You are on page 1of 150

TALLINNA ÜLIKOOL

HUMANITAARTEADUSTE DISSERTATSIOONID

TALLINN UNIVERSITY
DISSERTATIONS ON HUMANITIES

1
Janis Ešots

MULLĀ SADRĀ’S TEACHING ON WUJŪD:


A SYNTHESIS OF MYSTICISM AND PHILOSOPHY

TALLINN 2007

2
TALLINNA ÜLIKOOL
HUMANITAARTEADUSTE DISSERTATSIOONID

TALLINN UNIVERSITY
DISSERTATIONS ON HUMANITIES

Janis Ešots
MULLĀ SADRĀ’S TEACHING ON WUJŪD:
A SYNTHESIS OF MYSTICISM AND PHILOSOPHY

Department of Middle Eastern and Asian Studies, Estonian Institute of Humanities, Tallinn University, Tallinn,
Estonia.

The dissertation is accepted for applying for the degree Doctor philosophiae in Middle Eastern and Asian Literatures
and Cultures by the Doctoral Committee of Humanities on 19 March 2007.

Supervisor: Rein Raud (PhD, Professor, Tallinn University)


Leons Gabriels Taivans (PhD, Professor, Latvia University)
Opponent: Sajjad Rizvi (PhD, Professor, Exeter University)

The defence of the dissertation will be held at Tallinn University, Uus-Sadama 5 (U-328), Tallinn on May 29, 2007 at
2.00 pm.

Copyright: Janis Ešots, 2007


Copyright: Tallinn University, 2007

ISSN 1736-5031 (publication, online, PDF)


ISBN 978-9985-58-492-7 (publication, online, PDF)

ISSN 1736-3667 (abstract online, PDF)


ISBN 978-9985-58-493-4 (abstract online, PDF)

Tallinn University Press


Narva Road 25
10120 TALLINN
www.kirjastus.tlu.ee

3
CONTENTS

LIST OF PUBLICATIONS ............................................................................................................................................... 5


PREFACE .......................................................................................................................................................................... 6
INTRODUCTION ............................................................................................................................................................. 7
CHAPTER 1. Wujūd and the Reality of Wujūd .............................................................................................................. 18
1.1. Sufi Mysticism’s Understanding of Wujūd ....................................................................................... 18
1.1.1. Sufi Definitions of Wujūd ....................................................................................................... 18
1.1.2. Wahdat Al-Wujūd in Sufi Mysticism ...................................................................................... 25
1.1.3. Entification and Entity ............................................................................................................. 28
1.2. The Basic Principles of Sadrā’s Teaching on Wujūd ........................................................................ 35
1.2.1. The Principality of Existence in Respect to Quiddity .............................................................. 35
1.2.2. Analogical Gradation of Existence .......................................................................................... 36
1.2.3. Existential Causation: The Gnostic Approach ......................................................................... 42
1.2.4. The Real as the Necessarily Existent: The Proof of the Sincere.............................................. 48

CHAPTER 2. Horizons of Wujūd: Sadrā’s Cosmology .................................................................................................. 54


2.1. The Concept of Creation in Kalām, Philosophy and ‘Irfān .............................................................. 54
2.2. The World of Innovation................................................................................................................... 58
2.2.1. Sadrā’s Teaching on the World of Command and Mīr Dāmād’s
Theory of the Meta-Temporal Origination............................................................................... 62
2.3. Nature and the World of Nature........................................................................................................ 71
2.3.1. The History of the Concept of Nature in Islamic Philosophy:
Avicennan Trend...................................................................................................................... 71
2.3.2. Hamīd al-Dīn al-Kirmānī’s Teaching on Nature and Parallels to it
in the Thought of Sadrā............................................................................................................ 72
2.3.3. Ibn al-‘Arabī on Nature ............................................................................................................ 76
2.3.4. Sadrā’s Definitions of Nature................................................................................................... 77
2.3.5. Substantial Motion ................................................................................................................... 79
2.3.6. Substantial Motion and New Creation ..................................................................................... 84
2.4. The Soul and Its Properties ............................................................................................................... 87
2.4.1. The Peripatetic Influence ......................................................................................................... 87
2.4.2. Sadrā’s Definitions of the Soul ................................................................................................ 88
2.4.3. The Soulhood of the Soul......................................................................................................... 89
CHAPTER 3. Transformations of Wujūd: Sadrā’s Eschatology ..................................................................................... 92
3.1. Ma‘ād as a Universal Principle ......................................................................................................... 92
3.2. Pre-Existence of Souls to Bodies ...................................................................................................... 96
3.3. The Impossibility of Metempsychosis ............................................................................................ 105
3.4. The Spiritual Return ........................................................................................................................ 107
3.5. Corporeal Resurrection ................................................................................................................... 114
3.5.1. The Grave and the Awakening............................................................................................... 118
3.5.2. Rising ..................................................................................................................................... 119
3.5.3. Garden and Fire...................................................................................................................... 123
3.5.4. The Ramparts ......................................................................................................................... 125
CONCLUSION .............................................................................................................................................................. 128
MULLĀ SADRĀ WUJŪD ÕPETUS: MÜSTITSISMI JA FILOSOOFIA SÜNTEES. Kokkuvõte ............................ 134
REFERENCES............................................................................................................................................................... 136

4
LIST OF PUBLICATIONS
I. Janis Ešots 2005. A Comparative Study of Teachings of Sadr al-Dīn Qūnawī and Mullā Sadrā on Wujūd – A.
N. Baqershahi (ed). Mulla Sadra’s School and Western Philosophies: The Papers Presented at the Second
World Congress on Mulla Sadra (May 2004, Tehran, Iran). Vol. 1. Tehran: SIPRIn Publications, 313–320.
(Persian translation: “Barrasī-yi tatbīqī ārā’-yi Mullā Sadrā wa Sadr ad-Dīn Qūnawī dar bāra-i wujūd” in
Majmu‘a-i maqālāt-i muntakhab duvvumīn hamāish-i jahānī hakīm Mullā Sadrā (Awwal-i khurdādmāh-i 1383,
Tehrān), zīr-i nazar-i S. M. Khameneī, jild-i duvvum Mullā Sadrā wa digar falāsifa, Tehrān: SIPRIn
Publications 1385/2006, 183–190.)
II. Janis Ešots 2005. The Eschatology of Kant and Mullā Sadrā – Hamidreza Ayatollahy (ed). Papers of
International Conference On Two Hundred Years After Kant. Tehrān: Allameh Tabataba’i University Press,
25–33.
III. Janis Ešots 2005. The Principle of the Systematic Ambiguity of Existence in the Philosophy of Ibn Sina and
Mulla Sadra – Afkar (Journal of ‘Aqidah and Islamic Thought). Kuala Lumpur: Department of ‘Aqidah and
Islamic Thought, Academy of Islamic Studies, University of Malaya, Vol. 6 (Rabī‘ al-Awwal 1426/ May
2005), 161–170.
IV. Janis Ešots 2005. Mullā Sadrā’s Teaching on the World of Command and Mīr Dāmād’s Theory of Meta-
Temporal Origination (hudūth dahrī) – Transcendent Philosophy. London: IIS, Vol. 6, December 2005, 109–
128.
V. Janis Ešots 2003. The Gnostic Element of Sadra’s Doctrine on Causation – Safavi, Seyed G. Mulla Sadra and
Comparative Philosophy on Causation. London: Salman – Azade Press, 73–89.
VI. Janis Ešots 2002. Preexistence of Souls to Bodies in Sadra’s Philosophy – Transcendent Philosophy. London:
IIS, Vol. 3, Number 2, June 2002, 183–197.
VII. Janis Ešots 2002. Mas’ala-i kaynūnat-i nufūs qabl az abdān dar falsafa-i Mullā Sadrā – Khirādnāme-i Sadrā.
Tehrān: SIPRIn, Vol. 7, Number 28, 39–45.
VIII. Janis Ešots 2002. Садр ад-Дин аш-Ширази и “ирфанизация” философии – Историко-философский
ежегодник 2000. Mосквa: Наука 2002, 378–390.
IX. Janis Ešots 2000. Sadr al-Dīn Shīrāzī – mobtaker-i hikmat-i ‘arshī yā Sayrī dar istilāhāt-i Sadrā – Khirādnāme-i
Sadrā. Tehrān: SIPRIn, Vol. 5, Number 20 (September 2000), 61–66.
X. Janis Ešots 2000. Unification of Perceiver and Perceived and Unity of Being – Transcendent Philosophy.
London: IIS, Vol. 1, Number 3, December 2000, 1–7.
XI. Janis Ešots 1999. Rationalism and Mysticism: A Few Considerations Regarding the Superiority of the Divine
Wisdom – Islam-West Philosophical Dialogue. The Papers Presented at the World Congress on Mulla Sadra
(May 1999, Tehran). Vol. 4 “Mulla Sadra and Comparative Studies”, 157–171.
XII. Janis Ešots 1999. “al-Wāridāt al-qalbiyya fī ma‘rifat al-rubūbiyya”: risāla-ī az yak hakīm – Khirādnāme-i
Sadrā. Tehrān: SIPRIn, Vol. 4, Number 15 (June 1999), 74–82.

TRANSLATIONS OF SADRĀ’S WORKS INTO RUSSIAN:


1. Садр ад-Дин аш-Ширази. 2004. Престольная мудрость. Перевод, вступление и комментарии Яниса
Эшотса´. Москва: Восточная литература (151 c).
2. Садр ад-Дин аш-Ширази. 2000. Приходящее в сердце о познании Господствия. Перевод и комментарии
Яниса Эшотса. – Восток: Москва, № 2, сc. 109–132 и № 5, cс. 109–127.

5
PREFACE

The Arabic word wujūd literary means ‘finding’ (which presupposes the presence of the ‘finder’ (wājid)
and the ‘found’ (mawjūd)). If taken as a philosophical term, wujūd means ‘being/ existence’. The
Peripatetic first philosophy or metaphysics traditionally dealt with the mawjūd (‘existent’) in so far as it is
considered as mawjūd (‘existent’), its reality, states and properties. The seventeenth century Iranian
philosopher Sadr al-Dīn al-Shīrāzī, better known as Mullā Sadrā (979-80/1571-2 – 1050/1640), however,
put forward a thesis that what exists primarily and in the actual fact, is the wujūd (‘existence’) itself. What
else there exists apart from the existence, exists through the latter. Therefore, according to Sadrā,
philosophy must deal primarily with the wujūd, not with the mawjūd.
On the other hand, if taken in its mystical sense, the term wujūd refers to a certain intuition – that of
“finding” the Real (i.e., the Absolute/ Nondelimited Reality) behind the veil of phenomena. Depending on
the preparedness of the mystic, this intuition can be divided into different degrees. Even more
importantly, the habit of finding – i.e., the mystical intuition – can be developed by a number of
techniques. Thus, to a Sufi mystic, teaching about wujūd is a teaching about mystical intuition and its
gradual development.
Is it possible to synthesize the philosophical and mystical understanding of wujūd? If yes, can equilibrium
between the mystic and philosophical approaches be maintained or, by necessity, one of them is destined
to gain the upper hand in such a synthesis? Sadrā apparently believed that his “transcendent wisdom” (al-
hikma al-muta‘āliyya) represents such a harmonious synthesis. In my dissertation, I try to establish to
what degree such a claim is justified.
I assert that Sadrā must be qualified as a thinker of the Platonic trend (more precisely, as a follower of
Plotinus and Suhrawardī), who attempted to integrate his pivotal principle – that of analogical gradation
of existence (tashkīk al-wujūd) (which he borrowed from Suhrawardī) with certain Sufi teachings, in
particular those of the self-disclosure and entification of the Real and the new creation of the world in
every instant. The integration was achieved by Sadrā on the level of theoretical speculation, without
attempting to penetrate to the heart of the metaphysical intuition that underlies the teachings of theoretical
Sufi mysticism as represented by Ibn ‘Arabī school (namely, that of the gradual self-disclosure of the
Real). Despite his sympathy to the teachings of Ibn ‘Arabī and his followers, he remained an outsider in
respect to the Sufi tradition, who appropriated certain minor parts of the Akbarian doctrine for his own
Ishrāqī agenda.

6
INTRODUCTION
As Aristotle taught in his Metaphysics, the first philosophy deals with the existent in so far as
it is considered as existent1, its reality and its properties. In the Islamic Peripaticism, this
definition of the subject of the first philosophy2 was never challenged: its primary concern
was always thought to be the existent and its states. It is important to emphasize here that the
subject of philosophical inquiry and the topic of the discourse was precisely the existent (al-
mawjūd) and not the existence3 (wujūd, literally – ‘finding’). The seventeenth century Iranian
philosopher Sadr al-Dīn al-Shīrāzī, better known as Mullā Sadrā (979-80/1571-2 –
1050/1640), however, put forward a thesis that what exists primarily and in the actual fact, is
the existence itself; what else there exists apart from the existence, exists through the latter.4
Therefore, according to Sadrā, philosophy must deal primarily with the existence, not with the
existent – or, to put it otherwise, what the philosophers have in mind when they talk about
“the existent” (mawjūd) is the existence (wujūd) itself. The problem, however, is that
existence, as Sadrā admits, can only be grasped by “knowledge of witnessing” (‘irfān
shuhūdī).5 It has no quiddity (māhiya) and, therefore, cannot be a subject of philosophical
discourse. Intellect can grasp the nature of existence only indirectly, by examining its effects
and properties in the existents.
The Arabic word wujūd (‘finding’) presupposes the presence of the finder (wājid) and the
found (mawjūd).6 In its mystical sense, wujūd refers to a certain intuition – that of “finding”
the Real behind the veil of phenomena. Depending on the preparedness of the mystic, this
intuition can be divided into different degrees. Even more importantly, the habit of finding –
i.e., the mystical intuition – can be developed by a number of techniques. Thus, to a Sufi
mystic, teaching about wujūd is a teaching about mystical intuition and its gradual
development – quite a different affair than the philosophers’ set of postulates on the existent
and its states.
Is it possible to synthesize the philosophical and mystical understanding of wujūd (i.e.,
“finding” as existence and “finding” as mystical intuition)? If yes, can equilibrium between
the mystic and philosophical approaches7 be maintained or, by necessity, one of them is

1
See: Aristotle, Metaphysics, 1026a 31–34.
2
Al-falsafa al-ūlā (‘the first philosophy’, a title which al-Kindī gave to one of his treatises (see: al-Kindī,
Rasā’il al-falsafiyya, ed. Abū Rida, Cairo 1953, I)) and al-ilāhiyyāt (‘the divine things’) are both treated by
Muslim philosophers as synonyms of mā ba‘d al-tabī‘a (‘metaphysics’).
3
James W. Morris in his English translation of al-Hikma al-’arshiyya always renders wujūd as ‘being’, while
Sajjad H. Rizvi is careful to discern “a distinction between Being, the absolute prerogative of the One, and
existence, a derivative mode of Being that applies to contingent beings” (Sajjad H. Rizvi, “Mysticism and
Philosophy: Ibn ‘Arabī and Mullā Sadrā” in Peter Adamson and Richard R. Taylor (eds.), The Cambridge
Companion to Arabic Philosophy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 2005, 236).
4
Sadr al-Dīn al-Shīrāzī, Le Livre des penetrations metaphysiques (Kitāb al-Mashā‘ir), ed. Henry Corbin, 2nd
edition, Tehrān: Editions Tahuri 1982, 11 (of the Arabic text).
5
Sadr al-Dīn al-Shīrāzī, al-Hikma al-muta‘āliyya fī ’l-asfār al-‘aqliyya al-arba‘a, 9 vols., eds. R.Lutfī,
I.Amīnī, and F.Ummīd, 3rd edition, Beirūt: Dār ihyā al-turāth al-‘arabī 1981, part 9, 18.
6
Cf. W. Chittick’s statement: “Existence (or, to put it more precisely, wujūd – J.E.) in the full sense is not only
that which is there, but also that which finds what is there. The more intensely something is there, the more
intensely it finds. The fullest degree of existence is found in the fullest degree of presence, perception and
consciousness.” (William C. Chittick, “On the Teleology of Perception”, in Safavi, Seyed G. (ed.),
Perception According to Mulla Sadra and Western Schools of Philosophy, London: Salman – Azade Press
2003, 229).
7
By “philosophical approach” or “philosophy” I mean here wisdom, which is based rather on discussion and
logical reasoning than on intuition and unveiling; by “mystical approach” or “mysticism” I mean intuitive
unitive knowledge, based on intuition and unveiling rather than on discussion and logical reasoning.

7
destined to gain the upper hand in such a synthesis? Sadrā apparently believed that his
“transcendent wisdom” (al-hikma al-muta‘āliyya) represents such a harmonious synthesis.
His belief was shared by a number of Iranian and non-Iranian scholars.8 In the current
research, I shall try to establish to what degree such a claim is justified.9 Before beginning the
discussion on wujūd proper, in the introductory part I shall attempt to sketch Sadrā’s
philosophical portrait, considering his teaching against the background of the main
intellectual currents of his epoch, as well as to demonstrate the lasting importance of his ideas
and their impact on the key philosophical trends of the beginning of the 21st century.
Mullā Sadrā was one of the most outstanding intellectual figures in Iran during the rule of the
Safavid dynasty (907/1501-1148/1736) and, perhaps, the most complete embodiment of the
spirituality of the epoch. Like Safavid architecture, his philosophical project, known as the
“Transcendent Wisdom” (al-hikma al-muta‘āliyya)10, impresses with its ambitiousness and
grandeur. While walking through the numerous halls and passages of his magnificent
philosophical edifice, one wonders, however, what has been the purpose of the architect. Did
he just intend to surprise the visitor by the size and measure of his creation and its apparently
eclectic combination of different styles or is there some powerful spiritual message placed
behind this outward splendour and magnificence? If yes, what is the substance of that
message? Nothing is wrong, of course, in the very fact of borrowing ideas and theories from
the predecessors. These ideas and theories, however, are based on certain visions of the world
and particular metaphysical intuitions. Without penetrating into the heart of these visions and
intuitions, the ideas and theories as such cannot really become one’s spiritual property. It
appears that by the time when the so-called “school of Isfahan” (founded by Sadrā’s teachers
Bahā’ al-Dīn ‘Āmilī (953/1546-1030/1621), Mīr Dāmād Astarābādī (d. 1040/1631–1632) and
Mīr Findiriskī (d. 1050/1640–1641)) emerged, Akbarian (Ibn ‘Arabī’s) tradition in Iran was in
the state of decline, to the effect that the heart and the substance of its message was lost:
apparently, there was no-one in Iran, who could teach Ibn ‘Arabī’s (560/1165-638/1240)

8
Thus, for example, Muhsin S. Mahdi asserts: “Mullā Sadrā superimposed Ibn al-‘Arabī's mystical thought
(whose philosophic implications had already been exposed by a number of commentators) on the
“Aristotelian” – Illuminationist synthesis developed by Mīr Dāmād” (Muhsin S. Mahdi,”The Teachings of
Mulla Sadra” (sub-entry in “Islam”) in Encyclopædia Britannica 2006 (accessed 4 November 2006). Simon
Blackburn in the Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy states: “Mulla Sadra developed a unification of Sufi
mystical or illuminationist traditions (to me, though, Sufi and Illuminationist traditions are quite distinct from
each other – J.E.) in Islam with Neoplatonic influences: his main precursor was Ibn Arabi” (Simon
Blackburn, Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy, 3rd edition, Oxford: Oxford University Press 2005, 243).
9
It would definitely be interesting to examine, along with the influence of Ibn al-‘Arabī and his school, that of
Jalāl al-Dīn Rūmī. Certain Iranian scholars believe that Sadrā was more influenced by Rūmī than by Ibn al-
‘Arabī and even assert that his celebrated doctrines on the analogical gradation of wujūd and substantial
motion were borrowed from Rūmī’s Mathnawī (according to the oral remark of Professor Abū ’l-Kāsim
Rādfarr (Tehran University), made by him at the conference “Mawlānā Jalāl al-Dīn Balkhī-Rūmī and the
World Civilization” (The National Library of Kazakhstan, Almaty, 13–14 March 2007)). However, for a
number of reasons, in the current research, I have confined the discussion on Islamic mysticism to Ibn al-
‘Arabī and his school.
10
Apparently, the term was first used by Ibn Sīnā in his Ishārāt wa Tanbīhāt (Ibn Sīnā, al-Ishārāt wa ’l-
tanbīhāt, ma‘a Sharh Nasīr al-Dīn al-Tūsī, 3 vols., ed. S.Dunyā, Cairo 1960, Vol. 3, 401) Nasīr al-Dīn al-
Tūsī (597/1201-672/1274) in his commentary on the Ishārāt explains the term as follows: “The wisdom of
the Peripatetics is a purely discursive (bahthiyya) one, but, in such issues, the truth is established through
combining discourse (bahth) and theoretical inquiry (nazar) with unveiling (kashf) and tasting (dhawq). And
the wisdom which includes all of them is superior (muta‘āliyya) to the first one (i.e., the discursive wisdom –
J.E.)” (ibid.)

8
works thoroughly and systematically (if they were taught anywhere in Iran at all, this teaching
must have taken place in an entirely scholastic way).11
The dominant intellectual tradition of the Safavid epoch was Illuminationism or the Wisdom
of Illumination (hikmat al-ishrāq) (named so after the title of the main work of its founder
Shihāb al-Dīn Yahyā al-Suhrawardī (549/1154-587/1191)). Like the Ikhwān al-Safā’
(‘Brethren of Purity’) in the tenth century, the early Illuminationists not only engaged in
theoretical discussions, but also established and practised their own peculiar religious rites
(worshipping the celestial luminaries and separated souls as intermediaries between man and
God). Suhrawardī’s original teaching (though more research is still needed to establish its
exact character and sources), apparently, was deeply influenced, besides Peripaticism, by the
doctrines of Sahl ben ‘Abd Allāh al-Tūstarī (203/818-283/896), Husayn ben Mansūr al-Hallāj
(244/857-309/922) and the Salīmiyya school12 (the foremost exponent of whose doctrines was
Abū Tālib al-Makkī (d. 386/996), the author of the Qūt al-qulūb (“The Food of the Hearts”)).
Thus, it (Suhrawardī’s doctrine) was an attempt simultaneously to restore Peripaticism to its
initial purity and to combine it with the teachings of the Basrian (and, to a degree, Khorasan)
Sufis. Like Sadrā, Suhrawardī failed (or did not want) to notice that the verbal doctrines of
Peripaticism and Sufi mysticism each rests on its own particular metaphysical intuition, very
different from the other (differences in terminology being merely an outward manifestation of
this – much more deeper – inner intuitive difference). Sadrā’s teacher Mīr Dāmād, who
developed the famous theory of the meta-temporal origination (hudūth dahrī), can justly be
counted, along with Shams al-Dīn al-Shahrazūrī (d. after 687/1288), Qutb al-Dīn al-Shīrāzī
(634/1236-710/1311) and Ghiyās al-Dīn al-Dashtakī (d. 948/1541), among the most
significant figures of the Ishrāqī (Illuminationist) tradition.
In his early years Sadrā, according to his own statement13, was a devout follower of the
doctrine of his teacher Mīr Dāmād – in particular, of the latter’s theory of the principality of
quiddity/ whatness (asālat al-māhiya). Somewhere in his late forties or early fifties (the exact
date of this drastic change is difficult to establish), during his retreat to a mountain village of
Kahak (near Qum), he came to a conclusion that the real state of affairs is quite opposite and
became an ardent professor of the principality of existence (asālat al-wujūd), to the point of
denying the essencies any reality whatsoever – either external, or mental. In the context of our
discussion, it is important to ascertain if beyond this change of Sadrā’s philosophical stance
lies a transformation of the underlying metaphysical intuition, or it is simply a change of
standpoint from which to begin the reasoning, without necessarily having any genuine
experience of “unveiling” (kashf) behind it. In order to answer the question, we first have to
establish what exactly Sadrā understands by the expression “principality of existence”. Does
he refer by it to an epistemological stage of chaotification and the experience during which
the mystic perceives the things in their original undifferentiated state (say, as indistinct
apparitions and silhouettes looming through the mist)?14 Or is he concerned with a scholastic
issue of the priority – posteriority relationship between the essence of the thing and its
existence? Or, perhaps, he – intentionally or not – mixes up a gnostic issue and a scholastic

11
As it is well known, the atrocities of the fanatical Shiite ‘ulamā’ (imported by the Safavid kings from
Lebanon in order to teach masses the basics of Shiism) caused the exodus of Iranian intellectual and
economical elite to the Mogol India. Among those, who emigrated, where many scholars and Sufi masters.
12
On the Salīmiyya schookl see, e.g., Gerhard Böwering, The Mystical Vision of Existence in Classical Islam:
The Qur’ānic Hermeneutics of the Sūfī Sahl al-Tustarī (283/896), Berlin – New York: De Gruyter 1980.
13
See: Sadrā, Mashā‘ir, 35 (of the Arabic text).
14
On this kind of mystical existentialism which rests on the experience of ecstasy, see: Toshihiko Izutsu,
Sufism and Taoism: A Comparative Study of Key Philosophical Concepts, 2nd edition, Los Angeles:
University of California Press 1984, part II, chapter VI “Against Essentialism” (354–374).

9
one? While the entire dissertation must be viewed as an attempt to answer the above posed
questions, it can be said at this point that there are few reasons to suppose that Sadrā might
have had profound and lasting ecstatic experiences, anything more than perceiving the aroma
of the wine of ecstasy, without actually drinking it (not incidentally, in his quasi-mystical
poems, Sadrā rather invites ecstasy than describes real ecstatic experiences).
On the other hand, Sadrā’s treatment of the Rising (qiyāma) allows to suggest that, at the very
least, he was aware of the existence of the epistemological stages at which the reality is
perceived in an entirely different way than on the level of the ordinary sensory experience
(which serves as the ground for the traditional essentialist stance, which underlies the
philosophical system of Aristotle and that of Peripaticism in general). Since he was trained as
a philosopher in the Illuminationist tradition, following Suhrawardī, he tended to reduce the
difference between different epistemological stages to the difference in the intensity and
weakness of existence (tashkīk al-wujūd bi ’l-shidda wa ’l-da‘f). Whether we share fully his
approach or not, to understand it properly, we shall need to take this perspective and admit, as
a working hypothesis, that the principal difference between different levels of reality lies in
the strength and weakness of their particular existence. If, in the course of analysis, we
establish that the principle of the analogical gradation of existence (tashkīk al-wujūd) can
indeed be used as a universal tool to explain the structure of reality and that it never fails if
applied in this capacity, then we shall have to admit that Sadrā’s teaching on the principality
and analogicity of existence must truly be regarded as the most perfect philosophical doctrine
ever worked out. If, applying the principle of tashkīk al-wujūd bi ’l-shidda wa ’l-da‘f, we
come across (a) difficulty(-ies), then, in turn, we shall have to acknowledge that the
applicability of Sadrā’s doctrine has its limitations.
In the last decade or so, it has already become almost a sort of fashion to compare Sadrā’s
philosophy, in particular his doctrine of substantial motion (al-haraka al-jawhariyya), with
the Whitehedean teaching on Reality as Process. Such comparison is, in many aspects, just
and correct, and Sadrā does indeed treat the reality, at least in its sensible and physical level,
as a unidirectional evolutionary process (as Fazlul Rahman insightfully remarks15). In the
current research, however, my concern will be, first and foremost, to establish the principle of
change and its object and then to examine the latter’s changing properties.

***

A very brief account of the history of Sadrology must be given here, in order to elucidate the
background of the research tradition, against which my own dissertation must be considered
and which I claim to have developed in a certain aspect. It seems that, although Sadrā had at
least two eminent disciples, Mullā Mohsen Fayd Kāshānī (1007/1598-1090/1679) and ‘Abd
al-Razzāq Lāhijī (d. 1072/1662), his philosophy did not attract the attention of the Iranian
intellectual elite before the second half of the 18th century, when Muhammad Bīdābādī (d.
1197 or 1198/ 1783 or 1784) began to teach his main work the Asfār (Journeys) in his classes
of philosophy in Isfahan. The crucial role in propagating Sadrā’s teachings and making his
hikma muta‘āliyya the dominant philosophical doctrine in Iran, however belongs to
Bīdābādī’s disciple Mullā ‘Alī Nūrī (d. 1246/1830-1831), who, in his seminary in Isfahan,
taught the Asfār for more than sixty years, bringing up several generations of philosophers.
Judging from the surviving commentaries, it seems that Nūrī concentrated mainly on the
mystical element of Sadrā’s thought and, perhaps, treated the entire system as an ‘irfānī
enterprise. This approach was shared by at least some of his outstanding disciples, namely, by

15
See: Fazlul Rahman, The Philosophy of Mullā Sadrā, Albany, NY: SUNY Press 1975, 100.

10
Sayyed Radi Lārijānī (d. 1270/1853-1854) and Āqā Muhammad Ridā Qumshā’ī (1234/1819-
1306/1889). In turn, another Nūrī’s student Hājj Mullā Hādī Sabzavārī (1212/1797-1798 –
1295 or 1298/1797-1878 or 1881) considered Sadrā’s philosophy mainly in the context of
Peripatetic and Illuminationist traditions (it appears that, in his own thought, he attempted to
combine – though, to me, unsuccessfully – Sadrā’s doctrine of principality and analogical
gradation of existence with Mīr Dāmād’s theory of meta-temporal origination).
Another important exponent of Sadrā’s ideas in Iran in the second half of the 19th century was
Āqā ‘Alī Hakīm Mudarris Zunūzī (1234/1818-1307/1889), the central founding figure of the
philosophical school of Tehran, who, by the way, proposed a number of corrections to Sadrā’s
ontological and eschatological doctrines. Zunūzī’s treatise Badāyi‘ al-hikam (“The Marvels of
Wisdoms”) (in which he answers sixteen questions posed by the Qājār prince Badī‘ al-Mulk)
brought him the fame of the father of comparative philosophy in the Islamic philosophical
tradition16, and, owing to his personal contacts with the French thinker Arthur de Gobineau
(who was a minister in the French embassy in Tehran in 1855-1858 and 1862-1863), the name
of Mullā Sadrā (though not yet the fine points of his teaching) became known to European
intellectual elite.
In the twentieth century, Iran produced a number of distinguished philosophers of Sadrian
tradition, of whom Mirzā Mahdī Āshtiyānī (1306/1888-1372/1952), Seyyed Abū ’l-Hasan
Rafī‘ī Qazwīnī (1315/1897-1396/1975), Seyyed Muhammad Kāzim ‘Assār (1302/1884-
1396/1975), Abū ’l-Hasan Sha‘rānī, Seyyed Muhammad Husseyn Tabātabā’ī (d. 1404/1983)
and Seyyed Jalāl al-Dīn Āshtiyānī (1306/1927-1383/2005) were perhaps the most
important.(Tabātabā’ī not only initiated and supervised the new critical edition of the Asfār,
but also wrote very important commentaries on the book; Āshtiyānī, in turn, composed the
first comprehensive monograph on Sadrā’s life, works and philosophical views in Persian and
prepared the critical editions of a number of Sadrā’s treatises).
In 1912 and 1913, the German Islamicist Max Horten published two small works on Sadrā
(Die Gottesbeweise bei Schirazi and Das philosophische System von Schirazi), consisting
mostly of (unfortunately, often quite incorrect) translations of passages from Sadrā’s works.
Far from being a comprehensive exposition of Sadrā’s teachings, Horten’s works, however,
drew attention to his main ideas – those of principality and analogical gradation of existence.
In turn, Muhammad Iqbal in his Development of Metaphysics in Persia (1908) discussed
Sadrā’s doctrine of perception, in particular, the theory of the “identity of subject and
object”17 (more precisely, the “unification of the perceiver and the perceived” (ittihād al-
mudrik wa ’l-mudrak)), while Edward G. Browne in the fourth volume of his Literary History
of Persia drew a quite detailed picture of the historical background and cultural achievements
of Sadrā’s epoch. These four works, which appeared in the early 20th century, made Western
Islamicists aware of the existence of a powerful and sophisticated philosophical tradition in
Safavid Iran, the foremost figure of which was Sadrā, and acquainted them briefly with some
of his ideas. This slight and superficial acquaintance, however, did not begin to develop into a
deeper and more lasting relationship before the 1960-s, when the French Islamicist Henry
Corbin (1903–1978), who had by then travelled to Iran several times and spent there a
significant amount of time, working in the libraries, meeting Iranian scholars and lecturing on

16
See: S.H.Nasr, “From the School of Isfahan to the School of Tehran”, in Transcendent Philosophy, Vol. 2,
number 4 (December 2001), 6-9 and S.M.Mohaghegh Dāmād, “Nokhbegān-i ‘ilm wa ‘amal-i Īrān: Āqā ‘Alī
Modarres Tehrānī”, in Nāme-i Farhangestān-i ‘Ulūm, Tehrān: Farhangestān-i ‘Ulūm-i Īrān, Vol. 3, number 4
(Summer 1996), 147–151.
17
Muhammad Iqbal, Development of Metaphysics in Persia, London: Luzac 1908, 87.

11
Islamic philosophy, published several articles on Sadrā18 and, in 1964, the French translation
of Sadrā’s Mashā‘’ir (Penetrations)19 – the first ever complete translation of any of Sadrā’s
works in a European language.
Corbin’s translation of the Mashā‘ir is lucid and philosophically correct, and his commentary
– insightful and meticulous. In the introduction, he devotes some twenty-five pages to the
discussion of the problem of existence as it was apprehended by mediaeval Christian and
Muslim philosophers. One notices, however, that his treatment of the issue remains
predominantly scholastic and that in his discussion of the history of the problem of existence
in the Western mediaeval philosophy he, for the most part, relies on Étiene Gilson’s book
L’Être et l’essence. The relationship between Sadrā’s ontology and Ibn al-‘Arabī’s teaching is
only slightly and superficially touched. All in all considered, we can probably say that
Corbin’s treatment of Sadrā’s philosophy represents a mixture of deep insights and quite
groundless misconceptions (e.g., his belief that the doctrines of the theologians of the
Shaykhiyya School, in particular, those of Ahmad al-Ahsā’ī (1166/1753-1241/1826), must be
treated as a creative development of Sadrā’s teachings).20 I guess, however, that his interest in
Sadrā was, to a considerable degree, spurred exactly by these misconceptions: enthusiasm is
almost always based on a kind of wishful thinking.21
The hitherto only comprehensive monograph on Sadrā’s philosophical teachings and, until
now, the best work on Sadrā in English, is Fazlul Rahman’s Philosophy of Mullā Sadrā,
published by SUNY Press in 1975. Rahman not only gives an exact and detailed account of
Sadrā’s doctrine, perspicaciously detecting the analogical gradation of existence (tashkīk al-
wujūd) as its pivotal idea, from which the rest of his theories evolve and around which his
entire philosophy revolves22, but also very skilfully places it (Sadrā’s teaching) in the general
context of Islamic thought and reveals its primary and secondary sources. The main drawback
of Rahman’s work, apparently, is his scholastic treatment of Ibn al-‘Arabī’s teachings (“Ibn
al-‘Arabī who, although he often uses Sufi terminology, is a theosoph with a cognitive context
through and through”23). Besides, Rahman bases his research almost solely on the Asfār. This
limitation, by and large, prevents him from noticing the evolution of Sadrā’s views and does
not allow him to establish the correct chronology of Sadrā’s works.24

18
Apparently, the most important of them was “La place de Mollâ Sadrâ dans la philosophie iranienne”, in
Studia Islamica, Paris, Vol. XVIII, 81–113.
19
Henry Corbin (trad.), Le Livre des penetrations metaphysiques (Kitāb al-Mashā‘ir) Teheran – Paris: Librairie
d’Adrien Maisonneuve 1964.
20
See: Henry Corbin, “Introduction” in Sadr al-Dīn al-Shīrāzī, Le Livre des penetrations metaphysiques (Kitāb
al-Mashā‘ir), ed. Henry Corbin, 2nd edition, Tehrān: Editions Tahuri 1982, 48–50 (of the French section).
Ahsā’ī’s commentary on Sadrā’s Mashā‘ir (hitherto available only in a lithographic edition (Ahmad al-
Ahsā’ī, Sharh al-’arshiyya, Kerman: 1361 L.H.)) definitely testifies that he was completely unfamiliar both
with the tenets of Sadrā’s thought and with his philosophical terminology. On the Shaykhiyya School in
general, see: Henry Corbin, En Islam iranien, 2nd edition, Paris: Gallimard 1991, t. IV, 205–300.
21
In the late 1960-s and the early 1970-s, i.e., after the publication of Corbin’s translation of the Mashā‘ir and
before Rahman’s monograph came out, Pakistani scholar Ansari M. ‘Abdul Haq published several short
articles on different aspects of Sadrā’s thought in Islamabad (among them: Ansari M. ‘Abdul Haq, “Mullā
Sadrā’s Concept of Being”, in Islamic Studies, Islamabad, Vol. 6, 1967, 268–276; Ansari M. ‘Abdul Haq,
“The Metaphysics of Mullā Sadrā”, in Islamic Studies, Islamabad, Vol. 10, 1971, 291–317).
22
See: Rahman, Philosophy, 12.
23
Rahman, Philosophy, 4.
24
Thus, Rahman believes both the Mabdā’ wa ’l-ma‘ād and the Shawāhid al-rubūbiyya to be written after the
Asfār, while, to me, the dominating influence of Avicennan philosophy in these two works decisively proves
that they were composed before the Asfār. (References to the Asfār, found in both works, I believe, were
interpolated by Sadrā during later revisions.)

12
Seyyed Hosseyn Nasr’s (b. 1933) book Sadr al-Dīn Shīrāzī and His Transcendent Philosophy
(first published in 197825), as well as his numerous articles on Sadrā26, undoubtedly, were
very helpful in arousing interest in Sadrā (and the late mediaeval Islamic philosophy in
general) among the Western philosophers and Iranologists (especially their younger
generation). Nasr’s writings provide plenty of useful details about Sadrā’s intellectual
background, interesting (but often rather general) information about the sources of his
doctrines and, again, in a general manner, trace the influence of his thought in Qajar Persia.
For many years, Nasr has been the most prolific and influential propagator of the Sufi and
philosophical heritage of Iran in the West. His works may lack deep philosophical insight and
remarkable originality, and the discussion may often be limited to generalities, but, as
introductions to the intellectual history of Iran and to the thought of Sadrā, in particular, they
have proved to be most useful. However, I cannot fully share Nasr’s belief that Sadrā’s
philosophy represents a systematic metaphysical exposition of the teachings of Ibn al-‘Arabī
and his school.27
In 1981 James W. Morris’ translation of the Hikma al-’arshiyya (The Wisdom of the Throne)
– the first complete translation of any of Sadrā’s works in English, together with a very
detailed introduction, – came out in Princeton, USA.28 Until today, it remains the only reliable
translation of Sadrā’s text available in English. Except very few cases, Morris renders the –
often quite sophisticated – expositions of Sadrā’s ontological and eschatological doctrines
into plain and lucid philosophical English, providing the translation with extensive and
detailed commentaries. His introduction is very informative, but it does not contain an awful
lot of new and bold ideas – for the most part, Morris contents himself with elaborating the
theories of his predecessors (Rahman, Nasr, Corbin, Izutsu). Morris argues that “a central
unifying metaphor of Sadrā’s comprehensive writings is the path of enlightenment – the
spiritual journey from transcendence viewed as a problematic symbol or concept, to its
perception as a personal experience or event, to its full realization as the context and reality
underlying all experience”.29 His understanding of spiritual journey as the actualization of
transcendence seems to be inspired by reflection upon the title of Sadrā’s main work – al-
Hikma al-muta‘āliyya fī ’l-asfār al-‘aqliyya al-arba‘a (The Supreme/ Transcendent Wisdom
in Four Intellectual/ Noetic Journeys). I think, however, that the truth is much simpler –
namely, that the expression al-hikma al-muta‘āliyya refers to the fact that Sadrā’s
philosophical system deals with metaphysical (and those directly related to metaphysics)
issues only: as for the natural and exact sciences, unlike Ibn Sīnā (370/980-428/1037) and
Suhrawardī, Sadrā considers studying them to be below the dignity of divine (“god-like”)
sages (muta’allihīn). Morris’ theory of the quest and realization of transcendence, to me, has
more to do with the modern American spirituality than with the thought of Sadrā.
Despite the above stated reservations which I have about Morris’ work (which, in fact, have
to do more with the introductory essay than the translation proper), I have to acknowledge
25
Seyyed Hosseyn Nasr, Sadr al-Dīn Shīrāzī and his Transcendent Theosophy: Background, Life and Works,
Tehran: Iranian Academy of Philosophy 1978.
26
The most important of which are “Mullā Sadrā: his teachings”, in Seyyed Hossein Nasr and Oliver Leaman
(eds.), History of Islamic Philosophy, 2 vols., London: Routledge 1996, Vol. 2, 643–662 and “Sadr al-Dīn
Shīrāzī ‘Mullā Sadrā’”, in M. M. Sharif (ed.), A History of Muslim Philosophy, 2 vols., Vol. 2, Wiesbaden:
Otto Harrassowitz 1966, 932–961.
27
See: Nasr, Shīrāzī, 88. In particular, he writes there: “In the case of Ibn ‘Arabī especially, this [Sufi]
metaphysics presents itself as so many strokes of lightning, each of which illuminates an aspect of the
landscape of ultimate Reality. These flashes of light are transformed by Mullā Sadrā... into a more steady and
continuous light”.
28
James W. Morris (transl.), The Wisdom of the Throne, Princeton: Princeton University Press 1981.
29
Morris, Wisdom, 6.

13
that his work is by degrees superior to Parvīz Morewedge’s translation of the Mashā‘ir,
published in New York in 1992.30 In a nutshell, Morewedge’s command of philosophical
English is far from sufficient, wherefore, due to the many mistakes and even more
ambiguities found in his translation, it proves to be useless, if not misleading, for a non-
specialist reader. (Specialists will, perhaps, come across some inspiring renderings of Arabic
philosophical terms among Morewedge’s many errors and infelicities if their patience lasts
long enough to read the entire text, comparing every phrase and expression in Arabic with its
translation in English.) In any case, in its present non-revised state, there is little ground in
Morewedge’s translation to justify his claim that his work is an attempt to convince analytic
philosophers of the analytic nature of Sadrian argumentation.31 One has to fully agree with
Sajjad H. Rizvi that “if the translation were completed in a new [revised] edition, then it
would be a significant event in the study of Islamic philosophy”.32 The translator’s
introductory essay does not exceed six pages and only provides the most basic facts about
Sadrā’s life and works.)
In 2000 Christian Jambet (perhaps the most devout disciple of Henry Corbin), under the title
Se rendre immortel, published his masterly French translation of Sadrā’s eschatological
Risāla fī ’l-hashr (Treatise on Gathering)33 and two years later, in 2002, his big monograph
L’Acte d’être: la philosophie de la revelation chez Mollâ Sadrâ34 came out. By and large, as
Rizvi aptly remarks, Jambet’s book represents a detailed development and elaboration of
Corbin’s thesis that true Islamic philosophy is, by necessity, a prophetic one.35 Jambet
interprets Sadrā’s ontology as a hermeneutic for understanding God’s self-disclosure in the
cosmos and argues that Sadrā views the universe as a revelation of the divine act of Being.
The book consists of three parts: 1) la revolution métaphysique; 2) la revolution existentielle
and 3) le salut. In the first part, Jambet explores the structure of Being, with the God of
revelation as its ground and foundation. The metaphor of “the light of Being/ existence” is
discussed in detail, and the principles of principality and analogical gradation of existence are
examined. In the second part the issues of substantial movement, the soul and the world of
imagination are analyzed. The final part “The Salvation” deals with the philosophy of spirit,
return to God as unification of the knower and the known, God’s names and epiphanies. To
Jambet, the primary concern of philosophy is the salvation of the soul; Sadrā’s ontology,
therefore, must be considered as propaedeutics for his eschatology. In a nutshell, Jambet’s
book appears to be based on a highly tendentious reading of Sadrā’s philosophy and
represents an adaptation of his teaching to certain theses of Corbin and the author himself.
That said, one has to acknowledge that, despite the apparent questionability of its main thesis
(the alleged eschatological leitmotif of Sadrā’s “prophetic” philosophy), Jambet’s work
contains numerous insights, in particular regarding the Neoplatonic elements present in
Sadrā’s system.

30
Parviz Morewedge (transl.), The Metaphysics of Mulla Sadra (Kitāb al-Mashā‘ir), New York: SSIPS 1992.
31
Parviz Morewedge, Essays in Islamic Philosophy, Theology and Mysticism, Oneonta, NY: Department of
Philosophy at SUNY Oneonta 1995, XII–XIII.
32
Sajjad H. Rizvi, “Parviz Morewedge, The Metaphysics of Mullā Sadrā [being a translation of Kitāb al-
Mashā’ir]” in Transcendent Philosophy, London: IIS, volume 1, number 3 (December 2000), 124.
33
Christian Jambet (transl.), Se rendre immortel, suivi du Traité de la Résurrection de Mollâ Sadrâ Shîrâzî,
Paris: Fata Morgana 2000.
34
Christian Jambet, L’Acte d’être: la philosophie de la revelation chez Mollâ Sadrâ, Paris: Fayard 2002.
35
See: Sajjad H. Rizvi, “Christian Jambet, L’Acte d’être: la philosophie de la revelation chez Mollâ Sadrâ” in
Transcendent Philosophy, London: IIS, volume 3, number 4 (December 2002), 464–468.

14
Alparslan Acikgenc’s study Being and Existence in Sadrā and Heidegger36 elucidates the
common trends of Sadrā and Heidegger’s philosophy of Being (while Acikgenc’s recent
articles37, in turn, focus on similarities between Sadrā and Whitehead).
Since 1990, at least a dozen dissertations on different aspects of Sadrā’s thought have been
defended in Western Europe (United Kingdom, France, Belgium) and the USA. Brief
evaluations of these dissertations have been given by Sajjad H. Rizvi (who himself defended
his Ph. D. thesis on the modulation (i.e., analogical gradation – J.E.) of being in Sadrā’s
philosophy at Cambridge University in 200038), in his survey article “Approaching the Study
of Mullā Sadrā Shīrāzī”.39 The most outstanding of these studies, by no doubt, is Cécile
Bonmariage’s Le Réel et les réalités: la structure de la réalité de l’être chez Mullâ Sadrâ
Shîrâzî40, which shows not only her profound erudition regarding the Peripatetic, Neoplatonic
and Sufi background of Sadrā’s teachings, but also impressive command of the entire range of
issues the mediaeval philosophy in the Christian West and Muslim East concerned itself with.
The second volume of her dissertation consists of the French translations of large passages
from Sadrā’s philosophical works. In spite of her meticulous examination of the Sadrian
doctrine of the analogical gradation of existence, Bonmariage arrives at a conclusion that
Sadrā’s exact position on certain issues (e.g., that of oneness-and-manyness of existence41)
cannot be established with certainty due to his equivocation on the subject.42
Two recent books – Sajjad H. Rizvi and Seyed G. Safavi’s Mulla Sadra: Philosopher of the
Mystics43 and S.M. Khamenei’s Mulla Sadra’s Transcendent Philosophy44 – represent
introductions to Sadrā’s thought, aimed at wider non-specialist audiences in the West. They
provide the basic outline of his doctrines, without discussing fine points and going deep into
academic subtleties. The potential audience of these books is undergraduates of Islamic Studies
and academics who specialize in fields related to Islamic philosophy (but not in the latter itself).
In the USSR, the first research on Sadrā was Hazratkulov’s doctoral dissertation The
Philosophical Views of Sadr al-Dīn Shīrāzī, published in Dushanbe in 1985.45 In 2000 Esots

36
Alparslan Acikgenc, Being and Existence in Sadrā and Heidegger: A Comparative Ontology, Kuala Lumpur:
International Institute of Islamic Thought and Civilization 1993.
37
In particular, his “Philosophical Perception and Mystical Vision in Sadra within the Whiteheadean Context”,
in Transcendent Philosophy, London: IIS, volume 1, number 2 (September 2000), 101–117.
38
Sajjad H. Rizvi, Modulation of Being (Tashkīk al-Wujūd) in the Philosophy of Mullā Sadrā Shīrāzī,
unpublished Ph.D. dissertation, Cambridge: Cambridge University 2000. Rizvi deals with three facets of the
problem of wujūd in Sadrā’s thought – the reality of existence, mental existence and the language of
existence, showing how the notion of tashkīk applies to each of them.
39
Sajjad H. Rizvi, “Approaching the Study of Mullā Sadrā Shīrāzī (d.1641): A Survey of Some Doctoral
Dissertations”, in Transcendent Philosophy, London: IIS, Vol. 2, number 4 (December 2001), 59–72.
40
Cécile Bonmariage, Le Réel et les réalités: la structure de la réalité de l’être chez Mullâ Sadrâ Shîrâzî, 2 parties,
dissertation du grade de Docteur en Philosophie et letters, Louvain: Université catholique de Louvain 1998.
41
“If being is one and everything is but a mode or deployment of the divine true being, then in what sense can
it be said that particular beings really are?” (Bonmariage, Le Réel, 188; quoted from Rizvi, Approaching, 65).
42
Other recent Ph. D. dissertations on Sadrā include: Zailan Moris, Revelation, Intellectual intuition and
Reason in the Philosophy of Mulla Sadra: An Analysis of al-Hikma al-’arshiyya; Trad Hamade, Dieu, le
monde, et l’âme chez Mollâ Sadrâ al-Shîrâzî; Mohsen M. Saleh, The Verse of Light: A Study of Mulla
Sadra’s Philosophical Qur’an Exegesis; Ibrahim Kalin, Knowledge in Later Islamic Philosophy: Mulla
Sadra on the Unification of the Intellect and the Intelligible and Mahmud Khatami, The Unitary
Consciousness: Towards a Solution for the Ontological Crisis in Modern Theories of the Self.
43
Sajjad H. Rizvi and Seyed G. Safavi, Mulla Sadra: Philosopher of the Mystics, Cambridge: Islamic Texts
Society 2002.
44
Seyyed Muhammad Khamene’i, Mullā Sadrā’s Transcendent Philosophy, Tehrān: SIPRIn Publications 2004.
45
M. Хазраткулов, Философские взгляды Садриддина Ширази, Душанбе: Ирфон 1985.

15
published his Russian translation of Sadrā’s al-Wāridāt al-qalbiyya46 and in 2004 – that of al-
Hikma al-’arshiyya.47
In 1999 and 2004 two world congresses on Mullā Sadrā, organized by Sadra Islamic
Philosophy Research Institute (SIPRIn) (headed by Seyyed Muhammad Khamene’i), were
held in Tehran. The first of them was attended by most leading specialists in Islamic
philosophy and Sufism, and it was hoped by the organizers that the event would become a
significant stimulus for the development of Sadrian studies in the West. Unfortunately, for a
number of reasons, these expectations did not fulfil. Another promising attempt was
undertaken in 2000–2001 by the London Institute of Islamic Studies (initially supported by
SIPRIn). Its then director Seyed G. Safavi (now the President of the London Academy of
Iranian Studies) convened two conferences on major issues of Sadrā’s philosophy (in 2000 –
on perception; in 2001 – on causation), which attracted some of the best experts from Iran and
the West. It was planned to hold a series of conferences on particular aspects of Sadrā’s
thought. Unfortunately, for the time being at least, this promising project has been stopped
due to the lack of funds.48
There are few comprehensive studies on the concept and reality of existence49, and none of
them is very recent. Étienne Gilson’s L’Être et l’essence (1948) deals predominantly with the
history of the concept in ancient Greek thought and mediaeval (scholastic) and modern
European philosophy. Almost sixty years after its publication, it still remains unchallenged as
the most comprehensive study of the issue. Jacque Maritain’s work Existence and the Existent
(1950), in turn, deals predominantly with the relationship between existence and possibly
existent things. Among the studies on the treatment on Being/ existence by particular
philosophers, Anthony Kenny’s Aquinas on Being50 is of special importance.
Toshihiko Izutsu’s Concept and Reality of Existence (1971) remains the best comparative
study dealing with the notion of existence in European and Eastern philosophy. His
Fundamental Structure of Sabzavārī’s Metaphysics (1969), though devoted mainly to the
46
Садр ад-Дин аш-Ширази, «Приходящее в сердце о познании Господствия», перевод и комментарии
Яниса Эшотса, в Восток: Москва 2000, № 2, 109–132 и № 5, 109–127.
47
Садр ад-Дин аш-Ширази, Престольная мудрость, перевод, вступление и комментарии Яниса Эшотса,
Москва: Восточная литература 2004.
48
Of many excellent papers presented at Tehran and London conferences particularly important to my subject of
research were the following ones: Alparslan Acikgenc, “Philosophical Perception and Mystical Vision in Sadra
within the Whiteheadean Context”; Reza Akbarian, “The Principle of Primacy of ‘Existence’ over ‘Quiddity’ and
its Philosophical Results in the Ontological System of Mullā Sadrā”; idem, “Transsubstantial Motion and its
Philosophical Consequences”; Jawādī Āmulī, “The Transcendent Theosophy and the Theosopher”; Cécile
Bonmariage, “Elements pour la comprehension de la notion de tashkīk chez Mulla Sadra”; William C. Chittick,
“On the Teleology of Perception”; idem, “The Pertinence of Islamic Cosmology: Reflections of the Philosophy of
Afdāl al-Dīn Kāshānī”; Majid Fakhry, “Mullā Sadrā’s Concept of the Soul in Relation to Avicenna’s
Psychology”; Valerie J. Hoffman, “Al-Fārābī’s “True King” and Mullā Sadrā’s “Path”: Human Perfection and
Divine Action in Islamic Esoteric Traditions”; Ibrahim Kalin, “Between Physics and Metaphysics: Mullā Sadrā
on Movement”; Douglas P. Lackey, “The Affirmation of Flux and the Denial of Essence in Mullā Sadrā, and
Some Theological Puzzles that Result”; Latimah-Parwin Peerwani, “Mullā Sadrā on Imaginative Perception and
Imaginal World”; idem, “Reincarnation or Resurrection of the Soul? Mullā Sadrā’s Philosophical Solution to the
Dilemma”; Seyyed ‘Abbās Husaynī Qā’im-maqāmī, “Darāmadī bar nazariyahā dar burhān-i wujūdshenākhtī”;
Sabine Schmidtke, “The Doctrine of the Transmigration of Soul According to Shihāb al-Dīn al-Suhrawardī and
his Followers”; Jane I. Smith, “Barriers and Heights: Classical Islam and Mullā Sadrā on barzakh and a‘rāf” and
Sayyed Yahyā Yathribī, “Tahlīl-i intiqādī mas’ala-i asālat-i wujūd”.
49
By ”reality of existence”, I understand its principle and source – or, as Izutsu puts it, “that particular state that
underlies every act of perception and cognition” (Toshihiko Izutsu, “The Fundamental Structure of
Sabzawari’s Metaphysics”, in Sabzavārī, Hājj Mullā Hādī, Sharh ghurar al-farā’id aw sharh manzūma
hikma, qismat-i umūr-i ‘āmma wa jawhar wa ‘ard, 2nd edition, Tehrān: Anjuman-i Āthār wa Mafāhir-i
Farhangī 1384/ 2005, 27).
50
Anthony Kenny, Aquinas on Being, Oxford: Clarendon Press 2002.

16
thought of Sabzavārī, discusses the main principles of Sadrā’s ontology (those of principality
of existence and its analogical gradation) in some detail. As it is evident from the tenets and
structure of my study, I have relied on Izutsu’s works51 greatly, to the point that they can be,
in a certain sense, regarded as my principal source of inspiration.
The work which, in respect to its subject, comes closest to my study,52 apparently, is Sayyed
Jalāl al-Dīn Āshtiyānī’s Hastī az nazar-i ‘irfān wa falsafa (“Existence from the Standpoint of
[Islamic] Philosophy and Mysticism”) (1960).53 Āshtiyānī, however, is concerned mainly
with the philosophical understanding of existence, paying much less attention to the mystical
one. Furthermore, his book is, first and foremost, a comparative study of two particular texts –
Sadrā’s Mashā‘ir and Dāwūd al-Qaysarī’s (d. 751/1350) introduction to his commentary on
Ibn al-‘Arabī’s Fusūs al-hikam. It is highly questionable, whether the above text of Qaysarī
can be recognized as an epitome of the Sufi (even that of Ibn al-‘Arabī school solely) teaching
on wujūd. The texts of Ibn al-‘Arabī and Sadr al-Dīn Qūnawī (d.673/1274) seem to reveal this
teaching in more depth and detail. Certainly, the discourse of Ibn al-‘Arabī and Qūnawī is
often quite sophisticated and, at times, rather difficult to follow, while that of Qaysarī is much
more accessible. With full awareness of the latter difficulty, I have attempted to build my
discussion on the Sufi understanding of wujūd mainly on the texts of Qūnawī.

***
The first chapter “Wujūd and the Reality of Wujūd” consists of two parts, dealing with the
mystical (Sufi) and philosophical (predominantly Peripatetic) doctrines on wujūd respectively.
An attempt is then made to establish whether – and, if yes, to what extent – Sadrā’s teaching
on principality and analogical gradation of existence can be regarded as a successful synthesis
of both doctrines.
In the second chapter, the main levels (strata) of reality or “horizons” of existence, as viewed
by Sadrā, are examined and the implications of the gradation of existence are described. I then
compare the structure of analogically graded existence, offered by Sadrā, with the structures
suggested by Ibn Sīnā, Suhrawardī, Hamīd al-Dīn al-Kirmānī (d. after 411/1020-1) and Ibn al-
‘Arabī, considering Sadrā’s interpretation of innovation/ intellect, nature and soul against the
background of the relevant Peripatetic, Neoplatonic (Illuminationist and Ismaili) and Sufi
teachings.
The third chapter deals with the transformation of existence. In it, the modalities of the soul’s
existence before, with and after the physical body are discussed. I argue that Sadrā’s
eschatological doctrine, by and large, is a reinterpretation of Sufi (Ibn al-‘Arabī’s) teaching of
man’s inner (deliberate) self-transformation, known as the “change/ substitution of existence”
(tabdīl al-wujūd).

51
I mean Izutsu’s books Creation and the Timeless Order of Things, The Concept and Reality of Existence and
especially Sufism and Taoism: A Comparative Study of Key Philosophical Concepts and some of his articles,
in particular, “The Problem of Quiddity and Natural Universal in Islamic Metaphysics” (in Etudes
philosophiques présentées au Dr. Ibrahim Madkour) and “Mīr Dāmād and His Metaphysics” (introduction to
Mīr Dāmād’s Qabasāt).
52
Recently, Sajjad H. Rizvi has briefly addressed the treatment of wujūd by Ibn al-‘Arabī and Mullā Sadrā in
his article “Mysticism and Philosophy: Ibn ‘Arabī and Mullā Sadrā” (in Peter Adamson and Richard
R. Taylor (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Arabic Philosophy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
2005, 224–246, in particular 233–239).
53
Sayyed Jalāl al-Dīn Āshtiyānī, Hastī az nazar-i ‘irfān wa falsafa, Mashhad: Chāpkhāne-i Khurāsān 1379 L.H.

17
CHAPTER 1. WUJŪD AND THE REALITY OF WUJŪD
1.1. SUFI MYSTICISM’S UNDERSTANDING OF WUJŪD

1.1.1. Sufi Definitions of Wujūd

In order to be able to consider Sadrā’s teaching on Existence/ Finding (Wujūd) and the Reality
(i.e., the Principle)54 of Existence/ Finding (haqīqat al-wujūd) in the context of Sufi
Mysticism (`irfān), I shall have to draw a sketchy outline of the history of the problem of
wujūd (existence/ being/ finding) and wahdat al-wujūd (oneness/ unity of existence/ being/
finding) in theoretical Sufism (in full awareness that many of the observations presented
below may seem next to commonplace to the experts in the field).
The ambiguity of the term wujūd (depending on the context, it can mean either ‘existence’, or
‘being’, or ‘finding’, or all) has often been an issue in the philosophical (especially –
ontological), theological and mystical discussions which took place in the mediaeval Islamic
intellectual milieu, since neither philosophers, nor theologicians, nor Sufi mystics could do
without the employment of the term in their discourses.55 Recently some Western scholars
(the most prominent of whom is William Chittick (who wisely avoids translating the word
wujūd into English)) have also given their attention to the issue.
While the exact word wujūd does not appear in the Qur’an, the verb wajada (‘to find’)
appears there more than ten times. From the Sufi point of view, its employment in the 94th
verse of the surah “Joseph” is of particular importance: the old Jacob, who has lost his
eyesight out of the grief over the disappearance (and alleged death) of his beloved son Joseph,
perceives the aroma of his lost son as soon as the caravan carrying with it Joseph’s shirt
leaves Egypt (while he himself is tens of miles away in his home in Canaan) and exclaims:
“Truly, I find the scent of Joseph!” – which gives Sufi mystics a good cause to count him
(Jacob) as one of the “people of finding” (ahl al-wujūd) (while the entire story is often treated
as a symbolic description of the relations between the lover and his mystical beloved).
Also important is the verse 24th verse of the surah “Light”, in which it is told that
“the Unbelievers – their deeds are like the mirage in sandy deserts, which the man parched with
thirst mistakes for water; until when he comes up to it, he finds it to be nothing, but he finds
God at (i.e., in – J.E.) him”56
– whence we can conclude that the only thing that can truly and really be found is God.57
(Hence, God/ the Real is the Found One (mawjūd). But, upon more reflection, the mystic
realizes that He is simultaneously the (only) Finder and the Finding itself.)

54
“We do not mean by ‘reality’ (haqīqa) anything else except what is the principle (or: origin) (mabda’) of an
external trace (athar khārijī)” (Sadrā, Asfār, part 2, 319). Cf. C. Bonmariage’s translation in: Cecil
Bonmariage, “Acts of Men, Acts of God” in Safavi, Seyed G., Mulla Sadra and Comparative Philosophy on
Causation, London: Salman – Azade Press 2003, 300.
55
One of the outstanding mediaeval Muslim thinkers who paid attention to the etymological implications of
wujūd, was Afdāl al-Dīn Kāshānī, better known as Bābā Afdāl (d. ca 610/1213-1214). On his treatment of
wujūd, see: W.Chittick, “The Pertinence of Islamic Cosmology: Reflections of the Philosophy of Afdāl al-
Dīn Kāshānī” in Islam-West Philosophical Dialogue: The Papers presented at the World Congress on Mulla
Sadra (May 1999, Tehran), volume 2 “Mulla Sadra and Transcendent Philosophy”: Tehran: SIPRIn
Publications 1380/2001, 531–532. (Unfortunately, Chittick`s book on Bābā Afdāl The Heart of Islamic
Philosophy (Oxford: Oneworld 2001) was inaccessible to me at the time of writing the current work.)
56
The Holy Qur’ān, translated by Abdullah Yusuf Ali, Hertfordshire: Wordswordth Editions Ltd. 2000, 291.
57
Maurice Gloton in his introduction to the French translation of Ibn al-‘Arabī’s Inshā’ al-dawā’ir discusses
the implications of the usage of the verb wajada in this verse in great detail. See: Maurice Gloton,

18
It is commonly believed that in philosophical texts wujūd almost always means ‘being/
existence’ (Persian hastī), but in the mystical (‘irfānī) ones can mean either ‘existence’ or
‘finding’ (understood as ‘awareness’, ‘perception’ and ‘consciousness’). Generally, the older
the Sufi text, the greater the chance that wujūd means precisely ‘finding’. (Chittick points to
‘Ayn al-Qudāt Hamadānī (d. 525/1131) as one of the first Sufi authors who employed wujūd
in the philosophical sense – i.e., that of ‘existence/ being’58). Abū ’l-Qāsim Qushayrī
(d.465/1072) in his Risāla (“Treatise”) does not give a definition of wujūd, but treats it as the
utmost limit of wajd (‘ecstasis’) and applies it to the Real (haqq), stating that “finding (wujūd)
of the Real does not take place except after the vanishing of the mortal human nature
(bashariyya)”59. He points out that wujūd necessitates the perishment (istihlāk) of the servant
and compares the state of wujūd to drawning in the sea (i.e., to fanā’ – the annihilation of the
self). To Qushayrī, the possessor of (the state of) wujūd partakes in sobriety (sahw) and
obliteration (mahw) simultaneously: his sobriety takes place due to his subsistence through
the Real, while his obliteration occurs owing to his annihilation in the Real.60 Qushayrī’s
contemporary ‘Abdallāh Ansārī (d.481/1088) in his Manāzil al-sā’irīn (“Waystations of the
Travellers”) defines wujūd as “grasping (literally: ‘obtaining’ – J.E.) the reality of the thing”
(al-zafar bi-haqīqat al-shay`).61 In his Tabaqāt al-sūfiyya (“Strata of the Sufis”) Ansārī
indicates that the sign of wujūd is annihilation (fanā’).62
It is difficult to make decisive conclusions about Muhyi al-Dīn Ibn al-‘Arabī’s usage of the
term wujūd, given the vastness of his legacy, a significant part of which remains unpublished
as yet. Generally speaking, to him, wujūd has two basic meanings: in the first one, it is a
technical Sufi term which he explains as “finding the Real in ecstasy” (wijdān al-haqq fī ’l-
wajd)63 (and which, thus, refers to the subjective experience of the mystic); in the second
sense it points to the Real’s finding itself (i.e., its self-awareness), which encompasses all
levels of the created world (which, in fact, are nothing but different stages of its self-
disclosure (tajallī). Hence, it can be said that the Real finds itself through contemplating itself
in its essence (dhāt) and in its self-disclosure(s). What we refer to as the “created world”,
“cosmos” or “universe”, is actually a result (and, simultaneously, a tool) of the Real’s self-
contemplation through its self-disclosure. Hence, what is commonly known as “existence”, is
actually a kind of finding – the Real’s finding its perfections (kamālāt) in the loci of the
manifestations (mazāhir) of its names. This is true that philosophers tend to ignore (or openly
refuse to admit) the fact that the entified existence (al-wujūd al-‘aynī) of things is nothing else
but the Real’s permanent finding itself (wherefore wujūd is inevitably subjective) and to
ascribe to it objectivity. In fact, according to the teaching of Ibn al-‘Arabī (and Sufi mysticism
in general), there is no such thing as independent objective existence, since everything
existing in different levels of the cosmos is nothing else but meanings and forms present in
the Real’s mind and imagination.

“Introduction” in Ibn ‘Arabī, La production des circles, traduit et présenté par Paul Fenton et Maurice
Gloton, Paris: Éditions de l’Éclat 1996, XIX–XX.
58
See: W.C.Chittick, “Wahdat al-wujūd in India”, in the Proceedings of the Conference “Inner Dimension of
the Islamic World. The School of Ibn ‘Arabī” (22-23 January 2001). School of Asian and African Area
Studies, Kyoto University, Kyoto (forthcoming).
59
Abū ’l-Qāsim al-Qushayrī, al-Risāla al-qushayriyya, eds. ‘A.Mahmūd and M.Sharīf, Qum: Intishārāt-i Bīdār
1374 S.H., 132.
60
See: Qushayrī, Risāla, 133.
61
‘Abdallāh Ansārī, Manāzil al-sā’irīn, ed. A.Shirvānī, Qum: al-Matba‘a Quds 1417 L.H., 138.
62
‘Abdallāh Ansārī, Tabaqāt al-sūfiyya, ed. H.Āhī, Tehrān: Intishārāt-i Furūghī 1380 S.H., 137.
63
Al-Shaykh al-Akbar Muhyi al-Dīn Ibn al-‘Arabī, Istilāhāt al-sūfīyya, ed. A.S.Hamdān, Cairo: Maktabat
Madbūlī 1999, 9 and idem, al-Futūhāt al-makkiyya, Beirūt: Dār al-Sādir, non-dated, part 2, 538.

19
The oft-quoted definition of wujūd provided by Ibn al-‘Arabī’s foremost disciple and the most
remarkable systematizer and propagator of his teachings Sadr al-Dīn Qūnawī is the one given
in the Miftāh al-ghayb (“The Key of the Unseen”):
“Wujūd is one of the self-disclosures of the Unseen of the He-ness (ghayb al-huwiyya)64 and an
entification of one of its states, which is of the same kind as other essential states”.65
The passage, if considered outside its context, seems incompatible with Qūnawī’s own
assertion that “the Real is pure finding (read: self-awareness – J.E.) (al-haqq huwa al-wujūd
al-mahd)”66 , therefore I shall quote the paragraph in which it appears fully:
“The number of existents corresponds to the number of tenuities (raqā’īq) of names and
attributes, and their properties. And I told you what they are – so do remember! And every
relation is a property, and every property – a form, and every form – a specified locus of self-
disclosure of the all-comprehensive locus of self-disclosure, [comprising] [all] loci of self-
disclosure, whose source it is, and the disclosed one is the Real with its essential states, which
are distinguished from it (the Real – J.E.) by itself, and it is also the distinguisher of the afore-
mentioned universal loci of self-disclosure. And wujūd is one of the self-disclosures of the
Unseen of the He-ness, which is of the same kind as other essential states. And when their (self-
disclosures’ – J.E.) unification [that occurs] through the essential unity of gathering (ahadiyyat
al-jam‘) is considered, they are the Real; and when their multiplicity is taken into account, in
keeping with the property of distinction and manifestedness, the Real is they, and it is
manifested in respect of them and in accordance with them”.67
According to Qūnawī’s commentator Shams al-Dīn Ibn Hamza al-Fanārī (751/1350-1 –
834/1431), what is at issue here, is the relative existence (al-wujūd al-idāfī)68, that is, the
relation (idāfa) between a fixed entity and the unbounded finding/ existence (al-wujūd al-
mutlaq). However, what is not disclosed by any kind of disclosure – bound or unbound, is not
found, therefore, strictly speaking, it cannot be called wujūd. Hence, any kind of wujūd is a
sort of self-disclosure. This conclusion is supported by several passages in the Miftāh al-
ghayb, in which Qūnawī speaks of two kinds of unbounded wujūd:
“The unbounded wujūd has two respects, one of which consists in its being wujūd and nothing
else. And in this aspect [, in which “there is nothing like Him” (42:11),] it is the Real, which is
void of any manyness and compoundedness (tarkīb), attribute and quality (na‘t), name and trace
(rasm), relation (nisba) and property (hukm). On the contrary, it is pure wujūd, and we say: “It is
wujūd” [only] in order to make ourselves understood, not because wujūd is its true name.
Rather, its name is its very attribute, and its attribute is its very essence”.69
“... and [the second respect, in which “He is the Hearing, the Seeing” (42:11) is] when He
perceives or is witnessed, or addresses or is addressed, and [this happens] from behind the veil
of His inaccessible exaltation (‘izza) on the level of His Self [ – the veil,] which is known as
“the relation of His outward manifestedness (zāhiriyya)” and “the property of His manifestation
64
“He-ness”, now widely used in English translations of Arabic philosophical and mystical (Sufi) texts, is the
literal translation of huwiyya. Probably “haecceity” (‘this-ness’; ‘that in virtue of which an individual is the
individual that it is’ (Simon Blackburn, Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy, 159)), introduced into the
mediaeval philosophical Latin by Duns Scotus, would have been a more suitable rendering, if the American
philosopher of language David Kaplan had not recently attributed the latter term a new and completely
different meaning.
65
Sadr al-Dīn Qūnawī, Miftāh ghayb al-jam‘ wa ’l-wujūd, published in one volume with Shams al-Dīn Ibn
Hamza al-Fanārī, Misbāh al-uns bayna ’l-ma‘qūl wa ’l-mashhūd, ed. M.Khājavī, Tehrān: Intishārāt-i Mawlā
1374/1995, 125. The passage is quoted by Mullā Sadrā in: Sadrā, Asfār, part 2, 346.
66
Sadr al-Dīn al-Qūnawī, al-Nusūs miftāh mafātīh al-fusūs, quoted from: ‘Ali Ibn Ahmad Mahā’imī, Mashra‘
’l-khusūs ilā ma‘ānī al-nusūs, Qum: Markaz-i Intishārāt-i Daftar-i Tablīqāt-i Islāmī Hawze-i ‘Ilmī-i Qum
1379 S.H./1421 L.H., 255.
67
Qūnawī, Miftāh, 125.
68
See: Fanārī, Misbāh, 675.
69
Qūnawī, Miftāh, 22.

20
in the waystation (manzil) of “coming down” (tadallī)”, in the aspect of His undelimited
being’s/ finding’s joining the contingents, and His light’s dawning upon the entities of existents,
not otherwise. And when He flashes from this direction, His wujūd becomes entified, becoming
bound by the concomitant attributes of every entified thing... and this entification and
individualization is called “creation” (khalq) and “other [than God]”.70
The first kind of unbounded wujūd represents the state of undisclosedness and non-
entification. As a non-entified reality, it cannot be given any name and no attribute can be
ascribed to it, since names and attributes are nothing but entifications. Hence, wujūd is not its
true name. Rather, as the most common and most comprehensive of the Real’s names, i.e., as
the most universal of all entifications, it is used to point to what is not entified at all. In fact,
we have to deal here with a conventional misuse of the word.
In turn, in the second case the usage of the word wujūd appears to be fully justified, since it is
applied to the universal self-disclosure of the Real, which embraces the entire cosmos. This
universal self-disclosure is known among the Sufis by a number of names, such as “the breath
of the Compassionate” (nafas al-rahmān), “the existence/ finding dispersed over the
contingents” (wujūd munbasit ‘alā ’l-mumkināt), “the flow of finding/ existence” (sarayān al-
wujūd) and others.
A more careful reading of the writings of Qūnawī allows one to look at the issue from a
different perspective: namely, even in the first respect a certain kind of entification is present.
I mean here the Real’s oneness by reality, which consists in its conceiving of itself – the affair
which Qūnawī describes in his Nusūs (“Texts”) as the first entification.71 One’s conceiving of
oneself is self-awareness. Hence, the use of the word wujūd is most proper if it is understood
as the Real’s non-entified finding itself, i.e., its pure self-awareness.
In turn, the second aspect refers to the second entification of the Real, in which it manifests
itself as the origin (mabda`) of the world (cosmos).
“The originnatingness (mabda’iyya) of the Real (i.e., its being the originator of the World) is
(i.e., consists in its being – J.E.) the root of respects/ mental positions (i‘tibārāt) and the source
of relations and relationships manifest in the wujūd and non-manifest in the courtyard of
intellections and minds”.72
This second entification is called “the level of divinity” (martabat al-ulūhiyya) and “the
presence of oneness” (hadrat al-wahda).
The trend is followed by Qūnawī’s disciples, among them – by Sa‘īd al-Dīn al-Farghānī (d.
695/1296), best known for his Arabic and Persian commentaries on Ibn al-Fārid’s
(d.632/1235) Nazm al-sulūk (“Poem of the Wayfaring”), who interprets wujūd as finding in
several passages in his Muntahā al-madārik (“The Furthest Limit of Perceptions”).
He defines there the reality of wujūd in the following way:
“The reality of wujūd is that through which the entity finds itself in itself or in the other, or [that
through which it finds] the other in the other, [the “other” being] a locus (mahall), or a level
(martaba), or what is akin to them”.73
It is then explained that on the level of undifferentiated unity (ahadiyya) wujūd is “that
through which the Essence finds itself in itself in respect of [its] enwrapping (indimāj) in
itself the respects (i‘tibārāt) of oneness (wāhidiyya), [finding them] by undifferentiated

70
Qūnawī, Miftāh, 24–25.
71
See: Qūnawī, Nusūs, 132.
72
Qūnawī, Nusūs, p. 134.
73
Sa‘īd al-Dīn al-Farghānī, Muntahā al-madārik, Cairo: Maktab al-Sanā’ī’ 1876, quoted from Fanārī, Misbāh,
190.

21
finding, enwrapping differentiation – such finding which negates manyness, distinction and
otherness”.74
On the level of oneness or differentiated unity (wāhidiyya) wujūd can be considered in two
aspects:
“… one of them is the wujūd in the aspect of its being the locus of the self-disclosure of the
manifestation of the Real; and the second – the wujūd in the aspect of its being the locus of the
self-disclosure of the manifestation of the engendered existence (kawn)”.75
What is important about this definition (“that through which the entity finds itself”) is that it is
mostly based on the etymological implications of the word (“al-wujūd mā bihi wijdān”,
literally: “Wujūd is that through which finding takes place”). Wujūd is described here through
its effect/ trace (athar) and property (hukm) and, therefore, technically speaking, what we
have here is a tarsīm (description), not a ta‘rīf (definition proper).
In the cited passage wujūd is viewed as a tool of perception, a sort of ontological mirror,
necessary both for the Real and for the creation, in order to contemplate themselves and each
other. Its acting as a locus of self-disclosure (majla) does not contradict its being a self-
disclosure (tajallī): every self-disclosure can serve as a locus for other self-disclosures.
In practice, every mirror is either well-polished or rusty, convex or concave, wide or narrow
and so on. In theory, if considered as mirrors qua mirrors, they are identical and void of
accidents that distinguish them from each other. Similarly, wujūd, if considered regardless of
its entifications or lack thereof, is qualified as mutlaq (‘unbounded’). The unbounded being/
existence/ finding serves as a mirror for all entities.
In turn, all entities mirror the unbounded wujūd, but, due to their delimitations and difference
in their preparednesses (isti‘dādāt), the image which appears in these mirrors is always bound
and delimited, i.e., in this case mirrors impose their limitations upon the unbounded and
delimit it. The only exception is the entity of the Perfect Man (or: Fully Human Being) (al-
insān al-kāmil), which represents the isthmus (barzakh) between the unbounded and the
bound.
Yet another definition of wujūd is hidden deep in the text of the Mashāriq al-darārī (“The
Rising Places of the Pearls”) (Farghānī’s Persian commentary on Ibn al-Fārid’s Nazm al-
Sulūk). It explicitly deals with the ‘irfānī understanding of wujūd as finding:
“...as a [special] term of this tribe (i.e., the Sufis – J.E.), wajd (‘finding in ecstasy’) means
finding (read: satisfaction – J.E.) of the demand of this relative finding/ existence (wujūd mudāf)
for the presence of its unboundedness (itlāq), [which is achieved] by means of annihilation
(fanā’) and obliteration (mahw) of the manyness of descriptions (awsāf) and properties of
delimitation and distinction, and finding (i.e., satisfaction – J.E.) of the demand [to actualize]
the relation of disengagement (nisba mujarrad) and [to avoid] the delimitation of the property
of manyness of levels, which hitherto was prevailing over its oneness. When this finding (i.e.,
satisfaction of the demand – J.E.) becomes a habitude (malaka), it is called wujūd”.76
The definition occurs amidst a passage, in which the effects of samā‘ (‘listening’) are
discussed. In a nutshell, the meaning of the citation comes down to the well-known Sufi
axiom: “To make the Real one means to omit the ascriptions” (al-tawhīd isqāt al-idāfāt), i.e.,
in order to witness the Real as non-entified unbounded finding/ being, one needs to learn to

74
Fanārī, Misbāh, 191.
75
Fanārī, Misbāh, 191.
76
Sa‘īd al-Dīn Farghānī, Mashāriq al-darārī, ed. S.J.Āshtiyānī, 2nd edition, Qum: Markaz-i Intishārāt-i Daftar-i
Tablīqāt-i Islāmī Hawze-i ‘Ilmī-i Qum 1379/2000, 482.

22
omit the relations, relating it to the loci of manifestation (mazāhir). When this ability becomes
a habitude (malaka), it is called wujūd.
Hence, in the writings of Farghānī, wujūd can mean both finding/ existence in general sense
and a habitude of finding of the unbounded being/ existence, possessed by the bound and
delimited one (which results in the annihilation (fanā’) of the latter in the former).
‘Abd al-Razzāq al-Kāshānī (d.730/1330) discusses the concept of wujūd in two separate
entries of his Istilāhat al-sūfiyya (“Glossary of Sufi Terms”). In the first one, which deals
specifically with wujūd in the presence of bringing together (hadrat al-jam‘), he actually
repeats Farghānī`s definition:
“The wujūd is the Real’s finding its essence through its essence (and for this reason the presence
of bringing together (jam‘) (itself defined as “witnessing the Real without [witnessing] the
creation”77 – J.E.) is called “the presence of finding (wujūd)”)”. 78
In the second entry, in which he treats wujūd as one of the ten limits (nihāyāt) of the Sufi
path, Kāshānī first gives the general definition of wujūd (which significantly differs from that
presented in the first entry):
“Wujūd – and it is taken from His word “He finds (wajada) God [ever] with him” (24:39)79 and
from His word: “They would have find God provoking repentance (tawwāb), compassionate
(rahīm)” (4:64)80 – means ‘perception of the reality of the thing’, and it is the most sublime of
the levels of witnessing (shuhūd) (“seeing the Real through the Real”81) – I mean the finding
(wujūd) of the station, in which the trace of finding disappears completely due to obtaining the
One in the entity of preeternity, and what is intended is the Real’s finding its entity through its
entity, without trace and name”.82 (After that Kāshānī defines wujūd in respect to different
stages of Sufi path.)
In this latter definition, two things appear of particular importance. First, defining wujūd as
perception of the reality of the thing (which represents a slightly altered and more
philosophical version of Ansārī’s definition (“obtaining the reality of the thing”83)). Every act
of perception, thus, comes down to the Real’s perceiving (finding) itself. Second, qualifying it
as the most sublime (arfa) of the levels of witnessing (shuhūd). (It should be noted that, in his
Futūhāt al-makkiyya (“The Meccan Openings”), Ibn al-‘Arabī explains that “witnessing is
preceeded by knowledge of the witnessed – the knowledge, which is called “beliefs” (‘aqā’id),
wherefore confirmation and negation occur in witnessing”84.) Actually, the quoted passage
comprises two definitions, the former of which (“perception of the reality of the thing”) relates to
the latter (“the Real’s finding its entity through its entity”) as a universal to its particular. In all
likelihood, the second definition refers to the essential self-disclosure (tajallī dhātī) which is
possessed by the Real (and, as some argue, the accomplished mystics) only.
One notices that in both entries on wujūd found in his Istilāhat Kāshānī bases his definitions
on those of earlier Sufi masters (in the first entry – on that of Ibn al-‘Arabī; in the second – on
the one provided by Ansārī), but makes them more philosophical (at least – in terms of style
and expression), which might indicate that, a few generations after Ibn al-‘Arabī, the intensity
of ‘irfān as living mystical experience had decreased amidst his followers.

77
‘Abd al-Razzāq al-Kāshānī, Istilāhat al-sūfiyya, ed. M.Hādīzāde, Tehrān: Intishārāt-i Hikmat 1381 S.H., 22.
78
Kāshānī, Istilāhāt, 28.
79
Qur’ān, 291.
80
Qur’ān, 68.
81
Kāshānī, Istilāhāt, 124.
82
Kāshānī, Istilāhāt, 251.
83
Ansārī, Manāzil, 138.
84
Ibn al-‘Arabī, Futūhāt, part 2, 138.

23
The case of Dāwūd al-Qaysarī seems to support strongly the above guess: his treatises and, in
particular, the introduction of his commentary on Ibn al-‘Arabī’s Fusūs al-hikam (“Bezels of
Wisdom”) exemplify a kind of lucid and well-presented, but significantly simplified discourse
of the issues his predecessors dealt with on a more advanced level. Simultaneously, the
abundance of philosophical terms indicates that the audience his writings were aimed at had
quite sufficient acquaintance with the doctrines of Avicennan philosophy and Kalām. Hence,
the works of Qaysarī can probably be qualified as “secondary school textbooks” of Sufi
mysticism for non-Sufi intellectuals (while Ibn al-‘Arabī`s Fusūs and Qūnawī`s Miftāh were
definitely meant for doctoral students).
Importantly, Qaysarī was the first representative of Ibn al-‘Arabī school, who spoke of the
impossibility to define wujūd.85 What he had in mind was, of course, a verbal definition (ta`rīf
lafzī) (which, in fact, is a definition made by substitution of terms, i.e., the replacement of a
less-known term with a better-known one).86 Since, in terms of its ipseity (inniyya), wujūd is
the most evident of things, argued Qaysarī, it is impossible to define it, because there is
nothing better known and more evident than it. At the same time, he admitted that, in terms of
its reality (haqīqa), wujūd is the most obscure and the least known of things. Apparently, like
Qūnawī, Qaysarī meant that “the reality of the Real consists of the form of its knowledge of
itself, in the aspect of its entification in its [mental] conceiving of itself, in respect of the
oneness of knowledge, the knower and the known87, i.e., the form in which the Real discloses
itself to itself in the first self-disclosure, namely, that of the essence. Hence, the wujūd that is
dispersed over the contingents, i.e., entities and relations, which become manifest in the
second self-disclosure, is the shadow of the reality of wujūd. Naturally, the reality of the
possessor of a shadow cannot be perceived as it is by means of witnessing the shadow. (One
will notice that, while Qūnawī’s otherwise excellent discourse at times appear exceedingly
terse, Qaysarī’s explanations are often simply inadequate.)
Outwardly, this was exactly Qaysarī’s position on the point that was taken by Mullā Sadrā
and the representatives of his school, up to the late Sayyed Jalāl al-Dīn Āshtiyānī (at least in
the early stages of his career) and Jawād Āmulī. They hold that the ipseity of wujūd is the
most evident of all things, while its reality or quiddity (māhiya) – the most hidden and
obscure one. Hence, it is impossible to define wujūd. In his Mashā’ir (“Penetrations”) Sadrā
writes:
“The ipseity of wujūd is the most evident of things in terms of presence and unveiling, and its
quiddity is the most hidden in terms of conceptualization and penetration to its inner core”.88
However, Qaysarī, despite his philosophical inclination and the abundance of philosophical
terms in his discourse, remains on the mystical track. For him wujūd means, first of all,
finding and awareness (which on the outer cosmic level discloses itself as outer existence and
on the inner mental level manifests itself as mental existence). This can be well illustrated by
his interpretation of the issue of Rising (qiyāma). Following Ibn al-‘Arabī, Qaysarī speaks of
two kinds of Rising – the greater and the lesser one. He describes the first one as wujūd’s
making the things non-existent while manifesting itself in its oneness89 – in other words, as
disappearance of the subsequent entifications and return to the first entification (that of the
85
Sajjad H. Rizvi believes this to be an evidence that “the language of wujūd in this school (i.e., that of Ibn al-
‘Arabī – J.E.) undergoes a transformation through the encounter with philosophy”.
86
See: Dāwūd al-Qaysarī, Matla‘ khusūs al-kalam fī ma‘ānī fusūs al-hikam, Qum: Mu’assasa muhibbīn li-
tibā‘a wa ’l-nashr 1423 L.H., part 1, 17.
87
Qūnawī, Nusūs, 209.
88
Molla Sadra Shirazi, Le Livre des penetrations metaphysiques (Kitāb al-Mashā‘ir), ed. H.Corbin, 2nd edition,
Tehrān: Editions Tahuri 1982, 6 (Arabic text).
89
See: Qaysarī, Matla‘, part 1, 18.

24
Real’s knowledge of itself in respect of its non-differentiaton and the oneness of the
knowledge, the known and the knower), i.e., to the level of pure and undifferentiated finding/
(self-)awareness. (hence, the Greater Rising (al-qiyāma al-kubra) is just another name for the
essential self-disclosure (al-tajallī al-dhātī) of the Real.)
In turn, the Lesser Rising (al-qiyāma al-sughra) is described by Qaysarī as “[wujūd’s] self-
transmutation (tahawwul) from the world of the Witnessed into the world of the Unseen or
from one form into another one in the same world”.90 That is, in case of the Lesser Rising,
one entification of wujūd is replaced with another, which may belong either to the same
presence or to a different one.
Since Qaysarī’s simplified discourse of the key issues of Sufi mysticism abounds with
philosophical terms and expressions (while his treatment of ontological, cosmological and
eschatological matters remains mystical by its nature and essential characteristics), it was
prone to be mistreated as a kind of “Sufi philosophy” by the (relatively narrow but influential)
circle of philosophically educated non-Sufi intellectuals. I call it “mistreatment” because Sufi
mystics (including Qaysarī) and philosophers (I mean the representatives of Avicennan and
Suhravardian, i.e., Peripatetic and Illuminationist, traditions) used a good number of common
terms, but each of the groups (mystics and philosophers) employed them in a different sense.
In the given case, wujūd appears to be a particularly illustrative example of such
mistreatment.91.

1.1.2. Wahdat al-Wujūd in Sufi Mysticism

It seems that Chittick’s insightful, meticulous and exhaustive articles92, in which he examines
the history of the appearance of the expression wahdat al-wujūd and the reasons and modes of
its attribution to the teachings of Ibn al-‘Arabī and his school, have made, for the time being
at least, any further discussion of the topic unnecessary. However, in order to provide the
reader with sufficient information about the ‘irfānī context, in which I intend to consider
Sadrā’s teachings on wujūd, I shall have to discuss the subject briefly.
Although for several centuries Ibn al-‘Arabī and his school have been known as the professors
of the doctrine of wahdat al-wujūd, the Greatest Shaykh himself used the exact expression in
his writings very infrequently (as far as I know, only once).93 If it is understood in the sense of

90
Qaysarī, Matla‘, part 1, 18.
91
Dāwūd Qaysarī (who died in 751/1350) is the last major Sufi theorist mentioned in Sadrā’s works (thus, in
the Asfār Qaysarī’s name appears at least fourteen times). The names of such major 15th century figures –
representatives of Ibn al-‘Arabī school – as Shams al-Dīn Ibn Hamza al-Fanārī and ‘Abd al-Rahmān al-Jāmī,
to my knowledge, are never mentioned by Sadrā, therefore I refrain here from discussing their position on
wujūd. (Besides, their main books on theoretical mysticism (‘irfān nazarī) – Fanārī’s Misbāh al-uns (“The
Lamp of Intimacy”) (a commentary on Qūnawī`s Miftāh) and Jāmī’s Sharh Fusūs al-hikam (“The
Commentary on the Bezels of Wisdom”) and Naqd al-nusūs (“The Critique of the Texts”) (a commentary on
Ibn al-‘Arabī’s Naqsh al-fusūs (“The Imprint of the Bezels”)) represent rather skillful compilations of
quotations from the works of earlier Sufi authors (in particular, Qūnawī, who was the favourite of both) than
original works.
92
His most important and detailed article on wahdat al-wujūd is: W.C.Chittick, “Rūmī and wahdat al-wujūd”,
in Poetry and mysticism in Islam: the heritage of Rumi, eds. A.Banani, R.Hovannisian and G.Sabagh,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1994, 70–111. See also: Chittick, “Wahdat al-Shuhūd” (VIII.37) in
Encyclopaedia of Islam, 2nd edition (CD-ROM), Leiden: 1999, and: Chittick, Wahdat al-Wujūd in India.
93
The expression appears in the Awrād al-usbū‘ (“Prayers of the Week”), in the Wird Laylat al-jum‘a (Friday
night prayer), where Ibn al-‘Arabī addresses God in the following words: “I ask Thee by the mystery (sirr) –
the one through which Thou bringst together the opposites – to bring together my dispersed affair
(mutafarraq amrī) into gathering (jam‘) that makes me witness the unity of Thy Being (or: oneness of Thy

25
the Real’s finding itself and its awareness of itself as the only “found” or “existent” one – or
rather as the finder, the found and the finding – the expression describes an important part of
Ibn al-‘Arabī`s teaching on wujūd – but not the whole of it. This becomes evident from such
Ibn al-‘Arabī’s statements as the following ones:
“The Real is the entity of the wujūd (‘finding/ being found/ non-differentiated self-awareness’),
not anything else, and [what is known as] the attribution of the wujūd to the contingents is
[nothing else but] the Real’s manifestation to itself through their (i.e., the contingents’ – J.E.)
entities”.94
“There is nothing in the wujūd except God, and although the wujūd is one entity, it is multiplied
by the entities of the contingents, and, hence, it is one-and-many (al-wāhid al-kathīr)”.95
“The wujūd is the wujūd of the Real, and the property (hukm) is the property of the contingent,
together with its (the contingent’s – J.E.) fixedness in its privation (‘adam) [of finding and being
found]”.96
“The entity of wujūd is one, and the properties are different due to the difference between the
fixed entities”.97
Even without a detailed analysis of the four above quotations, it is evident that wahdat al-
wujūd (if understood as oneness of finding-and-being found or as unity of the universal self-
awareness) is always, except in the first (essential) self-disclosure of the Real, accompanied by
kathrat al-a‘yān (‘manyness of the entities’). The latter, while remaining themselves forever not
found and not finding, produce the manyness of the properties (kathrat al-ahkām), thus creating
an illusion of the multiplicity of wujūd(s). Moreover, in actual fact, what we witness is nothing
else but the Real’s manifestation to itself in different ways through its own infinite respects
(i‘tibārāt) or “tasks” (shu’ūn), i.e., relations (nisab) between its different names.
This principle (“oneness of wujūd and manyness of entities/ properties”) is expressed in
different ways by Qūnawī and Farghānī. Thus, Qūnawī writes in his I‘jāz al-bayān
(“Inimitability of Explication”):
“Know that distinction (tamyīz) pertains to knowledge (‘ilm), while unification (tawhīd) pertains
to wujūd”.98
In turn, Farghānī interprets wahdat al-wujūd and kathrat al-‘ilm as two subsequent stages of
the gnostic path, the apparent contradiction between which is removed and harmony is
established upon reaching the highest stage – the oneness of bringing together (ahadiyyat al-
jam‘) (pertaining to the Perfect Man solely).99

Existence) (wahdat wujūdika)” (Muhyi al-Dīn Ibn al-‘Arabī, Al-Tarīq ilā Allāh: al-shaykh wa ’l-murīd, ed.
Mahmūd Al-Ghurāb, Damascus: Dār al-Īmān 1991, 188 (cf. Gloton’s French translation in: Gloton,
“Introduction” in Ibn ‘Arabī, La production des circles, XXIII). As Mohsen Jahangirī points out, in the
Futūhāt at least two times Ibn al-‘Arabī employs expressions that are very close to wahdat al-wujūd: 1) “Fa
athbata ’l-kathra fī ’l-thubūt wa anfahā min al-wujūd; fa thabata ’l-wahda fī ’l-wujūd wa anfahā min al-
thubūt” (Ibn al-‘Arabī, Futūhāt, part 2, 502; cf. Mohsen Jahāngirī, Muhyi al-Dīn Ibn ‘Arabī: chehra-i
barjasta ‘irfān-i islāmī, 5th edition, Tehrān: Intishārāt-i Dāneshghah-i Tehrān 1383 S.H., 263); 2) “Fa ’l-
wahda fī ’l-ījād wa ’l-wujūd wa ’l-mawjūd lā yu‘qal wa lā yunqal illā fī lā ilahu illā huwa, fa hadhihi
ahadiyyat al-martaba wa hiya ahadiyyat al-kathra” (Ibn al-‘Arabī, Futūhāt, part 1, 715; cf. Jahāngirī, Ibn
‘Arabī, 263).
94
Ibn al-‘Arabī, Futūhāt, part 1, 328.
95
Ibn al-‘Arabī, Futūhāt, part 3, 276.
96
Ibn al-‘Arabī, Futūhāt, part 3, 566.
97
Ibn al-‘Arabī, Futūhāt, part 2, 519.
98
Sadr al-Dīn Qūnawī, I‘jāz al-bayān fī tafsīr Umm al-Qur’ān, esd. S.J.Āshtiyānī, Qum: Bustān-i Kitāb 1381
S.H., 291. Cf. Chittick’s English translation in: Chittick, “Rumi”, 107, note 39.
99
See: Farghānī, Mashāriq, 511. Cf. Chittick, “Rumi”, 80–81.

26
The manyness of knowledge is necessitated by manyness of the known entities (ma‘lūmāt),
while the oneness of wujūd (read: finding) results from the oneness of the found (mawjūd).
Apparently, we are doing here with two different kinds of awareness: the discriminating (i.e.,
knowledge (‘ilm)) and the non-discriminating (i.e., finding (wujūd)) (or, if you like,
conceptual (tasawwurī) and assertive (tasdīqī)) awareness). A peculiar characteristic of the
non-discriminating awareness is its indivisibility and the indefinability of its object – which
means that the object of this kind of awareness is forever one and no statements regarding the
nature of this object are ever made. (Note that in his definition of wujūd (“wujūd is finding the
Real in ecstasy”), given in a number of places100, Ibn al-‘Arabī limits the object of wujūd to
the Real, while Kāshānī is careful to point out that, in the last analysis, “every sort of wujūd
(finding) comes down to the Real’s finding its entity”101 (hence, the subject and the object of
wujūd is one – or, rather, the finder, the found and the finding is one and the same. Although
at times we fancy that we are finding the Real, the actual Finder is the Real who finds itself
through our entities (which, in turn, represent nothing else but the conceptual final result of
the “marriages” (i.e., interrelationships) between the Real’s different names)102 ).)
To sum up, the notion of wahdat al-wujūd (if understood as “oneness of finding”) certainly is
an important element of Ibn al-‘Arabī’s vision of the actual state of affairs. However, it is
definitely insufficient and one-sided if considered separately from kathrat al-a‘yān
(‘manyness of entities’) (the latter, in turn, necessitating manyness of knowledge). Moreover,
for Ibn al-‘Arabī and his closest followers, the aforementioned dichotomy is far too evident
and unquestionable to become an apt designation for their teachings. (Imagine a group of
people, describing themselves as the “professors of the brightness of daylight and the
tenebrity of the darkness of night”!)
As Chittick has explicitly shown, the label of the “professors of wahdat al-wujūd” stuck to
Ibn al-‘Arabī and his followers mainly owing to the efforts of the Hanbalite jurist Ibn
Taymiyya (d. 728/1328), who used the expression wahdat al-wujūd in the titles of two of his
polemical treatises – Ibtāl wahdat al-wujūd (“Showing the Falsity of Wahdat al-Wujūd”)103
and Risāla ilā man sa’ālaha ‘an haqīqat madhhab al-ittihādiyyūn ay al-qā’ilīn bi wahdat al-
wujūd (“A Treatise written to the one who asked me about the reality of the position of
Unificationists, that is, those who support Wahdat al-Wujūd”).104 Ibn Taymiyya dubbs Ibn al-
‘Arabī and his school as the professors of unification (ittihād) of God and creation and
incarnation (hulūl) of God in creation. In addition, he accuses them of supporting the idea of
(God’s) ineffectuality (ta‘tīl) (i.e., admitting the possibility of God’s leaving aside the
governing of his creation).

100
Ibn al-‘Arabī, Istilāhāt, 9; idem., Futūhāt, part 2, 538.
101
Kāshānī, Istilāhāt, 351.
102
Cf. the following lines from the Dīvān of Shams Tabrīzī:
O thou whose flute is all creation, [the flute], [which is] filled with thy tune!
If thou art not keen on listening (samā’), don’t touch the flute of the soul.
Thou breathed the breath of “I breathed”, thou blew in everything.
Since thy breath is the soul of the read, don’t wail without our read.
(Jalāl al-Dīn Rūmī, Guzide-i ghazaliyyat-i Mawlawī, ed. S.Shamisa, 5th edition, Tehrān: Mahārat Publishers
1375 S.H., 114.)
103
Ibn Taymiyya, Majmū‘āt al-rasā’īl wa ’l-masā’īl, ed. M.R.Ridā (n.p., n.d.), part 1, 61–120.
104
Ibn Taymiyya, Majmū‘a, part 4, 2–101.

27
“As for the faith in God”, – writes Ibn Taymiyya about Ibn al-‘Arabī and his followers, – “they
think that His wujūd is identical with the wujūd of the cosmos and that the cosmos has no other
maker than the cosmos itself”.105
(To what one can object that, according to Ibn al-‘Arabī, the cosmos does not have wujūd,
since wujūd is only possessed by the Real and that a non-existent (not found) thing cannot
have a maker of any sort.)
As Chittick points out, “Ibn Taymiyya considered wahdat al-wujūd synonymous with atheism
(i.e., ineffectuality (ta‘tīl) – J.E.) and unbelief, since he saw it as a denial of the distinction
between God and the cosmos”.106
In a nutshell, penetration to the core of the subtle and sophisticated (and at times shocking for
an ordinary experience and common sense) teachings of Ibn al-‘Arabī was well beyond the
scope and capacity of Ibn Taymiyya (and also many of the alleged supporters of the ideas of
the Greatest Shaykh), so he did what most of us would have done with a dangerous
troublemaker: dismissed his claims (to the extent he was able to understand them) and
branded him as a “spiritual criminal” (i.e., heretic). The label stuck well.

1.1.3. Entification and Entity

Two important concepts, which need to be explained in order to understand Sufi mysticism’s
vision of the structure of reality, are “entification” (ta‘ayyun) and “entity” (‘ayn). The literal
meaning of the Arabic word ta‘ayyun is “self-distinction”, while ‘ayn, in its broader sense,
refers to everything that is somehow distinguished. As a technical term, ta‘ayyun is used to
describe the actualization of the latent possibilities of self-distinction inherent within the non-
delimited wujūd, while ‘ayn is employed to refer to any particular possibility of self-
distinction. 107
Conventionally, we speak about two kinds of entities – the “fixed” (thābita) and the “found”
(or “existent”) (mawjūda) ones, the first group representing non-actualized possibilities,
“fixed” in the Real’s knowledge, and the second – actualized possibilities, “found” by the
Real and by ourselves. However, in reality the fixed realities never become “found” and
existent, but remain not found (ma‘dūm) forever. What appears in wujūd and is found, is their
properties (ahkām), effects (āthār) and traces (rusūm), which bind and delimit the unbounded
wujūd. As Ibn al-‘Arabī points out, “the entities, which are fixed in privation (‘adam) (i.e.,
non-existence – J.E.), have never felt the scent of the “found” (mawjūd)108 – i.e., have no
notion of it and have never experienced (“tasted”) it.
It should be mentioned here that, historically, Ibn al-‘Arabī was not the first Islamic thinker
who used the term “fixed entities” (a‘yān thābita): although the exact inventor of the term is
not known, it seems certain that it first came up in the discussions on the nature of creation,
which took place in the Mu‘tazilite circles. Generally, the Mu‘tazilites interpreted creation as
God’s giving existence to non-existent entities (ma‘dūmāt). Each of the latter was supposed to
be somehow distinguished from the rest – hence, they were called a‘yān as well. While they

105
Ibn Taymiyya, Majmū‘a, part 4, p. 73, quoted from: Chittick, “Rumi”, 85.
106
Chittick, “Rumi”, 86.
107
Cf. Chittick’s definition in: W.C.Chittick, “Sadr al-Dīn Qūnawī on Oneness of Being” in The International
Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 21, 1981, 183.
108
Muhyi al-Dīn Ibn al-‘Arabī, Fusūs al-hikam, ed. A. ‘Afīfī, 2nd edition, Tehrān: Intishārāt-i al-Zahrā 1370
S.H., part 1, 76. Cf. C. Dagli’s translation in: Muhyi al-Dīn Ibn al-‘Arabī, The Ringstones of Wisdom,
translated by Caner K. Dagli, Chicago: Kazi Publications 2004, 101.

28
could not be found and tasted, they were believed to possess a certain kind of existence (say,
that of logical possibility), which was described as “fixedness in privation (thubūt fī ’l-
‘adam)”.)
If so, there is only one entity that is “found” (mawjūd) in the true sense of the word – the
entity of wujūd (which takes us back to the previously discussed issue of wahdat al-wujūd).
According to Ibn al-‘Arabī and his followers, the creation and structure of the cosmos cannot
be properly understood unless it is viewed as a gradual entification (=self-distinction) of
wujūd or the Real. Apart from his magnum opus, Ibn al-‘Arabī deals in detail with the
entification (although not employing the term ta‘ayyun itself) of the Real in such treatises as
the Inshā’ al-dawā’ir al-ihātiyya ‘alā ’l-mudāhāt al-insān li ’l-khāliq wa ’l-makhlūq
(“Drawing the Circles which encompass the Correspondence of Human Being to the Creator
and the Creation”) and the ‘Aqlat al-mustawfiz (“The Fetters of the One Ready to Jump Up”).
However, since the writings of Qūnawī provide a more succinct and systematic discourse of
the issue, it is more convenient to examine a few passages from them, in particular, from his
Nass al-nusūs (“The Text of the Texts”), in order to get an overall picture of Ibn al-‘Arabī and
Qūnawī`s treatment of the subject.
Generally, Qūnawī speaks about two entifications of the Real, the first of which is often
referred to as the “true oneness” (or the “oneness of reality”) (al-wahda al-haqīqiyya) and the
second – as the “originatingness (i.e., the capacity of being the origin of things) of the Real”
(mabda’iyyat al-haqq).109 All subsequent stages of the Real’s entification are treated as
concomitants (lawāzim) of the Real’s knowledge of Himself (which, in turn, is itself a
concomitant (lāzim) of the first entification).
““The Unseen of the He-ness of the Real” (ghayb al-huwwiyyat al-haqq) is an allusion to the
Real’s unboundedness (itlāq) in the respect of non-entification. The true oneness of the Real,
obliterating all respects, and names, and relations, and relationships, consists in its intellection
of itself and perception of itself in the aspect of its entification. Although this intellection and
entificational (ta‘ayyunī) perception adjoins the aforementioned unboundedness [but is not the
unboundedness itself], in relation to the Real’s entification in the intellection of every intellecter
(muta‘aqqil), in every self-disclosure, it represents itself as an unbounded entification, which is
the broadest of all entifications, and the witnessing of the perfect ones, and it is the essential
self-disclosure which possesses the highest station of unification (tawhīd)”.110
Nothing can be said about the non-entified Unseen of the He-ness – which, likewise, cannot
be denominated by any name (not even by the name “the Real” (al-haqq) or “the Essence”
(al-dhāt)). What is conventionally named “the Essence” represents the true oneness, in which
no trace of manyness is perceived. The crucial point of the passage is the assertion that this
true oneness consists in the Real’s intellection of itself and its perception of itself in the aspect
of its (the Real’s) entification – which indicates that, by perceiving itself, the Real entifies
itself to itself, or rather that its very self-intellection (in which the intellecter, the intellected
and the intellection remain undifferentiated in any way) is, in a certain aspect, identical with
its self-distinction (=entification). (Hence, what is conventionally referred to as the “existence
of the cosmos” (wujūd al-‘ālam), is nothing but the Real’s multi-modal perception of itself.)
The second part of the quotation deals with the essential self-disclosure of the Real, i.e., the
Real’s disclosure through itself to itself – the disclosure, in which it discloses itself only to
itself and to the perfect ones (the poles and the solitaries).

109
See, for example: Qūnawī, Nusūs, 132–135.
110
Qūnawī, Nusūs, 132.

29
As Qūnawī’s commentator ‘Ali Ibn Ahmad al-Mahā’imī (776/1375-835/1432) points out,
since relations depend on entifications, and these relations rank in grades, the gradation of
entifications is also inevitable.111 Namely, the Real first perceives (becomes aware of) itself as
itself. Then it perceives its characteristics (such as oneness, necessity etc.). The perception of
these characteristics can only occur through/ due to the Real’s knowledge of itself: one must
first know/ establish the essence in order to ascribe to (or negate) it certain characteristics.
What we call “the essence” (al-dhāt) is, in fact, nothing else but the first entification of the
Real.
“The application of the name “essence” to the Real is not correct except in respect of its
entification ... [that] which is the first entification. And it (i.e., the first entification – J.E.)
encompasses the essential names – those which are “the keys of the Unseen” – through its
essence. And what is named “the essence”, does not differ from its names in any aspect, but, as
for the names, some of them differ from the others and oppose them, and some of them unite
with the others in the aspect of the essence’s encompassion of their entirety”.112
The first entification is often referred to as “undifferentiated oneness” (ahadiyya), because it
contains all attributes and perfections of the Real in a undifferentiated state. Since at this level
the essence is not distinguished from its names in any way, it is impossible to conceive of the
Real as the origin (mabda’) and the originator (mubdi’): nothing is originated yet. More
importantly, there is only one entity (conventionally referred to as “the essence”) entified in
the first entification. There is a group of people among mystics, known as the “folk of
bringing together and finding” (ahl al-jam‘ wa ’l-wujūd) or the “folk of one entity” (ahl al-
‘ayn al-wāhida)113, who deny the existence of manyness of any kind, thus also denying the
multiplicity of entities. They can also be regarded as the realizers of the first entification (i.e.,
the witnessers of the Real’s essential self-disclosure), with an important notice that the first
entification encompasses all subsequent entifications which occasion the manyness of entities.
While the manyness of entities is latent and not actualized in the first entification, it is not
dismissed as a possibility.
How is manyness brought into existence? This happens by means of knowledge, which is the
only intellected concomitant of the essence.
“And the essence has only one concomitant, not more, which differs from it only by relative
difference, and that concomitant is knowledge”.114
“And it (knowledge of itself – J.E.) is the mirror of the essence in the aspect of its (the essence’s
– J.E.) encompassing the essential names [ – the names] which do not differ from the essence in
any respect... and it, that is knowledge, is the root of the manyness of meanings and its source,
and I have said that knowledge is like a mirror of the known [entities], and also [like] that (i.e.,
the mirror – J.E.) of the essence [considered] together with its essential names, because in the
aspect of knowledge’s distinction from the essence, which is a mentally posited (i‘tibārī)
distinction, the entification of the Real in the Real’s intellection of itself through itself is
intellected [accidentally], and its essential knowledge [acts] like its mirror”.115
As Mahā’imī explains, since knowledge is the locus of impression of everything and
entification is impossible before impression (irtisām), that is through knowledge and in

111
See: Mahā’imī, Mashra‘, 101.
112
Qūnawī, Nusūs, 217–218.
113
See: Ibn al-‘Arabī, Futūhāt, part 3, 447, lines 15–17 and: W. Chittick, The Self-Disclosure of God : Principles
of Ibn al-‘Arabī’s Cosmology. New York: SUNY Press 1997, 183–184.
114
Qūnawī, Nusūs, 220.
115
Qūnawī, Nusūs, 221.

30
knowledge that the level of divinity or differentiated oneness (wāhidiyya) and other universal
levels and particular entities become entified.116
In other words, entification is a (ruling) property (hukm). In order to ascribe it to the object,
we must know the object first. Hence, knowledge is like the occasion (sabab) (i.e., the
immediate cause) of entification.
“And [differentiated] oneness is affirmed for the Real in the aspect of knowledge, and in it
(knowledge – J.E.) and through it the level of divinity (ulūhiyya) and other levels and known
entities (ma‘lūmāt) become entified due to the impression of the entirety in it”.117
“The Real’s being the origin (mabda’iyya) consists in its being the root of respects and the
source of relations and relationships, manifest in the wujūd and non-manifest in the courtyard of
intellections and minds. And what is described as the unbounded, one and necessary wujūd
(read: finding – J.E.), consists in the wujūd’s (finding’s – J.E.) entification in its divine essential
relation to knowledge, and in the aspect of this relation – and not in any other one – the realizer
calls the Real the “origin””.118
After the Real has become aware of itself as itself, in the respect of its knowledge, it becomes
aware of itself as the Necessary One Unbounded Wujūd (Finding). In the aspect of this
differentiated awareness, it is called by the realizers (i.e., the mystics who have succeeded in
establishing the true state of the affair (nafs al-amr)) the “Origin”.
The second entification is also known as “the level of differentiated oneness” (martabat al-
wāhidiyya) and “the level of divinity” (martabat al-ulūhiyya). “Differentiated oneness”
(wāhidiyya) refers to the essence in respect of its being the root and source of the divine
names and to their (names’) oneness in respect of the essence and manyness in respect of the
attributes.119 The difference between undifferentiated oneness (ahadiyya) and differentiated
one lies in the fact that on the level of differentiated oneness the distinction of the essence
from its (essential) names is intellected through their (names’) manifestation in it (the
essence) in actuality, while this is not the case on the level of undifferentiated oneness.120
Regarding the term “divinity” (ulūhiyya), it should be kept in mind that, what it refers to, is
nothing but a certain level of the Real’s entification – namely, the level on which the Real
appears as “God” (ilāh). Ibn al-‘Arabī and his followers hold that it is impossible to speak of
“God” without an object in respect to which He manifests Himself as God – i.e., without “that
which is godded over” (ma’lūh – the word is a participle, derived from the same root as ilāh).
Ma’lūh is more or less synonymous with marbūb (‘vassal’) (the one in respect to whom the
Lord (rabb) exercises his lordship (rubūbiyya)).121
Depending on whether the first and the second entifications are considered as two different
levels of manifestation of the single entity of wujūd or regarded as one level (which is
possible due to their sharing the absence of every engendered thing, in respect to them (i.e.,
the first and the second entifications), from itself and from its likeness)122, the mystics of Ibn
al-‘Arabī school speak about six or five universal “presences” (hadarāt) or “levels” (marātib)
(the “level” (martaba), according to Qūnawī, consists of “the reality of every thing not in the
aspect of its disengagement, but in the aspect of the intellection of relation that brings together
116
See: Mahā’imī, Mashra‘ , 221.
117
Qūnawī, Nusūs, 220.
118
Qūnawī, Nusūs, 134.
119
See: Kāshānī, Istilāhāt, 27.
120
See: Mahā’imī, Mashra‘ , 229.
121
See: W.Chittick, Self-disclosure, 59–61.
122
See: ‘A.Jāmī, Naqd al-nusūs fī sharh Naqsh al-fusūs, ed. W.Chittick, 2nd edition, Tehrān: Mu’assisa-i
pazhūhishī hikmat wa falsafa-i Īrān 1381, 31.

31
1) the reality of the thing [itself] and 2) the wujūd which makes manifest it and the realities
which accompany it”123).
According to Qūnawī, there are five universal levels or presences of the entification of
unbounded wujūd (also named the “breath of the Compassionate” and the “self-disclosure that
flows everywhere”):
1) the luminous unseen presence of knowledge, which encompasses every manifest thing
(al-hadra al-ghaybiyya al-‘ilmiyya al-nūriyya al-muhīta bi kull mā zahara) (to which
pertain disengaged meanings and knowledgeable relations and names);
2) opposite this presence lies the presence of manifestation (zuhūr) and the witnessed
[domain] (shahāda), to which pertain the manifest [part] of the engendered existence;
3) between these two presences is situated the presence of bringing together and finding
(al-jam‘ wa ’l-wujūd) and hiding and displaying (al-ikhfā’ wa ’l- i‘lān), the possessor of
which is (the Perfect) Human Being.124 (It is easy to notice that, for Qūnawī, five universal
presences are reducible to the three aforementioned, which, in turn, come down to a single
universal presence – that of the Perfect Human Being, the other four presences being
nothing but its particular levels.)
Two other presences, according to Qūnawī, serve as intermediaries:
4) the presence of the spirits and the preserved tablet, which is an intermediary between
the presence of the Unseen and that of the Perfect Man (being closer related to the
Unseen);
5) the presence of imagination (khayāl) or (imaginal) likeness (mithāl).
In turn, Kāshānī and ‘Abd al-Rahmān al-Jāmī (817/1414 – 898/1492) speak of six universal
presences or levels instead of five. In the introduction of his Naqd al-nusūs fī sharh naqsh al-
fusūs (“The Critic of the Texts Commenting the Imprint of the Bezels”) Jāmī lists these levels
as follows:
1) the Unseen of the Unseen (or: the Absent of the Absent) (ghayb al-ghuyūb), also known
as “the first Unseen”, “the first entification”, “the level of bringing together and finding”
(cf. Qūnawī!), “the oneness of bringing together” (ahadiyyat al-jam‘), “the station of
bringing together” and “the reality of realities”. On this level, there is no manifestation of
things of whatever kind present, due to the complete removal of their entities;
2) “the second Unseen”, also known as “the second entification”. It is called “the second
Unseen” due to the absence of engendered things from themselves and from their
likenesses (while they are present, fixed, realized and distinguished from each other in the
Real’s knowledge). This level is also known as “the world of meanings” (‘ālam al-
ma‘ānī), “the presence of the [thin] cloud” (hadrat al-‘amā’) (because of its being the
barrier that separates oneness and manyness), “the presence of impression (irtisām)” (due
to the impression of relative manyness, related to divine names, and real manyness, related
to the engendered being and the latter’s realities, in it), “the presence of pre-eternal
knowledge” and “the level of contingency”;
3) the level of spirits or the world of Command, the higher world and the world of
Dominion – the level of the manifestation of simple disengaged engendered realities to
themselves and to their likenesses;
4) the level of the world of Image, i.e., the level on which the subtle engendered indivisible
non-disconnectable non-connectable things are found;

123
Qūnawī, I‘jāz , 141.
124
Qūnawī, I‘jāz, 10.

32
5) the level of bodies, or the level of sense perception, or the world of the Witnessed. On
this level dense compound engendered things, which can be divided and disconnected, are
found;
6) the level which encompasses (or brings together) all (other) levels due to its property of
isthmus (barzakh) – the level of the Perfect Human Being.125
Jāmī provides a lot of details in his account (which, in turn, is based upon an even more
expansive discourse of Farghānī126), but it seems that he fails to emphasize the crucial point
that the five or six presences are universal levels of finding and awareness of one entity
(which, depending on the respect in which we consider it, can be called “the Real” as well as
“the creation”). (Although he quotes Mu‘ayyid al-Dīn al-Jandī (d. ca. 700/1300), saying that
“there is one entity in wujūd (‘finding/ awareness’), which is the entity of the unbounded real
finding/ awareness, and it – and no-one else – is “the found” (mawjūd) and “the witnessed”
(mashhūd)”127, he does not appear to attribute particular importance to the quoted statement.)
Qūnawī`s discourse on entification is much more (and perhaps – too) succinct, since he
focusses his attention on the issue of the Complete Human Being (the Perfect Man) and treats
four other presences as necessary intermediaries for the entification of the form of this – fifth
and central – presence (whereas, in respect of its rank and waystation, the Perfect Man
himself serves as an intermediary between the Real and the creation).
Qūnawī describes the Perfect Human Being as the possessor of the station of “oneness of
bringing together” (ahadiyyat al-jam‘) and the locus of the essential self-disclosure (tajallī
dhātī). In fact, his presence is that of the first entification (hence, the six-presence scheme,
proposed by Kāshānī, Jāmī and others appears to be faulty, because its first presence (in case
it is qualified as “the first entification”) coincides with the sixth one (the reality of the Perfect
Human Being)). The form of the Perfect Human Being cannot be fully actualized without the
actualization of four other presences, therefore its actualization necessitates their entification:
“Indeed the object of desire was the Perfect Man himself (literally: “in his entity” – J.E.), not
anything else, because of his being the complete locus of the self-disclosure of the Real, through
which the Real manifests itself in the aspect of its essence and the totality of its names, and
attributes, and properties, and [mentally posited] respects (i‘tibārāt), in keeping with its
knowledge of itself through itself in (or: regarding) itself”.128
“The first of the intellected levels is the entification which encompasses all entifications, and it
possesses the oneness of bringing together, and it pertains to the True Human Being, whose
form is Adam”.129
“And the heart of all forms of finding (al-suwar al-wujūdiyya) is the True Perfect Human Being
(al-insān al-kāmil al-haqīqī) [who is] the isthmus between necessity and contingency and the
all-encompassing mirror of the essence and the level [– when I say “the level”, I refer to] the
attributes of eternity and its properties, as well as [to] the newly-appearing events. For this
reason, the earth, which is the centre of the circle of finding/ existence, was established as the
locus of his vicegerency, and its (the earth’s – J.E.) station of meaning, which at present is
veiled by its form, possesses the rank of originatingness (i.e., serves as the point of origin – J.E.)
in sending forth (inbi‘āth) the merciful breath in order to engender the universal configuration
of finding. And, in this respect, it (the earth – J.E.) corresponds to the True Human Being, who
descends upon it by [virtue of] [his] vicegerency, because he (the Perfect Human Being – J.E.)

125
Jāmī, Naqd, 30-64, in particular 30–31.
126
See: Farghānī, Muntahā, part 1, 77–107, in particular 17–18 and 45.
127
Jāmī, Naqd, 29.
128
Qūnawī, Nusūs, 182.
129
Sadr al-Dīn al-Qūnawī, Kitāb al-Fukūk fī asrār mustanadāt hikam al-Fusūs, ed. M.Khājavī, Tehrān:
Intishārāt-i Mawlā 1371 S.H./1413 L.H., 192.

33
is the first in respect of rank and way-station, although he is the last in respect of form. And he
is the intermediary between the Real and the creation, and through him and from his level the
effusion of the Real and the assistance (madad) – that which is the occasion of the subsistence
of what is other than God – reach the world in its entirety, in its highness and lowness, and if he
(the Perfect Human Being – J.E.), in the aspect of his being the isthmus – that which does not
differ from any of the two sides, did not exist, nothing of the world would receive the unique
divine assistance because of the lack of correspondence and relationship, and the former (i.e.,
the divine assistance – J.E.) would not reach the world, and he was intended, and indeed he is
the intention (‘amd) of the heavens”.130
Like the heart in the human body and the earth in the visible cosmos, the Perfect Human
Being was intended first, but was completed last. The rest of the presences/ levels came into
being as particularizations of this – first and last and, therefore, universal and all-encompassing –
presence. Until the human body is not fully developed and exists as an embryo in mother’s
womb, it is not proper to speak of “heart” in the strict sense of the word: rather, we should
speak about some kind of prototype or “sprout” of heart. The same is also the case with the
Perfect Human Being: namely, if the presence of the True Human Being (i.e., the level of the
first entification) is considered without the subsequent presences, what we get is the appointed
vicegerent without an established locus of vicegerency and the central point of the circle
without the circle itself. He is the Real’s intended one and its object of desire. However, this
intention cannot be realized and the object of desire cannot be gained possession of except
through creating the intellectual, spiritual, imaginal and sensible presences with their
particular inhabitants. To achieve a state of perfect equilibrium, one must traverse (i.e.,
consider mentally, actualize in imagination and experience through sense perception) all
possible states of disequilibrium.
To summarize briefly the analysis of the treatment of the issue of entification by Ibn
al-‘Arabī`s school, it must be said that the most important – and perhaps the only (apart from
Ibn al-‘Arabī himself) reliable – exponent of this teaching was Sadr al-Dīn Qūnawī. To him,
the entification of the four universal presences (that of meanings, spiritual, imaginal and
sensible) is the necessary precondition of the entification of the form of the Perfect Human
Being (al-insān al-kāmil) (while his meaning and reality becomes entified by the first
entification). The entity of the Perfect Human Being is the centre of the circle of finding/
existence and the heart of the cosmos: whatever is found, is found through it. This entity is the
locus of the essential self-disclosure of the Real (but we know that this kind of self-disclosure
destroys its locus – which means, the Perfect Human Being does not have a particular and
specified entity, formed by a particular divine name which has the overwhelming influence
upon it). Due to a complete equilibrium of all divine names in it, the Perfect Human Being
might be called “the entity of non-entification”.
An important practical implication of the teaching on the Perfect Human Being is the belief in
the existence of the particular locus of its manifestation in the engendered world – the human
being who is referred to as “the pole” (qutb). (“The pole is the heart of the engendered wujūd
(finding) and the mirror of the one all-encompassing complete essential self-disclosure”.131)
The entities of the rest of the saints (literally: [God’s] clients) (awliyā’), in turn, perform the
functions of other parts of the spiritual body of “the Great Man” (al-insān al-kabīr), i.e., the
cosmos.

130
Qūnawī, Fukūk, 248.
131
Sadr al-Dīn al-Qūnawī, al-Nafahāt al-ilāhiyya, ed. M.Khājavī, Tehrān: Intishārāt-i Mawlā 1375 S.H./1417
L.H., 158.

34
1.2. THE BASIC PRINCIPLES OF SADRĀ’S TEACHING ON WUJŪD

1.2.1. The Principality of Wujūd in Respect to Quiddity

To the mystics of Ibn al-‘Arabī`s school, each of the things found in the external world
represent a particular kind of entification of the all-inclusive finding (al-wujūd al-‘āmm) and a
specific articulation of the Breath of the Compassionate. As I mentioned earlier, every fixed
entity (‘ayn thābita) is nothing else but a (particular or general) possibility of the entification
of wujūd. There is no sense to talk about the principality of possibility (asālat al-imkān) and
the mental positedness (i‘tibāriyya) of wujūd or vice versa, because wujūd and fixed entities
are interdependent and act as each other’s mirror.
For the philosophers, ever since the time of Plato and Aristotle (though the exact Arabic
philosophical terms wujūd and māhiya came into use much later), the question of the nature of
relationship between existence/ finding and quiddity has been an apple of discord – the
discord, the ultimate cause of which, it is now believed, lies in the difference of the character
of the initial mystical intuition. The professors of the “principality of quiddity” (asālat al-
māhiya), like Mullā Sadrā’s teacher Mīr Dāmād (d. 1040/1631 or 1632), based their
philosophical position, as Toshihiko Izutsu points out, “on an eidemic intuition of eternal
archetypes, a mystical experience of the trans-sensible essences of the things”132 – that is, on
an intuition of the eternal ideas of things, wherefore they can be qualified as Platonists. In
turn, the professors of the “principality of existence/ finding” (asālat al-wujūd), whom Izutsu
describes as the possessors of “a dynamic intuition of a dynamic reality”133, based their
philosophical doctrines upon the intuition of the all-encompassing flow of the primordial
creative energy (the cosmic Life).134 They believed that this dynamic creative reality or
energy manifests and existentiates itself in an infinite number of phenomenal forms, which
the intellect converts into static and fixed entities, which are referred to as “quiddities”
(māhiyāt). In a certain aspect, the entire history of metaphysics can be regarded as a never-
ending and non-gainable fight between these two basic intuitions – the intuition of immutable
essences and the intuition of the flow of existence/ finding. From a mystical (‘irfānī) point of
view, neither of the two intuitions is sufficient to reflect the true state of affairs, because each
of them focuses on one or two universal presences of the cosmic finding or self-awareness:
the first one – on the supra-temporal presences of pure meanings and disengaged spirits, the
second – on the imaginal and sensible ones. (Sadrā was well aware of this difference between
universal presences when he limited the domain of the applicability of the principle of the
substantial motion (al-haraka al-jawhariyya) to the physical and imaginal worlds and
remarked that this principle does not apply to the realities existent in the realm of Divinity
(suq‘ al-ulūhiyya).135)
Sadrā’s position on the existence/ finding – quiddity/ whatness (wujūd – māhiya) relationship
is succinctly expressed in the following statement: “Quiddity is an imitation (hikāya) of
existence/ finding”.136 In modern terms, he might have described it as a mental photography
of the infinite flow of wujūd, which registers the parameters of the latter at a particular instant.

132
T. Izutsu, “Mīr Dāmād and His Metaphysics”, in: Mīr Dāmād, al-Qabasāt, ed. M.Mohaghegh, 2nd edition,
Tehrān: Mu’assisa-i Intishārāt wa chāp dāneshghāh-i Tehrān 1374 S.H., 11–12.
133
Izutsu, “Mīr Dāmād”, 12.
134
See: Izutsu, “Mīr Dāmād”, 12.
135
On suq‘ al-ulūhiyya see e.g.: Sadr al-Dīn al-Shīrāzī, al-Mazāhir al-ilāhiyya fī asrār al-‘ulūm al-kamāliyya, ed.
S.M.Khāmene’ī, Tehrān: Sāzmān-i Chāp wa intishārāt Vazārat-i Farhang wa Irshād-i Islāmī 1378 S.H., 48.
136
See e.g.: Sadrā, Mashā‘ir, 7.

35
From the mystical point of view, both principles – the principality of existence/ finding and
the principality of quiddity – give a one-sided representation of the true state of the affair. The
mystics of Ibn al-‘Arabī school would say that wujūd and māhiya each possesses a particular
kind of principality or fixedness (thubūt) (refer to the earlier discussion on oneness of wujūd
and manyness of entities).

1.2.2. Analogical Gradation of Existence

It seems pretty certain137 that terms tashkīk (‘analogical gradation’ or ‘systematic ambiguity’)
and mushakkik (‘analogically graded’ or ‘systematically ambiguous’) were coined by the Arab
translators of Aristotle’s works on logic and their Neoplatonic commentaries, as an attempt to
translate the Greek word amphibolos (a term which is used to describe a certain kind of
homonym, namely, a word which is used in one and the same sense, but in different ways).
In the Jadal (“Topics”) of the Shifā’ (“Healing”) Ibn Sīnā defines an analogically graded (or:
systematically ambiguous) (mushakkik) term as follows:
“This is a term whose meaning is one, but this one meaning is not shared by all referents in an
identical way, as it is the case with a univocal (mutawātin) term, in case of which the same
meaning is shared [by all referents] in the same degree”.138
In the ‘Uyūn al-hikma (“Sources of Wisdom”) Ibn Sīnā presents the following division of
different modes of attribution:
“If a term is applied to many things, this [application] can be made in one sense [and] in the
same way (‘alā ’l-siwā), as [the word] “animal” is applied to man and horse, [and then] it is
called “univocal” (mutawātin). If it is applied in different senses, as [the word] ‘ayn is applied
to cash (dinār) and to an eye, it is called “shared” (mushtarak). If it is applied in one sense, but
not in the same way, it is called “analogically graded” (mushakkik), as it is the case with
“existence/ finding” (wujūd), which is applied both to substance and accident”.139
What Ibn Sīnā has in mind here, is the tashkīk fī mafhūm al-wujūd (‘analogical gradation of
the concept of existence/ finding’), a particular case of the tashkīk bi ’l-taqaddum wa ’l-
ta’akhkhur (‘analogical gradation through/ in terms of priority and posteriority’) – namely, he
states that the existence/ finding of substance is prior to that of accident.
As it is well known, Ibn Sīnā denies the tashkīk fī haqīqat al-wujūd (‘analogical gradation of
the reality of existence/ finding’). To him, there are two kinds of existents: the necessarily
existent (wājib al-wujūd) and the possibly existent (mumkin al-wujūd). In his discourse on the
“proof of the sincere” (burhān al-siddīqīn) (see the relevant subchapter) and elsewhere Bū
‘Alī takes great pains to demonstrate that their becoming one another (interchangeability) and
the analogical gradation of their realities (i.e., becoming more or less necessary or contingent
respectively) is impossible. The option of the analogical gradation of the single nature of
existence/ finding, on which insists Sadrā, seems to Ibn Sīnā particularly absurd (he only
admits this kind of tashkīk in quantities and qualities).

137
See: H.A.Wolfson, “The amphibolous terms in Aristotle, Arabic philosophy and Maimonides”, in Harward
Theological Review, 31 (1938), 173; C.Bonmariage, “Elements pour la comprehension de la notion de
tashkīk chez Mulla Sadra” in Islam – West Philosophical Dialogue. The papers presented at the World
Congress on Mulla Sadra (May 1999, Tehran), Vol. 2. Mulla Sadra and Transcendent Philosophy, Tehrān :
SIPRIn Publications 1380/2001, 127–146.
138
Ibn Sīnā, Shifā: Jadal, ed. F.El-Ahwani under the supervision of I.Madkour, Cairo: GEBO 1965, 118.
Cf. Bonmariage’s French translation in: Bonmariage, “Elements”, 128.
139
Ibn Sīnā, ‘Uyūn al-hikma, quoted from: Fakhr al-Dīn al-Rāzī, Sharh ‘Uyūn al-hikma, ed. A.al-Saqā, Tehrān:
1373 S.H./1415 L.H., Vol. 1, 117.

36
Historically, the issue of the tashkīk of the reality of wujūd is a by-product of Plato’s theory of
the eternal ideas of things140: the existence/ finding of the archetype of a thing was naturally
supposed to be stronger and more intense than that of its shadows and idols found in the
natural world.
According to Ibn Sīnā, who rejects the existence of the eternal ideas of things, the tashkīk in
the reality of existence/ finding is impossible for at least two important reasons:
1) it is impossible that the essence (dhāt) and the essential (dhātī) would be analogically
graded in respect of their instances (afrād). (Otherwise, it would be possible to claim that
“our cat is more cat than our neighbours’ cat”, i.e., that the cathood of the former is
stronger and more intense than that of the latter);
2) tashkīk in terms of intensity and weakness would necessitate specific difference (al-ikhtilāf
al-naw‘ī) between the instances of the nature in which the difference occurs, so that it (the
specific difference) would become the cause of the difference between their (instances’)
essential differentiae (al-fusūl al-dhātiyya) (hence, the instances of allegedly one nature
would, in fact, appear to represent different natures).
From what was said above, it is evident that analogical gradation of the reality of existence/
finding in terms of intensity and weakness (tashkīk fī haqīqat al-wujūd bi ’l-shidda wa ’l-da‘f)
only makes sense for the Platonic trend of philosophy with its belief in the external existence
of the archetypes of things, while it sounds nonsense to the followers of Aristotle, who grant
universals only mental (dhihnī) existence.
In classical Islamic philosophy, the most significant representative of the Platonic trend was,
apparently, Suhrawardī, better known as Shaykh al-Ishrāq (“the Master of Illumination”)
(after the title of his main work – Hikmat al-ishrāq (“The Wisdom of Illumination”)).
According to his teaching, God (or, more correctly, the creative principle of the cosmos) is
“the Light of Lights” (nūr al-anwār), inaccessible and infinite in its intensity, while the
cosmos consists of the hierarchy of lights, which are either pure (mahd) and disengaged
(mujarrad) or accidental (‘ārid) (by the latter Suhrawardī means the physical lights which, to
him, are shapes or forms of something else (i.e., higher spiritual lights), while pure spiritual
lights are lights in themselves). There is horizontal (or: latitudinal) (‘ardī) and vertical (or:
longitudinal) (tūlī) organization present in the hierarchy of lights. The first one deals with the
lords of (different) species (arbāb al-anwā‘), i.e., their angels or luminous archetypes. These
archetypes or angels do not relate to each other as cause and effect, which is the case with the
parts of the vertical order. Different levels of the vertical order, from the Light of Lights to the
weakest possible light, share the reality of light (haqīqat al-nūr), but differ from each other by
the degree of intensity which this shared reality possesses in every particular case. This
difference, allegedly present in the single reality of light, is called “the analogical gradation of
light” (tashkīk al-nūr).
In two of his works, namely, the Mashāri‘ wa ’l-mutārahāt (“Paths and Havens”) and the
Talwīhāt al-lawhiyya wa ’l-‘arshiyya (“Intimations of the Table and the Throne”), Suhrawardī
posed a number of proofs to support this principle and to refute Ibn Sīnā’s objections against
the analogical gradation of substance and the essence of the thing. Four centuries later, in the
relevant chapter of his Asfār (“Journeys”), Mullā Sadrā repeated Suhrawardī’s arguments in

140
This observation was made by Prof. Gholam Reza. A‘awānī in his lecture on Ibn Sīnā’s ontology, delivered
at the International Avicenna Colloqium in Hamādān (Iran) on 23 August 2004. (Unfortunately, the text of
the lecture is not published in the Proceedings of the Colloqium.) See also: Gholam Reza A‘awānī, “Why is
Mullā Sadrā Called Sadr al-Muta’allihīn”, in A.N.Baqershahi (ed.), Mulla Sadra’s School and Western
Philosophies: The Papers Presented at the Second World Congress on Mulla Sadra (May 2004, Tehran,
Iran), Vol. 1, Tehran: SIPRIn Publications 2005, 233–238.

37
favour of the analogical gradation of the essence in terms of intensity and weakness almost
verbatim, only changing nūr (‘light’) to wujūd (‘existence/ finding’).
In what follows, I shall briefly discuss Sadrā’s four main arguments in favour of the
analogical gradation of wujūd (the actual author of which, as mentioned above, was
Suhrawardī).
1) The essence and the essentials can be analogically graded in respect of their instances.
Suhrawardī and Sadrā both state that the sages of Fars (Iran) and the ancients in general
hold that some of the luminous substantial lights were causes of the others in respect of
their simple (non-compound) substantiality.141 However, the reference to the beliefs and
practice of the ancients can by no means be regarded as a philosophical proof, especially
because Ibn Sīnā, in a number of his writings, takes great efforts to demonstrate the
opposite.
Thus, in the Maqūlāt (“Categories”) of the Shifā’ he writes:
“I do not mean that one quantity is not greater or smaller than another one; what I mean is that
one quantity is not stronger and greater in its being a quantity than another one, which shares
with it [the concept of quantity], although the former is greater [than the latter] in respect of the
relative (idāfī) meaning – I mean the relative length”.142
A few lines later, he says:
“Know that “many” without relation is number and “many” in relation [to something] is an
accident of number. Likewise, the nature of blackness and temperature is identical in all black
and hot things respectively. Indeed, the diversity takes place in regard to specific features of
instances, not due to the substance of the shared quiddity and its root”.143
Then he goes on to explain:
“The true blackness does not become more intense or weaker, but what is blackness in
comparison with one thing, is whiteness in comparison with another. Whatever kind of
blackness is supposed, it does not become more intense or weaker as regards its selfhood, but
this happens when it is considered in comparison [with something]. Therefore the contrariety
(taqābul) of two sides includes what is situated between them, and the conditioning of true
opposition is not destroyed by the utmost limit of contradiction”.144
As we see, Ibn Sīnā univocally denies the possibility of the analogical gradation in terms of
intensity and weakness in the nature and substance of thing: according to him, it can be
applied to accidents only. Moreover, tashkīk can only be perceived if one accident is
considered in comparison with another. Sadrā explains that, as a result of a mental operation,
carried out by the assistance of the estimative faculty (wahm)145, a more intense instance is
perceived as a likeness (mithāl) of a weaker one, together with the allowance of addition
(tajwīz ziyāda), not as an increase of the intensity of the universal nature itself in some
instances or as a greater degree of manifestation of its universal traces in some instances (the
latter case is explained by the Peripatetics as being caused by the difference in the degree of
truthfulness of attribution of a single derivative to two instances from which it was derived).

141
Sadrā, Asfār, part 1, 432–433.
142
Ibn Sīnā, Shifā’: Qātiqūriyās, quoted from: Sadrā, Asfār, part 1, 434–435.
143
Ibn Sīnā, Shifā’: Qātiqūriyās, quoted from: Sadrā, Asfār, part 1, 435.
144
Ibn Sīnā, Shifā’: Qātiqūriyās, quoted from: Sadrā, Asfār, part 1, 435.
145
Estimative faculty is a potency to perceive an intelligible meaning, simultaneously attributing it to a particular
sensed thing (thus, in fact, identifying the intelligible meaning with a sensed affair). Chittick suggests to
translate wahm as ‘sense-intuition’ (William C.Chittick, “Teleology”, 224).

38
As a result, considering two blacknesses, the Peripatetics do not see one common affair in
which they differ. Instead, they establish in each of them the constituent through which the
difference occurs, namely, its species-forming differentia. Moreover, they detect in two
bodies – intensely black and weakly black – the concept in which the difference lies:
according to them, it is the concept of “black” (aswad); and, indeed, one of them possesses
that characteristic which is called “blackness” in a greater degree than the other.
Suhrawardī in the Mashāri‘ attempts to demonstrate the validity of the principle of the
analogical gradation of the essence and the essentials (his reasoning is repeated almost
verbatim by Sadrā in the Asfār). Shaykh al-Ishrāq argues that the difference between two
measures is in/ through the measure itself and the difference between two blacknesses is in/
through the very blackness. From accidents and shapes, Suhrawardī then moves to substances.
He argues that the Peripatetics deny the analogical gradation of substance in terms of intensity
and weakness due to the fault which inheres in their definition of substance (they define it as
“an existent which does not abide in a substratum (mawdū‘)”). However, he does not propose
any other definition of substance instead of the rejected one, but simply points out that, since
the corporeal substances are like shadows of the intelligible ones, it is impossible that the
former might equal the latter in substantiality, because, according to the teachings of the
school of Plato, the substantiality of the cause is prior to that of the effect.146
It is evident that Suhrawardī does not actually refute Ibn Sīnā`s (fairly sound and well-made)
arguments against the analogical gradation of the essence and the essentials. He also fails to
provide a better definition of substance instead of the rejected one. Suhrawardī’s criticism of
Ibn Sīnā has more to do with the difference in the basic approaches of two philosophers (in
other words, with their entirely different vision of the reality) – one can say that Suhrawardī
criticizes Ibn Sīnā for his not being a Platonic.
Interestingly, in the relevant chapter of the Asfār, after a detailed account of Ibn Sīnā’s
opinion on the issue, Sadrā does not present a refutation of it of any considerable substance
(except the aforementioned succinct reference to the beliefs of the ancients). This is in his
work al-Shawāhid al-rubūbiyya fī manāhij al-sulūkiyya (“The Witnesses of Lordship
Regarding the Methods of Wayfaring”) where he states that, unlike all other universal
meanings (=concepts), wujūd does accept analogical gradation:
“The universal meanings – be they either essentials or accidents – do not become stronger and
weaker, except wujūd, which differs in its essence in terms of perfection and imperfection,
priority and posteriority, poverty and wealth (or: independence) (ghinā), because it is entified
through its essence and, consequently, in its essence, it is [both] the prior and the priority, and
the posterior and posteriority, as it is also the perfect and perfection. And the privation (‘adam)
of it is imperfection and the imperfect, and the evil (sharīr) and evilness (sharr) in its
essence”.147
2) Analogical gradation in terms of intensity and weakness does not necessitate specific
difference (al-ikhtilāf al-naw‘ī) between the instances of the nature in which the difference
occurs. Sadrā asserts that the ancient Stoics have successfully proved that the instances of
the reality of existence/ finding do not differ from each other by their differentiae, despite
their diversity in terms of intensity and weakness. He points out that the Peripatetics
themselves have established the (fact of the) increase and decrease of the intensity of
qualities as regards the motion of a corporeal object in respect of the levels/ degrees of

146
See: Sh.Y.Sohravardi, Oeuvres philosophiques et mystiques, ed. H.Corbin, 2e edition, Tehran – Paris: Academie
Imperiale Iranienne de Philosophie et Depositaire Librairie Adrien Maisonneuve 1976, t. 1, 297–302.
147
Sadr al-Dīn al-Shīrāzī, al-Shawāhid al-rubūbiyya fī manāhij al-sulūkiyya, ed. S.J.Āshtiyānī, 2nd edition,
Qum: Būstān-i Kitāb 1382 S.H., 241.

39
qualities, such as temperatures and blacknesses. Besides, the Peripatetics also admit that a
single motion is an individual affair, possessing a connected he-ness from the beginning to
the end. Hence, holds Sadrā, it is evident that intense and weak degrees of blackness, in
respect of their blackening the body, share in their specific quiddity.
3) Diversity in respect of quality and diversity in respect of quantity represent the same kind
of analogical gradation. The rules of common usage (‘urf) in Arabic permit to apply terms
‘intensity/ strength’ (shidda) and ‘weakness’ (da‘f) only to qualities, while, in turn, the
terms ‘increase’ (ziyāda) and ‘decrease’ (nuqsān), and ‘manyness’ (kathra) and ‘fewness’
(qilla) can be applied to quantities only. However, a sage and philosopher is not concerned
with the observance of the rules of common usage.
Some commentators of Ibn Sīnā tried to distinguish intensity from greatness in measure by
claiming the increase in the intensity of quality to be limited, while alleging the increase in
quantity to be unlimited, but, according to Sadrā, the acceptance of the statement does not
necessarily lead to the establishment of two different kinds of analogical gradation pertaining
to quality and quantity respectively.
Another attempt to distinguish between intensity/ weakness and greatness/ smallness in
measure was made by those followers of Ibn Sīnā who asserted that something is called great
or small in measure when it is possible to point to the exact measure in which two things
equal each other and to establish the additional measure – the measure by which one thing
exceeds the other. To refute the assertion, Suhrawardī and Sadrā argue that the reality of every
number is constituted by “one” repeated a certain number of times, not by other numbers.
Therefore, every number is a simple (non-compound) species, which is not composed of other
numbers. (Thus, “four” is not constituted by “three” and “one”, nor is “three” constituted by
“two” and “one”.) When the intellect divides any number into parts, the form of that number
disappears and another form comes into existence.
4) The difference in terms of intensity and weakness and perfection and imperfection is not
limited to the accidents of quality and quantity, as the Peripatetics assert, but also applies
to the substance. This fourth principle is perhaps the most important and sensitive one,
because it deals with the issue of limitations of analogical gradation.
Suhrawardī148 (and Sadrā, who repeats him verbatim) points out that the limitation of intensity
and weakness to quality and quantity only contradicts the beliefs of the ancients, in particular
Empedocles and Plotinus, who regarded the substances of this lower world as the shadows of
the substances of the higher world. Sadrā explains that this means that they (the ancient sages)
treated the substances of the higher world as causes and those of the lower one as their effects,
because the substantiality of the cause is by necessity fuller and more complete than the
substantiality of the effect, and then adds that, to him, intensity has no other meaning except
this one, i.e., that some substances are more intense and stronger in their substantiality than
other ones. (This approach – to reduce all accidental differences to substantial one(s) – is most
typical of Sadrā, who regards substances as dynamic entities, whereas Ibn Sīnā believes them
to be static and immutable, while (as he hold) only accidents are subject to change.)
To summarize, analogical gradation of substance in terms of intensity and weakness is an
indispensable constituent of the (conventionally) essence-based (or perhaps it is better to say:
archetype-based) philosophical systems like those of Plato, Suhrawardī and Mīr Dāmād. (All
of them would agree that a table which exists in the domain of archetypes is undoubtedly
stronger than the one that is found in the material world, it is “more truly a table”.) In turn,
according to the sense experience based philosophy of Aristotle and Ibn Sīnā, the principle of
148
See: Sohravardi, Oeuvres, t.1, 13.

40
analogical gradation in terms of intensity and weakness is only applicable to two categories of
accidents – quality and quantity. (Since Peripaticism denies the existence of the realm of
archetypes or eternal forms of things, the sole basis of its judgments is the observations made
in the physical world by means of external senses. Obviously, this is absurd to claim that “my
cat is more cat than that of my neighbours”.)
Since the bulk of Sadrā’s texts (the Asfār in particular) consist of scrupulous analysis of other
people’s philosophical ideas and opinions, it is often difficult to understand his own position.
This is also the case with tashkīk. It seems, however, that what Sadrā actually believes in and
insists upon, is the analogical gradation of the reality of existence/ finding (and certainly not
that of the concept of substance (mafhūm al-jawhar)) in terms of intensity and weakness
(tashkīk haqīqat al-wujūd bi ’l-shidda wa ’l-da‘f) – namely, he holds that the wujūd of the
existential (wujūdī) cause is stronger than that of the existential effect.
The existential cause (al-‘illa al-wujūdiyya) is the cause of the existence of the effect – in
other words, that through which the latter subsists. Sadrā calls the relation which is
established between the existential cause and its effect the “illuminative relation” (al-idāfa al-
ishrāqiyya). According to him (his treatment of the issue differs significantly from
Suhrawardī’s approach), the illuminative relation is the relation which, properly speaking,
consists of one side only, because, what outwardly looks like the other side, actually
completely lacks the ability to subsist on its own, subsisting, instead, on the first side. Sadrā
refers to the relation that exists between the sun and its ray as the most illustrative example of
this kind of relation: the ray, he argues, has no true existence of its own. Hence, it must be
considered exactly as the sun’s illuminative relation.
Sadrā’s teaching on existence/ finding, in general, can be described as a special kind of
Platonism – namely, the Platonism of wujūd. According to him, the sensible wujūd is a
shadow of the imaginal one, which, in turn, itself is a shadow of the intelligible wujūd. Hence,
what is truly real, is only the intelligible wujūd; while imaginal and sensible (especially the
latter) wujūd is only a metaphor of this first true real wujūd, whose intensity is (or, at least,
seems to be) unlimited and infinite. (However, Sadrā admits that the number of human souls
which reach the realm of the intelligible wujūd is extremely small, the overwhelming majority
of them remaining in the precincts of the imaginal world.)
The decisive importance that Sadrā attributes to the notion of tashkīk permits us to say that the
general trend which he follows in his ontology is that of Plato, Plotinus and Suhrawardī. In
this overall Platonic scheme, the validity of the teachings of Ibn al-‘Arabī, and the theoretical
mysticism in general, seems to be limited to the intermediary world of imagination only.
In his Risāla al-hādiya (“Guiding Treatise”) Qūnawī reduces all kinds of tashkīk to difference
in manifestation of a certain reality, which, in turn, according to him, comes down to
difference in the preparedness (isti‘dād) of the particular loci of manifestation.
“If a reality differs in [respect of] its being stronger, or more prior, or more intense, or more
preferred, in the view of a verifier, all this comes down to [difference in] manifestation, not to
plurality (ta‘addud) occurring in the manifested reality, whatever reality it be – knowledge,
existence/ finding or other one. A [certain] receptacle may be better prepared [to serve as a
receptacle] for the manifestation of a [certain] reality as such than another receptacle, although
the reality is one in all cases. Ranking in excellence (mufādala) and difference occur between its
manifestations in accordance with the manifesting affair (al-amr al-muzhir), requiring [such]
entification of that reality which differs from its entification in another affair”.149

149
Sadr al-Dīn Qūnawī, al-Risāla al-hādiya al-murshidiyya, in Sadr al-Dīn al-Qūnawī and Nasīr al-Dīn al-Tūsī,
Murāsalāt, ed. Gudrun Schubert, Beirut: Jam‘iyyat al-mustashriqīn al-ālmāniyya 1416/1995, 166 (also

41
Qūnawī’s point can be explained by imagining a number of metallic mirrors – some of which
are well-polished, but the others rusty – which reflect one and the same object. Obviously, the
better polished the mirror, the brighter the reflection of the object (which is what analogical
gradation through intensity and weakness, according to Qūnawī, is about). However, the
reflected images also differ from one another in shape and size, this latter kind of difference
being caused by the difference in shape and size of the mirrors. (E.g., some of them are big
and others small; some are convex, the others are concave etc.) Certainly, this latter kind of
difference cannot be removed by polishing.
Hence, the verdict of theoretical mysticism on the doctrine of the tashkīk bi ’l-shidda wa
’l-da‘f is that, although the theory reflects an important aspect of reality, if it is proposed as
the key doctrine dealing with the core and heart of reality and most fully reflecting the true
state of affairs (as, in all likelihood, it is the case with Plato and the Platonic trend (the most
important representatives of which in Islamic philosophy are Suhrawardī, Mīr Dāmād and
Mullā Sadrā)), it proves to be able to provide only a simplified picture of reality – first of all,
because, in this doctrine, there is no place for the crucial Sufi teaching on the Real’s names
and attributes as the cause of the diversity of the phenomena of the witnessed and the absent
domains.

1.2.3. Existential Causation: The Gnostic Approach?

It is well known that the first elaborated doctrine of causation was worked out by Aristotle
more than two thousands years ago. Other theories which have appeared since then either
have been branches and extensions of Aristotelian basics or, if they ventured to deny them,
have ended up in some kind of agnosticism (e.g. Hume’s theory of “patterns” (into which the
things fall) or Ghazālī’s theory of “the habit of God” (‘ādat Allāh)). In the Islamic thought,
these are definitely the Peripatetics (mashā’iyyūn) who seem to be most concerned with the
topic. As for the Mystics (‘urafā’), terms “cause” (‘illa) and causation (‘illiyya) seldom
appear in their writings.
As far as I know, the only work in which Sadrā discusses the problem of causation at length,
is the Asfār, where the sixth “waystation” (marhala) of the first journey, entitled “On the
Cause and the Effect”, occupies most of the second part of the book (about 260 pages)150. The
overall scheme of the Asfār, claims Sadrā, is devised after the scheme of four journeys
accomplished by a perfect mystic (‘ārif) (not a philosopher!)151 – which means that,
travelling from one “waystation” of the book to another, the person in quest of the Truth, by
means of intellectual meditation (supported by certain ascetic practices), is supposed to
accomplish a deed of a mystic, rather than that of a philosopher. But, of course, this is merely
a claim. To be able to speak of the gnostic element in greater detail, I have to say a few more
words about Sadrā’s general approach to the problem of causation, as it appears in the Asfār.

quoted in: ‘Abd al-Rahmān al-Jāmī, al-Durra al-fākhira, ed. N.Heer and A.Mūsavī Behbahānī, 2nd edition,
Tehrān: Mu’assisa-i mutāle‘āt-i islāmī dāneshghāh-i Tehrān 1382/2003, 4–5).
150
There are other relevant chapters in different parts of the book, e.g. the second station of the first journey –
“On Making” (fī ’l-ja‘l) (Sadrā, Asfār, part 1, 396-446). Besides, the 4th, the 5th and the 6th ishrāqs
(“illuminations”) of the 4th shāhid (“witness”) of the 1st mashhad (“locus of witnessing”) of the Shawāhid al-
rubūbiyya also deal with the problem of causation (Sadrā, Shawāhid, 113–135).
151
Sadrā, Asfār, part 1, 13. Interestingly, Ibn al-‘Arabī speaks of three journeys only (to the Real, from the Real
and in the Real) and says nothing about the fourth journey, added by by Sadrā (the journey with the Real in
the creation) (see: Ibn al-‘Arabī, Muhyi al-Dīn, al-Isfār ‘an natā’ij al-asfār, ed. M. F. al-Jabr, Damascus: Dār
al-Hikma 2000, 38–39).

42
The issues Sadrā discusses at the beginning of the sixth station (of the first journey) seem to
be typically Peripatetic ones (e.g. causal necessity; common postulates regarding the four
causes etc.). Gradually Sadrā introduces some ideas of the Mutakallimūn (particularly, those
of Fakhr al-Dīn al-Rāzī (543/1149-606/1209), the author of the Mabāhith al-mashriqiyya
(“Illuminating Discourses”), and the Ishrāqīs (such as Suhrawardī’s idea that, in certain
circumstances, a compound cause can produce a simple effect), in order to demonstrate that
the apparent originality of these views is based on certain misunderstandings and inability to
penetrate to the crux of the approach of their predecessors. While, by and large, Sadrā seems
to follow the traditional Peripatetic line in his discourse, he is also eager to integrate in his
teaching some elements of other schools of thought, particularly the Sufi theorists’ idea of the
inclusion of the effect in its cause. On the whole, having studied the relevant chapter of the
Asfār, one gets the impression that Sadrā, in regard to the problem of causation, is trying to
reconcile and make compatible with each other a number of doctrines (those of Peripatetics
and Mystics, as well as those of Illuminationists and the Mutakallimūn) based on totally
different fundamentals. Being brought together, they cannot produce anything else but an
eclectic mixture, different parts of which are loosely connected with each other and do not
make a solid whole.
In reply to this, it could be said that the Asfār was apparently devised to be, first of all, a
textbook for advanced students of philosophy. To serve the purpose, it necessarily had to be a
book of an encyclopaedic approach, i.e., it had to deal with all existing approaches and
theories regarding every particular problem, e.g. causation. But in such a case, one should
argue, the title of the book – “Four intellectual (or: noetic) journeys” (al-Asfār al-‘aqliyya al-
arba‘a) is likely to be a mere metaphor with no reality behind it, because there is no guarantee
at all that an encyclopaedic discourse of philosophical matters will lead to any kind of
intellectual perfection apart from developing student’s skill of theoretical discourse and
logical reasoning.
What should we answer to this objection?
First of all, the problem of causation should not be regarded as a separate matter. Instead, it
should be put into the broader context of Sadrā’s philosophy. That Sadrā’s philosophy is
ontology-based, is a commonplace, the following quotation from the Mashā‘ir (“Penetrations”)
should suffice to prove it:
“… The problem of existence/ finding is the foundation of philosophical principles and the basis
for theological problems, and the pivot around which rotates the mill of the science of
Unification (tawhīd), and the science of Return (ma‘ād), and Mustering (hashr) of spirits and
bodies, and a lot of [other things], in finding which we have no companion and in obtaining
which we remain unmatched. If anyone is ignorant of the knowledge (=gnosis) of existence/
finding, his ignorance spreads upon the [very] sources of problems and upon the most important
of them, and, due to his unawareness of it (the problem of existence/ finding – J.E.), the
mysteries of knowledge and the secrets of it, and the knowledge of lordships (‘ilm al-
rubūbiyyāt) and their prophecies, and the knowledge of the soul and its conjunction [with its
Origin] and its return to the Origin of its origins and its ends escape from him”.152
Hence, there is no doubt that the problem of causation is viewed by Sadrā as a branch of a
more fundamental problem of existence/ finding. The key ontological principle of Sadrā, as
we know, is that of the principality of existence/ finding (asālat al-wujūd). In his own words,
the principle is briefly formulated thus:

152
Sadrā, Mashā‘ir, 4 (of the Arabic text).

43
Consequently, Sadrā believes that only the existence/ finding of a thing enjoys true reality,
while the quiddity is a mere mental limitation and abstraction (or, as the late Henry Corbin
would have put it, “imitation” (hikāya)), which does not enjoy any reality at all. Hence, it is
clear that the real cause of the thing, according to Sadrā, is the cause of its existence/ finding,
not the cause of its quiddity. As the lattter one (quiddity) is a mere mental concept, it is
evident that its constituents (muqawwimāt) are also mere abstractions of mind. Hence the
cause – effect relationship between any particular quiddity and its constituents is manifestly a
pure mental abstraction – and, as we know, what most befits Divine sages (muta’allihūn) is to
have business with true realities of the things, rather than to deal with their mental
abstractions and limitations.153
Now, the last quotation from the Mashā‘ir has already introduced us to another key principle
of Sadrā’s ontology – namely, the principle of the oneness (or: unity) of existence/ finding
(wahdat al-wujūd):
“…and the existences/ findings are nothing else but the rays and lights of the True Light and
Eternal Existence/ Finding – exalted be its sublimity! – except that each of them has its [own]
essential attributes and intelligible meanings [which are] called “quiddities”.
In other words, there is only one real Existence/ Finding (the Necessary One); the other
(contingent) beings are mere rays, illuminations and emanations of this Pure Light –
Existence/ Finding. Perhaps this principle is more explicitly defined elsewhere:
“There is nothing in wujūd except His (i.e., God’s – J.E.) essence, His attributes and His actions,
which are the forms of His names and the loci of manifestation of His attributes”.154
As Muhammad Khājavī writes in his preface to Sadrā’s Tafsīr, what Sadrā professes here is
the individual oneness (al-wahda al-shakhsiyya) of Existence/ Finding155, not a oneness of the
species (al-wahda al-naw‘iyya) – “except that when he saw it (the principle of the individual
oneness of Existence/ Finding – J.E.) to be [a matter which is] difficult [to grasp] for the
minds and [therefore to become] a motive for arguments and [his] opponents, he reduced it to
the oneness of the species and proceeded (i.e., continued his discourse – J.E.) in this way, thus
breaking the resistance of opponents and saving himself from the slander of the ignorants and
those pretending to be philosophers, hinting at what was his purpose, of the Truth and an
insightful view”156. As Khājavī points out, this oneness of the species admits the existence of
a number of systematically ambiguous grades (al-marātib al-mushakkaka), which differ from
each other by their intensity (shadda) and weakness (da‘f), priority (taqaddum) and
posteriority (ta’akhkhur). Besides, they also relate to each other as causes and effects – and,
hence, it becomes evident that one can speak of causation only in regard to the oneness of the
species. As for the individual oneness, the problem of causation is, properly speaking,
irrelevant to it, because, in this case, we cannot speak of two different entities related to each
other as cause and effect. Now, we have to keep in mind that the teaching of the oneness of
the species is, in fact, a reduction and simplification of a more lofty and subtle teaching of the
individual oneness of Existence/ Finding, in order to make the subtle ‘irfānī doctrine
comprehensible, to a degree, to those who have not yet reached the relevant station of Gnosis.
Therefore, one can say that, from Sadrā’s point of view, the reflection on the problem of
causation (like the cogitation on the problem of wujūd as a whole) is meant to serve as a

153
If we accept the division of four Aristotelian causes into existential causes (al-‘ilal al-wujūdiyya) (the
efficient (or the agent) cause and the final cause) and constituent causes (al-‘ilal al-taqwīmiyya) (the formal
cause and the material cause), it is evident that Sadrā is predominantly concerned with the first group.
154
Sadr al-Dīn al-Shīrāzī, Asrār al-āyāt, ed. M.Khājavī. Tehrān: Iranian Academy of Philosophy 1981, 24.
155
M.Khājavī, “Muqaddimma” in the Sadr al-Dīn al-Shīrāzī, Tafsīr al-Qur’ān al-Karīm, Qum: Intishārāt-i Bīdār
1366 S.H., part 1, 31 (of the introduction).
156
M.Khājavī, “Muqaddimma”, 31–32.

44
means for a spiritual wayfarer to help him to achieve a more elevated state of gnosis, the
relevant theories being considered as mere tools which enable him to proceed along the path
of the noetic (intellectual) service (which means, as soon as he will have passed the relevant
station, they will become useless to him).
But is not such a conclusion a bit hasty and premature?
To get an additional support for my claim, I shall now turn to some of Ibn al- ‘Arabī’s ideas
regarding causation – the ideas, reflection upon which will, hopefully, enable me to consider
the problem in a broader context of the ‘irfānī thought, so that, when I return later to the
original teaching of Sadrā, this would help me to draw some more decisive conclusions.
As for the Greatest Shaykh, he, like Sadrā, seems to have had a number of apparently
contradictory approaches to the problem. His dominating idea with respect to causation,
however, seems to be that of a complete inclusion of the effect in its cause, as far as its
existence is considered. To demonstrate this, Ibn al-‘Arabī uses two mathematical proofs. The
first proof is an arithmetic one and deals with the numerical unity:
“[All] numbers became manifest from the [number] “one”, in line with their certain ranks and,
consequently, the “one” brought the numbers into existence and the numbers divided the
“one”.157
By this statement, Ibn al-‘Arabī confirms that all numbers are actually included in “one”. As
every number is, in fact, “one”, repeated a certain number of times, it is, therefore, nothing
else than a sum of “ones” and, as such, a derivative from “one”.
In the Futūhāt, the same idea of the complete inclusion of the effect in its cause is expressed
in geometrical terms:
“The cosmos in itself is like the point in the centre of the circle, the encompassing
circumference of the circle and what is between them. The point [in the centre] is the Real (al-
haqq) and the empty space outside the circumference is non-existence (‘adam) or darkness, and
what is between the point in the centre and the empty space outside the circumference of the
circle, is the contingent [existence]… and we have given the [central] point because it is the
principle of the existence of the encompassing circumference (of the circle), which becomes
manifest by means of the point; and the contingent [existence], likewise, does not become
manifest [in any other way], except through the Real. Now, as for the circumference, if we
imagine lines [, leading] from the centre of the circle to the circumference, [– lines] which do
not end anywhere else except the point in the centre, then each of them, in such a case, will be
[a part] of this point [in the centre of the circle] [as its extension]”.158
However, an element of simplification is always present in such mathematical proofs, used to
demonstrate the validity of a certain metaphysical truth.
“He is indeed every thing in [His] manifestation and [, at the same time,] He is not the things in
His Essence – may He be Transcendent and Exalted! – but He is He and the things are the
things”.159
In other words, we can speak of the Real’s identity with the things only in the aspect of its
manifestation, regarding it as the Unbounded Existence/ Finding (al-wujūd al-mutlaq) and the

157
Ibn al-‘Arabī, Fusūs, 77. Cf. C. Dagli’s translation in: Muhyi al-Dīn Ibn al-‘Arabī, The Ringstones of
Wisdom, translated by Caner K. Dagli, Chicago: Kazi Publications 2004, 102.
158
Ibn al-‘Arabī, Futūhāt, part 3, 275. Russian scholar Andrey Smirnov gives a more detailed account of Ibn
‘Arabī’s views on the problem of causation in his excellent article: А.Смирнов, «Что стоит за термином
«средневековая арабская философия»» (“What do we mean by “Medieval Arabic Philosophy”) in the
Средневековая арабская философия (Mediaeval Arabic Philosophy) Moсква: Восточная литература
1998. 78–81).
159
Ibn al-‘Arabī, Futūhāt , part 2, 638.

45
Breath of the Compassionate (al-nafas al-rahmān), i.e., if we view it as the Manifest One (al-
Zāhir) and admit that the Manifest One, the manifestation (zuhūr) and the locus of
manifestation (mazhar) is one and the same thing, then we can say, the Real is, in this aspect,
identical with all things, as far as it is the Manifest One, as long as the manifestation
continues.
However, Abu ’l-‘Alā ‘Afīfī believes that, for Ibn al-‘Arabī, ”the causes are immaterial – or,
as it is said, non-existent (ghayr wujūdiyya) entities”160, i.e., the Divine Names. ”Indeed,” –
writes ‘Afīfī – they (the aforementioned entities –J.E.) are the causes of all existents, which
means they are universal intelligible realities which are manifested in forms of the outer
world… and the Divine Essence in the aspect in which it is considered in itself, i.e., as one
shorn of all attributes, which are attributed to it, is not the cause of any effect; and, indeed, it
is the cause of the existence/ finding of every effect in the aspect in which its attributes,
manifest in every part of existence/ finding, are attributed to it”.161
As I see it, two ‘Afīfī’s key points are, first, that the problem of causation is related to the
station of (differentiated) oneness (maqām al-wāhidiyya), not to the station of uniqueness
(=undifferentiated oneness) (maqām al-ahadiyya); second, that the true nature and the
essential character of every existent, according to Ibn al-‘Arabī, is determined by its “fixed
entity” (al-‘ayn al-thābita) (which is eternally present in the Real’s Knowledge). This
apparently static, quiddity-based view on causation, at first sight, seems to have little in
common with Mullā Sadrā’s dynamic existential vision. However, it must be kept in mind
that the Divine Names are, in fact, nothing else than particular modes (shu’ūn) in which we
witness one and the same reality, i.e., the Real’s essence or the True Existence/ Finding.162
To summarize, Ibn al-‘Arabī’s approach to the problem is, as it is peculiar to him, flexible and
multifaceted. What matters, is the way of looking at the issue: in result of the change of the
standpoint the cause and the effect can exchange their particular places, and, for the one who
sees the entirety of truth, “the cause becomes the effect of its effect and [, in turn,] its effect
becomes its cause”.163
Although reflection upon the consequences of a change of the standpoint is an important
element both of Ibn al-‘Arabī and Sadrā’s thought, Sadrā believes that a gradual modification
of the common approach, consisting of a number of apparently insignificant alterations, is
more productive than a sudden revolutionary change.164 In this case, too, the radical idea of
Ibn al-‘Arabī of the interchangeability of cause and effect is not supported by Sadrā, as we
can guess from its not being mentioned in his encyclopaedic account. I can suggest that the
idea was unacceptable to Sadrā for, at least, two reasons: first, because, from a purely
philosophical point of view, such an exchange would cause the metamorphosis of the reality
(inqilāb al-haqīqa), i.e., the cause, as far as it is considered as the cause, cannot become the
effect; second, because, according to the principles of the principality of existence/ finding
and the analogical gradation (tashkīk) of it, the existence/ finding of the cause is always
stronger and of more intensity than that of the effect. It is, therefore, impossible that the
weaker existent becomes the cause of the stronger one.

160
Ibn al-‘Arabī, Fusūs, part 2 (the commentaries), 247.
161
Ibn al-‘Arabī, Fusūs, part 2, 247.
162
Hence, every particular problem we encounter – such as the problem of causation – to a degree is caused by
the particular mode in which we witness the Reality.
163
Ibn al-‘Arabī, Fusūs, part 1, 185.
164
To understand this better, one has to compare the ideas of the “new creation” (khalq jadīd) and the
“substantial motion” (al-haraka al-jawhariyya) – two basic principles of Ibn al-‘Arabī and Sadrā’s teachings,
respectively (see the subchapter 2.3.6).

46
More importantly perhaps, for a mystic who professes the individual oneness of existence/
finding, there is no point to speak of the interchangeability of what is one as an individual –
his main concern is to witness this oneness (or rather as it is often said, to contemplate the
oneness in the manyness and the manyness in the oneness”).
Now I shall quote a passage from the Asfār which, I believe, could be regarded as an epitome
of Sadrā’s gnostic view on causation:
“… it has been unveiled that everything which can be named “existence/ finding”, whatever
kind of existence/ finding it be, is nothing else but one of the modes (shu’ūn) of the One [-and-]
the Eternal and one of the qualities (nu‘ūt) of its essence, and one of the flashes (lama‘āt) of its
attributes; and, consequently, what was stated at the beginning, that there is the cause and the
effect found, was stated in accordance with the remarkable theoretical view – but, eventually, in
keeping with the gnostic wayfaring, this [statement] was transformed into [an assertion] that, of
these two, the cause is a real thing, but the effect is [only] one of its aspects (jihāt), and [that]
causation and what is called the cause and its impact (ta’thīr) upon the effect, can be reduced to
the cause’s phasing (tatawwur) itself in a [certain] phase (tawr)165 and featuring (tahayyuth)
itself in a [certain] feature, [and that the effect is] not a real thing, [actually] differing from it
(the cause – J.E.)”.166
This gnostic approach, as we see, results in the denial of any ontological independence of the
effect and in a complete inclusion of its existence/ finding in the existence/ finding of its
cause. Whatever relation there exists between the cause and the effect, therefore, is not a
categorical (maqūliyya), but an illuminative (ishrāqiyya) one167 – i.e., a relation which
consists of an illuminating thing (mushriq) and its illumination (ishrāq) (e.g. the
aforementioned relation between the sun and its rays or that between the speaker and his
speech). As there is no real encounter (taqābul) of two different things in such a relation, the
relation (idāfa) being also the related thing (mudāf), it is clear that, from a logical point of
view, it is a metaphorical (majāzī), not a real (haqīqī) one, – wherefore we can, perhaps, say
that, for a mystic who professes the individual oneness of existence/ finding, the whole
problem of causation (like many other philosophical issues) is based on a metaphor (i.e., a
metaphorical relation between what is, in fact, one), not upon a reality, because, as Sadrā
himself states it:
"… the existent (mawjūd) and the existence/ finding (wujūd) are confined to one individual
reality which has no companion in true existentiality (mawjūdiyya) and has no peer (literally:
“second” (al-thānī) – J.E.) in its entity (fī ’l-‘ayn), and, in the dwelling of Existence/ Finding,
there is not anyone else, except the Dweller".168
Now, when it has become evident that Sadrā believes the traditional Peripatetic approach to
causation to be superficial and lacking due insight, there arises a question why he pays so
much attention to it, at least in the Asfār. The simplest answer is, possibly, that Sadrā regards
Peripatetic philosophy as the necessary propaedeutic (preparatory study) which has to be
studied before the students could be introduced to what can be called the "Transcendent
Philosophy" (al-hikma al-muta‘āliyya) in the proper sense of the term. As Sadrā definitely

165
Of course, by employing these terms (tawr; tatawwur) Sadrā alludes to the principle of the “substantial
motion”. It seems, however, that, since this principle does not pertain to the world of pure intelligibles (al-
ma‘qulāt al-mahda), the employment of a more general term – “modification” (tasha’un) would be more
appropriate to the purpose.
166
Sadrā, Asfār, part 2, 300–301.
167
The term "illuminative relation" (al-idāfa al-ishrāqiyya) was invented by Suhrawardī (see: Sohravardi,
Oeuvres, t. 1, 487). However, Sadrā interprets it in a very different way (see my article: J.Eshots,
“Unification of Perceiver and Perceived and unity of Being” in the Transcendent Philosophy, Vol. 1, № 3,
December 2000, 1–7).
168
Sadrā, Asfār, part 2, 292.

47
thinks his "Transcendent Wisdom" to be the best possible combination of theoretical and
practical parts of wisdom, it is clear that ascetic practices and sound theoretical background
are equally important constituents of his system, as his goal is to reach the place “where the
two seas meet".
As for Sadrā’s method of theoretical discourse, his well-known saying is: “We agree with
them in the beginnings and differ from them in the ends”169 (in other words, “we begin our
discourse in the usual manner of the Peripatetics (and the Illuminationists), but we end it in a
completely different way”). In brief, not infrequently in the Asfār Sadrā starts to discuss a
particular problem with a commonplace of Peripatetic (Avicennan) philosophy, then, slightly
changing and gradually altering it, slowly shifts the matter into the precincts of 'irfān – and
eventually we find ourselves in the gnostic sanctuary of Oneness (haram al-wahda) – or
rather find the Oneness and lose ourselves. The methodological basis of this approach is, of
course, the principle of the “substantial motion”. As for the choice of the starting point, it
seems to be determined by the supposed audience to which the particular work (the Asfār) is
addressed.170 Now, if we agree with James Morris that Sadrā’s immediate audience is “a
narrow group of highly educated scholars, trained for the most part in the religious schools
and at least superficially acquainted with the various theoretical disciplines… treated in his
philosophy”,171 it becomes evident why Sadrā had to start thence whence he started, i.e., from
the commonplaces of Avicennan philosophy: unlike popular Sufi teachings, intended for
common people, his teaching is meant for the learned ones – no wonder, therefore, that the
way in which he addresses them has to be match their learning and dignity. Besides,
causation, which is one of the most important problems of Peripatetic philosophy, certainly
seemed to Sadrā to be a particularly suitable topic to discuss in order to show the superiority
of the Gnostic approach to the philosophical one. By highlighting the universality of the
principles of the principality and oneness of existence/ finding, Sadrā showed the limited
applicability of such key concepts of Peripatetic philosophy as “cause” and “effect” and
demonstrated that, from the standpoint of the professors of the individual oneness of
existence/ finding, every duality (“twoness”) is only a metaphor.
“[In the beginning] was [only] God and nothing was with Him” – “and even now the case has
not changed”.172

1.2.4. God as the Necessarily Existent/ Found: The Proof of the Sincere

That all cosmological proofs of the Necessarily Existent, as ones that point to the cause by its
effect, possess a certain inconclusiveness and uncertainty, was well realized by the brightest
minds of Islamic Peripaticism, first of all, by Ibn Sīnā, therefore they attempted, to quote
Avicenna himself, “to adduce evidence through Him, not towards Him”173, i.e., to prove the

169
Sadrā, Asfār, part 1, 423, footnote 3 (where the statement is quoted by Sabzavārī).
170
For audiences towards which Sadrā’s writings were originally directed see more: J.W.Morris (transl.) The
Wisdom of the Throne, Princeton: Princeton University Press 1981, 39–41.
171
Morris, Wisdom, 39.
172
Both the hadīth and Abū ’l-Qāsim al-Junayd’s (the famous Sufi shaykh who died in Baghdad in 298/910)
remark upon hearing it are quoted many times by Sadrā and his commentators. See e.g.: Sadrā, Mashā‘ir, 89
(of the Persian text).
173
Ibn Sīnā, Al-Ishārāt wa ’l-tanbīhāt, ma‘a Sharh Nasīr al-Dīn al-Tūsī, ed. S.Dunyā, Cairo 1960, Vol.3, 483.
The English translation by Toby Mayer: Toby Mayer, “Ibn Sīnā’s Burhān al-siddīqīn” in the Journal of
Islamic Studies 12:1 (2001), 25.

48
Necessary through itself, without referring to the contingent. The question is whether this
objective can be achieved by means of philosophy in principle.
Ibn Sīnā made an attempt to fulfil the task in his famous burhān al-siddiqīn (proof of the
sincere).174 In brief, it can be reduced to the following: there is no doubt that there is
existence/ finding. Every existent is either necessarily existent in itself or contingently
existent in itself.175 If it is contingent, by virtue of its derivation ab extra, it is dependent on
the necessary.176 (The chain of contingents, either finite or infinite, will remain contingent by
its very nature.) Therefore every series composed of causes and effects, be it either finite or
infinite, terminates in the Necessarily Existent through itself.177
Though this proof does not deal with any particular physical phenomenon (such as motion),
evidently, it cannot dispense with adducing evidence of the necessary through the contingent.
By virtue of this, it belongs to the class of assertoric demonstrations (barāhīn ‘anniyya) and,
as such, does not provide us with full certainty.
As it is well known, Sadrā pointed out that Ibn Sīnā’s argument deals with the concept of
existence/ finding (mafhūm al-wujūd) and not with its reality (haqīqa).178 Therefore, he
argued, it cannot be considered as “the way of the sincere” (minhāj al-siddīqīn) in the true
sense of the term. But what about Sadra’s own proof?
It is based on four fundamental ontological premises, namely: 1) the principality of existence/
finding (asālat al-wujūd); 2) the analogically graded oneness (al-wahda al-tashkīkiyya) of
existence/ finding; 3) the principle “what is simple in its reality is all things” (basīt al-haqīqa
kull al-ashyā’); 4) the contingency of poverty (al-imkān al-faqrī)) that results in identifying
the reality of existence/ finding with the Necessary.
Here is the summary of the proof in Sadrā’s own words:
“The reality of existence/ finding, by virtue of its being a simple affair, not having a quiddity,
nor a constituent or a delimiter, is the Necessary itself, requiring the most complete perfection,
infinite in its strength, because every other level of it, which is poorer than this one in strength
(i.e., weaker), is not the pure reality of existence/ finding. Rather, it is the reality of existence/
finding together with a deficiency of it, and the deficiency of every thing is self-evidently other
than that thing [itself], and deficiency of existence/ finding is not existence/ finding – rather [it
is] privation of it, and this privation (=non-existence/ non-finding) accompanies existence/
finding not because of the root of existence/ finding, but because of the existence’s/ finding’s
falling into a subsequent (=descendent) level or [one, coming] after it. And deficiencies and
privations afflict the seconds in their capacity as seconds, and the First is in its most complete
perfection – that which has no limit and, in regard to which, it is impossible to conceive of
anything more complete than itself, and deficiency and poverty grow out of effusing (ifāda) and
making (ja‘l) and also terminate in them, and the he-nesses of the seconds are connected to the
First and their deficiency is aided by its perfection and their poverty (need) – by its
independence”.179

174
The most detailed version of it is to be found in his Ishārāt, namat 3, fusūl 9–15 (Ibn Sīnā, Ishārāt, Vol. 3,
447–455).
175
Ibn Sīnā, Ishārāt, Vol.3, 447. English translation by Mayer: Mayer, “Burhān”, 22.
176
Mayer, “Burhān”, 36.
177
Ibn Sīnā, Ishārāt, Vol.3, 455. English translation by Mayer: Mayer, “Burhān”, 35.
178
Sabzavārī remarks that Sadrā is speaking of the existence itself while Ibn Sīnā uses the concept of existence
to speak of particular existents and to reason to the existence of the Necessary Existent (Sadrā, Asfār, part 6,
21, note 1).
179
Sadrā, Asfār, part 6, 24.

49
If the reality of existence/ finding is not the Necessary, says Sadrā, then it is not the reality of
existence/ finding either, since necessity is one of its properties (ahkām). It should be noted
that he identifies the Necessary (wājib) with the Independent (ghanī) and the contingent
(mumkin) with the poor and needy (faqīr). The poverty of the latter is caused by deficiency of
existence/ finding, which means that the poor is poor in so far as it is not sheer existence/
finding (while the independent is independent exactly through its being pure existence/
finding). Hence, by its very nature, sheer existence/ finding does not admit poverty and need,
independence being its innate property. In the last analysis, all other existents except the
reality of existence/ finding are nothing but illuminative relations (al-idāfat al-ishrāqiyya),
modes (shu’ūn) and directions (jihāt) of this reality. As such, they can only be called
“existence/ finding” metaphorically, since they do not refer to the meaning of (the reality of)
existence/ finding by their essences.180 Thus, the individual oneness of existence/ finding is
established. Since existence/ finding is one, it cannot depend on anything else – simply
because there is none other to depend on (I do not take into account privations and deficiencies,
which result in sheer non-existence/ non-finding).
This reasoning allows us to realize the metaphorical character of the necessary – contingent
dichotomy and simultaneously shows us that the real cannot be truly proved through the
metaphorical. Hence, we can say that what Sadrā actually proved – whether intentionally or
not – was the philosophy’s inability to demonstrate its first principles – in particular, to prove
the reality of existence/ finding – which suggested its need for some kind of mystical
intuition.
It is worth mentioning that, to the best of my knowledge, unlike Ibn Sīnā, Sadrā never uses
the exact term burhān al-siddīqīn. As a rule, he replaces burhān with minhāj (‘way’), thus
indicating that the way of the sincere lies beyond the limits of philosophy proper. Moreover,
if Ibn Sīnā and his commentator Nasīr al-Dīn al-Tūsī (597/1201-672/1274) understand the
term siddīqūn simply as a synonym for “divine sages” or “metaphysicians” (ilāhiyyūn),
Sadrā’s understanding of it is different. While in his philosophical works (like the Asfār) he
suffices with a slightly altered definition of Ibn Sīnā, describing the siddīqūn as those who
adduce evidence (yastashhidūna) through Him towards Him181, in his Tafsīr, in the
commentary upon the eighteenth verse of the surah “The Iron”: “and Those who believe in
God and His Messengers – they are the Sincere”, Sadrā gives a more detailed explanation of
what he understands by the term “sincere” (siddīq):
“… the true faith of unveiling (kashf) [is] that which is possessed by [God’s] clients and chosen
mystics, and, indeed, they are the sincere (=attestants) (siddīqūn) and the witnessers (shuhadā’),
due to the utmost degree of their attesting (tasdīq), acquired through unveiling, and their passing
away (fanā’) from themselves, acquired through an inner [spiritual] struggle with the soul and
its commanding faculties.”182
Then he discusses at length four different levels of faith. The fourth and the highest level,
claims he, is that possessed by God’s clients, the sincere and the witnessers:
“The fourth [level] [consists in] witnessing this (the objects of faith – J.E.) through witnessing
the Real Existence/ Finding, and its attributes and traces, and in not seeing [these] acts and
traces as an independent existence/ finding, and in not looking at a thing without seeing in it the
Real, given the difference of mirrors in limpidity and turbidity, and the difference of the Real’s
manifestation in them in disclosedness and hiddenness.

180
Instead, they refer to existence together with deficiency of it, i.e., to insufficiency and poverty of existence.
181
Sadrā, Asfār, part 6, 13.
182
Sadrā, Tafsīr, Vol. 6, 229.

50
And the lights of undifferentiated unity (ahadiyya) have taken possession of such a servant, and
the blinding lights (sawāte‘) of the divine tremendousness (‘azama) have manifested themselves
to him, and they have turned him into crumbled dust183, and [thus] the mountain of his ipseity is
destroyed, and it collapses before him, and, at this station, the “others” perish from his view and
in his light the veils and curtains burn away, and the Real calls: “Whose is the kingdom today?”
and answers itself to itself: “God’s, the One, the Overwhelming” (40:16)184. And at this level the
faithful (mū’min) is called “[God’s] client” (walī), “sincere” (siddīq) and “witnesser” (shahīd).
…and [this faithful] is [called] “the sincere” because the perfection of the level of the sincere is
engendered by the perfection of the level of gnosis (ma‘rifa), and the most perfect level of
gnosis is witnessing (mushāhada), and the one who has witnessed the Real Existence/ Finding
and its level in perfection, and the all-enconpassingness of [its] effusion and the all-
inclusiveness of the mercy, pouring from it upon every thing, in such a way that there is no
partner to it either in existence/ finding, or in bestowing existence (ījād), is the most tremendous
sincere (=attestant) (al-siddīq al-a‘zam) – not anyone else, of those who have not known the
Real and its effusion otherwise than through a proof (dalīl) or by following authority (taqlīd),
without insight (basīra) and unveiling.”185
In the above quotation Sadrā’s gnostic understanding of the term siddīq is quite unmistakable:
the siddīqūn are none but those who have witnessed the Real through unveiling. Those who
know Him through a proof only, cannot be regarded as such. Thus, the minhāj al-siddīqīn is,
in fact, the way of mystics. Needless to say, it can hardly be travelled by means of logical
reasoning.
The late Tabātabā’ī wrote a few insightful glosses upon Sadrā’s discourse of the minhāj al-
siddīqīn, in which he pointed out that all ontological proofs of the Necessarily Existent are by
necessity assertoric (‘anniyya) ones, because we travel in them from some concomitants
(lawāzim) of existence/ finding (such as its being a reality fixed by its own essence or its
being the first cause) to some other (such as its being necessary through its essence).186
Of course, he was absolutely right – and so was he when he remarked that the principle of the
existence/ finding of the Necessary through essence is self evident (darūrī) to the human
being and that the demonstrations of it are, in fact, nothing but alertings (tanbīhāt).187
However, this was not necessarily due to Sadrā’s lack of insight and inability to distinguish
between philosophical and mystical approaches that he mixed them together (leaving it for
cleverer people of later generations to make the distinction). Rather, it seems that he did this
on purpose, in order to show the Peripatetic philosophers the limits of their method by
pointing out to its inability to conclusively prove its first principles, for which it can only give
assertoric demonstrations.
It is important to note that the key passage of the Asfār on the minhāj al-siddiqīn is based on
the supposition of the cause – effect relationship between different levels of wujūd (“the
reality of wujūd does not have any imperfection, and the imperfection afflicts wujūd due to its
being caused (ma‘lūliyya), and it is so because the effect can not equal its cause in the
excellence of existence/ finding ”188) as well as that of the specific oneness (the oneness of

183
An allusion to the Qur’anic verse: “and when His Lord disclosed Himself to the mountain, He made it
crumble to dust and Moses fell down thunderstruck” (7:143) (Qur‘ān, 128).
184
The English translation of the Qur’anic verse by Chittick: W.C.Chittick, The Sufi Path of Knowledge: Ibn al-
‘Arabi’s Metaphysics of Imagination, New York: SUNY Press 1989, 433.
185
Sadrā, Tafsīr, Vol. 6, 232.
186
Sadrā, Asfār, part 6, 29, note 1.
187
Sadrā, Asfār, part 6, 14, note 3.
188
Sadrā, Asfār, part 6, 16.

51
species) (al-wahda al-naw‘iyya) of existence/ finding (“there is no essential difference
between its instances (afrād) except in perfection and imperfection, and strength and
weakness, or due to additional affairs, as it is the case with the individuals of the same
quiddity of species”189). Now, one knows that elsewhere Sadrā dismisses both suppositions as
non-applicable to the reality of existence/ finding as the possessor of individual oneness
(“… and such is the case with the individual oneness (al-wahda al-shakhsiyya), which is the
very reality of existence/ finding in the eyes of the deeply-rooted [in knowledge] through a
special proof of Existence/ Finding …”190) – the reality, whose effects are nothing but its
directions (jihāt) and stages (atwār)191 (and, as such, they enjoy only metaphorical – not real –
wujūd). Hence, it is evident that the whole argument, as presented in the Asfār, is based on at
least two suppositions, which, though not outright false, are gross simplifications. By
necessity, the argument itself is also a simplification – a simplified discursive explanation of
an experiental issue, I would say.

***

Sadrā’s approach to the reality of existence/ finding represents a mixture between Platonic
and Aristotelian approaches. Like Aristotle, Sadrā believes it to be simple/ non-compound
(basīt). Like Plato, he believes it to infinitely surpass all other kinds of existence/ finding in
terms of strength/ intensity (shidda). Hence, the two main characteristics by which it differs
from the rest of wujūd are absolute simplicity/ non-compoundedness (basāta) and infinite
strength/ intensity (shadda).
Among the few passages in Sadrā’s works in which he attempts to give a sort of definition of
the reality of existence/ finding, the following one in the Mashā‘ir seems to be particularly
illustrative:
“By the “reality of existence/ finding” we mean that [kind of existence/ finding] to which
nothing, except pure existence/ finding is admixed, be it (the admixture – J.E.) either a limit
(hadd), or an end (nihāya), or an imperfection, or universality, or particularity, and it (the reality
of existence/ finding – J.E.) is [also] called the “Necessarily Existent/ Found” (wājib al-
wujūd)”.192
In the above quoted definition Sadrā treats the reality of existence/ finding as the pure idea of
existence/ finding – namely, as the existence/ finding unalloyed with any admixture and
impurity and, therefore, infinitely intense. Due to its purity and unalloyedness, this idea or
reality of existence/ finding relates to other kinds of existence/ finding as the highest level to
the lower ones (which are fully included in the former), as the following passage from the
same treatise also seems to confirm:
“Indeed, the whole of existence/ finding, regardless of the difference between its species and the
instances of its quiddity and the dissimilarity between its genera and differentiae in respect of
[their] limits (=definitions) and realities, is a single substance, possessing a single he-ness
(huwiyya), which [, however,] has high and descendent stations and degrees”.193

189
Sadrā, Asfār, part 6, 15.
190
Sadrā, Asfār, part 1, 179–180.
191
Sadrā, Asfār, part 2, 300–301. See the previous subchapter (1.2.3) and also my paper “The Gnostic Element
of Sadra’s Doctrine on Causation” in the Proceedings of the 2nd International Conference on Mulla Sadra:
Causation according to Mulla Sadra and other Schools of Philosophy. 5-6 May 2001 – SOAS (London),
London: Salman – Azade Press 2003, 86–98.
192
Sadrā, Mashā‘ir, 45 (of the Arabic text).
193
Sadrā, Mashā‘ir, 5 (of the Arabic text).

52
I would venture to assert that, all in all considered, Sadrā’s general treatment of the issue of
existence/ finding is predominantly Platonic, because this is exactly the Platonic doctrine of
the (realm of) forms/ archetypes, which necessitates the analogical gradation of existence/
finding, situating the pure and infinitely intense idea or reality (haqīqa) of existence/ finding
at the top of the pyramid of wujūd and its infinitely weak and extremely alloyed with the
impurities of matter tenuity (raqīqa) at its base.
The Sufi treatment of wujūd as self-awareness/ consciousness, although it was well known to
Sadrā, appears to have been unacceptable to him – mainly because he seems to have believed
that this approach is incompatible with the Platonic one. Hence, his transcendent philosophy
(al-hikma al-muta‘āliyya) should be qualified as a modification of Platonism (Platonism of
wujūd). Sadrā admitted the validity of the Sufi teaching on the individual oneness of
existence/ finding, but, apparently, understood that it will not be accepted by those wayfarers
who have not as yet experienced certain inner transformation (“the Greater Rising”).
Therefore, he built the greatest part of his discourse on the premises of the oneness of the
species of wujūd and its analogical gradation.

53
CHAPTER 2. HORIZONS OF WUJŪD: SADRĀ’S COSMOLOGY

2.1. THE CONCEPT OF CREATION IN KALĀM, PHILOSOPHY AND ‘IRFĀN

The underlying vision and basic intuition of Sadrā’s philosophy is one of constant flow and
perpetual motion towards perfection. The elements of other philosophical and mystical
teachings, in particular those of Ibn Sīnā and Ibn al-‘Arabī, serve Sadrā as rough building
material. Therefore, Sadrā’s treatment of the cosmological theories of Peripaticism and
theoretical mysticism should be qualified as radical reshaping, not merely an adjustment. I
shall try to demonstrate the veracity of this statement in the present chapter.
Although the theories on creation and development of the cosmos that appeared in Muslim
thought since the time of the Mu‘tazilites (the first philosophical school in the world of Islam)
have been examined by other researchers in sufficient detail, I shall, nevertheless, make an
attempt to present a sketchy outline of the major trends found in these teachings, in order to
have an opportunity to consider Sadrā’s own theory against the background of those of his
most important predecessors.
This task is, however, complicated by the obvious diversity of approaches taken by different
schools and individuals, which is reflected in the diversity of the employed terms. Apparently,
the most general terms used to describe the act of creation (but also its product) is khalq
(designating creation as production of some new thing on a previously unemployed pattern or
the determination of the proportions (taqdīr) of something which is to be brought into
existence194 ). In the aforementioned sense the term khalq is used mainly by the theologians
(mutakallimūn) and mystics, while the philosophers seem to prefer either the very general fi‘l
(‘act’) or hudūth (literally ‘happening, occurrence’, in theological sense – ‘origination’). The
difficulty with the terms fi‘l and khalq is that, depending on the context, they can mean either
the act, or its product, and not infrequently it is possible to read them in both meanings. This,
fortunately, is not the case with hudūth (if understood as the ‘new arrival’ or ‘origination’). A
newly arrived thing is named hādith or muhdath, but never hudūth, whence the possibility of
confusion is excluded. It seems that the early Mutakallimūn always understood hudūth as new
arrival in time, that is, as temporal origination (in which sense it is the opposite of qidam
(literally ‘oldness, antiquity’, technically – ‘eternity’), considering the former as an essential
attribute of creation (created world) and the latter – as that of God. (Indeed, as creatures that
enjoy a temporally limited existence, we can only testify to God’s oldness and His being
ancient, i.e., much older than ourselves and everything around us. The notion of eternity
proper is beyond our understanding.) With the appearance of other theories on the subject
among the Muslim Peripatetics this sort of new arrival in time or temporal origination came to
be known as hudūth zamānī.
The Peripatetic philosophers believed the physical world to be eternal. For this reason, they
maintained the applicability of the principle of temporal creation only to certain parts of the
world, namely to the existents of the sublunary sphere, the domain of engendered existence
and corruption (kawn wa fasād), not to the world as a whole. What applied to the world in its
entirety, according to Ibn Sīnā and his followers, was the principle of hudūth dhātī (‘the
essential origination’). That is, the Peripatetics believed the world to be created in its essence,
not in time. This “essential origination” was, in fact, just another name for contingency:
according to the falāsifa (Peripatetic philosophers), the world had a principle outside it, which
perpetually necessitated its existence, while in its essence it remained forever contingent. The
actual meaning of the essential origination (hudūth dhātī), thus, can be described as making
194
See: R.Arnaldez, “Khalq” (IV.980a) in Encyclopaedia of Islam, 2nd edition (CD-ROM), Leiden: Brill 1999.

54
the world “necessary through the other” (wājib bi ghayrihi). This borrowed necessity of the
world was understood by the falāsifa as its perpetual support by the Necessarily Existent and
the former’s subsistence through the latter. In other words, God was regarded as the
existential cause (‘illa wujūdiyya) of the world and the world – as God’s existential effect.
Therefore, creation could by no means be regarded as a single instantaneous act (as most of
the Mutakallimūn were inclined to think). On the contrary, it was an everlasting act of the
Necessary – the perpetual endowment of the contingent with existence.
On this point, there was no principal disagreement between the philosophers and the mystics,
although the exact terms, in which the idea of God’s perpetual support of the world was
expressed, were quite different in each tradition. Creation definitely was not the main concern
of Ibn Sīnā and his followers, who considered the God – world relationship, first and
foremost, in terms of necessity and contingency195, wherefore, in the last analysis, creation
came down to the necessary’s lending existence to the contingent. Thus, in his Al-Mabda’ wa
’l-ma‘ād (“Beginning and the End”) Ibn Sīnā says:
“Innovation (ibdā‘) is perpetual making “something” (ta’yyis) what is “nothing” (lays) in its
essence, in such a way which does not depend on any other cause except the essence of the First
One, without the intermediation of any matter, tool, meaning and interconnection”.196
Similarly, in the Ta‘līqāt (“Explanatory Notes”) he describes the “newly arrived” (muhdath)
as “everything that becomes “something” after being absolutely “nothing”, that is, after its
being non-existent in its essence, not in a certain state of existence”.197
It is easy to notice that, while Ibn Sīnā describes creation in its absolute sense as perpetuity
(the Necessary’s perpetual giving existence to the contingent or its perpetual providing the
latter with “somethingness”), this perpetuity is understood by him as something static and not
subject to change and development. What is contingent in itself, can become necessary
through the other. However, there is no way in which its contingent essence could increase in
its strength and intensity and gradually approach the domain of necessity. Nor is “giving
perpetuity” (idāma) thought as infinite series of instantaneous bringing the thing into
existence and immediate depriving it of the latter, in order to replace it with its likeness
(mithāl) in the following instant.
Apart from creation in its absolute sense, Islamic philosophy deals with a number of
phenomena which can be described as relative or limited creation and each of which represent
a creation of certain kind. Usually, the philosophers distinguish three of them: ibdā‘ in the
narrower sense (creation of the Intellect and intelligible affairs), khalq in the narrower sense
(creation of natural existents) and takwīn (creation of those compound natural existents which
are subject to engendering and corruption).198
In its narrower sense, the term ibdā‘ describes the production, without the anteriority of
matter or time, of incorruptible and eternal existents, whether incorporeal (the separated
intellects) or corporeal (the celestial spheres).199 The Isma‘ili philosophers (e.g. Abū Ya‘qūb
al-Sijistānī200) usually consider the term in connection with the divine command “Be!” (Kun!)

195
Among the most recent publications on this topic, see especially: T. Mayer, “Burhān”.
196
Ibn Sīnā, al-Mabda’ wa ’l-ma‘ād, ed. A.Nūrānī, Tehrān: Intishārāt-i mo’assisa-i motāle‘āt-i islāmī
dāneshgāh-i Mac Gill (shu‘ba-i Tehrān) 1984, 77.
197
Ibn Sīnā, al-Ta‘līqāt, ed. A.Badavī, Qum: Būstān-i Kitāb Press 1379 S.H., 98.
198
See e.g.: Sadrā, Tafsīr, Vol.1, 218.
199
See: L.Gardet, “Ibda’” (III.663b) in the Encyclopaedia of Islam.
200
See: Abū Ya‘qūb al-Sijistānī, “Kitāb al-Yanābi’”, § 40 in Henry Corbin, Trilogie ismaelienne, Teheran-Paris:
Librairie Adrien Maisonneuve 1961.

55
(36:82)201, through which the primordial establishing of the world takes place. Ismai‘ili
thinkers often oppose the world of these incorruptible and eternal existents (‘ālam al-
mubda‘āt) (or the world of Command (‘ālam al-amr)) to that of the natural ones (‘ālam al-
makhlūqāt).
The basic concept employed by Sadrā to describe God’s creative activity is the concept of
speech (kalām). Speech is an attribute of the speaker and subsists through him by the
subsistence of the act through the actor. The speaker brings speech into existence through his
breath (nafas), that is, the air that comes out from his bosom.202
Quoting one of the mystics of Ibn al-‘Arabī school, Sadrā writes:
“The world did not become manifest otherwise than through [God’s] Speech – or, rather, the
world in its entirety is nothing but different kinds of speech, in accordance with its twenty-eight
stations and way-stations found in the Breath of the Merciful, which is an existential effusion
pouring out from the spring of effusing and mercy, whereas the contingents are entifications of
this existential effusion. The intelligible substances are the higher letters (hurūf ‘āliyyāt), which
are God’s perfect words (kalimāt Allāh al-tāmāt) – the ones which neither perish, nor become
less perfect. The corporeal substances are nominal and actual compound existents (murakkabāt
ismiyya wa fi‘liyya) that are subject to disintegration (tahlīl) and corruption (fasād), and to their
separated and concomitant attributes and accidents, like flexibility (binā’) and non-flexibility
(i‘rāb). And all of them (i.e., intelligibles and bodies – J.E.) subsist through the existential
Breath of the Merciful, which in their terminology is called “the Real through which creation
takes place” (al-haqq al-makhlūq bihi)203, like the letters and words subsist through the breath of
the speaker – a human being created in the form of the Merciful, in accordance with its (the
Breath’s – J.E.) way-station and places of articulation (makhārij)”.204
The above quotation (as well as a good number of similar ones found in Sadrā’s writings)
testifies that he considered the terminology of Sufi mysticism and Kalām to be more adequate
for description of creational processes than the language of Avicennan philosophy. All
creatures, whether spiritual or corporeal, are God’s words (kalimāt Allāh), and, therefore, are
articulations and entifications of His inarticulate and non-entified Speech, creative energy or
Breath of the Merciful. The speech becomes articulate when the breath subsequently passes
through a number of the places of articulation (makhārij al-hurūf) and twenty-eight principal
articulations are brought into existence. Arranged in different sequences, these articulations
form words.
In respect to the way in which they are intended, three kinds of words can be distinguished.
“Know that the first intention (gharad) of the speaker in [his] desire (irāda) of speech is the
configuration (inshā’) of the entities of letters and words and bringing them into existence from
the hidden thought (damīr) to the places of articulation, and this is the entity of communication
(i‘lām). But necessitating a trace (athar), in keeping with a [certain] command, prohibition,
reporting (ikhbār), wish (tamannā’), summoning (nidā’), inquiry (istifhām) or else, is the
second intended and the second furthest limit (ghāya), apart from making known, because there
are three kinds of speech: the highest, the medium and the lowest. The highest speech is the one,
in which the speech itself is the first essential intended, and there is no nobler and more
important intended than it due to its being the furthest limit to what comes after it. And this is
like the innovation of the world of Command through His word: “Be!” and [through] nothing

201
Qur’an, 373.
202
See: Sadrā, Asfār, part 7, 3–4.
203
The term, which is employed by Ibn al-‘Arabī in the Futūhāt several times (II 60:12, 104: 6; III 77: 25),
apparently belongs to the Seville Sufi ‘Abd al-Salām Ibn Barrajān (d. 536/1141) (on him, see, e. g.:
Muhammed al-‘Adlūnī al-Idrīsī, at-Tasawwuf al-andalūsī: asusuhu an-nazariyya wa ahamm madārisahu,
Casablanca: Dār al-thaqāfa 2005, 83–90).
204
Sadrā, Asfār, part 7, 5.

56
else, and they (the innovated substances – J.E.) are God’s perfect words and the realities
(inniyāt) of the intelligibles – the ones which neither perish, nor become less perfect… and
God’s intention in configurating them is nothing but His command…
The medium kind of speech is that in which the speech has another intended (maqsūd) (i.e.,
object – J.E.) apart from the speech itself, but this second intended is necessitated by it (the
speech – J.E.) as a concomitant without a possibility of detachment (infikāk) in actual fact (fī ’l-
wāqi‘). This is like the command to the celestial angels and the governors of the heavenly
spheres and luminaries to [perform] what He has obligated them to perform, that is, the acts of
governance (tadbīrāt), giving movement (tahrīkāt) and yearning (ashwāq), and the acts of
worship (‘ibādāt) and devotion in respect to other intelligible furthest limits, and inevitably they
“disobey not God in what He commands them” (66:6).205 The same is the case with the angels
of earthly natures and elemental bodies, such as the governors of mountains, seas, clouds, winds
and rains. Whenever God’s command reaches them – either without an intermediary or through
the intermediation of another command, not through the intermediation of [natural] creation
(khalq) – they obey it and do not revolt.
The lowest kind of speech is the one in which the entity of speech has another intended and at
times it (the intended – J.E.) does not oppose the speech, and at times it does. Even if the
intended does not oppose the speech, there is a possibility of its opposition and disobedience,
since in this case it is not preserved from an error and disobedience. An example of this sort of
speech is God’s command to the obliged ones (mukallifīn) and His addressing them, namely the
two weighty ones (al-thaqalān), that is the jinn and the people, through the intermediation of
descending the kingdom (mulk) and dispatching the messengers”.206
This theory is an extension and elaboration of the well-known Ibn al-‘Arabī’s teaching on two
kinds of Command – the engendering (takwīnī) and prescriptive (taklīfī) ones. The first is
delivered without an intermediary and therefore cannot be disobeyed; the second is delivered
through the intermediation of a law-giving prophet and can be ignored.207 The novelty of
Sadrā’s theory lies in introducing the third kind of command – the innovative one (amr
ibdā‘ī), which represents a sort of speech in which the speech itself is the only intended
(maqsūd) of the speaker. Sadrā places this kind of speech as the first in the hierarchical order.
Importantly, along with God’s innovative and engendering commands (by which the world of
Intellect and the world of Nature, respectively, are brought into existence), Sadrā counts the
third kind of speech – the law-giving command (amr tashrī‘) (i.e., the command given
through/ in the form of a certain religious law brought by one of the great prophets) among
the forms of God’s creative activity. What distinguishes this latter kind of activity from the
others is the object’s ability to resist the creative command and disobey it. For this reason, the
third kind of God’s speech, namely His law-giving command, can be regarded as the highest
one in respect to the freedom of the object. However, while acknowledging that creation is
not complete without this third kind of God’s creative activity – the law-giving (tashrī‘) one
(i.e., without delivering a religious law), I shall currently limit the discussion to the first and
the second kinds, namely innovation (ibdā‘) and engendering (takwīn).

205
The English translation of the Qur’anic verse belongs to W.C.Chittick: Chittick, Self-disclosure, 435.
206
Sadrā, Asfār, part 7, 5–6. Cf. Sadrā, Mafātīh al-ghayb, ed. M.Khājavī, Beirūt: Mu’assasa al-ta’rīkh al-‘arabī
1999, part 1, 93-96 (the passage is examined by C. Dagli in: Caner K. Dagli, “Consciousness and Causation
in Mulla Sadra” in Safavi, Seyed G., Mulla Sadra and Comparative Philosophy on Causation, London:
Salman – Azade Press 2003, 240–241).
207
See e.g.: Chittick, Self-disclosure, 292–294.

57
2.2. THE WORLD OF INNOVATION

Each of the two kinds of God’s creative activity necessitates the existence of the world of its
own. The division of the cosmos into two parts – the world of immaterial and incorruptible
existents and the world of the material and corruptible ones, characteristic of the Isma‘ili
philosophy, is also typical of Sadrā’s thought. Thus, in the Mashā‘ir he writes:
“God’s act (fi‘l) is divided into command (amr) and creation (khalq). This [natural] creation is a
temporally originated one (hādith zamānī)”.208
In the Shawāhid Sadrā refers to the two modes of existence of things and their emergence
from the first governance (al-tadbīr al-awwal) as innovation and engendering:
“The existence of things and their emergence from the first governance occurs in two ways: as
innovation (ibdā‘), which is the emergence of existence from the Necessary [-and-the-] Real
without the participation of the aspect of receptivity (qābiliyya), and as engendering (takwīn),
which depends on the readiness of the receptacle”.209
In general terms, it would not be wrong to assert that, for Sadrā, innovation (ibdā‘) is a
synonym for the Qur’anic “command” (amr) and vice versa. The same seems to be the case
with “creation” (khalq) and “engendering” (takwīn). Yet another pair of synonyms for amr/
ibdā‘ and khalq/ takwīn is ‘aql/ tabī‘a (‘intellect/ nature’) – the terms which Sadrā understands
differently from his predecessors (I shall return to this latter pair of terms a bit later).
The existents of the world of Command or Innovation differ from those of the world of
Creation or Engendering by their immateriality, incorruptibility and lack of quiddity
(māhiya). Since they are immaterial, they are not created in time. Since they are incorruptible,
they are not subject to change and transmutation. Since they do not have quiddity, they do not
differ from God (=the Real) and from each other in their essences: the difference is only in the
degree of (fullness) of reality possessed.
The professors of the principality of existence may perceive the world in terms of the Divine
Speech while the affirmers of the principality of quiddity can see it as the Divine Book.
However, both groups confirm the analogicity between the processes of speech and writing in
the cosmos and the human being. For this reason, Sadrā finds it convenient to describe God’s
creativity in terms of speech. Not only creativity in general, but also its manifestations on
every level of existence (kinds of speech) can be aptly described in these terms, as we see it in
the Asrār al-āyāt (“Mysteries of the Qur’anic Verses”), in the chapter devoted to the
discussion of the issue of “God’s perfect words”:
“Know that between the Originator and the world (i.e., the world of Nature and natural bodies –
J.E.) there are luminous intermediaries and active occasions (asbāb fa‘‘āla), which apparently
stand above creation (khalq), but below the Creator, because they are God’s veils, luminous
pavilions and everlasting radiances, like the radiance of this sensible (mahsūs) sun, which (the
radiance of the sun – J.E.) is like an isthmus between the radiant essence and the things
illuminated by it. These intermediaries are referred to as “God’s words” and the “perfect
words”…
The task of these words is perpetual effusion. Certainly, these intermediaries are simple
existential he-nesses and essences separated from corporeal matters and lifted above the world
of time and place. Since every separated [substance] is a spiritual affair, its existence is identical
with its knowledge and perception. Hence, inevitably, these intermediaries are holy intellects
and noble spirits…

208
Sadrā, Mashā‘ir, 58 (of the Arabic text).
209
Sadrā, Shawāhid, 277.

58
In the aspect of God’s communicating (making known) realities through them, they are called
“words” (kalimāt). In the aspect of their necessitating the existence of engendered things
(kā’ināt) at every moment they are called “God’s command” (amr Allāh) and “His compelling
decree” (qadā’ahu al-hatmī). In the aspect of their maintaining the life of [other] existents, they
are called “the spirit” (al-rūh) …In their essence these [three] are one, but this one is multiplied
through the multiplicity of the kinds of traces, or in respect to the directions of its effusion upon
things, or in respect to its connections (ta‘alluqāt) with them, and becomes many through their
manyness – as it happens with existence, which is one reality, but becomes many through the
manyness of quiddities …
To conclude, God’s word is an existent spiritual affair which supports prophets through
revelation (wahy), inspires God’s clients through charismatic acts (karāmāt) and revivifies the
hearts of the wayfarers among the [true] believers through faith (īmān)”.210
As we see, “words” (kalimāt) is only one of many designations of the intermediaries between
God and the world of Nature, which are thus named in the aspect of their communicating
realities (haqā’īq) through perpetual existential effusion.
In terms of sense perception, the notion of the world of Command as envisaged by Sadrā is
best explained by the symbol of the radiance of the sun: while the radiance is certainly
different from the luminary, it represents itself as its continuation. The peculiarity of this
continuation is the decrease of its intensity (and, therefore, the increase of its weakness) in
proportion with its nearness to the surface of the earth (read: the world of Engendering) and
distance from its source (read: God’s Essence). Another characteristic of this radiance (read:
the world of Command) is its evident and total dependence on its source: as soon as a cloud
hides the sun, the radiance disappears instantly (although its effects and traces (e.g. warmth)
may last for some time). These characteristics allowed Sadrā to describe the world of
Command in its entirety as the “illuminative relation” (al-idāfa al-ishrāqiyya) of God’s
essence, in the same sense in which the radiance of the sun can be called the illuminative
relation of the latter.
As God’s essence is simple in its reality (basīt al-haqīqa), so its extension and “radiance”,
namely the world of Command, is also simple, if it is considered as pure (illuminative)
relation of the former, without taking into consideration its relationship with the world of
Nature and serving as intermediary between God and the engendered existents. If, however, it
is considered in connection with the world of Nature and Engendering, it becomes multiplied
through the multiplicity of its effects and traces upon different parts of the latter. Thus, a ray
which falls on a black surface warms it sooner than a ray which falls on a white one. It is,
however, obvious that the actual differentiation takes place only upon God’s Command’s
entering the realm of Nature.
The existents of the world of Command or Innovation relate to each other as different aspects
and layers of light:
“The world of Command is a single existent in its essence, but it is multiple in respect to the
effusions (ifādāt) and the acts of bringing into existence (ījādāt)… and it is the world of Light,
which in its entirety is [nothing but] levels of divinity, which are like simple (non-compound)
layers that differ in respect of the strength and weakness of their luminosity. Each of the layers
is encompassed and subjugated by the layer which is higher than it [in the hierarchy], and so it
continues up to the Light of Lights, and everything is encompassed by the ruling authority
(sultān) of its light and the assault of its greatness, and obliterated by them”.211

210
Sadrā, Asrār, 74–75.
211
Sadrā, Asrār, 106.

59
Sadrā’s treatment of the realm of immaterial existence in terms of the hierarchy of light was
not a novel one: the merit of replacing the static Aristotelian system of intellects with the
dynamic hierarchy of lights, as it is well known, belongs to Suhrawardī. However, while the
latter concentrated on the general rules and principles of the behaviour of light that apply both
to the separated and material lights, Sadrā focussed his attention mainly on the differences
between the two kinds of light, which resulted, in particular, in his detailed analysis of the
rules that govern the world of material lights, that is, the world of Nature.
Apart from the vertical (or: latitudinal) (tūlī) division, which in the above quotation is
described in terms of subjugated layers or strata, there exists a horizontal (or: longitudinal)
(‘ardī) one – that is, division in respect of the directions towards which a certain segment of
light is focused. This segmental or directional division of the force-field of light represents the
order of the archetypes of engendered existents or their “lords of species” (arbāb al-anwā‘).
This takes us to Sadrā’s treatment of Platonic forms or “likenesses” (al-muthul al-aflātuniyya).
Most researchers either believe that in his treating the issue Sadrā closely followed
Suhrawardī (this seems to be the opinion of S.J.Āshtiyānī212), which is generally truth, but not
a full truth, or hold that he dealt with the issue in a rather confused manner (this appears to be
the substance of Fazlul Rahman’s evaluation213), which is establishing the fact without
discussing its reasons.
I am inclined to think that, what looks like confusion, actually is the result of the unequal
distribution of attention, so characteristic of Sadrā: while some important issues are dealt with
in great ( at times, it seems, almost excessive) detail, he refers to many other significant ones
in passing, in a few remarks scattered among his voluminous writings.
In Sufi view, the entity (‘ayn) of every thing is a product of a series of “marriages” (nikāhāt)
between God’s names, starting from the “mothers of names” (ummahāt al-asmā’), i.e., the
most universal ones, and ending with the most particular. Obviously, entities that belong to
one existential direction (a certain aspect of existence) differ from those that pertain to
another one. If there is any analogue of the Platonic form or “likeness” at all in theoretical
Sufi mysticism (‘irfān nazarī), it is this common existential direction shared by a number of
entities. While each entity itself is a particular name of God, the dominant common
characteristics shared by a number of entities is also a God’s name – a more general and
encompassing one. Thus, the Sufi theorists understand Platonic forms as God’s names or
general existential directions, which are present in the Unbounded Existence – in a
differentiated or undifferentiated way, depending on the level of entification.
Despite the different terminology, employed by the Sufis of Ibn al-‘Arabī school and the
Illuminationist philosophers (Suhrawardī and his followers), their general understanding of
the mechanism of the emergence of the horizontal (or: latitudinal) (‘ardī) division of
existence (i.e., that of existential trends or Platonic forms) appears to be more or less
identical, as far as one can conclude from the few short passages devoted to the topic that are
found in Suhrawardī’s Hikmat al-ishrāq. In particular, he writes:
“The priority of some dominating lights to others is intellectual, not temporal; but no man can
reckon their number or determine their ranks. They are not ordered only vertically, for some are
equal to others. Because the higher lights possess many luminous aspects or interact with each
other, the existence of other equal dominating lights may occur from them. Were this not so,
equal species would not occur. Those dominating lights that come into being from the higher
dominating lights, by virtue of their beholding the Light of Lights and every other higher light,

212
See: S.J. Āshtiyānī, Sharh-i hāl wa ārā’-yi falsafī-yi Mullā Sadrā, 3rd edition, Qum: Būstān-i Kitāb Press
1378 S.H., 221–242 (where the author actually discusses the views of Suhrawardī, not those of Sadrā!).
213
See: Rahman, Philosophy, 46–49 and 147–149.

60
are nobler than those which occur from the aspect of rays. Among the rays, there are also ranks
and levels. Thus, among the dominating lights are mother-lights (cf. “the mothers of names” in
Sufi terminology! – J.E.) – the fundamental vertical lights with few radiant and substantial
intermediaries – while others are lights horizontal in their ranks from intermediate rays”.214
What we learn from this passage about the archetypal lights, comes down to the following: 1)
they are ordered horizontally (latitudinally); 2) they are the product of the interactions of the
intermediate rays that are irradiated by the dominant vertical lights, but not of the mutual
effects of these lights themselves upon each other; 3) they can also be treated as luminous
aspects (or: directions) (jihāt) of the higher lights; 4) there is a sort of gradation in terms of
intensity and weakness between these horizontal lights (e.g. the light of the lord (luminous
intelligible form) of human species is obviously stronger than that of the mosquito); 5)
although this is not stated explicitly, we can conclude that the archetypal lights are a by-
product of the interaction of the higher dominant vertical lights.
Thus, Platonic forms or the luminous lords of species (arbāb al-anwā‘) of material existents
(frequently referred to as “idols” or “talismans”), which dwell in the world of Innovation,
represent the result of the interplay of the rays of the dominant vertical lights. The relationship
of each of these forms or lords of species to its respective species is described by Sadrā in
following words:
“Every corporeal substance has a perfect and complete specimen (fard) in the world of
Innovation, which is the root and the principle, and other specimens are its branches, effects and
traces. This first specimen, due to its completeness and perfection, has no need in any matter
and locus, on which it would depend, which [independence] is not the case with the others.
Indeed, [the rest of them,] due to their weakness and imperfection, have need in matter, either in
their essences or in their acts”.215
One notices that the difference between the lord of species and its vassals (i.e., between a
Platonic form and its “idols”) lies solely in the possessed degree of perfection and intensity.
This difference is not an essential one. Therefore, it is possible to overcome it. This allows us
to conclude that there is not any distinct border between the world of Innovation and that of
Engendering. At least theoretically, the existents that belong to the latter can gradually
transform themselves into those of the former, the vassals thus becoming united with their
respective lords of species. The need for matter and locus can be overcome through increase
in perfection and intensity.
I am aware that the above conclusions, in particular, the statement on the absence of a distinct
borderline between the world of Innovation and that of Engendering, seem to contradict
certain other principles of Sadrā’s cosmology. Thus, in the first part of the third journey of the
Asfār Sadrā states:
“The divine (read: Platonic – J.E.) forms… are simple (=non-compound) existences that differ
from each other. They are not afflicted by contingency… These divine forms do not belong to
the world (i.e., the world of Nature or Engendering – J.E.) and to what is other than God. Their
existence is not different from the Real Existence, and they do not exist in (or: through)
themselves and owing to themselves. Rather they can be counted among the levels of divinity
and stations of Lordship. They exist by one existence [with God] and subsist by one subsistence
[with Him], while the world is “what is other than He”, and it (the world, i.e., the world of
Nature – J.E.) is nothing but bodies, their forms, natures, accidents and matters. The new arrival
(i.e., temporal origination – J.E.) and self-renewing of all of them has been established through
a demonstration, in the discussion on corporeal substances. There is nothing eternal (qadīm) in

214
Suhrawardī, The Philosophy of Illumination, edited and translated into English by John Walbridge and
Hossein Ziai, Provo: Brigham Young University Press 1999, 119.
215
Sadrā, Asfār, part 2, 62.

61
the world [of Nature]. What is eternal, is God, His decree, His knowledge, His command and
His perfect words”.216
Sadrā, thus, seems to altogether deny any difference – except that of intensity – between
God’s Essence (the Unbounded Existence) and the forms of the species present in the world
of Innovation and to count them as part of the realm of Divinity (al-suq‘ al-ilāhiyya).
Moreover, he asserts the eternity (qidam) of these forms (i.e., the lords of species) and the
new arrival (temporal origination) of their “vassals” that pertain to the world of Nature. How
can the eternal become temporally originated and vice versa? A standard answer of a pre-
Sadrian philosopher would be that such becoming is impossible, because it presupposes “an
overthrow (i.e., metamorphosis – J.E.) of the reality (inqilāb al-haqīqa). To Sadrā, however,
eternity and temporal originatedness seem to be no more than characteristics of certain stages
or grades of existence – characteristics, which point to certain degrees of intensity and
weakness of existence, respectively. Weak and unstable existence is commonly referred to as
hādith (‘newly arrived’ or ‘temporally originated’); strong and intense one – as qadīm
(‘eternal’). The totality of strong and intense existents is known as “the world of Innovation”
(‘ālam al-ibdā‘); the entirety of the weak ones – as the “world of Nature” (‘ālam al-tabī‘a)
(while Nature itself is understood as a flowing substance (jawhar sayāl) whose reality is self-
renewal and flow217).
Sadrā himself explicitly states the actual inevitability of the metamorphosis of the reality of a
thing and the change of its configuration (nash’a) in the Asrār, where he writes:
“The transfer from the natural configuration to the other-worldly configuration is impossible
otherwise than through the overthrow of the substance (‘inqilāb al-jawhar) and change of
essence (tabaddul al-dhāt) because the first and the other configurations differ in their species
and are distinguished from one another in the kind of their existence, not [only] in their
descriptions and accidents”.218
The first and the other configurations (al-nash’āt al-awla wa ’l-ukhra), mentioned in the
quotation, correspond to engendering (takwīn) and innovation (ibdā‘) respectively. Hence,
transfer from the first configuration to the other one is, in fact, transfer from engendering to
innovation. The necessity for receptacle (qābil) or matter only pertains to the initial weaker
stages of existence of substantial form. In the more advanced and stronger ones these two are
no longer required.

2.2.1. Sadrā’s Teaching on the World of Command and Mīr Dāmād’s Theory of the
Meta-Temporal Origination

The idea of the necessity of some sort of intermediary between eternity and time, to my
knowledge, was first expressly formulated by Proclus in his Στoιχείωσις θεoλoγική
(“Elements of Theology”)219, but the immediate source of Mīr Dāmād’s theory should be
thought in the philosophy of Ibn Sīnā, who employed the term dahr (‘aeon’ or ‘meta-time’) in
his discourses to point to the existence with time (not in it) and to the relationship of the
unchanging to the changing:
“The intellect can think of three kinds of engendered existence: 1) the existence in time (fī ’l-
zamān), that is, the [category] “when” [which pertains to] the changing things, which have a
216
Sadrā, Asfār, part 6, 233–234.
217
See: Sadrā, Hudūth al-‘ālam, ed. M.Khājavī, Tehrān: Mawlā 1366 S.H., p. 206 and Sadrā, Asrār, 84–85.
218
Sadrā, Asrār, 87.
219
See: Proclus, Elements of Theology, ed. E.R.Dodds, Oxford: Oxford University Press 1933, 229. (Sajjad
H. Rizvi, however, holds that Mīr Dāmad was more clearly influenced by Iamblichus than Proclus.)

62
beginning and an end, and their beginning is other than (or: differs from) their end. In other
words, they are passing (muqtadiyyan) and are always in flow, and are perpetually in the state of
passing and self-renewal; 2) the existence with time (ma‘a ’l-zamān), which is called “the meta-
time” (or: “the aeon”) (al-dahr). This [kind of] existence encompasses time, and time is inside
this existence, because it (time – J.E.) is configured (or: originated) (yanshi’a) from the
movement of the celestial sphere, and this kind of existence is (read: can be described as – J.E.)
the relation of the fixed (thābit) to the changing (mutaghayyir), except that the estimative
faculty (wahm) cannot perceive it, because it sees everything in time, and it sees everything that
enters it in terms of “was” and “is”, and the past, the present and the future, and applies to
everything “when”, [placing it] either in the past, or in the present, or in the future; 3) the
existence of the fixed (immutable) with the fixed (immutable). It is called “the everlasting” (al-
sarmadī), and it encompasses the meta-time (aeon)”.220
“The relation of the eternities (abadiyyāt) to time is meta-time. Time is changing, but the
eternities do not change”.221
As we see, Ibn Sīnā uses dahr in two senses (which are, however, closely intertwined with
each other): 1) to refer to an intermediate ontological level that is situated between pure
eternity and time proper – a sort of “meta-time” or existence with time, not becoming afflicted
with its properties; 2) to point to a relation of the fixed and the eternal-without-end (abad) to
the changing and temporal. In the aspect of this relation, he envisages two parallel ontological
levels – that of meta-time and that of time proper (the level of the sarmad or everlastingness,
which is thought as the relation of one fixed entity (God’s Essence or one of His attributes) to
another (i.e., to an other attribute), has no direct relation with the world of changing
existents).
Ibn Sīnā then explains the difference between being in time and being with time. A thing
which is in time changes through the change of the latter and all accidents of time are
ascribed to it. The moment of its beginning (or that of the beginning of its act) differs from
the moment of its end. In turn, a thing which is with time does not change through the change
of time and the accidents of time are not ascribed to it.222
According to Proclus, the contents of this intermediate ontological level are the heavenly
bodies, matter and probably time itself.223 In turn, Ibn Sīnā seems to count among the contents
of dahr the celestial sphere (falak) and time (regarding which, he points out that it is
impossible to attribute to it “when”; as for the celestial sphere, he describes it as “unchanging
in its essence” and the “subject (hāmil) of time, whose locomotive faculty (or: power)224 (al-
quwwa al-muharraka) is the actor of time”225). Since, according to Ibn Sīnā, Platonic forms of
things (their lords of species) have no objective (external) existence and the universals are
conceptualizations that exist only in the mind, there is no point in ascribing them existence in
meta-time (aeon). Generally, the notion of dahr is interpreted by Ibn Sīnā in terms of rest and
movement and designates an intermediary between the Eternal Immobile Prime Mover and
the temporally originated existents that are perpetually subject to (some kind of) movement,

220
Ibn Sīnā, Ta‘līqāt, 170.
221
Ibn Sīnā, Ta‘līqāt, 46.
222
See: Ibn Sīnā, Ta‘līqāt, 170.
223
See: Proclus, Elements, 229 and F.Rahman, “Mīr Dāmād’s Concept of Hudūth Dahrī: A Contribution to the
Study of God-World Relationship Theories in Safavid Iran” in the Journal of Near East Studies, Vol.39, №
2, Chicago: Chicago University Press 1980, 140.
224
Chittick suggests to translate quwwa as ‘potency’: “Given that every faculty is at the same time a potentiality,
quwwa can better be translated as ‘potency’” (Chittick, “Teleology”, 222).
225
Ibn Sīnā, Ta‘līqāt, 170–171.

63
which eventually comes down to engendering and corruption (kawn wa fasād), namely the
furthest celestial sphere (al-falak al-aqsā) or the firmament.
Mīr Dāmād’s theory of hudūth dahrī seems to be developed from the above discussed seminal
ideas of Proclus and Ibn Sīnā, with this difference that, in his system, the most important
objects of the meta-temporal origination are the intelligible substances, i.e., the vertical and
horizontal intellects. A devout follower of Suhrawardī, he professes the principle of the
principality of essence (asālat al-māhiya) and treats existence as a secondary intelligible that
has no referent in the outside. Therefore, according to him, the object of meta-temporal
origination is the essence of the thing. Furthermore, meta-temporal origination is preceded by
meta-temporal non-existence (non-existence in meta-time) (‘adam dahrī). Like Suhrawardī,
Mīr Dāmād holds that the intelligibles of the vertical order differ from each other by strength
and weakness of their quiddities, thus also subscribing to Shaykh al-Ishrāq’s theory of
analogical gradation (tashkīk) (which, as we know, was later taken over by Sadrā, who,
however, interpreted it in a very different way).
As it was explained above, before Mīr Dāmād put forward his theory of meta-temporal
origination, there were two dominant approaches in Islamic thought to the issue of hudūth.
The theologians (mutakallimūn) believed the world to be temporally originated (hādith
zamānī) after its temporal non-existence (‘adam zamānī). The philosophers (I mean the
Peripatetics – Ibn Sīnā and his followers) held that the world as a whole was eternal in time
(qadīm zamānī), but originated in its essence (hādith dhātī), i.e., contingent and utterly and
perpetually dependent on its cause – the Necessary Existent (wājib al-wujūd).
Mīr Dāmād’s point was that the philosophers were right in their belief that origination in its
true sense had nothing to do with time. However, their theory of essential origination, which
came down to the ascription of the attributes of necessity and contingency to God and the
world respectively, failed to detect the exact receptacle (wi‘ā’) of the origination of the world.
The importance of his own doctrine of meta-temporal origination, by and large, lied in the
fact that it offered a solution of the above problem.
Hudūth dahrī is a kind of origination which occurs outside time and place – but also outside
God’s Essence. What is outside time and place (and, therefore, outside matter) and outside
God’s Essence, is His command (amr) or innovation (ibdā’), a single creative act, which
occurs in a durationless instant – “Our command is but a single (act) – like the twinkling of
an eye” (54:50).226 But, obviously, the effect of a single action, if it is simple and non-
compound in every aspect, must also be a single affair, as the well-known philosophical
(Neoplatonic by its origin) axiom states: “Nothing issues from one but one”. How, then, the
obvious and undeniable multiplicity of things arise? According to the stance taken by the
essentialists, from Plato to Mīr Dāmād, the sensible things are nothing but shadows of their
primordial intelligible forms. These intelligible forms, Platonic “likenesses” or archetypes,
certainly, stand above the domain of time and belong to the world of Command or the
ontological level of meta-time. Hence, the source of multiplicity must be sought there and,
apparently, its emergence has something to do with God’s first (and only) creative act or with
its effect.
I shall now quote a couple of passages from Mīr Dāmād’s Qabasāt (“Embers”), which might
shed some light on the possible ways for the solution of the problem.
“When the first issue (al-sādir al-awwal), which is called the “First Element of the World of
Command”, issues from the Originator, who is Real and One in every aspect (exalted be His
authority!), in it appears a combination of intertransfusing (or: interconnected) (mutasāfiqa)

226
Qur’an, 460.

64
respects, [such as] contingency in itself (or: in essence) and necessity through the other,
quiddity and ipseity (inniyya), intellection of the substance of [its own] essence and intellection
of the essence of the Real-the-Originator-the-Effuser-the-Beginning. In conformity with these
respects, there appear many aspects in the essence of the Innovator, [who is] the Real [and] the
One. And, because these aspects produce the respects of delimitation, the Complete Actor is one
in essence, but multiple in the respects of delimitation, which multiply the essence of the
substratum (mawdū‘). Therefore, He is the author and the innovator of the essence of the First
Intellect, which is contingent in its essence, and the producer of its (the First Intellect’s – J.E.)
ipseity, which is necessary through the other, and the effuser of the substance of its (the First
Intellect’s – J.E.) essence, which intellect the substance of its essence and the essence of its
actor”.227
Ibn Sīnā, Suhrawardī and Mīr Dāmād believe the source of multiplicity to lie in the first
intellect or the first dominating light. Different aspects of its contemplation, they hold, give
rise to the second intellect, the first celestial sphere and the soul of the first celestial sphere. In
turn, Sadrā holds that the Real, being simple in its reality, encompasses all things (basīt al-
haqīqa kull al-ashyā’).228 For the sake of its being simple in its reality, it does not accept
multiplicity. As we see, Mīr Dāmād ascribes manyness and multiplicity to God himself, albeit
only if He is considered in His respects of delimitation (haythiyyāt al-taqayyudiyya) – i.e., in
the aspect of His acts, not in that of His essence. Therefore, the stance taken by Mīr Dāmād
differs from the attitude of Sadrā significantly: while the former, negating the plurality in
God’s essence, ascribes it to His acts and effects, the latter denies the actual plurality even in
the world of Command. What is usually considered as its plurality is, in fact, only plurality in
respect to its effects in the world of Nature.
Furthermore, one can question whether the Originator’s originating the quiddity of the first
issue and His creating its ipseity can be considered, even theoretically and in mind, as two
different aspects of His act, or as two acts. Sadrā’s answer would definitely be “no”, because,
according to his principles, quiddity is a mere possibility (imkān) of a certain kind (direction,
aspect) of existence. This possibility can be actualized or it can remain forever in a non-
actualized state, but, as such, it is not created and originated by any kind of creation and
origination.
It seems that Mīr Dāmād understands God’s originating the first issue (al-sādir al-awwal) as
His creation of a universal and all-encompassing principle, which contains in itself all
particular principles to be actualized gradually at the subsequent stages of origination.
“The relation of the Active Intellect to the world of elements, or rather the relation of the First
Intellect, which is the (Prime) Element of the universal order, and the Element of the world of
contingency, to other parts of the order is that of a drawing point to the drawn line and a rotating
spark to the witnessed [luminous] circle, an intermediate movement to the finite one, a flowing
instant to continuous extended time, in [the aspect of] the former’s “drawing” the latter, together
(i.e., simultaneously – J.E.) with the former’s being outside of the latter and not being
constituted by it. Hence, it is known that God is the One who created the effusing intellect, the
drawing point, the revolving spark, the intermediate movement and the flowing instant, and
grasped it (i.e., each of them – J.E.) with the hand of His power, and made it rotate, and
revolved it, and made it travel, and gave it movement, in accordance with His knowledge,

227
Mīr Dāmād, Qabasāt, 220.
228
The idea of the simplicity of the Good (and, concomitantly, of the Intellect) belongs to Plotinus, who
discusses it in the 7th treatise of the 6th Ennead, in particular in VI.7.9 and VI.7.32 (where he states: “He (the
Good – Y. E.) is none of these things, and He is all things” (Ούδεν ουν τουτο των οντων και πάντα
ουδεν μέν) – Плотин, Эннеады, Шестая эннеада, Санкт-Петербург: Издательство Олега Абышко
2005, 139 и 204).

65
judgment, will and desire, in order to give perfection to the basic trend of the impression of
good in the order of existence”.229
On the basis of the above quotation, it can be concluded that, according to Mīr Dāmād, the
entire world of Command is created and initially exists as a point of light, the vertical
intellects or dominant lights being nothing else but its gradual extensions. In the process of
extension, the initial intensity weakens and wears off. (A similar theory of the gradual
extension of a point of light as the cause of the existence of the visible universe was
developed by Robert Grosseteste in his treatise De luci seu de inchoatione formarum.230)
However, while Sadrā views origination, first and foremost, in terms of analogical gradation
of existence (tashkīk al-wujūd), Mīr Dāmād’s primary concern seems to be the relationship
between God’s decree (qadā’) and its gradual actualization (“measuring out”) (qadar). I am
inclined to think that the main source of inspiration for his theory of meta-temporal creation
was the Qur’anic teaching on qadā’ and qadar (which was developed in great detail in the
Mutazilite Kalām).
While the relation of God’s command to natural creation and engendering, as envisaged by
Mīr Dāmād, can be illustrated by a number of examples – as the relation of a point to the line
drawn by it, the relation of a spark to the fiery circle, the relation of God’s decree to its
measuring out, the relation of potentiality to actuality or the relation of non-differentiation
(ijmāl) to differentiation (tafsīl), it is more difficult to grasp (the nature of) God’s relation to
His command. Is it that of the creator of the point to the point and the originator of the spark
to the spark? I think, in philosophical terms, the best description of this relation is exactly the
aforementioned one – i.e., the relation of the originator of the principle to that principle.
Mentally, this universal principle can be divided into an infinite number of levels and aspects
(which can be referred to as particular principles). Neither the universal, nor the particular
principles are temporally originated. The existentialists (those who, like Sadrā, profess the
principality of existence) would say that they are not originated at all, by any kind of
origination, their distinction from each other being nothing but a product of mental reflection
and abstraction in the mind (intizā‘ fī ’l-‘aql). The essentialists (those who, like Mīr Dāmād,
believe in the principality of quiddity (whatness)), however, hold these principles to be
originated – but neither by temporal origination (the absurdity of such supposition is self-
evident), nor by essential one (which, they say, is not origination proper and should be
understood as mere priority by essence (taqaddum bi ’l-dhāt)). According to them, they are
originated by meta-temporal origination (hudūth dahrī), which occurs with time, but not
within it. Hence, the world of Command is not simply a continuation of God’s essence and
attributes, which differs from the Godhead only in intensity (as Sadrā holds). According to
Mīr Dāmād, the difference lies in the ontological status (sarmad against dahr) and in world’s
of Command being originated by meta-temporal origination (which is regarded by Mīr
Dāmād as God’s only essential creative act).

229
Mīr Dāmād, Qabasāt, 408–409.
230
See: Robert Grosseteste, Opera, eds. A.Shishkov and K.Vinogradov, Moscow: URSS 2003, 72-84 and:
A.Speer, “Physics or Metaphysics? Some Remarks on Theory of Science and Light in Robert Grosseteste” in
J.Marenbon (ed.), Aristotle in Britain during the Middle Ages, Turnhout: Brepols 1996, 73-90. I have
discussed some parallels between Suhrawardī and Grosseteste’s teachings in my article “Two Mediaeval
Versions of the Metaphysics of Light: Robert Grosseteste and Shihāb al-Dīn Yahyā Suhrawardī”, published
in the journal Humanities and Social Sciences (Riga: University of Latvia), number 2 (46) (December 2005),
110–122.

66
Another important difference between Mīr Dāmād and Sadrā lies in the fact that the latter
treats the celestial spheres as part of the world of Nature, while Mīr Dāmād, as most pre-
Sadrian philosophers, believes them to belong to the world of Innovation. According to Mīr
Dāmād, the world of Command (Innovation) consists of two principal levels: the world of
immaterial intellects and the world of celestial spheres. Furthermore, every temporal existent
also exists on the level of meta-time (as a Platonic form and archetype), but not every meta-
temporal existent exists in time.
“Among the made (i.e., originated – J.E.) things, there are: 1) such which do not undergo
transmission (intiqāl) from one state to another, and such a thing is pure act and sheer fixity (or:
immutability), which, in the aspect of its existence in itself, does not become connected with
(or: dependent on) time or instant, in the same way as it does not become connected with it
(time or instant – J.E.) in the aspect of its existence in relation to the maker and its proceeding
from the latter; 2) such which do change in their existence and undergo transmission from an
actual task (or: state) to a potential one and vice versa. And such things, in the aspect of their
existence in themselves, inevitably become connected with time, or instant, or matter, or
substratum, although in the aspect of their existence in relation to their maker they are not
connected with any of them. Therefore, such a thing has (i.e., is placed within – J.E.) a period of
time if it is considered in itself, but there is no period of time between it and its maker. Also, it
possesses matter if it is considered in itself, but this is not the case in the aspect of its
proceeding from the maker and its existence in relation to this maker. That is [to say], its
presence to itself is wrapped by the veils of matter. Therefore, it is not material and temporal in
this respect (i.e., in respect to its maker – J.E.), but only in respect of its essence as it is per se.
[On the Division of Contingent and Possible Things.] Among the possible things, there are such,
which, according to their essential possibility (jawāz dhātī), are completely ready to receive the
effusion. If their he-ness is not connected with matter, as this is the case with intelligible
substances, they have meta-temporal innovative beginning. If they are existentially connected
with matter, as this is the case with the movements of the celestial spheres and their natural
forms, they have meta-temporal invented (ikhtirā‘iyya) beginning.
And there are such, whose readiness to accept the effusion is not actualized otherwise than
through that kind of possibility, whose meaning is preparedness (isti‘dād), and these are the
engendered ones (kā’ināt). In respect of its origination in meta-time, such possible thing has a
meta-temporal invented origin; in respect to its creation in time, it has a temporal engendered
beginning.
Hence, the originated things can be divided into innovated (mubda‘āt), invented (mukhtari‘āt)
and engendered (mukawwanāt). Making (ja‘l) and leaving trace (or: displaying effects) (ta’thīr)
manifests itself either as origination in meta-time, which is either innovation or invention, or as
origination in time, which is artisanry and engendering. Of them, the highest in excellence is
innovation, which is making an unbounded something from the unbounded (or: absolute)
nothing. The most worthy of the name of innovation is the making of quiddity itself through
simple making”.231
Origination in its true sense, thus, is limited to the innovation of quiddity (ibdā‘ al-māhiya)
(in other words, to the creation of the archetypes (or “lords of species”) of things), asserts Mīr
Dāmād. As we know, these archetypes are originated by meta-temporal origination (essential
origination (hudūth dhātī), according to Mīr Dāmād, is nothing but priority by/ through
essence (taqaddum bi ’l-dhāt)232).
From this point of view, the world of separated intelligibles, originated by hudūth dahrī, is the
only truly real world. Temporal origination is caused by and temporalities (zamāniyyāt) come

231
Mīr Dāmād, “Īmādāt”, in Mīr Dāmād, Musannafāt, ed. A.Nūrānī, Tehrān: Anjoman-i Āthār wa Mafākhir-i
Farhangī 1381 S.H., part 1, 45–46.
232
See e.g.: Mīr Dāmād, Īmādāt, 23.

67
into existence due to the imperfection of certain quiddities, which [imperfection] make
impossible their subsistence as an individual existent (shakhs), but allows them to subsist as
species.
In this connection, the images of point and line, spark and luminous circle, flowing instant
and time seem to be more apt to describe the relation of the archetype (lord of species),
originated by meta-temporal origination, to its instances, “talismans” and “shadows” that are
perpetually brought into existence in the material world by temporal origination than to
explain the relation of the First Intellect to what is below it (because what is below it are other
intellects, which also are originated and exist only meta-temporally, being always with time,
but never in it. Otherwise, one has to conclude that the First Intellect also relates to other
vertical intellects as a lord of species to his species and that every higher level of existence
relates to all levels below it as dahr to zamān, i.e., that the Second Intellect relates to the First
one as zamānī to dahrī and as an instance to its lord of species, while relating to the Third one
as dahrī to zamānī and as a lord of species to its instance and “shadow” – and so on, until we
come to the world of Engendering, which is the lowest level of existence.
Sadrā’s approach does not raise the problem of the interrelationship between intellects of the
vertical order, since in his system their differentiation and distinction from each other is a
purely mental affair (amr dhihnī) and a product of the reflection of mind: in actual fact, they
are (simultaneously) one and many. As part of the Godhead and the Domain of Lordship, they
are actually (but not essentially) one, but they can be distinguished either through analogical
gradation in terms of intensity and weakness (tashkīk bi ’l-shidda wa ’l-da‘f), which
distinction gives rise to the order of vertical intellects (‘uqūl tūlī), or in respect of the different
directions and focuses of rays and segments of radiance (God’s act).
Furthermore, Sadrā treats the celestial spheres, their souls and movements as part of the world
of Nature and subjects of substantial motion, while Mīr Dāmād believes them to belong to the
world of Command and, therefore, to be immutable in their essences (not in acts). However,
he distinguishes them from the separate intellects by calling the celestial spheres, their
movements and forms (i.e., souls) mukhtara‘āt (‘inventions’) and the separated intellects –
mubda‘āt (‘innovations’). The mukhtara‘āt are essentially connected with (and dependent on)
matter (albeit an incorruptible one), while the mubda‘āt have no connection with it.
In so doing, he follows the Peripatetic tradition, in which both the celestial spheres and their
souls are treated as by-products of the innovative origination. (The well-known belief of the
philosophers is that, when the First Intellect reflects upon its source and originator, this
reflection brings into existence the Second Intellect; when it reflects upon its essence in
relation to its source, the soul of the first celestial sphere is brought into existence; finally,
when it reflects upon its essence without relation to its source (seeing itself as non-existent),
this reflection brings into existence the first celestial sphere.) The question is: can a separated
(from matter) (and, therefore, incorruptible) substance give rise to a material and corruptible
one? The pre-Sadrian philosophers held that, with the exception of the corruptible sublunary
sphere, produced by the lowest intellect (commonly referred to as the “Active Intellect” (al-
‘aql al-fa‘‘āl)), the spheres produced by other intellects were material, but incorruptible. The
cause of the corruptibility of the sublunary sphere was the (relative) weakness of this lowest
intellect and the exhaustion of its creative power.
The admittance of the possibility of such exhaustion, in turn, gave additional support to the
theory of the analogical gradation of existence (tashkīk al-wujūd), developed by Suhrawardī
and elaborated by Sadrā. Indeed, if such exhaustion of creativity existed, it had to be a gradual
and stage-by-stage process. Hence, the matter from which the second celestial sphere was
created had to be more corruptible than that of the first one, while the matter of the third

68
sphere had to be of less strength than that of the second, and so on, because the basic
principles of falsafa excluded the possibility of jump (i.e., a sudden significant change of
qualities).
If the principle of analogical gradation is applicable to the matter of celestial spheres, their
respective governors (the souls) must strive to relieve them of their imperfection and
weakness and to bring them to perfection, thus also perfecting themselves. Hence, both the
celestial spheres and their souls must be in perpetual motion, experiencing “dressing after
dressing” (al-labs ba‘d al-labs). Therefore, the domain of immutability in Sadrā’s system is
limited to the world of Innovation proper, i.e., to the region of dominant separated lights (also
referred to as the “domain of Lordship”).
Both Sadrā and his teacher Mīr Dāmād distinguish between essential possibility (imkān dhātī)
(a sheer and unconditioned possibility of existence) and possibility of preparedness (imkān
isti‘dādī) (readiness of matter to receive a certain form, which (readiness) depends on another
previously received form, the previous form acting as matter and receptacle in respect to the
subsequent one), ascribing the latter only to the existents of the world of Engendering.
However, while Mīr Dāmād holds that possibility of preparedness is irrelevant to celestial
spheres, because he believes their matter to be incorruptible and, therefore, not subject to
change, Sadrā’s opinion is opposite: he believes them to be in perpetual state of perfecting
themselves through alteration of position (wad‘), which entails perpetual change of form and
development of preparedness.
That said, I have to admit that the central issue of Mīr Dāmād’s theory of hudūth dahrī is that
of separated substances, in particular, the archetypes, or lords of species, and their relation to
their material instances, “shadows” and “talismans”, which experience perpetual temporal
engendering.
Why did Sadrā not subscribe to Mīr Dāmād’s theory of hudūth dahrī (and, to my knowledge,
never employed the expression itself)? Meta-temporal origination is the origination of
quiddity (-ies) (or bringing it/ them into existence in a durationless instant). Sadrā holds that
quiddity is never brought into existence (“has never felt the scent of existence”, as Ibn al-
‘Arabī says about fixed entities233) – I mean the external existence. Rather, to him, it
represents a mental photograph of a certain aspect or direction (jiha) of the flow of existence.
In the world of Command, this aspect manifests itself as a ray of light which distinguishes
itself from other rays by its specific direction. As far as this direction is specified, it is not any
other direction, nor is it all directions. In so far as a thing is defined as something, it is not
anyhing else: by defining a thing we implicitly admit that it is not all things. This
specification is a purely mental operation. We do not give outer existence to a concept that
exists in our mind (e.g. to the concept of the “Companion of the Originator” (sharīk al-
bārī’)): there is no way we can do it, as much as we wanted.
Since quiddities are nothing but mental pictures and imitations (muhākāt) of the aspects/
directions of the outer reality, they exist only in our mind as afterthoughts of our intuitions.
We do not originate them, but abstract them, as an attempt to logically define an intuitively
perceived reality.
Since quiddities are not created (brought into external existence), there is no point in
allocating to them a special kind of origination (the meta-temporal one).

233
Ibn al-‘Arabī, Fusūs, part 1, 76.

69
One, however, notices that, while Sadrā rejects the theory of the hudūth dahrī, he does not
reject the notion of dahr, but treats it as a relation between different kinds of existents, not as
a mode of existence.
“The existents which do not exist either through motion, or in it, do not exist in time. Rather,
their fixity is considered [as being] with the changing ones, and this withness is called dahr”.234
Celestial spheres exist in motion, so fixity cannot be ascribed to them. What can be regarded
as fixed, are only the vertical and horizontal separated intellects, the latter of which are the
lords of the species of their vassals – natural existents. Hence, what can be described as dahr
is the lord’s of species relation to its vassal. However, in the numerous passages of Sadrā’s
works in which this relation is examined the term dahr appears very infrequently. Instead,
Sadrā describes the relationship between the lord of species (a separated horizontal intellect or
rather a ray of light which, in certain aspect, can be distinguished from other rays and
radiances) and its vassal (an ever self-renewing and perpetually “flowing” natural body) as
that of “cause-effect”, “root-branch” or “spirit-body” one. The relation “meta-time – time” is,
in fact, treated by Sadrā as a concomitant of existential causal relationship between the
spiritual lord of species and its material vassal.
In Sadrā’s analogicity-and-movement based approach, there is no clear-cut distinction
between spirits and bodies, roots and branches, causes and effects, the world of Command
and the world of Nature. Each can gradually change into its opposite. The system of concepts
which was constructed to demonstrate a static intuition could serve as means to explain and
prove a dynamic one only if entirely different meaning was attributed to the key concepts
(i.e., if they were viewed in light of an entirely different intuition). The concept of dahr, as the
domain of immutable once-and-forever originated quiddities, is inseparable from the static
intuition. For this very reason, there was no place for it in the conceptual system designed to
reflect the intuition of dynamics.
According to the principles of analogical gradation of existence and substantial motion, one
and the same particular existence (al-wujūd al-khāss) can pertain to both the world of
Command and the world of Nature, depending on the particular stage and phase of its
development which is at issue. The existence of command (al-wujūd al-amrī) (also known as
the “innovated existence” (al-wujūd al-ibdā‘ī)), when it descends from the presence of the
Divine Essence and reaches the horizon of natural bodies, due to the decrease of its intensity,
acquires the properties of natural existence (al-wujūd al-tabī‘ī) and vice versa – when the
strength of the natural existence increases, it assumes the properties of the existence of
command and innovation. The entire process of the origination of natural existents and their
return to God is envisaged by Sadrā as descending and ascending the arcs of the circle of
being through decrease and increase of their intensity of existence.
The change of intensity entails and necessitates the change of properties. Engendering and
corruption, peculiar of the world of elements, is simply a concomitant and a witness of
weakness and exhaustion of intensity, while immutability and fixity, characteristic of the
domain of Lordship, is a concomitant of strength and high intensity. Since the increase and
decrease of intensity is a gradual affair, it is, in fact, impossible to draw a distinct borderline
between the world of Innovation and Command and that of natural creation. Rather, we
should speak of the isthmus, or border region, or transitional phase(s) that separate(s) them.
In Sadrā’s process-based approach, “Intellect” (‘aql) refers to the principle of immutability
and fixity, which, albeit in a different degree, determines the characteristics of the high-

234
Sadrā, Asfār, part 3, 182.

70
intensity existence, while “Nature” points to the principle of changeability and flowing, which
exerts decisive influence upon the low-intensity one.
I shall now examine the properties of the low-intensity existence spectrum, commonly known
as “the world of Nature”, in order to proceed to the discussion on the border region between
two spectra in the final part of this chapter.

2.3. NATURE AND THE WORLD OF NATURE

2.3.1. The History of the Concept of Nature in Islamic Philosophy: Avicennan Trend

“Nature” (φύσις) as a philosophical term, as far as we know, was introduced by Aristotle, who
employed it to describe a universal form of engendering235 and believed it (nature) to be the
only proof of the existence of Intellect (νoυς).
In turn, Plotinus called it the logos (divine intellect) acting in a visible form. To him, it was
the last of the logoi and the dead one, i.e., incapable of producing another logos and
producing only visible forms. According to Plotinus, Nature was generated by the Universal
Soul and was the object of its (the Soul’s) contemplation (whereas the object of Nature’s own
contemplation was natural bodies).236
The early Muslim Peripatetics commonly treated nature as the essential first principle of
motion and rest. Thus, Kindī defined it as the “beginning (or: principle) (ibtidā’) of motion
and rest after motion”.237 This approach was, by and large, followed by Ibn Sīnā, many of
whose remarks on the subject represent paraphrased passages from Aristotle’s Physics. E.g. in
the ‘Uyūn al-hikma he states:
“Nature is an occasioner (sabab) in that it is a certain essential principle (mabda’; άρχη) of
motion and rest to that, in which it is inherent, essentially, not by accident”.238
Elsewhere in the ‘Uyūn Ibn Sīnā restates the same idea, replacing “motion” (haraka) with
“change” (taghayyur) and “rest” (sukūn) with “stability” (thubūt):
“Nature is the essential first principle (mabdā’ awwal) for the essential movement of that in
which it is present, in short, for every essential change (taghayyur) and every essential
immutability (thubūt)”.239
A more careful examination of the relevant passages in Ibn Sīnā’s works, however, allows us
to conclude that nature occasions motion only in a body which is not in its natural state and/
or position. (Apparently, this was apprehended by Kindī, when he spoke of nature as “the way
that leads to rest” (al-tarīq ilā al-sukūn).240) In the Najāt (“Deliverance”) this is explained by
Avicenna in the following way:
“If nature requires the motion of a certain thing, this thing is not in its natural state, and nature
moves it [only] in order to return it to its natural state and to reach the latter. When the natural

235
See: Т.Г. Сидаш, «Натурфилософия Плотина» в Плотин, Эннеады, Вторая эннеада, 23.
236
See: Плотин, Эннеады, Третья эннеада, 64–65.
237
al-Kindī, Rasā’īl al-falsafiyya, ed. Abu Ridā, Cairo: 1950, part 1, 169, quoted from: R.Arnaldez, “Haraka wa
sukūn” (III.169 b), in EI.
238
Ibn Sīnā, ‘Uyūn al-hikma, quoted from: D.E.Pingree and S.Nomanul Haq, “Tabī‘a” (X.25 a), in EI.
239
As A.-M. Goichon points out, this statement represents a free translation of a passage from the second book
of Aristotle’s Physics (see: R. Arnaldez, “Haraka”).
240
See: R. Arnaldez, “Haraka”.

71
state is reached, the necessitator (mawjib) of the motion is lifted, and the [natural] motion of the
thing becomes impossible …
Every motion through nature is a natural flight from a [certain] state, and whenever such a flight
occurs, it is a fleeing from a disagreeable state”.241

Undoubtedly, nature tries to return the body to its natural state by the nearest way possible. In
case of local (makānī) motion, this attempt is manifested in the straightness (istiqāma) of
motion. As soon as the natural state is fully achieved and actualized, the natural motion comes
to an end. This allowed Kindī to describe the state of rest as the “realization of actuality and
the last fulfilment”.242
In a short passage in the Ta‘līqāt Ibn Sīnā states with certainty that nature is not the actor
(fā‘il) and the cause (‘illa) of the thing, namely that it is capable neither of bringing a thing
into existence, nor of sustaining it. Its function comes down to creating preconditions for
bestowal of a certain form upon matter, that is to say, to perfecting and refining the imkān
isti‘dādī:
“In reality, nature is incapable of more than giving motion (tahrīk) and preparation (i‘dād),
through which the matter which is moved by it (i.e., nature – J.E.) can receive the form, towards
which it (matter) is moved, and nature is neither the actor, nor the effuser (mufīd) of existence.
Rather, the effuser is the Bestower of forms (wāhib al-suwar), whereas nature is the mover of
the thing, which moves it towards what is effused upon it by the Bestower of forms. It performs
no other act except moving the thing towards its furthest limit (ghāya) – that, through which it
(the thing) is presented to the First Actor, and it (nature – J.E.) seems to perform this function
unwillingly, as if it were being compelled”.243

Nature is presented here as the innate organizing principle of matter, “consciousness of the
unconscious”. Like matter, it is passive and inert in itself and seems to perform its function
“as if it were being compelled” (this enigmatic expression, probably, led Sadrā to suppose the
existence of two different natures, one of which obeys the soul willingly (because ii is a part
and a level of the soul), but the other – unwillingly and under compulsion244).

2.3.2. Hamīd al-Dīn al-Kirmānī’s Teaching on Nature and Parallels to It in the Thought of Sadrā

It is difficult to tell, to which extent Sadrā was acquainted with the Ismai‘ili teachings on
nature, the most detailed presentation of which is found in Hamīd al-Dīn al-Kirmānī’s Rāhat
al-‘aql (“Quietude of Intellect”). (Kirmānī’s manuscripts were not widely available in the
libraries of Safavid Iran.) Although Kirmānī’s formal definition of nature virtually repeats the
Aristotelian one (“nature is the principle of movement and rest of the thing in which it is
essentially inherent”245), his actual understanding of it is much closer to (in fact, almost
identical with) that of Plotinus, who treats nature as the active element of corporeal existents,
their form, life and soul (viewing these three terms almost as synonyms (“the realm of Nature,

241
Ibn Sīnā, al-Najāt min al-gharq fī bahr al-dalālāt, ed. M.T.Dāneshpazhūh, 2nd edition, Tehrān: Tehran
University Press 1379 S.H., 212–213.
242
Kindī, Risā’īl, part 1, 86, quoted from: R.Arnaldez, “Haraka”.
243
Ibn Sīnā, Ta‘līqāt, 209.
244
Sadrā, al-Hikma al-’arshiyya, ed. G.Āhanī, Isfahān: Kitābfurūshī-yi Shahriyār 1341 S.H., 233.
245
Hamīd al-Dīn al-Kirmānī, Rāhat al-‘aql, Beirūt: Dār al-Andalūs 1983, 296, quoted from: Daniel De Smet, La
Quiétude de l’intellect: Neoplatonisme et gnose ismaélienne dans l’oeuvre de Hamîd ad-Dîn al-Kîrmânî
(Xe/Xie s.), Leuven: Peeters 1995, 324, n. 62.

72
which is Life, [also] named “the Soul”)).246 Daniel De Smet in his Quiétude de l’intellect lists
three important points in which Kirmānī’s treatment of nature differs from the Aristotelian
one and coincides with that of Plotinus: 1) Nature emanates from the celestial world; 2) the
difference between animated and unanimated nature disappears, all earthly creatures
possessing soul; 3) Nature is understood as pure form, synonymous to Soul and Life, and not
as entity composed of form and matter.247 Kirmānī’s most important point is that Nature is
two-partial in its essence and represents simultaneously the active and the passive principles,
acting both as matter which receives form and as the moving form of every thing. As matter,
Nature gives the thing its corporeality, i.e., body; as form, it gives it the soul and prepares it
for the receipt of effusion of the Active Intellect.248
“It was explained earlier that, when the thing which is known as the “prime matter” (hayūla)
came into existence, this (coming) happened without an intention on the part of the innovation
(=the first innovated or the First Intellect – J.E.), so that prime matter would find its cause in the
latter. And it lacked the excellence that was in the possession of the other, namely the actual
intellects, emanating from the noblest relation – the one which [is found] in the innovation,
(which (innovation – J.E.) is [simultaneously] the first innovated), but the divine solicitude
(‘ināya), which pervades everything, turned towards it (the prime matter – J.E.), and from the
blinding radiance (sutū‘) of its (solicitude’s – J.E.) lights was engendered that, whose
engendering in it (the prime matter – J.E.) was possible, in keeping with its (the engendering’s –
J.E.) ranks in excellence.
And we say: this existent, which was the prime matter, was one thing, having two parts in its
essence, through which it existed. Each of these two parts [,in turn,] is divided into [many]
parts, which have one common name and many [particular] names, each of which is the proper
name of one of these [specified] parts. Furthermore, every part has two relations: 1) a relation to
what is the source of its existence in the world of Innovation, which is the First Innovated, and
through this relation it is one. This relation is [established] in the aspect of its (the relevant
part’s – J.E.) substance and through it its quiddity is known; 2) a relation to the existents whose
existence is through it. Through this relation it (the part of the prime matter J.E.) is multiple, and
this relation is [established] in the aspect of its acts in these existents.
[As for] the first part, when it is related to what is the source of its existence, wayfaring the path
of encompassing its quiddity, [we find that] it is the actual life, emanating from the world of
Holiness, [which life is] not independent in its existence through (or: in) its essence and is not
separated from that on which its existence depends, because its existence [arises] from the non-
separated relation, and it permeates the world of Body. The heavens and the earth are full of it;
nothing is void of it and nothing is hidden from it. [This Life-Nature] acts in the corporeal
world, giving everything its first perfection – that which concerns its existence (literally: being
existent).
When it is related to the existents that exist through it, [then,] generally, wayfaring the path of
encompassing its act, [we find that] it is the mover of everything in which it resides and the
perfection of its existence through its existence, while [considered] particularly, it is that which,
in respect to its acts, [is present] in every part. When it moves bodies by circular motion, it is
the orbit; when it moves fire and air up, it is lightness; when it moves water and something
heavy down towards its centre, it is heaviness; when it moves the plant to grow, it is the
vegetative soul; when it moves the animal to seek pleasure, it is the animal soul; [finally,] when
it moves to encompass the existents [by knowledge (?)], it is the rational soul. All this, through
(or: in the aspect of) its being an actor, is one nature, but through its acts in different matters –
those in which it acts – it is multiple …

246
See: De Smet, Quiétude, 324.
247
See: De Smet, Quiétude, 324, n. 63. Cf. Плотин, Эннеады, Третья эннеада, 8.2., 426.
248
See: Kirmānī, Rāhat, 269–273.

73
When the second part of matter is related to what is the source of its existence, attempting to
encompass its quiddity, [we find that] it is potential life, emanating from the world of
Holiness, not independent through (or: in) its essence and not without need [, in respect of this
existence,] in the first part – that which is the actual life. The existence of the world of Body
consists in it (the second part of prime matter – J.E.), and is acted upon in it. It (the second
part – J.E.) is receiving through its act, and gives from its essence to every existent its first
perfection – that which is inseparable from its being existent, [but does it] in cooperation with
its pair (i.e., the first (active) part – J.E.).
When it is related to the existents, the source of whose existence it is, in a general way, it is a
three-dimensional body, but [when it is related to them] in a particular way, that is, in
accordance with the manner in which each thing receives the act of the actor, [then,] if it
moves by circular motion, it is celestial spheres and luminaries; if it moves by rectilinear
motion, it is fire, air, water and earth; if it moves in all directions (up, down, right, left,
forwards, backwards), without leaving its place, it is the plant; when it moves in all directions,
leaving its place and experiencing transmission (intiqāl), it is the animal, and all this is one
Nature and one Body. But, [if considered] in accordance with [the manner of] its receiving the
effects of the actor, it becomes multiple”.249

Thus, Kirmānī treats Nature as the fundamental life-giving principle of the corporeal
universe, in which he distinguishes the active and the passive components. Such approach,
certainly, is much closer to the Platonic understanding of Nature than to the Aristotelian one:
according to Plato, the bodily cosmos, which is originated, has two causes – The Author (or:
Demiurge) (bārī’) and the prime matter; according to Aristotle the eternal corporeal world has
one cause – its Prime Mover. However, Kirmānī’s treatment of Nature is not identical with
the (Neo)Platonic approach either: much like Aristotle, Kirmānī considers Nature (namely its
active component) to be the mover of the corporeal universe – in its totality and in its parts.
One may wonder whether Kirmānī’s teaching of two natures has anything in common with an
outwardly similar hypothesis of Sadrā. The latter hypothesis, however, applies only to the
higher animals, in particular, to human beings. According to it, there are two natures inherent
in human being, one of which emanates from the essence of the soul, being its level and
faculty, whereas the other inheres in the elements and members of the body. The first obeys
the soul willingly and spontaneously, while the second does it unwillingly and under
compulsion.250 If we project this theory on the macrocosmic level, some similarity between it
and Kirmānī’s teaching becomes evident: both thinkers discern the active and the passive
aspects of Nature. However, in the system of Kirmānī Nature is, more or less, the substitute
for the Platonic Universal Soul; for Sadrā it is one of the (lower) levels of the soul or the soul
in the aspect of its dependence on the body.251
Kirmānī’s approach is much broader than Ibn Sīnā’s one: while Avicenna treats nature as
occasioner (sabab), responsible for the preparatory possibility (imkān isti‘dādī) and
bestowing upon body motion (more specifically, that kind of motion, whose purpose is the
achievement of rest), Kirmānī believes it to be both motion and rest, the mover and the moved
(body), act and being acted upon (infi‘āl), actuality and potentiality and, perhaps most
importantly, actual and potential life or, more precisely, the emanation (inbi‘āth) of Life that
has emanated from the world of Holiness.
Kirmānī’s remarks on the origin of Nature are succinct. He views Nature as the by-product
and the secondary result of the first emanation (the primary result of which is the Second
249
Kirmānī, Rāhat, 269–271.
250
See: Sadrā, ‘Arshiyya, 233.
251
See: Sadrā, Asfār, part 3, 67.

74
Intellect). In one respect, Nature is a potential intellect, which unites in itself prime matter and
form.252 In another respect, Kirmānī seems to identify it with prime matter which is animated
through the act of immaterial intellects.253 It relates to what ranks below it in the cosmic
hierarchy as the separated intellects relate to itself – i.e., acting upon the existents of a lower
rank, it leaves in them traces and effects which are essentially similar to those left in itself by
the pure intellects, as this passage seems to testify to:
“…so that it would be known that solicitude (‘ināya) flows in every existent [,pervading it]
from above and, in this act, it acts as Nature, in keeping with its status of a power flowing in it
(the world of bodies – J.E.) from the world of Divinity, which (power – J.E.) [sympathetically]
inclines towards what is actualized by the intention of pure intellects, namely [towards] the
bodies which precede it (Nature – J.E.) in excellence (sharaf), [manifesting itself as] ordering in
levels (tartīb) [those] bodies [that are] formed from such matters which cannot be used for the
creation of higher [celestial (?)] bodies and creating from these matters the noble animals and
placing what is incapable of producing higher incorruptible bodies among the existents through
a sort of creation, in conformity with what suits it, in a way which is similar to the act of the
pure intellects upon what was actualized by the intention of the innovation – that which is the
first innovated, which precedes them in excellence, that is, [by] the glorification and praising of
the Most High (praise be to Him!), and encompassing its [own] essence and rejoicing owing to
this encompassing, – namely upon the prime matter, which does not have a degree of that which
transcends it in excellence, that is, of the actual intellect, and it is not in conformity with its
[actual] waystation that they (the pure intellects – J.E.) make it, through what flows in it,
namely [through] their lights, similar to their essences in act and an occasion of the existence of
other than it, and give it forms that suit it, such as [those of] the celestial spheres, luminaries and
the others”.254
In short, when the prime matter is acted upon by the immaterial intellects, their lights and
energies permeate it, thus making it, to a degree, similar – in act, not in essence, – to these
intellects. Namely, the prime matter becomes capable of acting as the life-giving and
animating principle which pervades every part and level of the corporeal world. But, in its
passive aspect, Nature itself is this corporeal world in its entirety, ranked in degrees and
levels. Therefore, it would not be wrong to say that Nature acts upon itself, actualizing its
own potentiality. Although Kirmānī evidently prefers to describe Nature as Life – or, more
precisely, as that kind of Life, which permeates and sustains the world of the bodies
(material universe), I believe it is possible, employing different terms, to call it the principle
of corporeal existence. I mean that, when existence descends from the level of pure
intellects to the level of natural bodies, it manifests itself as Nature. Regardless of their
particular concerns and different terminology, on this principal point the positions of Kirmānī
and Sadrā (but not that of Ibn Sīnā!) seem to coincide. This coincidence does not necessarily
testify to Sadrā’s acquaintance with this particular Kirmānī’s work. However, with a high
degree of certainty, it can be asserted that Sadrā was aware of the existence of the perspective
of thought that opens after one has realized that in the bodily world Life always manifests
itself as Nature. The novelty of Sadrā’s approach lies in considering the issue in the context of
and as an evidence to the principle of the analogical gradation of existence (tashkīk al-wujūd).
Finally, I would like to observe that Kirmānī’s cosmological doctrine is based on an earlier
teaching of Abū ’l-Ya‘qūb al-Sijistānī, discussed in detail in his Kitāb al-Yanābi‘ (“Book of
the Sources”). The potential affair which emanates from the First Innovation (al-mubda‘
’l-awwal) is called by Sijistānī “the Universal Soul” (al-nafs al-kulliyya). From the Universal
Soul, according to Sijistānī, emanate prime matter and form, which become intermediaries for

252
See: Kirmānī, Rāhat, 80.
253
See: Kirmānī, Rāhat, 167.
254
Kirmānī, Rāhat, 225.

75
the origination of the material world.255 Postulating the existence of a common originating
principle of prime matter and form, i.e., the Nature (tabī‘a), Kirmānī, by and large, followed
the approach of Sijistānī. In this sense, either consciously or not, Sadrā’s cosmology, as far as
it is recognizes two fundamental existential levels – the world of Command/ Innovation and
the world of Nature/ Engendering – follows the trend which was established by the Ismai‘īlī
thought, in particular by Kirmānī.

2.3.3. Ibn al-‘Arabī on Nature

Although Ibn al-‘Arabī’s influence on Sadrā’s teaching on Nature is, no doubt, significant, I
dare to assert that it is not as crucial as that of the Neoplatonists.
Generally, Ibn al-‘Arabī speaks about two natures, the first of which relate to the second as
mother to daughter. The first nature is the one which receives the traces and effects of God’s
names. This nature is, in fact, the Cloud (‘amā) and the Breath of the Merciful:
“Nature is more worthy to be attributed to the Real than anything else, because everything else
becomes manifest only in that which becomes manifest from Nature, that is, the Breath, which
permeates the cosmos … And look at the inadequacy of the property of the [First] Intellect, for
in reality it is one of the forms of the Cloud and the Cloud is one of the forms of Nature”.256
Nature manifests itself to the cosmos only in and through its traces, remaining forever unseen
and hidden in its essence.
“Nature is the highest, greatest mother of the cosmos, of whom the cosmos never sees the entity,
only the effects, just as it never sees anything of the Real but its effects, never its entity”.257
Ibn al-‘Arabī calls this nature the “highest and greatest mother” (al-umm al-‘āliyāt al-kubrā)258,
while Chittick qualifies it as “the receptivity that allows the existent thing to become manifest”
(thus treating it as the passive/ receptive cosmic principle (cf. the Chinese yin).259
The second nature is the one which receives the traces and effects of the First Intellect. Ibn
al-‘Arabī calls it “the second mother” and the “daughter of the Greatest Nature”. It acts as an
intermediary between the Universal Soul and the Dust (habā’) (i.e., the prime matter).260
In a number of places Ibn al-‘Arabī discusses the relation between Command and Nature. To
him, this relationship is like that between man and woman:
“A woman in relation to a man is like Nature in relation to the Divine Command, since the
woman is the locus of the existence of the entities of the children, just as Nature in relation to
the Divine Command is the locus of the manifestation of the entities of the corporeal bodies.
Through it they are engendered and from it they become manifest. So there can be no Command
without Nature and no Nature without Command. Hence the engendered existence depends
upon both”.261

One notices that Ibn al-‘Arabī sees the main difference between Command and Nature in
activity and receptivity peculiar to each of them respectively. Therefore, to him, the world of
Command means the world in which activity dominates over receptivity and the world of
255
See: F.Daftary, A Short History of the Ismailis: Traditions of a Muslim Community, Edinburgh: Edinburgh
University Press 1998, 95.
256
Ibn al-‘Arabī, Futūhāt, part 3, 420, quoted from: Chittick, Knowledge, 140.
257
Ibn al-‘Arabī, Futūhāt, part 4, 150, quoted from: Chittick, Knowledge, 141.
258
See e.g.: Ibn al-‘Arabī, Futūhāt, part 4, 150.
259
Chittick, Knowledge, 140.
260
See: Chittick, Knowledge, 140.
261
Ibn al-‘Arabī, Futūhāt, part 3, 90, quoted from: Chittick, Knowledge, 141.

76
Nature – the world in which receptivity has the upper hand over activity. This domination,
however, does not depend on the intensity of existence as such – or, at least, the intensity of
existence is not the only factor which makes the male dominate over the female or vice versa.
In all likelihood, Sadrā would have agreed that Nature is the breath of the Merciful – but he
would have added that not everything that can be qualified as breath of the Merciful is Nature:
to him, Nature typifies the lowest kind of existence – the one which lacks permanence and
stability and, therefore, is forced to perpetually renew and reproduce itself.

2.3.4. Sadrā’s Definitions of Nature

In his Risāla fī hudūth al-‘ālam (“Treatise on the Origination of the World”) Sadrā provides
such definition of nature:
“[Nature is] a thing, whose reality consists of self-renewal (tajaddud) and flow (sayalān)”.262
In the Asrār we find a more expanded version of the same definition:
“Inevitably, among the existent substances must exist a flowing substance, self-renewing in its
essence, the mode of whose existence consists in passing (inqidā’) and self-renewal, in such a
way that it is impossible to conceive of fixity and continuance (istimrār) neither in respect of its
existence, nor in respect of its non-existence…, and this substance cannot be an immaterial and
incorporeal one – otherwise the potentiality (power) of preparedness (al-quwwa al-isti‘dādiyya)
would not be [present] in it. On the contrary, it is a material substance, in which some sort of
potentiality and some sort of act are present”.263
In the first definition nature is treated as a habitude of action, while in the second one – as the
principle and source of change. The novelty of Sadrā’s approach can be better apprehended if
we keep in mind that philosophers previous to him considered the principle of change and
renewal to be either motion or time – but never nature. Sadrā holds that this testifies to his
predecessors’ lack of insight: according to him, they failed to apprehend that motion is an
attribute of nature and a concomitant of its existence, but time – the measure of the self-
renewal of the substance of nature. What is even more important, they were unable to
understand that, in its low-intensity spectrum, existence does not manifest itself otherwise
than as, in and through this flowing affair (i.e., nature), whose “marks” (‘alāmāt) time and
movement are.
“A gradual transition (literally: coming out) (khurūj) from potentiality to actuality constitutes
the meaning of motion and [that of] its existence in mind, in conformity with the outside. That
through which the transition from potentiality to actuality takes place, is nature. The thing
which receives (i.e., serves as the receptacle for – J.E.) the transition, is matter. The transitioner
(makhraj) (i.e., the maker of transition, its efficient cause – J.E.) is another terrestrial or celestial
substance. The measure of transition is time, whose [true] reality is nothing else than the
measure of self-renewal and passing”.264
To explain his point, Sadrā compares movement with an individual (shakhs) whose spirit is
nature and time – with an individual whose spirit is meta-time. According to him, nature
relates to the soul, or rather to the intellect, as a ray relates to the sun, the former being
individuated through the individuation of the latter.265

262
Sadrā, Hudūth, 206.
263
Sadrā, Asrār, 84–85.
264
Sadrā, Hudūth, 208.
265
See: Sadrā, Hudūth, 228.

77
In a passage, crucial for the understanding of Sadrā’s views on natural existence (al-wujūd al-
tabī‘ī), he qualifies the latter as a self-renewing and gradual (tadrījī) one:
“An essentially self-renewing affair (which is the nearest actor (al-fā‘il al-aqrab) of motion –
J.E.) is the kind of the existence of bodily nature, which has an intelligible reality with God
and a gradual continuous he-ness in matter (which is a [purely] potential affair). In the same
way as, according to the common belief of philosophers, existence itself is differently
actualized in things in the aspect of strength and weakness, independence and need, priority
and posteriority, some [individual] existences are gradual (tadrījī) in their essence and he-
ness, not through (or: due to) an attribute which is predicated to them. Such [, for example,] is
the existence of bodily nature. And this kind of existence, because of its not being able to last
perpetually in its he-ness, is gradually actualizing and self-renewing in its engendered being
(mutajaddid al-kawn)”.266
Apparently, lasting and perpetuality of an individual existence has something to do with its
strength and intensity. Depending on the degree of the latter, this existence displays different
properties. Low-intensity existences cannot actualize themselves instantaneously and become
fully present now and here. Instead, they require temporal and spatial continuity in order to
actualize themselves and to display their properties. Or perhaps low-intensity existence itself
generates tempo-spatial continuity, in which case time and space are nothing but
concomitants of the former? If so, the reason of Sadrā’s non-acceptance of Mīr Dāmād’s
theory of hudūth dahrī is evident: in all likelihood, he considered time and meta-time (as well
as space and meta-space (the space of the world of Soul or the world of Imagination) to be
concomitant properties of certain spectra of intensity. Upon decrease or increase of intensity,
these properties convert one into another (time becoming meta-time and vive versa). (Hence,
time and space must also be interconvertible, but this conversion, apparently, depends on a
different principle, not that of the change of intensity.)
According to Sadrā, the border region between the act of nature and the act of soul is the
“beginning of the horizon of the animal” (awā’īl ufq al-hayawān). This border region also
separates material sensible engendered existents from immaterial formal imaginal ones.267
Can this sensible material perpetually self-renewing entity, namely nature as understood by
Sadrā, be described as self-contemplating logos, whose self-contemplation brings into
existence all natural bodies? That is, does Sadrā’s definition of nature is compatible with that
of Plotinus? The main difficulty in making them compatible lies in the fact that each of them
results from a different vision. Plotinus’ vision is one of sublime contemplation of the One,
while Sadrā’s intuition is that of perpetual flow towards perfection. To Plotinus, the sensible
universe comes into existence due to impurity and alloying of contemplation. When the
contemplating subject manages to purify itself, this impurity disappears. In turn, to Sadrā
nature is a flow which brings the lower up and makes the unaware and unconscious aware and
conscious. But, very much like Plotinus, Sadrā admits that our need in sense experience is
confined to the initial stages of perception and holds that on higher stages the soul does not
require a sensible object in order to perceive its (the object’s) “likeness” in its own world (that
of Imagination). Thus, Plotinus and Sadrā agree that the realm of Nature is one of semi-
conscious and alloyed contemplation, therefore the soul must inevitably leave it during its
spiritual progress (ascent) towards the intelligible. However, unlike Plotinus, Sadrā stresses
the positive aspect of nature: it is the gate that opens towards the realm of divinity and the
flow which brings everything unconscious towards consciousness.

266
Sadrā, Hudūth, 253.
267
See: Sadrā, Asfār, part 5, 347.

78
Sadrā would definitely agree with Kirmānī’s treatment of Nature as Life and bestower of the
first perfection upon the existents of the bodily world. He would also affirm that nature is the
mover of every natural existent. However, Sadrā never makes an explicit division between
the active and the passive (receptive) aspects of nature, as Kirmānī does, treating nature
simultaneously as the mover of the body and the body itself. According to Sadrā’s principles,
such division is a relative affair: what truly and really is, is the flow of existence, which
manifests itself as the movement of the body. The mover of the body is a direction of the
dominant light or higher intelligible existence, which exerts influence upon the lower light or
sense existence. Hence, the solution of the problem of movement lies in the principle of the
analogical gradation of existence (tashkīk al-wujūd), not in the interplay of activity and
receptivity.

2.3.5. Substantial Motion

I shall now proceed to the discussion of substantial motion (al-haraka al-jawhariyya), to


subsequently examine how this theory is related to Ibn al-‘Arabī’s teaching on the new
creation (al-khalq al-jadīd).
One of the earliest definitions of motion in Islamic philosophy belongs to Kindī: “Motion is a
change of the state of the essence” (al-haraka tabaddul hāl al-dhāt).268 This definition,
however, provokes more questions than it provides answers. What exactly is state? Does the
change of state necessitate the change of essence? If yes, in which way?
The problem of motion received more substantial treatment in the works of Ibn Sīnā, who
wrote in the Najāt:
“[The word] “motion” is employed to describe (1) a gradual change of a stable state in the body,
in such a manner that through this change the body directs itself towards something and (2) the
arrival through this change at this thing”.269
He then adds that motion must manifest itself as leaving the previous state and that this state
must be capable of decreasing and increasing, because that of which the body gradually
comes out, directing itself towards something [different], remains, in such a way that its
remaining does not contradict [the body’s] coming out of it – otherwise, coming out of it
would be an instantaneous affair, not a gradual one. Then, continues his reasoning Ibn Sīnā,
the state of such a body is either similar in every moment of this coming out, or not. But it
cannot be similar, because, if it had been similar, then coming out of it would not have
occurred, since everything, coming out of which occurs gradually, remains, without being
similar in itself in respect of its state, during its coming out of this state. Such a thing,
inevitably, allows increase and decrease.
Among the states which experience motion Ibn Sīnā names whiteness and blackness, heat and
cold, length and shortness, nearness and distance, greatness and smallness in volume.270
Following Aristotle, he describes motion as act (fi‘l) and the first perfection of the thing in
potentiality, in that aspect in which it is in potentiality:

268
Kindī, Rasā’īl, part 1, 196, quoted from: R.Arnaldez, “Haraka”.
269
Ibn Sīnā, Najāt, 203.
270
Ibn Sīnā, Najāt, 203–204.

79
“Motion is what is conceived from the state of the body, due to its gradual coming out of stable
form (hay’a), and it is coming out of potentiality into actuality in a continuous manner, not
instantaneously”.271
As it is well known, Aristotle and Ibn Sīnā limited motion to four of ten categories – namely
to place (or “where”) (πoύ/ ayn), position (κείσθαι/ wad‘), quality (πoιόν/ kayf) and quantity
(πoσoν/ kamm).272 Regarding substance (oύσία/ jawhar), Ibn Sīnā’s view was that it does not
experience motion. Although engendering (kawn) and corruption (fasād) of substance
outwardly resemble motion, in fact they cannot be regarded as such, because, according to Ibn
Sīnā, they occur instantaneously, not gradually.273
In the philosophy of Mullā Sadrā the (existence of) substantial motion is an undeniable and
self-evident truth (despite which, Sadrā made a lot of effort to demonstrate it in many ways).
Perhaps only the principle of the analogical gradation of existence can be regarded as more
significant and entailing more important consequences than the principle of substantial
motion (but, in fact, both are intertwined and inseparable from each other).
But, in order to understand what Sadrā meant by ”substantial motion” and why he was so
unshakeably convinced of its existence, we need to examine his concept of motion first,
finding out how it differs from that of Ibn Sīnā.
Sadrā describes motion as “a flowing state, whose existence is between pure potentiality and
pure act and whose concomitant is a finite gradual continuous affair which has no existence
that is described with presence and all-comprehensiveness (jam‘iyya) elsewhere except in the
estimative faculty (wahm)”.274 Technically this definition represents a combination of two
Avicennan definitions of motion, each of which deals with the latter in a different aspect. In
the first definition Ibn Sīnā describes motion as “a continuous intelligible affair of the object,
moving from the place of the beginning [of the movement] to the place of its end”.275 This
definition deals with the finite (qat‘iyya) movement, which exists only in our mind (dhihn) or
estimative faculty (wahm), but is not found in the outside, “among the entities” (fī ’l-a‘yān).
Notice that Sadrā treats it as the concomitant of the real motion that exists in the outside.
The second definition describes motion as “an existential affair [that exists] in the outside and
which consists in the body’s being in an intermediate position between the place of the
beginning [of its movement] and the place of its end, so that, whichever point between these
two is taken, its (the body’s – J.E.) “before” and “after” is not in it (the supposed point – J.E.).
This state lasts as long as the thing continues to be moving”.276 This is the definition of the
“intermediate movement” (al-haraka al-tawassutiyya), i.e., the movement as it is perceived
by our sense faculties. Sadrā describes it as a “flowing state” (hāla sayyāla) between
potentiality and actuality. Despite his criticisms of the above quoted Avicennan definitions277
(which result from Sadrā’s extreme existentialist position and his denying any reality to
quiddity), one cannot fail to notice that he develops his teaching on movement on the basis of
Ibn Sīnā’s doctrine. In other words, Sadrā treats an intermediate movement, understood as a
flowing affair, as a reality which exists in the outside, while he views the finite one as a

271
Ibn Sīnā, Najāt, 208.
272
See: Ibn Sīnā, Najāt, 204–208.
273
See: Ibn Sīnā, Najāt, 205.
274
Sadrā, Asfār, part 3, 59.
275
Ibn Sīnā, Shifā’, quoted from: Sadrā, Asfār, part 3, 31.
276
Ibn Sīnā, Shifā’, quoted from: Sadrā, Asfār, part 3, 32.
277
See: Sadrā, Asfār, part 3, 32–37.

80
concomitant of the former, which exists only in the estimative faculty – i.e., he sees the finite
movement as a shadow of the intermediate one.
However, if we consider movement as the mobility of a thing (mutaharrikkiyyat al-shay’), it
is nothing but self-renewal (tajaddud) and passing (inqidā’). Its proximate cause (al-‘illa al-
qarība), by necessity, must also be an affair which is not stable in its essence – otherwise, the
parts of movement would not become non-existent. Or perhaps it is more appropriate to say
that motion is an essential concomitant of the existence of this affair, which is fixed in its
quiddity and self-renewing in its existence – and, if it is so, it is more suitable to focus our
attention on the accompanied (malzūm), not on the accompanying (lāzim). The accompanied
affair, whose concomitant is motion, is, of course, nature (tabī‘a).
“The proximate cause of every species of motion is nature, and it is the substance which
constitutes the body and through which the body is actualized as a species, and it (and not
motion – J.E.) is the first perfection of the natural body in the aspect of its actual existence.
Hence, it is established and verified that every body is an affair which is self-renewing in its
existence and flowing in its he-ness (or: ipseity) (huwiyya), although it is fixed in its quiddity,
and through this, it differs from motion, because the meaning of the latter is self-renewal and
passing”.278
In other words, there is no such a thing as stable body, as far as its existence is considered. On
the contrary, every body should be considered as a particular aspect of the flow of existence –
an aspect, whose apparent stability results from an error of our sense perception. Motion is
not external to such a body and is not predicated to it from outside. Rather, this is a certain
quiddity which is predicated to one or another aspect or level of existence.
The principles of Peripatetic philosophy require an unchanging substratum for every change.
In Sadrian philosophy, in which body is viewed as an existentially self-renewing and
perpetually flowing affair, it apparently cannot serve as such substratum. Sadrā solves the
arising difficulty by stating that the requirement for the stability of substratum applies only to
those motions which are not existential concomitants of nature (for example, passage from
one place to another, transmutation and growth). As Tabātabā’ī remarks in his gloss, this
assertion, in fact, testifies that Sadrā believes that all categories move through the movement
of the substance which is their substratum. Tabātabā’ī also notes that non-concomitant
movements, which occur in the categories of place, position, quality and quantity, do not rely
on the nature of the moving substance as such, but, nevertheless, the furthest limits of these
non-concomitant movements are the concomitant ones, which directly depend on the nature
of their substratum.279
Another difficulty concerning the substratum of movement lies in the fact that, according to
Aristotle and Ibn Sīnā, it consists of something potential and something actual. Sadrā’s
answer to them (and probably also to Kirmānī) is that the postulate of the existence of two
different affairs, one of which is potential and another actual, is a product of mental analysis
(tahlīl ‘aqlī), while in reality the potential and the actual is one and the same thing and belong
to one existential direction. The fixity of movement manifests itself as its self-renewal, and,
likewise, the fixity of that through which movement occurs, that is, nature which is
engendered in the bodies, manifests itself as its essential self-renewal. But what is the
mechanism of this fixity-and-self-renewal? According to Sadrā, it is based on the possibility
of preparedness (imkān isti‘dādī), and the self-renewal of nature manifests itself as “dressing
after dressing” (al-labs ba‘d al-labs). As Fazlul Rahman justly remarks, the self-renewal is

278
Sadrā, Asfār, part 3, 62.
279
See: Sadrā, Asfār, part 3, 62, note 2.

81
perceived by Sadrā as an “essentially evolutionary and unidirectional individual process-
entity”.280
To understand this properly, we must keep in mind that the reality of prime matter is nothing
else than potentiality and preparedness, while the reality of form is nature with its self-
renewing temporal origination. Through its evolving preparedness, the prime matter receives
a new form in every instant, each form having a different matter, which accompanies it by
necessity. In turn, this matter is prepared to receive another form, different from that which
necessitated it (matter) through preparedness. Thus we find that form is prior to matter in
essence, but its (the form’s) individual he-ness (ipseity) is posterior to matter in time. Hence,
both form and matter possess self-renewal and perpetuity through the other. The popular
belief that the form of a non-compound body is one and unchanging arises from the similarity
of the changing forms. In actual fact, however, these forms are one by their philosophical
definition (hadd) and meaning, but they are not one in number, because they are renewed and
replaced with each other in every instant, in a continuous manner.281 This made Tabātabā’ī
conclude that Sadrā saw existence as one continuous flowing affair, from which hypothetical
limitations (i.e., the intelligible quiddities – e.g. those of man, animal, plant etc.) are
abstracted by mind.282
“There is one continuous (or: uninterrupted) individual existence, which has infinite limitations
in potential in respect to instants, hypothesized in its time, and [, therefore,] in it exist an infinite
number of species – in potentia and in meaning, not in actu and in [actual] existence”.283
The difficulty with the apparent lack of an unchanging and persisting substratum (mawdū‘) in
substantial motion, to which pointed Ibn Sīnā, is easily resolved if we agree to treat substance
not as a static affair, but as a dynamic one and as an individual process. 284
“Although it is necessary that the substratum of every movement subsists through its existence
and individuation, in the individuation of a corporeal substratum, it is sufficient that there is
matter which is individuated through the existence of some [sort of] form, quality and quantity,
and it (matter – J.E.) can change in respect to the particularities of each of them (i.e., form,
quiddity and quantity – J.E.)”.285
In other words, the subsistence of the substratum is achieved through the existence of matter
and some indeterminate form, quality and quantity. As Fazlul Rahman observes, this
indeterminate form, quality and quantity behaves vis-à-vis the progressively emerging infinity
of determinate forms, qualities and quantities “as a genus does vis-à-vis concrete species”.286
Hence, the persisting substratum is an unbounded body (jism mutlaq), i.e., a body-in-general,
not a particular body, while the unity of the moving substance is one of the process-entity or
the event-structure.287
On the other side, as Tabātabā’ī remarks, if the movement lacks unity of continuity, the
subsistence of substratum alone does not provide the unity of movement. Moreover,
according to Tabātabā’ī, while the subsistence of substratum is a necessary precondition of
the accidental movements (such as the movements in quality, quantity, position and place),
because they are accidents, whose existence is only possible in substratum and whose

280
Rahman, Philosophy, 100.
281
See: Sadrā, Asfār, part 3, 63–64.
282
See: Sadrā, Asfār, part 3, 64, note 2.
283
Sadrā, Asfār, part 3, 86.
284
See: Rahman, Philosophy, 100.
285
Sadrā, Asfār, part 3, 87–88.
286
Rahman, Philosophy, 100.
287
See: Sadrā, Asfār, part 3, 92–93 and: Rahman, Philosophy, 100–101.

82
individuation takes place through it, this is not the case with the material substance, which
exists through itself and, in its individual unity, does not require anything else apart from its
own existence, which is simultaneously its individuation.
The material substance, says Tabātābā’ī, insofar as it is considered as the possessor of
substantial motion, is both the movement and the moving one, because its selfhood which is
movement is attributed to its selfhood which is substance. In a nutshell, accidental movements
in respect of their unity and individuality require a substantial substratum, a possessor of unity
and individuality, as a root and basis of their flowing unity and individuality.288 While
accidents need substance as their substratum and cannot exist without it, the substance has no
need in a substratum other than itself. Since Sadrā views every corporeal and psychic
substance as an evolutionary and unidirectional process, its actual substratum is nothing else
than the continuity of this process.289
Does Sadrā’s theory of substantial motion, as gradual and evolutionary unidirectional
movement towards perfection, constitute a revolutionary new teaching in the context of
Islamic philosophy? By no means – the idea, probably stemming from the Neoplatonic
concepts of processio and reditus, found its expression in the well-known teaching of scala
naturae, which was equally popular in the mediaeval Europe and the mediaeval Muslim
East.290 The uninterrupted chain of being, which ascends from the lowest and simplest to the
highest and most complex creatures, was viewed as the product of gradual emanation and
natural growth of things in perfection. Among the first Muslim philosophers who discussed
the issue in their treatises in detail were the Brethren of Purity (Ikhwān al-Safā’). Thus, they
wrote:
“Know, o brother, that the sublunary beings begin from the most imperfect and lowest states
and then ascend towards the most perfect and eminent state. This occurs with the passage of
time and with every instant, since their nature does not receive the emanation from the spherical
forms at one single time, but gradually, one thing after another”. 291
Sadrā’s merit lies in discussing this Neoplatonic theory in terms of Peripatetic philosophy and
in overcoming the resistance of the latter by interpreting material substance as a continuous
flow and evolutionary process, instead of viewing it as a static and unchangeable entity.
Besides, while Ikhwān al-Safā’ focus their attention on the universal chain of being, Sadrā’s
main concern lies with a particular corporeal or psychic substance. This is not mineral’s
becoming plant and plant’s developing into animal that concerns Sadrā, but body’s becoming
soul and soul’s becoming intellect, this world’s growing into the other one (the hereafter) and
the transformation of the first (corporeal) configuration (al-nash’a al-awla) into the other
(spiritual) one (al-nash’a al-ukhra). This is primarily an eschatological concern: this-worldly
life, events, phenomena are regarded by Sadrā as preparatory stage(s) and shadow(s) of the
other-worldly one(s) (the eschatological implications of the theory of substantial motion will
be discussed in detail in the third chapter).
In the world of Nature all substances are subject to substantial motion, because the existence
of a material substance, regardless of the corruptibility (in case of elemental bodies) or the
288
See: Sadrā, Asfār, part 3, 87, note 1.
289
See: Rahman, Philosophy, 100.
290
On scala naturae, see: A.Lovejoy, The Great Chain of Being, Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press
1936.
291
Ikhwān al-Safā’, Rasā’īl, 4 vols., Beirūt: Dār al-Sādir 1957, Vol. 2, 183, quoted from: D. De
Smet, “The Sacredness of Nature in Shi’I Isma‘ili Islam” in K.van Berkel and A.Vanderjagt (eds), The Book
of Nature in Antiquity and Middle Ages (Groningen Studies in Cultural Change. 10), Louvain: Peeters 2005,
87, note 8. Cf. also Y.Marquet’s French translation in: Y.Marquet, “La determination astrale de l’ evolution
selon les Freres de la Purete” in Bulletin d’Etudes Orientales 44 (1992), 129.

83
incorruptibility (in case of celestial ones) of its matter, can only be envisaged as an
unidirectional evolutionary process – or, to say it more precisely, in respect to its existence,
every material substance is an individualized unidirectional evolutionary process. During its
development, this substance becomes subject to an infinite number of changes and alterations
– “dressing after dressing”, which means that, in order to assume a new and higher form, it
does not need to take off the previous lower one (e.g. in order to assume the form of animal
soul, the substance does not need to abandon and take off the form of the vegetative one).
Quite the opposite, in order to be able to receive a higher form, the substance must first
receive the lower one (thus, in order to be able to receive the form of animal soul, the
respective substance must first receive that of the vegetative one). Sadrā calls this rule (the
principle of) “the lower possibility” (al-imkān al-akhass) (which is to be understood as the
necessity to previously actualize the lower possibility in order to allow the actualization of the
higher one) and, in the ascending arc of being, places it opposite the well-known Peripatetic
rule of “the higher possibility” (al-imkān al-ashraf) (according to which, the actualization of
the lower possibility is only possible through and after the actualization of the higher one) in
the descending arc. More importantly, the existence of natural body is only possible and can
be conceived of as substantial motion and stability in flow. The particular evolutionary path
taken by a certain aspect of the flow of material existence (thought of in terms of substantial
motion) is determined by its particular principle, referred to as its “nature” (tabī‘a). This
particular principle or nature of the body is, in fact, nothing but tenuity (raqīqa) that links the
reality (haqīqa) or immaterial archetype of the thing with its material idols. Although nature
is the proximate cause of substantial motion, the ultimate goal of the latter is to bring the
substance out of the world of Nature, placing it among the inhabitants of the world of
Command, that is, to increase the intensity of its existence to a level sufficient to make
possible it to exist as pure disengaged dominating light (nūr mujarrad qāhir) or Intellect.

2.3.6. Substantial Motion and New Creation

I shall now attempt to compare Sadrā’s theory of substantial motion with Ibn al-‘Arabī’s
teaching on new creation (khalq jadīd). During the 20th century it became almost a
commonplace belief among the experts in Islamic philosophy that Sadrā’s theory represents
nothing else than a philosophical demonstration of Ibn al-‘Arabī’s teaching on new creation
(Sadrā himself being partially responsible for the spread and strengthening of the belief, since
in his discourses on substantial motion he had employed the expression khalq jadīd a number
of times292). Is it really so? Or is Sadrā’s usage of the aforementioned Qur’anic and Sufi term
merely a rhetorical technique, designed to capture the attention of the audience and to intrigue
them? Before I try to answer these questions, I must first briefly examine the concept of new
creation and its history.
As Ibn al-‘Arabī himself acknowledges, his idea of the perpetual renewal of creation was, at
least partially, inspired by the Ash‘arite teaching on substances and accidents. As it is well
known, the Ash‘arites believed the world to consist of immutable substances and ever
changing accidents. Their famous axiom was “The accidents do not remain for two moments”
(al-a‘rād lā tabqā zamānayn). While the Ash‘arites viewed substance as the underlying
substratum of accidents, they hold that the substances of which the world consists have no
independent existence in themselves, but wholly depend on God’s power, which continually
recreates the world in every instant (needless to say, such understanding of substance
(jawhar) makes it practically synonymous with atom (al-jawhar al-fard, literally – “an

292
See e.g.: Sadrā, Asrār, 63, 86.

84
indivisible particle”)).293 In the twelfth chapter of the Fusūs, which contains one of the most
important discussions on khalq jadīd, Ibn al-‘Arabī admits that two groups – the Ash‘arites
and the Relativists (hisbāniyya) – in their reasoning have approached to the understanding of
the mystery of perpetual creation, but, states he, both have failed to penetrate to its heart and
core. As for the Ash‘arites, they have grasped the perpetual renewal of some of the existents,
namely the accidents, but they have not realized that the world in its entirety represents
nothing else than the totality (majmū‘) of accidents, for which reason it entirely changes in
every moment. In turn, the Relativists have apprehended that the world perpetually changes in
its entirety, but they have failed to notice the oneness of the entity of the substance which
receives the form of the world and which does not exist otherwise than through it (whereas
the form also cannot be conceived otherwise than through this substance).294
Importantly, in this discussion Ibn al-‘Arabī defines the new creation as the “self-renewal of
the affair with every breath” (tajdīd al-amr ma‘a ’l-anfās)295, which (self-renewal) is
necessitated by the facts that “God manifests Himself [anew] in every breath”296 and that “a
[particular] self-disclosure is never repeated”.297 (However, Ibn al-‘Arabī’s commentator
Mu’ayyad al-Dīn al-Jandī remarks that the Real’s essential self-disclosure is one and eternal,
and, if considered without any relation, it never changes in any way. The perpetual change
and alteration of the Real’s self-disclosures witnessed by (certain strata of) mystics are
occasioned by the change of the preparedness of the receptacles.298)
One notices that, every time, a new creation is necessitated by and depends on a new breath.
These breaths represent fragments or instances of the all-encompassing Breath of the Merciful
(nafas al-Rahmān). It seems not unreasonable to assume that perpetual origination, in a way,
results from the fragmentation of the Breath of the Merciful in respect to its particular
receptacles, which, due to their limitations and difference in preparedness, cannot receive this
all-encompassing breath in its entirety at one time, but are only able to do this gradually,
dividing it in different directions and aspects according to the division that exists between
God’s names. Hence, in the same way as no human being, due to the narrowness of his breast,
can partake of the Breath of the Merciful otherwise than through a series of subsequent
breaths, our mystical intuition cannot conceive of creation otherwise than as of an (infinite)
chain of self-disclosures, every link of which simultaneously marks the appearance of a new
form and the disappearance of the previous one. Thus, the teaching of new creation in Ibn al-
‘Arabī’s thought deals mainly with the relationship between the limited existence and the
unlimited one.
Due to its confinement in time and space, the material universe is also confined in meaning –
or probably the actual case is vice versa: its limitation in meaning manifests itself as spatial
and temporal limitation(s).The narrowness of the receptacle, thus, makes the Real’s act upon
it to be actualized gradually, step by step, instant after instant (=breath after breath), creation
after creation. (Sadrā would certainly say that this narrowness and confinement results from
the weakness/ lowness of intensity of the natural existence – or that at its lower degrees of
intensity existence manifests itself as natural one, i.e., as an existence which is confined in
time and space and cannot simultaneously assume more than one particular form.)

293
See: S. van den Bergh, “Dhawhar” (II.493a) in EI.
294
See: Ibn al-‘Arabī, Fusūs, 125.
295
Ibn al-‘Arabī, Fusūs, 125.
296
Ibn al-‘Arabī, Fusūs, 126.
297
Ibn al-‘Arabī, Fusūs, 126.
298
See: Mu’ayyad al-Dīn al-Jandī, Sharh Fusūs al-hikam, 2nd edition, ed. S.J.Āshtiyānī, Qum: Būstān-i Kitāb
1381 S.H., 494–495.

85
A number of passages found in the Futūhāt testify that the perpetual new creation of the
world is necessitated by the narrowness of the receptacle. However, to Ibn al-‘Arabī, this
receptacle is existence (=finding) itself:
“Within the Treasuries are found the individuals of genera. These individuals are infinite, and
that which is infinite does not enter into existence, since everything confined by existence is
finite”.299
“The possible things are infinite, and there cannot be more than the infinite. But the infinite
does not enter into existence at once (daf‘atan); rather it enters little by little, without an end”.300
But, upon a more careful examination of the above quotations, one realizes that, what the
Greatest Shaykh understands here by existence is the external and natural existence.
Furthermore, one notices that, to Ibn al-‘Arabī, new creation is not a unidirectional and
evolutionary process – i.e., the subsequent form is not necessarily more perfect in any aspect
than the previous one. Also, in new creation, through assuming a new form, the (material)
existence unclothes itself of the earlier one, wherefore the process must be described as
“dressing after undressing” (al-labs ba‘d al-khal‘), not as “dressing after dressing” (al-labs
ba‘d al-labs), as it is the case with substantial motion. This is, apparently, the most important
difference between Ibn al-‘Arabī and Sadrā’s teachings on khalq jadīd and haraka jawhariyya
respectively. Ibn al-‘Arabī is overwhelmed by the vision of the perpetual renewal of the
world, which can probably be characterized as the attempt of the finite to grasp the infinite
and the try of the limited to take grip of the unlimited – the task, which can never be
completed. Sadrā, in turn, envisages the material world as a flowing substance which, in its
every part and by every instant, moves one – albeit an immeasurably small - step closer
towards spirituality and perfection.
The new creation, as it is understood by Ibn al-‘Arabī, i.e. the limited’s attempt to express and
manifest the unlimited, takes place in keeping with a certain regular pattern (likeness is
normally replaced with likeness, not opposite with opposite) – the pattern which is cyclically
repeated and recreated. For this reason, it can be described as a cyclical event and presented
graphically as circular motion.
In turn, substantial motion as envisaged by Sadrā, i.e., as unidirectional evolutionary process
and gradual spiritualization of material existence, occurring due to the increase of the latter’s
intensity, can be graphically presented as a half of the circle, i.e., as its ascending arc. What
happens to the moving substance once it has reached the summit of the arc? According to
Sadrā, it remains with the Godhead, becoming existentially one with its noetic archetype (the
respective dominating light).
This difference in approaches results from a more principal difference between the visions of
the two thinkers: while, to Ibn al-‘Arabī, existence is an accident of the fixed entity, the
presence or absence of which does not in any way change the quiddity/ whatness of the
respective entity and its status in God’s mind, to Sadrā, there is no such thing as an externally
non-existent entity, eternally present in God’s mind. Rather, the existence is the only thing
which is/ exists, whereas quiddities are nothing else than its potential limitations, which does
not really exist, but are abstracted by the mind from the perpetual flow of (one and the same)
existence and its different aspects.
Although there is a noticeable and undeniable parallel between Sadrā’s vision of the flow of
existence and Ibn al-‘Arabī’s teaching on the Breath of the Merciful, there is apparently more
consequence in Sadrā’s position, which denies the whatnesses any reality whatsoever. On the
299
Ibn al-‘Arabī, Futūhāt, part 3, 361, quoted from: Chittick, Knowledge, 96.
300
Ibn al-‘Arabī, Futūhāt, part 2, 482, quoted from: Chittick, Knowledge, 96.

86
contrary, regarding Ibn al-‘Arabī’s teaching, it must be said that the existential status of the
places of articulation (makhārij al-hurūf), passing through which the inarticulate breath
becomes articulated, thus giving birth to letters and words, remains ambiguous and is not
(cannot be?) explained properly.
That said, I have to add that when Sadrā employs the term khalq jadīd, he does it either to
designate the self-renewal of (bodily) nature in general301 or to point to the ultimate limit of
this self-renewal – the developing of the (configuration of) this world into that of the other
one (the hereafter).302 (The former was discussed above; the latter will be examined in detail
in the third chapter.)

2.3. THE SOUL AND ITS PROPERTIES

As it was said above, different parts of the spectrum of wujūd possess different properties.
This difference arises from change of the wujūd’s intensity. (Cf. the different properties of
water in temperatures below 0° C, between 0° and 100° C and above 100° C.) Thus far, I have
attempted to examine the properties of the top and the bottom of the range of existence (i.e.,
those of Intellect/ Innovation and Nature/ material origination). Between these two principal
ranges or levels of intensity, there is a sort of a border area or the medium spectrum, usually
referred to as “the soul” (al-nafs). I shall now attempt to succinctly examine its specific
properties and characteristics, which allow to distinguish it from both extremes.
The range of the so-called natural existence is the domain of the sense perception (hiss); the
range of the innovative (ibdā‘ī) one – the realm of the Intellect (‘aql) and the intellection
(ta‘aqqul). The middle part of the spectrum of existence – i.e., the psychic (nafsānī)
existence, manifests itself as imagination (khayāl) or imaginary perception (takhayyul).
This is probably the point where Sadrā’s cosmology comes closest to that of Ibn al-‘Arabī,
treating existence (wujūd) as perception (idrāk) and erasing the border between ontology and
epistemology. To identify itself fully with the latter (Ibn al-‘Arabī’s teaching), it needed to
accept the principle of the parallelism between the “great man” and the “small one”, i.e., the
universe and the human being. This identification was never made explicitly by Sadrā,
because the acceptance of the theory would inevitably lead to an outright rejection of the
Aristotelian cosmology and, by necessity, to its replacement with the Neoplatonic one,
reintroducing the notion of the cosmos as living and conscious being and representing the
psychic world as the product of the imagination of the Universal Soul. If the cosmos is a
living and conscious being, there is no need for the omnipotent and omnipresent god (unless
we interpret him as the reality of existence (haqīqat al-wujūd)).

2.4.1. The Peripatetic Influence

Following Aristotle, al-Fārābī and Ibn Sīnā had viewed and defined the human soul in relation
to the body, as its form, power, faculty and entelechy. According to the principles of Sadrā’s
philosophy, this approach was wrong, because the body represented an existence of a lower
rank and intensity and, as such, could not give an adequate representation of the reality that
was of a higher intensity of existence. Although, to my knowledge, Sadrā never applies the
term in his discourse on the soul-body relationship, he definitely views the body as the

301
See e.g.: Sadrā, Asrār, 63; 86–87.
302
See e.g.: Sadrā, Asfār, part 8, 17.

87
“illuminative relation” (al-idāfa al-ishrāqiyya) of the soul, i.e., as a sort of radiance, irradiated
by the latter (thus, in the Asfār he writes: “The true body – the one, in which the flow of the
light of sense and life occurs essentially, not accidentally, – relates to the soul as radiance
relates to the sun”303). What appealed to Sadrā in Fārābī and Ibn Sīnā’s teachings on the soul
was their admittance of the possibility of the soul’s development into an actualized intellect,
by means of which (development) it gradually became more and more independent of the
body and continued to exist after its separation from the body (i.e. the physical death).
I believe this Peripatetic theory of the development of the soul and its ascent from the level of
the material intellect (al-‘aql al-hayulānī) to that of the acquired one (al-‘aql al-muktasab) –
and not Ibn al-‘Arabī’s teaching on the new creation – was the primary and the most essential
source of inspiration for Sadrā’s doctrine of substantial motion. One important reason to
assert this lies in the fact that the aforementioned development of the soul is based on the
principle “dressing after dressing” – i.e., in order to take on a new higher form, the soul does
not have to put off the previous one, but keeps it as a concomitant of the new one.

2.4.2. Sadrā’s Definitions of the Soul

Apart from the standard Peripatetic definition of the soul as the first entelechy (perfection) of
the natural body304 (which he considers to be correct but incomplete, because it does not deal
with the essence of the soul, but only with its relation to the body), Sadrā offers at least two
alternative definitions.
The first one describes the soul in relation to the acts that proceed from it:
“I call every active faculty (quwwa fā‘iliyya) which produces traces not in a univocal (or: one
and the same) way “the soul”. This expression names this faculty not in the respect of its simple
(non-compound) essence, but in the aspect of its being the principle (or: source) of such-like
acts (i.e., acts that occur not in a univocal manner – J.E.)”.305
The second one also defines the soul in respect to its actions, but in this case – by stating that
they are carried out through one or more intermediaries, not directly:
“We treat as the soul the faculty of the natural body whose rank is such that it performs its acts
by employing (literally: “by making serve to itself”) (istikhdām) other faculties [that are] under
it”.306
This second definition cannot be properly understood if considered without connection with
Sadrā’s famous principle “the soul is all faculties” (al-nafs kull al-quwa), which (principle) is
a branch and an instance of the more general principle, mentioned above, namely “a thing
which is simple is all things” (basīt al-haqīqa kull al-ashyā’), which is to be understood to the
effect that a more intense degree of existence contains in itself all weaker ones.
“It was previously established that the Author (al-bārī’) is all things without multiplication [of
His essence]. Therefore, whatever is closer to Him, is stronger in its oneness and brings together
in itself more meanings, to the effect that every existent is a world in itself, [ – a world] which
imitates (or: reproduces (?)) the world of Lordship. The human soul brings together in itself all
that is dispersed in the body and the forms of the bodily members, that is, faculties and tools.
The difference in the shapes of the bodily members is the shadow of (i.e., reflects – J.E.) the
difference among the perceptual and locomotive faculties, whose tools are dispersed in other

303
Sadrā, Asfār, part 9, 99.
304
See e.g.: Sadrā, Asfār, part 8, 17.
305
Sadrā, Asfār, part 8, 5.
306
Sadrā, Asfār, part 8, 17.

88
bodily parts with (or: through) the dispersion of spirit which disperses [itself] from the heart into
veins and arteries. These faculties, regardless of their differences and division into branches, are
brought together in the existence of the soul, and the soul unifies itself with them by a
unification [akin to] the actual unification of the intellect with the intelligible substances”.307

2.4.3. The Soulhood of the Soul

The soul begins its life as a corporeal faculty (al-quwwa al-jismāniyya), which, due to the low
intensity (=weakness) of its existence, conceives of itself as of and manifests itself in a
multitude of faculties, which, in turn, can only exercise their power by means of the natural
body and its members, employed by these faculties as (their respective) tools.
According to Sadrā’s vision, all material things – or rather prime matter itself – experience
perpetual spiritualization. This spiritualization of matter should be understood as gradual
increase of the intensity of its existence. A certain phase of the process of spiritualization and
a definite range of intensity, which has certain specific properties, is commonly referred to as
“the [human] soul” (al-nafs [al-insāniyya]). At the lowest limit of the spectrum, the soul is
almost completely “immersed” in matter and represents nothing more than a bodily power/
faculty. Upon reaching the highest limit of the spectrum, it fully disengages itself from (any
sort of) the body and becomes pure spirit:
“You must know that the soul, which is the form of the human being, is corporeal by its
[temporal] origination (jismāniyyat al-hudūth) and spiritual by its subsistence (rūhāniyyat al-
baqā’), because, as it was established earlier, the passive intellect is the last of the corporeal
meanings and the first of the spiritual ones. The human being is a road stretched between the
two worlds, and he is simple by his spirit, but compound by his body. The nature of his body is
the purest of the earthly natures, and his soul is the first of the levels of the noble souls. He has a
rank that permits him to assume an angelic form. When he turns away from what befits him
best, [then] he deserves that [to which he has turned himself] rather than ascent to the ranks of
the noble ones. He takes off the human form, and the angelic form eludes him, and through his
actions he assumes either devilish, or [predatory] beastly, or brutish form, and remains in the
flame of fires, without ascending to the degrees of gardens”.308
To Sadrā, the term nafs designates a certain spectrum of existence, possessing a particular
level of intensity and displaying specific properties, which are not displayed by the higher and
lower (stronger and weaker) spectra. In view of this, the “soulhood” (nafsiyya) of the soul is
not an accident that occurs to it when it takes charge of a natural body, as both Peripatetics
commonly hold (their belief being rooted in the gnostic myth of the imprisonment of the soul
in the body by the evil Demiurge309). Rather, the “soulhood” of the soul is a particular kind of
existence, which is exemplified by the soul as long as the latter depends on the physical body
and employs its faculties.
“The soulhood of the soul is not a relation accidentally occurring to its existence, as the
common philosophers thought, likening the soul’s relation to the body to that of a ruler to his
city or a captain to his ship. Rather the soulhood of the soul is its particular mode of existence,
[which is] not like the state of ruler, captain, father or the rest of those who [first] have their
own proper essence, which [then] happen to become related with the other, after their essence

307
Sadrā, Asfār, part 8, 121–122.
308
Sadrā, Shawāhid, 311.
309
Among the Muslim thinkers, the theme was developed by Ibn Sīnā in his Risāla fī ’l-tayr (“Treatise on the
Bird”) (see: Ibn Sīnā, “Risāla fī ’l-tayr”, in H.Corbin, Avicenne et le récit visionnaire, t.2, Teheran_Paris:
Librairie d’Adrienne Maisonneuve 1954, 26–39) and by Shihāb al-Dīn Yahyā Suhrawardī in several treatises,
particularly in the Risāla fī ’l-ghurba al-gharbiyya (“Tale of the Occidental Exile”) (see: Shihabuddin Yahya
Suhrawardi, The Philosophical Allegories and Mystical Treatises, a Parallel Persian-English Text, ed. and
transl. W.M.Thackston Jr, Costa Mesa: Mazda Publishers 1999, 106–126.

89
has [already] come into existence, – because it is impossible to conceive of such existence of the
soul – as long as it remains the soul – in the aspect of which it does not depend on the body and
does not employ its faculties, unless its existence is so transformed and its substantiation
strengthens to such a degree that it becomes self-sufficient in its essence and ceases to depend
on the natural body, and “returns to his people rejoicing” (84:9) or “burns in a blazing fire”
(111:3)”.310
To properly understand the character of the soul’s dependence upon the body, it must be kept in
mind that the soul needs the body in its acts, whereas in its essence it is fully independent even
during its residence in the natural world. Furthermore, depending on the standpoint taken, one
can discern either one or two intermediaries between the soul and the body proper – namely, the
animal spirit (al-rūh al-hayavānī) and the heart (qalb), which must be treated as borderline
substance(s) between psychic and physical realms. The role of the animal spirit is discussed by
Sadrā in one of his early treatises, namely al-Wāridāt al-qalbiyya fī ma‘rifat al-rubūbiyya (“The
Inrushes of the Heart Concerning the Knowledge of the Lordship”), where he writes:
“The carrier (or: subject) (hāmil) of all faculties of the human soul and its vicegerent is the
vaporous animal spirit, which emanates from the pure and subtle part of the mixtures (ikhlāt) in
the same way as the [bodily] members emanate from their (mixtures’ – J.E.) impure and dense
part, its (animal spirit’s – J.E.) locus of origin being the conically shaped heart”.311
“… these elements and pillars continue to mix perpetually, until finally [their mixing] results in
[giving existence to (?)] the human body. The human body [, in turn,] continues to refine and
unify itself, and to purify and to change itself, until this results in its [animal] spirit – the one
which is a subtle body that emanates from the heart, from its left cavity. In respect to its purity
and refinement, its light and luminosity, and its distance from the opposites (closeness to which
causes corruption), this animal spirit resembles the body of the celestial sphere. Therefore it
becomes the mirror for the rational soul, through which it perceives existence in its entirety”.312
Speaking in terms of intensity of existence, a more intense and stronger existence (the psychic
one, i.e., the soul) cannot perceive and govern a weaker existence (i.e., the natural one or that of
the sensible body) otherwise than through an intermediary that shares the characteristics of both.
Hence, it is evident that external forms can be perceived by the soul only accidentally, serving
as temporal preparatory tools until the essential perception is fully developed.
“The five perceived ones (i.e., things perceived by five external faculties of the soul – J.E.)…
are hidden (ghaybiyya) (i.e., not perceived externally – J.E.) luminous likenesses that exist in
another world, not the qualities that are called “the sensible ones” (mahsūsāt) [which are not
perceived] otherwise than accidentally, and they (the qualities essentially perceived by the soul
– J.E.) are psychic qualities (kayfiyyāt nafsāniyya), and if you want to learn the truth, [you must
know that] these faculties do not subsist by the bodily parts, but rather the bodily parts subsist
by their command, because the demonstration shows unshakeably that if some thing inheres in
some other thing and the existence of this inherent thing in itself is its very existence in its
locus, [then] it is impossible that it would exist in one world and its locus – in another. Hence,
the inherent thing and that in which it inheres [both] are in one [and the same] world, and the
perceiver and the perceived are of one kind”.313
In other words, the perceiver (mudrik) and the perceived (mudrak) always belong to one and
the same configuration (nash’a) and level of existence. This truth constitutes Sadrā’s famous
principle of the “unity (or: unification) of the perceiver and the perceived” (ittihād al-mudrik
wa ’l-mudrak), according to which the real objects of our perception are the forms created by
310
Sadrā, ‘Arshiyya, 238–239. Cf. J.Morris’s earlier English translation, from which I borrow the translation of
the Qur’anic verses (Morris, Wisdom, 139).
311
Sadr al-Dīn al-Shīrāzī, al-Wāridāt al-qalbiyya fī ma‘rifat al-rubūbiyya, ed. A.Shafī‘īhā, Tehrān: Iranian
Academy of Philosophy 1979, 83–84.
312
Sadrā, Wāridāt, 90.
313
Sadrā, ‘arshiyya, 236.

90
and residing in our soul. The external sensible forms are only needed in the initial stages of
the development of the human soul when its “soulhood” has not yet become strong enough,
because it is still deeply immersed in matter (one can argue, as Plato does, that the real
purpose of the soul’s recourse to these outer forms is to facilitate its “remembering”
(recollection) of their luminous intelligible likenesses, but, to my knowledge, there are no
indications in Sadrā’s texts that would prove his support of Plato’s claim).
“The truth about seeing, as God has revealed to us, is that, after meeting these specified
preconditions (i.e., the provision of the externally visible things that can be seen with our outer
eyes – J.E.), with God’s permission, from the soul arise forms, dependent (mu‘allaqa) on it, [ –
forms] which subsist through it and are present to it, and appear as likenesses (of the outer
forms – J.E.) in its own world, not in this [outer] world”.314
These forms, once brought into existence, are preserved by the faculty (or: power) of
imagination (quwwa al-khayāl) and constitute our store of the hereafter.
The key faculty of the human soul – the one which makes it soul – is the faculty of
imagination, which stores and preserves the images received by the common sense (al-hiss al-
mushtarak). These two faculties (faculty of imagination and common sense), in fact, represent
one faculty or power, in which two aspects – that of receipt and that of preservation – which
differ from each other in terms of strength and weakness and perfection and imperfection, can
be distinguished. While during its bodily existence the soul is all external and internal
faculties, after its separation from the natural body it retains only the faculty of imagination –
or rather itself becomes pure imagination (by which becoming I mean the soul’s perpetual
creating immaterial measurable likenesses (muthul miqdāriyya ghayr mādiyya)).
When the intensity of the intelligible light-existence, which constitutes the world of
Innovation, decreases, it leaves the horizon of Intellect and dawns over the horizon of
imagination. On this horizon, each ray of the intelligible light is transformed into an
immaterial measurable likeness. When, in turn, the light of existence leaves the horizon of
imagination (or that of the soul proper) and dawns over the horizon of Nature, appearing in
the world of Sense, this subtle immaterial image thickens and hardens, becoming seemingly
firm and unchangeable. Then we refer to it as to “material natural body” (al-jism al-tabī‘ī al-
mādī). Thus, according to Sadrā, in the last analysis, all existential changes and metamor-
phoses come down to more or less radical change of the intensity of wujūd.

314
Sadrā, ‘arshiyya, 237.

91
CHAPTER 3. TRANSFORMATIONS OF WUJŪD:
SADRĀ’S ESCHATOLOGY

3.1. MA‘ĀD AS A UNIVERSAL PRINCIPLE

The Arabic term for eschatology is ‘ilm al-ma‘ād (‘the knowledge/ science of return/
resurrection’). Ma‘ād is the verbal noun (masdar), derived from the verb a‘āda, (the fourth
verbal form of the verbal root ‘a-w-d), which means ‘to return something to somebody, to
recommence, to reiterate’.315 Literally, ma‘ād designates the place of return. However, as a
theological and philosophical term, it combines in itself the sense of return and that of
recommencement/ reiteration, denoting simultaneously the process of return to God (i.e., to
the reality and principle of existence) and resurrection or the second creation.
Ma‘ād as an eschatological concept denoting return/ resurrection is divided into ma‘ād rūhānī
(‘spiritual return’) and ma‘ād jusmānī (‘corporeal restoration’). According to the
Mutakallimūn, ma‘ād rūhānī consists in the return of the spirits to their restored bodies.
According to the Falāsifa, it should be understood as the return of a particular human soul to
the Active Intellect. As for the ma‘ād jusmānī, most Peripatetic philosophers tend to negate it
(thus, in fact, negating any kind of return/ resurrection for the overwhelming majority of
human beings – all those, whose souls fail to ascend to the Active Intellect and unite with it).
Ibn Sīnā was in doubt regarding the subject – however, as one can conclude from the succinct
remarks in the Shifā’ (“Healing”) and [al-Risāla] al-Adhawiyya (”The Enlightening
[Treatise]”), he was ready to admit that the bliss of the blissful ones in the hereafter might be
caused by perception of imaginal forms, similar to dream images, but of stronger and more
lasting effect than the one provoked by witnessing the latter.316
The return of every thing towards its root and principle is recognized as an axiom by all
currents of Islamic philosophy and theology. Therefore, the lasting argument between
different theological and philosophical schools concerns not the if of ma‘ād (i.e., its actual
occurrence), but its how (i.e., its qualities and characteristics). The return/ restoration of all
existents is an important consequence of the principle of substantial motion, therefore it is no
wonder that Sadrā discusses ma‘ād as a universal cosmological principle in most of his
works. Thus, in the ‘arshiyya he says:
“…every natural substance has an essential motion, and creation and sending forth (ba‘th), and
beginning and return. The philosophers have established for natures essential furthest limits, as
well as essential beginnings, and the return of every thing is to that [affair] from which it begins.
The return of the bodies is to [bodily] faculties, the return of faculties – to souls, the return of
souls – to spirits, and the return of everything is to Him (may He be exalted!)”.317
In light of Sadrā’s basic philosophical principles, the return to God must (and can only be)
understood as the increase of the intensity of existence, its strengthening and becoming
simpler and more inclusive. Therefore, the soul’s return to the intellect is nothing else than an
intensification of its existence. (Elsewhere Sadrā, following Plotinus, describes intellects as
powerful senses and senses as weak intellects.318)
Different kinds of ma‘ād are discussed in detail in the Risāla fī ’l-hashr (“Treatise on
Gathering”) (hashr (‘gathering, mustering, assembling’) in Sadrā’s terminology is
315
See e.g.: R.Arnaldez, “Ma‘ād” (V.892.b), in EI.
316
See: Sadrā, Asfār, part 9, 150–151, where the relevant passage from Ibn Sīnā’s Adhawiyya is quoted.
317
Sadrā, ‘arshiyya, 284.
318
Sadrā, Asfār, part 9, 101. Cf. Plotinus, Enneads VI.7.7: ειναι τάς αίσθήσεις ταύτας άμυδρας νοήσεις, τας δε
εκεϊ νοήσεις εναργεϊς αισθήσεις (Плотин, Эннеады, Шестая Эннеада, Трактаты VI-IX, 176) and the
Uthūlūjiyā: nasifu tilka ’l-hasā’īs fa naqūlu: innahā ‘uqūl da‘īfa wa nasifu tilka-’ļ- ‘uqūl fa naqūlu: innahā
hasā’īs qawiyya (A.Badavī (ed.), Aflotīn ‘inda –’l-‘arab (Uthūlūjiyā), 3rd edition, Qum: Intishārāt-i Bīdār
1413 L.H., 147).

92
synonymous to ma‘ād). Sadrā distinguishes seven kinds of gathering: 1) gathering of pure
intellects; 2) gathering of rational souls; 3) gathering of animal souls; 4) gathering of
vegetative faculties and other bodily natures; 5) gathering of minerals and elements; 6) the
return of engendered self-renewing natural sensible forms; 7) the return of prime matter and
material bodies.319
The philosopher gives four proofs of the gathering of intellects. First. The he-nesses of
intellects are pure existences without quiddity/ whatness and lights unalloyed with darkness.
Difference between them and the Light of Lights and between themselves is only in
perfection and imperfection, and intensity and weakness, therefore their he-nesses are not
separated from God’s ipseity. Second. The principle of the nobler possibility demands
continuity of meaning between the Light of Lights and what is supposed to be the Proximate
Light, and also between the latter and the light which follows it, of the intelligible lights that
differ from each other only through/ in intensity and weakness – otherwise, the lack of such
continuity would necessitate the existence of an infinite number of hierarchically ranked
lights confined between two confines (mahsūra bayn al-hāsirayn). Third. Since there is no
veil between the Intellect and the Real, the former is able to witness in itself the Real,
although without penetrating to the depth of the latter (otherwise the Intellect would
encompass the Real and dominate it), and the Real discloses itself to the Intellect by an
essential self-disclosure, the very existence of the Intellect consisting of this Real’s self-
disclosure in the form of its essence. Fourth. Due to the absence of any veil between the
Innovator and the Intellect, the latter perceives the essence of the Innovator (which (essence)
is light at the utmost degree of its manifestation) without an intermediary and the assistance of
another form – i.e., as an essentially perceived form, the perceiver and the perceived form
becoming one thing.
As for the rational souls, they either possess an intellectual perfection or not. The souls
which possess it (the souls of the celestial spheres and some human souls) become intellect in
actu (‘aql bi ’l-fi‘l), and, inevitably, they are gathered in God, because they are gathered in the
Intellect, and what is gathered in what is gathered in another thing, is gathered in the latter.
The human souls which possess a potentiality of intellectual perfection, but fail to actualize it
during their natural life (i.e., life in the natural body) go to intelligible (noetic) Fire (Hell).
After spending a certain period there they are either gathered in the Intellect or, due to
continuous association with low and base affairs, their potentiality of perfection fades away
and disappears.
The souls of other animals after natural death return to their respective intellectual form, i.e.,
their archetype or lord of species. This return is similar to the return of the faculties of the
human soul to the latter.
Sadrā emphasizes that every individual human being with his specified he-ness, which is
distinct from other individual he-nesses, after his natural death enjoys some kind of
subsistence through his self-perceiving essence, while other animals, which, to him, do not
possess essential self-awareness, do not enjoy it. This is probably one of the most arguable
points of Sadrā’s doctrine of universal gathering or resurrection. Elsewhere, he states that
most people do not have the rational soul.320 Hence, what subsists must be the animal soul
which is common to all animals. It is difficult to understand why Sadrā believes some of the
animal souls to perceive themselves and to be aware of themselves, while he denies this self-
perception and self-awareness to the others. If the imaginative faculty is part and parcel of the

319
See: Sadr al-Dīn al-Shīrāzī, Risāla fī ’l-hashr, ed. M.Khājavī, 2nd edition, Tehrān: Mawlā 1377 S.H., 8.
320
See: Sadrā, Asfār, part 9, 372.

93
animal soul, all animals must possess it, though in different degree. If all animals possess it
and are aware of themselves, they must all enjoy some sort of psychic individual subsistence.
The apparent inconsistency of this part of Sadrā’s doctrine, to my mind, can be eliminated by
admitting that, unlike other animals, human beings perceive themselves as distinct individual
he-nesses, i.e., are aware not only of themselves, but also of their individuality. This latter
kind of awareness, to me, might indeed be regarded as the cause of their subsistence as
individual existences after the natural death.
As for the vegetative soul, that kind of it which permeates the semen in its progress and
perfection ascends to the degree of animal; some part of that kind ascends even higher – to the
degree of human being. (By these two kinds of the vegetative soul Sadrā means the lower
level of the animal and rational souls, responsible for feeding, growth and reproduction.)
Other kinds of the vegetative soul in their motion towards God are not able to dispense with
the vegetative perfection due to the fortification (ta’akkud) of their food-based existence
(wujūd ghadā’ī) and (strengthening of) their ipseity of growth and reproduction, because the
thing’s fortification in a lower degree prevents it from ascending to a higher one. Therefore,
the station to which this latter kind of vegetative soul is gathered is lower than that of the two
other ones.
Similarly, if mineral and elemental forms are transformed into vegetative or animal forms,
they are gathered through the gathering of the latter. If they are not transformed, they are
gathered in and return to their relevant lords of mineral and elemental species.
The return of sensible material forms (such as sensible fire and water), likewise, is to their
other-worldly counterparts (i.e., the imaginal forms of the world of isthmus (barzakh).
Finally, the return of prime matter, material bodies and motion is to non-existence,
perishing (bawār) and ceasing (inqitā’). This is so because every thing returns to its root and
principle, and the principle of prime matter is possibility (imkān), and that of motion –
potentiality of preparedness (quwwa isti‘dādiyya), and return to possibility cannot be anything
else than ceasing and perishing.
Alternatively, employing the Sufi terminology, it can be said that everything returns to God
through the Perfect Man, who is the locus of manifestation (mazhar) of God’s Greatest
Name. All other things are also loci of manifestation of different God’s names, but the names
which they manifest are smaller and less encompassing. The reality of the Perfect Man is
more intense and simpler than the realities of all other things. Due to its utmost simplicity and
extreme intensity, it encompasses in itself all lower, less intense and less simple (more
complex) things. To put it more definitely, the Perfect Man is the level of existence that
comes after the Reality of Existence or God proper. However, as far as the differentiation of
existence into levels is a mental affair, the Perfect Man is a mental abstraction.
One notices that in his treatment of the issue, Sadrā is strongly influenced by Neoplatonists, in
particular by Plotinus, as the quotations from the Uthūlūjiyā (Arabic paraphrase of selected
passages from the 4th, 5th and 6th Enneads) show. However, to Plotinus, there is no way in
which the lower logos might transform itself into a higher one: how could the image of the
sun, reflected on the surface of a pool, transform itself into the actual sun? To Sadrā, the
relation between a higher and a lower (stronger and weaker) logoi is like the relation between
the sun and its ray, i.e., the illuminative one. Therefore, the lower logos does not differ from
the highest in its essence (because this essence is nothing more than a certain level, or aspect,
or direction of existence). Owing to the oneness and analogical gradation of existence, the
possibility of ascent (as well as that of descent) is always present.

94
Having thus discussed the universal levels of existence and their respective gatherings, we
must keep in mind that, to Sadrā, the furthest limit of every thing is the Reality of Existence
and the Necessary One. All things move towards it by substantial essential motion – the
motion through which the substance phases itself in different existential phases, rising from
the lowest levels to the highest ones.321
In the conclusive (8th) chapter of the Risāla fī ’l-hashr we come across two intriguing
statements: 1) “the whole of existence is like one continuous circle which rotates around
itself”322; 2) “the whole of the world is a sensing and rational animal”.323 The perpetual
rotation of the circle of existence around itself presupposes the eternity of existence, not the
eternity of the world/ cosmos. The latter, being a sensing and rational animal, has its natural
lifespan, as all animals do. In the concluding passage of the treatise Sadrā discusses the issue
of the day of Lordship (yawm al-rubūbiyya) (which he also calls “the day of separation”
(yawm al-fasl)) and “the day of God” (yawm ilāhī) (which he also refers to as “the day of
bringing together” (yawm al-jam‘). One day of Lordship equals a thousand years of human
count, while one day of God adds up to fifty thousand years. The notion of the day of
Lordship is inspired by the Qur’anic verse: “He governs the affair from the heaven to the
earth, and then it (the affair – J.E.) ascends to Him in a day, whose length is one thousand
years according to your reckoning” (32:5)324; the idea of the day of God takes its origin from
another verse: “The angels and the Spirit ascend to Him in a day which lasts fifty thousand
years” (70:4).325
Sadrā’s commentator Mullā ‘Alī Nūrī (d. 1246/1830-1) believes every seventh day of the
eternal year to be the day of the Intermediate Rising ( al-qiyāma al-wasta), which occurs
through the Blowing of Terror (nafkha al-faza‘) (while the Greater Rising happens through
the Blowing of Stunning (nafkha al-sa‘q)).326 There is a point in his reasoning: in the Asrār
Sadrā calls the death (return) of the soul “the death of Terror” (mawt al-faza‘) and the death of
the spirit “the death of Stunning” (mawt al-sa‘q).327 However, he does not describe the death
of the soul (or its return to the intellect) as the “intermediate Rising”. Moreover, to the best of
my knowledge, Sadrā never employs the term “intermediate Rising” (al-qiyāma al-wasta)
(while he speaks of the greater and lesser Risings many times). Instead, as at least one passage
in the Tafsīr testifies, he considers the seven “weeks” of God’s eternal year as smaller meta-
historical cycles – parts of the great cosmic cycle (which shows that, in this part of his
teaching, he was influenced by Ikhwān al-Safā’ – and perhaps by other Ismai‘ili thinkers).328
One notices, however, that Sadrā’s statements regarding the greater cosmic cycle and the
universal Greater Rising are brief and elusive. He believes existence to be eternal, while holds
the cosmos (the sensing rational animal) to be perishing, in its parts and in its entirety. The

321
See: Sadrā, Hashr, 80–118.
322
Sadrā, Hashr, 118.
323
Sadrā, Hashr, 122.
324
Qur’an, 346.
325
Qur’an, 503.
326
See: Sadrā, Tafsīr, part 6, 346-347. Ibn al-‘Arabī – Sadrā’s theory of two blowings is inspired by the
Qur’anic verses: “And the Trumpet is blown (or: and the forms are blown into – J.E.), and what is in the
heaven and in the earth swoons (sa‘iqa) away, except whom God wishes [not to swoon]. Then, it is blown
(or: the forms are blown into – J.E.) the second time – and, lo, they stand, looking around” (39:68) (Qur’an,
394) and: “And the Trumpet will be blown (or: the forms will be blown into – J.E.), and [everything] in the
heavens and the earth will be terrified except whom God wishes [not to be terrified], and all will come
humbly” (27:87) (Qur’an, 318).
327
See: Sadrā, Asrār, 167.
328
See: Sadrā, Tafsīr, part 6, 160–161.

95
question is, whether he believes the cosmos to be a sort of Phoenix/ Simurgh – a creature
which periodically burns itself to ashes, in order to come forth again with new life? (If so, the
great day or eternal year of God must be treated as something like Indian kalpa or Chaldean
great year.) Unfortunately, neither the Risāla fī ’l-hashr, nor other Sadrā’s writings contain
explicit statements on the issue: it might have been rather dangerous to openly propagate the
(age old) idea of the periodical perishing and rebirth of the (physical, psychic and spiritual/
intelligible) cosmos in its entirety, thus associating oneself with the non-believers.
In the remaining part of the chapter I shall deal with the return of the human soul. As the
highest and most sophisticated kind of ma‘ād, it encompasses and contains in itself the ma‘ād
of all lower and less perfect existents, therefore, it can be said that the return of the human
soul is (or presupposes) the return of everything.
This is obvious that the return journey can only be commenced after reaching the destination
of the onward journey and completion of the mission for the sake of which that journey was
undertaken. What is this mission? To give existence to what is non-existent in itself, but is
capable of coming into existence through the other – i.e., to pure possibility.

3.2. PRE-EXISTENCE OF SOULS TO BODIES

Sadrā’s famous principle “the soul is corporeal by its origination (hudūth) and spiritual by its
subsistence (baqā’)” seems to imply the impossibility of any kind of pre-existence of souls to
bodies. If so, Sadrā’s view on the topic must be in disagreement with the verses of the Qur’an
and the Imamite doctrine, which unequivocally ascribe to the human soul a kind of existence
preceding the creation of the material body. Moreover, the aforementioned principle seems to
be inconsistent from a purely philosophical point of view as well, because one of the key
principles of the classical Islamic philosophy is: “Every thing returns to its root (or: source)
(asl)”. How can then – one should ask – the thing, which is entirely corporeal by its creation,
return to the realm of the spirit? After all, one can only return to the place which it comes
from.
Interestingly, Sadrā himself seems (or pretends?) to be unaware of any of these
contradictions. In his works, he explicitly declares his adherence to the Qur’anic, Prophetic
and Imamite teachings on the pre-existence of souls and repeatedly quotes the relevant
passages from the Qur’an and the sayings of the Prophet and Imams.
In the Qur’an, this is the so-called “Covenant of Alast” verse (7:172), which speaks of the
pre-existence of human souls in the most unequivocal way:
“When thy Lord drew forth from the Children of Adam – from their loins – their descendants,
and made them testify concerning themselves, (saying): “Am I not your Lord (who cherishes
and sustains you)?” – they said: “Yea, we do testify!” (This), lest ye should say on the Day of
Judgment: “Of this we were never mindful””.329
Of the sayings of the Prophet which concern the topic, Sadrā often quotes the following one:
“The spirits (of men) are armies drawn up in ranks: [Those who recognize one another are in
harmony and those who dislike one another are in disagreement]”.330
As for the sayings of the Shiite Imams, the following one, attributed to Ja‘far al-Sādiq, is
apparently Sadrā’s favourite one:

329
Qur’an, 132.
330
Morris, Wisdom, 141.

96
“God created us (i.e., the Imams – J.E.) from the light of His Greatness and Majesty, then gave
our creation a form from the clay [which was] hidden under the Throne, and made the light
inhabit this form, and we were people of light; and He created the spirits of our followers from
our clay”.331
Sadrā claims that the essential principles of his philosophy (including that of the corporeal
character of the origination of the soul) have been unveiled to him directly by God. Does God
contradict Himself in Sadrā’s teachings? Before we can get to the root of this – real or
apparent – contradiction, we need to examine in more detail what kind of existence the souls
allegedly enjoy before the origination of their natural bodies. It is well known that earlier
Islamic philosophers – Ibn Sīnā in particular – held that any kind of the soul’s pre-existence to
the body is impossible, because the admittance of such pre-existence would inevitably lead to
a number of absurdities, such as transmigration of souls, eternity (qidam) of the soul,
multiplicity of individuals of a single species and their differentiation without matter and
material preparedness, the soul’s divisibility after its unity (like the one which is inherent in
contiguous quantities), or its ineffectuality (ta‘tīl) before the origination of the body.
Sadrā’s solution of the difficulty is based on three principles: 1) the principle of the
principality of existence; 2) the principle of the analogical gradation of existence; 3) the
principle “the thing which is simple by its reality is all things”. I shall try to explain how it
works.
First of all, according to the principle of the principality of existence, the quiddity (māhiya) of
the thing, being a mere mental abstraction, does not possess any reality whatsoever (“has
never felt the fragrance of [the outward] existence”). Now, existence possesses various levels
(marātib), which differ as regards their intensity and weakness. The properties (ahkām) and
traces (āthār) of the weaker level, as far as they concern its existence (not its non-existence
(privation) (‘adam)), are fully possessed by the stronger one. As one which is closer to the
Necessary Being, the latter is also simpler. Its more perfect simplicity allows it to be more
things as far as their existence is considered (of course, we are now discussing only the
vertical order of the universe, leaving aside the horizontal one, which is based on the
difference among God’s names and attributes and their interaction).
To clarify the point, Sabzavārī, one of the most eminent representatives of Mullā Sadrā’s
school, often compares the world of the entified existence with a cone. Let me quote from his
commentary to the Asfār:
“The world of the entified existence is like a cone: the light of its summit is at the Necessary
One (may He be exalted!) and its base is at the matters (mawwād), because in every thing which
is nearer to the Necessary One, prevail the properties of necessity, such as oneness and
simplicity, while in every thing which is nearer to the matters, prevail the properties of
contingency (imkān), such as manyness and compoundedness (tarkīb)”.332

331
Sadrā,’arshiyya, 239. Cf. J.W.Morris’s English translation in: Morris, Wisdom, 141. One
will notice the difference between the spirits of the Imams, which are created from the pure Divine Light, and
those of their followers, which are created from the clay the Imams’ bodies of light. (Hence,
only a second rate spirituality (that with the alloy of the clay of the Throne) can be ascribed to the latter,
while that of the first rate (the pure essential spirituality, which is void of the alloy of the clay) is
confined to the Prophet and Imams.)
332
Sadrā, Asfār, part 8, 321, note 2.

97
Graphically, it might look something like this:

We come to the conclusion that, in the vertical descendent order, the existence of the lower
and weaker level is fully included in that of the higher and more intense one. Sadrā himself
confirms this view in the following words:
“…as an intense light contains the levels of lights which are lower than it – though not in a way,
in which a compound thing contains a simple one – so a strong existence includes in it what is
in weak existences, which are lower than it, and it causes the effects, which are caused by
them”.333

Therefore, if we view the human soul as a certain level of existence, as such it is fully
included in the relevant higher level (whatever we call it: the intellect, the νoυς, the
subjugating light (al-nūr al-qāhir)) of existence, which is stronger and more intense (what it
lacks in comparison with the lower level (the soul), is the particular limit of privation and
non-existence, which is possessed by the soul due to its greater proximity to the world of
matters).
Now, every existent has its particular lord – “lord of the species” (rabb al-naw‘). This lord of
the species, which is a member of the horizontal chain (al-silsila al-‘ardiyya) of intellects
(and, as such, enjoys a kind of intellectual/ noetic existence), is the soul’s perfect cause (while
it is itself an effect of the Universal Intellect and a direction (or: aspect) (jiha) of it).
Earlier we learnt334 that, in keeping with the gnostic wayfaring (al-sulūk al-‘irfānī), only “the
cause is a real thing but the effect is [merely] an aspect of its aspects”335 and that the effect is
not a separate thing, differing from its cause. This gives Sadrā a full right to assert that “the
human souls exist before the bodies through the perfection of their cause and occasion

333
Sadrā, Asfār, part 8, 148.
334
See subchapter 1.6. (Existential Causation: the Gnostic Approach) and also my paper: Y.Eshots,
“The Gnostic Element of Sadra’s doctrine on causation” in the Proceedings of the 2nd International
Conference on Mulla Sadra: Causation according to Mulla Sadra and other Schools of Philosophy. 5-6 May
2001 – SOAS (London), London: Salman – Azade Press 2003, 73–89.
335
Sadrā, Asfār, part 2, 300.

98
(sabab), and a perfect occasion entails the occasioned thing [and brings it forth] together with
it; and so the soul exists together with its occasion, because its occasion is perfect by its
essence and complete by its benefaction (tāmm al-ifāda) and if a thing is such, [the thing]
[which is] occasioned by it does not become detached from it.”336 Hence, he concludes:
“…when you have obtained the knowledge of certainty of its (the soul’s – J.E.) existence before
the body and have known the meaning of “occasion” and “being occasioned”, and [learnt] that the
essential occasion is the completeness of the occasioned (thing), and its furthest limit (ghāya),
you have obtained the knowledge about its engendered existence before the body through the
perfection of its being and its independence (ghanā)”.337
Apart from the Asfār, the problem of the pre-existence of souls is also discussed in the Tafsīr.
Sadrā’s commentary on the 22nd verse of the surah “The Heifer” contains a discussion on the
“Covenant of Alast”. While the employed terminology is slightly different (instead of terms
“occasion” (sabab)/ “the occasioned thing” (musabbab) or “cause” (‘illa)/ “effect” (ma’lūl),
Sadrā uses the set “reality” (haqīqa)/ “tenuity” (raqīqa)), the overall treatment of the problem,
as well as the general conclusion, is very similar. I shall quote here the most essential part of
the discussion:
“The realizers (muhaqqiqīn) among the folk of unification (ahl al-tawhīd) say that the one who
is addressed by the words of God: (may He be exalted!): “Am I not your Lord?”, in respect of
making the covenant, is the reality (haqīqa) of the human being, which exists in the Divine
World and the Realm of Lordship; and indeed, every natural species has its noetic reality and
separated (i.e., from the matter – J.E.) form, and its likeness of light in the world of noetic
realities and divine likenesses, [which were] known to the lordly sages and ancient gnostics as
“the forms of what is in the knowledge of God” – and they called them “the lords of the
species”, and some of them held that each of these lords of the species is an angel, entrusted, by
the permission of God, to preserve the other individuals of the species – the species, whose form
he is at God, in the world of separate forms and noetic likenesses of light and his (the lord’s of
the species – J.E.] relation to them (the other individuals of the relevant species – J.E.) is that of
the root to the branches and that of the light to the shadows.
The difference between the reality of the human being and other realities lies in [the fact] that
each of the latter is a vassal (marbūb) of one [particular] name among the names of God, but the
reality of the human being is the locus of manifestation of the name “God” (Allāh), which
contains in itself [all] other names, and its vassal, and in [the fact] that other instances (afrād)
cannot descend from the level on which they stand and ascend from one station to another, in
order to reach the divine presence, while this is not the case with the reality of the human being,
which alone is prepared to act through its engendered form (al-sūra al-kawnīyya) as the lordly
vicegerent and through its noetic form it is prepared to remain faithful to the covenant in the
end, as [it is prepared] to the reception, in order to receive and conclude the covenant, in the
beginning”.338
Sadrā attributes tremendous importance to the opposition “reality”/ “tenuity” (haqīqa/ raqīqa)
(which, as we have seen, he identifies with the opposition between the lord of the species and
an individual belonging to the relevant species). As this opposition seems to constitute the
very core339 of the problem of pre-existence of souls, I shall quote here a part from the chapter
in the Asfār, which deals with the nature of this opposition:
336
Sadrā,Asfār, part 8, 346–347.
337
Sadrā, Asfār, part 8, 347.
338
Sadrā, Tafsīr, part 2, 243.
339
Cf. the comments of Sabzavārī: “The reality’s being in its lofty station is (i.e., presupposes – J.E.) the tenuity’s
inclusion in it; and the tenuity’s [coming] to the earth is (=means) the reality’s becoming (sayrūra) the tenuity
without its lofty station; and around this rotate all the symbols of the sages and allusions of the prophets, such as
“eternity” (qidam), “origination” (hudūth), “effusion” (ifāda), “descent” (tanazzul), “ascent” (su‘ūd), “falling”
(hubūt), “particles” (dharrāt) and “seeds” (barazāt)” – Sadrā, Asfār, part 8, 332, note 2.

99
“Know that particular corporeal forms are universal realities which exist in the world of God’s
command and decree (qadā’), as He (may He be exalted!) said: “There is no thing, whose
storehouses are not at Us, and We send them down but in a known measure” (15:21).340 The
“storehouses” (khazā’īn) are the universal noetic realities, and each of them has [its] particular
tenuities, which exist through particular measured occasions (asbāb qadarī), such as specific
matter and position, as well as [certain] time and place. The universal realities exist at God in a
principal way (bi ’l-asāla) and these sensible tenuities exist through the ruling (or: property)
(hukm) of dependence and inclusion. The realities [if taken] as universalia in their lofty divine
existence are not transmitted, but their tenuities, through the ruling (or: property) of continuity
(ittisāl) and transmutation, and encompassing of other levels, descend and display themselves in
the moulds of apparitions and [material] bodies, as it was said earlier in regard to the meaning
of the descent of the angels to the creation by God’s command; and the tenuity is the reality
through the ruling of continuity, and the difference between them is only in respect of intensity
and weakness, and perfection and deficiency”.341
These quotations allow me to assert that, in a general way, the pre-existence of souls to bodies
is understood by Sadrā as the pre-existence of reality to tenuity, the occasion (the cause) to
the occasioned thing (the effect) and the lord of the species to the individual of that species. It
is important to underline that this pre-existence bears an essential (dhātī)342, not a temporal,
character, i.e., the existence of the reality and the occasion is prior to that of the tenuity and
the occasioned thing in essence, not necessarily in time. Hence, the existence of the soul is
prior to that of the (natural) body in/ through essence, not in/ through time – and this is,
indeed, this essential pre-existence (or the absence of it), which really concerns Sadrā.
The difference among individual human souls, says Sadrā, is caused by the difference among
the active directions (al-jihāt al-fā‘iliyya) and intellectual aspects (al-haysiyyāt al-‘aqliyya) in
the reality of the human being (his lord of the species), which, in turn, is caused by the
influence of different divine names and attributes and their interaction. In his Tafsīr Sadrā
explains the idea in the following way, employing the illuminationist terminology:
“…the reality of the human being, which exists before these earthy (turābī) engendered states
(akwān) in the world of the Lordly Presence, possesses noetic directions and aspects, which
multiply in it due to the multiplication of the necessary illuminations of light and the
multiplication of the contingent deficiencies, and manyness of joinings, which occur between
light and darkness, necessity and contingency, perfection and deficiency; and these noetic
directions are the occasions (asbāb) of multiplicity of the engendered states in the individuals of
the human kind”.343
Having ascertained these important points, I must add that this essential pre-existence has
several stations or levels. Though, to my knowledge344, Sadrā does not speak at length about
these stations in any of his works, he briefly enumerates them in some of his treatises, in
particular, in the Asrār, where he writes:
“…[God] took their (i.e., the children’s of Adam – J.E.) spirits from the loins of their noetic
father – and this is the noetic station of “cutting into patterns” (maqām ‘aqlī tafsīlī) the
individuals of human kind, [which follows] after the existence of their entities in God’s
knowledge in a simple noetic manner; and He said, pointing to another station, [which comes]
after the aforementioned stations: “[We said:] “O Adam! Dwell thou and thy wife in the

340
I have used here Chittick’s English translation of the verse, which was taken from: Chittick, Self-Disclosure, 36.
341
Sadrā, Asfār, part 8, 126–127.
342
Both Sabzavārī and Nūrī speak of the meta-temporal or aeonic (dahrī) pre-existence as well.
343
Sadrā, Tafsīr, part 2, 244.
344
Unfortunately, Sadrā’s glosses to Qutb al-Dīn Shīrāzī’s commentary on the Hikmat al-Ishrāq, which are said
to contain important discussion on the pre-existence of souls, were not available to me. Prof. Hossein Ziai
told me in 2002 that he has prepared the text for the edition but, until now, I have not got any notice
regarding the publishing of the book.

100
Garden; and eat of the bountiful things therein as (where and when) ye will; but approach not
this tree, or ye run into harm and transgression”345 – and this is also a configuration (or:
modality) (nash’a), previous to this [this-wordly] existence”.346
In this passage, Sadrā mentions at least three stations (maqāmāt) or configurations/ modalities
(nasha’āt) of the soul, prior to its this-wordly station and configuration, in which it exists
together with the material body:
1) the station, in which the soul exists as an entity in God’s knowledge; station of non-
differentiation, succinctness and simple noetic existence, which, in fact, in not in any way
different from the existence of God (maqām basīt ‘aqlī; maqām ijmālī ‘aqlī);
2) the station, in which the souls are “cut into patterns”, i.e., the station of noetic
differentiation (which is also the station of bearing witness at the Day of the Covenant of
Alast);
3) the station of the imaginal forms (al-suwar al-mithāliyya), which is the world of
apparitions (ashbāh) (the station of the imaginal Garden, in which Adam and Eve dwelt
before their coming to the world of engendered nature).
While it is possible to mentally discern other stations in the soul’s descendant journey, the
given three ones constitute its three main phases, in complete accordance with Sadrā’s
teachings of three worlds (sensible, imaginal and intelligible/ noetic) and two risings (qiyāma)
– the greater and the lesser, where the latter is understood as the soul’s return to the world of
imaginal forms and apparitions, whereas the former means its return to the world of fully
separated spirits (pure noetic forms). What should be emphasized here, is the fact that the
fixed entities of souls, which exist in God’s knowledge, do not possess any existence of their
own. Instead, they exist through the existence of God, being not differentiated from Him in
any way, as far as their existence (which is their subsistence through God) is considered.
Hence we can conclude that the souls, if taken as the fixed entities in God’s knowledge,
preexist to their natural bodies by the pre-existence of God to “what is other than God” (in
this case, the lord of the species of the human being is itself nothing else but an active
direction of the Universal Reality). Since Sadrā relates the world of noetic forms to the
“divine region” (al-suq‘ al-ilāhī) or the Godhead, which is not “other than God” (mā siwā
Allāh), but exists with/ through the existence of God, this is correct in regard to the second
station as well. Hence, the first and the second stations pre-exist to the third and the following
stations in the arc of descent as “what is with God” pre-exists to “what is other than God”.
How does the pre-existence of the soul agree with its origination (hudūth) together with the
body?
To answer this question, we must pay attention to the specific status of the human soul in the
universe – the status, which distinguishes it from all other existents, namely, its being the
locus of manifestation of the name “God” (Allāh), which contains in itself all other God’s
names. This unique status, which the human soul has obtained through the knowledge of all
God’s names, allows it to travel freely from one station and modality to another (i.e., to
witness itself in its intellectual, psychic and natural aspects, seeing itself simultaneously as
reality and tenuity). Sadrā emphasizes the uniqueness of the ontological status of the human
soul more than once. E.g. in the Asfār he states:
“The human soul does not possess a certain (literally: known) (ma‘lūm) station in he-ness
(huwiyya) and a definite degree in existence, as it is the case with other natural, psychic and
intelligible existents: each of them has a certain station. On the contrary, the human soul

345
Qur’an, 7.
346
Sadrā, Asrār, 186.

101
possesses different stations and degrees, and it has preceding and subsequent configurations,
and in each station and world it takes on a different form”.347
After a few pages, he says:
“…they (“those who are firmly rooted in knowledge” (rāsihīn fī ’l-‘ilm), i.e., the “realizers”,
those who have established the true state of the affair – J.E.) hold that the soul has many modes
(shu’ūn) and stages (atwār) and, notwithstanding its simplicity, possesses [a number of]
existential states (al-akwān al-wujūdiyya), some of them – before the nature, some – with the
nature, and some – after the nature”.348
Hence, one can conclude that what is originated after the acquisition of a specific
preparedness and the fulfilment of certain preconditions is neither the reality of the human
soul, nor the fixed entities of individual souls – rather it is one of the existential states,
possessed by a particular soul. A few lines later Sadrā explains the point more precisely:
“What depends on the body [in its origination] is one of the soul’s modalities, the preparedness
of the body being the precondition of the existence of this this-wordly configuration (or:
modality) of the engendered nature; and this is the direction (=aspect) of the soul’s poverty,
need, contingency and deficiency, not the direction (=aspect) of its necessity, independence and
perfection”.349
It should be noted that what Sadrā (as well as the representatives of the falsafa tradition in
general) call “the soul” (al-nafs) in the strict sense of the term, is actually this-worldy
configuration of the soul, in which it exists together with the engendered nature and material
body. If we take the word “soul” in this strictly philosophical sense, there is no doubt
whatsoever about the corporeal origination of the soul inasmuch as it is the soul (al-nafs bi mā
hiya al-nafs) (i.e., as far as it is confined to its this-wordly modality and “withness”
(companionship) of the engendered nature).
“…it has been established earlier that the existence of the soul and its being the soul is one and
the same thing, and, in regard to this existence, it is a form, which is related (lit.: ascribed)
(mudāf) to the body and administers it… and what needs the body, is the soul’s dependent
(ta‘alluqī) existence, and its direction (aspect) of being the soul, and its administration
(tasarruf) of the body, and its becoming perfect in it. This kind of existence pertains to the
soul’s essence and is originated through the origination of the body; it becomes invalid through
the invalidation of it, in the sense that the soul, inasmuch as it is the soul, the possessor of the
bodily nature, is invalidated and its substance transforms itself into another kind of existence
according to its substantial perfection, which is directed towards the furthest limit; and
annihilation of the thing into its furthest end and its principle is more noble and more preferable
[than its subsistence through itself]”.350
It is evident that Sadrā does not question the invalidation (butlān) of the soul’s this-wordly
configuration, i.e., the corruption of the soul inasmuch as it is taken as the bodily nature and
has no doubt about the corruption of the corporeal and originated modality of its existence.
Hence, his famous principle “the soul is corporeal by its origination and spiritual by its
subsistence” should not be understood in terms of al-mabda’ wa ’l-ma‘ād (‘the place of
beginning and the place of return’). Instead of pointing to the place of the soul’s beginning
(allegedly the “body”) and its place of return (“spirit”), the principle provides us with brief
formulae of two subsequent modalities of the soul: its this-wordly and temporally originated
configuration/ modality is corporeal (and hence corruptive), while its other-wordly and

347
Sadrā, Asfār, part 8, 343.
348
Sadrā, Asfār, part 8, 346.
349
Sadrā, Asfār, part 8, 347. The passage is discussed in detail by M.Khājavī in: Muhammad Khājavī, “Soul, Its
Reality and Its Perfectionary Journey in Mulla Sadra’s Philosophy”, in the Transcendent Philosophy,
London: IIS, Vol. 4, number 2, June 2003, 82–83.
350
Sadrā, Asfār, part 8, 375.

102
subsistent configuration is spiritual. (One can also say: the soul’s corporeal configuration is
temporally originated, while its spiritual modality is subsistent.)
One notices that Sadrā is careful not to use the word “soul” when he speaks about the
intelligible/ noetic modality which exists before the material body, while he readily applies it
to the modality which comes after the corporeal modality. Indeed, if the soul during its
residence in the material body reaches a degree of perfection which allows it to unite with the
Active Intellect and to return directly to its lord of the species, it becomes a noetic form and a
pure intellect, and therefore cannot be called “the soul” in the strict sense of the term. Like
other philosophers, Sadrā, however, has little doubt that this lofty degree is reached only by a
handful of the individuals of the human species. As for the remaining majority, their souls
reach such a degree of separation from the matter, which only allows them to travel as far as
the world of Imagination. In this case, the soul’s existence after the natural body is based on
the subsistence of its faculty of imagination. Though it has not reached the threshold of the
Godhead (al-suq‘ al-ilāhī), thus becoming a pure intellect, it enjoys a kind of imaginal
existence (similar to what we experience in dreams) and resides either in the imaginal Garden
or in the imaginal Fire (i.e., witnesses either beautiful and agreeable or ugly and disagreeable
forms, which are the likenesses of its acquired habits (malakāt)). In the latter case, it is
absolutely correct to characterize this post natural modality of the soul as its spiritual
subsistence.
It is quite clear that the soul’s existence after the body cannot be fully understood without the
true knowledge of its existence before the body, and vice versa, since our knowledge of the
beginnings and the ends rests on the principle of the parallelism and reciprocal
correspondence of the stations of the descending and ascending arcs of the circle of Being.
“The furthest limits (=ends) and the places of beginning are parallel to each other and [they are]
situated [exactly] opposite each other”.351
“Every degree of the ascending arc [of the circle of Being] is situated [exactly] opposite its
counterpart, which is one of the degrees of the descending arc”.352
In keeping with this principle, every station and modality of the soul’s existence before the
natural body has a counterpart in its existence after this body. Those counterparts are of one
and the same genus, although their entities are different. A brief account of these parallel and
mutually corresponding stations/ modalities of the circle of Being is given in most of Sadrā’s
works. Thus, in the ‘arshiyya, Sadrā writes:
“Know, my beloved, that we came to this world from the Garden of God, which is the
Enclosure of Holiness, through which are holified the holy ones, and from this garden to the
Abode of Life and the Garden of Bodies, and from there to this world, [which is] the Abode of
Deed (‘amal) without Reward; and from this world we go to the Abode of Reward without
Deed; and those of us, whose innate disposition (fitra) has remained sound and whose deeds are
beautiful, go to the Garden of God, if they are among those drawn near [to God], the ones who
have become perfect in this world, or to the Garden of Life, if they are among the People of the
Right Side; and those, whose deeds were ugly and whose hearts have become black, remain
under (=in) the Fire of God’s wrath, in Gehenna”.353

351
Sadrā, ‘arshiyya, 273.
352
Sadrā, ‘arshiyya, 273.
353
Sadrā, ‘arshiyya, pp. 274–275.

103
On the basis of the above-quoted passages from the Asrār and the ‘arshiyya, we can draw the
following circle:

“When the human spirit reaches the stage of its sacred father, the end of the circle of being joins
up with its beginning, and the separation of the engendered existence is removed from it by the
existential connective substance of meaning.”354
Hence, it is evident that, for Sadrā, the denial of the soul’s existence before the body actually
implies the denial of its existence after the body, since the latter existence is understood by
him as the soul’s return to its beginning and source, after its obtaining bodily, psychic and
intellectual perfections. The denial of the soul’s existence before the body, through the
existence of its principle and source, would lead to the denial of any kind of its existence after
the body; whence we should have no other choice than to follow the path of the Aeonists
(dahriyyūn) and the Naturalists (tabī‘iyyūn), which, in turn, would invalidate the Transcendent
Wisdom.
As for the exact way of the soul’s pre-existence to the body, in a nutshell, it can be
characterized as the existence of the effect and the occasioned thing through its cause and
occasion. This pre-existence bears an essential, not a temporal, character and consists of
several stations and at least two existential modalities – the noetic (intellectual) and the

354
Sadrā, Tafsīr, part 2, 247.

104
psychic (imaginal). The soul, though it is a shadow of its noetic cause and principle, pre-exists
the natural body as a more intense light pre-exists a weaker one. This body, then, is the effect
of the soul and the soul, being its cause, brings it to perfection, which eventually allows it to
enter the world of separated intellects and subjugating lights. The intellect, which subjugates
the soul, in turn, uses the body as a tool to bring the soul itself to the highest possible
perfection, which results in its becoming the actual intellect, i.e., in the actualisation of its
hidden intellectual potentiality. Since this actualisation cannot take place otherwise than by
means of the natural body, the latter is originated, in order to ensure the possibility of the
soul’s progress towards perfection. Hence, the natural modality is an indispensable stage of
the soul’s journey towards perfection, while the natural body is nothing else than a specific
level (martaba) of the soul.

3.3. THE IMPOSSIBILITY OF METEMPSYCHOSIS

Sadrā strongly denies the possibility of metempsychosis or transmigration of souls (tanāsukh)


if the soul is understood as the principle of bodily faculties and the administrator of a
particular material body, because such possibility is in complete contradiction with his
teaching on the substantial motion of the soul.
“The soul has an essential connection with the [natural] body, and their composition is a unified
[and] natural one, and each of them performs a substantial essential motion together with the
other”.355
The soul begins its existence as a material body, in order to be gradually developed into and
actualized as the soul proper. This initial natural stage of the soul’s development requires its
existence as a sensing affair (amr hāss). When the intensity of the soul’s existence has
achieved a certain degree, it becomes able to subsist without a material body, as pure
imagination (though the latter itself can be treated as a kind of “body” – i.e., an imaginal
body/ likeness of intelligible meanings). The substantial motion, according to Sadrā, is a
unidirectional evolutionary affair in respect both to the soul and to the body (and eventually
leads to their complete unification in the realm of pure Intellect).356 Having become a purely
perceptual existence (wujūd idrākī), the soul dispenses with the five external senses. Its
development into pure consciousness is an essential and, therefore, inevitable affair, holds
Sadrā, because once a thing is actualized as a certain species, its return to sheer potentiality in
respect to that species is impossible.357
Besides, between the form and the matter of every natural compound affair exists a sort of
unity, which makes impossible subsistence of one of them and perishing of the other, in so far
as they are considered as form and matter, because the former relates to the latter as perfection
to imperfection. This is also true in respect to genus and differentia.
The soul in the aspect of its being the soul (the perfection of a material body and its
administrator) is the specific form (sūra naw‘iyya) of that body and the formal cause of the

355
Sadrā, Asfār, part 9, 2.
356
Cf. Chittick’s statement: “Contrary to what was thought by some of the earlier philosophers, disengagement
(i.e., separation (tajarrud) – J.E.) does not imply a rejection of the body. This is because the essential reality
of the body is formal, not material. The more the soul is strengthened, the more the body’s intellective form
is intensified and the more its existence is consolidated” (Chittick, “Teleology”, 237). Chittick is, perhaps,
influenced by the popular Sufi belief that “the entire body of the saints becomes the soul”. I am inclined to
think that already in the imaginal (psychic) realm/ spectrum of wujūd the terminology which is based on
distinction between the soul and the body becomes irrelevant.
357
See: Sadrā, Asfār, part 9, 2.

105
quiddity of the obtained psychic species. In turn, the body, in the aspect of its being the body,
is the matter of the soul that is essentially connected with it and the material cause of the
species. Therefore, in respect to the soul’s natural receiving (or: passive) connected existence
(al-wujūd al-ta‘alluqī al-infi‘ālī al-tabī‘ī), its subsistence without a natural body is
impossible. But, unlike other souls, human souls have another kind of existence apart from
the bodily one. In respect to its separated existence, the soul cannot become connected with a
material body – be it either the one in which it used to reside before the separation or other.
Metempsychosis must not be confused with the corporeal return. Metempsychosis (tanāsukh)
in the sense of the transfer of the soul from one elemental or natural body to another – be it
either more or less perfect – is impossible. What is not only possible, but also inevitable, is
the transformation of the soul from its this-worldly natural and bodily configuration to the
other-worldly one and its assuming an other-worldly form (imaginal body), in conformity
with its this-worldly states and habits. As it was stated earlier, there are four principal paths
which can be taken by the soul in its essential development in the other (imaginal) world. It
can assume a luminous angelic form if it fears God and strives to be virtuous, or a devilish
one – if it chooses the path of evil and wickedness. If it makes no conscious choice, but
follows its animal passions, the soul takes either the form of a predatory beast – if the
habitude of wrath (ghadab) predominates over that of the appetite, or the form of a lustful
brute – if the appetite (lust) (shahwa) predominates over wrath.
In respect to this other-worldly form or imaginal body the soul does not act as the
administrator and mover. Rather, this imaginal body is its shadow and concomitant (lāzim), to
which the soul pays little (if any) attention.358 Naturally, the owner of the shadow cannot use
the shadow as means for achieving perfection, nor can the shadow have any sort of influence
upon him or change his state in any way.
The situation is more complicated, if the soul has acquired a number of intense virtues and
vices. Sadrā supposes that the imaginal body of such soul successively assumes a number of
different angelic and animal forms in keeping with the presently predominant virtue or vice. If
one or more of the evil passions developed in the soul during its natural life gradually fade
away and disappear in the afterlife, the relevant imaginal form (of a certain animal which
symbolizes that passion) gradually becomes less and less intense, until it is replaced with
another imaginal animal form, which symbolizes a different passion. This change of the
soul’s imaginal bodies, to Sadrā, is a true and undeniable affair in the eyes of the folk of
revealing, but, as he asserts, it cannot be regarded as metempsychosis, because it simply
reflects the change of the soul’s inner state.359
To this, one can probably object that, according to the principle of analogical gradation of
existence, sense (hiss) must be treated as weak imagination (khayāl da‘īf). Hence, the natural
sensible body also is a mirror – though less perfect than the imaginal one – of the soul’s inner
state(s). If we admit that sense and imagination differ from each other only in the degree of
intensity, what can prevent the soul from changing its sensible (=low-intensity imaginal) body
according to its newly acquired inner state? Sadrā holds the preventing affair must be the
specific preparedness possessed by the matter of a particular body. But the transformed soul
(or, say, the transformed individual spirit) can probably adapt matter for the expression of its
(the soul’s) state through continuously exerted influence upon it (matter).
On a pre-discursive level, Sadrā’s denial of metempsychosis is rooted in his dominant
intuition of the perfectional flow of existence and its intensifying movement (al-haraka al-

358
See: Sadrā, Asfār, part 9, 19.
359
See: Sadrā, Asfār, part 9, 30–31.

106
ishtidādiyya). Absorbed by this intuition, he believes all affairs that entail regress or
weakening of existence, after its becoming strong, to be in disagreement with the universal
principles of philosophy (which, in fact, are the product of his reflection upon the
consequences of the aforementioned intuition) and, therefore, impossible and absurd.
One particular group of human beings – the divine sages or “those perfect in knowledge” (al-
kāmilūn fī ’l-‘ilm) – according to Sadrā, become free from both this-worldly natural and
other-worldly imaginal bodies through unification with the Active Intellect.360

3.4. THE SPIRITUAL RETURN

As it was mentioned above, the Mutakallimūn distinguished between corporeal and spiritual
ma‘ād, treating the first as the resurrection of material bodies and the second – as restoration
of spirit in the latter. None of the two kinds of ma‘ād in their traditional theological sense is
compatible with the principles of Peripatetic philosophy, therefore the falāsifa dismissed the
possibility of the occurrence of corporeal return altogether and reinterpreted the spiritual
return in accordance with the underlying intuition of their doctrine. At least in case of Ibn
Sīnā this intuition can be defined as an acute awareness of the evil nature of the natural
sensible world and, consequently, a burning desire to intellectually flee from it towards the
spiritual and intelligible one, which is perceived as pure good or the closest station to the
latter that can be possibly attained. Albeit with different acuteness, since the times of Plato,
this intuition was shared by most outstanding Greek and Muslim philosophers, wherefore we
can probably describe the falsafa tradition as that of intellectual flight from the evil,
personified by prime matter.
The teaching of Muslim philosophers, from Ibn Sīnā to Sadrā, on ma‘ād rūhānī cannot, in all
likelihood, be properly understood without an awareness of the aforementoned fact – namely,
that philosophy, as a method of reflection and a way of life, is a flight from the sensible
towards the intellectual. In view of this, it is just natural that all philosophers agree upon the
substance and necessity of spiritual (read: intellectual (‘aqlī)) return.
For this very reason, Sadrā’s doctrine on ma‘ād rūhānī is, apparently, one of the least original
components of his philosophy. Although in its most mature version, presented in the Asfār,
Sadrian teaching on spiritual return differs from Avicennan one in some important points (e.g.
in the understanding of the substance of the Active Intellect (al-‘aql al-fa‘‘āl)), on the whole
it represents a slightly altered repetition of the latter (a good deal of Sadrā’s text consisting of
paraphrased passages from Ibn Sīnā’s writings).361
In view of this, I shall first give a succinct account of Ibn Sīnā’s teaching on spiritual return,
as it is presented in his al-Mabdā’ wa ’l-ma‘ād, and then examine the points in which Sadrā’s
treatment of the issue differs from that of Ibn Sīnā.
In a nutshell, according to Ibn Sīnā, the spiritual return of the human soul consists in its
theoretical faculty’s (al-quwwa al-nazariyya) attainment of the acquired intellect (al-‘aql al-
mustafād) through establishing a contact with the Active Intellect (al-‘aql al-fa‘‘āl). (The
Active Intellect, as he explains, is that of the separated intellects which is the nearest to us.
The Greek term νους ποετικος was first introduced by Aristotle in his De Anima (III.5), where
he used it to refer to the active part of the human soul. Alexander of Aphrodisias in his

360
See: Sadrā, Asfār, part 9, 6.
361
Cf. e.g. Sadrā, Asfār, part 9, 124 and Ibn Sīnā, Mabdā’, 111–112; Asfār, part 9, 135 and Mabdā’, 113.

107
commentary on the passage describes the Active Intellect as god362 – apparently because he
perceives νους ποετικος as a logos which, through its self-contemplation, brings into existence
the world below it.)
Behind this Avicennan theory of spiritual return/ resurrection as attaching the theoretical
faculty of one’s rational soul to the Active Intellect, apparently, lies the intuition that, in the
true sense, the cosmos does not exist otherwise than as the Intellect, or rather, as intellection
(intellectual perception). The theoretical faculty of the soul – the only part of it, which, to Ibn
Sīnā, survives the natural death, in fact, is nothing else but perception and awareness. To
enjoy genuine happiness in this life and the afterlife, it must separate itself from the impurities
of prime matter, becoming pure intellection (ta‘aqqul/ idrāk ‘aqlī) – which, to Ibn Sīnā’s
belief, is the very mode of the existence of the eternal intellects.
In Ibn Sīnā’s opinion, the existents which pertain to the domain of sense cannot be truly
perceived and do not deserve to be called “the perceived”. What can be truly and really
perceived are the Pure Good and the spiritual substances (i.e., the intellects or the
intellections):
“The perceived (mudrak) and the received (munāl) is not the eaten [thing], or the scent, or what
is similar to them, but the thing which is pure splendour and sheer good – the one from which
effuses every good, and every order (nizām), and every pleasure, and also what counts as the
angelic spiritual substances – those which are the essentially beloved ones.”363
The theoretical faculty of the rational human soul is originated together with the body as pure
potentiality of intellection. In this purely potential state, it is referred to as “the potential
intellect” (al-‘aql bi ’l-quwwa) or “the (primo-) material intellect” (al-‘aql al-hayulānī).
The name is given to it due to its similarity to the prime matter of bodies, which, not
possessing any form in itself, is capable of assuming every sensible form: not having any
intelligible form of its own, the potential or material intellect has a capability to take on every
intelligible form.364 This potential intellect (intellection) is defined by Ibn Sīnā as “the
readiness (literally: shaping – J.E.) of the soul” (tahayyu’ li ’l-nafs)365 or “a sheer
preparedness (isti‘dād) of the soul to assume all forms”.366 This potentiality of intellection is
actualized by the Active Intellect (whose activity should be understood as its being the
intellect (intellection) in actu (al-‘aql bi ’l-fi‘l) and whose being the intellect does not differ
from its being the intellected (ma‘qūl)).
The first thing originated by the act of the Active Intellect upon the material intellect is the
habitual intellect (intellectus in habitu; al-‘aql bi ’l-malaka). It represents the form of the
primary intelligibles (al-ma‘qūlāt al-uwla), i.e., axiomatic truths (some of which – e.g. “The
whole is greater than its part” – are actualized without having recourse to logical reasoning
and practice and some other – e.g. “Every terrene body is heavy” – through practice). The
theoretical faculty of the soul “follows” these forms and “submits” itself to them in order to
obtain other – more sophisticated – ones (i.e., the secondary intelligibles). The actualization
of the habitual intellect gives the soul a possibility to use syllogism (qiyās) and logical
definition (hadd). However, the conclusions of the syllogism and the logical definition are
accepted as true and valid only due to the effusion of the light of the Active Intellect.
When the soul actualizes in itself the acquired intelligibles – though without their actual
occurrence in it, in the aspect of their actualization in it, – it becomes the actual intellect
362
See: F.Rahman, “’Akl” (V.892.b), in EI.
363
Ibn Sīnā, Mabdā’, 111–112.
364
See: Ibn Sīnā, Mabdā’, 97.
365
Ibn Sīnā, Mabdā’, 96.
366
Ibn Sīnā, Mabdā’, 97.

108
(intellect in actu; al-‘aql bi ’l-fi‘l) (which means that the soul becomes able to intellect them
whenever it wishes, without having to seek them anew). When, in turn, the actual existence of
these intelligible forms in the soul is considered, these intelligibles are collectively called “the
intellect that is acquired (or: obtained) from outside” (‘aql mustafād min al-khārij) (that is,
from the Active Intellect – J.E.), through demand (talab) or device (hīla). Therefore, it can be
called the “actual intellect” in respect to itself and the “acquired intellect” in respect to its
actor.367
The only intelligible form which is essentially perceived by the acquired intellect is that of the
Active Intellect. All other intelligible forms are perceived through the latter, in an accidental
manner.
“It was explained [earlier] that… the [individual] intellect refines the intelligibles from the
sensible affairs and makes itself similar to the former, and that it intellects through a habitude
acquired from the thing which is intellect in its essence and intelligible in its substance – not
that kind of the intelligible, which is separated (or: abstracted) by the intellect from a non-
intelligible shape, thus becoming [accidentally] intelligible. And it is more proper for such a
substance to be the principle (mabdā’), so that the rest, which is not intelligible in its essence,
might be intellected through it. And this is so because the thing which is something in its
essence is the principle in respect to every thing which is not the aforementioned thing”.368
Thus, to Ibn Sīnā and his followers (in this case, including Mullā Sadrā) the spiritual return/
resurrection means the unification of the theoretical faculty of the rational human soul with
the Active Intellect (the nearest of the separated intellects in respect to the inhabitants of the
sublunary sphere). Through this unification, it permanently perceives the Sheer Good and the
Necessarily Existent, the separated intellects and its own essence. This permanent unalloyed
intellection, together with awareness of it, necessitates its eternal bliss.
This takes us to the issue of the bliss and misery of the soul. While the soul resides in the
natural body, it can enjoy two kinds of bliss, one of which pertains to the theoretical faculty
and the other – to the practical one. The theoretical bliss is the perfection of the soul’s essence
taken without relation to the body and consists in its becoming a knowing (‘ālim) and
intellectual (‘aqlī) substance. Practical happiness is the perfection of the soul considered in
the aspect of its connection with the body and consists in its possessing the shape (property)
of bringing under control (istīlā’) the latter. After the natural death, only theoretical bliss
continues.
It is important to note, however, that pleasure (ladhdha) which accompanies perception does
not result from acquisition of perfection. Rather it consists in perception of the agreeable
(mulā’im). The agreeable for the rational soul is the intellection (ta‘aqqul) of the Sheer Good,
the existents that are engendered from it in a hierarchical order (i.e., the separated intellects)
and its own essence. Its pleasure, therefore, consists in its perceiving (awareness) of this
(theoretical) perfection.
Two kinds of obstacles – essential and accidental ones – can prevent the soul from attainment
of happiness and make it suffer. Essential imperfection consists in conscious determining
oneself on partiality and denial, while possessing yearning for intellectual perfection, and in
forsaking attempt to fully acquire the actual intellect. Ibn Sīnā qualifies this as an incurable
disease, which after the natural death results in an everlasting intellectual suffering,
incomparably more intense than any kind of physical pain.369 (Sadrā in the Asfār identifies the

367
Ibn Sīnā, Mabdā’, 99.
368
Ibn Sīnā, Mabdā’, 102.
369
See: Ibn Sīnā, Mabdā’, 113.

109
souls which possess the potentiality of intellectual perfection, but do not actualize it and
consciously neglect it as the “hypocrites” (munāfiqūn).370)
In turn, accidental imperfection consists in the soul’s taking on bodily shapes (i.e., accidents)
(al-hay’āt al-badaniyya) due to its habit to submit to the wishes of the body. These acquired
bodily shapes (traces) remain in the soul after its separation from the material body through
physical death, preventing it from experiencing intellectual happiness. Since they are alien to
the substance of the soul, their presence in it causes it to suffer. However, Ibn Sīnā is inclined
to think that, after a certain period of time, these shapes fade away and perish.371 It is not
unlikely that Sadrā’s teaching on the suffering of the grave (‘adhāb al-qabr) was inspired by
this Avicennan idea of the temporally accidental suffering of the soul due to its associating
itself with the natural body.
The above discussed true (read: intellectual) happiness and suffering, however, is the share of
a relatively small number of human souls. As for the majority of the human souls, in which
the yearning towards intelligibles does not develop expressly and with certainty, Ibn Sīnā
believes them to possess certain illusory (wahmiyya) or suppositional (zanniyya) happiness or
suffering. He refers to the opinion of Fārābī that, after their natural death, these souls, due to
their yearning for the natural body, might somehow relate themselves to celestial and
atmospheric bodies, which could serve as the loci of manifestation (mazāhir) for forms,
created in their imagination (according to Fārābī and Ibn Sīnā, both imagination (creating
images) (takhayyul) and estimation (attributing a particular illusory meaning to a certain
image) (tawahhum) require a corporeal substratum – a postulate which will be most
vigorously attacked by Sadrā).372
As Sadrā himself states on a number of occasions373, there is no disagreement between him
and the earlier Muslim philosophers on the issue of spiritual (or, to put it more precisely,
intellectual (‘aqlī)) return. In his earlier works, such as al-Mabdā’ wa ’l-ma‘ād and al-
Shawāhid al-rubūbiyya, the chapters on ma‘ād rūhānī represent, by and large, compilations of
paraphrased passages from the writings of Ibn Sīnā. In some later works, like the ‘arshiyya,
Sadrā does not discuss the topic at all, only making a brief statement about his full agreement
with the predecessors (while he discusses there the corporeal return in great detail). Therefore,
this is probably only in the tenth chapter of the fourth journey of the Asfār,374 where the issue
is treated by him both in detail and with some originality. This originality, however, has more
to do with the style and less with the subject-matter – namely, Sadrā quotes certain Qur’anic
verses and employs Qur’anic images, outwardly attempting to demonstrate the complete
agreement between revelatory wisdom and philosophical intuition, but, in the actual fact,
interpreting the Qur’anic text in accordance with his philosophical concern of the attainment
of intellectual perfection. A particularly good example is Sadrā’s treatment of those human
beings, which, while possessing ability and taste for intellectual perfection, do not actualize it,
deliberately abandoning the path leading towards unification with the Active Intellect, and,
instead, turning to imaginal and sensible pleasures, as the “hypocrites” (munāfiqūn).
“The miserable ones divide in two groups… one of which consists of the inhabitants of this
world, and the universal veil [which is] cast on their hearts… and another group, which consists
of the hypocrites (munāfiqūn) – those, who, in principle, possess preparedness and, in respect to
their innate nature (fitra) and first configuration, receive the light of true knowledge (ma‘rifa),

370
See: Sadrā, Asfār, part 9, 132. The passage will be examined later.
371
See: Ibn Sīnā, Mabdā’, 113.
372
See: Ibn Sīnā, Mabdā’, 114–115.
373
See e.g.: Sadrā, ‘arshiyya, 245.
374
Sadrā, Asfār, part 9, 121–184.

110
but go astray from the path and their hearts become veiled by the veil, obtained owing to
acquisition of vices through committing acts of disobedience and performing the acts of brutes
and predatory beasts, and plotting devilish schemes, until dark shapes and gloomy habits take
root [in them]”.375
Sadrā then states that, due to these acquired habits, their souls experience a painful suffering,
being “tied up” and “shackled” by “the shackles of material affections (‘alā’īq al-hayūlā) in
the darkness of this-worldly desires (shahawāt al-dunyā)”.376
This picturesque description, based on the Qur’anic imagery, shows that Sadrā confuses
essential intellectual suffering with accidental one. The suffering of the soul which has failed
to actualize its ability for intellectual development, to Ibn Sīnā, consists in the painful
awareness of this failure:
“In the same way as sensible pain consists in sensing what is contrary to one’s [object of]
yearning and in awareness of movement towards its opposite, this [intellectual] pain also
consists in the same [sort of awareness]”.377
In turn, tormenting bodily shapes (read: desires), which result from the soul’s submitting itself
to the bodily appetites in this-worldly life, are, rather, accidental obstacles that will be
eventually removed if the soul has an experience of unification with the Active Intellect.
In its metaphorical sense, as a denomination of those human beings who fail to actualize their
potentiality for perfection, the term munāfiqūn, apparently, was first used by the Sufi theorists
of Ibn al-‘Arabī school – probably, by Qaysarī, who wrote in his commentary on the Fusūs:
“As for the hypocrites – those who possess the preparedness of perfection and the preparedness
of imperfection, although they experience pain due to their awareness of perfection and the
impossibility to achieve it, since their preparedness of imperfection predominates, they consent
to remain imperfect and their pain wears off after the Vengeful’s taking [His] vengeance upon
them through making them suffer, and their suffering becomes sweet (i.e., pleasant – J.E.), as
we observe this happen with the one, who first does not consent to a base affair, then, when it
happens with him, and he is afflicted with it, and it is produced by him a number of times, he
becomes disposed to it and gets used to it, and begins to take pride in it, after being ashamed of
it”.378
Sadrā quotes the above passage of Qaysarī in the 28th chapter of the 4th journey of the Asfār
(“On the manner in which the inhabitants of Fire remain eternally in it”). His not taking Ibn
Sīnā’s point on the intellectual suffering and attempts (inspired by Qaysarī) to correct it result
from his belief that the absence of something (in the given case – the absence of intellectual
perfection and union with the Active Intellect) is a non-existent affair (amr ‘adamī) and, as
such, cannot cause either pleasure or suffering. Hence, the cause of suffering must be
something existent and found (say, the “shackles of material affections” and the “scorpions of
this-worldly appetites”).
In the 30th chapter of the 4th journey of the Asfār (“On the entification of the locus of suffering
and punishment in Fire”) Sadrā clarifies his position, to the effect that the rational soul (the
divine spirit, the locus of wisdom and knowledge and an intellectual substance perceiving the
purely intelligible forms) is blissful in this world and in the hereafter, since, in actual fact, it
never leaves its noble place (the world of the Intellect), and does not belong to the world of
misery in any aspect. This soul, however, is not found in most human beings379 (i.e., it cannot
375
Sadrā, Asfār, part 9, 132.
376
Sadrā, Asfār, part 9, 132.
377
Ibn Sīnā, Mabdā’, 113.
378
Qaysarī, Matla‘, part 1, 435.
379
Sadrā, Asfār, part 9, 372.

111
be actualized partially or exist as mere potentiality and yearning, as Ibn Sīnā seems to admit).
What does not exist (is not found), cannot experience either pleasure or pain. On the other
hand, wrath (ghadab) and appetite (shahwa) are natural perfections of the animal soul, by
means of which the latter lauds and praises God. Whatever the animal soul does, driven by
wrath and appetite, is its natural act, and natural acts are not liable to punishment.
The real locus of suffering, argues Sadrā, must therefore be something mixed between the
rational and the animal souls. To him, it is the rational soul in the aspect of its connection with
the animal soul, before the former’s becoming the actual intellect. This mixed affair is like an
isthmus, which brings together both sides. In the aspect of its being the animal soul, it is the
object of punishment; in the aspect of its being the rational soul, it perceives the pain.380
According to this theory, the punishment is inflicted upon the animal soul for its disobeying
the commands of the rational soul. However, the animal soul seems to be unaware of its being
punished, because the awareness of punishment and award pertains to the manifestations of
the rational soul. Therefore, it appears that the rational soul, attempting to punish the animal
soul, in fact punishes itself. The above theory is likely to have its source in the teachings of
certain Mutakallimūn (probably Ghazālī or Rāzī). There is a trace of incompleteness on it,
because, alongside with sound ideas, it seems to include a touch of absurdity as well.
Furthermore, since true bliss pertains to the rational soul proper and consists in its witnessing
the Sheer Good and the intellects, even a total obedience of the animal soul to the rational one
cannot give it more than illusory and imaginal happiness. Therefore, the unhappiness and
misery, caused by disobedience, must likewise be a metaphorical and imaginal affair. Hence,
the above discussed kind of misery cannot be regarded as true and real misery. In a nutshell,
while true (read: intellectual) happiness is reserved for a small minority of people (those who
possess the rational soul, i.e., have fully actualized its theoretical faculty, attaining unification
with the Active Intellect), the true misery, for the above stated reasons, cannot exist at all.
Hence, since the admittance of its existence does not agree with the key principles of Sadrā’s
thought, the lot of the overwhelming majority of human beings in the hereafter is an imaginal
affair – either imaginal bliss (sa‘āda khayāliyya) or imaginal misery (shaqāwa khayāliyya).
Before I proceed to corporeal (read: imaginal) resurrection, a few words must be said about
Sadrā’s understanding of the Active Intellect (al-‘aql al-fa‘‘āl). As most Peripatetic terms, it
was invented by Aristotle, who, however, used it only once – in De Anima III.5, apparently in
order to refer to the active part of the rational human soul, which actualizes its passive
counterpart. Due to the brevity and obscurity of the passage, the opinion of the commentators
divided: while Alexander of Aphrodisias, as it was mentioned above, believed the νους ποετικος
to be God, Themistius insisted on its being nothing more than a part of the human soul.
Ibn Sīnā, who had to rely on the Arabic translations (of rather poor quality) and the
commentary of Fārābī, treated the ‘aql fa‘‘āl as the lowest member of the hierarchy of
separated substances, which, in their totality, constituted the intellectual (noetic) universe. He
held it to be responsible for providing material objects with individual forms and the human
intellect – with universal ones (whence, in the latter Peripatetic tradition – both in the East
and the West – it was often called the “Giver of Forms” (Dator formarum; wāhib al-suwar)).
It must be admitted that Ibn Sīnā’s teaching on establishing a permanent contact with the
Active Intellect (ittisāl bi ’l- ‘aql al-fa‘‘āl) is not void of certain contradictions, due to the
conflicting influences of Aristotle and Plotinus (although Ibn Sīnā did not know Plotinus by
name and believed the Uthūlūjiyā to be written by Aristotle, he was, undoubtedly, deeply
influenced by some Plotinian ideas, discussed in the latter book).

380
Sadrā, Asfār, 371.

112
What, after all, is understood by “being in touch” (ittisāl) with the Universal Intellect and/ or
“unification” (ittihād) with it? Does it mean achieving the most sublime state of perceiving/
witnessing the Pure Good and unification with it, as Plotinus believed? Or is it simply an
acquisition of a skill to separate the intelligible forms of things from their material shapes,
i.e., an ability to invent logical definitions, consisting of genus and differentia (e.g. “man
(=human being) is a rational animal”)? In the latter case, as Sadrā points out381, it is difficult
to earnestly believe that possession of such knowledge and awareness of possessing it can
cause happiness which is incomparably more intense than any sort of sensory pleasure.
Therefore, we must either treat this unification in Plotinian sense or agree that, at times, Ibn
Sīnā presents himself as a complete simpleton.
In Sadrā’s cosmology, as I attempted to demonstrate in the 2nd chapter, the division of the
world of Intellect into a number of levels is a mental (dhihnī) affair. Therefore, Sadrā treats
the Active Intellect not as a vertical intellect, but as a horizontal one – namely, as the lord of
the human species.
“When the light – the one which is its (the human soul’s – J.E.) intelligible form – becomes
more intense, it unites with the universal human spirit, which is called “the Spirit of Holiness”,
“the Active Intellect” and “the Active Principle” – the one, the width and wideness of whose
existence is such that its relation towards all human individuals, instances and specimen is one
and the same”. 382
The identification of the Active Intellect with the archetype of the human species, however,
poses several questions, which Sadrā does not explicitly answer. According to the principle
“every thing returns to its root/ principle”, the return of the rational human soul to its lord of
species must be a universal affair. Hence, all human souls return to their “soul-giver” (ravān-
bakhsh) and the universal human spirit (in fact, they always remain with it, although their
preoccupation with bodily affairs may make them forget this). Therefore, spiritual/
intellectual ma‘ād must be understood as actualization of awareness of the true state of things
(i.e., restoring the ability to perceive oneself as the eternal intellectual human being). How
does this awareness or the intellection of one’s intelligible self relate to the awareness/
intellection of the Sheer Good? Sadrā does not examine this relationship in a speculative
discourse, presenting instead a paraphrase of the introduction of Suhrawardī’s Safīr-e Sīmurgh
(“The Shrill Cry of the Simurgh”) (in which the Persian word Sīmurgh is replaced with its
Arabic analogue ‘Anqā’).383 In the Ishrāqī tradition, ‘Anqā/ Sīmurgh is a symbol of the
Universal Intellect (al-‘aql al-kullī)384 and, concomitantly, of all particular intellects (while in
the Sufi tradition of Ibn al-‘Arabī school ‘Anqā’, on the contrary, refers to prime matter385).
The import of Sadrā’s statement “the arrival of the wayfarers at their destination occurs owing
to the assistance of this holy bird”386 seems to be that an individual human soul acquires
awareness of God, Sheer Good and the Light of Lights through coming in touch (ittisāl) and
unification (ittihād) with the awareness of the Active Intellect (i.e., through annihilating its
individual awareness in the universal one).

381
Sadrā, ‘arshiyya, 244.
382
Sadrā, Asfār, part 9, 144.
383
See: Sadrā, Asfār, part 9, 144–146. Cf. Suhrawardī’s Persian text in: Shihāb al-Dīn Suhrawardī, Safīr-i
Sīmurgh, Tehrān: Mawlā 1374 S.H., 7–8.
384
Sayyed Ja‘far Sajjādī holds that Sīmurgh is the symbol of the Universal Soul (nafs-i kullī), but his arguments
do not appear to be convincing. See: S.J.Sajjādī, Sharh-i risā’īl-i fārsī-yi Suhrawardī, Tehrān: Hawze-i
hunarī 1376 S.H., 173.
385
See: Kāshānī, Istilāhāt, 105.
386
Sadrā, Asfār, part 9, 146.

113
In the falsafa tradition, wayfaring (sulūk) is commonly understood as separation from matter
and actualization of the intellect. Sadrā’s theory of spiritual return, which is simultaneously a
teaching on theoretical wayfaring (al-sulūk al-nazarī), gives a fairly typical description of this
intellectual method. This description has some originality of expression, but adds little to the
ideas of his predecessors. His attempts to correct Avicennan doctrine on ma‘ād rūhānī in
accordance with the Platonic spirit of his own philosophy, e.g. the interpretation of the Active
Intellect as the lord of the human species, testify to his awareness of the imperfection and
inner contrariety of the former doctrine, but, at the same time, his suggested improvements
make it even more contradictory.

3.5. CORPOREAL RESURRECTION

To Sadrā, the difference between the kinds of perception (sensible, imaginal, and intellectual)
is a difference in the intensity of existence, not in essence. Therefore, as it was previously
mentioned, like Plotinus, he believes senses to be weak intellects and intellects – strong
senses.387 If so, his statement that most human beings do not experience spiritual (i.e.,
intellectual) return/ resurrection should be understood to the effect that they do experience it,
but their experience is weak and of low intensity, therefore, it should be better described as
imaginal one. The usage of the traditional theological terms ma‘ād rūhānī instead of ma‘ād
‘aqlī and ma‘ād jusmānī for ma‘ād khayālī is only for the sake of convenience and in order to
avoid undesired problems with the exoteric scholars (al-‘ulamā’ al-zāhirīn).
Therefore, while Ibn Sīnā is uncertain (or, to put it better, has little care) about the ma‘ād of
those human beings which fail to come in touch with the Active Intellect, Sadrā is very
certain that they do experience it, though it is an experience of a lesser intensity than spiritual
(intellectual) return/ resurrection. The necessity of the imaginal ma‘ād is, thus, dictated by the
principles of the principality and analogical gradation of existence, and is most convincingly
proved by Sadrā. His proof of the necessity of corporeal (imaginal) return/ resurrection is
based on several important premisses, which, simultaneously, appear to be the key principles
of Sadrā’s philosophy in general.
First. In every existent thing, the principle of its being existent (=being found) (mawjūdiyya)
is its existence (finding), while quiddity only follows existence (as a shadow follows its
possessor). Hence, the reality (haqīqa) of every thing is its specific kind of existence, not its
quiddity. Existence is, therefore, an entified he-ness (al-huwwiyya al-‘ayniyya), which cannot
be imitated by any mental affair. It is not possible to refer to it otherwise than through pure
knowledge of witnessing (‘irfān shuhūdī).388
Second. The individuation (tashakhkhus) of every thing is nothing else than its specific kind
of existence (nahw wujūdihi al-khāss). Existence and individuation are unified in their
essence, while they differ as concepts. The so-called individuating accidents (al-‘awārid al-
mushakhassa) are, in fact, only signs and concomitants of an individual existential he-ness,
and even in this capacity they can be accepted only if taken not in their entities and
individuals, but as perpetual changeability of limitation (or: definition) (hadd) (and, hence,
quiddity) in the accident.389 (I.e., what subsists is accident-in-general, while its intensity is in
perpetual change. This change of the intensity of accident, naturally, is caused by and must be
viewed as the concomitant of the perpetual change of the intensity of substance.)

387
Sadrā, Asfār, part 9, 101.
388
See: Sadrā, Asfār, part 9, 185. Cf. Ibn Sīnā’s statement in the Ishārāt: “It is not possible to point to the First
One except by pure intellectual knowledge (‘irfān ‘aqlī)” (Ibn Sīnā, Ishārāt, 275).
389
See: Sadrā, Asfār, part 9, 185.

114
Third. The nature of existence accepts intensity and weakness by its very essence (which is
simple and non-compound both externally and mentally). Hence, the difference between its
instances is not by essential differentia, accident or any other individuator that is added to the
principle of this nature (as the Peripatetics hold), but by essential intensity and weakness and
(essential) priority and posteriority. However, the universal concepts that are essentially
attributed to the instances of existence and extracted from them (i.e., the quiddities) differ
from each other by genus, differentia and accident. Therefore, it is said that existence differs
in species, because the essentialists (those who believe in the principality of quiddity) treat
different levels of intensity of existence as different species.
Fourth. Existence accepts intensifying motion (al-haraka al-ishtidādiyya) and substance is
capable of an essential transformation (istihāla) of its substantiality. Parts and limitations of a
single continuous motion, as it was previously established, do not exist in actu, but only in
potentia and as abstractions of the mind. Hence, all parts of such motion exist by one and the
same existence. (At the utmost, Sadrā is ready to grant the quiddities abstracted from different
stages and levels of substantial motion some sort of undifferentiated existence (wujūd
ijmālī).)390
Fifth. Every compound thing is what it is through its form, not through its matter. Matter is
nothing else than the subject (carrier) of the potentiality and possibility of the thing and the
substratum of receiving/ passivity (infi‘āl) and motion. Therefore, if one supposed the
subsistence of the form of a compound thing without matter, he would find the thing existing
in the totality of its reality.
Sixth. The individual oneness (unity) of every thing – which is the same as its existence – is
not univocal in fashion and does not pertain to the same degree to all existents. On the
contrary, like existence itself, it is ambiguous and analogically graded: in continuous
quantities (measures) it manifests itself as continuity and uninterruptedness; in time and
gradual affairs – as ceasing and self-renewal; in numbers – as actual manyness; in natural
bodies – as potential manyness. Furthermore, in separated substances it manifests itself
otherwise than in material ones, because their capacity as “vessels” of existence is different.
(The latter postulate seems to reflect the influence of Mīr Dāmād’s teaching (though radically
reinterpreted by Sadrā) on wi‘ā al-dahr and wi‘ā al-zamān.). As one’s separation from matter
and substantiation increases and he grows more powerful and more perfect, he becomes able
to encompass more and more things and bring together more and more different affairs, until
eventually he actualizes in himself the form of existence in its entirety. Due to its ability to
encompass everything, the human soul moves freely up and down the scale of existence,
decreasing and increasing its intensity at its will. Owing to its phasing itself in different
phases, one and the same thing can be at times connected with matter and at other times –
separated from it (while this separation also has different degrees).
Seventh. The he-ness and individuation of the body occur through its soul, not through its
bulk (matter). Even if a natural form is changed into an imaginal one, the he-ness of human
being, regardless of all transformations, remains (one and) the same, because it exists as a
gradually actualized continuity. The soul, as the form of perfection and completeness of
human being, is the principle of its essence and the place of the origin of its faculties and tools
(such as eyes, ears, nose etc.), and the source of its dimensions and parts, which preserves all
them in this natural engendering and simultaneously gradually changes them into parts of the
spiritual (i.e., imaginal) body, and then into simple intellectual substance. The change of
matter is not an obstacle for the subsistence of a compound thing, because matter constitutes it
not in the aspect of its specification and entification, but as genus and something indefinite

390
See: Sadrā, Asfār, part 9, 186.

115
and non-specified (amr mubham).391 (The latter postulate, as it was mentioned above, plays a
crucial role in Sadrā’s teaching on substantial motion.)
Eighth. The imaginal faculty does not reside in any part of material human body. Moreover,
it does not exist in any direction (aspect) of the natural world. It exists in an intermediate
substantial world, which is situated between the world of intellectual (noetic) substances and
the world of material natural existents (i.e., in the world of Imagination (‘ālam al-khayāl) or
that of Likeness (‘ālam al-mithāl)).
Ninth. Imaginal forms (and perceptual forms in general) do not penetrate into the substratum
of the soul, or into any other locus. They subsist through the soul as the act subsists through
its actor, not as the received affair subsists through its receiver. As long as the soul is
connected with the (natural) body, its sense perception is different from imagination, because
the former requires external matter and specific preconditions, but the latter does not require
them. But after the soul’s coming out of the natural world the difference between sensing and
imagination disappears, because, when the imaginal faculty grows strong and comes out of
the “dust” (ghubār) of the natural body, all faculties unify and return to the common sense
(al-hiss al-mushtarak), and the imaginal faculty replaces all other faculties. In another aspect,
the soul’s power, knowledge and appetite becomes one thing, therefore, by imagining the
objects of appetite, the soul simultaneously makes them present.
Tenth. In the same way as measurable forms and bodily shapes and figures are produced by
the actor with the participation of matter, which receives them in accordance with its
preparedness, they are also produced by active directions and their perceptual aspects without
its participation. (Sadrā believes that celestial spheres and planets are produced by the
intellects exactly in this way – as pure acts of thought).392 Basing his reasoning on Ibn al-
‘Arabī’s discourse on himma (‘aspiration’) in the Fusūs393, Sadrā asserts that intensity and
weakness of the imaginal forms one perceives depends on his ability or inability to bring
together his aspiration.
Eleventh. There are an infinite number of worlds and configurations existent, but all they can
be divided into three genera: 1) the world of perpetually engendering and corrupting natural
forms; 2) the world of sensible perceptual forms; 3) the world of intellectual forms and
archetypes. The peculiarity of the human soul consists in its being gradually engendered in
each of these three worlds, while subsisting as individual. Beginning with its earliest infancy,
the human being undergoes natural engendering (al-kawn al-tabī‘ī), in conformity with which
he is a “smooth-skinned” (i.e., natural) human being (insān basharī). In the process of
substantial motion, his existence gradually becomes purer and subtler, as a result of which
purification he experiences the psychic engendering (al-kawn al-nafsānī), in conformity with
which he is the other-worldly psychic human being (insān nafsānī ukhrawī), the object of
Sending Forth (Awakening) (ba‘th) and Rising (qiyām). Then he is gradually transferred from
the psychic engendering to intellectual (noetic) one (al-kawn al-‘aqlī) and becomes the
intellectual (noetic) human being. (What we get here, in a nutshell, is Plotinus reinterpreted in
accordance with the theory of substantial motion.)
One has to fully agree with Fazlul Rahman, who considered these eleven principles to be not
only the constituents of Sadrā’s proof of corporeal resurrection, but also “the main principles
of his philosophy and their consequences”.394 But Rahman does not pose a question, why this
is the case, i.e., why Sadrā’s proof of ma‘ād jusmānī, as presented in the Asfār395, consists of
391
See: Sadrā, Asfār, part 9, 190–191.
392
See: Sadrā, Asfār, part 9, 192–193.
393
See: Ibn al-‘Arabī, Fusūs, part 1, 88–89.
394
Rahman, Philosophy, 255. For his account of these principles, see: Rahman, Philosophy, 255–257.
395
Sadrā, Asfār, part 9, 185–197.

116
the (most masterly composed) summary of Sadrā’s philosophy proper. The importance and
sensitivity of the issue can only be understood properly if it is considered in the context of
Sadrā’s relationship with the audiences towards which his writings were directed and his full
awareness of their preparednesses and the set of beliefs they adhered to.396 My observation is
that, when Sadrā presents his arguments of a major issue of his teaching, they often look like
roadmaps depicting the stages of transformation of a common (exoteric) religious belief into a
philosophical truth. What we encounter in the given case, is the transformation of the dogma
of the resurrection of natural bodies into the doctrine of the subsistence of imaginative faculty
and its becoming the substratum of the experiences of the afterlife.
Apart from its religious importance, the issue of corporeal return also concerned Sadrā as a
particular instance of the lower possibility (al-imkān al-akhass). The theory of the lower
possibility, as we remember, demands that in the ascending movement towards God all lower
evolutionary stages of perfection must be fully actualized before the ascending affair can
move to a higher stage. Hence, it is impossible to “jump” from the sensible world to the
intellectual one, bypassing the domain of imagination. Rather, the overwhelming majority of
the human souls remain forever enjoying themselves in the imaginal Garden or suffering in
the imaginal Fire (for this reason, Sadrā compares human souls with ways (sirātāt), only some
of which arrive at the destination, while the others stop at some intermediate point without
reaching the intended place397).
Even more importantly, Sadrā apparently felt that his predecessors, like Ibn Sīnā and
Suhrawardī, have failed to do the justice to ma‘ād jusmānī, treating it as an uncertain and
insignificant affair. It does not follow hence, nevertheless, that Sadrā did not share his
predecessors belief that, whosoever has ability and preparedness for it, must strive to achieve
unification with the Active Intellect at all cost. Of course, he did share it fully, as we saw it in
the previous subchapter during the discussion on the “hypocrites”. Moreover, unlike Ibn Sīnā,
Sadrā viewed separation (tajarrud) as a gradual process that takes no less than one’s lifetime
to complete – not as an instantaneous (durationless) act of thought. The greatest part of the
road, along which the folk of tajrīd have to travel in order to achieve unification with the
Active Intellect, according to Sadrā, goes through the domain of imagination. If so, the
roadmap of spiritual return proper does not give a full account of the complexity of the issue
of ma‘ād. What the common Peripatetic tradition understands as “spiritual return” represents
little more than development of the skill to conceptualize sense data. Ibn Sīnā’s Neoplatonic
treatment of coming in touch with the Active Intellect as intellection of Pure Good (which
cannot be conceptualized and defined by genus and differentia) disagrees with the Aristotelian
understanding of tajarrud as conceptualization of sense experiences, thus revealing the
contradictoriness of his approach. In any case, imagination is not a major issue in Peripatetic
interpretations of ma‘ād. Sadrā’s interpreting the Active Intellect as the lord of human
species, together with his treatment of separation as a gradual affair, make imagination an
essential phase of the evolution of the human soul from sense into intellect.
The domain of Imagination and its landmarks are described by Sadrā in terms of the Qur’anic
eschatology – or one will also be just in asserting the opposite, namely, that the Qur’anic
eschatology is interpreted by him as a series of events pertaining to the imaginal phase of the
soul’s substantial evolution. I shall now attempt to examine some of these landmarks – the
Grave (al-qabr), the Sending Forth/ Awakening (al-ba‘th) and the Rising (al-qiyāma) –
proceeding subsequently to the analysis of the experiences of Garden and Fire.

396
For a more detailed account of these audiences, see: Morris, Wisdom, 39–41.
397
See: Sadrā, ‘arshiyya, 264.

117
3.5.1. The Grave and the Awakening

Although the influence of Ibn al-‘Arabī’s teaching on the barzakh (‘isthmus’)398 on Sadrā’s
conception of the Grave is considerable, it seems that its principal source must be sought in
Ibn Sīnā’s seminal remarks on the bodily shapes (al-hay’āt al-badaniyya) that inhere in the
soul due to its habit to obey the wishes of the body, wherefore the soul, in fact, identifies itself
with the latter. After the soul’s separation from the natural body, these shapes remain in the
soul, causing accidental suffering due to the presence in it of what is alien to its essence.399 To
Sadrā, this is exactly the soul’s habit to identify itself with the natural body that causes it to
suffer or to experience bliss in the Grave:
“When the spirit abandons the natural body, it retains some sort of connection with this body –
not with its material parts, as some of the recent [scholars] have thought400… – but with the
body in its entirety in the aspect of its (i.e., the body’s – J.E.) form and the shape of its frame
(haykal), which remain in its (the soul’s – J.E.) memory. And the soul, when it abandons the
body, carries with it the estimative faculty, which perceives particular meanings through its
essence and corporeal (read: imaginal – J.E.) forms – through employing imagination.
…when a human being dies and imagines his essence as [an affair which is] separated from this
world, and [mistakenly] identifies it as that very human being which is dead and buried – the
one which died in his form – [in the same manner as in dream visions he witnesses himself in
the same form in which he exists in this world, and witnesses the affairs by true witnessing
through his inner sense]401 – and finds his body in the grave, and perceives the pain that afflicts
the body as sensible punishment, in keeping with what the true Laws tell us, this is the suffering
of the Grave (‘adhāb al-qabr). But, if he is a blessed one, he imagines what is promised by the
Law in an agreeable form, in conformity with the objects of his beliefs, such as gardens, rivers,
parks, page-boys, houris, cups of the allotted [substance] (i.e., wine – J.E.), and this is the
reward of the Grave (thawāb al-qabr)… and the true Grave consists of these shapes”.402
Grave is the first other-worldly stage of the soul’s substantial evolution, at which the soul
continues to identify itself with its natural body, in spite of its actual separation from the
latter, and imagines that as/ through this natural body it receives sensible reward and sensible
punishment for its this-worldly acts performed in conformity with its beliefs or contrary to
them. Thus, “grave”, “reward” and “punishment” are imaginal and illusory affairs that exist
only in the consciousness of the soul. If the latter did not identify itself with the natural body
and did not believe in posthumous reward and punishment, it would not experience them.
Experiences of the Grave result solely from our estimations (awhām). However, it is
impossible to avoid burial in the psychic grave and not to identify our self with the natural
body otherwise than through an intense and lasting experience of separation (tajrīd) from the
latter. How is such experience provoked? There must have been a complex of ascetic
exercises (riyādāt), practised by the people of separation (ahl al-tajrīd) previously to Sadrā (a
good number of allusions to such exercises are dispersed among the writings of

398
See e.g.: Ibn al-‘Arabī, Futūhāt, part 1, 304-307 and part 3, 249–250.
399
See: Ibn Sīnā, Mabdā’, 113.
400
Apparently, Sadrā refers to the famous theory of the Shi‘i Mutakallim Sadr al-Dīn al-Dashtakī al-Shīrāzī
(828/1425–903/1497) (discussed in the latter’s Risāla fī ’l-ma‘ād) on the twofold connection of the soul with
the natural body – through the animal spirit and directly with parts of the body. While the first connection is
destroyed by natural death, the second, as Dashtakī holds, remains intact. Dashtakī believes that every
particle of the natural body is somehow “branded” by the soul during their coexistence. By this “brand”,
different parts of the destroyed body will recognize each other upon Rising, coming together and restoring
the decayed shape, after which the soul will return to it. (See: Sadrā, Asfār, part 9, 205.)
401
Sadrā, Mafātīh, part 2, 726.
402
Sadrā, Asfār, part 9, 219. According to Khājavī, the last paragraph is a paraphrase of a passage from Ghazālī’s
al-Madnūn bihi ‘alā ghayr ahlihi (“What Must Be Kept from the Unworthy”) (see: Sadrā, Mafātīh, part 2, 726).

118
Suhrawardī403). As for Sadrā, most of his works can (and must) be treated as textbooks of
theoretical separation (let us remember that he called his magnum opus “Four intellectual (or:
noetic) journeys” (al-Asfār al-‘aqliyya al-arba‘a)).
Gradually the intensity of the images of the Grave fades away and the soul becomes aware
that its estimative faculty has made an error, identifying itself with the physical shape of the
dead body. It realizes that, as a non-compound spiritual affair, it is all things that its scope of
intensity allows it to encompass. This gradual wearing off of the intensity with which the soul
perceives itself as its former natural body is called “Sending Forth” (or: “Awakening”) (ba‘th)
and “coming out of the Grave”.
“Awakening consists of the soul’s coming out of the dust of these shapes, like an embryo comes
out of its strong dwelling, and the difference between the state of Grave and the state of
Awakening is like the difference between man’s state in the womb of his mother and that of his
coming out of it, and, indeed, the state of Grave is a specimen of the states of Rising”.404
When the time for Rising comes, the man wakes up from the sleep of the Grave and, willingly
or not, directs himself towards God. Rising from the Grave, i.e., ceasing to identify oneself
with the natural body with its wishes and appetites, is one of the essential stages of the soul
and an indispensable phase of its substantial development. Since it is an essential affair, its
occurrence cannot be prevented by accidental obstacles (such as habits and attachments,
referred to by Ibn Sīnā as “bodily shapes”). However, the presence of the latter in the soul can
make it perceive the event of Rising (and the essential motion in general) as something
unpleasant and painful. Once the soul comes out of the “Grave”, it ceases to identify itself
with and imagine itself in the shape of its natural body, but its previous bodily affections
remain in it, therefore it is limited (muqayyad) in its creative activity and can only produce
images (imaginal forms) of the objects of its affections. Such relative captivity of its
imaginative faculty can be described as “imaginal Fire (Hell)” (al-nār al-khayāliyya), while
relative freedom of this faculty in producing forms may be considered as “imaginal Garden
(Paradise)” (al-janna al-khayāliyya).

3.5.2. Rising

According to Sadrā, Rising (qiyāma) is a state of consciousness and a stage of perceptual


existence (al-wujūd al-idrākī), at which a complete destruction of habitual this-worldly
images and manifestations of existence occurs. He believes that the Qur’anic verses which
describe the events of the Last Day (e.g. “When the sight is dazed, and the moon is buried in
darkness, and the sun and the moon are joined together” (75:8-10)405, “and the heavens shall
be opened as if these were doors, and the mountains shall vanish, as if they were a mirage”
(78:19-20)406, “when the sun is folded up, when the stars fall, loosing their lustre” (81:1-2)407)
should be understood as allusions to such transformation of consciousness. The focal point of
this transformation is witnessing the unbounded existence – existence which is not limited in
any way.

403
See e.g.: Suhrawardī, Philosophy of Illumination, 1–5 and 159–162.
404
Sadrā, Asfār, part 9, 219. Cf. Ibn al-‘Arabī’s statement: “The period of barzakh, in relation to the last
configuration, correspond’s to the woman’s carrying the embryo in her belly” (Ibn al-‘Arabī, Futūhāt, part 3,
250. The English translation by Chittick in: Chittick, Self-Disclosure, 351).
405
Qur’an, 514.
406
Qur’an, 520.
407
Qur’an, 526.

119
In Sufi terms, Rising is equivalent to the Real’s essential self-disclosure (al-tajallī al-dhātī) –
the disclosure, in which it manifests itself as the Unbounded (or: Absolute) Existence (al-
wujūd al-mutlaq). This essential self-disclosure, as it was mentioned earlier, destroys the
locus of its manifestation , i.e., the “mountain” of the soul’s he-ness, wherefore it ceases to
perceive itself as an individual with a set of specific characteristics and, instead, becomes
aware of itself as of the whole of existence (i.e., a drop comes to perceive itself as the ocean).
Following the Sufi theorists, Sadrā describes this transformation of consciousness as “the
return of its (the soul’s – J.E.) [specified] existence to the existence of the Real through lifting
(or: removing) its delimited existence”.408
When the manifestation of the light of oneness grows strong,
The shadow of frames is lifted from the world.409
The experience of coming in touch with Pure Existence/ Finding (witnessing the essential
self-disclosure of the Real) brings the awareness of existence as flow and, hence, the
apprehension of the instability and illusory character of all existential images and forms
(particular existences). Therefore, sarayān al-wujūd (‘flow of existence’) is, first and
foremost, an intuition produced by the “risen” consciousness that has been “awakened” from
the illusion of stability of the (sensible and psychic) world, as Sadrā seems to testify in the
following passage on the Rising, found in the ‘arshiyya:
“Know that the Rising… is inside the veils of the heavens and the earth and that it relates to this
world as human being relates to womb and bird to egg; and whoso has not destroyed the
building of the outer, the inner states are not revealed to him, because the Unseen and the
Witnessed cannot be brought together in one locus (mawdi‘)…
And the mystic witnesses these states and awe-inspiring affairs [of Rising] upon the
manifestation of the authority (sultān) of the other world to his essence, and hears the call:
“Whose is the Kingdom today? God’s, who is the One and the Overwhelming” (40:16)410 and
sees “the heavens [being] rolled up in His right hand” (39:67)411, and, upon [the occurrence of]
the Rising, sees this earth quaking and the mountains [being] broken into pieces, so that there is
no stability and no solidity in them, and, when the veil is removed through the Greater and
Lesser Risings, he sees every thing in its root, without the error of the sense and the doubt of the
estimative faculty, and he [also] sees the compound individual possessors of positions (i.e., the
natural bodies – J.E.) as [perpetually] self-renewing and transforming matters and forms,
together with their different accidents – those through which their existence as sensible
individuals, whose loci of manifestation are the tools (i.e., the organs – J.E.) of senses and their
receptabilities, is completed. And at Rising they (the “possessors of positions”, i.e., natural
bodies – J.E.) are seen by another kind of seeing and at the other-worldly locus of witnessing
they do not possess this [sensible] existence, but at the Plain of Rising the mystic witnesses
(=perceives) the things in their principal realities by his other-worldly sense, illuminated by the
light of Sovereignty, and he witnesses the mountains as “plucked wool-tufts” (101:5)412, and
[then] understands the meaning of His word: “They ask you concerning the mountains. Say: my
Lord will uproot them and scatter them as dust. He will leave them as plains smooth and level.
Nothing crooked or curved wilt thou see in their place” (20:105-107).413 And on that day he sees
the fire of Gehenna “encompassing the unbelievers (i.e., the natural existents – J.E.)” (9:49)414
and sees how the bodies are being burnt and “the skins are being roasted through” (4:56)415, and

408
Sadrā, Mafātīh, part 2, 723.
409
Sadr al-Dīn al-Shīrāzī, Majmu‘a-i ash‘ār, ed. M.Khājavī, Tehrān: Intishārāt-i Mawlā 1997, 62.
410
The English translation of the verse by Chittick: Chittick, Knowledge, 433.
411
Qur’an, 394.
412
Chittick, Self-Disclosure, 367.
413
Qur‘an, 259.
414
Qur’an, 149.
415
Qur’an, 67.

120
the flesh is being melted [in the fire] “whose fuel is men and stones” (2:24)416, and [how] the
seas are boiling over with a swell”.417
The vision of Rising, generally speaking, is the vision of oneness of the true existence (“the
Real”) and illusoriness of its limitations. Upon a closer examination, however, one finds that
what is at issue is not an absolute individual oneness (according to which, “all is He”418), but
a sort of oneness-in-manyness and manyness-in-oneness (wahda fī ’l-kathra wa kathra fī ’l-
wahda): though the mystic perceives the perpetual change and “flow” of the natural bodies,
he simultaneously witnesses the stability of their principal realities (al-haqā’īq al-asliyya)
(which, as it was indicated earlier, should be understood as directions (jihāt) and aspects of
the reality of existence (or “rays” of the Light of Lights), which appear (can be discerned) at a
certain level of its weakening and “descending”. Therefore, it can be stated that in the above
quoted description of the experience of Rising Sadrā combines the approaches of Sufi
mysticism and Neoplatonism. The dominating intuition is, apparently, that of the natural
world as Fire (Hell) (“He sees the fire of Gehenna encompassing the unbelievers, and sees
how the bodies are being burnt, and the skins are being roasted through, and the flesh is being
melted in the fire, whose fuel is men and stones”), whence he considers all its inhabitants – in
particular those who develop liking for and affection to it – to be “unbelievers” (kāfirūn),
while those who have cut their spiritual connections with the natural world, turning their
aspirations towards and putting their trust into the truly real intellectual/ noetic existence, but
still remain in this world in the aspect of their bodily frames (or the animal soul in general)
can be treated as “Abrahams”, being placed amidst fire, but not burning in it.419
In the Asfār Sadrā identifies the experience of Rising as change of the this-worldly
configuration into the other-worldly one or as “change/ replacement of existence” (tabdīl al-
wujūd), which can occur both before and after the natural death (in the former case it is called
“voluntary death” (al-mawt al-irādī)420).
““We have lifted the veil, and today thy sight is piercing” (50:22)421 – because of the change of
their (the mystics and the “risen ones” – J.E.) this-worldly configuration into an other-worldly
one. And when their configuration, and their hearing, sight and [other] senses are changed into/
replaced with [the other-worldly] hearing, sight and senses, [simultaneously,] in respect to them,

416
Qur’an, 5.
417
Sadrā, ‘arshiyya, 267–268.
418
This seems to have been the dominant intuition of the ecstatic (in particular, Persian) mysticism since the 11th
century at least. According to some testimonies, the expression was first employed by ‘Abdallāh Ansārī, but,
apparently, it was Jāmī who managed to express it in the most impressive way:
A neighbour, an intimate friend and a travelling companion, all is He.
In pauper’s rugs and in king’s satin, all is He.
In the assembly of separation and in the closet of gathering, all is He.
By God, all is He, then [again], by God, all is He.
(‘Abd al-Rahmān Jāmī, “Lawāī’h”, in: M.M.T.Majlisī, Risāle-i tashwīq al-sālikīn, with the attachment of
A.Jāmī’s Lawāī’h and F. ‘Irāqī’s Lawāme‘, Tehran: Nūr-i Fātima Publishers 1996, 62. Cf. Chittick’s
translation (W.C.Chittick, Sufism: A Short Introduction, Oxford: Oneworld 2000, 75).)
419
According to the Qur’an, when Abraham, who had come to believe in the True-and-One God, destroyed the
images of his tribal gods, his tribesmen sentenced him to death in fire, but the fire, obeying God’s command
(“We said: O Fire! Be thou cool and (a means of) safety for Abraham!” (Qur’an, 266-267)), did not burn
him. The symbol of Abraham, to my knowledge, is never employed by Sadrā, but it would be a very
appropriate one to indicate the state of the separated souls (of the wise men and mystics) in the kingdom of
Nature.
420
See: Sadrā, Asfār, part 9, 238.
421
Qur’an, 446.

121
are changed all existents that are [found] in the heavens and on the earth, because they also have
a this-worldly configuration and an other-worldly one”.422
“And through this change/ replacement in existence, regardless whether it occurs before the
[natural] death, with it, or after it, the human being becomes worthy of entering Garden and the
Dwelling of Peace, and through it is established the difference between the inhabitants of
Garden and the inhabitants of Fire. As for the inhabitants of Garden, they have illuminated
hearts and [wide] opened breasts, and purified bodies, and forms separated from the dirt of
natural matter, which is not the case with the inhabitants of Fire, because in the essences of the
latter the change/ replacement of the natural existence has not taken place”.423
The term tabdīl al-wujūd (‘change/ replacement of existence’) has strong Sufi connotations:
the Sufis believe there is a class of God’s clients/ friends, called abdāl (‘the changed/ replaced
ones’), whose bad character traits He replaces with (or makes look as) good ones. Since the
abdāl enjoy God’s special favour, they should not be judged by common standards. Rūmī,
however, interprets tabdīl rather as ripening (strengthening) of one’s individual existence:
Who are the abdāl? Those who become “replaced” (or: “substituted”).
Through replacement (or: substitution) their wine becomes vinegar.424
Though, as far as I know, Sadrā never refers to the Rūmī’s verse in his writings, like all
educated Persians, he had certainly studied the Mathnawī and, in all likelihood, had come
across the verse on some occasion. Besides, Rūmī’s conception of three essential stages of the
Sufi path (“[First] I was raw, [then] became ripe, [then] was burnt to ashes” (Khām bodam,
pokhta shodam, sūkhtam)425) might have been an important – though not the only – source of
inspiration for Sadrā’s doctrine of substantial motion of the soul. However, according to Rūmī
(and the Sufis in general), the intensifying motion results in the de-entification of the entity
and in the annihilation (fanā’) of the limited existence in the non-limited one. To be a
“changed one” (badal, pl. abdāl), in the eyes of a Sufi, means to witness the Real (the
Unbounded Existence) in all particular and limited existences – not to witness the archetypes
of the things and not even to meditate upon the existents as the manifestations of different
God’s names.
In Sadrā’s interpretation, however, tabdīl al-wujūd is, first and foremost, tabdīl al-nash’a
(‘change of the configuration’): upon the increase of the intensity of the soul’s this-worldly
(=sensible) existence, it gradually changes into the other-worldly (=imaginal) one. In this
case, the “Rising”, apparently, refers to the moment when the soul becomes fully aware of
the occurrence of the change, while the change itself is a gradual affair that usually takes
one’s lifetime – in the natural body – to be completed.
Furthermore, to Sadrā, tabdīl al-wujūd means simultaneously Rising, the change of sense
existence to imaginal one and entering the (imaginal) Garden. Remaining on the sensible level
of existence means, properly speaking, remaining in the Fire of Nature without Rising. Is,
then, the Garden of the prophets and God’s clients, to which the former invite us, the
imaginal Garden, while that of the philosophers is the intellectual one? I shall attempt to
answer this question in the next subchapter.

422
Sadrā, Asfār, part 9, 282.
423
Sadrā, Asfār, part 9, 283.
424
Jalaluddin Rumi, The Mathnawi, ed. R.A.Nicholson, London: Luzac and Co 1925–1940, book 3, verse 4000.
425
Jalāl al-Dīn Rūmī, Dīvān-i Shams-i Tabrīzī, Tehrān: Intishārāt-i Amīr-i Kabīr 1354 S.H., 372.

122
3.5.3. Garden and Fire

Depending on the degree to which the soul is able to identify itself as the unbounded
existence (or: absolute being) (al-wujūd al-mutlaq), its post-Rising (ba‘d al-Qiyāma)
existence pertains either to Garden (Paradise) or Fire (Hell). Furthermore, Sadrā distinguishes
two gardens – the Garden of Those Drawn Near to God (jannat al-muqarribīn) (i.e., the
Intellectual or Noetic Paradise) and the Garden of the People of the Right Side (jannat ahl al-
yamīn) (the Imaginal Paradise) and two fires – the Fire of the People of the Left Side (nār ahl
al-yasīr) (the Imaginal Hell) and the Fire of Nature (nār al-tabī‘a) (the natural world proper).
Undoubtedly, two gardens and two fires represent nothing but certain ranges of perceptual
existence (wujūd idrākī) between which there are no clear-cut borders. Each particular range
of the scale of perceptual existence corresponds to a certain cosmological level: the Garden of
Those Drawn Near to God – to the world of Innovation/ Intellect; the Fire of Nature – to the
world of Nature and Engendering; the Imaginal Garden and the Imaginal Fire – to the
intermediate world of the Soul (the former – in the aspect of the soul’s independence of the
natural body, while the latter – in the aspect of its dependence on/ connection with the latter).
According to the principle of tashkīk al-wujūd, the soul’s post-Rising existence is an analogically
graded affair which allows the possibility of the existence of an infinite number of degrees of
intensity, the higher of which are referred to as “Garden” and the lower – as “Fire”.
“The Sensible (read: Imaginal – J.E.) Garden [belongs] to the People of the Right Side and the
Intelligible One – to those drawn near to God (and they are “the highest”). And, likewise, the
Fire is two fires: the Sensible Fire and the Fire of Meaning. The sensible one is [created] for the
unbelievers, and the Fire of Meaning – for the arrogant hypocrites, [that is,] the sensible [fire] is
for the bodies and that of meaning – for the hearts. Both the Sensible Garden and the Sensible
Fire are worlds of measurable quantity, [but] one of them is the form of God’s mercy and
another – the form of His wrath, and Garden is created by essence, but Fire – by accident, and
there is a secret in it”.426
The secret to which Sadrā refers, apparently, consists in Fire’s being a concomitant (lāzim) of
Garden and in wrath’s accompanying mercy – namely, Garden could not be created otherwise
than together with Fire. However, the human soul which begins its existence as part of Fire
(the world of Nature) is not meant to remain in it forever. On the contrary, through a gradual
increase of the intensity of its existence, it is supposed to ascend from Fire to Garden, but it
cannot begin its existence as the soul elsewhere except in Fire (the natural world). Fire is not
an evil. Rather, an evil is a belief that there is nothing in existence except Fire and the refusal
to come out of it.
What pertains to the other world (al-ākhira) proper is the Garden of the People of the Right
Side and the Fire of the People of the Left side, i.e., Garden and Fire as psychic realities. Both
of them are imaginal affairs, but the Imaginal Garden is created by unbounded and non-
delimited imagination (imagination of the soul which is convinced of the rightfulness of its
actions and its worthiness of entering Garden), while the Imaginal Fire is a product of bound
and delimited imagination of the soul which perceives itself as transgressor and, therefore, is
tormented by its conscience.
From another aspect, the entire psychic world (the domain of imagination) can be considered
as Garden, while the natural world in its totality may be treated as Fire, because, as long as
the soul is connected with and dependant on prime matter, it is tormented by the perpetual
change and instability inherent in the world of Nature, which does not permit it to
contemplate itself and its principle (whereas the experiences of Imaginal Garden should be
understood exactly as images in which the soul contemplates itself and its lord). The

426
Sadrā, Asfār, part 9, 322. Cf. Sadrā, ‘arshiyya, 273.

123
following passage in the Asfār (almost verbatim repeated in the Asrār as well) is particularly
suggestive of such interpretation:
“As for the inhabitants of Fire, there is no doubt concerning the self-renewal of their skins and
transformation of their bodies, and their turning from one form into another… because their
natures [manifest themselves as] material bodily faculties… and it was previously established
that the acts and receivings (infi‘ālāt) of material faculties are finite, therefore ceasing and
change are inevitable in them. Then, change of bodies and transformation of matters must
inevitably have its cause in a circular movement produced by celestial bodies, which encompass
the engendering and corrupting bodies – possessors of directions. And the judgment concerning
the inhabitants of Fire is [made] in accordance with what God’s command gives them through
the locomotive faculty, put in the Furthest Body, which compels it to move and [through] the
luminaries (i.e., the fixed stars – J.E.) [that remain] fixed in respect to the travelling of the seven
bright ones (i.e., the planets – J.E.)… and they have influence upon the creation of the
inhabitants of Fire through inflicting upon them different kinds of suffering and sorts of
punishments in accordance with what is required by their previous practices, principles of their
actions, their beliefs and intentions…
As for the inhabitants of Garden, they do not experience this kind of change, transformation,
engendering and corruption, because their configuration is lifted above the natural configuration
and its properties, and their movements and actions are of different kind, wherefore they do not
experience tiredness and exhaustion, nor are their deeds afflicted by weariness, because their
movements and actions are not corporeal, but are like operations of estimative faculty (wahm)
and movements of inner consciousness (damīr) that occur without [entailing] tiredness,
weariness, exhaustion and fatigue, since, in respect to them (the inhabitants of Garden – J.E.),
the heavens and their movements are “rolled up”, due to their standing on the right side and
possessing a station at which time and place are “rolled up”. In their time, the past and the
future of this [our] time are brought together, and their place contains everything that the
heavens and the earth contain in themselves. Nevertheless, the Garden of the Deeds and its
pleasures undoubtedly must be counted among sensible affairs, except that, although they are
sensible affairs, they are not material and natural ones, but their forms are perceptual ones,
whose entified existence is their very sensibility (or: being sensed) (mahsūsiyya), and
everything that is in this Garden has a psychic existence… Despite this, in the world of gardens
take place self-renewals [which manifest themselves as] engendering of forms of Garden,
[emerging] not from material occasions, but from the active directions of the soul and God’s
tasks (shu’ūn)… And thus it has been established that the principle of changes in the horizons
(i.e., in the natural world – J.E.) takes its beginning in the world of souls, and the configuration
of gardens427 is the configuration of souls, and inside them are found psychic engendered
affairs”.428
If we take this stance and interpret Garden as the world of the Soul and Imagination, and Fire
as the world of Nature, the experience of Rising, apparently, must be understood as “the
moment of truth”, at which the inhabitant of the natural world realizes the true character of the
latter, i.e., witnesses it as Fire and, therefore, makes a firm decision to strive for coming out of
it – which coming out, however, does not necessarily mean his physical death. Rather, it
means a change of the state of his consciousness, in particular, his abandoning the habit to
identify himself with his bodily shape and its pleasures and pains. To attain psychic or
imaginal bliss, it is sufficient to stop to identify one’s self with his natural body. Whoso is
able to conceive of himself as of pure soul and imagination, having nothing to do with the
physical body, comes out of Fire and enters Garden. In this sense, entering Garden is a
common experience of all human beings that occurs during sleep – and sometimes at the state
of awakeness – when we see dreams or have dream-like visions. The visions of prophets and
God’s clients, according to Sadrā (though the original idea apparently belongs to Suhrawardī),
427
Apparently, Sadrā means that each human soul possesses its own imaginal Garden and employs here the
plural form to refer to the totality of them.
428
Sadrā, Asfār, part 9, 381–382.

124
also pertain to the world of Imagination, but differ from those of ordinary people by their
greater intensity, due to which they can externalize these visions and make other people
witness them.
“Whoever has understood how God exercises His power in respect to the existence of
imagination, and [in respect to] what is found by the soul in a single instant, such as huge bodily
forms and [gigantic] dimensions, and their attributes and states, will easily affirm the
corporealization of spirits (tajassud al-arwāh) and the assumption of bodily forms by the
intentions, and the immediate bringing to [one’s] presence the objects of appetites [that occur]
through sheer aspiration, intention and appetite, not in the direction of bodily matter. And to this
kind [of imaginal affairs] pertain the appearance of angelic individuals to prophets and God’s
clients, and their (the angels’ – J.E.) descending with prophetic revelation (wahy) and
charismata, in forms of sensible bodies, [which happen] owing to the manifestation of the
authority (sultān) of the other world to their (i.e., the prophets and God’s clients’ – J.E.) hearts
and to their inner faculty. Some of the People of Revealing have been left in doubt, whether
they have seen what they have seen – namely, the forms which appeared and made themselves
present to them – with the eye of sense or with the eye of imagination. The truth [about these
forms] is that they are forms [which are] [firmly] established in existence and that they are
stronger in obtaining (i.e., are perceived more intensively – J.E.) than natural forms, except that
a precondition for obtaining them in the most complete manner is the predomination (or: the
overwhelming influence) (ghalaba) of the active faculty of the soul, i.e., the form-making
(musawwara) [faculty], and preserving them through intense aspiration”.429
The experiences of prophets and God’s clients, thus, take place in the Garden of Imagination,
but, unlike the ordinary people (whose imaginative faculty is weaker due to their engagement
with the bodily affairs), the latter are able to externalize their visions, so that they produce
effects in the natural world (this phenomenon is commonly referred to as the kharq al-‘āda
(‘disruption of the habit’)). Interpreting the gift of sainthood (walāya) in terms of the extreme
intensity of the imaginative faculty and understanding himma (’aspiration’) as the ability to
externalize imagined forms and to make them subsist in the outside is most typical of Ibn al-
‘Arabī and Qūnawī’s apprehension of the nature and properties of sainthood – to the extent
that it is probably not utterly wrong to describe them as ahl al-khayāl (‘people of
imagination’) par excellence. As numerous accounts, found in their writings, show, both Ibn
al-‘Arabī and Qūnawī had many intense visionary experiences. Sadrā seems to fully take their
stance in his treatment of high intensity of imagination as the key property of sainthood.
Now, if the Garden in which the experiences of prophets and God’s clients take place – and to
which they invite the common folk – is the Garden of Imagination or the Garden of Soul,
who, then, inhabits the Garden of Intellect? Sadrā’s answer, apparently, is that the difference
between intelligible and imaginal realms is a relative (nisbī) and/ or a mental (dhihnī) affair:
imagination can and must be treated as weak intellection. Hence, the prophets, God’s clients
and true knowers (or “divine sages”), whose perceptual faculty has been developed to its
perfection, reside simultaneously in both gardens – essentially in the Intelligible/ Noetic
Garden and concomitantly – in the Imaginal one, because their essences, due to their
simplicity, have become all things.

3.5.4. The Ramparts

A few words must be said about Sadrā’s treatment of the Ramparts (or: Heights) (A‘rāf). The
issue of A‘rāf is discussed in verses 46 – 53 of the seventh surah (called by the same name).
Sadrā seems to have drawn his inspiration particularly from the verse 7:46: “Upon the
Ramparts, there are people who know everyone by his marks”.430 Traditionally the
429
Sadrā, Asrār, 231–232.
430
Qur’an, 119.

125
commentators of the Qur’an and the Mutakallimūn had identified the A‘rāf with a wall
erected between Garden and Fire, mentioned in the verse 57:13 (“A wall with a door [in it] is
put up between them. In its inner side is mercy, in the outer side – wrath”431). The men on the
Ramparts were, in turn, identified as the people, the weight of whose good and bad deeds is in
perfect balance, wherefore, it was said, they could not enter either Garden or Fire, but
remained in the isthmus between them, partially experiencing both states.
Sadrā dismisses the interpretation of the Mutakallimūn as lacking due insight and, instead,
proposes his own:
“…the inhabitants of Ramparts are the perfect in knowledge and gnosis, those who recognize
each group of people by their [specific] marks and, by the light of their insight, see the
inhabitants of Garden and the inhabitants of Fire, and their states in the other world… However,
they (the inhabitants of Ramparts – J.E.) are counted as belonging to this [natural] world in
respect to their bodies… and, thus, through their bodies they are earthly beings, but through heir
hearts – heavenly ones. Their apparitions (or: silhouettes) (ashbāh) belong to the mat (farsh) [of
Nature]; their spirits pertain to the Throne (or: Canopy) (‘arsh). They have not yet died by
natural death so that they might enter Garden in body, as they have entered it in spirit… When
they come out of the [natural] world, their hope becomes its very fulfilment and their
potentiality – the very actuality and obtaining, but before this their state is an intermediate
perfection (kamāl barzakhī) between the states of the inhabitants of Garden and the inhabitants
of Fire, because their hearts partake in the pleasures of Garden, such as faith and [true]
knowledge (ma‘rifa), but their bodies are tormented by the torments and pains of this [bodily]
world”.432
The symbolism of the passage from the ‘arshiyya, to me, is transparent: Sadrā interprets the
Ramparts (A‘rāf) as the situation of the people (sages and mystics) whose souls have
experienced the Greater Rising before their natural death and (final) separation from the
material body. By their souls, they belong to the other (imaginal) world; by their (natural)
bodies, they still reside in this (physical and sensible) one.433 (This is most likely that Sadrā
counts himself as one of this group.) Such interpretation of “the Ramparts” makes one even
more confident that, in the most esoteric sense, Sadrā regards the natural world as the true
Fire, while he sees the other world – the world of Imagination – in its entirety as Garden.
“Knowing everyone by his mark”, in all likelihood, must be understood as the ability to
recognize those who, like themselves, after dying by voluntary death before dying by natural
one, have “risen” from the “graves” of matter by their explicit and implicit attitudes towards
this-worldly and other-worldly affairs.

* * *
As we have seen, traditional Islamic eschatological concepts are interpreted by Sadrā as states
and phenomena of perceptual existence (wujūd idrākī). The central concept of Rising
(qiyāma), according to Sadrā, refers to the moment of truth, which brings intense awareness

431
Qur’an, 471.
432
Sadrā, ‘arshiyya, 278.
433
The twenty-second chapter (“the Bezel of the Wisdom of Intimacy in the Word of Elias”) of Ibn al-‘Arabī’s
Fusūs is likely to have been Sadrā’s direct source of inspiration. Ibn al-‘Arabī writes there: “The mystics here
appear as if they [still] were in the form of this world, due to what pertains to them of its properties. But [in
actual fact] God, the Most High, has [already] changed them, in their insides, into the other-worldly
configuration (al-nash’a al-ukhrawiyya)… and, by their [true inner] form, they are not known to anyone
except the one to whom God reveils them through his insight and he understands. And there is no knower of
God, [knowing Him} through His self-disclosure, who has not been changed into the other-worldly
configuration and has not been “gathered” in the world and “risen” in his grave, and he sees what you do not
see and witnesses what you do not witness.” (Ibn al-‘Arabī, Fusūs, part 1, 186. Cf. C. Dagli’s translation in:
Muhyi al-Dīn Ibn al-‘Arabī, The Ringstones of Wisdom, translated by Caner K. Dagli, Chicago: Kazi
Publications 2004, 213).

126
of the perpetual change and instability of the world of Nature and erases the borderline
between sense and imagination, replacing the illusion of stability and permanence of the
surrounding world with the intuition of the flow of existence (sarayān al-wujūd).
Furthermore, Sadrā believes this flow to be a unidirectional motion of the substance towards
higher and higher degrees of intensity, wherefore there is no return possible from a higher
level of substantial evolution to a lower one. The inhabitants of the Garden of Imagination
never come back to the earth of natural existence. Therefore, metempsychosis (unless we
interpret it as the change of the imaginal body of the soul in keeping with the change of the
soul’s dominant virtue or vice) is impossible.
As for the spiritual and corporeal returns, Sadrā interprets them as intellectual/ noetic (‘aqlī)
and imaginal resurrections respectively. Unlike Ibn Sīnā, who apparently believed
imagination to be a hindrance to the spiritual return (the soul’s coming in touch or unification
with the Active Intellect), Sadrā holds that spiritual (read: intellectual/ noetic) resurrection
cannot occur otherwise than through corporeal (read: psychic/ imaginal) one, because sense
(hiss/ ihsās), imagination (khayāl/ takhayyul) and intellection (‘aql/ ta‘aqqul), to him,
represent three degrees of the ever-increasing intensity of perception (perceptual existence).
According with his principle of the lower possibility (al-imkān al-akhass), in the ascending
movement, the lower possibility must be actualized first before the actualization of a higher
one can occur.
Depending on the standpoint taken, different affairs can be considered as “the Garden” (al-
janna) and “the Fire” (al-nār) (i.e., Paradise and Hell). The natural existence, due to its
perpetually experienced engendering and corruption, is most worthy of the name of Fire,
though there can be manifestations of Garden in it (i.e., at times particular loci of the natural
world can be perceived as belonging to Garden, if they are seen with the eye of imagination).
Intellectual existence, in turn, must be considered as Garden in the true sense of the word
(because, to Sadrā, the real bliss consists only in witnessing intellectual/ intelligible – not
psychic/ imaginal affairs). As for the world of Soul, it contains in itself both the Imaginal
Garden and the Imaginal Fire. However, Sadrā apparently believes that in its essence it is
Garden, which is sometimes mistakenly perceived as Fire due to the painful psychic
experiences (which, nevertheless, last only as long as the soul remains attached to its natural
body by keeping in itself bodily desires, which cannot be satisfied after its separation from the
natural body).
The souls which during their natural lifetime experience – at least partial – spiritual Rising
and realize the true character of this and other worlds, but, for the time being, remain
connected with their natural bodies, to Sadrā, can be best described as “the men of the
Ramparts” (rijāl al-a‘rāf) – those who know the inhabitants of both worlds by their marks.
In view of the aforementioned peculiarities, Sadrā’s eschatological doctrine can be defined as
a teaching on the transformations of perceptual existence, in which particular attention is paid
to the analysis of the states and properties of imagination.

127
CONCLUSION

As it was demonstrated in the first chapter, the Sufis use terms wujūd and mawjūd
predominantly in the sense ‘finding’ and ‘found’ respectively. The finding at issue in Sufism
is a sort of metaphysical intuition, similar to that of kashf (‘unveiling’). The object of this
finding – the found (mawjūd) – is, ultimately, none but the Real (al-haqq). This is univocally
stated by the famous Sufi definition of wujūd as “finding the Real in ecstasy” (wijdān al-haqq
fī ’l-wajd).434 Such interpretation of wujūd and mawjūd seems to be supported (and perhaps
inspired) by the Qur’anic usage of the verb wajada (‘to find’) (in particular in the verse
24:39435).
In turn, the ninth century Arab translators of Aristotle’s works used the terms wujūd and
mawjūd to render into Arabic Greek words το ειναι (‘being/ existence [in a certain way]’) and
το ον (‘the being/ existent [which exists in a certain manner]’).436 Muslim Peripatetics – in
particular Ibn Sīnā – in fact, did not attribute to words wujūd and mawjūd the meaning of
‘existence’ and ‘existent’ (after all, these two Latin terms themselves, as Gilson has shown437,
only began to be employed in their modern sense in the seventeenth century), but read them,
in conformity with the sense-setting rules of the Arabic language, exactly as ‘finding’ and
‘found’. The difference is that, for Ibn Sīnā and his followers, wujūd and mawjūd mean
‘finding’ and ‘found’ either by sense perception or by logical reasoning.438 What is found by
sense perception, is called mawjūd tabī‘ī (‘natural existent’) and is the subject of natural
sciences (tabī‘īyyāt). What is found by logical reasoning, is called mawjūd ta‘līmī (‘abstract
existent’) or mawjūd dhihnī (‘mental existent’) and is the subject of mathematical sciences
(riyādiyyāt). Both kinds of “found things” (=existents) (mawjūdāt) are, however, subject to a
number of common laws. The science which deals with these common laws of existence and
existent – “the states of the found (=existent), in so far as it is considered [only] as found
(=existent) – in ancient and mediaeval philosophical tradition was known as “metaphysics”
(Arabic mā warā’ (or: mā ba‘d) al-tabī‘a) or “the first philosophy” (al-falsafa al-ūlā) and in
modern times (starting from the eighteenth century) came to be known as “ontology”
(‘science of being/ existence’).
Sadrā’s understanding of the subject of the first philosophy is in no way different from that of
Ibn Sīnā: in many works he repeats the standard Peripatetic definition of this subject as “the
unbounded found (existent) (mawjūd mutlaq)439 – or, more precisely, as “the states of the
found (existent), in so far as it is [considered as] found (existent) and the primary divisions of
the unbounded found (existent), without [their] becoming a particular kind of the found
(existent), pertaining to natural or mental existents (tabī‘īyyāt aw ta‘līmiyyāt)”.440

434
Ibn al-‘Arabī, Istilāhāt, 9 and Ibn al-‘Arabī, Futūhāt, part 2, 538.
435
The mystical implications of the verse are discussed by Ibn al-‘Arabī in detail in the 178th chapter of the
Futūhāt (see: Ibn al-‘Arabī, Futūhāt, part 2, 338–339; cf. M. Gloton’s French translation in: Ibn al-‘Arabī,
Muhyi al-Dīn, Traité de l’Amour, traduit par Maurice Gloton, Paris: Albin Michel 1986, 138–140).
436
Étienne Gilson, L’Être et l’essence, Paris: Vrin 1948, 38.
437
Gilson, L’Être, 41–43.
438
Abū Barakat al-Baghdādī (about 470/1077-after 560/1164), however, believes mawjūd to mean thing’s being
„in such a state that it could be perceived (kawnahu bi haythi yudrak)” (Abū Barakat al-Baghdādī, Kitāb al-
Mu‘tabar, Haydarābād 1358 L. H., part 3, 20, quoted from: Izutsu, “The Fundamental Structure”, 30).
439
Sadrā, Asfār, part 1, 24.
440
Sadrā, “al-Masā’il al-qudsiyya” in Sadr al-Dīn al-Shīrāzī, Se risāle-i falsafī (Mutashābihāt al-Qur’ān, al-
Masā’īl al-qudsiyya wa Ajūbāt al-masā’īl), 2nd edition, ed. S.J.Āshtiyānī, Qum: Markaz-i intishārāt-i daftar-i
tablīghāt-i islāmī hawze-i ‘ilmī-i Qum 1378 S.H., 191.

128
God, or the Truly Existent, according to Peripatetic tenets, cannot be found by sense perception.
Hence, He is found by means of logical reasoning (induction) and is, therefore, conceived of
as a logical necessity (the Necessarily Found (Existent) (wājib al-wujūd)) and, by virtue of
this, is a mental existent (mawjūd dhihnī/ ta‘līmī) like the higher genera (ajnās ‘āliyya).
In turn, (theoretical) Sufism, as represented by Ibn al-‘Arabī school, bases its teachings on the
presumption of perpetual experiencing of the Real through its subsequent and never repeating
self-disclosures, perceived by mystical/ metaphysical intuition. (At least) in case of
accomplished mystics, sense perception is believed to become an integral part and aspect of
this intuition (wherefore it is said that they see God in this world with their bodily eyes).
In order to understand the role of the concept of wujūd in Sufi teachings, the opposition
wahdat al-wujūd – kathrat al-‘ilm (or kathrat al-ithbāt) (‘oneness/ unity of finding/ existence’
– ‘manyness/ plurality of knowledge’ (or ‘manyness/ plurality of fixity’) seems to be of
particular importance. This opposition pertains to the level of the Real’s differentiated
oneness/ unity (wāhidiyya or wahdāniyya) and must be understood to the effect that the Real
finds itself as one single entity, but knows itself by/ through (infinite) different names and
attributes (e.g., as the Knowing, the Willing, the Merciful etc.) (The same, of course, is the
case with each of us – each of us finds (=perceives) himself as one entity, while he knows this
one entity to possess (countless) different characteristics.) These different facets of one being,
though, do not exist as separate entities in the outside world. They do exist (‘are fixed’) as
separate things/ entities only in the Real’s (or our) consciousness. This fixity (thubūt) in one’s
consciousness is referred to as “knowledge” (‘ilm). Now, its plurality/ manyness is based on
malzūm – lāzim relationship, i.e., concomitance: each characteristic which the Real knows
itself to possess entails another one (e.g., its life entails knowledge, knowledge – will, etc.).
All entities, fixed in the Real’s consciousness (“mind”), thus, are nothing but its own infinite
characteristics (which are concomitants of its more general characteristics and the product of
the latters’ “marriages” (nikāhāt)). But the Real finds all them (i.e., all us) by one undivided
and non-differentiated finding.
What, if any, parallels can be drawn between wahdat al-wujūd wa kathrat al-‘ilm, professed
by the Sufis of Ibn al-‘Arabī school, and asālat al-wujūd bi ’l-nisba ’l-māhiya (‘principality
of existence/ finding in relation to whatness/ quiddity’)? As I attempted to show above,
principality of finding/ existence in relation to quiddity, as posed by Sadrā, is a speculative
issue, which, perhaps, is based on his misunderstanding of the principle of asālat al-māhiya
(‘principality of whatness/ quiddity’). What Suhrawardī had in mind by posing the latter
principle was that certain essence (which he treated as a ray or direction of light) possessed
certain essential states and properties, regardless of its actualization in the sensible world or
lack thereof (i.e., its being or not being found by sense). Sadrā, who followed this – Platonic
by nature – teaching in his youth, at some point concluded it to be false and, instead, put
forward the theory of the asālat al-wujūd. According to it, all attributes and properties of a
thing were the attributes and properties of its existence (‘being found’); the whatness/
quiddity was nothing but a shadow of existence, having no reality at all. However, if we agree
with Sadrā that whatnesses/ quiddities have no reality whatsoever441 (or, at best, have it “by
following” (bi ’l-tab‘iyya), i.e., as mind’s attempt to grasp different aspects of (external)
wujūd by imitating them), it remains unclear what causes the evident differentiation of wujūd.
Is self-differentiation wujūd’s inherent property? As the doctrine of tashkīk al-wujūd – the
pivotal doctrine of his philosophy – shows, Sadrā seems to have been inclined to think so.

441
The Sufis of Ibn al-‘Arabī school hold that, while the fixed entity (‘ayn thābita), undoubtedly, has never felt
the fragrance of outer existence/ is never found in the outside, through its properties, it establishes a certain
mode or aspect, in which the Unbounded Finding/ Existence finds/ manifests itself.

129
Further, if we accept the postulate of wujūd’s self-differentiation, it still remains unclear, what
makes this self-differentiation to occur according to a certain pattern – in other words, who or
what is responsible for the structure of wujūd? Is it not the Real’s knowledge of itself as the
Sufis hold? Sadrā gives no definite answer to this question.
The main impulse that made Sadrā to dismiss asālat al-māhiya and to claim principality for
existence/ finding, apparently, came from the teachings of Ibn al-‘Arabī (in particular, from
certain passages in the Fusūs442 ). That said, Ibn al-‘Arabī uses the terms wujūd (‘finding/
existence’) and ‘ilm (‘knowledge’) / thubūt (‘fixity’) to refer to two different kinds of the
Real’s awareness of itself – the non-differentiated (wujūd) and the differentiated (‘ilm/ thubūt)
ones. Furthermore, wujūd and ‘ilm/ thubūt are interdependent and act as each other’s mirrors:
namely, fixed entities mirror the unbounded and non-delimited wujūd and the unbounded
wujūd, in turn, acts as the mirror of these entities – or, to put it otherwise, the fixed entities
provide loci for the manifestation of wujūd (“self-disclosure of the Real”), while unbounded
wujūd (=the Real) provides loci for the manifestation of the entities, fixed/ established in the
Real’s knowledge. Thus, wujūd and ‘ilm (and, hence, the “known things” (ma‘lūmāt) or
“fixed entities” (a‘yān thābita)) are interdependent and in need of each other. Taking a certain
standpoint, it is possible to talk about the principality of existence/ finding and derivatedness
and shadowiness of knowledge (and the known things). Taking the opposite standpoint,
though, one can claim principality for knowledge (and the entities fixed in it) and assert the
derivatedness of wujūd. Therefore, Ibn al-‘Arabī describes the relationship between wujūd
and ‘ilm (and ma‘lūmāt) as interdependence. Principality of either existence/ finding or
knowledge (and the known entities) is, to him, a relative affair.
However, as I have attempted to demonstrate, the pivotal principle of Sadrā’s philosophy
appears to be not the principality of existence/ finding, but the analogical gradation of the
latter in terms of intensity and weakness (tashkīk al-wujūd bi ’l-shidda wa ’l-da‘f). This
pivotal principle (upon which most, if not all, of his other theories rest) results, as a logical
consequence, from Plato’s theory of ideas, according to which, the intelligible images or
archetypes of things are much more real (and, therefore, it can be said, enjoy much stronger
existence, or are found more intensively) than their sensible likenesses and material instances.
The pivotal position of this principle in Sadrā’s thought allows me to qualify him as a
(predominantly) Platonic philosopher (who was particularly influenced by Plotinus and
Suhrawardī).
Considering Sadrā’s teachings on two principal strata of wujūd – the world of innovation/
Command and that of Nature – against other relevant Neoplatonic doctrines (in particular,
those of Plotinus, Kirmānī and Mīr Dāmād), I, however, come to the conclusion that, partly
due to the incorporation of many elements of Aristotelianism, Sadrā’s thought (like that of
Suhrawardī) represents a significantly reduced form of Platonism. Like Suhrawardī, Sadrā
reduces the difference between the Real or Necessarily Existent (The Light of Lights, in
Shaykh al-Ishrāq’s terminology) and other existents (lights) to difference in intensity
(strength) and weakness of existence (which reduction, in potentia at least, allows these other
existents (lights) to become (or to strive to become) the Light of the Lights). This reduction of
difference between the Real or the Necessarily Existent and the creation or possible existents
to the difference of intensity only made Sadrā to dismiss Mīr Dāmād’s teaching on meta-
temporal origination, as well as to replace the Neoplatonic teaching on Nature with that of
Aristotle and Ibn Sīnā.

442
E.g., the above quoted statement from the forth chapter: “The fixed entities (in Sadrā’s view, identical to
whatnesses/ quiddities – J.E.) have never felt the (slightest) scent of the found/ existent” (Ibn al-‘Arabī,
Fusūs, part 1, 76).

130
As it was explained earlier, the principle of the analogical gradation in terms of intensity and
weakness (tashkīk bi ’l-shidda wa ’l-da‘f) follows as a logical consequence from Plato’s
theory of ideas. In Islamic philosophy, this principle was introduced by Suhrawardī, who
considered it being interrelated with the principality of whatness/ quiddity (asālat al-māhiya).
Sadrā’s own explanation of the principle of the analogical gradation of existence/ finding, as
given in the Asfār443, allows me to qualify it as tashkīk wujūd al-māhiya (‘the analogical
gradation of the existence/ finding of the whatness/ quiddity’) and comes down to grading
the latter’s existence in intelligible, imaginal and physical grades. The whatness/ quiddity of,
say, a fly, remains the same regardless whether it enjoys intellectual, imaginal or physical
existence. This is not the case that what exists in the natural world as a fly, becomes a bird in
the imaginal world and a dragon in the intellectual one. Hence, the increase and decrease of
the intensity of the existence of a certain whatness/ quiddity must be understood as
intellectualization (ta‘aqqul) and corporealization (tajassum) of this existence, i.e., as the
change of the latter’s modality (while the quiddity remains the same). The substantial motion,
thus, comes down to the increase of the intensity of the thing’s (i.e., the essence’s) existence.
That is to say, an affair (e.g., the human soul), which begins to exist as an entirely corporeal
thing, gradually comes to experience, first, imaginalization (takhayyul) and, subsequently,
intellectualization. This substantial motion, or increase in the intensity of existence, can also
be treated as the tenuity’s (raqīqa) gradual return to its reality (haqīqa) (or, as the Sufis do it,
reduced to the gradual perfection and refinement of the preparedness (isti‘dād) of the
receptacle (qābil) or locus of manifestation (mazhar)). Although Ibn al-‘Arabī’s teaching on
the “new creation” (as numerous references to the latter, found in Sadrā’s works, seem to
suggest) is likely to have been the principal source of Sadrā’s inspiration for proposing the
theory of substantial motion, he appears to have missed the focal point of Ibn al-‘Arabī’s
doctrine. Ibn al-‘Arabī defines the “new creation (or: new measuring out)” (khalq jadīd) as
“the renewal of the affair with every breath” (tajdīd al-amr ma‘a ’l-anfās)444 or “the change of
the world with every breath [occurring] in one entity”.445 This renewal or change, as Kāshānī
indicates, results from the difference of the relations of wujūd in respect to each possible thing
in every instant446 and is based on the mystical intuition, which perceives the world
(=cosmos) (‘ālam) as the Real’s imagination (khayāl). Though Ibn al-‘Arabī sometimes refers
to the process of new creation (as perceived by a particular mystic) as taraqqī (‘advancing,
developping’)447, this advancing is not to be interpreted as advancing towards and reaching
certain final and ultimate perfection, e.g., child’s becoming adult or a minor clerk’s becoming
the director of a company. Rather, this is an imaginal advancing – the kind of advancing
which we experience in dreams (and, therefore, it is called by Ibn al-‘Arabī taraqqī ba‘d al-
mawt (‘advancing after the death’)448), not unsimilar to the Real’s advancing from task to
task.449
Sadrā’s “substantial motion”, in turn, is a finite unidirectional evolutionary affair. Upon
reaching the desired perfection (be it physical or psychic – as we know, according to Sadrā,
there is no haraka jawhariyya in the world of intellect, because intellect is a fully perfected
soul), it ceases. Therefore, substantial motion (also referred to by Sadrā as the increase of the

443
Sadrā, Asfār, part 1, 440–445.
444
Ibn al-‘Arabī, Fusūs, part 1, 125.
445
Ibn al-‘Arabī, Fusūs, part 1, 125.
446
See: Kāshānī, Istilāhāt, 133.
447
E.g., Ibn al-‘Arabī, Fusūs, part 1, 124.
448
Ibn al-‘Arabī, Fusūs, part 1, 124.
449
According to the Qur’ān, “every day He (i.e., God – J.E.) is upon a [different] task” (55:29) (the English
translation by W.C.Chittick (Chittick, Knowledge, 98; cf. Qur’ān, 462)).

131
intensity (“strengthening”) of the thing’s existence (tashdīd al-wujūd)) must be understood as
the instance’s gradual return to its archetype (lord of species). The expressions haraka
jawhariyya, tashdīd al-wujūd and tajawhur (‘substantialization’), thus, are all used by Sadrā
to describe the process of the thing’s gradual return to its root and principle (asl). Both
concepts – “new creation” and “substantial motion” – are employed by their authors to
describe certain perfectionary journeys. However, in each case, this journey appears to be of
an entirely different character. While Ibn al-‘Arabī has in mind an infinite journey in the
realm of (the cosmic) imagination, Sadrā is concerned with the finite journey of a physical
and psychic instance to its intelligible archetype.
Sadrā’s eschatology, by and large, must be qualified as Platonic, because he interprets the
soul’s gathering (hashr) as its return to its respective (human or other) lord of species
(intelligible archetype). This return, as it was stated above, is understood by him as gradual
intensification of the soul’s existence (which presupposes tajarrud (‘separation’,
‘disengagement’, i.e., the soul’s getting free of (corporeal and psychic) matter and quitting
it)).450 Since the human soul (and, probably, the soul of the higher animals) (unlike the souls
of plants and lower animals) is endowed with imaginal faculty (which, along with memory, is
responsible for creating its particular individuality), it, however, usually cannot return to its
intelligible archetype (lord of the human species, identified by Sadrā with the Active Intellect)
immediately after its leaving the physical body, but has to linger in the world of imagination
(‘ālam al-khayāl) for a certain period. Only the souls of the divine sages (al-hukamā’ al-
muta’allihīn) during their residence in the physical body reach such a degree of intensity of
existence which is sufficient for the immediate entering the world of intellect (thus becoming
themselves intellects) and unifying with the lord of the human species. The overwhelming
majority of the human souls, though, only reach such degree of the intensity of existence
which allows them to travel from the natural world to the domain of imagination. Hence, the
spiritual (read: intellectual) return (ma‘ād rūhānī (iqrā: ‘aqlānī)) is, apparently, the share of
the elite (of the elite) of mankind, while most human beings, for the time being, seem to be
destined to experience only corporeal (read: imaginal) return (ma‘ād jusmānī (iqrā: khayālī)).
The possibility of the further intensifying of their existence in the hereafter (that would allow
these – as yet intellectually unripe – souls to enter the world of intellect and unite with the
lord (archetype) of human species) is not ruled out by Sadrā – rather, it is implicitly indicated,
but never affirmed explicitly.
The discussion of the issues related to the corporeal (i.e., imaginal) return and the soul’s
abiding in the world of imagination (the imaginal garden and fire; the states occurring at the
time of and accompanying Rising), as it was noticed earlier by James Morris451, represents a
compilation of quotations from Ibn al-‘Arabī’s Futūhāt (in particular, from the chapter 64).
Acknowledging his debt to Ibn al-‘Arabī in the issue of corporeal (imaginal) return, Sadrā,
however, undoubtedly believes this kind of return to be inferior to the spiritual (intellectual)
one (which is allotted only to the divine philosophers (the “truly perfect”, in Sadrā’s view)).
0As it is well known, the teachings of Ibn al-‘Arabī and his school deal predominantly with
imagination and the imaginal world. In terms of Sadrā’s gradation of wujūd, this means they
are concerned with the medium intensity existence. Hence, though the Sufi teachings may be
fully valid in respect to this range of the intensity of the unbounded existence, the highest and
most intense level of wujūd – that of intellect – is, apparently, inaccessible to them. The states
of this higher level of existence, as a matter of fact, can only be correctly described by those

450
See Chittick’s discussion on tajarrud in William C. Chittick, The Heart of Islamic Philosophy, Oxford:
Oneworld 2001, 76 079 and Chittick, “Teleology”, 225.
451
See, e.g.: Morris, Wisdom, 184, note 176.

132
whose own individual existence has reached this highest level of intensity – namely, by the
divine sages – the masters of the Transcendent (in fact, Ishrāqī) Philosophy.452
Thus, the analysis of the eschatological part of Sadrā’s philosophy makes me qualify this
philosophy as a late mediaeval Islamic variety of Platonism, which incorporates in itself, on
inferior rights, certain minor elements of the teaching of Ibn al-‘Arabī (while the pivotal
principles of Sadrā and Ibn al-‘Arabī’s thought – those of tashkīk al-wujūd (‘analogical
gradation of existence/ finding’) and tajallī al-haqq (‘self-disclosure of the Real’) respectively
– for the above given reasons, appear to be incompatible).
To the Sufis, as it was stated above, wujūd refers to a certain ecstatic experience (“finding the
Real in ecstasy”, or, in other words, experiencing the oneness/ unity of the Absolute Reality,
underlying the multiplicity of phenomena and manifested through it). Sadrā, however,
believes the highest level of mystical experience (haqq al-yaqīn (‘the true certainty’)) to
consist in “[the mystic’s] finding the divine and engendered realities (al-haqā’īq al-ilāhiyya
wa ’l-kawniyya) and their concomitants in his (own) essence through tasting and finding”453 –
or, in other words, in entering the World of Innovation (the realm of intelligible archetypes or
Platonic ideas) and unification with the lord of human species (though he emphasizes that
these intelligible realities or ideas (lords of the species) of the things are nothing but rays and
radiances (aspects and segments of radiance) of the Reality of Existence.)
Upon a scrupulous analysis, one cannot fail to notice that Sadrā’s teaching on the horizontal
and vertical division of existence/ finding (i.e., on its levels and aspects) represents but a
slightly modified version of Suhrawardī’s teaching on the analogical gradation of light
(tashkīk al-nūr). Sufi teaching on wujūd, based on a very different kind of ecstatic experience,
was only partially accepted (and understood) by Sadrā. All in all considered, he must be
qualified as a thinker of the Neoplatonic (more precisely, Ishrāqī) trend. He attempted to
integrate his pivotal principle – that of tashkīk al-wujūd (which he borrowed from
Suhrawardī) with certain Sufi teachings, but lacked proper training in (both practical and
theoretical) Sufism. The integration was therefore only achieved at the level of logical
speculation – not that of metaphysical intuition. Despite his sympathy to the teachings of Ibn
al-‘Arabī and his school, he remained an outsider in respect to the Sufi tradition, who
appropriated certain minor parts of the Akbarian doctrine for his own Ishrāqī agenda.

452
The evidence of the achievement of this highest level of intensity – that of intellect – according to Suhrawardī
and Sadrā, is the experience of tajarrud (the soul’s separation from the physical body). Thus, in the Īqāz al-
nā’īmīn Sadrā says: “The man is not counted among the divine sages (al-muta’allihīn) until he does not
acquire a habitude of taking off [and putting on] his body, so that the body, in relation to him, becomes like a
shirt, which he takes off at times and puts on at other times” (Sadr al-Dīn al-Shīrāzī, Īqāz al-nā’īmīn, ed.
M.Mu’ayyadī, Tehrān: Cultural Studies and Research Institute 1982, 57. Apparently, the passage paraphrases
paragraph 274 in J. Walbridge and H. Ziai’s edition of Suhrawardī’s Hikmat al-ishrāq (Suhrawardī, The
Philosophy of Illumination, eds. Walbridge, John, and Ziai, Hossein, Provo: Brigham Young University Press
1999, 160–161).
453
Sadrā, Īqāz, 58.

133
MULLĀ SADRĀ WUJŪD ÕPETUS: MÜSTITSISMI
JA FILOSOOFIA SÜNTEES

Kokkuvõte

Araabia sõna wujūd tähendab kirjanduslikult ‘leidmist’ (eeldab ‘leidja’ (wājid) ja ‘leitava’
(mawjūd) kohalolekut). Vaadates seda filosoofilise terminina, tähendab wujūd ‘olemist/
eksisteerimist’. Esimene peripateetiline filosoofia või metafüüsika tegeles põhiliselt mawjūd-
ga (‘eksisteeriv’) määral, mil seda peetakse mawjūd-ks (‘eksisteeriv’), selle reaalsuse, olekute
ja omadustega. 17. sajandi Iraani filosoof Sadr al-Dīn al-Shīrāzī, kes on laiemalt tuntud Mullā
Sadrā nime all (979-80/1571-2 – 1050/1640), tuli aga välja teesiga, et see, mis eksisteerib
primaarselt ja tegelikult, on wujūd (‘eksistents’). See, mis eksisteerib eraldi eksistentsist,
eksisteerib läbi viimase. Seetõttu peab Sadrā arvates filosoofia tegelema eelkõige wujūd-ga,
mitte mawjūd-ga.
Teisest küljest, vaadeldes seda müstilises mõttes, viitab termin wujūd kindlale intuitsioonile –
tõelise “leidmisele” (s.t absoluutne/piiritlemata tõelisus) nähtuse loori taga. Sõltuvalt müs-
tilise valmisolekust võib seda intuitsiooni jagada erinevatesse astmetesse. Mis veelgi tähtsam,
leidmise harjumust – s.t müstilist intuitsiooni – on võimalik välja töötada erinevate tehnikate
abil. Seega on sufi müstikule õpetus wujūd-st õpetus müstilisest intuitsioonist ja selle järk-
järgulisest arengust.
Kas on võimalik sünteesida wujūd filosoofilist ja müstilist mõistmist? Kui jah, siis kas on
võimalik säilitada tasakaal müstilise ja filosoofilise lähenemise vahel või on paratamatult
ühele määratud saada domineerivaks sellises sünteesis? Sadrā nähtavasti uskus, et tema
“kõrgem tarkus” (al-hikma al-muta‘āliyya) esindab sellist harmoonilist sünteesi. Käesolevas
väitekirjas püüan välja selgitada, mil määral on selline väide õigustatud.
Sissejuhatuses on esitatud wujūd probleem, nagu Sadrā seda mõistis, koos sadroloogia üldise
ajaloo lühikese ülevaatega.
Esimene peatükk “Wujūd ja Wujūd reaalsus” koosneb kahest alapeatükist, kus on vastavalt
vaadeldud wujūd müstilist (välja töötanud Ibn ‘Arabī ja edasi arendanud Qūnawī, Farghānī jt)
ning filosoofilist (välja töötanud Ibn Sīnā ja Suhrawardī ning muutnud Sadrā) doktriini.
Esimeses alapeatükis on üksikasjalikult uuritud sufi wujūd definitsiooni ning leidmise/
eksistentsi samasuse (wahdat al-wujūd) ja selle entifikatsiooni (ta‘ayyun) õpetust. Teises
alapeatükis on esitatud Sadrā eksistentsi ülemvõimu teooriate analüüs ja selle analoogne
gradatsioon. Sadrā vaateid põhjuslikkusele ja burhān al-siddīqīn teooriale on arutatud ka
teemadena, mis on otseselt seotud wujūd analoogse gradatsiooniga.
Teises peatükis “Wujūd: Sadrā kosmoloogia silmapiirid” (koosneb neljast alapeatükist)
vaadeldakse Sadrā eksistentsi põhilisi reaalsuse või “silmapiiri” astmeid, s.t uuritakse inno-
vatsiooni (ibdā’), olemuse (tabī‘a) ja hinge (nafs) maailmu ning kirjeldatakse gradatsiooni
eksistentsi implikatsioone. Võrdlen Sadrā poolt väljapakutud analoogselt gradueeritud
eksistentsi struktuuri Ibn Sīnā, Suhrawardī, Hamīd al-Dīn al-Kirmānī ja Ibn ‘Arabī poolt
väljapakutud eksistentsi struktuuridega, võttes arvesse Sadrā innovatsiooni/intellekti, olemuse
ja hinge tõlgendust tähtsate peripateetiliste, neoplatonistlike, ismailiitide, valgustus- ja sufi
õpetuste taustal. Teises alapeatükis on üksikasjalikult arutatud Sadrā innovatsioonimaailma
õpetust, võrreldes seda Mīr Dāmād meta-ajalise tekke teooriaga. Neljandas alapeatükis
uuritakse Sadrā olemusliku liikumise teooriat (al-haraka al-jawhariyya), võrreldes seda Ibn
‘Arabī uue loomise õpetusega (al-khalq al-jadīd).

134
Kolmas peatükk “Wujūd muundumised: Sadrā eshatoloogia” koosneb viiest alapeatükist ja
vaatleb eksistentsi muundumist. Selles arutatakse hinge eksisteerimist enne füüsilist keha,
koos sellega ja peale füüsilist keha. Arvan, et Sadrā eshatoloogiline doktriin on suuresti
sufismile omane (Ibn ‘Arabī) inimese sisemise (tahtlik) muundumise õpetus, mida tuntakse ka
“eksistentsi muutuse/asendamise” (tabdīl al-wujūd) taastõlgendusena. Esimene alapeatükk
vaatleb ma‘ād (‘tagasitulek’) universaalse printsiibina. Seejärel arutatakse hingede eelnemist
kehadele ja taassünni võimatust. Viimased kaks alapeatükki vaatlevad hingelist tagasitulekut
ja kehalist taassündi.
Lõppsõnas kinnitan, et Sadrā peab olema Platoni koolkonna kompetentne mõtleja (täpsemalt
Plotinuse ja Suhrawardī järglane), kes püüdis integreerida oma pöördelist printsiipi –
eksistentsi analoogset gradatsiooni (tashkīk al-wujūd) (mille ta laenas Suhrawardī-lt) teatud
kindlate sufistlike õpetustega, eriti tegelikkuse eneseavalduse, entifikatsiooni ja maailma uue
loomisega igal hetkel. Sadrā saavutas integratsiooni teoreetilise spekulatsiooni tasandil,
püüdmata tungida metafüüsilise institutsiooni südamesse, mis rõhutab teoreetilise Sufi
müstitsismi õpetusi, nagu neid esindab Ibn ‘Arabī koolkond (tegelikkuse järk-järguline
enesepaljastus). Vaatamata sellele, et talle olid Ibn ‘Arabī ja tema järglaste õpetused sümpaat-
sed, jäi ta sufi traditsioonist väljasolevaks, kuid lülitas Akbariani doktriini kindlad väikesed
osad enda Ishrāqī töösse.

135
REFERENCES

A‘AWĀNĪ, G. R. 2005. Why is Mullā Sadrā Called Sadr al-Muta’allihīn – A. N. Baqershahi (ed). Mulla
Sadra’s School and Western Philosophies: The Papers Presented at the Second World Congress on Mulla Sadra
(May 2004, Tehran, Iran), Vol. 1, Tehran: SIPRIn Publications, 233–238.
‘ABDUL HAQ, A. M. 1970. An Aspect of the Metaphysics of Mullā Sadrā. – Islamic Studies. Islamabad, Vol.
9, 331–353.
‘ABDUL HAQ, A. M. 1971. The Metaphysics of Mullā Sadrā. – Islamic Studies. Islamabad, Vol. 10, 291–317.
‘ABDUL HAQ, A. M. 1967. Mullā Sadrā’s Concept of Being. – Islamic Studies. Islamabad, Vol. 6, 268–276.
‘ABDUL HAQ, A. M. 1970. The Psychology of Mullā Sadrā. – Islamic Studies. Islamabad, Vol. 9, 173–181.
ACIKGENC, A. 1993. Being and Existence in Sadrā and Heidegger: A Comparative Ontology. Kuala Lumpur:
International Institute of Islamic Thought and Civilization.
ACIKGENC, A. 2000. Philosophical Perception and Mystical Vision in Sadra within the Whiteheadean Context.
– Transcendent Philosophy. London: IIS, Vol. 1, No 2, 101–117.
AFNĀN, S. M. 1964. Philosophical Terminology in Arabic and Persian. Leiden: Brill.
AHSĀ’Ī, A. Sharh al-’arshiyya. Kerman: 1361 L.H.
AKBARIAN, R. 2001. The Principle of Primacy of ‘Existence’ over ‘Quiddity’ and its Philosophical Results in
the Ontological System of Mullā Sadrā. – Transcendent Philosophy. London: IIS, Vol. 2, No 4, 73–90.
AKBARIAN, R. 2002. Transsubstantial Motion and its Philosophical Consequences. – Transcendent
Philosophy. London: IIS, Vol. 3, No 2, 161–182.
ĀMULĪ, J.‘A. 1996. Rahīq-i Makhtūm: Sharh Asfār arba‘a, 10 vols. Tehrān: Intishārāt-i al-Zahrā.
ĀMULĪ, J.‘A. 1380/2001. The Transcendent Theosophy (al-hikma al-muta‘āliyya) and the Theosopher (hakīm
muta’allih) – Islam – West Philosophical Dialogue. The papers presented at the World Congress on Mulla Sadra
(May 1999, Tehran), Vol. 1. Mulla Sadra and Transcendent Philosophy, Tehrān: SIPRIn Publications, 1–30.
ANSĀRĪ, ‘A. 1417 L.H. Manāzil al-sā’irīn. Ed. A. Shirvānī. Qum: al-Matba‘a Quds.
ANSĀRĪ, ‘A. 1380 S.H. Tabaqāt al-sūfiyya. Ed. H. Āhī. Tehrān: Intishārāt-i Furūghī.
ANSCOMB, G. E., GEACH, P. T. 1961. Three Philosophers: Aristotle, Aquinas, Frege. Ithaca, NY: Cornell
University Press.
AQUINAS, T. 2004. De ente et essential – Thomas Aquinas. – Opera. Ed. A. Appolonov. Moscow: URSS, 134–
191.
ARISTOTLE. 1941. The Basic Works of Aristotle. Ed. R. McKeon. New York: Random House.
ARISTOTLE. 1998. Metaphysics. Transl. H. Tancred-Lawson. London: Penguin.
ARNALDEZ, R. 1999. Haraka wa sukūn (III.169 b). – Encyclopaedia of Islam, 2nd edition (CD-ROM). Leiden:
Brill.
ARNALDEZ. R. 1999. Khalq (IV.980a). – Encyclopaedia of Islam, 2nd edition (CD-ROM). Leiden: Brill.
ARNALDEZ, R. 1999. Ma‘ād (V.892.b). – Encyclopaedia of Islam, 2nd edition (CD-ROM). Leiden: Brill.
ĀSHTIYĀNĪ, S.J.al-Dīn. 1379 L.H. Hastī az nazar-i ‘irfān wa falsafa. Mashhad: Chāpkhāne-i Khurāsān.
ĀSHTIYĀNĪ, S.J.al-Dīn. 1378 S.H. Sharh-i hāl wa ārā’-yi falsafī-yi Mullā Sadrā. 3rd edition. Qum: Būstān-i
Kitāb Press.
BADAVĪ, ‘Abd al-Rahmān (ed). 1413 L.H. Aflotīn ‘inda ’l-‘arab (Uthūlūjiyā). 3rd edition. Qum: Intishārāt-i
Bīdār.
BALLANFAT, P. 1999, 2000. Considérations sur la conception du cœur chez Mullâ Sadrâ. – Kâr-Nâmeh,
Cahier del’Association pour la recherché interdisciplinaire en literature persane. # 5, Paris, 33–46 et # 6, Paris,
67–84.
BARNES, J. (ed). 1995. The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
BERGSON, H. 1991. L’évolusion créatrice. Paris: Gallimard.
BERGSON, H. 2001. Time and Free Will. Transl. F. L. Pogson, Nineola. NY: Dover Publications.
BLACKBURN, S. 2005. Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy. 3rd edition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

136
BONMARIAGE, C. 2003. Acts of Men, Acts of God. – Safavi, Seyed G. Mulla Sadra and Comparative
Philosophy on Causation. London: Salman – Azade Press, 295–307.
BONMARIAGE, C. 1380/2001. Elements pour la comprehension de la notion de tashkīk chez Mulla Sadra. –
Islam – West Philosophical Dialogue. The papers presented at the World Congress on Mulla Sadra (May 1999,
Tehran). Vol. 2. Mulla Sadra and Transcendent Philosophy. Tehrān: SIPRIn Publications, 127–146.
BONMARIAGE, C. 1998. Le Réel et les réalités: la structure de la réalité de l’être chez Mullâ Sadrâ Shîrâzî. 2
parties, dissertation du grade de Docteur en Philosophie et letters. Louvain: Université catholique de Louvain.
BROWNE, E. G. 1954. A Literary History of Persia. 4 vols., 2nd edition. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
BROWNE, E. G. 1950. A Year amongst the Persians, 1887–1888. 2nd edition. London: Luzac.
BÖWERING, G. 1980. The Mystical Vision of Existence in Classical Islam: The Qur’ānic Hermeneutics of the
Sūfī Sahl al-Tustarī (283/896). Berlin – New York: De Gruyter.
CARLO, W. E. 1966. The Ultimate Reducibility of Essence to Existence in Existentialist Metaphysics. The
Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
CHITTICK, W. C. 2001. The Heart of Islamic Philosophy. Oxford: Oneworld.
CHITTICK, W. C. 2003. On the Teleology of Perception. – Safavi, Seyed G. (ed). Perception According to
Mulla Sadra and Western Schools of Philosophy. London: Salman – Azade Press, 220–244.
CHITTICK, W. C. 1380/2001. The Pertinence of Islamic Cosmology: Reflections of the Philosophy of Afdāl al-
Dīn Kāshānī. – Islam-West Philosophical Dialogue: The Papers presented at the World Congress on Mulla Sadra
(May 1999, Tehran). Vol. 2. Mulla Sadra and Transcendent Philosophy. Tehran: SIPRIn Publications, 529–542.
CHITTICK, W. C. 1994. Rūmī and wahdat al-wujūd. – Poetry and mysticism in Islam: the heritage of Rumi.
Eds. A. Banani, R. Hovannisian, G. Sabagh. Cambridge, Mass.: Cambridge University Press, 70–111.
CHITTICK, W. C. 1981. Sadr al-Dīn Qūnawī on Oneness of Being. – The International Philosophical
Quarterly. Vol. 21, 171–184.
CHITTICK, W. C. 1997. The Self-Disclosure of God: Principles of Ibn al-‘Arabī’s Cosmology. New York:
SUNY Press.
CHITTICK, W. C. 2000. Sufism: A Short Introduction. Oxford: Oneworld.
CHITTICK, W. C. 1989. The Sufi Path of Knowledge: Ibn al-‘Arabi’s Metaphysics of Imagination. New York:
SUNY Press.
CHITTICK, W. C. 1999. Wahdat al-Shuhūd (VIII.37). – Encyclopaedia of Islam. 2nd edition (CD-ROM).
Leiden: Brill.
CHITTICK, W. C. 2001. Wahdat al-wujūd in India. – Proceedings of the Conference “Inner Dimension of the
Islamic World. The School of Ibn ‘Arabī” (22–23 January 2001). School of Asian and African Area Studies.
Kyoto University, Kyoto (forthcoming).
COOPER, J. 1998. Mulla Sadra Shirazi. – E. Craig (ed). The Routledge Encyclopaedia of Philosophy. London:
Routledge, Vol. 6, 595–599.
CORBIN, H. 1954. Avicenne et le récit visionnaire. Teheran – Paris: Librairie d’Adrienne Maisonneuve.
CORBIN, H. 1983. Cyclical Time and Ismaili Gnosis. Transl. Ralph Manheim and James W. Morris. London:
Kegan Paul.
CORBIN, H. 1991. En Islam iranien. 4 tomes, 2nd edition. Paris: Gallimard.
CORBIN, H. 1982. Introduction – Sadr al-Dīn al-Shīrāzī. Le Livre des penetrations metaphysiques (Kitāb al-
Mashā‘ir). Ed. Henry Corbin, 2nd edition. Tehrān: Editions Tahuri, 1–86 (of the French section).
CORBIN, H. 1978. Philosophie iranienne et philosophie compare. Téhéran: Académie Impériale Iranienne de
Philosophie.
CORBIN, H. La place de Mollâ Sadrâ dans la philosophie iranienne. – Studia Islamica. Paris, Vol. XVIII, 81–
113.
CORBIN, H. 1967. La thème de la resurrection chez Mollâ Sadrâ Shîrâzî (1050/1640) commentateur de
Sohrawardî (587/1191). – Studies in Mysticism and Religion presented to Gershom G. Scholem. Jerusalem, 71–
115.
CORBIN, H. 1961. Terre céleste et corps de resurrection: de l’Iran mazdéen à l’Iran shî’ite. Paris: Buchet-
Chastel.

137
CORBIN, H. 1961. Trilogie ismaelienne. Téhéran – Paris: Librairie Adrien Maisonneuve.
CORBIN, H. in collaboration with Nasr, S. H., Yahya, O. 1964–1986. L’Histoire de la philosophie islamique. 2
tomes. Paris: Gallimard.
DAFTARY, F. 1998. A Short History of the Ismailis: Traditions of a Muslim Community. Edinburgh: Edinburgh
University Press.
DAGLI, C. K. 2003. Consciousness and Causation in Mulla Sadra. – Safavi, Seyed G. Mulla Sadra and
Comparative Philosophy on Causation. London: Salman – Azade Press, 229–245.
DAVIDSON, H. A. 1992. Alfarabi, Avicenna and Averroes on Intellect: Their Cosmologies, Theories of the
Active Intellect and Theories of the Human Intellect. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
DAVIDSON, Herbert A. 1987. Proofs of Eternity, Creation and the Existence of God in Medieval Islamic and
Jewish Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
DE BOER, T. J. 1967. History of Philosophy in Islam. New York: Dover Publications.
DE SMET, D. 1995. La Quiétude de l’intellect: Neoplatonisme et gnose ismaélienne dans l’oeuvre de Hamîd
ad-Dîn al-Kîrmânî (Xe/Xie s.). Leuven: Peeters.
DE SMET, D. The Sacredness of Nature in Shi’i Isma‘ili Islam. – K. van Berkel, A.Vanderjagt (eds). The Book
of Nature in Antiquity and Middle Ages (Groningen Studies in Cultural Change. 10). Louvain: Peeters.
DE SMET, D. 1999. Le Souffle du Miséricordieux (Nafas ar-Rahmān): un élément pseudo-empédocléen dans la
métaphysique de Mullā Sadrā aš-Šīrāzī. – Documenti e studi sulla tradizione filosofica medievale X, Sismel:
Edizioni del Galluzo, 467–486.
DRUART, T.-A. 2000. The Human Soul’s Individuation and Its Survival After the Body’s Death: Avicenna on
the Causal Relation Between Body and Soul. – Arabic Sciences and Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, Vol. 10, 259–274.
EL-BIZRI, N. 2000. The Phenomenological Quest between Avicenna and Heidegger. Binghampton: Global
Publications.
ESHOTS, Y. 2005. A Comparative Study of Teachings of Sadr al-Dīn Qūnawī and Mullā Sadrā on Wujūd. – A.
N. Baqershahi (ed). Mulla Sadra’s School and Western Philosophies: The Papers presented at the Second World
Congress on Mulla Sadra (May 2004, Tehran, Iran). Vol. 1. Tehran: SIPRIn Publications, 313–320. (Persian
translation: “Barrasī-yi tatbīqī ārā’-yi Mullā Sadrā wa Sadr ad-Dīn Qūnawī dar bāra-i wujūd” in Majmu‘a-i
maqālāt-i muntakhab duvvumīn hamāish-i jahānī hakīm Mullā Sadrā (Awwal-i khurdādmāh-i 1383, Tehrān),
zīr-i nazar-i S.M. Khameneī, jild-i duvvum Mullā Sadrā wa digar falāsifa, Tehrān: SIPRIn Publications
1385/2006, 183–190.)
ESHOTS, Y. 2003–2004. Magnification of Luminaries in Suhrawardi’s Philosophy – Ceļš (LU TF teoloģisks un
kultūrvēsturisks izdevums), Nr. 55, 66– 80.
ESHOTS, Y. 2005. Mullā Sadrā’s Teaching on the World of Command and Mīr Dāmād’s Theory of Meta-
Temporal Origination (hudūth dahrī) – Transcendent Philosophy. London: IIS, Vol. 6, December 2005, 109–
128.
ESHOTS, Y. 2002. Preexistence of Souls to Bodies in Sadra’s Philosophy. – Transcendent Philosophy. London:
IIS, Vol. 3, No 2, June 2002, 183–197.
ESHOTS, Y. Rationalism and Mysticism: A Few Considerations Regarding the Superiority of the Divine
Wisdom. – Islam-West Philosophical Dialogue. The Papers Presented at the World Congress on Mulla Sadra
(May 1999, Tehran). Vol. 4. Mulla Sadra and Comparative Studies, 157–171.
ESHOTS, Y. 2005. The Eschatology of Kant and Mullā Sadrā. – Hamidreza Ayatollahy (ed). Papers of
International Conference On Two Hundred Years After Kant. Tehrān: Allameh Tabataba’i University Press, 25–
33.
ESHOTS, Y. 2003. The Gnostic Element of Sadra’s Doctrine on Causation. – Safavi, Seyed G. Mulla Sadra and
Comparative Philosophy on Causation. London: Salman – Azade Press, 73–89.
ESHOTS, Y. 2005. The Principle of the Systematic Ambiguity of Existence in the Philosophy of Ibn Sina and
Mulla Sadra. – Afkar (Journal of ‘Aqidah and Islamic Thought). Kuala Lumpur: Department of ‘Aqidah and
Islamic Thought, Academy of Islamic Studies, University of Malaya. Vol. 6 (Rabī‘ al-Awwal 1426/ May 2005),
161–170.
ESHOTS, Y. 2005. Two Mediaeval Versions of the Metaphysics of Light: Robert Grosseteste and Shihāb al-Dīn
Yahyā Suhrawardī. – Humanities and Social Sciences, Latvia. Riga: University of Latvia, No 2 (46), (December
2005), Essays in Religion, 110–122.

138
ESHOTS, Y. 2000. Unification of Perceiver and Perceived and Unity of Being. – Transcendent Philosophy.
London: IIS, Vol. 1, No 3, December, 1–7.
ESHOTS, Y. 2002. Mas’ala-i kaynūnat-i nufūs qabl az abdān dar falsafa-i Mullā Sadrā. – Khirādnāme-i Sadrā.
Tehrān: SIPRIn, Vol. 7, No 28, September 2002, 39–45.
ESHOTS, Y. 2000. Sadr al-Dīn Shīrāzī – mobtaker-i hikmat-i ‘arshī yā Sayrī dar istilāhāt-i Sadrā. –
Khirādnāme-i Sadrā. Tehrān: SIPRIn, Vol. 5, No 20, September 2000, 61–66.
ESHOTS, Y. 1999. “al-Wāridāt al-qalbiyya fī ma‘rifat al-rubūbiyya”: risāla-ī az yak hakīm – Khirādnāme-i
Sadrā. Tehrān: SIPRIn, Vol. 4, No 15, June 1999, 74–82.
FAKHRY, M. 1980. A History of Islamic Philosophy. 2nd edition. New York: Columbia University Press.
FAKHRY, M. 1381/2002. Mullā Sadrā’s Concept of the Soul in Relation to Avicenna’s Psychology. – Islam-
West Philosophical Dialogue: The Papers presented at the World Congress on Mulla Sadra (May 1999, Tehran).
Vol. 4. Mulla Sadra and Comparative Studies. Tehran: SIPRIn Publications, 3–10.
FANĀRĪ, Shams al-Dīn Ibn Hamza al-. 1374/1995. Misbāh al-uns bayna ’l-ma‘qūl wa ’l-mashhūd. Ed. M.
Khājavī. Tehrān: Intishārāt-i Mawlā.
FĀRĀBĪ, Abū Nasr al-. 1910. Mabādī al-falsafa al-qadīma. Cairo.
FARGHĀNĪ, Sa‘īd al-Dīn al-. 1876. Muntahā al-madārik. Cairo: Maktab al-Sanā’ī’.
FARGHĀNĪ, Sa‘īd al-Dīn al-. 1379/2000. Mashāriq al-darārī. Ed. S. J. Āshtiyānī. 2nd edition. Qum: Markaz-i
Intishārāt-i Daftar-i Tablīqāt-i Islāmī Hawze-i ‘Ilmī-i Qum.
FRANK, R. 1978. Beings and Their Attributes: The Teaching of the Basrian School of the Mu‘tazalah in the
Classical Period. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.
GARDET, L. 1999. Ibda (III.663b). – Encyclopaedia of Islam. 2nd edition (CD-ROM). Leiden: Brill.
GARDET, L., Anawati, G. C. 1970. Introduction à la théologie musulmane: essai de théologie compare. 2nd
edition. Paris: Fayard.
GHAZĀLĪ, Abū Hāmid al-. 1381/1961. Faysal al-tafraqa bayna ’l-islām wa ’l-zandaqa. Ed. Sulaymān Dunyā.
Cairo: Īsā ’l-Bābī al-Halabī.
GHAZĀLĪ, Abū Hāmid al-. 1289/1872–1873. Ihyā’ ‘ulūm al-dīn. 4 vols. Cairo: Būlāq.
GHAZĀLĪ, Abū Hāmid al-. al-Madnūn bihi ‘alā ghayr ahlihi.
GERSON, L. 1994. Plotinus. London: Routledge.
GILSON, É. 1949. Being and Some Philosophers. Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies.
GILSON, É. 1948. L’Être et l’essence. Paris: Vrin.
GLOTON, M. 1996. Introduction – Ibn ‘Arabī, La production des circles. Traduit et présenté par Paul Fenton et
Maurice Gloton. Paris: Éditions de l’Éclat, XI–XLVII.
GOBINEAU, A. de. 1923. Les religions et les philosophies dans l’Asie centrale. 2nd edition. Paris: Maisonneuve.
GOICHON, A.-M. 1938. Lexique de la langue philosophique d’Ibn Sīnā. Paris: Desclée de Brouwer.
GRAHAM, A. 1965. ’Being’ in Linguistics and Philosophy. – Foundations of Language: International Journal
of Language and Philosophy. Supplementary Series. Vol. 1. Dordrecht, 223–231.
GRIFFEL, F. 2002. The Introduction of Avicennean Psychology into the Muslim Theological Discourse. –
Transcendent Philosophy. Vol. 3, No 4, December 2002, 357–370.
GROSSETESTE, R. 2003. De luci seu de inchoatione formarum. – Robert Grosseteste. Opera. Eds. A.
Shishkov, K. Vinogradov. Moscow: URSS, 73–86.
HA’IRI YAZDI, M. 1992. The Principles of Epistemology in Islamic Philosophy – Knowledge by Presence.
Albany, NY: SUNY Press.
HAMADE. 1992. Trad. Dieu, le monde, et l’âme chez Mollâ Sadrâ al-Shîrâzî. Doctorat de nouveau regime.
Paris: Université de Paris I-Panthéon-Sorbonne.
HARTMAN, E. 1977. Substance, Body and Soul. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
HEIDEGGER, M. 1977. Basic Writings. Transl. David Krell, Frank Capuzzi, Glenn J. Gray. New York: Harper
and Row.
HEIDEGGER, M. 1988. Being and Time. Transl. John Macquarrie, Edward Robinson. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.

139
HOFFMAN, V. J. 1381/2002. Al-Fārābī’s “True King” and Mullā Sadrā’s “Path”: Human Perfection and Divine
Action in Islamic Esoteric Traditions. – Islam-West Philosophical Dialogue: The Papers presented at the World
Congress on Mulla Sadra (May 1999, Tehran). Vol. 4. Mulla Sadra and Comparative Studies. Tehran: SIPRIn
Publications, 171–189.
HORTEN, M. 1912. Die Gottesbeweise bei Schirazi. Bonn: Friedrich Cohen Verlag.
HORTEN, M. 1913. Das philosophische System von Schirazi (1640). Strassburg: Karl J. Trübner.
IBN AL-‘ARABĪ, Muhyi al-Dīn. 2000. al-Isfār ‘an natā’ij al-asfār. Ed. M. F. al-Jabr, Damascus: Dār al-Hikma.
IBN AL-‘ARABĪ, Muhyi al-Dīn. al-Futūhāt al-makkiyya. Beirūt: Dār al-Sādir, non-dated.
IBN AL-‘ARABĪ, Muhyi al-Dīn. 1370 S.H. Fusūs al-hikam. Ed. A.‘Afīfī. 2nd edition. Tehrān: Intishārāt-i al-
Zahrā.
IBN AL-‘ARABĪ, Muhyi al-Dīn. 1999. Istilāhāt al-sūfīyya. Ed. A. S. Hamdān. Cairo: Maktabat Madbūlī.
IBN AL-‘ARABĪ, Muhyi al-Dīn. 2004. The Ringstones of Wisdom. Transl. Caner K. Dagli. Chicago: Kazi
Publications.
IBN AL-‘ARABĪ, Muhyi al-Dīn. 1991. al-Tarīq ilā Allāh: al-shaykh wa ’l-murīd. Ed. Mahmūd al-Ghurāb.
Damascus: Dār al-Īmān.
IBN AL-‘ARABĪ, Muhyi al-Dīn. 1986. Traité de l’Amour. Traduit par Maurice Gloton. Paris: Albin Michel.
IBN RUSHD. 1938–1948. Tafsīr mā ba‘d al-tabīah. 3 vols. Ed. Maurice Boyuges. Beirūt: Dār al-mashriq.
IBN SĪNĀ. 1991. Fī Ithbāt al-nubuwwa. Ed. Michael E. Marmura. 2nd edition. Beirūt: Dār al-nahār.
IBN SĪNĀ. 1960. al-Ishārāt wa ’l-tanbīhāt, ma‘a Sharh Nasīr al-Dīn al-Tūsī. Ed. S. Dunyā. Cairo.
IBN SĪNĀ. 1984. al-Mabda’ wa ’l-ma‘ād. Ed. ‘A. Nūrānī. Tehrān: Intishārāt-i mo’assisa-i motāle‘āt-i islāmī
dāneshgāh-i Mac Gill (shu‘ba-i Tehrān).
IBN SĪNĀ. 1379 S.H. al-Najāt min al-gharq fī bahr al-dalālāt. Ed. M. T. Dāneshpazhūh. 2nd edition. Tehrān:
Tehran University Press.
IBN SĪNĀ. 1954. Risāla fī ’l-tayr – Henry Corbin. Avicenne et le récit visionnaire. Teheran-Paris: Librairie
d’Adrienne Maisonneuve.
IBN SĪNĀ. 1965. Shifā: Jadal. Ed. F. El-Ahwani under the supervision of I.Madkour. Cairo: GEBO.
IBN SĪNĀ. 1379 S.H. al-Ta‘līqāt. Ed. ‘Abd al-Rahmān Badavī. Qum: Būstān-i Kitāb Press.
IBN SĪNĀ. 1373 S.H./1415 L.H. ‘Uyūn al-hikma – Fakhr al-Dīn al-Rāzī. Sharh ‘Uyūn al-hikma. Ed. A. al-Saqā.
Tehrān.
IBN TAYMIYYA. 1990. Majmū‘āt al-rasā’īl wa ’l-masā’īl. Ed. M. R. Ridā (n.p., n.d.).
IBRAHIM, T., Sagadeeev, A. 1990. Classical Islamic Philosophy. Moscow: Progress.
IDRĪSĪ, Muhammed al-‘Adlūnī al-. 2005. at-Tasawwuf al-andalūsī: asusuhu an-nazariyya wa ahamm
madārisahu. Casablanca: Dār al-thaqāfa.
IKHWĀN AL-SAFĀ’. 1957. Rasā’īl. 4 vols. Beirūt: Dār al-Sādir.
IQBAL, M. 1908. Development of Metaphysics in Persia. London: Luzac.
IVRY, A. L. 1974. (transl). Al-Kindī’s Metaphysics: A Translation of Ya‘qūb Ibn Ishāq al-Kindī’s treatise “On
First Philosophy” (Fī al-Falsafa al-Ūlā). Albany, NY: SUNY Press.
IZUTSU, T. 1994. Creation and the Timeless Order of Things. Ashland, OR: White Cloud Press.
IZUTSU, T. 1971. The Concept and Reality of Existence. Tokyo: The Keio Institute of Cultural and Linguistic
Studies.
IZUTSU, T. 1384/ 2005. The Fundamental Structure of Sabzavārī’s Metaphysics. – Sabzavārī, Hājj Mullā Hādī,
Sharh ghurar al-farā’id aw sharh manzūma hikma, qismat-i umūr-i ‘āmma wa jawhar wa ‘ard. 2nd edition.
Tehrān: Anjuman-i Āthār wa Mafāhir-i Farhangī, 1–152.
IZUTSU, T. 1374 S.H. Mīr Dāmād and His Metaphysics. – Mīr Dāmād. al-Qabasāt. Ed. M. Mohaghegh. 2nd
edition. Tehrān: Mu’assisa-i Intishārāt wa chāp dāneshghāh-i Tehrān.
IZUTSU, T. 1974. The Problem of Quiddity and Natural Universal in Islamic Metaphysics. – Etudes
philosophiques présentées au Dr. Ibrahim Madkour. Ed. O. Amine. Cairo: GEBO, 131–177.
IZUTSU, T. 1984. Sufism and Taoism: A Comparative Study of Key Philosophical Concepts. 2nd edition. Los
Angeles: University of California Press.

140
JAHĀNGIRĪ, M. 1383 S.H. Muhyi al-Dīn Ibn ‘Arabī: chehra-i barjasta ‘irfān-i islāmī. 5th edition. Tehrān:
Intishārāt-i Dāneshghah-i Tehrān.
JAMBET, C. 2002. L’Acte d’être: la philosophie de la revelation chez Mollâ Sadrâ. Paris: Fayard.
JAMBET, C. 2000. (transl). Se rendre immortel, suivi du Traité de la Résurrection de Mollâ Sadrâ Shîrâzî.
Paris: Fata Morgana.
JĀMĪ, ‘Abd al-Rahmān al-. 1382/2003. al-Durra al-fākhira. Eds. N. Heer, A. Mūsavī Behbahānī. 2nd edition.
Tehrān: Mu’assisa-i mutāle‘āt-i islāmī dāneshghāh-i Tehrān.
JĀMĪ, ‘Abd al-Rahmān al-. 1996. Lawā’īh – M. M. T. Majlisī. Risāle-i tashwīq al-sālikīn, with the attachment
of A. Jāmī’s Lawāī’h and F. ‘Irāqī’s Lawāme‘. Tehran: Nūr-i Fātima Publishers, 39–81.
JĀMĪ, ‘Abd al-Rahmān. 1381 S.H. Naqd al-nusūs fī sharh Naqsh al-fusūs. Ed. W. C. Chittick. 2nd edition.
Tehrān: Mu’assisa-i pazhūhishī hikmat wa falsafa-i Īrān.
JANDĪ, Mu’ayyad al-Dīn al-. 1381 S.H. Sharh Fusūs al-hikam. 2nd edition. Ed. S. J. Āshtiyānī. Qum: Būstān-i
Kitāb.
JUZI, M. R. 1999. The Influence of Ibn al-‘Arabī’s Doctrine of the Unity of Being on the Transcendental
Philosophy of Sadr al-Dīn Shīrāzī. – Leonard Lewisohn, David Morgan (eds). The Heritage of Sufism. 3 vols.
Oxford: Oneworld, Vol. 3, 266–272.
KALIN, I. 2006. Knowledge in Later Islamic Philosophy: Mulla Sadra on the Unification of the Intellect and the
Intelligible. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
KALIN, I. 1380/2001. Between Physics and Metaphysics: Mullā Sadrā on Movement. – Islam – West
Philosophical Dialogue. The papers presented at the World Congress on Mulla Sadra (May 1999, Tehran). Vol.
1. Mulla Sadra and Transcendent Philosophy. Tehrān: SIPRIn Publications, 301–328.
KĀSHĀNĪ, ‘Abd al-Razzāq al-. 1381 S.H. Istilāhat al-sūfiyya. Ed. M. Hādīzāde. Tehrān: Intishārāt-i Hikmat.
KELLER, C. A. 1986. Le monde islamique et les doctrines de reincarnation. – C. A. Keller (ed). La
Réincarnation: Theories, raisonnements et appreciations. Bern, 181–203.
KENNY, A. 2002. Aquinas on Being. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
KHĀJAVĪ, M. 1378 S.H. Du Sadr al-Dīn yā du awj-i shuhūdu andisha dar jahān-i islām. Tehrān: Intishārāt-i
Mawlā.
KHĀJAVĪ, M. 1366 S.H. Lawāme‘ al-‘ārifīn fī ahvāl-i Sadr al-muta’allihīn. Tehrān: Intishārāt-i Mawlā.
KHĀJAVĪ, M. 1366 S.H. Muqaddima – Shīrāzī, Sadr al-Dīn al-. – Tafsīr al-Qur’ān al-Karīm. 7 vols. Ed. M.
Khājavī. Qum: Intishārāt-i Bīdār, part 1, 9–131 (of the introduction).
KHĀJAVĪ, M. 2003. Soul, Its Reality and Its Perfectionary Journey in Mulla Sadra’s Philosophy. –
Transcendent Philosophy. London: IIS, Vol. 4, No 2, June 2003, 78–93.
KHĀJAVĪ, M. 1999, 2000. Ta‘rīfī az wahdat-i wujūd. – Khirādnāme-i Sadrā. Tehrān: SIPRIn, Vol. 5, No 17,
December 1999, 50–60; No 19, June 2000, 48–62.
KHĀMENE’Ī, S. M. 1379. Mullā Sadrā: zindaqī, shakhsiyyat wa maktab-i Sadr al-muta’allihīn. Part 1. Tehrān:
Bunyād-i hikmat-i islāmī Sadrā.
KHĀMENE’Ī, S. M. 2004. Mullā Sadrā’s Transcendent Philosophy. Tehrān: SIPRIn Publications.
KHATAMI, M. 2004. From A Sadraean Point of View: Toward An Ontetic Elimination of the Subjetivistic Self.
London: Salman – Azadeh Publications.
KHATAMI, M. 1996. The Unitary Consciousness: Towards a Solution for the Ontological Crisis in Modern
Theories of the Self. Unpublished Ph.D. dissertation. University of Durham.
KHURRAMDASHTĪ, Nāhīd Bāqirī. 2000. Kitābshināsī-i Mullā Sadrā (A Comprehensive Bibliography of Mullā
Sadrā). Tehrān: SIPRIn and the National Library.
KINDĪ, Ya‘qūb Ibn Ishāq al-. 1950. Rasā’īl al-falsafiyya. Ed. M. ‘A.Abū Ridā. Cairo: Dār al-fikr al-‘arabī.
KIRMĀNĪ, Hamīd al-Dīn al-. 1983. Rāhat al-‘aql. Ed. Mustafā Ghālib. Beirūt: Dār al-Andalūs.
KRAEMER, J. L. 1986. Philosophy in the Renaissance of Islam. Leiden: Brill.
KRAYE, J., Ryan, W. F., Schmitt, C. B. (eds). 1986. The Pseudo-Aristotle in the Middle Ages: The Theology
and other Texts. London: The Warburg Institute.
LACKEY, D. P. 1380/2001. The Affirmation of Flux and the Denial of Essence Mullā Sadrā, and Some
Theological Puzzles that Result. – Islam – West Philosophical Dialogue. The papers presented at the World

141
Congress on Mulla Sadra (May 1999, Tehran). Vol. 2. Mulla Sadra and Transcendent Philosophy. Tehrān:
SIPRIn Publications, 281–287.
LANDOLT, H. 2000. La transmigration de l’âme (tanâsukh) dans le shî’isme et le soufisme. – Annuaire de
l’Ecole pratique des hautes etudes, t.108. Paris: EPHE, 242–244.
LEAMAN, O. 1985. An Introduction to Medieval Islamic Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
LOVEJOY, A. 1936. The Great Chain of Being. Cambridge (Mass.): Cambridge University Press.
MAHĀ’IMĪ, ‘Ali Ibn Ahmad. 1379 S.H./1421 L.H. Mashra‘ ’l-khusūs ilā ma‘ānī al-nusūs. Ed. S. J. Āshtiyānī.
Qum: Markaz-i Intishārāt-i Daftar-i Tablīqāt-i Islāmī Hawze-i ‘Ilmī-i Qum.
MAHDĪ, M. S. 1969. (transl). Al-Fārābī’s Philosophy of Plato and Aristotle. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
MAHDI, M. S. 2006. The Teachings of Mulla Sadra (sub-entry in “Islam”). – Encyclopædia Britannica 2006
(accessed 4 November 2006).
MAJLISĪ, M. M. T. 1996. Risāle-i tashwīq al-sālikīn. With the attachment of A. Jāmī’s Lawāī’h and F. ‘Irāqī’s
Lawāme‘. Tehran: Nūr-i Fātima Publishers.
MARCOTTE, R. D. 2004. IRJĀ‘ ILĀ NAFSI-KA: Suhrawardī’s Apperception of the Self in light of Avicenna.
– Transcendent Philosophy. London: IIS, Vol. 5, Mar-Dec 2004, 1–21.
MARITAIN, J. 1950. Existence and the Existent. New York: Dover.
MARQUET, Y. 1992. La determination astrale de l’ evolution selon les Freres de la Purete. – Bulletin d’Etudes
Orientales, 44.
MAYER, T. 2001. Ibn Sīnā’s Burhān al-siddīqīn. – Journal of Islamic Studies. Oxford: Oxford University Press,
Vol. 12, 18–39.
MC EVOY, J. 2000. Robert Grosseteste. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
MICHOT, J. R. 1986. La destine de l’homme selon Avicenne. Louvain: Peeters.
MĪR DĀMĀD. 1381 S. H. Īmādāt – Mīr Dāmād. – Musannafāt. Ed. ‘A. Nūrānī. Tehrān: Anjoman-i Āthār wa
Mafākhir-i Farhangī, part 1, 1–48.
MĪR DĀMĀD, al-Qabasāt. 1374 S.H. Ed. M. Mohaghegh. 2nd edition. Tehrān: Mu’assisa-i Intishārāt wa chāp
dāneshghāh-i Tehrān.
MISBAH YAZDĪ, M. T. 1999. Philosophical Instructions. Transl. M. Legenhausen, A. Sarvdalir. Binghampton:
SSIPS & Global Publications.
MISBAH YAZDĪ, M. T. 2001. Two Critical Issues in Sadrian Philosophy: Substantive Motion and Its Relation
to the Problem of Time, and the Principality of Existence. – Transcendent Philosophy. London: IIS, Vol. 2, No
2, June 2001, 77–86.
MODARRES TEHRĀNĪ, Āqā ‘Alī. 1378 S.H. Majmu‘a-i musannafāt. 3 vols. Ed. Mohsen Kadīwar. Tehrān:
Intishārāt-i Ittilā‘āt.
MOHAGHEGH DĀMĀD, S. M. 1996. Nokhbegān-i ‘ilm wa ‘amal-i Īrān: Āqā ‘Alī Modarres Tehrānī. – Nāme-i
Farhangestān-i ‘Ulūm. Tehrān: Farhangestān-i ‘Ulūm-i Īrān. Vol. 3, No 4, Summer 1996, 129–152.
MOHAGHEGH, M., Izutsu, T. 1977. The Metaphysics of Sabzavārī. Delmar NY: Caravan Books.
MOMEN, M. 1985. An Introduction to Shi‘i Islam: The History and Doctrines of Twelver Shi‘ism. New Haven:
Yale University Press.
MOREWEDGE, P. 1995. Essays in Islamic Philosophy, Theology and Mysticism. Oneonta, NY: Department of
Philosophy at SUNY Oneonta 1995.
MOREWEDGE, P. 1992. (transl). The Metaphysics of Mulla Sadra (Kitāb al-Mashā‘ir). New York: SSIPS.
MORIS, Z. 1998. Mullā Sadrā’s Doctrine of the Primacy of Existence (asālat al-wujūd) – al-Shajarah. Kuala
Lumpur: ISTAC, Vol. 3, 113–134.
MORIS, Z. 2003. Revelation, Intellectual intuition and Reason in the Philosophy of Mulla Sadra: An Analysis of
al-Hikma al-’arshiyya. London: Routledge & Curzon.
MORRIS, J. W. 2005. The Reflective Heart: Discovering Spiritual Intelligence in Ibn ‘Arabi's Meccan
Illuminations. Louisville, KY: Fons Vitae.
MORRIS, J. W. 1981. (transl). The Wisdom of the Throne. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
NASR, S. H. 2001. From the School of Isfahan to the School of Tehran. – Transcendent Philosophy. Vol. 2, No
4, December 2001, 1–26.

142
NASR, S. H. (ed). 1992. Islamic Spirituality: Foundations. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
NASR, S. H. (ed). 1961. Mullā Sadrā Commemoration Volume. Tehran: Tehran University Press.
NASR, S. H. 1996. Mullā Sadrā: his teachings. – Seyyed Hossein Nasr, Oliver Leaman (eds). History of Islamic
Philosophy. 2 vols. London: Routledge, Vol. 2, 643–662.
NASR, S. H. 1997. Sadr al-Dīn Shīrāzī and his Transcendent Theosophy: Background, Life and Works. 2nd
edition. Tehran: Institute for Humanities and Cultural Studies.
NASR, S. H. 1966. Sadr al-Dīn Shīrāzī ‘Mullā Sadrā’. – M. M. Sharif (ed). A History of Muslim Philosophy. 2
vols, Vol. 2. Wiesbaden: Otto Harrassowitz, 932–961.
NASR, S. H., Aminrazavi, M. (eds). 1996. The Islamic Intellectual Tradition in Persia. London: Curzon Press.
NASR, S. H., Leaman, O. 1996. History of Islamic Philosophy. 2 vols. London: Routledge.
NEWMAN, A. 1986. Towards a reconsideration of the “Isfāhan School of Philosophy”: Shaykh Bahā’ī and the
role of the Safawid ‘Ulamā’. – Studia Iranica. Paris, t. 15, fasc. 2, 165–199.
NOMANUL HAQ, S., Pingree, D. E. 1999. Tabī‘a (X.25 a). – Encyclopaedia of Islam, 2nd edition (CD-ROM).
Leiden: Brill.
OWENS, J. 1978. The Doctrine of Being in the Aristotelian Metaphysics. 3rd edition. Toronto: Pontifical Institute
of Mediaeval Studies.
PEERWANI, L.-P. 2000. Mullā Sadrā on Imaginative Perception and Imaginal World. – Transcendent
Philosophy. London: IIS, Vol. 1, No 2, September 2000, 81–96.
PEERWANI, L.-P. 1991. Quranic Hermeneutics: The Views of Sadr al-Dīn Shīrāzī. – BRISMES Proceedings of
the 1991 International Conference on Middle Eastern Studies, SOAS, London, July 1991. Exeter: BRISMES,
468–477.
PEERWANI, L.-P. 2002. Reincarnation or Resurrection of the Soul? Mullā Sadrā’s Philosophical Solution to the
Dilemma. – Transcendent Philosophy. London: IIS, Vol. 3, No 2, June 2002, 115–130.
PETERS, F. E. 1968. Aristotle and the Arabs: The Aristotelian Tradition in Islam. New York: New York
University Press.
PLOTINUS. 1952. The Six Enneads. Transl. Stephen MacKenna, B. S. Page. Chicago: Encyclopaedia
Britannica.
PROCLUS. 1933. Elements of Theology. Ed. E. R. Dodds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
QĀ’IM-MAQĀMĪ, S.‘A.H. 2000. Darāmadī bar nazariyahā dar burhān-i wujūdshenākhtī. – Khirādnāme-i
Sadrā. Tehrān: SIPRIn, Vol. 5, No 19, June 2000, 32–47.
QAYSARĪ, Dāwūd al-. 1423 L.H. Matla‘ khusūs al-kalam fī ma‘ānī fusūs al-hikam. Qum: Mu’assasa muhibbīn
li-tibā‘a wa ’l-nashr.
QUINE, W. V. 1969. Ontological Relativity and Other Essays. New York & London: Columbia University
Press.
QŪNAWĪ, Sadr al-Dīn al-. 1381 S.H. I‘jāz al-bayān fī tafsīr Umm al-Qur’ān. Ed. S. J. Āshtiyānī. Qum: Bustān-i
Kitāb.
QŪNAWĪ, Sadr al-Dīn al-. 1371 S.H./1413 L.H. Kitāb al-Fukūk fī asrār mustanadāt hikam al-Fusūs. Ed. M.
Khājavī, Tehrān: Intishārāt-i Mawlā.
QŪNAWĪ, Sadr al-Dīn al-. 1374/1995. Miftāh ghayb al-jam‘ wa ’l-wujūd. – Fanārī, Shams al-Dīn Ibn Hamza al-
. Misbāh al-uns bayna ’l-ma‘qūl wa ’l-mashhūd. Ed. M. Khājavī. Tehrān: Intishārāt-i Mawlā, 1–144.
QŪNAWĪ, Sadr al-Dīn al- and Nasīr al-Dīn al-Tūsī. 1416/1995. Murāsalā. Ed. G. Schubert. Beirūt: Jam‘iyyat
al-mustashriqīn al-ālmāniyya.
QŪNAWĪ, Sadr al-Dīn al-. 1375 S.H./1417 L.H. al-Nafahāt al-ilāhiyya. Ed. M. Khājavī. Tehrān: Intishārāt-i
Mawlā.
QŪNAWĪ, Sadr al-Dīn al-. 1379 S.H./1421 L.H. al-Nusūs miftāh mafātīh al-fusūs – ‘Ali Ibn Ahmad Mahā’imī.
Mashra‘ ’l-khusūs ilā ma‘ānī al-nusūs. Ed. S. J. Āshtiyānī. 2nd edition. Qum: Markaz-i Intishārāt-i Daftar-i
Tablīqāt-i Islāmī Hawze-i ‘Ilmī-i Qum.
THE HOLY QUR’ĀN. 2000. Transl. Abdullah Yusuf Ali. Hertfordshire: Wordswordth Editions Ltd.
QUSHAYRĪ, Abū ’l-Qāsim al-. 1374 S.H. al-Risāla al-qushayriyya. Eds. ‘A. Mahmūd, M. Sharīf. Qum:
Intishārāt-i Bīdār.
RAFĪ’Ī QAZVĪNĪ, Sayyed Abū ’l-Hasan. 1376 S.H. Ghawsī dar bahr-i ma‘rifat. Tehrān: Intishārāt-i Islām.

143
RAFĪ’Ī QAZVĪNĪ, Sayyed Abū ’l-Hasan. 2001. On the Four Journeys (Risālat tahqīq fī ’l- Asfār al-arba‘a).
Transl. S. S. H. Rizvi. – Transcendent Philosophy. London: IIS, Vol. 2, No 3, September 2001, 35–44.
RAHMAN, F. 1999. ’Akl (V.892.b). – Encyclopaedia of Islam. 2nd edition (CD-ROM). Leiden: Brill.
RAHMAN, F. Al-Asfār al-arba‘a. – Encyclopaedia Iranica. Vol. 2, 744–747.
RAHMAN, F. 1975. The God – World Relationship in Mulla Sadra. – George F. Hourani (ed). Essays on
Islamic Philosophy and Science. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.
RAHMAN, F. 1980. Mīr Dāmād’s Concept of Hudūth Dahrī: A Contribution to the Study of God-World
Relationship Theories in Safavid Iran. – Journal of Near East Studies. Vol. 39, No 2. Chicago: Chicago
University Press.
RAHMAN, F. 1975. The Philosophy of Mullā Sadrā. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.
RĀZĪ, Fakhr al-Dīn al-. 1966. al-Mabāhith al-mashriqiyya. 2 vols. Tehrān: Maktabat al-Asadī.
RĀZĪ, Fakhr al-Dīn al-. 1373 S.H./1415 L.H. Sharh ‘Uyūn al-hikma. Ed. A. al-Saqā. Tehrān.
RESCHER, N. 1996. Process Metaphysics. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.
RIST, J. M. 1967. Plotinus: The Road to Reality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
RIZVI, S. H. 2001. Approaching the Study of Mullā Sadrā Shīrāzī (d.1641): A Survey of Some Doctoral
Dissertations. – Transcendent Philosophy. London: IIS, Vol. 2, No 4, December 2001, 59–72.
RIZVI, S. H., Christian Jambet. 2002. L’Acte d’être: la philosophie de la revelation chez Mollâ Sadrâ. –
Transcendent Philosophy. London: IIS, Vol. 3, No 4, December 2002, 464–468.
RIZVI, S. H., Seyed G. Safavi. 2002. Mulla Sadra: Philosopher of the Mystics. Cambridge: Islamic Texts
Society.
RIZVI, S. H. 2000. Modulation of Being (Tashkīk al-Wujūd) in the Philosophy of Mullā Sadrā Shīrāzī.
Unpublished Ph.D. dissertation. Cambridge: Cambridge University.
RIZVI, S. H. 2005. Mysticism and Philosophy: Ibn ‘Arabī and Mullā Sadrā. – Peter Adamson, Richard R. Taylor
(eds). The Cambridge Companion to Arabic Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 224–246.
RIZVI, S. H. 2000. Parviz Morewedge. The Metaphysics of Mullā Sadrā [being a translation of Kitāb al-
Mashā’ir]. – Transcendent Philosophy. London: IIS, Vol. 1, No 3, December 2000, 121–124.
RIZVI, S. H. 2003. Rethinking Causation in the World Process: A Sadrian Approach. – Proceedings of the 2nd
International Conference on Mulla Sadra: Causation According to Mulla Sadra and Other Schools of
Philosophy. 5–6 May 2001 – SOAS (London). London: Salman – Azade Press, 271–291.
RIZVI, S. H. 2000. Roots of an Aporia in Later Islamic Philosophy: the Essence – Existence Distinction in the
Metaphysics of Avicenna and Suhrawardi. – Studia Iranica. Paris, Vol. 29, 61–108.
RŪMĪ, Jalāl al-Dīn. Dīvān-i Shams-i Tabrīzī, Tehrān: Intishārāt-i Amīr-i Kabīr 1354 S.H.
RŪMĪ, Jalāl al-Dīn. 1375 S.H. Guzide-i ghazaliyyat-i Mawlawī. Ed. S. Shamisa. 5th edition. Tehrān: Mahārat
Publishers.
RUMI, Jalaluddin. 1925–1940. The Mathnawi. Ed. R. A. Nicholson. London: Luzac and Co.
RUSSELL, B. 1972. Our Knowledge of the External World. London: George Allen & Unwin.
SABZAVĀRĪ, Hājj Mullā Hādī. 1384/ 2005. Sharh ghurar al-farā’id aw sharh manzūmeh hikmat, qismat-i
umūr-i ‘āmma wa jawhar wa ‘ard. 2nd edition. Tehrān: Anjuman-i Āthār wa Mafāhir-i Farhangī.
SADUGHI SOHA, M. 1980. a Bio-Bibliography of Post-Sadr-ul-Muta’allihīn Mystics and Philosophers.
Tehrān: Iranian academy of Philosophy.
SAFAVI, S. G. (ed). 2003. Causation According to Mulla Sadra and Other Schools of Philosophy. London:
Salman – Azade Press.
SAFAVI, S. G. 2002. Mulla Sadra on Causation. – Transcendent Philosophy. Vol. 3, No 4, December 2002,
347–356.
SAFAVI, S. G. (ed). 2003. Perception according to Mulla Sadra and Western Schools of Philosophy. London:
Salman – Azade Press.
SAJJĀDĪ, S. J. 1376 S.H. Sharh-i risā’īl-i fārsī-yi Suhrawardī. Tehrān: Hawze-i hunarī.
SALEH, M. M. 1994. The Verse of Light: A Study of Mulla Sadra’s Philosophical Qur’an Exegesis.
Unpublished Ph.D. dissertation. Philadelphia: Temple University.
SARTRE, J.-P. 1956. Being and Nothingness. Transl. Hazel Barnes. New York: Washington Square Press.

144
SCHMIDTKE, S. 1380/2001. The Doctrine of the Transmigration of Soul According to Shihāb al-Dīn al-
Suhrawardī (killed 587/1191) and his Followers. – Islam-West Philosophical Dialogue: The Papers presented at
the World Congress on Mulla Sadra (May 1999, Tehran). Vol. 2. Mulla Sadra and Transcendent Philosophy.
Tehran: SIPRIn Publications, 461–477.
SHEHADI, F. 1975. Arabic and the Concept of Being. – George F. Hourani (ed). Essays in Islamic Philosophy
and Science. Albany, NY: SUNY Press, 147–157.
SHEHADI, F. 1961. Metaphysics in Islamic Philosophy. New York: Delmar Books.
SIJISTĀNĪ, Abū Ya‘qūb al-. 1961. Kitāb al-Yanābi‘ – Henry Corbin. Trilogie ismaelienne. Téhéran-Paris:
Librairie Adrien Maisonneuve.
SIPRIn, 1380-/2001-. Islam-West Philosophical Dialogue: The Papers presented at the World Congress on
Mulla Sadra (May 1999, Tehran), 8 volumes, Tehran: SIPRIn Publications.
SHĪRĀZĪ, Sadr al-Dīn al-. 1981. Asrār al-Āyāt. Ed. M. Khājavī. Tehrān: Iranian Academy of Philosophy.
SHĪRĀZĪ, Sadr al-Dīn al-. 1341 S.H. al-Hikma al-’arshiyya. Ed. G. Āhanī. Isfahān: Kitābfurūshī-yi Shahriyār.
SHĪRĀZĪ, Sadr al-Dīn al-. 1981. al-Hikma al-muta‘āliyya fī ’l-asfār al-‘aqliyya al-arba‘a. 9 vols. Eds. R. Lutfī,
I. Amīnī, F. Ummīd, 3rd edition. Beirūt: Dār ihyā’ al-turāth al-‘arabī.
SHĪRĀZĪ, Sadr al-Dīn al-. 1366 S.H. Hudūth al-‘ālam. Ed. M. Khājavī. Tehrān: Mawlā.
SHĪRĀZĪ, Sadr al-Dīn al-. 1982. Īqāz al-nā’īmīn. Ed. M. Mu’ayyadī. Tehrān: Cultural Studies and research
Institute.
SHĪRĀZĪ, Sadr al-Dīn al-. 1982 S.H. Kasr asnām al-jāhiliyya. Ed. Mohsen Jahāngirī under the supervision of S.
M. Khāmene’ī.Tehrān: Bunyād-i hikmat-i islāmī Sadrā.
SHĪRĀZĪ, Sadr al-Dīn al-. 1982. Le Livre des penetrations metaphysiques (Kitāb al-Mashā‘ir). Ed. Henry
Corbin. 2nd edition. Tehrān: Editions Tahuri.
SHĪRĀZĪ, Sadr al-Dīn al-. 1381 S.H. al-Mabdā’ wa ’l-ma‘ād fī ’l-hikma al-muta‘āliyya. 2 vols. Eds.
Muhammad Dhabīhī, Ja‘far Shāhnazarī under the supervision of S. M. Khāmene’ī. Tehrān: Bunyād-i hikmat-i
islāmī Sadrā.
SHĪRĀZĪ, Sadr al-Dīn al-. 1999. Mafātīh al-ghayb. 2 vols. Ed. M. Khājavī. Beirūt: Mu’assasa al-ta’rīkh al-
‘arabī.
SHĪRĀZĪ, Sadr al-Dīn al-. 1997. Majmu‘a-i ash‘ār. Ed. M. Khājavī. Tehrān: Intishārāt-i Mawlā.
SHĪRĀZĪ, Sadr al-Dīn al-. 1378 S.H. al-Mazāhir al-ilāhiyya fī asrār al-‘ulūm al-kamāliyya. Ed. S. M.
Khāmene’ī. Tehrān: Sāzmān-i Chāp wa intishārāt Vazārat-i Farhang wa Irshād-i Islāmī.
SHĪRĀZĪ, Sadr al-Dīn al-. 1377 S.H. Risāla fī ’l-hashr. Ed. M. Khājavī. 2nd edition. Tehrān: Mawlā.
SHĪRĀZĪ, Sadr al-Dīn al-. 1376 S.H. Risāle-i se asl. Ed. M. Khājavī. Tehrān: Mawlā.
SHĪRĀZĪ, Sadr al-Dīn al-. 1378 S.H. Se risāle-i falsafī (Mutashābihāt al-Qur’ān, al-Masā’īl al-qudsiyya wa
ajūbāt al-masā’īl). 2nd edition. Ed. S. J. Āshtiyānī. Qum: Markaz-i intishārāt-i daftar-i tablīghāt-i islāmī hawze-i
‘ilmī-i Qum.
SHĪRĀZĪ, Sadr al-Dīn al-. 1391 L.H. Sharh Usūl al-Kāfī, in one volume with Mafātīh al-ghayb. Tehrān:
Maktaba al-Mahmūdī.
SHĪRĀZĪ, Sadr al-Dīn al-. 1382 S.H. al-Shawāhid al-rubūbiyya fī manāhij al-sulūkiyya. Ed. S. J. Āshtiyānī. 2nd
edition. Qum: Būstān-i Kitāb.
SHĪRĀZĪ, Sadr al-Dīn al-. 1366 S.H. Tafsīr al-Qur’ān al-Karīm. 7 vols. Ed. M. Khājavī. Qum: Intishārāt-i
Bīdār.
SHĪRĀZĪ, Sadr al-Dīn al-. 1979. al-Wāridāt al-qalbiyya fī ma‘rifat al-rubūbiyya. Ed. A. Shafī‘īhā. Tehrān:
Iranian Academy of Philosophy.
SMITH, J. I. 1381/2002. Barriers and Heights: Classical Islam and Mullā Sadrā on barzakh and a‘rāf. – Islam-
West Philosophical Dialogue: The Papers presented at the World Congress on Mulla Sadra (May 1999, Tehran).
Vol. 4. Mulla Sadra and Comparative Studies. Tehran: SIPRIn Publications, 53–72.
SMITH, J. I., Haddad, Y. Y. 1981. The Islamic Understanding of Death and Resurrection. Albany, NY: SUNY
Press.
SOHRAVARDI, Sh. Y. 1976. Oeuvres philosophiques et mystiques. Ed. Henry Corbin. 2nd edition. Tehran –
Paris: Academie Imperiale Iranienne de Philosophie et Depositaire Librairie Adrien Maisonneuve.

145
SPEER, A. 1996. Physics or Metaphysics? Some Remarks on Theory of Science and Light in Robert Grosseteste
– J. Marenbon (ed). Aristotle in Britain during the Middle Ages. Turnhout: Brepols, 73–90.
SUHRAWARDI, Sh.Y. 1999. The Philosophical Allegories and Mystical Treatises. A Parallel Persian-English
Text. Ed. and transl. W. M. Thackston, Jr. Costa Mesa: Mazda Publishers.
SUHRAWARDĪ. 1999. The Philosophy of Illumination. Eds. Walbridge, J., Ziai, H. Provo: Brigham Young
University Press.
SUHRAWARDĪ, Shihāb al-Dīn. 1374 S.H. Safīr-i Sīmurgh. Tehrān: Mawlā.
TABĀTABĀ’Ī, M. H. 1984. Nihāyat al-hikma. Tehrān: al-Zahra.
VAN DEN BERGH, S. 1999. Dhawhar (II.493a). – Encyclopaedia of Islam. 2nd edition (CD-ROM). Leiden:
Brill.
WALBRIDGE, J. 1992. The Science of Mystic Lights: Qutb al-Dīn Shīrāzī and the Illuminationist Tradition in
Islamic Philosophy. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
WALKER, P. E. 1996. Abu Ya‘qub al-Sijistani: Intellectual Missionary. London: I.B. Tauris.
WALKER, P. E. 1991. The Doctrine of Metempsychosis in Islam. – W. B. Hallaq, D. P. Little (eds). Islamic
Studies Presented to Charles J. Adams. Leiden: Brill, 219–238.
WALKER, P. E. 1999. Hamīd al-Dīn al-Kirmānī: Ismaili Thought in the Age of al-Hākim. London: I.B. Tauris.
WALKER, P. E. 1994. Platonisms in Islamic Philosophy. – Studia Islamica. Paris, Vol. 79, 5–25.
WALZER, R. 1963. Greek into Arabic: Essays on Islamic Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
WHITEHEAD, A. N. 1979. Process and Reality. Eds. D. R. Griffin, D. W. Sherburne. New York: The Free
Press.
WISNOVSKY, R. 2000. Notes on Avicenna’s Concept of Thingness (Shay’iyya). – Arabic Sciences and
Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Vol. 10, 181–221.
WOLFSON, H. A. 1938. The amphibolous terms in Aristotle, Arabic philosophy and Maimonides. – Harward
Theological Review. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, Vol. 31.
WOLFSON, H. A. 1971. The Philosophy of the Kalam. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
YATHRIBĪ, S. Y. 1380. Tahlīl-i intiqādī mas’ala-i asālat-i wujūd. – Majmu‘a-i maqālāt-i hamāish-i jahānī
hakīm Mullā Sadrā, khordādmāh 1378, jild-i duwwum “Mullā Sadrā wa hikmat-i muta‘āliyya”. Tehrān:
Bunyād-i hikmat-i islāmī Sadrā, 27–48.
ZANJĀNĪ, Abū ‘Abdallāh al-. 2000. al-Faylasūf al-irānī al-kabīr Sadr al-Dīn al-Shīrāzī Mullā Sadrā, hayātuhu
wa usūl falsafatihi. 2nd edition. Tehrān: Mu‘tamar ihyā’ dhikrā al-Faylasūf Sadr al-Dīn al-Shīrāzī.
ZIAI, H. 1990. Knowledge and Illumination: A Study of Suhrawardī’s Hikmat al-Ishrāq, Atlanta. Georgia:
Scholars Press.
ZIAI, H. 1996. Mullā Sadrā: his life and works. – S. H. Nasr, O. Leaman (eds). History of Islamic Philosophy.
London: Routledge, Vol. 2, 635–642.
ZIAI, H. 1993. Sadr al-Dīn Shīrāzī wa bayān-i falsafī ‘hikmat-i muta‘āliya’. – Irānshenāsī. Rockville, Maryland:
Keyan Foundation, Vol. 5, No 2, 353–364.

КИРМАНИ, Хамид ад-Дин ал-. 1995. Успокоение разума. пер. A. B. Смирнов. Мoсквa: Ладомир.
ПЛОТИН. 2005. Эннеады, Шестая эннеада. Санкт-Петербург: Издательство Олега Абышко.
САДР АД-ДИН АШ-ШИРАЗИ. 2004. Престольная мудрость. Перевод, вступление и комментарии
Яниса Эшотса. Москва: Восточная литература 2004.
САДР АД-ДИН АШ-ШИРАЗИ. 2000. Приходящее в сердце о познании Господствия – перевод и
комментарии Яниса Эшотса. – Восток: Москва, № 2, 109–132; № 5, 109–127.
СИДАШ, Т. Г. 2005. Натурфилософия Плотина – Плотин. – Эннеады, Вторая эннеада. Санкт-Петербург:
Издательство Олега Абышко.
CМИРНОВ, А. В. 2001. Логика смысла: теория и ее приложение к анализу классической арабской
философии и культуры. Москва: Языки славянской культуры.
СМИРНОВ, A. B. 1986. Что стоит за термином «средневековая арабская философия» – M. T. Степанянц
(ред). Средневековая арабская философия. Moсква: Восточная литература, 42–82.
ХАЗРАТКУЛОВ, М. 1985. Философские взгляды Садриддина Ширази. Душанбе: Ирфон.
ЭШОТС, Я. 2002. Садр ад-Дин аш-Ширази и “ирфанизация” философии. – Историко-философский
ежегодник 2000. Mосквa: Наука, 378–390.

146
ELULOOKIRJELDUS
Nimi: Jānis Ešots
Sünniaeg ja -koht: 26.08.1966, Riia
Kodakondsus: Läti

Haridus
1973–1984 Jaunjiljava Keskkool
1985–1991 Moskva Kirjandusinstituut, tõlkeosakond, pärsia keel, (ilu)kirjanduse tõlkija

Teenistuskäik
2006– Läti Ülikool, Aasia uuringute instituut, nooremteadur
2002– Läti Ülikool, Aasia uuringute osakond, kaasaegsete keelte teaduskond, lektor
2004–2005 Läti Ülikool, religiooniajaloo osakond, teoloogia teaduskond, lektor
2001

Grandid
2006–2007 Läti Riikliku Kultuurkapitali Fond
2005–2006 Läti Ülikool, Kristaps Morbergi Stipendium
2004–2006 Läti Teadusnõukogu
1989–1991 Moskva Kirjandusinstituut, Pavel Antokolski Stipendium

Võõrkeelteoskus
inglise, vene ja pärsia keel kõnes ja kirjas
kl. araabia, kl. kreeka, prantsuse ja türgi keel

147
CURRICULUM VITAE
Name: Janis Ešots
Date and place of birth: 26.08.1966, Riga
Citizenship: Latvian

Education
1973–1984 Jaunjiljava Secondary School
1985–1991 Moscow Institute of Literature, Department of Translation,
Persian language, translator of (fiction) literature

Employment
2006– University of Latvia, Institute of Asian Studies, Junior Research Fellow
2002– University of Latvia, Department of Asian Studies, Faculty of Modern
Languages, lecturer
2004–2005 Department of the History of Religions, Faculty of Theology, University
of 2001 Latvia lecturer

Grants
2006–2007 The Grant of the Latvian State Cultural Capital Foundation
2005–2006 Kristaps Morbergs Fellowship for Doctoral Students, University of Latvia
2004–2006 The Latvian Council of Science Research Grant for Doctoral Students
1989–1991 Pavel Antokolsky Fellowship for Young Translators,
Moscow Institute of Literature

Languages
speaking, reading and writing knowledge of English, Russian, Persian
reading knowledge of classical Arabic, classical Greek, French, Turkish

148
TALLINNA ÜLIKOOL
HUMANITAARTEADUSTE DISSERTATSIOONID
1. СЕРГЕЙ ДОЦЕНКО. Проблемы поэтики А. М. Ремизова. Автобиографизм как конструктивный принцип
творчества. Таллинн: Изд-во ТПУ, 2000. 162 стр. Таллиннский педагогический университет. Диссертации по
гуманитарным наукам, 1. ISSN 1406-4391. ISBN 9985-58-135-0.
2. MART KIVIMÄE. Ajaloomõtlemise kolm strateegiat ja nende dialoogisuhted minevikuga (lisades tõlgitud
R. Koselleck, J. Rüsen, E. Nolte). Historismi muutumise, arendamise, ületamise probleemid. Tallinn: TPÜ kirjastus,
2000. 201 lk. Tallinna Pedagoogikaülikool. Humanitaarteaduste dissertatsioonid, 2. ISSN 1406–4391. ISBN 9985-
58-164-4.
3. НАТАЛЬЯ НЕЧУНАЕВА. Минея как тип славяно–греческого средневекового текста. Таллинн: Изд-во
ТПУ, 2000. 177 стр. Таллиннский педагогический университет. Диссертации по гуманитарным наукам, 3.
ISSN 1406-4391. ISBN 9985-58-125-3.
4. ОЛЕГ КОСТАНДИ. Раннее творчество В. Каверина как литературный и культурный феномен. Таллин: Изд-
во ТПУ, 2001. 142 стр. Таллиннский педагогический университет. Диссертации по гуманитарным наукам, 4.
ISSN 1406–4391. ISBN 9985-58-180-6.
5. LAURI LINDSTRÖM. Album Academicum Universitatis Tartuensis 1918–1944. Rahvus, sugu, sünnikoht ja kesk-
hariduse omandamise koht üliõpilaskonna kujunemist ja kõrghariduse omandamist mõjutavate teguritena. Tallinn:
TPU Press, 2001. 92 p. Tallinn Pedagogical University. Dissertations on Humanities Sciences, 5. ISSN 1406-4391.
ISBN 9985-58-190-3.
6. AУРИКA MEЙMPE. Руccкиe литератoры-эмигрaнmы в Эcmoнии 1918–1940. Нa матepиaлe пеpиoдическoй
печaти. Таллин: Изд-во ТПУ, 2001. 165 стр. Таллиннский педагогический университет. Диссертации по
гуманитарным наукам, 6. ISSN 1406-4391. ISBN 9985-58-205-5.
7. AIVAR JÜRGENSON. Siberi eestlaste territoriaalsus ja identiteet. Tallinn: TPÜ kirjastus, 2002. 312 lk.
Tallinna Pedagoogikaülikool. Humanitaarteaduste dissertatsioonid, 7. ISSN 1406–4391. ISBN 9985-58-239-X.
8. DAVID VSEVIOV. Kirde-Eesti urbaanse anomaalia kujunemine ning struktuur pärast Teist maailmasõda
Tallinn: TPÜ kirjastus, 2002. 104 lk. Tallinna Pedagoogikaülikool. Humanitaarteaduste dissertatsioonid, 8.
ISSN 1406-4391. ISBN 9985-58-242-X.
9. ROMAN KALLAS. Eesti kirjanduse õpetamise traditsioon XX sajandi vene õppekeelega koolis. Tallinn: TPÜ kir-
jastus, 2003. 68 lk. Tallinna Pedagoogikaülikool. Humanitaarteaduste dissertatsioonid, 9. ISSN 1406–4391. ISBN
9985-58-256-X.
10. KRISTA KERGE. Keele variatiivsus ja mine-tuletus allkeelte süntaktilise keerukuse tegurina. Tallinn: TPÜ kirjastus,
2003. 246 lk. Tallinna Pedagoogikaülikool. Humanitaarteaduste dissertatsioonid, 10. ISSN 1406-4391. ISBN 9985-58-
265-9.
11. АННА ГУБЕРГРИЦ. Русская драматургия для детей как элемент субкультуры: 1920–1930-е годы. Тал-
линн: Изд-во ТПУ, 2004. 168 стр. Таллиннский педагогический университет. Диссертации по гуманитарным
наукам, 11. ISSN 1406–4391. ISBN 9985-58-302-7.
12. VAHUR MÄGI. Inseneriühendused Eesti riigi ülesehituses ja kultuuriprotsessis (1918–1940). Tallinn: TPÜ
kirjastus, 2004. 146 lk. Tallinna Pedagoogikaülikool. Humanitaarteaduste dissertatsioonid, 12. ISSN 1406-4391.
ISBN 9985-58-344-2.
13. HEIKKI OLAVI KALLIO. Suomen ja Viron tiedesuhteet erityisesti Viron miehitysaikana vuosina 1940–1991.
Tallinn: Tallinnan Pedagogisen Yliopiston kustantamo, 2004. 243 lk. Tallinnan Pedagogisen Yliopiston. Huma-
nististen tieteiden väitöskirjat, 13. ISSN 1406-4391. ISBN 9985-58-350-7.
14. ÜLLE RANNUT. Keelekeskkonna mõju vene õpilaste eesti keele omandamisele ja integratsioonile Eestis.
Tallinn: TLÜ kirjastus, 2005. 215 lk. Tallinna Ülikool. Humanitaarteaduste dissertatsioonid, 14. ISSN 1406-4391.
ISBN 9985-58-394-9.
15. MERLE JUNG. Sprachspielerische Texte als Impulse für schriftliche Textproduktion im Bereich Deutsch als
Fremdsprache. Tallinn: Verlag der Universität Tallinn, 2006. 186 S. Universität Tallinn. Dissertationen in den
Geisteswissenschaften, 15. ISSN 1406-4391. ISBN 9985-58-409-0
16. ANDRES ADAMSON. Hertsog Magnus von Holmsteini roll Läänemere-ruumis Liivi sõja perioodil. Tallinn:
TLÜ kirjastus, 2005. 156 lk. Tallinna Ülikool. Humanitaarteaduste dissertatsioonid, 16. ISSN 1736-3624. ISBN
9985-58-427-9.
17. АИДА ХАЧАТУРЯН. Роман В.С. Маканина «Андеграунд, или Герой нашего времени»: Homo urbanis в поле
«усреднения». Таллинн: Изд-во ТПУ, 2006. 146 стр. Таллиннский педагогический университет. Диссертации
по гуманитарным наукам, 17. ISSN 1736–3624. ISBN-10 9985-58-435-X. ISBN-13 987-9985-58-435-4.

149
18. JULIA TOFANTŠUK. Construction of Identity In The Fiction of Contemporary British Women Writers (Jeanette
Winterson, Meera Syal, and Eva Figes). Tallinn: Tallinn University Press, 2001. 160 p. Tallinn University.
Dissertations on Humanities Sciences, 18. ISSN 1736-3624. ISBN 978-9985-58-479-8.

ILMUNUD VEEBIVÄLJAANDENA
ИННА АДАМСОН. Модальный смысл дезидеративности: от семантической зоны к семантической типо-
логии высказываний (на материале русского языка). Таллинн: Изд-во ТПУ, 2006. 131 стр. Таллиннский педа-
гогический университет. Диссертации по гуманитарным наукам. ISSN 1736-3624. ISBN 978-9985-58-455-2.
MARIS SAAGPAKK. Deutschbaltische Autobiographien als Dokumente des zeit- und selbstempfindens: vom ende
des 19. Jh. Bis zur umsiedlung 1939. Tallinn: Verlag der Universität Tallinn, 2006. 163 S. Universität Tallinn.
Dissertationen in den Geisteswissenschaften. ISSN 1406–4391. ISBN 978-9985-58-469-9.

ILMUNUD MONOGRAAFIANA
ANNE LANGE. Ants Oras. Monograafia. Tartu: Ilmamaa, 2004. 493 lk. ISBN 9985-77-163-X.

150

You might also like