You are on page 1of 6

ISSUES CATEGORIES TAGS SHOP DIGITAL PODCASTS FORUM

Sign In

Search

Your complimentary articles

You’ve read one of your four complimentary articles for this month.

You can read four articles free per month. To have complete access to the
thousands of philosophy articles on this site, please
SUBSCRIBE NOW

Nietzsche Past & Future

To Forget or To Remember?
Paul Doolan on what Nietzsche thought we can, and can’t, get out of
history.
The final work of the French philosopher Paul Ricoeur, History, Memory, Forgetting (2008), provides a
densely argued defence of the concept of collective memory. In one chapter he considers the short
work on historiography by Friedrich Nietzsche, On the Advantage and Disadvantage of History for Life
(1874). Ironically, what earned Nietzsche this special attention was Ricoeur’s need to ‘set apart’
Nietzsche’s work because it “contributes nothing to the critical examination of the historical operation.”
Ricoeur saw Nietzsche as assaulting remembrance. By contrast, David Rieff, who attacked the concept
of collective memory in his 2016 book, In Praise of Forgetting, applauds Nietzsche, and encourages
the reader to take up Nietzsche’s moral imperative of ‘active forgetting’. Ricoeur and Rieff are on two
different sides when it comes to social memory, but both authors share the view that Nietzsche
prioritised forgetting over remembering history. As it turns out, both are wrong.

Nietzsche did assert that forgetting is a sign of health, claiming that “it is possible to live with almost no
memories, even to live happily, as the animal shows: but without forgetting it is quite impossible to live
at all” (Advantage, trans. Peter Preuss, p.10). He further argued in On the Genealogy of Morals (1887)
that forgetting is an active capacity, vital for “governing, anticipating, planning ahead” – a capacity
whose function can be compared to that of a concierge “preserving mental order, calm and decorum” –
and repeats that forgetting is a sign of ‘robust health’ (pp.39-40, trans. Douglas Smith). He claimed that
a happy life of health, strength, and fruitfulness can only be lived within a horizon that one draws
around oneself. The antidote he recommended to combat an overdose of the historical was to have the
strength “to forget and enclose oneself in a limited horizon.” (Advantage, p.62)

However, Nietzsche saw his own age as being dominated by a particular type of bad historical practise:
scientific, objective history. “History,” he wrote, “conceived as pure science and become sovereign,
would constitute a kind of closing out of the accounts of life for mankind… With a certain excess of
history life crumbles and degenerates, and finally, because of this degeneration, history itself
degenerates as well.” (p.14) He described this objective type of history as aspiring to ‘the status of a
mirror’. Here the historian refrains from playing the judge but simply ascertains and describes. He
concludes, “I dislike the tired and used-up men who wrap themselves in wisdom and have an
‘objective’ view.” (p.132) He regarded the claim to objectivity as no more than a form of superstition.
One of the fallacies of the approach to history that makes the false claim to objectivity, is that it leads
the historian to make generalizations based on perceived laws. But “so far as there are laws in history,
laws are worth nothing and history is worth nothing.” (p.55) In Nietzsche’s view there are no absolutes
and no certainties about the past (except, perhaps, the idea that there are no absolutes).

Nietzsche opposed the type of history practiced by the stuffy professional historians who dominated
German universities also because it stifled any life-giving impulse. However, as the German theorist
Hans-Georg Gadamer argued, “Nietzsche’s view that historical study is deleterious to life is not, in fact,
directed against historical consciousness as such, but against the self-alienation it undergoes when it
regards the method of modern historical sciences as its own true nature” (Truth and Method, trans. Joel
Weinsheimer and Donald G. Marshall, 2013, p.316). In other words, aiming for absolute objectivity kills
what is vital in human nature. Nietzsche’s fear was that scientific history robs living things of their vital
aura.

Michel Foucault, a philosopher fascinated by historical development, argued that what Nietzsche
ultimately objected to was the historian’s pretension to have gained a suprahistorical perspective that
lends historical judgments an ‘apocalyptic objectivity’. Such historical accounts falsely present
themselves as crystal clear mirrors of completed historical developments (‘Nietzsche, Genealogy,
History’, trans. Donald F. Bouchard and Sherry Simon, in The Foucault Reader, ed. Paul Rabinow,
1991, pp.86-87). Foucault agreed with Nietzsche that the modern historian creates a charade in which
he “effaces his proper individuality” and replaces it with “the fiction of a universal geometry… to adopt a
faceless anonymity.” (p.91) Nietzsche’s perspectivism means that on the contrary, our historical
interpretations will always be coloured by our presuppositions. We might today talk of our positionality :
the socio-political contexts that shape our identity, perspectives and biases. Any historian’s denial of his
or her own positionality is, frankly, a form of dishonesty. But, Nietzsche never meant to condemn the
entire practice of studying history, thereby endorsing absolute forgetfulness. Instead, he saw the
historian’s task as being to embrace the creative aspect of representing the past. Nietzsche proposed
that the historian should “describe with insight what is known, perhaps a common theme, an everyday
melody, to elevate it, raise it to a comprehensive symbol and so let a whole world of depth of meaning,
power and beauty be guessed in it.” (Advantage, p.36)

This creative act of the historian seems to me to be essential. Nietzsche practised it himself. He used
historical criticism when attacking religion in, for instance, 1888’s The Anti-Christ. He also used a
historical approach in his polemical revaluation of Western morality in On the Genealogy of Morals the
previous year.

Nietzsche understood that to demand of people that they should never attempt to remember and never
practice history would be asking the impossible. On the contrary, “only through the power to use the
past for life and to refashion what happened in history, does man become man.” (Advantage, p.11) He
enumerated ways in which history can be useful: firstly, presenting monumental examples of greatness
from the past; secondly, offering contentment and pleasure through approaching the past with
reverence; and thirdly, using history in a critical manner to shatter and destroy something that
endangers life. What is essential in each of these approaches is that none are objective. Rather, the
historian begins her creative work from a certain perspective.

Nietzsche realised that a historical sense always draws from a perspective, and that this perspective
should never be concealed. The worst form of concealment came about through the pretentious appeal
to scientific objectivity. Nietzsche did not prefer forgetting over remembering, but he did alert us to the
fact that remembering is a creative act.

© Paul Doolan 2020

Paul Doolan teaches History and Philosophy at Zurich International School.

Article tools
Print
Email
Discuss (0)
Share

More articles from this issue

Related articles
Cape Fear
Farewell To Nietzsche
What Nietzsche Really Said by Robert Solomon and Kathleen Higgins
Nietzsche’s Therapy
I Am Dynamite! by Sue Prideaux
Ibn Khaldun and the Philosophy of History
Thus Sang The Manic Street Preachers
Nietzsche & Evolution
Nietzsche’s Übermensch: A Hero of Our Time?
Nietzsche’s Hammer

Tags
Nietzsche
philosophy of history

Advertisement
ABOUT CONTACT FOR AUTHORS TERMS & CONDITIONS

© Philosophy Now 2020. All rights reserved.

You might also like