astray. The claim that benevolence is the ethically a basic element of human nature. As HUME (1711–
most important feeling rests on the supposition that 1776) put it, benevolence is a natural virtue. There
it is the indispensable motive for acting for the good is no doubt a causal explanation of why it is basic,
of others. but understanding benevolence does not require de-
The Oxford English Dictionary defines “benevo- ciding whether the explanation is evolutionary, theo-
lence” as a “disposition to do good, kindness, gen- logical, or psychological. Benevolence then has the
erosity, charitable feeling (toward mankind).” To following characteristics: (1) it is primarily an emo-
this list may be added the cognate expressions of tive disposition to care about the good of others;
ALTRUISM, humaneness, compassion, and LOVE (un- (2) it is an ethically desirable character trait, hence
derstood as agape or caritas). In what follows, both a virtue; (3) its dominant emotive element is cogni-
the precise boundaries between benevolence and its tively guided and it motivates action; and (4) it is a
cognates and the distinction between it and BENEF- basic component of human nature found in all nor-
ICENCE, the tendency to act for the good of others, mal human beings. The conjunction of these char-
will be ignored. Benevolence then is a virtue, an eth- acteristics defines limited benevolence, but there is
ically desirable CHARACTER trait, because it fosters also general benevolence.

134
benevolence

The difference between limited and general be- totle’s, who treats benevolence (the various forms of
nevolence is the addition of universality and IMPAR- philia) as one expression of self-concern. Rational
TIALITY to the four characteristics just noted. Lim- agents care about the good of others because a good
ited benevolence is supposed to be universally life necessarily involves various relationships with
possessed by all normal human beings, but general other people, and these would be impossible without
benevolence goes beyond this in being directed uni- caring for the good of those to whom the agents are
versally toward all human beings. Champions of thus related. The Stoics reject this Aristotelian view
general benevolence do not hold the obviously false on the grounds that there are numerous benevolent
view that all normal human beings have a disposi- and ethically commendable actions that cannot plau-
tion to foster the welfare of all other human beings. sibly be assimilated to self-concern. They argue that
Their view is that, as a matter of fact, all human self-concern and benevolence are irreducibly differ-
beings have limited benevolence, and, as a matter of ent sources of human motivation, that self-concern
ethics, they ought also to transform limited into gen- develops first and benevolence only later, and that
eral benevolence. According to them, ethical prog- both are guided, but neither is created, by reason.
ress consists in expanding limited benevolence until The Stoics may be seen, therefore, as occupying in
it embraces all human beings. this respect a position in between Aristotle, on the
The universality of benevolence, however, does one hand, and utilitarians and Kantians, on the
not fully express the ethical vision of its defenders, other.
for universality is compatible with unequal benevo- Part of the significance of this dispute is its effect
lence, provided everybody receives some of it. The on how the role of reason in ethics is conceived. On
ethical vision also requires benevolence to be im- the Aristotelian view, part of the role of reason is to
partial. The underlying assumption is that from an remove obstacles from the way of natural and basic
ethical point of view all human beings are equal and dispositions. On the Stoic and utilitarian views, part
hence they deserve to be cared for equally. General of the role of reason is to develop natural and basic
benevolence, therefore, has the four characteristics dispositions in the direction of universality and im-
of limited benevolence and two additional ones: partiality. On the Kantian view, part of the role of
(5) it is universal, in being directed toward all hu- reason is to motivate agents to follow universal and
man beings; and (6) it is impartial, in being directed impartial principles, regardless of what feelings they
toward all human beings equally. happen to have. These views are not logically incom-
Benevolence being natural and basic does not, of patible, but they nevertheless point in different
course, exclude the presence of other natural and directions.
basic elements of human nature. One central ques- It exacerbates these disputes that the ethical im-
tion about benevolence is how it is related to these portance of both limited and general benevolence is
other elements. The question is central because one open to serious questions. Doubts about general be-
of these other elements is self-concern, benevolence nevolence may be formulated by noting that the nat-
may conflict with it, and it has far-reaching ethical ural sphere of limited benevolence is the agents’ im-
implications how particular ethical theories cope mediate context, including their FAMILY, friends,
with their conflict. Utilitarians and Kantians agree and perhaps some other people to whom they are
that benevolence and self-concern often conflict and personally connected. General benevolence requires
that the task of reason is to resolve their conflict. the expansion of this sphere to include everyone
But utilitarians think that the resolution depends on equally. But as agents go from those they know and
strengthening the feeling of benevolence by expand- understand toward the vast majority of human be-
ing it from its limited to general form and thereby ings whom they do not know and whose MOTIVES
subordinating the feeling of self-concern to it, and outlooks they could understand, if at all, only
whereas Kantians think that ethics requires reliance with great effort, so their benevolence peters out.
on reason, not on feelings of whatever kind. The idea that people have the same obligation to
It is an important difference between ancient and foster the welfare of total strangers as they do of
modern ethical theories that many of the former deny people to whom they are tied by love, fellowship, or
that benevolence may conflict with self-concern. Per- custom is widely unrealistic. It is also dangerous be-
haps the most influential view of this kind is Aris- cause it diverts their ethical concern from their own

135
benevolence

context in which their responsibilities are usually in the long run, for it protects ethics. But ethics itself
clear and difficult enough to discharge. The more may require blaming wrongdoers, expressing public
general benevolence becomes, the less room it leaves condemnation, or punishing wrongdoing regardless
for private relationships and obligations stemming of whether any good may come of it. Insofar as
from them in which universality and impartiality agents are motivated by limited benevolence, they
play no role. Limited benevolence cannot simply be will be disinclined to engage in nonbenevolent
extended to general benevolence because they are blame. The ethical importance of limited benevo-
incompatible with each other. lence must be demoted to allow for this type of non-
Defenders of general benevolence respond to benevolent motivation, or else a significant part of
these doubts by asking: suppose that it is known of ethics is excluded by exaggerating the importance of
remote strangers that they undeservedly suffer and limited benevolence.
resources to help them are available, is there not Defenders of limited benevolence may respond to
then an obligation to care about them? The critics’ these objections by arguing that the part of ethics
response is to acknowledge the obligation, but deny that is excluded by their emphasis ought to be ex-
that its existence constitutes a defense of the ethical cluded because ethics ought to be composed only of
claims of general benevolence, for the ground of this benevolent elements. But this claim is itself an eth-
obligation may be justice, duty, or rights. The dis- ical one, and it conflicts with ethical claims that at-
pute, therefore, leads back to limited benevolence tribute fundamental importance, not to benevo-
and to the question of whether it has the ethical im- lence, but to justice, duty, or rights. It appears
portance its defenders claim. If it does, then it may therefore that the defense of the ethical importance
indeed be the motivation underlying the claims of of limited benevolence presupposes the framework
justice, duty, or rights. of a particular ethical theory: utilitarianism. If utili-
Doubts about the importance of limited benevo- tarianism is correct, benevolence is fundamentally
lence may be put by granting its motivational force important; if not, not.
and ethical value, while pointing out that exagger-
See also: ALTRUISM; BENEFICENCE; BUTLER; CARE;
ating its importance is incompatible with ethical
CHARACTER; CHARITY; CHRISTIAN ETHICS; DUTY AND
considerations whose motivational force is as strong
OBLIGATION; EGOISM; EMOTION; EUDAIMONIA, -ISM;
and as valuable as those of limited benevolence. One
FAMILY; FRIENDSHIP; HUME; HUTCHESON; IMPARTI-
such consideration arises from ethical conflicts.
ALITY; LOVE; MORAL SENSE THEORISTS; MOTIVES;
Limited benevolence may conflict with justice, duty,
PERSONAL RELATIONSHIPS; RATIONALITY VS. REA-
or rights. It may prompt FORGIVENESS, while justice
SONABLENESS; SCHOPENHAUER; SYMPATHY; UNI-
may require PUNISHMENT. The frequency of such
VERSALIZABILITY; UTILITARIANISM; VIRTUES; VIRTUE
conflicts shows that as a matter of fact limited be-
ETHICS.
nevolence cannot be the ethically most important
motive because justice, duty, and rights often moti-
vate ethically commendable but contrary actions. If Bibliography
defenders of limited benevolence deny this, then
Annas, Julia. The Morality of Happiness. New York: Ox-
they need an argument to support their claim. Such
ford University Press, 1993. See chapters 11–12 for
an argument must appeal to some motives deeper ancient controversies about benevolence.
than either limited benevolence or whatever con- Aristotle. Nicomachean Ethics. Translated by W. D. Ross,
flicts with it. But, then, the most important ethical revised by J. O. Urmson. In The Complete Works of
motive would be that deeper one and the importance Aristotle, edited by Jonathan Barnes. Princeton: Prince-
attributed to limited benevolence would have to be ton University Press, 1984. See Books 8 and 9 for the
correspondingly reduced. discussion of philia.
A second consideration pointing to the same con- Brandt, Richard B. “The Psychology of Benevolence and
Its Implications for Philosophy.” Journal of Philosophy
clusion has to do with the various forms and
73 (1976): 429–53. A survey of the psychological
strengths of blame occasioned by the violation of literature.
ethical requirements. Blame is certainly not benev- Butler, Joseph. Fifteen Sermons. London: Bell, 1953
olent: it is not directed at the good of the person [1726]. Combined Christian and moral sense school
blamed. It may be said, however, that it is benevolent account.

136
Bentham, Jeremy

Hume, David. A Treatise of Human Nature. Edited by abolition of CAPITAL PUNISHMENT, relief for the poor,
L. A. Selby-Bigge. Oxford: Clarendon, 1960 [1737]. A representative DEMOCRACY, birth control, sexual lib-
classic defense of the fundamental moral importance
of benevolence.
eration, and the humane treatment of animals.
Kekes, John. “The Sentimentalism of Benevolence.” In A self-declared son of the Enlightenment (follow-
Against Liberalism. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, ing VOLTAIRE [1694–1778], d’Alembert [1717–
1997. Criticism of ethical theories based on 1783], BECCARIA [1738–1794], and Helvetius
benevolence. [1715–1771]), Bentham believed that established
Mill, John Stuart. Utilitarianism. Indianapolis: Hackett, patterns of legal and political thought, which fos-
1979 [1861]. A classic statement of the utilitarian
tered superstition, acquiescence, and CORRUPTION,
position.
were major obstacles to improvement of the lot of
Outka, Gene. Agape. New Haven: Yale University Press,
1972. A contemporary Christian account. humankind. He sought to destroy the established
Roberts, T. A. The Concept of Benevolence: Aspects of patterns and build in their place a structure of prac-
Eighteenth-Century Moral Philosophy. London: Mac- tical thought and discourse that was rational, deter-
millan, 1973. Account of the moral sense school as re- minate, and accessible to all. To this end he sought
flected in the writings of Hutcheson, Butler, and Hume. to purge language—especially the language of law,
Schopenhauer, Arthur. On the Basis of Morality. Trans- morality, and politics—of all illusory fictions. Fol-
lated by E. F. J. Payne. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill,
lowing the lead of LOCKE (1632–1704), he devel-
1965. Tr. of Die beiden Grundprobleme der Ethik
[1841]. Argument for benevolence as the foundation oped an elaborate theory of language that grounded
of ethics. all discourse in terms that refer only to “real,” i.e.,
Sidgwick, Henry. The Methods of Ethics. Indianapolis: publicly observable, entities. His theory remarkably
Hackett, 1981 [1874]. A classic utilitarian account. anticipates much of contemporary philosophy of
Smart, J. J. C. Essays Metaphysical and Moral. Oxford: language in the tradition of Bertrand RUSSELL
Blackwell, 1987. A contemporary utilitarian account.
(1872–1970).
See essays 22 and 23.
Bentham argued, for example, that talk of moral
Smith, Adam. The Theory of Moral Sentiments. Indianap-
olis: Liberty Classics, 1976 [1759]. A classic account right and wrong can be given substantial meaning
of the basis of virtues in benevolence. only if it is tied to the consequences of actions for
Social Philosophy and Policy 4, no. 2 (1987). Special is- human HAPPINESS, which itself must be understood
sue containing important contemporary articles on be- in terms of empirically observable PLEASURE and the
nevolence and beneficence. absence of pain. Similarly, he argued that our talk of
Taylor, Richard. Good and Evil. New York: Macmillan,
laws, RIGHTS, and obligations is illusory nonsense
1970. Contemporary view of ethics as based on
benevolence. unless it is rooted in reference to canonically for-
mulated, verbal expressions of will of recognized
John Kekes lawmakers and backed by credible sanctions. Unlike
the “fictions” of common law or NATURAL LAW the-
ories, “real laws” are rules the existence, content,
Bentham, Jeremy (1748–1832) and AUTHORITY of which depend strictly on these
Bentham articulated the first secular version of UTIL- publicly accessible empirical facts and not on indi-
ITARIANISM and laid the philosophical foundations vidual judgments of the reasonableness, justice, or
of modern legal positivism. He was born in London even utility of the rules. On this essentially Hobbes-
and lived most of his life there. After studying law ian basis, Bentham developed a very sophisticated
at Lincoln’s Inn, he turned to a career of radical criti- theory of law and adjudication.
cism and reform of English law, society, and politics. Inspired by Helvetius, Bentham sought to artic-
By the early nineteenth century, the influence of his ulate a utilitarian “science of legislation”—a set of
work had spread throughout Europe, India, and rational principles in terms of which laws and social
Latin America. Although caricatured as a doctrine reform proposals could be assessed. Two basic prop-
of cold-hearted calculation (Disraeli labeled it “bru- ositions ground this science: (a) the master norma-
tilitarianism”), his views proved a major source of tive principle, the “principle of utility”; and (b) a
progressive social reform in Victorian England. Ben- basic generalization about human nature, the “self-
tham was a powerful advocate of prison reform, the preference principle.”

137
Bentham, Jeremy

ness, he concludes, must take the shape of the great-


The Principle of Utility
est happiness principle, for this principle alone gives
The view that utility provides the only rational equal weight to the happiness of each person.
basic standard of moral evaluation can be found in Formulation. Bentham’s principle of utility is an
the systems of THEOLOGICAL ETHICS of Richard ordering of two complementary principles: (1) “the
CUMBERLAND (1631–1718) and Francis HUTCHE- greatest happiness principle” and (2) “the happiness
SON (1694–1746). It was also embraced in one form enumeration principle.” According to 1, the only
or another in the secular works of such Enlighten- proper ultimate end of action is the greatest happi-
ment figures as HUME (1711–1776), Beccaria, Hel- ness of each member of the community. This leading
vetius, and Priestly (1733–1804). While Hutcheson principle sets the tone and direction of utilitarian
introduced the phrase “greatest happiness of the deliberation. Principle 2 comes into play when
greatest number” (Inquiry Concerning Moral Good agents are forced by conflicts among the INTERESTS
and Evil, 1726), Bentham seems to have encoun- they must consider to choose the good of some at
tered it first in Beccaria’s Dei delitti e della pene the expense of others. In those cases, 2 requires the
(1764). Bentham, however, articulated and clarified agent to seek the greatest happiness of the greatest
the principle in its secular version and applied it number. Bentham makes clear that on his principle
more extensively and systematically than any of his of utility human beings are not merely “receptacles”
predecessors or contemporaries. into which pleasure or pain are poured. The focus
Philosophical Defense. Bentham typically treated of his utilitarian concern is not on happiness as some
the principle of utility simply as an axiom of his en- abstract good but rather on the concrete happiness
terprise in need of no defense. But, as Harrison of each individual person.
noted, Bentham suggested a line of defense that re- This emphasis is underscored by Bentham’s last
veals much about his understanding of it. He ob- known gloss on the principle of utility. We must first
served, first, that moral judgments demand justifi- seek the greatest happiness of all members “without
cation. Justification is possible, he argued, only if the exception in so far as possible,” he insists, but we
language of morality is a public language, accessible must seek “the greatest happiness of the greatest
to all members of the community—that is, only if number of them on every occasion on which the na-
the reasons offered in justification appeal to publicly ture of the case renders the provision of an equal
accessible considerations rather than to merely sub- quantity of happiness for every one of them impos-
jective opinions. Pleasures and pains are publicly ob- sible.” This strongly suggests that the basic utilitar-
servable facts, accessible to everyone. So the lan- ian aim is the greatest equal happiness in the com-
guage of pleasures and pains alone provides the munity, and, where trade-offs of the happiness of
necessary public basis for moral judgments. This some for the happiness of others are unavoidable,
necessary public basis, he continues, also forces us that alternative which most closely approximates
to recognize that, from the MORAL POINT OF VIEW, greatest equal happiness must be chosen.
everyone’s happiness is equally significant. My hap- It is not clear how seriously to take this late, egal-
piness, of course, is of great importance to me, but itarian formulation of the principle of utility. It may
it is not likely to carry such weight with Smith, who represent Bentham’s final attempt to solve an objec-
may accord that importance only to his happiness. tion to the “greatest happiness of the greatest num-
These assessments, appropriate enough from our pe- ber” principle which troubled him greatly. Accord-
culiar, subjective points of view, cannot hope to win ing to this objection, the principle requires only that
general public approval. Thus if moral judgments the agent choose that alternative which would get
are to meet the test of publicity, they cannot be made the largest number of votes were the choice put to
from any subjective point of view but only from a all those affected by the action, allowing the agent
suitably public or impartial point of view. From this to ignore the degree of loss suffered by the minority.
impartial point of view, the happiness of any one Bentham’s last formulation, by counseling the agent
person is no more or less important than that of any to approximate equal distribution of happiness,
other (John Stuart Mill expressed this in the princi- forces the agent to accord moral significance to the
ple “each is to count for one and no one for more sacrifices of the minority as well as the gains of the
than one”). Our moral concern for human happi- majority. Some critics claim that Bentham’s princi-

138
Bentham, Jeremy

ple of utility requires one to choose that action Bentham was a direct- or act-utilitarian or an
which produces the greatest amount of happiness, indirect- or rule-utilitarian). The evidence is mixed.
no matter how it is distributed, but this view fails to There is no doubt that Bentham concentrates
recognize the sensitivity and complexity of the prin- largely on utilitarian grounds for legislation. How-
ciple. Concern for the distribution of happiness ever, in his account of utilitarian judicial reason-
played an important role in Bentham’s formulation ing, where one would expect a clear statement of
and defense of his principle. indirect-utilitarianism, Bentham seems to have em-
Equality. Distribution of the means of happiness braced a direct-utilitarian reading.
also played an important though more ambiguous
role in Bentham’s political theory. He clearly artic-
Hedonism and Egoism
ulated the now standard utilitarian argument for
economic arrangements that approximate equality Bentham’s theory of human nature draws directly
of income and wealth. Human psychology is such on the Empiricist tradition from HOBBES (1588–
that the ability of wealth to produce happiness de- 1679) to Hume and Hartley (1705–1757). It also
creases as the amount of wealth one already pos- inherited some of the confusion typical of this tra-
sesses increases (the marginal utility of wealth di- dition. Bentham clearly embraced psychological he-
minishes), he observed. For example, other things donism, the view that every human action is caused
being equal, more happiness can be produced by dis- by the agent’s desire for some pleasure or aversion
tributing a marginal $100 to a person who has only to some pain. This frequently led him to express a
$1,000 than to a person who has $100,000. Thus position very close to psychological egoism, the view
the distribution of wealth that most closely approx- that human beings act only in pursuit of their own
imates EQUALITY is likely to produce the greatest private interest. In fact, occasionally he claims that
happiness for the greatest number, if other things are every human agent acts only to maximize his or her
equal. However, as he was quick to point out, con- net happiness. When he is careful, however, Ben-
ditions are seldom equal. In order to protect general tham admits that human beings, even the most sav-
“security” and “subsistence” and promote “abun- age, can be moved by SYMPATHY with the good or
dance” (economic productivity), INEQUALITY of ill of others (even at the expense of their private in-
wealth is often necessary. Since equality is subordi- terests). But his HEDONISM leads him to insist even
nate to these other goals, in Bentham’s view, in- here that they are moved by their own pleasure,
equality of wealth can often be justified on utilitarian since sympathy is just the pleasure one takes in the
grounds. In contrast, inequality of political power, good others enjoy, as malice is the pleasure one takes
he argued, is seldom justified. Equality of POWER in the evil others suffer. While this may be so, it does
does not threaten subsistence or abundance and is not follow that the pleasure human beings derive
absolutely necessary for security—especially secu- from the well-being of others is the operative motive
rity against depredation of the many by the ruling of their actions.
few. On this basis, Bentham mounted a powerful ar- It is unlikely that Bentham firmly held the strong
gument for representative democracy and nearly psychological egoist view that it is not possible for
universal franchise. human beings to act contrary to their present judg-
Scope. Although it has been the subject of recent ment of their own best interest. Occasionally, he
debate, most commentators now agree that Ben- states clearly that what he means by the claims that
tham’s principle of utility instructs each agent to “of action the sole efficient cause is interest” is just
maximize the happiness not only of all humankind that action is caused by the motive or desire which
but of all sentient creation. The proper question to is at the moment “most forcibly influencing,” regard-
ask of any potential objects of moral concern, says less of whether it is self-regarding or other-regarding.
Bentham, is not “Can they reason?” or “Can they But he often trades on the ambiguity of his use of
talk?” but “Can they suffer?” On another matter, “interest” in ways that create confusion about what
commentators still disagree about whether Ben- his view really is.
tham intended his principle to be consulted in every This confusion aside, however, Bentham did
case or only when agents wish to determine what clearly and consistently advocate a strategic version
laws and rules to follow (i.e., they dispute whether of the egoist doctrine. He claimed that human beings

139
Bentham, Jeremy

are more likely in any particular case to be moved MILL [1806–1873] assumed, a claim about the
by considerations of their own private interest than place of these activities in a general view of human
by any other motive, especially when they exercise good.) Designed as a framework to guide the legis-
power over others. Thus the only safe assumption lator who seeks rationally and humanely to restruc-
for the legislator or political constitution writer to ture social behavior and INSTITUTIONS, the theory
make is that people will act only to advance their has a decidedly technocratic character. However,
private (“sinister”) interests. The aim of law and so- when Bentham belatedly turned his attention to per-
cial morality more generally, according to Bentham’s sonal morality in his Deontology, the technocratic
“duty-and-interest-junction principle,” is to provide character remained. Bentham coined the word DE-
individuals with adequate MOTIVES, through the ONTOLOGY, but his use of it is directly opposite cur-
threat of sanctions, to comply with the dictates of rent usage inspired by Kant. The ultimate aim of
the utility principle, thereby securing artificially a “deontology,” as of legislation, is to motivate behav-
convergence of individual self-interest and utilitar- ior that maximizes community happiness. But while
ian duty. the law’s basic technique is to alter the shape of in-
The clearest application of this principle is Ben- dividual interests with threats of punishment, the
tham’s utilitarian deterrence theory of PUNISHMENT. technique of deontology is to mobilize reasons of
Punishment is justified not by appeal to desert or private (though perhaps hidden or long-range) in-
retribution but by the fact that public knowledge of terest already available to the agent. While recent
the punishment of some violators is likely to deter utilitarian theories have abandoned Bentham’s he-
others from socially harmful behavior, because the donism and ambivalent egoism, they still cling in
course of that behavior will then appear too costly some fashion to this dubious Benthamite legacy.
to the agent. Behavior in the interest of the com- See also: ANIMALS, TREATMENT OF; CAPITAL PUNISH-
munity as a whole is thereby made consistent with MENT; CORRECTIONAL ETHICS; DEMOCRACY; EGOISM;
the self-interest of each individual member. EQUALITY; GOOD, THEORIES OF THE; HEDONISM;
In his constitutional theory Bentham seems to HUME; IMPARTIALITY; INDIVIDUALISM; JUSTICE, DIS-
have given the artificial identification of interests a TRIBUTIVE; LEGAL PHILOSOPHY; MILL, JAMES; MILL,
slightly different form. A recent commentator has JOHN STUART; PAIN AND SUFFERING; PLEASURE; PUN-
argued that proper adjudication under law, in Ben- ISHMENT; RATIONALITY VS. REASONABLENESS; SYM-
tham’s theory, depends heavily on the enlightened PATHY; UTILITARIANISM.
utilitarian judgment of judges. The aim of Ben-
tham’s complex constitutional arrangements is not
Bibliography
to supply each judge with sufficiently strong self-
interested reasons for doing what utility requires,
Selected Works by Bentham
but rather to filter out or neutralize all sources of
Bentham’s Theory of Fictions. Edited by C. K. Ogden. Pat-
possible conflicts of interest, thereby freeing up the
erson, NJ: Littlefield, Adams, 1959. Bentham’s writ-
“moral aptitude” of the judge for the task of disin- ings on language, logic, ontology, and epistemology.
terested utilitarian deliberation. Collected Works of Jeremy Bentham. Edited by J. H.
Burns, J. R. Dinwiddy, and F. Rosen. London: Athlone
Press; Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1968–. In
Private Deontology progress; twenty-two volumes published to date. When
Unlike recent utilitarian theories, the focus of completed, this will be the definitive edition of Ben-
tham’s writings. Works of philosophical interest al-
Bentham’s utilitarianism was primarily social and in- ready published in this series are A Comment on the
stitutional. Personal or private morality was never Commentaries [1775] and A Fragment on Government
more than marginal to his interests. (Harrison has [1776], edited by Burns and H. L. A. Hart, London,
shown that Bentham’s claim that, given equal quan- 1977; An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and
tities of pleasure, push-pin—the children’s game Legislation [1789], edited by Burns and Hart, London,
1970, 2nd edition with new introduction by Hart, New
“pin the tail on the donkey”—is as good as poetry,
York: Methuen, 1982; Constitutional Code [1830],
was addressed to the question of what importance volume 1, edited by Rosen and Burns, Oxford, 1983;
the state should attach to various activities when de- Deontology [1834] together with A Table of the Springs
ciding which of them to support. It was not, as J. S. of Action and The Article on Utilitarianism, edited by

140
bioethics

A. Goldworth, Oxford, 1983; First Principles Prepa- bioethics


ratory to Constitutional Code, edited by P. Schofield,
Oxford, 1989; ‘Legislator of the World’: Writings on Bioethics, a complex domain of inquiry, debate, and
Codification, Law, and Education, edited by P. Scho- decision making, has emerged over the past several
field and Jonathan Harris, Oxford, 1998; Of Laws in decades, with most commentators dating its origins
General [1782], edited by Hart, London, 1970.
to the 1960s. In that decade, vital decisions about
Parliamentary Candidate’s Proposed Declaration of Prin-
ciples. London, 1831.
the allocation of scarce, newly developed dialysis
machines received national attention in the public
Works of Jeremy Bentham. Edited by J. Bowring. 11 vols.
New York: Russell and Russell, 1962. First published press. The medical community was reassessing the
in Edinburgh, 1838–43. An inferior edition, but indis- ethical integrity of American research with human
pensable until the Collected Works is completed. subjects. New treatment capacities prompted recon-
sideration of the traditional relationship between
doctors and patients and raised new concerns about
Works about Bentham
the difficulty of distinguishing between saving life
The Bentham Committee. The Bentham Newsletter. Lon- and prolonging death. Bioethics is the critical ex-
don: The Committee, 1978–88. Published scholarly es- amination—both for theoretical and for practical
says on all aspects of Bentham’s thought and times.
purposes—of the moral dimensions of decisions
Included a running bibliography of recent Bentham
scholarship. made about such matters.
Dinwiddy, John. Bentham. Oxford: Oxford University Bioethics now includes, but only as a part, a dis-
Press, 1989. Very useful, short introduction to Ben- tinct and idiosyncratic academic discipline—com-
tham’s moral and political theories. plete with a largely agreed-upon but evolving subject
Halevy, Elie. The Growth of Philosophic Radicalism. matter; an identifiable and increasingly organized
Translated by M. Morris. London: Faber and Faber, group of practitioners; a set of conditions of profes-
1972 [1928]. Extensive bibliography of classical stud- sional admissibility that is still contested; and an un-
ies of Bentham and his era.
usually diverse academic and public following. Spe-
Harrison, Ross. Bentham. London: Routledge and Kegan
Paul, 1984. The best available general assessment of
cialized bioethics research centers have proliferated
Bentham’s philosophical doctrines. Useful bibliography. from the early 1970s, when the newly founded In-
Hart, H. L. A. Essays on Bentham: Jurisprudence and Po- stitute for Society, Ethics, and the Life Sciences (The
litical Theory. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1982. Critical Hastings Center) and the Kennedy Center for Bio-
discussions of Bentham’s contributions to jurispru- ethics were the only such sites, to the late 1990s in
dence and political theory. which dozens of such sites flourish around the
Kelly, Paul J. Utilitarianism and Distributive Justice: Jer- United States and abroad. The literature of bioeth-
emy Bentham and the Civil Law. Oxford: Clarendon ics, at first an occasional scattering of articles and
Press, 1990.
editorials, now includes an extensive array of jour-
Long, Douglas G. Bentham on Liberty. Toronto: Univer-
nals and books of various levels of distinction, an
sity of Toronto Press, 1977.
encyclopedia of bioethics in its second edition, and
Lyons, David. In the Interest of the Governed. Oxford:
Clarendon Press, 1973. even a recently published, comprehensive, and finely
Parekh, Bhikhu. Jeremy Bentham: Ten Critical Essays. crafted historical analysis.
London: Frank Cass, 1974. Throughout its history medicine has reflected on
Postema, Gerald J. Bentham and the Common Law Tra- ethical aspects of clinical responses to illness and
dition. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986. injury, and debate about issues like ABORTION and
———, ed. Jeremy Bentham: Moral, Political, and Legal EUTHANASIA have been perennial. But modern bio-
Philosophy. 2 vols. Aldershot: Ashgate, 2001. ethics took shape when writers from various tradi-
Rosen, Fred. Jeremy Bentham and Representative De- tional disciplines and from the public press devoted
mocracy. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983. increasing attention to the proliferating moral chal-
Steintrager, James. Bentham. Ithaca, NY: Cornell Univer- lenges associated with technologically sophisticated
sity Press, 1977.
contemporary medical care and biological and medi-
Utilitas. 1989–. Interdisciplinary studies of classical and cal research. That attention, on the part of physi-
contemporary utilitarian thought.
cians, scientists, lawyers, journalists, philosophers,
Gerald J. Postema theologians, sociologists, economists, and others, re-

141
bioethics

flected growing professional and public recognition alone among the developed nations in having a large
that in modern health care new factors require de- uninsured population).
cisions—by individuals, institutions, and society— Bioethics remains thoroughly interdisciplinary, al-
that are not simply medical or legal in nature, but though those who pursue it at the highest levels of
depend fundamentally on ethical reasoning and eth- quality tend to do so from the perspective of a solid
ical choice. These factors include the rapidly ex- grounding in one of the traditional disciplines—typ-
panding base of scientific knowledge; the conse- ically law, literature, philosophy, religious studies,
quently increased effectiveness of medical and and sociology of medicine—or in the professional
scientific procedures; resulting challenges to our ethos of clinical practice. Indeed, bioethics is atypi-
understanding of basic notions of life, death, sick- cal as an academic domain in that many of its prac-
ness, and health; the greater visibility through the titioners try (often with little success) to distance
MASS MEDIA of scientific knowledge and the possi- themselves from the term ‘bioethicist’, preferring to
bilities both of its practical applications and its retain professional identification with the discipline
abuse; and changing and conflicted societal expec- which provides their intellectual grounding. Only re-
tations regarding health care. cently have scholars and teachers emerged who
Activity with bioethical content takes many identify themselves primarily as bioethicists, and the
forms. Academic bioethicists teach in various set- notion of bioethics as an independent discipline re-
tings, contribute to the professional literature, and mains controversial.
address practical applications of their work in vari- Many issues addressed by bioethics are theoreti-
ous kinds of service activities. Members of institu- cal, speculative, and abstract; many others are di-
tional review boards assess the adequacy of protec- rectly connected with matters of immediate practical
tion of human and animal research subjects, and concern. Bioethics is thus a major component of
what is called APPLIED ETHICS, which brings to bear
institutional ethics committees in hospitals, nursing
on practical ethical problems the sort of ethical anal-
homes, and health plans consult on specific cases,
ysis that had its origins in theoretical endeavors, es-
address matters of institutional policy, and provide
pecially in philosophical ethics and in the ethical
educational programs. Thousands of such people, in
analyses of religious traditions. Initially, the most in-
addition to academic bioethicists, participate ac-
fluential perspectives were from the analytic West-
tively in bioethical deliberations as part of their pro-
ern philosophical tradition emphasizing personal
fessional responsibilities. Their need for related con-
autonomy, respect for individuals, justice, and BE-
tinuing education has helped expand demand for
NEFICENCE, and from such Western religious tradi-
workshops, meetings, and conferences in bioeth-
tions as CASUISTRY and Talmudic scholarship. Fur-
ics—of which there were perhaps a few each year
ther influences have come from constitutional law
two decades ago, and which occur now almost and narrative theory and, more recently, feminist
weekly. and non-Western thought.
Initially, the term ‘bioethics’ to many was synon- Because of their practical dimensions, and be-
ymous with ‘medical ethics’, despite the existence of cause of widespread public interest in health-related
nonmedical ethical issues in the biological sciences. matters, bioethical questions have been the concern
Later, ‘biomedical ethics’ addressed a broader range of presidential and congressional commissions; con-
of issues in ethics and the life sciences. Now, finer gressional hearings; state legislatures, commissions,
distinctions are commonly made, such as among and task forces; and other public forums at national
clinical ethics (e.g., MEDICAL ETHICS and NURSING and, more recently, international levels. Bioethics is
ETHICS), research ethics (e.g., the proper use of hu- now widely and regularly covered by the print and
man and animal subjects, the propriety of genetic electronic media and is even a recurrent theme in
screening for low-penetrance genetic markers for mass-market entertainment. Relations between the
untreatable diseases, or the release of genetically al- media and professionals in bioethics have them-
tered agents into the environment), and health pol- selves become the focus of analysis and dispute as
icy ethics (e.g., protection of the PRIVACY of genetic bioethicists reflect and debate about their role in
information, or health system reform to address the public education, judicial proceedings, and policy
lack of universal coverage in the United States— formation.

142
bioethics

Some additional questions on the agenda of bio- health law specialists, and hospital house officers. It
ethics concern treatment of chronically ill patients is also pursued by some scholars who profess little
and of very frail elderly patients; regulation of health interest in practical decision making, but who see
care; defining the scope of medical prerogative— the biological and health care contexts as concep-
e.g., clarifying the extent to which a patient’s life- tually rich fields for theoretical philosophical, theo-
style choices are a physician’s proper concern; TRUST logical, or other scrutiny. Some philosophers have
and respect in the relationship between provider and even argued that the focus on issues in medicine has
patient; decision making on behalf of decisionally so enriched the study of ethics as to have saved it
incompetent patients; controlling the use of genetic from a loss of all human relevance, by forcing a ster-
information and manipulation; and the justifiability ile tradition of moral inquiry to confront real moral
and regulation of technologically assisted human re- issues as they are experienced in people’s lives.
production. Addressing such questions unavoidably The maturation of bioethics has been reflected in
raises fundamentally philosophical issues—about the establishment and solidification of professional
autonomy, dependency, equity, RESPONSIBILITY, in- organizations devoted to its pursuit. Most recently
tergenerational justice, the social nature of the hu- (1998), in the United States, the American Society
man condition, and more. for Bioethics and Humanities emerged from the con-
In pursuit of these matters, bioethics has brought solidation of the American Association for Bioeth-
together scholars and practitioners who otherwise ics, the Society for Health and Human Values, and
would have had little exposure to one another’s dis- the Society for Bioethics Consultation, thereby cre-
ciplines. Their interactions, at times baffling or con- ating a unifying forum for discussion within the pro-
tentious, have typically been mutually enriching. fession. The American Society for Law and Medicine
Reactions to work in bioethics—not merely to in- continues to emphasize legal aspects of bioethics.
dividual works but to the enterprise as a whole— At the global level, the International Association
have ranged from admiration to disdain, and diverse of Bioethics both constitutes a network of commu-
expectations, disappointments, and criticisms have nication across national boundaries and facilitates
surrounded it even as it has grown in scope, accep- an understanding of the global nature of many of the
tance, and influence. substantive problems in health care ethics. For ex-
Among the most prominent criticisms of bioeth- ample: increased international trade spreads infec-
ics are that: it is not serious, well-grounded schol- tious diseases to new areas; the aggressive marketing
arship; it has no well-defined and clear methodology; of American tobacco products in Asia, in ways pro-
it lacks any solid conceptual foundation but is based hibited at home, will increase the burden of disease
instead on the shifting sands of moral sentiment; it in developing countries; and clinical trials of new
is too abstractly removed from the realities of clini- pharmaceutical products often take place in multiple
cal practice to merit being taken seriously; it is un- countries with differing standards of ethical scrutiny
teachable because morality depends on CHARACTER for clinical research. And health-related information
rather than on intellect; it pursues unanswerable flows at the speed of light around the world. Such
questions; its utility has not been demonstrated; it issues prompt bioethicists to consider the moral sig-
absorbs valuable time, distracting health care pro- nificance of national boundaries, to investigate the
viders, policy makers, and researchers from dealing possibility of international standards, and to worry
directly with the problems they face; and it is itself about the perils of moral imperialism.
ethically problematic, because it either implicitly en- Specific bioethical issues such as the medical
dorses traditional values that ought to be challenged plight of refugees or political prisoners have long
or undermines traditional values that ought to be been acknowledged by various international profes-
advocated and reinforced. Many such criticisms sional associations. A sharply increased recognition
have contributed to the development of the field, as of bioethics at the global level, however, is reflected
bioethicists have refuted some and responded con- in its explicit incorporation into the agendas of or-
structively to others. ganizations such as the European Community and
Bioethics is now well established in the curricu- the World Health Organization. The WHO-related
lum of most colleges and universities and plays a role Council for International Organizations of Medical
in the training of health care students of many kinds, Sciences, for example, initiated an ongoing dialogue

143
bioethics

on Health Policy, Ethics, and Human Values at an ings, and joins debates in so many contexts, it has
international meeting in Athens in 1984, and has also become an unusually self-critical and reflective
since catalyzed or conducted much additional in- discipline. Its nature, purposes, and legitimacy have
quiry into bioethical issues that have substantial in- become a recurrent theme for inquiry.
ternational dimensions. Bioethics has catalyzed discourse in many settings
Further, as more is understood about the range of about the foundations of social policy and the ap-
factors influencing health status in populations— propriate modes of address—academic, political,
not just sanitation and adequate nutrition, but fac- professional, and public—to contested issues about
tors such as literacy, economic stability, opportuni- which people feel deeply and differently. It has for
ties for women, other aspects of respect for human that reason come to be viewed as a provocative and
rights, and a sense of capacity to influence one’s own instructive model for civil deliberation in a context
destiny—the concern with ethical issues related to of diversity of values and perspectives.
health care shades into concern with a much broader As they consider the full spectrum of issues re-
range of ethical aspects of human affairs. Just as clar- lated to the achievement and maintenance of health
ity about the scope of medical matters is elusive, the and the associated problems of resource allocation,
scope of bioethics is also hard to discern sharply, and the forums of PUBLIC POLICY have called increasingly
itself becomes a subject for bioethical inquiry. on professionals in bioethics to assist in their delib-
Although the agenda of bioethics has expanded erations. Health care has changed fundamentally in
greatly as it has encompassed questions about health recent years: we recognize now the unavoidable
status and about the ethics of organizational deci- need to develop wisdom about the imposition of lim-
sions, it also has intensified its focus on more sharply itations; we see the organizational structures of
defined domains, such as ethical issues as they per- health care transforming in ways we do not like yet
tain to specific populations—for instance, those
cannot seem to control; we know that new genetic
with disabilities, or who have AIDS and are preg-
knowledge and capacities will have powerful con-
nant, or who seek genetic testing for untreatable dis-
sequences we cannot fully anticipate. Each of these
eases. Feminist perspectives, too, have enriched bio-
phenomena, and others, generates renewed energy
ethics, both by calling overdue attention to issues
for bioethical deliberations.
that affect women differentially and by deepening
Thus, the transformation of information handling
the profession’s understanding of interpersonal and
capacities has had a profound impact on bioethics,
social issues as they affect all people.
as on other intellectual domains. Electronic data-
Each of the ways in which bioethics has changed
bases raise substantive questions about the tension
has placed new demands on its practitioners. It
between concerns for privacy and opportunities for
quickly became valuable—some would say essen-
tial—for bioethicists concerned with medical ethics valuable research or improved patient care. Public
to have clinical exposure, because interacting with access to thousands of Web sites about health-
real patients, providers, and family members in related matters, from the authoritative through
medical settings facilitates understanding more the iconoclastic to the fraudulent, confront health
deeply the clinical realities as they are experienced care providers with the challenge of patients arriv-
by those involved. Such understanding is necessary ing with new kinds of expertise, superstition, or
for those who seek to be credible and helpful in ad- demand.
dressing actual clinical cases. Similarly, it has be- The professional practice of bioethics has also
come essential for bioethicists, depending on the fo- been changed by the Internet. A recently established
cus of their attention, to learn about such matters as electronic bioethics discussion group has created an
health economics, molecular genetics, radiation ex- international conversation among hundreds of pro-
periments, health status in refugee camps, and hu- fessionals in bioethics that facilitates research and
man rights policies and politics, in order to pursue helps shape the agenda of inquiry. Participants
their inquiries with rigor and persuasiveness. sometimes provide information that others might
Perhaps because bioethics reflects such diversity value, such as a notice of impending legislation, or
of focus and of disciplinary grounding, addresses is- raise specific questions about where to find a refer-
sues about which ordinary people have strong feel- ence or what the status is of a current case, law, or

144
bioethics

bill. Typically, someone answers such questions al- might be effective in illuminating problems related
most immediately. to the need to limit health care; are there ethical risks
Mostly, however, the content of the postings is in requiring health care students to practice certain
substantive exchange. A review of the topics ad- procedures on one another—such as pelvic exami-
dressed over the few weeks prior to this writing pro- nations done by female nursing students on one an-
vides a useful overview of issues at the center of other, with neither uncoerced consent nor assur-
contemporary bioethical discussion. Some of the ances of confidentiality regarding the findings?
content has been about foundational or general New directions in bioethics include an expanding
questions: what can be said to those who question body of empirical inquiry into the ways in which val-
whether there is a rational basis for ethical decisions; ues are honored or violated in health care contexts
do health care providers have any special responsi- and into the consequences of public policy decisions
bility to work in behalf of social justice in health that have been shaped by bioethical arguments. Al-
care, and if so how might that be integrated with though bioethics will sustain controversy as it con-
their clinical responsibilities; how can a balance be tinues to evolve, its rapid rise to intellectual promi-
found between societal and individual benefits in nence and practical influence, and the certainty that
making health care decisions; what counts as medi- continued developments in the medical and biologi-
cal in an era of concern with preventive and public cal sciences will raise or accentuate ethical issues,
health measures? ensure that it will remain active and vital.
Other topics are more explicitly clinical: how phy- See also: ABORTION; AGENCY AND DISABILITY; ANI-
sicians should reply to inquiring patients who ask
MALS, TREATMENT OF; APPLIED ETHICS; AUTONOMY
about the physician’s health; how to manage post- OF MORAL AGENTS; BIOLOGICAL THEORY; CHARAC-
death ventilation while awaiting the arrival of sur-
TER; COMPUTERS; CONSENT; ENVIRONMENTAL
vivors of the deceased; when if ever it is appropriate ETHICS; EUTHANASIA; FEMINIST ETHICS; FUTURE GEN-
to treat a patient for the benefit of someone else;
ERATIONS; GENETIC ENGINEERING; HARM AND OF-
how nurses ought to respond, in the process of treat-
FENSE; ISLAMIC MEDICAL ETHICS; KILLING/LETTING
ment already under way, when challenged by a le- DIE; LIBRARY AND INFORMATION PROFESSIONS; LIFE
gitimate surrogate. And in addition to perennial AND DEATH; LIFE, RIGHT TO; MEDICAL ETHICS, HIS-
matters in clinical ethics, such as how much to tell
TORICAL; NARRATIVE ETHICS; NUCLEAR ETHICS;
a fragile patient who appears not to want to know
NURSING ETHICS; PAIN AND SUFFERING; PRINCIPLISM;
the truth about his condition, there is increasing
PRIVACY; PUBLIC HEALTH POLICY; PUBLIC POLICY; RE-
concern with the changing organizational contexts
PRODUCTIVE TECHNOLOGIES; TECHNOLOGY; THEORY
within which health care is provided: is health care AND PRACTICE; TRUST.
ethics facilitated or impeded by the need for corpo-
rate compliance with the external requirements of
bodies such as accrediting agencies; what ethical Bibliography
problems are faced by health care administrators The literature of bioethics has, in thirty years, grown from
specifically in their capacity as administrators? almost nothing to tens of thousands of items. These few
Many topics explicitly concern matters of law: illustrative resources can provide an efficient route into
that literature.
what requirements of legal discovery apply to hos-
Council for International Organizations of Medical Sci-
pital ethics committee consultations; what protec-
ences. Geneva: World Health Organization. Various re-
tions against financial responsibility do health care ports and proceedings published over more than
surrogates have; how have different states developed twenty years addressing issues of values in medicine,
priority lists for the selection of surrogate decision medical research, and health policy from international
makers; what federal measures might be needed to perspectives.
protect genetic privacy adequately, especially given Hastings Center Report. The leading journal in bioethics
for nearly three decades; see especially the section “In
the prospect of a national database in which each
the Literature” which provides briefly annotated no-
person has a health identifier number? Pedagogical tices of important publications in the field from many
matters, too, are frequent: can an enlightened ethical sources.
inquiry be based on a code of ethics such as that of Jonsen, Albert R. The Birth of Bioethics. New York: Ox-
the American Medical Association; what readings ford University Press, 1998. The only comprehensive

145
bioethics

overview of the development of bioethics over the past


thirty years. Excellent bibliographical references. Evolutionary Ethics
Moreno, Jonathan D. Deciding Together: Bioethics and The most popular approach to evolutionary ethics
Moral Consensus. New York: Oxford University Press,
1995. Explores ethical decisions by groups of people, is to claim that natural selection, the mechanism
such as hospital committees, whose individual values largely responsible for evolution, results in ethically
or judgments may diverge. valuable products. Since this is so, people should not
New York State Task Force on Life and the Law. Ten re- interfere with natural selection. We might even pro-
ports from an influential state commission published mote it. This form of evolutionary ethics results in
since 1986, including Assisted Reproductive Technol-
“Social Darwinism,” the belief that the “struggle for
ogies: Analysis and Recommendations for Public Pol-
icy (1988). existence” is good. Since it is good, government in-
President’s Commission for the Study of Ethical Problems terference in the struggle is wrong. There should be
in Medicine and Biomedical and Behavioral Research. no welfare state. We might even establish eugenics
11 vols. Washington, D.C.: Government Printing Of- programs to promote natural selection.
fice, 1981–83. An influential collection of reports from There are major difficulties with Social Darwin-
a federal commission.
ism. The most obvious is its brutality, a particularly
Rachels, James. “When Philosophers Shoot from the Hip:
objectionable attribute for an ethical theory. On
A Report from America.” Bioethics 5 (1991): 67–71.
A comment on the role of bioethicists in addressing the these grounds, T. H. Huxley (1825–1895) suggests
public. we ought to combat natural selection rather than
Reich, Warren T., ed. Encyclopedia of Bioethics. Rev. ed. promote it. Another difficulty is that Social Darwin-
5 vols. New York: Macmillan, 1995. Revised edition of ists understand Charles DARWIN’s (1809–1882)
a standard four-volume reference first published in phrase “struggle for existence” literally, whereas
1978.
Darwin explicitly says he is using “struggle” meta-
Sherwin, Susan. No Longer Patient: Feminist Ethics and
Health Care. Philadelphia: Temple University Press,
phorically.
1992. An early and influential presentation of feminist Moreover, natural selection does not appear to
perspectives on medical ethics. culminate in ethically valuable products. Indeed, we
Silvers, Anita, David Wasserman, and Mary Briody Ma- do not know where it culminates. It may operate on
howald. Disability, Difference, Discrimination: Per- Earth for another 3 billion years, and we do not
spectives on Justice in Bioethics and Public Policy. Lan-
know what it has produced on other planets. If nat-
ham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 1998. Interchanges
among the authors on a cluster of issues only recently ural selection does not culminate in ethically valu-
receiving a sustained focus of attention. able products, the Social Darwinists have commit-
ted the logical fallacy first noted by David HUME
Samuel Gorovitz
(1711–1776) of deriving an “ought” from an “is.”
Herbert SPENCER (1820–1903) is the classical ex-
ponent of another version of evolutionary ethics.
biological theory This version rests on the idea that, whatever the evo-
The classical term for efforts to connect biological lutionary mechanism may be, the history of life is
theory with ethics is “evolutionary ethics.” However, progressive, ascending like a ladder to its final goal.
evolutionary ethics has progressed far enough that Spencer thinks HAPPINESS and heterogeneity are its
dividing it into three parts clarifies the issues. Here, goals. A twentieth-century follower of Spencer’s,
then, the term “evolutionary ethics” is restricted to E. O. Wilson, sees the human mind as its goal.
attempts to use the theory of EVOLUTION, or parts of This version of evolutionary ethics also has prob-
it, as an important component of ethical theories. lems. The first is empirical. The history of life is not
“Evolved ethics” applies to attempts to uncover demonstrably progressive. The applicable metaphor
evolved human dispositions relevant to ethics and, is not a ladder but a bush with its top severed by a
typically, to justify such dispositions as truly ethical. horizontal plane representing the present. On this
Evolved ethics is a subdivision of the modern field plane lie the human mind, the bee’s sting, and the
of sociobiology. “Religion and ethics” refers here to mold’s slime, with nothing to indicate which is most
the influence of evolutionary ethics and evolved valuable. The second difficulty is logical. This ar-
ethics on RELIGION. gument commits the NATURALISTIC FALLACY first

146
biological theory

named by G. E. MOORE (1873–1958), the error of it says we can no longer validly claim that all mem-
equating natural properties with ethical ones. bers of our species are radically separated from all
Recently, James Rachels has developed a new var- other organic beings morally, just because of species
iant of evolutionary ethics. His version rests on the membership.
central thesis of evolution, that species evolve from On the other hand, people steeped in biology and
one another. Before Darwin, people thought bio- committed to versions of evolved ethics criticize Ra-
logical species immutable and variations within chels for reaching beyond biology into reason for the
them unimportant. Darwin stood this idea on its justification of ethical arguments. However, reason
head. Species are mutable, and the variations within provides justifications, and attempts to develop eth-
them essential, for without variations, natural selec- ical theories totally within biology have difficulties
tion would have nothing to select. As a result, Dar- with justification.
win considered the divisions biologists draw among
species arbitrary. The Darwinian picture places in-
Evolved Ethics
dividual organisms at the center of biology and rel-
egates species to the sidelines. Theories of evolved ethics claim the human ca-
Rachels next argues that traditional Western pacity for ethics and/or particular ethical disposi-
ethics rests on the pre-Darwinian view of the cen- tions evolved. Versions that try to justify following
trality of species. Traditionally, Western ethics has these dispositions assert that we ought to do what
lifted our species to the pinnacle of ethical impor- we evolved to do.
tance while treating all other organisms as our ser- When Darwin’s contemporaries read his On the
vants and slaves. But if species are arbitrary and in- Origin of Species (1859), some saw its implications
dividuals and their variations central, the old ethics for human beings and argued that the moral and
rests on false foundations. Rachels calls for a new spiritual aspects of humanity lie outside the reach of
ethical foundation, with individuals and their vari- natural selection. In Chapter III of The Descent of
ations central. He calls his new ethics “moral Man (1871), Darwin attempts to counteract this re-
individualism.” sponse by demonstrating that the human moral
Rachels develops the ethical side of his theory sense (conscience) could have evolved.
from the ancient moral and legal principle that equal He begins by claiming that other animals have
cases should be treated equally. We argue that we altruistic dispositions of SYMPATHY and LOVE to-
should not torture people because people feel pain, ward their kin and their social group. These dispo-
TORTURE is painful, and pain a moral EVIL. Other sitions are social, not distinctively moral. What is
animals also feel pain. Under Rachels’s reasoning, if distinctively moral is CONSCIENCE, our sense of duty.
they feel pain as we do, then we should not torture Conscience evolves at the individual and social
them, for equal cases should be treated equally. level. Individually, conscience develops because our
Rachels applies his theory to a wide range of memory, foresight, and intelligence lead to inner
cases. He discusses the value of life, with its issues conflicts between our immediate passions and our
of SUICIDE, EUTHANASIA, and vegetarianism, and he enduring altruistic dispositions. When we compare
reflects on the use of animals in psychological, medi- the two, we feel a duty to follow our enduring dis-
cal, pharmacological, and cosmetic experiments. His positions, thereby resolving the conflict. Socially,
theory does important work in clarifying ethical is- conscience derives from the praise and blame of oth-
sues. Rooted in the center of biology, it has firm ers and from reason. Praise and blame heighten con-
foundations. science while reason enables us to realize the justice
Critics have attacked Rachels’s theory on two of others’ judgments.
grounds. Philosophers who reject the use of empir- Darwin argues that, as people come to live in
ical facts in ethical theories see Rachels as breaking larger groups, reason suggests they expand their
Hume’s law or committing the naturalistic fallacy. sympathies to the larger group. People attain the
However, Rachels violates neither. He never argues highest morality when reason extends sympathy to
that Darwin’s theory is ethically good, only that it all humanity and beyond, to all sentient beings.
describes the organic world accurately. And, he ar- Darwin’s ideas on the evolution of ALTRUISM and
gues, Darwin’s description matters to ethics because conscience are still influential. They acquired new

147
biological theory

depth in 1964 when William Hamilton revolution- the moral proposition, “People ought to act
ized the study of altruism by explaining animal al- altruistically.”
truistic behavior mathematically as a branch of be- Richards claims he has not committed the natu-
havioral genetics. Hamilton’s work marks the ralistic fallacy because we use the same rule when
beginning of sociobiology—the genetical study of we say, “Thunder ought to follow lightning,” and
animal social behavior—and of modern evolved when we declare, “People ought to act altruistically.”
ethics. If each sentence uses “ought” causally, we do use the
His basic idea is simple. The evolutionary goal of same rule. However, both these “oughts” entail
all organisms is to have as many copies of their own causal determinism. Thunder must follow lightning
genes survive in the next generation as possible. The because lightning causes thunder. People must act
direct way to do this is to produce offspring and, if altruistically because genes cause altruistic behavior.
they need care, to care for them. However, close kin But, philosophers do not consider deterministic be-
who are not offspring also carry copies of the organ- havior moral. Moral behavior must be freely chosen.
ism’s genes, and if they need help, the organism will Richards attempts to avoid this problem by con-
increase copies of its genes in the next generation by struing the second sentence as a moral one prescrib-
helping them. The help is “altruism,” and the mech- ing behavior. But if the second sentence is moral,
anism “kin selection.” Altruism evolved in numerous Richards slides illegitimately from causal use of
organisms, including us. While the evolution of al- “ought” to a moral use, thereby committing the fal-
truism is not yet an ethical theory, it lays the grounds lacy of ambiguity as well as the naturalistic fallacy.
for many efforts to derive ethics from evolution. The problem of determinism plagues Ruse’s and
The most viable of these efforts is Peter Singer’s. Wilson’s theories also. Like Richards, Ruse and Wil-
Like Darwin, Singer argues that kin and group se- son argue that human morality rests ultimately on
lection have resulted in altruism in us. But altruism human sentiments, and that our moral sentiments
is not distinctly ethical. Ethics develops as a mode evolved. They derive the moral “ought” from the fac-
of reasoning in a group context when conflicts occur tual “is” on prudential grounds by emphasizing the
between individuals. According to Singer, successful power of our biology to constrain us. If we try to
reasoners must reason impartially, considering contravene the “dictates” of our evolved moral sen-
equally the interests of all parties to disputes. Be- timents, we will suffer psychological and social
cause reason is impartial, it also helps us expand our stress. However, this places Ruse and Wilson on the
caring beyond immediate kin to all people and, even- horns of a dilemma. If the dictates of our sentiments
tually, to all sentient beings. However, because our determine our behavior so strongly we cannot dis-
evolved altruism focuses on kin and clan, reason obey, we are not free creatures and, so, not moral
alone is not likely to overcome our parochialism. We ones. If we can disobey, we can make MORAL RULES
need to develop rules and INSTITUTIONS to help us opposing our evolved sentiments.
extend our sympathies. Their dilemma forces Ruse and Wilson to justify
Knowledge of the narrowness of our evolved al- their theory by default. They claim our moral senti-
truism is helpful. It facilitates critiques of the ethics ments provide the only justification for our moral
of kin and clan and undermines ethical justifications beliefs and actions. Rachels, Singer, and even Dar-
based on NATURAL LAW. R. D. Alexander has devel- win demonstrate the falsehood of this claim.
oped these critiques most fully. Moreover, Ruse’s and Wilson’s version of evolved
Michael Ruse and E. O. Wilson (together and ethics provides no way to resolve moral conflicts if
separately) and Robert J. Richards claim that certain our moral sentiments clash. Robert Trivers success-
ethical imperatives evolved and we ought to follow fully argues that natural selection produces conflict-
them. Richards deliberately borrows from Darwin’s ing moral sentiments.
descriptive ethics, emphasizing group selection. He Francisco Ayala has developed a theory of
asks us to assume that natural selection produces evolved ethics in explicit contrast to Ruse and Wil-
dispositions in us to act for the good of the group son. Ayala claims general intelligence evolved in hu-
and to believe such altruistic dispositions moral. man beings because of its adaptive advantage, and
From these two empirical assumptions, he derives that morality is a by-product of general intelligence.

148
biological theory

Further, he argues that only the proclivity to judge man capacities, for example, one born without a
actions right or wrong evolved, not moral NORMS. neocortex. As evolved creatures, we must be judged
The central strength of Ayala’s argument is that along with other animals, and some of us will be
the conditions necessary for general intelligence are found wanting.
the same conditions required for morality, namely, Third, in an issue of the journal Zygon devoted
the capacity to anticipate consequences, to make to evolved ethics and CHRISTIAN ETHICS, the general
value judgments, and to choose between alternative conclusion is that Christian ethics is untenable in the
courses of action. Its weakness is empirical. Those light of evolution. Presented by Ruse, the main ar-
who study intelligence have demonstrated convinc- gument rests on the evolution of altruism through
ingly that we do not possess general intelligence. In- kin selection. Kin selection promotes altruism to-
stead, we have separate intelligences, for example, ward kin and clan. Christian ethics demands that we
mathematical, linguistic, and musical. Neurobiology love all equally. Thus, Christian ethics may be im-
supports the idea of diverse intelligences by showing possible to live by. If our ethics stem from our
that our brains contain modules specialized for vari- evolved sentiments, Christian ethics may even ap-
ous functions. pear to us to be “morally perverse.”
Moreover, general intelligence without values is These are the main negative arguments. On the
helpless. Without values, we may be able to list all positive side, it is possible that the human capacity
the consequences of an action, but we cannot choose for religion, and even for communion with God,
which action is best. We function well because our evolved. The universality of religion suggests that
basic values are built in. And, if our basic values are our religious dispositions are products of evolution.
built in and we evolved, they evolved. Neurobiological work has uncovered particular ar-
eas in our brains suited to contemplation. Perhaps
these areas evolved in response to the presence of
Religion and Ethics
God much as our vision evolved in response to light.
Both evolutionary ethics and evolved ethics im- If so, God exists as objectively in our environment
pact religion, which is itself intimately connected as light does. If so, this has ethical implications.
with ethics for most people. Below are three argu- The second argument looks at creation from a
ments from evolutionary and evolved ethics under- cosmological perspective in addition to a biological
mining religion, followed by three supporting it. one. Cosmology explains the origin, structure, and
First, natural selection, the main mechanism of motion of atoms, molecules, planets, stars, and gal-
evolution, is morally nasty. For natural selection to axies without invoking God’s action. It discloses an
function, more organisms must be born than can autonomous cosmos, free of God’s intervening su-
survive to reproduce. Selection selects some for sur- pervision. Autonomy develops and increases within
vival and reproduction, and all the others die, some- the cosmos after natural selection begins to operate,
times horribly. This poses a very serious problem for for organisms capable of making choices evolve.
belief in a God who is benevolent, omniscient, om- With human evolution, creatures appear who make
nipotent, and who planned and created the universe. extremely complex choices both as individuals and
If natural selection is part of God’s plan, the plan in groups, increasing autonomy once more. Many of
looks ugly. If selection is not part of God’s plan, God these choices involve ethics.
is either not omniscient or not omnipotent, or both. A cosmological perspective also reveals an in-
The workings of natural selection make the philo- crease of complexity, variety, and creative synergy in
sophical problem of evil even more difficult to solve the cosmos from the Big Bang forward, which nat-
than it has been traditionally. ural selection within the cosmos again serves to en-
Second, as Rachels argues, the bare fact that spe- hance. Rather than being a separate, morally nasty
cies evolve from one another means our species is mechanism for biological evolution, natural selec-
not unique, and species’ divisions are arbitrary. We tion is subsumed under the general development of
must compare individuals when we ask ethical ques- the universe toward positive qualities. And because
tions. Individually, it may happen that an adult chim- we are the most complex, creative, and autonomous
panzee has a more valuable life than a human infant, creatures on Earth, we can find our meaning and
especially an infant who will never attain adult hu- value in these qualities.

149
biological theory

Finally, Darwin’s and Singer’s work points to- COSMOPOLITAN ETHICS; DARWIN; EVOLUTION; FAM-
ward a positive connection between the evolution of ILY; GENETIC ENGINEERING; GROUPS, MORAL STATUS
altruism and the Christian ethical commandment to OF; IMPARTIALITY; INDIVIDUALISM; LIFE, MEANING
love all equally. Altruism springs from love of kin OF; MORAL COMMUNITY, BOUNDARIES OF; MORAL
and clan. It makes human sociality possible. Without PSYCHOLOGY; NATURAL LAW; NATURALISM; NATURE
it, life would be nasty, brutish, and short. But since AND ETHICS; PHILOSOPHICAL ANTHROPOLOGY; PHI-
we are symbol-wielding, institution-building crea- LOSOPHY OF RELIGION; RECIPROCITY; RELIGION; SO-
tures, altruism need not be limited to literal kin. We CIAL CONTRACT; SOCIAL PSYCHOLOGY; SYMPATHY;
say, symbolically, that all people are brothers and sis- TECHNOLOGY AND NATURE; THEOLOGICAL ETHICS.
ters. We apply terms like “daughter” to those unre-
lated to us, calling them “daughters-in-law.” We es-
tablish institutions that demand we treat all equally Bibliography
and condemn nepotism. In doing these things, we Alexander, Richard D. Darwinism and Human Affairs.
can and do extend our capacity to love beyond kin Seattle: University of Washington Press, 1979.
and clan to embrace all humanity, and even all- Bradie, Michael. The Secret Chain, Evolution and Ethics.
sentient beings. New York: State University of New York Press, 1994.
Yet, Singer is correct when he says extending our History and criticism of evolutionary and evolved
ethics, including their relevance to animal rights.
altruism is difficult. With the best of intentions, we
Darwin, Charles. On the Origin of Species. London: John
stumble and fall. The distance between our evolved
Murray, 1859. The beginning of it all.
altruism and our ideals may give us a new under-
———. The Descent of Man and Selection in Relation to
standing of the Christian doctrine of original sin, Sex. 2 vols. London, 1871. Darwin’s ethical theory.
that side of our nature leading us to egocentricity Hamilton, William D. “The Genetical Evolution of Social
and nepotism. Moreover, the difficulty of loving be- Behaviour I and II.” Journal of Theoretical Biology 7
yond kin and clan also implies that we need a God (1964): 1–51. The beginning of sociobiology.
such as Christianity posits, one who forgives. Nitecki, Matthew H., and Doris V. Nitecki, eds. Evolu-
As increasing numbers of people have explored tionary Ethics. Albany: State University of New York
the relationship between biological theory and Press, 1993. A well-balanced collection of new essays
by leaders in the fields of evolutionary and evolved
ethics, they have uncovered significant connections.
ethics.
Rachels argues that the arbitrary nature of species
Rachels, James. Created from Animals: The Moral Impli-
means we need to focus on individuals when we cations of Darwinism. Oxford: Oxford University
think morally. Darwin and Ayala find our aptitude Press, 1991. Excellent short account of the theory of
for ethics has evolved. Kin selection says our capac- evolution, Darwinism and religion, speciesism, and
ity for love and altruism has also evolved. Ruse and moral individualism. The book to read.
Wilson claim some of our specific ethical disposi- Richards, Robert J. Darwin and the Emergence of Evolu-
tions evolved. tionary Theories of Mind and Behavior. Chicago: Uni-
versity of Chicago Press, 1987. Evolutionary ethics,
Evolutionary and evolved ethics are relevant to
Darwin’s ethical theory, Richards’s ethical theory, criti-
the problem of evil and the moral status of our spe- cisms, bibliography.
cies. They help elucidate our capacity for religion Rolston, Holmes, ed. Biology, Ethics, and the Origins of
and our ability to follow the Christian ethical com- Life. Boston: Jones and Bartlett, 1995. Wide-ranging
mand to love all equally. Although there is no in- collection of new essays from the cosmos to a global
eluctable causal or logical connection between bio- Earth ethic.
logical theory and ethics, ethics can no longer be Ruse, Michael. Taking Darwin Seriously. Oxford: Black-
done adequately without considering the contribu- well, 1986. Spencer, social Darwinism, Wilson,
bibliography.
tions of biology to our understanding of our place in
Ruse, Michael, and E. O. Wilson. “Moral Philosophy as
the universe, our attraction to religion, our capacity Applied Science.” Philosophy 61 (1986): 173–92. A
for doing moral philosophy, and the evolution of our seminal early essay in evolved ethics.
ethical sentiments, particularly our altruism. Singer, Peter. The Expanding Circle: Ethics and Socio-
biology. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 1981.
See also: ALTRUISM; ANIMALS, TREATMENT OF; AU- Thompson, Paul, ed. Issues in Evolutionary Ethics. Al-
TONOMY OF ETHICS; COMPETITION; CONSCIENCE; bany: State University of New York Press, 1995. Col-

150
blackmail

lection of previously published seminal essays in person’s wife about her husband’s infidelity, or to
evolved ethics. threaten to do so. The ethical analogue to the legal
Trivers, Robert L. “Parent-Offspring Conflict.” American issue is less clear, but it suffices for our purposes to
Zoology 14 (1974): 249–64.
note that, taken individually, none of the compo-
Wesson, Robert, and Patricia A. Williams, eds. Evolution
and Human Values. Amsterdam: Rodopi, 1995. Col- nents of “ordinary blackmail” is normally thought to
lection of new essays in evolutionary ethics, evolved be morally odious in a way which approaches the
ethics, religion, and social implications. common attitude toward blackmail. Hence the no-
Williams, Patricia A. “Christianity and Evolutionary tion of blackmail used here is set apart from “extor-
Ethics: Sketch toward a Reconciliation.” Zygon: Jour- tion”, a coercive request accompanied by a threat to
nal of Religion and Science 31 (1996): 253–68. A re- carry out an illegal act (for example, the threat to
sponse to Zygon 29, no. 1.
beat someone up); and also from the threat to spread
———. Doing without Adam and Eve: Sociobiology and
Original Sin. Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 2001. Ex-
false information, which might fall under the notion
planations of theory of evolution and sociobiology. Ap- of “defamation”. Likewise, we are assuming that the
plication of evolved ethics to Christianity and the prob- blackmailer’s advantage did not come about illicitly
lem of evil. (e.g., through wire-tapping). Requests to pay the
Wilson, E. O. On Human Nature. Cambridge: Harvard blackmailer in unacceptable “currency” (e.g., that
University Press, 1978. Evolved ethics; annotated bib- the person being blackmailed perform an immoral
liography in the “Notes.”
or illegal act) also lie outside of blackmail in the
Zygon: Journal of Religion and Science 29, no. 1 (1994).
sense which concerns us. We must distinguish “or-
Issue devoted to Christianity and evolutionary and
evolved ethics. dinary blackmail” from these different cases if we
Zygon: Journal of Religion and Science 34, no. 3 (1999). are to consider its inherent difficulties, since these
Issue devoted to evolved ethics and religion. cases bring up different issues. Finally, it is impor-
tant to realise that the narrow notion of blackmail
Patricia A. Williams
that we are considering is not limited to the threat-
ening use of information (as in Q’s blackmailing Z).
If, for example, one asked all shops of a certain kind
blackmail to pay one a monthly retainer for not carrying out
The issue of blackmail involves a significant element the credible threat of opening a competing shop
of paradox, and brings up in novel ways central top- nearby, problems might arise which fall within our
ics such as the permissibility of threats and offers, area of concern.
the relations between morality and the law, the role It has been claimed that the idea of “ordinary
of consequentialist and nonconsequentialist ethical blackmail” gives rise to two paradoxes, which will
considerations, and the limits of freedom. Its relative now be addressed.
neglect by philosophers is therefore unfortunate.
The notion of blackmail is often applied loosely,
The Conceptual Paradox of Blackmail
owing to confusion or an attempt to use its strong
pejorative implication rhetorically. Here it will be The first difficulty with the common view of
considered in a narrow sense, which includes the blackmail is that all its components—the asking for
following features: (a) a declaration of INTENTION to goods, the threat to do what one is permitted to do,
act (or refrain from acting) in a legally permissible and the carrying out of the act itself—are in them-
(and nonobligatory) way which the target of black- selves permissible; so where does the powerful ob-
mail would (it is thought) find unwelcome; ac- jection to blackmail come from? We have no similar
companied by (b) an offer not to carry out the in- difficulty with understanding common attitudes to-
tention on condition of receiving legally permissible ward extortion, for if one is not allowed to beat peo-
compensation. ple up then it is understandable that one is not al-
The paradigmatic example is Q threatening to lowed to threaten to do so, let alone demand
tell Z’s wife about Z’s involvement with another payment for desisting. It has been countered that in
woman, unless Z pays him a large sum of money. Let “ordinary blackmail” the request for money is
us call this “ordinary blackmail”. It is legal to ask for backed up by a threat, and that this combination
money, and likewise it is not illegal to tell another brings forth something new, which is the focus of

151
blackmail

concern. Thus there is nothing paradoxical about the cut funds for groups who do not support them. And
fact that in themselves the elements which make up the threat to use force or economic sanctions is a
the practice of blackmail are permissible. common staple in international relations. Perhaps
The ethical significance of combined acts may in- many instances of pushing up prices of scarce goods
deed transcend the significance of their individual or services in effect constitute monetary demands
elements, so that if the first paradox is taken as for- backed by threats. Why are all of these fundamen-
mal it can be dismissed. However, the way in which tally different from blackmail, from a moral point of
the “alchemy” of the novel emergence of badness or view?
wrongness operates in this case remains somewhat One way of approaching the philosophical diffi-
mysterious, and noting the innocuous nature of the culty of blackmail is to assume that our common
elements of “ordinary blackmail” helps bring this intuitions are correct. Under this interpretation the
out. If one may threaten to do what one is allowed puzzle merely becomes one of how to justify the
to do, offering not to do so in return for limited mon- status quo. Even then we still have our philosophical
etary compensation does not seem to bring forth work cut out. But a true philosophical attitude will
such radical and novel heinousness. And this sense seek to question more deeply whether common in-
of dissatisfaction is increased when we reflect on tuitions are justified at all. One of the effects of
other factors. For example, the person being black- thinking deeply about the Substantive Paradox is to
mailed would in fact often prefer to be offered the call into question basic assumptions about RIGHTS
option of paying the blackmailer, and would accept and moral limits. Note that the consequences of the
if offered. Allowing the would-be blackmailer to sell Substantive Paradox threaten to spread in both di-
news of the affair to the press but not allowing him rections. We may come to feel that we need to take
to sell his silence to Z would not be welcomed by Z. a more tolerant moral stance toward “ordinary
Such concerns are substantive, and hence point us blackmail” and decriminalize it. But alternatively
in the direction of the second paradox. common practices which resemble blackmail may be
seen as the moral equivalents of blackmail, and
therefore less tolerable morally and legally. In any
The Substantive Paradox
case the prospect is disconcerting.
The Substantive Paradox represents the main A number of attempts to solve the Substantive
philosophical difficulty with blackmail. It follows Paradox have appeared in the literature. First, it is
from the apparent similarity between cases of “or- possible to offer a cynical explanation of common
dinary blackmail” and common practices in social attitudes. One such explanation is that the thought
and economic life, which are not taken to be ex- of being blackmailed in the ordinary ways is fright-
tremely reprehensible by morality, and are not pro- ening to the rich and powerful in society, who may
hibited by law. Many examples of this sort in fact be less concerned with, say, the threats of employers
conform to the explication of the two features of or politicians. That “ordinary blackmail” be taken so
blackmail elucidated above. In many labour disputes seriously is therefore just what one would expect.
workers legally threaten to cease work, while em- But the cynical sort of explanation does not provide
phasising the damage they can inflict, in order to justification, and we should attempt to go beyond it.
gain higher salaries; and employers similarly It is possible to concede that in MORAL TERMS the
threaten to close down operations or hire other similarity between “ordinary blackmail” and the
workers if their demands are not accepted. In di- threatened social practices is great, but still perceive
vorce cases the partners can threaten to prolong the the possibility for legal justification of common prac-
proceedings if the settlement does not go their way. tice, thereby explaining away the paradox. For ex-
Boycotts of goods or services may be threatened as ample, difficulties with enforcement may justify a
backing for various sorts of demands. People may divergent legal attitude, without deep underlying
ask for money in order not to raise fences unpleasant moral differences. This approach is problematic,
or even harmful to their neighbours. Victims may however. First, although the issue of blackmail in-
threaten to sue companies under tort law, thereby herently involves both moral and legal matters, the
bringing them adverse publicity, unless compensa- case for paradox can be limited to the moral side. It
tion is forthcoming. Politicians indirectly threaten to would be hard to deny that we hold blackmailers to

152
blackmail

be morally despicable, irrespective of any legal sanc- good about it to overcome the badness. This ap-
tion. Such a severe negative attitude is not com- proach requires the specific justification of the given
monly expressed toward those who (say) engage in practices. Consequentialist, rights-oriented, con-
sharp economic BARGAINING. Even our strictly eth- tractual, and virtue-based ethics approaches may all
ical intuitions seem to tolerate practices which, on be able to contribute here, but the first seems to ac-
closer inspection, may seem indistinguishable from quire a particular authority if this philosophical di-
“ordinary blackmail”. Second, arguing by way of a rection is taken. For example, the nastiness of using
firm distinction between the moral and the legal is- information might be increased through its appear-
sues would involve a high price. If our difficulties ance in the gutter press, but there are other good
with blackmail engendered a huge gap between the reasons to maintain a free press. The use of threats
two, this in itself would be a surprising and disturb- and offers in “quasi-blackmail” form in economic
ing result. Finally, the moral and the legal seem par- bargaining may likewise be justified because of its
ticularly entwined in the matter of blackmail: eth- economic efficiency or by virtue of the right both to
ical disapproval is an integral feature of its legal offer and withhold one’s labour or employment. But
circumscription. no equivalent saving graces can be found in “ordi-
A third way in which philosophers and jurists nary blackmail”. “Ordinary blackmail” is coercive,
have tried to deal with the Substantive Paradox is exploitative, invasive, etc., like many other social
by seeking to identify a feature of “ordinary black- practices, but the point is that there is very little
mail” which distinguishes it ethically from rough so- good about it. Decriminalizing “ordinary blackmail”
cial practices which seem so similar. This route is would cause widespread social discomfort, gener-
the most alluring, because it would diffuse the Sub- ating fear for individual privacy as invasion becomes
stantive Paradox: once you look closely “ordinary commercially viable. Moreover, an atmosphere
blackmail” and the threatened practices may turn would prevail in which each person constitutes a po-
out to be substantially different. However, it has not tential enemy. Yet few benefits can be expected.
proved easy to formulate such a “litmus test”. The
See also: BAD FAITH; BARGAINING; BRIBERY; BUSINESS
candidates considered have included, among others,
ETHICS; CENSORSHIP; COERCION; CONSENT; CONSE-
coerced versus uncoerced choices, the invasion of
QUENTIALISM; CONTRACTS; CORRUPTION; CORREC-
PRIVACY, the rights of third parties, the idea of EX-
TIONAL ETHICS; DECEIT; DETERRENCE, THREATS, AND
PLOITATION, and the distinction between harming
RETALIATION; ENVY; EXPLOITATION; FORGERY; FREE-
and not benefitting. The specific discussions are
DOM OF THE PRESS; HOMOSEXUALITY; INTENTION; IN-
complex and intriguing, but have not been mani-
TERNATIONAL JUSTICE: CONFLICT; LEGAL PHILOSO-
festly successful. The suggestions offered seem to
PHY; POLICE ETHICS; PORNOGRAPHY; PRIVACY; PUBLIC
succeed only in limited types of cases, or to beg the
AND PRIVATE MORALITY; REVENGE; RIGHTS; SECRECY
question by making crucial moral assumptions as to
AND CONFIDENTIALITY; TERRORISM; TRUST; WAR
what is morally disallowed which are shown to be
AND PEACE.
contentious by the issue of blackmail. For example,
the gutter press may invade a person’s privacy and
exploit her weaknesses in order to make money out Bibliography
of her in a way that is similar to blackmail, and a
Clark, Michael. “There Is No Paradox of Blackmail.” Anal-
threat to raise a fence on one’s land to the detriment ysis 54 (1994): 54–61. The case against the Formal
of one’s neighbour, unless the latter pay, would seem Paradox.
to be a case of coerced choice and outright harming; Feinberg, Joel. “The Paradox of Blackmail.” Ratio Juris 1
and yet neither practice would be viewed in the same (1988): 83–95. A careful investigation of the difficul-
way as “ordinary blackmail”. ties, with a legal orientation, particularly trying to dis-
Finally, perhaps it is not that “ordinary blackmail” tinguish the different types of blackmail.
and the practices discussed are inherently ethically Fletcher, George P. “Blackmail: The Paradigmatic Crime.”
University of Pennsylvania Law Review 141 (1993):
very different, but rather that there are merely fur-
1617–38. A good critical explication of the Substan-
ther reasons to allow the other practices to continue. tive Paradox and attempts to solve it. This paper ap-
“Ordinary blackmail” is singled out, not because its pears in a volume devoted to blackmail, and many of
bad features are unique, but because there is nothing the other articles are helpful as well.

153
blackmail

Gorr, Michael. “Liberalism and the Paradox of Blackmail.” Bradley’s sole work on moral philosophy is Eth-
Philosophy and Public Affairs 21 (1992): 43–66. Dis- ical Studies (1876), a second edition of which, with
tinguishing various forms of blackmail and exploring
the pragmatic difficulties of criminalizing similar
additional notes, appeared in 1927; it was reprinted
practices. in 1962 and again in 1988. The work ranges from a
Lindgren, James. “Unraveling the Paradox of Blackmail.” discussion of “the vulgar notion of responsibility”
Columbia Law Review 84 (1984): 670–717. A fine (which requires, among other things, an enduring
critical survey of legal scholarship, particularly of at- self—something, Bradley claims, the philosophical
tempts to distinguish blackmail from similar practices theories of both determinism and indeterminism
that are legal.
cannot, to their detriment, allow for) to an account
Mack, Eric. “In Defence of Blackmail.” Philosophical
of the relation between morality and RELIGION (in
Studies 41 (1982): 273–84. The strongest case for le-
galising blackmail. which it is said that morality leads into religion and
Murphy, Jeffrie G. “Blackmail: A Preliminary Inquiry.” The that no truly religious person can be immoral). In
Monist 63 (1980): 156–71. A good introduction to the between, the work contains a negative critique of
problem and a thoughtful investigation, particularly in both hedonistic UTILITARIANISM and the doctrine of
trying to find factors distinguishing blackmail from “duty for duty’s sake” (for both are one-sided or “ab-
similar practices.
stract,” hence, for Bradley, inadequate), and it pre-
Smilansky, Saul. “May We Stop Worrying about Black-
sents a spirited defense of self-realizationist ethics,
mail?” Analysis 55 (1995): 116–20. The case for the
Substantive Paradox, also considering blackmail which which finds significant though not final expression
is not information-based. in “my station and its duties.”
Bradley introduces the heart of his ethics in essay
Saul Smilansky
II, “Why Should I Be Moral?” This question, he
claims, is improper because it presupposes, gener-
ally, that whatever is good is good as a means—
Bradley, F[rancis] H[erbert] hence either everything is good (relative to some-
(1846–1924) thing or other) or nothing is good (in itself)—and
Bradley’s father was a well-known preacher who, by because it presupposes, specifically, that being moral
two successive wives, fathered twenty children. An or virtuous is at best good merely as a means to a
older half-brother became headmaster at Marlbor- nonmoral end—which is repugnant to “the moral
ough (a school Bradley attended for two years), and consciousness.” But the question is proper if under-
a younger full brother, A. C. Bradley, achieved re- stood as posing these and similar questions: Is mo-
nown as a literary scholar and critic. In 1865, Brad- rality an end in itself? If so, how or in what way?
ley entered University College, Oxford, where he did Are morality and the end for humankind contro-
not distinguish himself in philosophically oriented vertible notions, or is morality only one part, aspect,
subjects; but he persevered, receiving a fellowship or side of the whole end for humanity? The very
(to be terminated only upon marriage) from Merton formulation of these questions shows that Bradley’s
College in 1870. Bradley never married, and he re- entrance into ethics is guided more by ARISTOTLE
mained a Fellow for fifty-four years. Extremely con- (384–322 B.C.E.) than by HEGEL (1770–1831),
servative in political matters (he hated even the though once Bradley finds himself within ethics, his
name of Gladstone) and highly eccentric in personal position takes a decidedly Hegelian turn.
practices (he allegedly prowled the grounds of his The end in itself, Bradley claims, is self-realization.
college at night, shooting cats), Bradley became a This end is not something that the moral agent,
central figure of late-nineteenth-century British ide- through some activity, produces in the sense of a
alism and, accordingly, a relentless and often insight- product that exists outside the agent and outside her
ful critic of the prevailing “School of Experience” activity (as with, say, a painting by an artist); thus it
(empiricism). Largely because of weak health, be- is not something that the agent can in turn receive
ginning as early as 1871, he was a near recluse, from without and feel (as states of PLEASURE are).
though he traveled frequently to the warmer climate The end in itself is to be realized in the moral agent
of southern France. A few months before his death, through her activity, such that it may be called an
Bradley was awarded the Order of Merit by King end “internal to” the activity. In sum, the moral end
George V. is the morally good or virtuous self, or, in the idiom

154
Bradley, F. H.

of KANT (1724–1804), the good will (which is good “already on the threshold of immorality”). But Brad-
through its willing alone). But now, as Bradley sees ley recognizes the problems and limitations of the
it, Kant must be left behind: “Realize yourself” does ethics of “my station”; for one thing, the community
not mean merely to “be a whole” in the Kantian of a person may be “in a confused or rotten condi-
sense, that is, in the sense of consistency (“it is no tion”; for another, and this statement must be added
human ideal to lead the ‘life of an oyster’”); it is to to the two cited just above, “You can not confine a
“be an infinite whole,” which apparently means (fol- man to his station and its duties.” These thoughts
lowing Hegel’s notion of Sittlichkeit) to become a lead Bradley to the essay on “ideal morality,” which
member of a social whole such that you desire to do deals with the nonsocial self, that is, the self that
only what you, as a member of a social whole, ought finds it obligatory to search for beauty and truth:
to do—in which case, you experience no limit or “Man is not man at all unless social, but man is not
restriction from without, this being a central mean- much above the beasts unless more than social.”
ing of infinity. In the course of this convoluted bit of Even within “my station” there can occur a level of
reasoning, Bradley corrects Goethe’s admonition, morality higher than that of merely carrying out my
“Be a whole or join a whole,” by saying, “You can duties as a possessor of various stations or roles; it
not be a whole unless you join a whole.” is (I think) the constant manifestation of a good
As hinted at already, Bradley denies that the self moral character in all aspects of life, including (and
to be realized is the self presupposed by hedonism these Bradley mentions) eating, sleeping, walking.
(i.e., the “feeling self”) or the self of the doctrine of (Perhaps he has in mind the idea from Aristotle that
“duty for duty’s sake” (i.e., the purely formal self) the truly noble man manifests his nobility in even his
whose “morality” (it is said, following Hegel again) gait.)
lacks all matter or content. The self to be realized is, To the charge that his ethics contradicts absolute
first of all, the social self, and it is realized (indeed, morality (the “right in itself” thesis), thereby making
it is real) only by carrying out the duties of one’s morality relative and therefore nonexistent, Bradley
station in society. In response to the objection that counters that “unless morals varied, there could be
this position is “mere rhetoric,” “a bad metaphysical no morality”; the ethics of any state in human EVO-
dream,” because it assumes the “priority” of the state LUTION is justified (hence, in a sense, absolute) for
or society over the individual, Bradley uses his typ- that state, but to demand an ethics justified for all
ical ploy: He argues that this objection presupposes ages is futile. Moral philosophy, Bradley stresses, is
something—here, the notion of “the individual”— not to reform the world but to provide an account
that cannot be justified—an abstraction, a fiction, a of what, at any given time, morality amounts to. Nor
nonentity. Reference might be made at this point to is it to instruct us as to what is right and wrong in
Bradley’s distinctive style, which T. S. Eliot (1888– particular cases: “The decision rests with percep-
1965) once called “perfect,” as illustrated perhaps tion.” No moral theory, including that of “my sta-
by these remarks: “The child is not fallen from tion,” can eliminate all “collisions of duties,” and to
heaven”; “he is not born into a desert, but into a expect otherwise, Bradley insists, is to be deluded.
living world.” While jettisoning the notion of the in- Moreover, every act can be considered right and
dividual, Bradley also rejects the theory of natural wrong, since, Bradley notes, from at least one “side”
rights—largely on grounds resembling those of very it can be “subsumed under a good rule” and from at
recent advocates of VIRTUE ETHICS and communitar- least one other counted as violating a good rule. (To
ian ethics. (It is surprising that these recent move- point this out to ordinary people, Bradley says, is
ments recognize no significant debt to Bradley.) likely to “debauch” and “corrupt” them.) Finally, full
Bradley’s account of “my station” can be summed realization of the self reaches beyond even “ideal”
up in two statements: “To be moral is to live in ac- morality (within which there is always a “something
cordance with the moral tradition of one’s country” to be done”) to religion (where, somewhere and
(which Bradley quotes from Hegel), and, “There is somehow, “all is done”). This suggests the mystical
nothing better than my station and its duties, nor notion that the individual self can achieve satisfac-
anything higher or more truly beautiful” (said in re- tion (and become truly “what it is”) only in the
sponse to the person who would improve upon the “world self,” the Absolute—but on this note we
morality of his society and who, Bradley remarks, is have gone far beyond ethics.

155
Bradley, F. H.

See also: COMMUNITARIANISM; HEGEL; IDEALIST be rational for one agent and irrational for another.
ETHICS; SELF AND SOCIAL SELF; VIRTUE ETHICS. An unresolved problem is that faulty acquisition of
a desire, and its extinction by exposure to evidence,
will not necessarily go together (e.g., if early trauma
Bibliography
produces an aversion that withstands cognitive
Selected Works by Bradley psychotherapy).
Brandt’s theory of the right concerns the moral
Appearance and Reality. London, 1893; 2d ed., 1897. Ap-
code for society that people would choose if fully
pearance is contradictory, and reality is consistent, ex-
periential, and all-inclusive (the Absolute). rational, in the following sense. Individuals remove
Collected Essays. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1935. all desires that are irrational according to the cog-
Essays on Truth and Reality. Oxford: Clarendon Press, nitive psychotherapy test. Then, while fully aware of,
1914. and attentive to, all relevant information (including
Ethical Studies. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1988 [1876]. facts about themselves and the INSTITUTIONS of their
A reissue of the 1962 edition, edited and introduced society), they choose a common code to live under.
by Richard Wollheim. As a utilitarian, Brandt would like to be able to
Principles of Logic. 2d ed. Oxford: Oxford University assert the strong conclusion that a happiness-maxi-
Press, 1922 [1883]. Bradley attacks traditional subject-
mizing code definitely would emerge from such a
predicate logic and the inductive logic of J. S. Mill.
process. But he realizes that persons varying in the
degree or scope of their BENEVOLENCE would not all
Works about Bradley arrive at the same code. So he settles for weaker
Manser, Anthony, and Guy Stock, eds. The Philosophy of conclusions: (1) Since impartial benevolence is not
F. H. Bradley. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984. Con- irrational, some people would choose a happiness-
tains two essays explicitly on Bradley’s ethics: one by maximizing code. (2) Even pure egoists would ben-
David Bell and one by Crispin Wright.
efit from a code containing the familiar happiness-
Nicholson, Peter P. The Political Philosophy of the British
promoting rules (of, for example, nonaggression);
Idealists: Selected Studies. New York: Cambridge Uni-
versity Press, 1990. Defense of Bradley on social mo- hence, even they would select a code that overlaps
rality and self-realization. a happiness-maximizing code in many of its core
Wollheim, Richard. F. H. Bradley. Baltimore: Penguin elements. (3) Somewhat benevolent people would
Books, 1959. A very helpful commentary, though only choose codes that overlap even more with happiness-
part of one chapter deals with Bradley’s ethics. maximizing codes.
John Atwell Why doesn’t Brandt derive the strong conclusion
by stipulating impartial benevolence as a feature of
those who choose a moral code? He feels that moral
theory should be capable of justifying a code to peo-
Brandt, Richard B. (1910–1997) ple with various motivations. Showing a code is ra-
In a series of influential works, Brandt has developed tional, in his sense, should incline even an egoist to
a sophisticated form of rule-utilitarianism and has favor it. Such a person would not be moved by a
applied it to such topics as ABORTION, SUICIDE, the demonstration that the code would be chosen by im-
rules of war, and welfare rights. This article focuses partially benevolent people.
on his most systematic work, A Theory of the Good As it is rational for at least some people to favor
and the Right (1979). a happiness-maximizing moral code, Brandt outlines
In his theory of the good, Brandt applies a twist what such a code is like. It consists of a plurality of
to the familiar account of a person’s good as the rules that are simple enough to be learned, together
satisfaction of her desires. He allows only rational with procedures for dealing with conflicts among the
desires to count, where the criterion of rationality is rules. The content of these rules resembles that of
whether the desire would survive maximum expo- traditional morality, except when certain precepts of
sure to facts and logic in a process of cognitive psy- the latter derive from false beliefs or social condi-
chotherapy. This proposal has two virtues: It dis- tions that no longer hold. Brandt also argues that a
counts most desires based on defective processes of happiness-maximizing code would be economically
acquisition, while allowing that the same desire may egalitarian (because of the declining marginal utility

156
Brentano, Franz Clemens

of income), with departures from EQUALITY allowed “A Utilitarian Theory of Excuses.” Philosophical Review
to provide incentives and take care of special NEEDS. 78 (1969): 337–61.
“Utilitarianism and the Rules of War.” Philosophy and
Perhaps the most novel idea here is Brandt’s use
Public Affairs 1 (1972): 145–65.
of a pragmatic criterion to deal with rule complexity
Brandt, Richard, and Jaegwon Kim. “Wants as Explana-
and rule conflict. The appropriate level of complex- tions of Actions.” Journal of Philosophy 60 (1963):
ity, and the correct procedure of conflict resolution, 425–35.
is determined by what would produce the most HAP-
PINESS, given the cognitive and motivational limita-
Gregory S. Kavka
tions of those who will live under the rules. This
suggestion may solve, for utilitarians, some of the
problems arising from the fact that any act falls un-
Brentano, Franz Clemens
der a multitude of accurate descriptions and a mul-
(1838–1917)
titude of possible rules. A German philosopher and psychologist, Brentano
taught at the universities of Würzburg and Vienna.
See also: BENEVOLENCE; DESIRE; EXCUSES; GOOD,
His most influential philosophical work was the Psy-
THEORIES OF THE; HAPPINESS; IMPARTIALITY; META-
chologie vom empirischen Standpunkt (1874), in
ETHICS; MORAL RULES; NORMS; PSYCHOANALYSIS;
which he emphasized the importance of the concept
PSYCHOLOGY; RATIONAL CHOICE; SOCIAL CONTRACT;
of intentionality. His principal ethical writings were
UTILITARIANISM; WELFARE RIGHTS AND SOCIAL
the Ursprung sittlicher Erkenntnis (1889) and Grund-
POLICY.
legung und Aufbau der Ethik (1952), the latter pub-
lished posthumously.
Brentano’s theory of value is based on the analogy
Bibliography he believed to hold between intellectual and emotive
phenomena. As did DESCARTES (1596–1650), Bren-
Selected Works by Brandt
tano assumed that all mental phenomena are di-
“The Concept of a Moral Right and Its Function.” Journal rected on the objects of our ideas. We may take an
of Philosophy 80 (1983): 29–45. intellectual stand toward such objects, thereby hav-
“The Concepts of Obligation and Duty.” Mind 73 (1964): ing a belief about them; and we may take an emo-
374–93.
tional stand toward these objects. In each case, the
“The Definition of an ‘Ideal Observer’ Theory in Ethics.” attitude is either positive or negative: We may affirm
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 15 (1954):
or deny the object of the idea; and we may love or
407–13.
hate that object. And the emotive attitudes, like the
Ethical Theory. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall, 1959.
intellectual attitudes, may be correct or incorrect.
Hopi Ethics: A Theoretical Analysis. Chicago: University
of Chicago Press, 1954.
Brentano’s theory is primarily a theory of intrinsic
value, a theory of what is good or bad “in itself” or
“Moral Philosophy and the Analysis of Language.” The
Lindley Lecture, Department of Philosophy, University “as an end.” To say that a thing is intrinsically good,
of Kansas, 1963, pp. 1–24. Published by the Depart- according to him, is to say that it is correct to love
ment of Philosophy, University of Kansas. that thing as an end; and to say that a thing is in-
“Rational Desires.” Proceedings and Addresses of the trinsically bad is to say that it is correct to hate that
American Philosophical Association 43 (1970): 43–64. thing as an end. Brentano believed that we can be
“Some Merits of One Form of Rule-Utilitarianism.” Uni- immediately aware of the correctness of certain of
versity of Colorado Studies in Philosophy 3 (1967): our emotive attitudes, just as we can be immediately
39–65.
aware of the correctness (i.e., the truth) of certain
A Theory of the Good and the Right. Oxford: Oxford Uni-
of our intellectual attitudes. In each case, the cor-
versity Press, 1979.
rectness consists in a relation of appropriateness or
“Toward a Credible Form of Utilitarianism.” In Morality
FITTINGNESS between the attitude and its object.
and the Language of Conduct, edited by Hector-Neri
Castañeda and George Nakhnikian, 107–43. Detroit: Brentano’s theory of intrinsic value is pluralistic.
Wayne State University Press, 1963. He constructed a hierarchy of values in which PLEA-
“Traits of Character: A Conceptual Analysis.” American SURE plays a subordinate role. The only bearers of
Philosophical Quarterly 7 (1970): 23–37. intrinsic value, according to Brentano, are conscious

157
Brentano, Franz Clemens

states. And every conscious state, as a conscious bribery


state, contains some part that is intrinsically good.
Bribery has long been a topic of interest to legal
Every correct judgment is intrinsically good; so, too,
scholars, but serious work on the topic by philoso-
is every correct emotion and every enrichment of our
phers is of very recent date.
intellectual life. Since every intrinsic EVIL is itself a
conscious state, there can be no intrinsic evil that
does not include some intrinsic good. Among the Analysis of the Concept
things that are “predominately bad” are error, pain, The following are all clear instances of bribery:
every unjustified act of HATE (especially the hatred
of that which is good), and every unjustified act of 1. A gambler gives a professional boxer a new
LOVE (especially the love of that which is bad). Sen- car in exchange for the boxer’s losing a
sory pleasure is, as such, intrinsically good. fight.
Brentano stressed the importance of what G. E. 2. A defendant pays a judge or juror to decide
MOORE (1873–1958) was to call “the principle of a case in her favor.
organic unities.” Such unities are illustrated by 3. A businessman pays a purchasing agent to
“pleasure in the bad” and “displeasure in the good.” purchase products from his company.
The intrinsic value of the whole is not a function
merely of the intrinsic value of its parts. Brentano In all of these cases, an individual (the briber) pays
appealed to organic unities in dealing with the prob- another individual (the bribee) something of value
lem of evil. in exchange for the bribee’s doing something that
His ethics is based on his theory of value. He for- violates a special duty or special obligation that at-
mulated the “supreme ethical maxim” this way: taches to an office occupied, or a role or practice
“Choose the best that is attainable.” According to participated in, by the bribee. To be bribed is to ac-
one plausible interpretation, the maxim tells us that cept a payment that compromises a special duty or
if the agent is justified in believing that the conse- special obligation that one has. Paying someone to
quences of his act are intrinsically better than those violate a moral duty that holds for all human beings
of any alternative act, then the act is right. regardless of their particular circumstances—for ex-
ample, the duty not to murder others—is not an in-
See also: EMOTIVISM; FITTINGNESS; GOOD, THEORIES stance of bribery.
OF THE; INTENTION; VALUE, THEORY OF. All of the philosophers who have proposed defi-
nitions of bribery endorse the outlines of the analysis
sketched above. However, there is considerable dis-
Bibliography agreement about the nature of the special duties in-
volved in bribery. Some contend that these must be
Works by Brentano duties owed to specific third parties for whom one
is an employee or agent. Others contend that the
The Foundations and Construction of Ethics. London:
bribee’s special duties need not be derived from be-
Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1973 [1952].
ing the employee or agent of a third party. This dis-
The Origin of Our Knowledge of Right in Wrong. London:
Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1969 [1889].
pute about the proper analysis of the concept has
important consequences for the normative assess-
ment of bribery. In nonslave, noncaste societies, peo-
Works about Brentano ple assume the duties of office, employment, and
agency of their own FREE WILL. And it is plausible
Chisholm, Roderick M. Brentano and Intrinsic Value. to claim that one has an implicit promise or contract
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986.
to fulfill the duties of one’s office or position.
Kraus, Oskar. Die Werttheorien: Geschichte und Kritik. Any satisfactory account of bribery must be able
Brünn: Rudolf M. Rohrer, 1937.
to distinguish between bribery and extortion. Very
McAlister, Linda. The Philosophy of Brentano. London:
roughly, extortion involves threatening another with
Duckworth, 1976.
harm unless she pays one something of value. For
Roderick M. Chisholm example, the threat by a foreign official to cease do-

158
bribery

ing business with a company unless it pays him large overturned by weightier moral considerations.
sums of money is a case of extortion rather than brib- Weighty financial obligations (e.g., the need to fund
ery. Many of the payments forbidden by the anti- life-saving surgery) might override the ordinary pre-
bribery provisions of the United States Foreign Cor- sumption against accepting bribes. Moreover, some
rupt Practices Act constitute extortion payments institutional obligations arise within organizations
rather than bribery payments. Bribery must also be whose very aims are immoral (e.g., the Gestapo).
distinguished from practices that are tantamount to The existence of these obligations prompts us to ask
tipping. In some countries, government officials whether there is any kind of prima facie moral duty
and businesspeople expect nominal payments in ex- to fulfill institutional duties that promote immoral
change for performing routine tasks (e.g., passing ends. Does the Gestapo agent who freely promises
goods through customs). When such payments are to obey the Führer thereby incur a prima facie (albeit
openly condoned as a means for officials to supple- clearly overridden) moral duty to help murder Jews?
ment their incomes, and do not secure special favors The foregoing does not address the moral status
incompatible with the duties attaching to the offi- of offering bribes. Bribers sometimes have special
cials’ positions, the payments should not be viewed duties and obligations of their own that would be
as bribes but rather as tips. violated by the offer of a bribe. For example, it might
be contrary to the explicit policies of a person’s em-
ployer to promote sales by offering bribes to pro-
What’s Wrong with Bribery?
spective buyers. The wrongness of offering a bribe
The moral status of accepting a bribery payment may also be partly accounted for by something like
to violate special duties or obligations that one owes the following principle: It is prima facie wrong to
depends crucially on the moral status of the special cause or induce another person to do something that
duties or obligations in question. In cases in which is morally wrong, all things considered. Conversely,
one’s special duties derive from one’s voluntary par- in at least some cases in which it would be morally
ticipation in offices or roles whose goals are morally permissible, all things considered, for someone to
permissible, there are typically several kinds of rea- accept a bribe to do X (e.g., paying a guard in a
sons for thinking it morally wrong to accept bribes concentration camp to allow someone to escape),
to violate those duties. (1) Violating the duties in there may be no moral presumption whatever
question is tantamount to a breach of promise or against offering her a bribe to do X.
breach of contract. For, by hypothesis, one has vol- There are other significant moral questions relat-
untarily adopted an office or role to which specific ing to bribery; among them are the following: the
duties attach; one has agreed or consented to fulfill moral status of extortion payments and threats, and
those duties. (2) Acceptance of the bribes and sub- the extent (if any) to which the recipients of bribery
sequent failure to fulfill the duties in question often payments are morally obligated to do the things they
have very bad consequences. For example, if a busi- have been paid to do.
nessperson accepts a bribe to purchase a product or
See also: AUTHORITY; BUSINESS ETHICS; COERCION;
service that is either inferior to or costlier than some-
CONTRACTS; CORRUPTION; CULTURAL STUDIES; DE-
thing that he could have purchased, then he is ham-
CEIT; DETERRENCE, THREATS AND RETALIATION;
pering the efficiency of his company. Acceptance of
DUTY AND OBLIGATION; ECONOMIC SYSTEMS; FIDU-
the bribe also harms the competitors of the firms he
CIARY RELATIONSHIPS; GOVERNMENT, ETHICS IN;
is being paid to favor. The acceptance of bribes by
INSTITUTIONS; MULTICULTURALISM; PARTIALITY; PO-
government officials may lead to such undesirable
LICE ETHICS; POLITICAL SYSTEMS; PROMISES; RECI-
consequences as the pollution of the environment,
PROCITY; RESPONSIBILITY.
the endangerment of the health and safety of work-
ers, or the noncollection of taxes. Bribery also has
indirect bad consequences in that it tends to dimin- Bibliography
ish public TRUST in the political, legal, and/or eco-
Carson, Thomas L. “Bribery, Extortion, and ‘The Foreign
nomic system(s). Corrupt Practices Act.’” Philosophy and Public Affairs
The moral obligations appealed to here are only 14 (1985): 66–90. Defends the view that accepting a
prima facie or presumptive obligations and can be bribe involves the violation of an implicit promise or

159
bribery

agreement. Argues that many of the payments prohib- NIETZSCHE (1844–1900) into Polish and, with
ited by the FCPA are extortion payments and questions Franz Rosenzweig (1886–1929), the Hebrew Bible
the legitimacy of the FCPA’s prohibition on extortion
payments. Includes references to legal scholarship on
into German. His thought underwent development
the FCPA. from a mystical phase stimulated by Meister Eck-
———. “Bribery and Implicit Agreements: A Reply to hardt (1260–1327) and by Indian thought, through
Philips.” Journal of Business Ethics 6 (1987): 123–25. German idealism, on to Taoism and existentialism,
Danley, John. “Toward a Theory of Bribery.” Business and ending in the dialogical philosophy of I and Thou
Professional Ethics Journal 2 (1984): 19–39. Defines (1923). During the early days of Nazism when Jews
bribery as follows: the offering or giving or promising were expelled from the public schools in Germany,
to give something of value with the corrupt intent to
Buber helped develop a separate Jewish educational
induce a person to violate the duties of his or her role
or office. Argues that accepting bribes is not always system. In 1933 he emigrated to Israel where he
prima facie wrong. taught and worked for Arab-Jewish unity until his
DeAndrade, Ken. “Bribery.” Journal of Business Ethics 4 death.
(1985): 239–49. Defends the view that bribery in- The central concept of Buber’s thought is con-
volves the “alienation of agency.” tained in the title of his major work: I and Thou (Ich-
Donaldson, Thomas, and Patricia Werhane, eds. Ethical Du), a concept he contrasts with the I-It (Ich-Es).
Theory in Business. 3d ed. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Pren-
“Thou” suggests something personal, “It” something
tice Hall, 1988. See “Ethics and the Foreign Corrupt
Practices Act” by Mark Pastin and Michael Hooker, pp. impersonal. But the I-Thou relation is not confined
48–53 (argues that many of the payments prohibited to the interpersonal sphere. For Buber there are also
by the FCPA are extortion payments and questions the I-Thou relations possible with things found in nature
legitimacy of the FCPA’s prohibition on extortion pay- and with “spiritual beings” or “forms of the spirit”
ments); and “Moral Dimensions of the Foreign Corrupt
(geistige Wesenheiten), the sources and products of
Practices Act: Comments on Hooker and Pastin” by
Kenneth D. Alpern, pp. 54–59 (argues that the FCPA, inspiration in the realms of art, philosophy, and
in particular its prohibition of payments which consti- RELIGION.
tute extortion payments rather than bribes, is morally I-It constitutes the world of orientation which
defensible). comprises the everyday world as well as the special
Fremantle, Adam, and Sherman Katz. “The Foreign Cor- worlds of knowledge, both theoretical and practical,
rupt Practices Act Ammendment of 1988.” Interna- which are familiar to us. Whatever we meet is fitted
tional Lawyer 23 (1989): 755–67.
into the framework of what we already know and
Noonan, John T. Bribes. New York: Macmillan, 1984. A
monumental historical study with many interesting an-
evokes routinized responses, each of which involves
ecdotes by a distinguished legal scholar. only an aspect of our own being. But genuine meet-
Philips, Michael. “Bribery.” Ethics 94 (1984): 621–36. ing with a “Thou” involves a call of greater or lesser
Defines bribery as follows: “P accepts a bribe from R depth to reorganize that world. It gathers our whole
if and only if P agrees for payment to act in a manner self and pours inspiration into the forms the reor-
dictated by R rather than doing what is required of him ganization takes. I-Thou involves respons-ibility, a
as a participant in his practice.” Argues that accepting
capacity to respond to the call to change, to renew,
bribes is not always prima facie wrong.
———. “Bribery, Consent and Prima Facie Duty: A Re-
to convert our attention.
joinder to Carson.” Journal of Business Ethics 6 The primordial distance (Urdistanz) characteris-
(1987): 361–64. tic of human beings directs us beyond the functional
circle of the senses and the routinized worlds of un-
Thomas L. Carson
derstanding and response to the wholeness of each
thing within the whole of being. This structural fea-
ture of humanness is lived through most deeply
Buber, [Mordekhai] Martin when a meeting with a Thou furnishes a glimpse
(1878–1965) through to the eternal Thou. In Genesis, this expe-
Born in Vienna, Buber was influenced as a child by rience culminates when each thing is perceived as a
the Hasidic mystical piety of joy in the everyday and, word addressed by JHWH, whose speech makes
as a student, by Ludwig FEUERBACH’s (1804–1872) things to be.
notion of the relation of Ich und Du (I and thou). Ethical RESPONSIBILITY is ultimately linked to
Widely learned in languages, he translated Friedrich such experience. But in the course of time, the

160
Buddha

“Thou shalt” expressed, for example, in the Ten Buddha (6th century B.C.E.)
Commandments, which addresses us personally and
(Also: Gautama Buddha; Siddhārtha; the Enlight-
situationally, is transformed into the impersonal and
ened.) The founder of Buddhism, born in the village
abstract “One should.” All such ethical abstractions
of Lumbini, southern Nepal. His personal name was
must be led back to the concrete meeting with the
Siddhārtha, family name Gautama. As the son of a
Thou. When they are not, then “there is nothing that
ruler of the Sākya clan, he was also known as Sāk-
can so hide from us the face of our fellow-man as
yamuni. Siddhārtha is said to have renounced his
morality can,” just as “religion can hide from us as
well-to-do life at home at the age of twenty-nine after
nothing else can the face of God.”
becoming aware of suffering in the world, including
See also: EXISTENTIAL ETHICS; FEUERBACH; HISTORY the sufferings of old age, sickness, and death. For six
OF WESTERN ETHICS, 10, 11: NINETEENTH- AND years he wandered the Ganges River Valley studying
TWENTIETH-CENTURY CONTINENTAL; INDIA; JEWISH traditional religious teachings. For a time he joined
ETHICS; LEVINAS; MYSTICISM; NIETZSCHE; RELIGION; ascetics in their rigorous lifestyle. Later, however, he
RESPONSIBILITY; TAOIST ETHICS. repudiated the overelaborate ceremonialism of tra-
ditional religion and discounted both theistic beliefs
in various gods and philosophical commitment to
Bibliography
absolute reality, including concepts of Ātman and
Brahman. For the remaining forty-five years of his
Works by Buber
life, he propagated his new Dharma, or truth, and
Between Man and Man. Translated by R. G. Smith. Bos- formed the San̄gha or Buddhist organization and
ton: Beacon, 1961 [1936]. A collection of essays, sev-
monastic order.
eral of which deal with ethical themes.
The Buddha’s main concern was how to remove
Eclipse of God. New York: Harper, 1952. Contains an im-
portant chapter on religion and ethics. suffering and EVIL from life. His teachings aimed to
Good and Evil. New York: Scribner’s, 1953 [1952]. A obtain nirvān. a, or salvation, in a sorrowful world.
biblical exploration. During his life he is said to have avoided the discus-
I and Thou. Translated by W. Kaufmann. New York: sion of purely theoretical or metaphysical issues. He
Scribner’s, 1970 [1923]. Buber’s central work. sought to enlighten people on the most urgent and
Der Jude und seine Judentum. Koln: Melzer, 1963. A col- important problems of suffering, its origin, its ces-
lection of essays spanning Buber’s career. sation, and the way leading to its cessation. These
The Knowledge of Man. Translated by M. Friedman. New teachings are called the Four Noble Truths of
York: Harper and Row, 1965. Collection of later Buddhism.
essays.
The First Noble Truth states that suffering is uni-
Werke. 3 vols. München: Kosel, 1962–3. I. Schriften zur
versal. All life includes the sufferings of birth, old
Philosophie—II. Schriften zur Bibel—III. Schriften
zum Chassidismus. This and Der Jude contain the texts age, and DEATH. The Buddha did not deny that we
selected from the four areas of his completed works do experience PLEASURE and HAPPINESS in life, but
Buber thought worthy of republication. he stressed that all things, including happiness, are
conditioned and transitory. In essence, happiness is
Works about Buber
also relative and entails unhappiness.
For whatever exists there must be a cause of its
Friedman, Maurice. Martin Buber’s Life and Work. 3 vols. existence. The Second Noble Truth discusses the
New York: Dutton, 1981–83. Authoritative biography
by the major English translator of Buber’s works. causes of suffering. The Buddha pointed out that
Friedman, Maurice, and Paul Schilpp, eds. The Philoso-
suffering has its source in craving and ignorance, an
phy of Martin Buber. La Salle, IL: Open Court, 1967. analysis that has both psychological and epistemo-
Essays on Buber’s thought from various perspectives, logical aspects. These aspects are interrelated: Crav-
with a reply by Buber. ing and ignorance originate interdependently. Hu-
Wood, Robert E. Martin Buber’s Ontology. Evanston, IL: man beings may appear to be free, but in reality they
Northwestern University Press, 1969. Select commen- are bound by blind PASSION and unconscious
tary on I and Thou drawing on all of Buber’s works.
DESIRE.
Robert E. Wood In this analysis, life is suffering, but it is not hope-

161
Buddha

less. The last two Noble Truths provide the Buddha’s dhārtha Gautama was mythologized and even dei-
gospel of HOPE. Since whatever exists would cease fied. The question, “Who was the Buddha?” has
to exist if its cause disappeared, the Third Noble arisen. Was he a man or a divine being, and does he,
Truth holds that suffering can be eliminated by elim- even today, represent absolute reality?
inating craving and ignorance. The extinction of suf- Different Buddhists have held different view-
fering is described as the state of nirvān. a. The points. Hı̄nayāna or Theravāda Buddhists showed a
Fourth Noble Truth shows the way leading to the tendency to portray the Buddha, even during his
cessation of suffering. This way is called the Eight- early life, as going beyond the phenomenal into the
fold Path and consists of maintaining right view, transcendental realm and as a transcendent figure.
right aspiration, right speech, right conduct, right With the rise of Mahāyāna Buddhism, the Buddha
livelihood, right effort, right mindfulness, and right was regarded both philosophically and religiously as
concentration. WISDOM, morality, and mental dis- supramundane and transcendent. The Buddha is
cipline together lead one to nirvān. a. said to have a threefold body, termed Trikāya. The
Morality plays an important role along the path three bodies are described as the body of truth or
to nirvān. a. To become enlightened, one should Dharmakāya; the body of bliss or Sambhogakāya;
speak, act, and live ethically and kindly. Right speech and the body of transformation, Nirmānakāya.
advises one to shun gossip, slander, harsh words, When the Buddha is viewed as a man, he is the Nir-
and foolish talk. Right conduct teaches the avoid- mānakāya, the historical Siddhārtha Gautama who
ance of killing, stealing, lying, adultery, and intoxi- was born at Lumbini. When the Buddha is viewed
cation. Right livelihood means that one should en- as divinely enlightened, he is the Sambhogakāya, a
gage in WORK that does not injure other living teacher to the bodhisattvas to help them in their
beings. The Buddhist is expected to lead a life of work of saving sentient beings. And when viewed
service and loving kindness rather than one focused from a metaphysical and universal point of view, he
on profit and indulgence. This moral life has much is the transcendent Dharmakāya, ultimate reality.
to do with compassionate motivation since external The historical Buddha is understood as the incar-
behavior springs from an inner mental state. So the nation of the transcendent Buddha who takes incar-
enlightened life depends on right effort, right mind- nations for the salvation of sentient beings. Ulti-
fulness, and right concentration to purify one’s men- mately, certain Buddhists believe, everything in the
tal state. Morality, according to the Buddha, is not world, although distinct in nature and activity, is one
merely a matter of EMOTION but has noetic or intel- in essence and manifests Buddha’s nature.
lectual aspects; it involves the right view or under-
See also: BUDDHIST ETHICS; DESIRE; EMOTION; EVIL;
standing of oneself and the world.
HAPPINESS; HEDONISM; HOPE; PAIN AND SUFFERING;
Buddhist ethics counsels against a hedonistic way
PASSION; RELIGION; THEISM; WISDOM.
of life but does not advocate an ascetic lifestyle. The
Buddha himself tried and abandoned asceticism. In
his first sermon to five mendicants after his enlight-
Bibliography
enment, he taught that devoting oneself to ascetic
practices with an exhausted body only made the Ch’en, Kenneth K. S. Buddhism, the Light of Asia. Wood-
mind more confused. It would not even produce a bury, NY: Barron’s Educational Series, 1968.
worldly knowledge. The Buddha compared asceti- Cheng, Hsueh-li. Empty Logic: Mādhyamika Buddhism
cism to trying to light a lamp with water; there from Chinese Sources. New York: Philosophical Li-
brary, 1984; 2d ed., Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1991.
would be no chance of dispelling the darkness. The
Conze, Edward. Buddhism, Its Essence and Development.
Eightfold Path is truly a middle way, which re-
New York: Harper and Row, 1951.
nounces the extremes of both HEDONISM and
De Bary, William Theodore, ed. The Buddhist Tradition in
asceticism. India, China and Japan. New York: Random House,
Buddhism as the middle way became very impor- 1969.
tant in different parts of Asia after the Buddha’s Jayatilleke, K. N. The Message of the Buddha. Edited by
death. Early Buddhism developed in a scholastic di- Ninian Smart. New York: Free Press, 1975.
rection and then into Mahāyāna (Great Vehicle) Kalupahana, David J. Buddhist Philosophy: A Historical
Buddhism. During this historical expansion, Sid- Analysis. Honolulu: University Press of Hawaii, 1976.

162
Buddhist ethics

Rahula, Walpola. What the Buddha Taught. New York: To be a moral person, one should be attentive to
Grove Press, 1959. good deeds. But taking intoxicating liquors may
Robinson, Richard H. Buddhist Religion. Belmont, CA: cause mental confusion and sluggishness, and some-
Dickenson, 1970.
times physical violence. Therefore the fifth precept
Thomas, E. J. The Life of the Buddha as Legend and His-
warns against intoxication. This precept concerns
tory. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1949.
the soundness of both bodily and mental states.
Hsueh-li Cheng From an unsound psychological state, good behavior
can scarcely result. Today, alcohol and drugs are of-
ten at the root of crime in society. Buddhism is
keenly aware of these problems and asks its adher-
Buddhist ethics ents to refrain from alcohol and drugs.
I. Ethics seems to have played a more important role These five precepts are obligatory for most Bud-
in Buddhism than in many other world religions. Un- dhists; they are duties all Buddhist laymen ought to
like Christianity, Islam, and Hinduism, Buddhism observe. Their practice is not without utilitarian
does not believe in the existence of a god as the cre- benefits in the Buddhist understanding. In the first
ator and governor of all things. Buddhist scriptures place, the virtuous person may be able to obtain
seldom discuss divine providence or the problem of great wealth through his industry. Second, the rep-
creation. For Buddhists, salvation or nirvān. a rests utation of his deeds will spread abroad. Third, what-
not so much with divine mediation as with human ever society he enters, he enters confident and self-
effort. Human beings will be responsible for what possessed. Fourth, he will die without anxiety.
they do and will reap what they sow. Moral culti- According to some Buddhist schools, he will be re-
vation, rather than faith, worship, and sacrifice to a born in the heavenly realm after DEATH. Thus there
supreme being, dictates human destiny. Moral dis- is a fivefold benefit for the moral person who prac-
cipline and practice are at the core of Buddhism, tices virtue.
whose message is succinctly stated as “Avoid evil, In addition to the five precepts, there are many
do good and purify the mind: this is the teaching of more precepts to be followed by the serious Buddhist.
the Buddhas” (Dhammapada, verse 183). They are designed to bring the Buddhist nearer to the
So, to be a Buddhist is to be a moral person. A ideal of religious life. The monk or bhikkhu has to
good person, according to the Buddha, should ob- observe 227 precepts. Generally speaking, these pre-
serve five basic precepts: (1) do not kill, (2) do not cepts aim at simplifying life. Living a simple life, one
steal, (3) do not commit adultery, (4) do not speak will not be distracted by worldly affairs and can de-
falsely, and (5) do not take intoxicating liquors. vote oneself whole-heartedly to spiritual discipline.
These are the minimal requirements for a lay Bud- Laymen are encouraged to live more like monks by
dhist to follow. Their perfect observance is seen as observing some of these precepts, such as (1) absti-
a storehouse of virtue. nence from taking life; (2) abstinence from taking
The first four Buddhist precepts are similar to the what is not given; (3) abstinence from sexual un-
last four of the Ten Commandments in the Christian cleanness; (4) abstinence from speaking falsely;
Bible; they are also found in Hindu moral law. All (5) abstinence from drinking intoxicating liquors;
these religions teach that religious men should live (6) abstinence from eating at forbidden times; (7) ab-
lives pure of heart and honest of INTENTION. They stinence from dancing, singing, playing music, and
urge us to avoid indulgence in sensory pleasures and seeing shows; (8) abstinence from using garlands,
urge us to be kind to our fellows. However, Buddhist perfumes, unguents, or taking a high seat. While the
morality seems to have treasured the value of life Buddhist layman should keep the five precepts
much more than Christian and HINDU ETHICS. Most throughout his life, he may follow these eight pre-
religions have encouraged believers to sacrifice and cepts on particular occasions. The eighth, four-
offer animals as a part of religious worship. But in teenth, and fifteenth days of every half lunar month
Buddhism, loving kindness is not limited to human are considered to be holy days. During these holy
beings, but is extended to all sentient beings. Fore- times the Buddhist layman might fast or take no
most among Buddhist virtues is to abstain from tak- meals after noon; refrain from dancing, singing,
ing any animal or human life. and seeing shows; and avoid using garlands, per-

163

You might also like