You are on page 1of 11

jun06_Article4 5/15/06 4:16 PM Page 405

Journal of Economic Literature


Vol. XLIV (June 2006), pp. 405–414

A Review of Steven Shavell’s


Foundations of Economic Analysis
of Law
RICHARD A. POSNER∗

Steven Shavell’s Foundations of Economic Analysis of Law (Harvard University


Press, 2004) is a major theoretical contribution to “law and economics,” the applied
field of economics that studies the economic properties and consequences of legal doc-
trines and institutions. It is a field of immense practical importance, but unfamiliar to
many economists—a situation that Shavell’s book bids fair to rectify. This review
essay situates Shavell’s book in the history of economic scholarship about law and uses
the book as a springboard for speculation about new directions in that scholarship.

A fter receiving his doctorate in economics


from MIT in 1973, Steven Shavell began
teaching economics at Harvard. He moved
has done little in what in law would be con-
sidered the “advanced” subjects, such as
constitutional law, environmental law,
to the law school in 1980. Beginning that antitrust law, labor law (including pension
year, and without abatement since, he has law and the law of employment discrimina-
published several books and more than one tion), corporate and securities law, interna-
hundred articles, all on economic analysis of tional law, regulated industries, and
law, all theoretical, and all or virtually all on bankruptcy. A surprising omission, because
the basic or, as he terms them, central fields of its similarity to contract law, is family law.
of law as a lawyer would recognize them— In noting that Shavell has not covered the
torts, contracts, property, criminal law, pro- entire vast field (as it has become) of eco-
cedure, and remedies—with some attention nomic analysis of law (or “law and econom-
as well to jurisprudence, including the nor- ics” as it is often called), I do not intend
mative adequacy of the economic approach belittlement. The scope and quality of his
to law. He has done no empirical work, and work are remarkable. He is a superb theo-
retician, and the major theoretical contribu-

Posner: Judge, U.S. Court of Appeals for the Seventh
tor to most of the areas of economic analysis
Circuit; Senior Lecturer, University of Chicago Law of law in which he has written. He is the
School. I thank William Landes and Andrei Shleifer for leading figure in the “third generation” of
helpful comments on a previous draft of this review, and
Meghan Maloney for helpful research assistance and cite
law and economics scholars and, before
checking. turning to his latest and most important

405
jun06_Article4 5/15/06 4:16 PM Page 406

406 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XLIV (June 2006)

book, Foundations of Economic Analysis of analysis of (all) law, though an even greater
Law, I need to say a few words about the his- landmark was Ronald Coase’s article on
tory of economic analysis of law—a field social cost (Coase 1960). Coase himself, par-
that, despite its theoretical interest and prac- adoxically, has rejected the concept of eco-
tical importance, remains unfamiliar to nomics as the theory of rational choice and
many economists.1 has indeed disclaimed any interest in law
Traditionally, economics was thought to be except insofar as it affects the economy
defined by its subject rather than by its (Coase 1988, 1984; Posner 1995, ch. 20).
method. Its subject was the economy; and Nevertheless, and of signal importance to
the legal system, though understood to economic analysis of law, Coase’s article con-
affect the economy, was not thought to be tains an insightful analysis of the economiz-
itself an economic system in the sense of a ing properties of tort law; more important, it
social activity that could profitably be stud- focused attention on transaction costs, which
ied in economic terms. (Climate affects the are central to the understanding of the law as
economy but the climate is not an economic an economic system.
system.) With the startling exception of Coase, Becker, Guido Calabresi (then a
Jeremy Bentham’s utilitarian analysis of law professor, now a judge), and a few others
criminal punishment, which anticipated by comprise what I am calling (with apologies to
more than 150 years Gary Becker’s econom- Bentham) the “first generation” of economic
ic theory of criminal punishment, there was analysts of law. Their major contributions to
very little economic writing on law outside the field were complete by about 1970, the
those areas, mainly antitrust and public util- year that Calabresi published his influential
ity/common carrier regulation, where the book The Costs of Accidents.2 The second
law seemed to have explicitly incorporated generation, of younger scholars such as
economic concepts, such as, in the case of myself and Becker’s students William Landes
antitrust, monopoly and competition. and Isaac Ehrlich, began publishing in the
A more sustained, extensive engagement late 1960s (see, for example, Posner 1972b;
of economics with law had to await recogni- Becker and Landes 1974). They used the
tion (which again had been anticipated by theoretical approaches of the first generation
Bentham) that economics is a theory as well to extend economic analysis into a variety
as an “area study”—specifically the theory of—eventually into almost all—fields of law,
of rational choice, a theory that can in prin- with particular emphasis on exploring the
ciple be applied to any social activity (even degree to which the law, especially the com-
nonhuman), thus including law, even when mon law, might actually be a system for pro-
law regulates nonmarket activities, such as moting the efficient allocation of resources.3
crime, adjudication, or marriage. The lead- Despite the archaic, moralistic vocabulary of
ing economist in refashioning economic the law, the second generation of economic
theory as the theory of rational choice and analysts of law took seriously the possibility
enormously extending the application of that the (implicit, intuitive) logic of the law
economics to nonmarket activity has been
Becker, who began publishing in the 1950s. 2
The subject of a recent retrospective symposium
His book on the economics of racial dis- (“Symposium: Calabresi’s The Costs of Accidents: A
crimination (Becker 1957), and his article Generation of Impact on Law and Scholarship” 2005). But
of equal importance was Calabresi’s article with A.
on the economics of crime and its punish- Douglas Melamed (1972), which first analyzed the eco-
ment (Becker 1968; see Posner 1993), were nomic difference between property rights and liability as
landmarks in the emergence of economic means by which the legal system directs the allocation of
resources.
3
This is a particular theme in Posner (1972b) and in
1
For a fuller discussion, see Posner (2001, ch. 1). subsequent editions of that work.
jun06_Article4 5/15/06 4:16 PM Page 407

Posner: A Review of Foundations of Economic Analysis of Law 407

might indeed be economics. Their work, attention never flagging, has produced a
much of it by law professors rather than by steady stream of pathbreaking work for a
professional economists, was characterized quarter of a century, sharply focused on a con-
by close attention to legal doctrines, proce- vergent body of issues and yielding the unified
dures, and institutions. Formal modeling was theory of law set forth in Foundations—to
not emphasized and theoretical rigor was which at last I turn.
often absent in the work of the law profes- This massive tome of more than 700 pages
sors. But as a result of the close attention to is best described as an economic treatise on
the law itself, the work of the second genera- the basic fields of law that I listed at the out-
tion had and continues to exert an immense set—torts, contracts, remedies, etc. These are
influence on legal education (both teaching fields to which Shavell has made important
and scholarship) and a growing influence on contributions, which naturally are empha-
legal doctrine and on the practice and admin- sized though not to the exclusion of other
istration of law. By the time Steven Shavell major contributions—the hundreds of refer-
began publishing, economic analysis of law ences listed in the forty–four–page bibliogra-
was already recognized to be the foremost phy make the book among other things an
interdisciplinary field of legal scholarship. immensely valuable guide to the scholarly lit-
This was the legacy of the first and second erature of economic analysis of law. There is
generations of economic analysts of law. only one field covered in the book to which
That economic analysis of law continues to Shavell (2004) has not made major contribu-
grow in scope, insight, and influence is, how- tions, and that is intellectual property—and it
ever, due in considerable measure to the is the book’s thinnest, least interesting section
work of the third generation, Shavell’s gen- (pp. 137–74).
eration. This generation is dominated by Although many of the most interesting
technically sophisticated economists, such as ideas presented in the book date from work
Oliver Hart (1995), A. Mitchell Polinsky, and by Shavell and others in the early 1980s and
of course Shavell himself, and by law profes- even earlier, there is much that is recent
sors who have a doctorate (or, in a minority (see, for example, references to Shavell’s own
of cases, an ABD) in economics, such as recent work in Shavell 2004, pp. 711–13);
Lucian Bebchuk, Louis Kaplow, and Alan the book is up to date. And Shavell has done
Sykes. (This is a very incomplete list.) something fresh and interesting that signifi-
Whereas the second generation tended to cantly enhances its value as a reference work
work the extensive margin, bringing more and teaching supplement—which is to
and more doctrines, procedures, and institu- exclude math from the text but place mathe-
tions under the lens of economics, the third matical versions of a number of the analytic
generation has tended to cultivate the inten- points made in the text in footnotes. The
sive margin, bringing new insights into fields mathless text makes the book intelligible to
such as torts and contracts that had already the mathless reader, which is to say to the
received considerable attention from the average law professor, law student, lawyer,
second generation. and judge, all of whom can benefit immense-
Shavell is the leading figure of the third ly from the book. The mathematical foot-
generation—and only in part because of his notes will enable the economist reader who
seniority (at 59, he is one of the oldest of the may not have encountered economic analysis
leading figures of the generation, and so he of law before to see it expressed in the formal
has had more time to publish and become well models with which he is familiar.
known and influential than the others). He is There are now a number of book-length
not only a gifted theoretician but also a treatments of economic analysis of law, but
dogged, careful, thorough worker, who, his there is no book quite like Foundations.
jun06_Article4 5/15/06 4:16 PM Page 408

408 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XLIV (June 2006)

There are quite a few textbooks, most of criticize Shavell for stopping after 737 pages.
which proceed by first introducing the read- The book does exactly what he set out to do,
er to the basic economic principles that are and what he set out to do is immensely
relevant and then applying them to a hand- important. But I want to dispel any impres-
ful of legal rules (see, for example, Polinsky sion that economists might take away from
2003; Cooter and Ulen 2000; Friedman reading the book that economic analysis of
2000; Miceli 2004; Spurr 2005). Shavell law is exhausted in Shavell’s treatment.
skips that stage, presupposing the reader’s To begin with, what Shavell means by eco-
knowledge of the most elementary princi- nomic analysis of “law” is not what a lawyer
ples of economics, and this enables him to would understand by the term. The lawyer
discuss more legal rules and in greater would expect the book to be about the law as
depth. The same approach is taken in my it exists in statutes and cases and in the cus-
own textbook treatise.4 It is somewhat toms and practices of lawyers and judges and
longer than Shavell’s and covers a much prosecutors and the rest of the law’s drama-
larger area of the law and in greater detail, tis personae—which is to say, the law as it is
but my economic treatment of issues on stated in legal treatises and judicial decisions
which our two books overlap lacks the depth plus the law in action, that is, the law as it is
and rigor of Shavell’s treatment. There are actually practiced and enforced. The lawyer
also encyclopedic works on economic analy- would be wrong in that understanding of
sis of law (Newman 1998; Bouckaert and De Shavell’s book. The “law” that Shavell ana-
Geest 2000), necessarily unwieldy and het- lyzes is an abstract or stylized—a simpli-
erogeneous; a number of anthologies of arti- fied—version of actual law; it is law minus
cles on law and economics (see, for detail and texture, law trimmed to fit the
example, Oppenheimer and Mercuro 2005; economic model. Often this works fine in
Wittman 2003; Posner 2000; Backhaus capturing the essential features of the sub-
1999; Katz 1998; Dau-Schmidt and Ulen ject; indeed, it is hard to imagine how man-
1998; Posner and Parisi 1997; Coleman and ageable economic models of law, as of other
Lange 1992); and some general introducto- institutions or activities, could be developed
ry works that are not quite textbooks (for without considerable simplification of the
example, Harrison 2003; Mercuro and phenomenon being modeled. So “negli-
Medema 1997).5 Shavell’s book, in short, gence” to Shavell means failure to use due
fills a significant gap. care, as a result of which an injury occurs;
The word “foundations” in Shavell’s title is and he explains what this might mean in eco-
a double entendre. In one sense it refers to nomics, namely (an insight surprisingly
the legal subject matter analyzed in the anticipated by a judge, Learned Hand, in a
book, which consists, as I said, of the basic, 1945 case) that the expected cost of the
or foundational, fields of law and aspects of injury (the cost of the injury if it occurs dis-
the legal system. In another sense, the word counted by the probability that it will occur)
refers to the analytic foundations of econom- exceeded the cost of a precaution that would
ic analysis of law, which are the principles of have prevented the injury from occurring.
economics. Those foundations are vital, but Although judges rarely speak in cost–benefit
the foundations of an edifice are not the terms, cost–benefit analysis is a close
entire edifice. In so saying, I do not mean to approximation to the negligence inquiry.
There are various buttressing rules of negli-
gence (assumption of risk, contributory and
4
The current edition is Posner (2003). comparative negligence, last clear chance,
5
There are a number of books dealing with economic
analysis of particular fields of law, such as accident law, but etc.), some of which are discussed by Shavell
of course they are not comparable to Shavell’s in scope. but many not; and there are fascinating cases
jun06_Article4 5/15/06 4:16 PM Page 409

Posner: A Review of Foundations of Economic Analysis of Law 409

that test and probe the rules, and these are imagine making the same offer to the
also not discussed. So there is considerable neighbor himself!
simplification in his treatment of the con- The book has other limitations stemming
cept of negligence but there is no significant from its stylized treatment of law. There is,
distortion. unsurprisingly, a certain insensitivity to the
His treatment of tort law, however, is practical dimensions of law, as in the sugges-
incomplete. Shavell rightly emphasizes the tion that a higher-level court “could readily
role of tort law in deterring inefficient accomplish harmonization [of the law—that
behavior, a role that follows directly from is, ‘reconciliation of conflicting interpretation
rational-choice theory (the threat of liabili- by different trial courts’] on its own initia-
ty operating as a price for engaging in risky tive,” without need to allow appeals (p. 463).
behavior), but barely mentions the growing That would not be a court at all, in any rec-
literature in cognitive psychology (a litera- ognizable sense. Or consider his advocacy of
ture sometimes referred to as “behavioral substituting for the patent system a govern-
economics” when used by economists), mental reward for valuable inventions (pp.
which bears on the ability and inclination of 161–65), an approach that would generate
people to respond to risk and to the finan- rent-seeking on a colossal scale. Or his (relat-
cial incentives and disincentives created by ed) advocacy of entitling a finder of lost prop-
tort liability (see, for example, Parisi and erty to a mandatory reward from the owner
Smith 2005; Sunstein 2000). To what based on “the optimal recovery effort” (p. 43,
extent, for example, do people actually n. 21)—a determination that a court would
understand and act upon the various risks find extremely difficult to make and that
that law deals with and sometimes creates, would not even be worth making. Most lost
such as the risk of punishment for commit- property is of little value; when it is of sub-
ting a crime? Do financial consequences of stantial value, the owner can post a reward,
tort liability actually add anything to the which is legally enforceable; there is little
deterrent effect that is exerted by fear of reason for (further) public intervention.
being killed or injured in an accident,6 or of And it seems odd to wonder as Shavell (p.
being fined for dangerous behavior? Do 205) does why there should be strict liability
consumers actually read the fine print of for allowing a wild animal to escape and
installment contracts? If they don’t, does it injure someone but not for an automobile
matter? Shavell remarks that “a person driver’s running down a pedestrian. The only
might pay his neighbor to plant a screen of way to prevent the wild animal from escaping
bushes around an unsightly garbage area so may be not to have a wild animal on one’s
that the person can enjoy a better view” (p. property in the first place, an activity-level
86), but what is interesting is how rare such change (the not having) that strict liability
transactions are, that is, value-maximizing would induce but negligence liability would
transactions in noncommercial settings. not. Besides, a pedestrian can usually avoid
Their rarity seems to reflect a peculiar shy- injury by being careful even if drivers are
ness about “commodifying” certain rela- negligent, but it is very difficult to protect
tionships. One might offer a neighbor’s oneself against a rampaging wild animal.
teenage son money to mow one’s lawn; but Strangest of all is Shavell’s (pp. 58–59)
proposal that gifts (not just charitable gifts
6
Shavell (pp. 284, 395) suggests not, though without but all gifts) should be subsidized on the
discussion. He may be correct, but he is incorrect to sug- ground that very often a sum of money pos-
gest that, if so, tort liability will have little effect on the sessed by one person would confer a greater
incidence of automobile accidents; for by increasing the
cost of driving (via the effect on liability insurance rates), it total utility if it were transferred to another
will reduce the accident rate (Grayston 1973). person. That is true but the proposal would
jun06_Article4 5/15/06 4:16 PM Page 410

410 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XLIV (June 2006)

entail a massive administrative structure for claiming that compensation for taking prop-
redistributing wealth. It is an example of erty by eminent domain is not required even
how a commitment to utilitarianism can lead if property owners are risk averse because
one astray. Utility is a useful concept in eco- they should be able to purchase insurance
nomics but the idea that a society should against the taking of their property. This is
strive to maximize utility (and whose utili- doubtful on two grounds. First, the risk may
ty?—just members of the society, or foreign- not be susceptible of quantification, in
ers too, or maybe, as the classical utilitarians which event there is no basis for setting an
thought, animals too?—and what about insurance premium.8 Second, moral hazard
unborn generations?) cannot be taken seri- would deter an insurance company from
ously once one actually starts to think about insuring a property for more than its market
it. In part 7 of Foundations—“Welfare value. But it is precisely the “more” that the
Economics, Morality, and the Law,” consist- property owner fearful of eminent domain
ing of three short chapters—Shavell advo- would want to insure because, in an eminent
cates utilitarianism as the proper framework domain proceeding, he would be entitled to
for evaluating social welfare. He does so (and thus “insured” for) the market value of
without discussing the many disabling objec- his property.
tions to utilitarianism as a normative system. Shavell (pp. 72–76) criticizes the rule of
He is not a philosopher. He misunderstands adverse possession (which in some circum-
“wealth maximization,” which is simply the stances allows a person who occupies anoth-
Kaldor–Hicks criterion (potential Pareto er person’s land to obtain title to it without
superiority) and he misunderstands “classic the owner’s consent) seemingly without real-
corrective justice” to be the principle that izing that adverse possession requires not
“the wrongdoer must make his victim whole” only open (visible) occupancy visibly
(p. 635).7 adverse,9 but also that the occupant have a
Occasionally, Shavell’s refusal to engage good faith belief that he is the true owner of
with the actual rules of the legal system leads the property. Shavell (p. 53) discusses the
to error. These errors are frequent rather bona fide purchaser rule (the rule that some-
than occasional in the chapter on property, one who buys in good faith can obtain good
which is one of the weaker chapters in the title even if the seller was not authorized to
book—and not only because it is the chapter sell) on the assumption that it enables a thief
in which he discusses intellectual property. to pass good title. This is incorrect; the rule
Not that there aren’t many fine insights even allows a purchaser, again if he is acting in
in this chapter. I was particularly struck by a good faith, to obtain ownership of property if
novel, counterintuitive but sound argument for example the seller was an agent of the
for the power of eminent domain: that even original owner and in selling rather than
if the utility of a person’s property to the per- renting the good exceeded his instructions;
son is less than the utility that the property but not if the property was stolen.
would confer on society at large if the prop-
8
erty were put to some public use, there may Insurance presupposes risk. Uncertain events (in
Frank Knight’s distinction between risk and uncertainty—
be no price that the owner would accept to the first calculable, the second not) cannot be insured
part with the property voluntarily because of against. The Lloyd’s syndicate in London traditionally
diminishing marginal utility of money (p. would insure anything—but that is just an example of the
fact that some people will gamble without knowing the
125, n. 24). But in further discussion of emi- odds.
nent domain, Shavell (pp. 127–28) stumbles, 9
That is, the owner must be on notice that the posses-
sor’s claim is inconsistent with his (the original owner’s)
title. A tenant has possession of his landlord’s property, but
7
On these issues, see Posner (2001, ch. 3; 1990, chs. his possession is not inconsistent with the landlord’s con-
11–12). tinued ownership.
jun06_Article4 5/15/06 4:16 PM Page 411

Posner: A Review of Foundations of Economic Analysis of Law 411

I do not wish to exaggerate; Shavell’s legal idea of when law conforms to the dictates of
mistakes are few, given the length and scope economic efficiency and when it does not—
of the book. It is curious but true that, and why not, a question of political economy
although economics is intellectually more that Shavell does not discuss. The lack of an
sophisticated than law and though there is— empirical dimension to the book under-
recognition of this point is close to the heart mines Shavell’s (p. 670) conclusion that eco-
of economic analysis of law10—a considerable nomic efficiency “sometimes is consistent
isomorphism between law and economics, no with our legal system and other times con-
one, however bright, who is not a lawyer can flicts with it.” What he has analyzed is a
get the law quite right. Law is like a language stripped-down model of our legal system,
that you have to be a native speaker of to not the system itself. No actual system cor-
speak correctly. Shavell is not a lawyer, and a responds exactly to an economic model of it.
strength of his work is his determination to The question that must be answered to
stick to his last, as an economic theorist determine how efficient an actual legal sys-
(which he fails to do only when he discusses tem is, is in what specific respects a change
philosophy); and that is fine. in the system would increase efficiency. That
Another thing that Shavell is not is an is an empirical question.
empiricist (if he were, he would have to con- These critical comments must be placed
front the challenges that behavioral econom- in perspective. Consdering the length of
ics mount to the traditional rational-choice Shavell’s book, I find remarkably little in it to
model that Shavell employs), although he criticize or disagree with. Just as Thomas
cites many empirical studies in the econom- Aquinas’s Summa Theologica is the defini-
ics of law and by doing so usefully reminds tive summation of medieval scholasticism, so
the reader that there is by now a very exten- with a little extravagance can Foundations of
sive body of such studies. Econometric Economic Analysis of Law be described as
analysis of law is enabled by the prominence the summa of the third generation of eco-
of quantitative measures of legal activity— nomic analysis of law. So it is timely to con-
such as number of cases of various kinds,11 sider whether a fourth generation has
number of reversals and affirmances, num- appeared on the scene. It has. It differs from
ber of accidents and crimes of various the preceding generations in part in its inter-
kinds—even the number of abortions (John national, comparative, and historical focus
J. Donohue and Steven D. Levitt 2001)— (see, for example, Shleifer 2005; Glaeser and
and the size of fines and length of prison Shleifer 2002; La Porta, Lopez-de-Silanes,
sentences. Explaining changes in these and Shleifer 2006), whereas the previous
measures over time and across different focus had been on modern Anglo–American
legal jurisdictions is a challenging but feasi- law, though with exceptions. The variety of
ble undertaking. We need to have a better legal systems, across nations and through
time, is marked and calls for explanation.
(Shavell notes from time to time salient dif-
10
For an early example, see Posner (1972a). ferences between Anglo–American and
11
The book contains a curious error concerning num-
ber of cases, however. It states that 2.3 million civil cases European law, but does not try to explain
were filed in federal courts in 2000. Id. at 390. This is them.) The consequences of that variety for
almost ten times the actual number, which was 259,517 in economic development are potentially very
fiscal 2000 (Administrative Office of the United States
Courts 2000, table C). An even odder mistake, because it great (a point grasped long ago by Max
is purely arithmetic, is the statement that the number of Weber) and provide a rich field for empirical
Americans in prison or jail, 1.9 million, is 3 percent of the study. The rising generation also displays a
nation’s adult population (p. 534). The total adult popula-
tion of the United States is 300 million, which means that greater interest in the effect of human cog-
the percentage imprisoned is less than 1 percent. nitive limitations on the law (the domain of
jun06_Article4 5/15/06 4:16 PM Page 412

412 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XLIV (June 2006)

behavioral economics) in normative systems as well as on rational-choice theory. They are,


that are distinct from but intersect with law, first, situating law in the total system of social
such as custom and social norms, and— control, which includes custom (much
though this is just beginning—in the appli- emphasized by Friedrich Hayek and, earlier,
cation to law of the new (new to economic by theorists of the common law), morality,
analysts of law at any rate, and unmentioned reputation, and emotion; and second, explain-
in Shavell’s book) field of organizational eco- ing the behavior of judges. These central
nomics (on which see, for example, Roberts actors in the legal systems especially of com-
2004). mon law jurisdictions are surrounded by con-
There is a degree of artificiality in my gen- straints that seem designed to strip them of all
erational divisions. The generations overlap the incentives on which the model of rational
both in time and in methods and subject choice is based. The judicial career is careful-
matter. Members of the second generation ly constructed to deny the judge any benefit
are continuing to do second, third, and even (or cost) from deciding a case one way or the
fourth generation work; third generation other or, indeed, from exerting himself. Not
work will undoubtedly continue for many only are judicial salaries fixed, with no bonus-
years. Shavell’s Foundations is not the com- es or reductions based on performance, but,
pletion of that work, but it does so well what in many judicial systems, including the U.S.
it does that it allows us to see more clearly federal judiciary, judges have lifetime tenure
what remains to be done—the agenda for and can be removed only for the grossest mis-
what I am calling the fourth generation. conduct. Yet judicial decisions, including
I said that Shavell is not an empiricist, a those of federal judges, do not appear to be
psychologist, or a lawyer. The new agenda random or judges strikingly lazy. So what is
will draw heavily on the skills denoted by their motivational structure?
these vocations. Let me amplify the main These first three agenda items are all
items on the agenda sketched very briefly empirical in emphasis. And rightly so, not
above. One is the comparative study of legal only because economic analysis of law has
institutions. To study the effects of a social been tilted too far toward theory but also
institution empirically using econometric because with the growth of the Web and of
methods such as multiple regression, it is digitized data generally, far more data for the
helpful to have a lot of variation; and there is quantitative study of law and legal institu-
much more variation in legal institutions tions are readily and cheaply available,
when one is comparing nations than when searchable, and, in short, eminently usable
one is comparing states within the United than was true only a few years ago. The
States. The legal systems of our states, with recent founding of the Journal of Empirical
the principal (though not only, Berkowitz and Legal Studies is a portent of new empirical
Clay 2005) exception of Louisiana, are based opportunities in law that economic analysts
on the English (common law) system; the of law are in the best position to exploit.
legal systems of most other nations are based Fourth—and this relates to the economic
on the Continental (civil law) model. The two analysis of law in developing countries—is
models differ in doctrines, procedures, legal the use of economic analysis to generate fea-
professions, and judicial careers and struc- sible, concrete, needed legal reforms.
tures. There is even more variation across Economic analysis of law does not have such
systems when the nations compared include intrinsic fascination that it can flourish in an
the nations of the developing world, most of academic hothouse, with no real-world
which have very inadequate legal institutions. applications. It is not like archeology, which
The second and third items on the agenda flourishes as a field because of a disinterest-
are related in drawing on cognitive psychology ed fascination with ancient civilization. The
jun06_Article4 5/15/06 4:16 PM Page 413

Posner: A Review of Foundations of Economic Analysis of Law 413

continued vitality of economic analysis of law judiciaries, strongly centralized and hierar-
depends on its being able to contribute to chic (“U-form”), and the U.S. judiciaries,
the improvement of law. The opportunities which are much more loosely coordinated
are notable in developing countries because (“M-form”).
their economic problems are bound up with Organizational economics also has much to
the inefficiency of their legal institutions; the contribute to unraveling the mystery of judicial
challenge is to reform those institutions motivation. For organizational economists are
piecemeal in the absence of the kind of mindful of the limited feasibility of perform-
political and economic infrastructure that ance measures even in business firms and the
supports the legal institutions of the wealthy resulting need to establish incentive systems
countries. There are numerous opportuni- that are not based on efforts to determine a
ties for economics-guided reform of our own worker’s marginal product—systems that may
laws and legal institutions as well. But to be not rely on direct economic incentives at all
feasible, proposals for reform have to be (Roberts 2004, pp. 173–76).
anchored in exact knowledge of the charac- REFERENCES
ter, structure, and consequences of the exist-
Administrative Office of the United States Courts.
ing laws and institutions. A knowledge of the 2000. Judicial Business of the United States Courts:
economics of stylized legal rules is not good Annual Report of the Director. Washington, D.C.:
enough. Administrative Office of the United States Courts.
Backhaus, Jürgen G., ed. 1999. The Elgar Companion
Fifth, and closely related: in this task of to Law and Economics. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.
feasible reform, the literature in organiza- Becker, Gary S. 1957. The Economics of Discrimination.
tional economics, as yet neglected by eco- Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Becker, Gary S. 1968. “Crime and Punishment: An
nomic analysts of law, has an important role Economic Approach.” Journal of Political Economy,
to play. What distinguishes that field is that 76(2): 169–217.
its practitioners are not content to study styl- Becker, Gary S., and William M. Landes, eds. 1974.
Essays in the Economics of Crime and Punishment.
ized models of organization (for example, New York: Columbia University Press.
the “M-form” versus the “U-form”). They Berkowitz, Daniel, and Karen Clay. 2005. “American
study, often in the course of consulting for, Civil Law Origins: Implications for State
Constitutions.” American Law and Economics
actual organizations. So far, it is mainly con- Review, 7(1): 62–84.
ventional business firms that are being stud- Bouckaert, Boudewijn, and Gerrit De Geest, eds.
ied, but the principles of organizational 2000. Encyclopedia of Law and Economics.
Cheltenham: Elgar.
economics are equally applicable to nonmar- Calabresi, Guido, and A. Douglas Melamed. 1972.
ket organizations (see, for example, “Property Rules, Liability Rules, and Inalienability:
Garicano and Posner 2005). Judiciaries and One View of the Cathedral.” Harvard Law Review,
85(6): 1089–1128.
law firms illustrate the centrality of organiza- Coase, Ronald H. 1960. “The Problem of Social Cost.”
tion to the legal system. Such striking devel- Journal of Law and Economics, 3: 1–44.
opments as the sudden, enormous surge in Coase, Ronald H. 1984. “The New Institutional
Economics.” Journal of Institutional and Theoretical
litigation that began (in the United States) at Economics, 140(1): 229–31.
the end of the 1950s, the essentially effort- Coase, Ronald H. 1988. The Firm, the Market, and the
less way in which that expansion was accom- Law: Essays in the Institutional Structure of
Production. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
modated by a judicial system already Coleman, Jules, and Jeffrey Lange, eds. 1992. Law and
described as overburdened, and the vast Economics. New York: New York University Press.
recent increase in the size and geographical Cooter, Robert, and Thomas S. Ulen. 2000. Law and
Economics. Third edition. Reading: Addison Wesley
scope of law firms, are puzzling phenomena Longman.
that organizational economics may illumi- Dau-Schmidt, Kenneth G., and Thomas S. Ulen, eds.
nate. It may also help to explain the causes 1998. Law and Economics Anthology. Cincinnati:
Anderson Publishing.
and consequences of the striking organiza- Donohue, John J., III, and Steven D. Levitt. 2001.
tional differences between the Continental “The Impact of Legalized Abortion on Crime.”
jun06_Article4 5/15/06 4:16 PM Page 414

414 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XLIV (June 2006)

Quarterly Journal of Economics, 116(2): 379–420. Polinsky, A. Mitchell. 2003. An Introduction to Law
Friedman, David D. 2000. Law’s Order: What and Economics. Third edition. New York: Aspen
Economics Has to Do with Law and Why It Matters. Publishers.
Princeton: Princeton University Press. Posner, Eric A., ed. 2000. Chicago Lectures in Law and
Garicano, Luis, and Richard A. Posner. 2005. Economics. New York: Foundation Press.
“Intelligence Failures: An Organizational Economics Posner, Richard A. 1972a. “A Theory of Negligence.”
Perspective.” Journal of Economic Perspectives, Journal of Legal Studies, 1(1): 29–96.
19(4): 151–70.. Posner, Richard A. 1972b. Economic Analysis of Law.
Glaeser, Edward L., and Andrei Shleifer. 2002. “Legal Boston: Little, Brown and Company.
Origins.” Quarterly Journal of Economics, 117(4): Posner, Richard A. 1993. “Gary Becker’s Contributions
1193–1229. to Law and Economics.” Journal of Legal Studies,
Grayston, Richard W. 1973. “Deterrence in 22(2): 211–15.
Automobile Liability Insurance—The Empirical Posner, Richard A. 1995. Overcoming Law.
Evidence.” Insurance Counsel Journal, 40(1): Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
117–29. Posner, Richard A. 2001. Frontiers of Legal Theory.
Harrison, Jeffrey L. 2003. Law and Economics in a Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Nutshell. Third edition. St. Paul: West Group. Posner, Richard A. 2003. Economic Analysis of Law.
Hart, Oliver. 1995. Firms, Contracts, and Financial Sixth edition. New York: Aspen Publishers.
Structure. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Posner, Richard A., and Francesco Parisi, eds. 1997.
Katz, Avery Wiener, ed. 1998. Foundations of the Law and Economics. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.
Economic Approach to Law. New York: Oxford Roberts, John. 2004. The Modern Firm: Organizational
University Press. Design for Performance and Growth. Oxford: Oxford
La Porta, Rafael, Florencio Lopez-de-Silanes, and University Press.
Andrei Shleifer. 2006. “What Works in Securities Shavell, Steven. 2004. Foundations of Economic
Laws?” Journal of Finance, 61(1):1–32. Analysis of Law. Cambridge: Harvard University
Mercuro, Nicholas, and Steven G. Medema. 1997. Press.
Economics and the Law: From Posner to Post- Shleifer, Andrei, ed. 2005. “Comparative Law.”
Modernism. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Special Issue, American Law and Economics
Miceli, Thomas J. 2004. The Economic Approach to Review, 7(1).
Law. Stanford: Stanford University Press. Spurr, Stephen J. 2005. Economic Foundations of Law.
Newman, Peter, ed. 1998. The New Palgrave Mason: Thomson/South-Western.
Dictionary of Economics and the Law. New York: Sunstein, Cass R., ed. 2000. Behavioral Law and
Stockton Press. Economics. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Oppenheimer, Margaret, and Nicholas Mercuro, eds. Press.
2005. Law and Economics: Alternative Economic ”Symposium: Calabresi’s The Costs of Accidents: A
Approaches to Legal and Regulatory Issues. Armonk, Generation of Impact on Law and Scholarship.”
N.Y.: M. E. Sharpe. 2005. Maryland Law Review, 64(1–2).
Parisi, Francesco, and Vernon L. Smith, eds. 2005. The Wittman, Donald A., ed. 2003. Economic Analysis of
Law and Economics of Irrational Behavior. the Law: Selected Readings. Malden: Blackwell
Stanford: Stanford University Press. Publishers.

You might also like